Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Alf Ross - Tu-Tu

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5

Westlaw Delivery Summary Report for IP USER,NOVUS

Your Search:
Date/Time of Request:
Client Identifier:
Database:
Citation Text:
Lines:
Documents:
Images:

"alf ross"
Friday, February 14, 2014 01:43 Central
INOPJIN-1
HVLR
70 HVLR 812
578
1
0

The material accompanying this summary is subject to copyright. Usage is governed by contract with Thomson Reuters, West and their affiliates.

70 HVLR 812
70 Harv. L. Rev. 812
Harvard Law Review
March, 1957

Comment

*812 T-T [FNb1]

Alf Ross [FNa1]

Copyright (c) 1957 by the Harvard Law Review Association; Alf Ross

ON the Nosulli Islands in the South Pacific lives the Not-cif tribe, generally regarded as one of the more primitive peoples to be found in the world today. Their civilization has recently been
described by the Illyrian anthropologist Ydobon, from whose account the following is taken. [FN1]

This tribe, according to Mr. Ydobon, holds the belief that in the case of an infringement of certain taboos for example, if a man encounters his mother-in-law, or if a totem animal is killed, or if
someone has eaten of the food prepared for the chief there arises what is called t-t. The members of the tribe also say that the person who committed the infringement has become t-t. It is very
difficult to explain what is meant by this. Perhaps the nearest one can get to an explanation is to say that t-t is conceived of as a kind of dangerous force or infection which attaches to the guilty
person and threatens the whole community with disaster. For this reason a person who has become t-t must be subjected to a special ceremony of purification.

It is obvious that the Not-cif tribe dwells in a state of darkest superstition. T-t is of course nothing at all, a word devoid of any meaning whatever. To be sure, the above situations of
infringement of taboo give rise to various natural effects, such as a feeling of dread and terror, but obviously it is not these, any more than any other demonstrable phenomena, which are designated as
t-t. The talk about t-t is pure nonsense.

*813 Nevertheless, and this is what is remarkable, from the accounts given by Mr. Ydobon it appears that this word, in spite of its lack of meaning, has a function to perform in the daily language
of the people. The t-t pronouncements seem able to fulfill the two main functions of all language: to prescribe and to describe; or, to be more explicit, to express commands or rules, and to make
assertions about facts. [FN2]

If I say, in three different languages, My father is dead, Mein Vater ist gestorben, and Mon pre est mort, we have three different sentences, but only one assertion. Despite their differing
linguistic forms, all three sentences refer to one and the same state of affairs (my father's being dead), and this state of affairs is asserted as existing in reality, as distinct from being merely imagined.
The state of affairs to which a sentence refers is called its semantic reference. It can more precisely be defined as that state of affairs which is related to the assertion in such a way that if the state of
affairs is assumed actually to exist then the assertion is assumed to be true. The semantic reference of a sentence will depend upon the linguistic usages prevailing in the community. According to
these usages a certain definite state of affairs is the stimulus to saying My father is dead. This state of affairs constitutes the semantic reference of the pronouncement and can be established quite
independently of any ideas the speaker may possibly have concerning death for example, that the soul at death departs from the body.

On the other hand, if I say to my son Shut the door, this sentence is clearly not the expression of any assertion. True, it has reference to a state of affairs, but in a quite different way. This state of
affairs (the door's being shut) is not indicated as actually existing, but is presented as a guide for my son's behavior. Such pronouncements are said to be the expression of a prescription.

According to Mr. Ydobon's account, within the community of the Not-cif tribe there are in use, among others, the following two pronouncements:

(1) If a person has eaten of the chief's food he is t-t.


(2) If a person is t-t he shall be subjected to a ceremony of purification.
*814 Now it is plain that quite apart from what t-t stands for, or even whether it stands for anything at all, these two pronouncements, when combined in accordance with the usual rules of
logic, will amount to the same thing as the following pronouncement:

(3) If a person has eaten of the chief's food he shall be subjected to a ceremony of purification.
This statement obviously is a completely meaningful prescriptive pronouncement, without the slightest trace of mysticism. This result is not really surprising, for it is simply due to the fact that
we are here using a technique of expression of the same kind as this: When x = y and y = z, then x = z, a proposition which holds good whatever y stands for, or even if it stands for nothing at all.

Although the word t-t in itself has no meaning whatever, yet the pronouncements in which this word occurs are not made in a haphazard fashion. Like other pronouncements of assertion they
are stimulated in conformity with the prevailing linguistic customs by quite definite states of affairs. This explains why the t-t pronouncements have semantic reference although the word is
meaningless. The pronouncement of the assertion N. N. is t-t clearly occurs in definite semantic connection with a complex situation of which two parts can be distinguished:

(1) The state of affairs in which N. N. has either eaten of the chief's food or has killed a totem animal or has encountered his mother-in-law, etc. This state of affairs will hereinafter be
referred to as affairs 1.
(2) The state of affairs in which the valid norm which requires ceremonial purification is applicable to N. N., more precisely stated as the state of affairs in which if N. N. does not submit
himself to the ceremony he will in all probability be exposed to a given reaction on the part of the community. This state of affairs will hereinafter be referred to as affairs 2.
Given the existence of these two states of affairs, the pronouncement that N. N. is t-t is assumed to be true. Thus, the combination of the two states, in consequence of the definition, is the
semantic reference of the pronouncement. It is quite another matter that the members of the Not-cif tribe are not themselves aware of this, but rather, in their superstitious imaginings, ascribe to the
pronouncement the occurrence of a dangerous force, a different reference from that which it has in reality. This, however, does not prevent one from discussing quite reasonably *815 whether or not a
person in given circumstances really is t-t. The reasoning, then, sets out to show whether the person in question has committed one of the relevant infringements of taboo and whether the
purification norm is applicable to him in consequence.

An assertion to the effect that N. N. is t-t can thus be verified by proving the existence of either the first or the second state of affairs. It makes no difference which, because according to the
ideology prevailing in the tribe these two states of affairs are always bound up with one another. It is therefore equally correct to say N. N. is t-t, because he has eaten of the chief's food (and
therefore must be subjected to a ceremonial purification) or N. N. is t-t, because the purification norm is applicable to him (because he has eaten of the chief's food). The latter does not preclude
the possibility of also saying at the same time The purification norm is applicable to N. N. because he is t-t (because he has eaten of the chief's food). The vicious circle which apparently results
here is in reality nonexistent, since the word t-t stands for nothing whatever, and there thus exists no relation, either causal or logical, between the presumed t-t phenomenon and the
application of the purification norm. In reality all three statements as indicated in the added parentheses express, each in its own way, nothing more than that the person who has eaten of the
chief's food shall undergo a ceremonial purification.

What has been said here in no way upsets the assertion that t-t is a meaningless word. It is only the statement N. N. is t-t to which, taken in its entirety, semantic reference can be
ascribed. But there cannot be distinguished in this reference a certain reality or quality which can be ascribed to N. N. and which corresponds to the word t-t. The form of the statement is
inadequate in relation to what is referred to, and this inadequacy is of course a consequence of the superstitious beliefs held by the tribe.

Thus any attempt to ascribe to the word t-t an independent semantic reference in propositions like the following is doomed to failure:

(1) If a person has eaten of the chief's food he is t-t.


(2) If a person is t-t he shall be subjected to a ceremony of purification.
The attempt might be made in the following possible ways:

*816 (a) In proposition (1), for t-t substitute affairs 2; and in proposition (2), for t-t substitute affairs 1. Each will then acquire a meaning on its own. [FN3] But this solution is
inadmissible, because the two propositions constitute the major and minor premises for the conclusion that a person who has eaten of the chief's food shall be subjected to a ceremony of
purification. The word t-t, therefore, if it means anything at all, must mean the same thing in both of them.
(b) In both propositions, for t-t substitute affairs 1. This will not do, for in that case proposition (1) becomes analytically void and without any semantic reference whatever. For the
sense of it will be: When a person has eaten of the chief's food, the state of affairs exists where he has either eaten of the chief's food or killed a totem animal or ....
(c) In both propositions, for t-t substitute affairs 2. This will not do either, for in that case proposition (2) becomes analytically void, as can be demonstrated by exact analogy with the
above paragraph.
Mr. Ydobon tells of a Swedish missionary who had worked for a number of years among the Not-cif tribe, ardently endeavoring to make the natives understand that t-t signified nothing
whatever and that it was an abominable heathen superstition to maintain that something mystical and indeterminable comes into being because a man encounters his mother-in-law. In this, of course,
the good man was quite right. However, it was an excess of zeal which led him to denounce anyone who continued to use the word t-t as a sinful heathen. In so doing he overlooked what has
been demonstrated, that quite apart from the fact that the word in itself has no semantic reference whatever and quite apart from the ideas of mystical forces attaching to it, pronouncements in which
the word occurs can nevertheless function effectively as the expression of prescriptions and assertions.

Of course it would be possible to omit this meaningless word altogether, and instead of the circumlocution:

(1) He who kills a totem animal becomes t-t;


(2) He who is t-t shall undergo a ceremony of purification,
*817 to use the straightforward statement:

(3) He who has killed a totem animal shall undergo a ceremony of purification.
One might therefore ask whether when people have realized that t-t is nothing but an illusion it would not be advantageous to follow this line. As I shall proceed to show later, however,
this is not the case. On the contrary, sound reasons based on the technique of formulation may be adduced for continuing to make use of the t-t construction. But although the t-t formulation
may have certain advantages from the point of view of technique, it must be admitted that it could in certain cases lead to irrational results if against all better judgment the idea that t-t is a reality is
allowed to exert its influence. If this should be the case, it must be the task of criticism to demonstrate the error and to cleanse one's thinking of the dross of such imaginary ideas. But even so, there
would be no grounds for giving up the t-t terminology.

But perhaps it is now time to drop all pretense and openly admit what the reader must by now have discovered, that the allegory concerns ourselves. It is the argument concerning the use of terms
such as right and duty approached from a new angle. [FN4] For our legal rules are in a wide measure couched in a t-t terminology. We find the following phrases, for example, in legal
language:

(1) If a loan is granted, there comes into being a claim;


(2) If a claim exists, then payment shall be made on the day it falls due.
*818 This is only a roundabout way of saying:

(3) If a loan is granted, then payment shall be made on the day it falls due.
The claim mentioned in (1) and (2), but not in (3), is obviously, like t-t, not a real thing; it is nothing at all, merely a word, an empty word devoid of all semantic reference. Similarly, our
assertion to the effect that the borrower becomes pledged corresponds to the allegorical tribe's assertion that the person who kills a totem animal becomes t-t.

We too, then, express ourselves as though something had come into being between the conditioning fact (juristic fact) and the conditioned legal consequence, namely, a claim, a right, which like
an intervening vehicle or causal connecting link promotes an effect or provides the basis for a legal consequence. Nor, really, can we wholly deny that this terminology is associated for us with more
or less indefinite ideas that a right is a power of an incorporeal nature, a kind of inner, invisible dominion over the object of the right, a power manifested in, but nevertheless different from, the
exercise of force (judgment and execution) by which the factual and apparent use and enjoyment of the right is effectuated.

In this way, it must be admitted, our terminology and our ideas bear a considerable structural resemblance to primitive magic thought concerning the invocation of supernatural powers which in
turn are converted into factual effects. Nor can we deny the possibility that this resemblance is rooted in a tradition which, bound up with language and its power over thought, is an age-old legacy
from the infancy of our civilization. [FN5] But after these admissions have been made, there still remains the important question whether sound, rational grounds may be adduced in favor of the
retention of a t-t presentation of legal rules, a form of circumlocution in which between the juristic fact and the legal consequence there are inserted imaginary rights. If this question is to be
answered in the affirmative, the ban on the mention of rights must be lifted. I believe that this question must be *819 answered in the affirmative and shall take the concept of ownership as my point
of departure.

The legal rules concerning ownership could, without doubt, be expressed without the use of this term. In that case a large number of rules would have to be formulated, directly linking the
individual legal consequences to the individual legal facts. For example:

If a person has lawfully acquired a thing by purchase, judgment for recovery shall be given in favor of the purchaser against other persons retaining the thing in their possession.
If a person has inherited a thing, judgment for damages shall be given in favor of the heir against other persons who culpably damage the thing.
If a person by prescription has acquired a thing and raised a loan that is not repaid at the proper time, the creditor shall be given judgment for satisfaction out of the thing.
If a person has occupied a res nullius and by legacy bequeathed it to another person, judgment shall be given in favor of the legatee against the testator's estate for the surrender of the
thing.
If a person has acquired a thing by means of execution as a creditor and the object is subsequently appropriated by another person, the latter shall be punished for theft.
An account along these lines would, however, be so unwieldy as to be practically worthless. It is the task of legal thinking to conceptualize the legal rules in such a way that they are reduced to
systematic order and by this means to give an account of the law in force which is as plain and convenient as possible. This can be achieved with the aid of the following technique of presentation.

On looking at a large number of legal rules on the lines indicated, one will find that it is possible to select from among them a certain group that can be arranged in the following way:

F -C
1

F -C
1

F -C
1

F -C

F -C

F -C

F -C
1

F -C

F -C

F -C

F -C

F -C

F -C

F -C

F -C

F -C

The conditioning fact F is connected with the legal consequence C , etc. This means that each single one of a certain totality of *820 conditioning facts (F - F ) is connected with each single one of
1

a certain group of legal consequences (C - C ); or, that it is true of each single F that it is connected with the same group of legal consequences (C + C + C ); or, that a cumulative plurality of
1

legal consequences is connected to a disjunctive plurality of conditioning facts.

These n x p individual legal rules can be stated more simply and more manageably in the figure:

TABULAR OR GRAPHIC MATERIAL SET FORTH AT THIS POINT IS NOT DISPLAYABLE


O (ownership) merely stands for the systematic connection that F as well as F , F F entail the totality of legal consequences C , C , C C . As a technique of presentation this is expressed
1

then by stating in one series of rules the facts that create ownership and in another series the legal consequences that ownership entails.
It will be clear from this that the ownership inserted
between the conditioning facts and the conditioned consequences is in reality a meaningless word, a word without any semantic reference whatever, serving solely as a tool of presentation. We talk as
if ownership were a causal link between F and C, an effect occasioned or created by every F, and which in turn is the cause of a totality of legal consequences. We say, for example, that:

(1) If A has lawfully purchased an object (F ), ownership of the object is thereby created for him.
2

(2) If A is the owner of an object, he has (among other things) the right of recovery (C ).
1

It is clear, however, that (1) + (2) is only a rephrasing of one of the presupposed norms (F - C ), that purchase as a conditioning fact entails the possibility of recovery as a legal consequence. The
2

notion that between purchase and access to recovery something was created that can be designated as ownership *821 is nonsense. Nothing is created as the result of A and B exchanging a few
sentences legally interpreted as a contract of purchase. All that has occurred is that the judge will now take this fact into consideration and give judgment for the purchaser in an action for recovery.

What has been described here is a simple example of reduction by reason to systematic order. In the final instance it is, to be sure, the task of legal science to undertake this process of
simplification, but this task has largely been anticipated by prescientific thought. The idea of certain rights took shape at an early stage in history. A systematic simplification can be carried out, of
course, in more ways than one, and this explains why the categories of rights vary somewhat from one legal system to another, though this circumstance does not necessarily reflect a corresponding
difference in the law in force.

The same technique of presentation can frequently be employed without the idea of an intervening right. In international law, for example, one series of rules may state which area belongs to a
specific state as its territory. That this area has the character of territory is per se meaningless. This characterization has meaning only when taken together with another set of rules expressing the
legal consequences that are attached to an area's character as territory. In this example it would also be possible to state the legal relations without using the interpolated concept territory, although
such a statement would undeniably be complicated.

Sometimes the intermediate link is not a single right, but a complex legal condition of rights and duties. This is the case, for example, when in family law a distinction is made between the
conditions for contracting marriage and the legal effects of marriage, when in constitutional law a distinction is made between the acquisition of nationality and the legal effects of nationality, or in
administrative law between the creation of civil-servant status and its legal effects. In these and similar situations it is usual to speak of the creation of a status. Whatever the construction, the reality

behind it is in each case the same: a technique which is highly important if we are to achieve clarity and order in a complicated series of legal rules.

Ownership, claim, and other words, when used in legal language, have the same function as the word t-t; they are words without meaning, without any semantic reference, and *822
serve a purpose only as a technique of presentation. Nevertheless, it is possible to talk with meaning about rights, both in the form of prescriptions and assertions.

With regard to prescriptions, this emerges from the foregoing. The two propositions A person who has purchased a thing has the ownership of it and A person who has the ownership of a thing
can obtain recovery of it together produce the meaningful prescriptive rule that a person who has purchased a thing can obtain recovery of it.

With regard to assertions, the following holds good by exact analogy with the exposition given above in respect to t-t assertions: the assertion that A possesses the ownership of a thing, when
taken in its entirety, has semantic reference to the complex situation that there exists one of those facts which are said to establish ownership, and that A can obtain recovery, claim damages, etc. It is
thus possible with equal correctness to say:

A has the ownership of the thing because he has purchased it (and can therefore obtain recovery, claim damages, etc.)
and

A has the ownership of the thing because he can obtain recovery, claim damages, etc. (because he has purchased it).
The latter does not preclude its being possible also to say:

A can obtain recovery of the thing and claim damages, etc., because he has the ownership of the thing (because he has purchased it).
Just as in the case of the corresponding t-t formulations, there is here no vicious circle, since ownership does not stand for anything at all, and there thus exists no relation, either causal or
logical, between the supposed phenomenon of ownership and the legal consequences mentioned. All three pronouncements as indicated by the added parentheses express, each in its own way,
nothing more than that the person who has purchased a thing can obtain recovery of the same, claim damages, etc.

On the other hand it is impossible to ascribe to the word ownership an independent semantic reference in the arguments operating with the word. [FN6] Any attempt to take it as a designation
*823 of either legal facts or of legal consequences, of both together, or of anything else whatever, is foredoomed to failure. Let us, for example, consider the following syllogisms:

(A) If there is a purchase, there exists also ownership for the purchaser. Here there is a purchase. Therefore there exists also ownership for the purchaser.
(B) If ownership exists, the owner can obtain recovery. Here there is ownership. Therefore recovery can be obtained.
Together (A) and (B) express the meaningful rule that a person who has purchased a thing can obtain recovery of it. This conclusion holds good whatever ownership may stand for, or even if it
stands for nothing at all. For ownership there could be substituted old cheese or t-t and the conclusion would be just as valid.

On the other hand, it is impossible in this conclusion to ascribe to the word ownership a semantic reference such that each of the conclusions (A) and (B) considered in isolation can acquire
meaning or legal function. The conceivable possibilities of such an attempt are the same as those given above in the analysis of the corresponding t-t propositions, and the results also
correspond:

(a) If we substitute for ownership in (A) the cumulative totality of legal consequences, and in (B) the disjunctive totality of conditions, (A) and (B) each acquire meaning, but cannot be
combined in a syllogism since the middle term is not the same.
(b) If in both cases we substitute for ownership the disjunctive totality of conditioning facts, the major premise in (A) becomes analytically void and thus without any semantic reference.
*824 (c) If in both cases we substitute for ownership the cumulative totality of legal consequences, then the major premise in (B) becomes analytically void.
I will leave it to the reader to work out for himself the correctness of these assertions by exact analogy with the analysis of the corresponding t-t pronouncements.

The observations I have made here are well fitted to throw light on a most interesting controversy conducted in recent years in Scandinavian literature between Per Olof Ekelf and Ivar Strahl
concerning the meaning in which the concept of rights is taken when used in legal reasoning. [FN7] Ekelf started the discussion in an attempt to find out what states of affairs could be substituted in
such reasoning for an expression couched in terms of rights. This attempt is the same thing as a quest for the semantic reference of the term. It is interesting to follow the course of the controversy, as
it amusingly illustrates the correctness of what has been maintained here.

In broad outline, the course of the controversy was as follows. Ekelf began by assuming that the term claim (this is the term he operated with in his examples, which in other respects were
completely analogous to the (A) and (B) formulations adduced above) does not stand for the same thing in both (A) and (B), but respectively for the legal consequence and the legal fact. This
corresponds exactly with the possibility marked by (a) in the experiment set out above. Strahl countered with the powerful argument that such an interpretation was inadmissible because the term
must of necessity be used with one and the same meaning in both the (A) and (B) propositions because these constitute the premises of a conclusion. Strahl made himself the spokesman for the
position that the concept of rights in both propositions stands for the juridical fact, the disjunctive totality of conditioning facts. This position corresponds to the possibility set out above under (b). To
this Ekelf replied with the argument that if that is so the major premise in case (A) becomes analytically void. Subsequently Ekelf adopted Strahl's theory that the word must stand for the same state
of affairs in both (A) and (B), but maintained that it did not follow as a matter of course that this state of affairs common to both was necessarily the juridical fact. He discovered that the
conclusion*825 comprising (A) and (B) held good whatever was substituted for the rights concept whether juridical fact, legal consequence, or both of them together. But he got no further. He
did not realize that the conclusion would hold good even if for the concept of rights there were substituted old cheese or t-t.

In this controversy it was Strahl who came closer to the truth, when he asserted that the concept of right in case (A) is used to designate the circumstance which in case (B) serves as juridical fact
and went on to characterize this as a device serving the technique of presentation. But what Strahl did not see was that the concept of a right does not designate any circumstance at all, and that the
right as fact is not a fact at all, and that it is hopeless to attempt to ascribe a meaning to the major premises in the (A) and (B) syllogisms when each of them is considered in isolation. For the
device serving the technique of presentation means that the two propositions have meaning only as fragments of a larger whole in which they both occur, causing the concept of rights as the
common middle term in a syllogism to vanish as completely meaningless.

In making these critical observations I have not in any way intended to belittle the value of the research undertaken by Ekelf and Strahl. On the contrary, I think that Ekelf's substitution method
was a fortunate line to take and that it sharpened the issues; and I must add that it was along these lines that I was led to the view which I believe to be the true one, that the concept of rights is a tool
for the technique of presentation serving exclusively systematic ends, and that in itself it means no more and no less than does t-t. [FN8]

[FNb1]. This Comment was originally published in FESTSKRIFT TIL HENRY USSING (Borum & Illum ed. 1951). It will appear in the near future in the first issue of the forthcoming

Scandinavian Studies in Law, a periodical designed to acquaint English-speaking scholars with developments in Scandinavian legal thought and jurisprudence.

[FNa1]. Professor of Law, University of Copenhagen. LL.B., University of Copenhagen, 1922, J.D., 1934; Ph.D., University of Uppsala, 1929.

[FN1]. YDOBON, THE NOTCIFONIAN WAY OF LIFE: STUDIES IN TABOO AND T-T (1950).

[FN2]. On the distinction between prescriptive and descriptive language, see HARE, THE LANGUAGE OF MORALS (1952).

[FN3]. Proposition (1) would mean, If a person has eaten of the chief's food, he shall be subjected to a ceremony of purification; and proposition (2), If a person has either eaten of the chief's food
or , he shall be subjected to a ceremony of purification.

[FN4]. The Swedish missionary of the fable refers to the late Professor A. V. Lundstedt. Throughout his writings, e.g., 1 LUNDSTEDT, DIE UNWISSENSCHAFTLICHKEIT DER
RECHTSWISSENSCHAFT (1932), he has emphasized that the only demonstrable reality in the so-called situations of rights consists in the function of the machinery of the law. Under given
conditions a person can, according to the law in force, institute proceedings and thereby set the machinery of the law in motion, with the result that the public power is exercised for his benefit. He
can achieve judgment and execution by force, creating for himself an advantageous position, a possibility of action, an economic benefit. And that is all. One can readily agree with the author up to
this point. But then, instead of proceeding to ask what is characteristic of the situations designated as rights and how the concept of rights may be analyzed and used as a tool for the description of
these situations, Lundstedt gives a peculiar twist to his critical account by saying that rights do not exist and that anybody using this term is talking rubbish about something that does not exist.
Similar views have been defended by Lon Duguit, 1 DUGUIT, TRAIT DE DROIT CONSTITUTIONNEL (3d ed. 1927), and earlier by Jeremy Bentham, e.g., BENTHAM, THE LIMITS OF
JURISPRUDENCE DEFINED 57-88 (1945).

[FN5]. Axel Hgerstrm has cited weighty arguments in support of the magical origins of Roman legal conceptions. HGERSTRM, DER RMISCHE OBLIGATIONSBEGRIFF (1927). Modern
research in sociology and history of religion also points in the same direction. See Ross, TOWARDS A REALISTIC JURISPRUDENCE 214-44 (1946); MAX WEBER ON LAW IN ECONOMY
AND SOCIETY 106 (Rheinstein ed. 1954).

[FN6]. In an article published shortly after the original publication of the present Comment, but evidently without knowledge of it, Anders Wedberg arrived at conclusions similar to mine:
It may be shocking to unsophisticated common sense to admit such meaningless expressions in the serious discourse of legal scientists. But, as a matter of fact, there is no reason why all
expressions employed in a discourse, which as a whole is highly meaningful, should themselves have a meaning. It appears likely that many expressions employed by other sciences,
especially the so-called exact sciences, lack interpretation and solely function as vehicles of systematization and deduction. Why should not the situation be the same within legal science?

Wedberg, Some Problems in the Logical Analysis of Legal Science, 17 THEORIA 246, 273 (Sweden 1951).
A similar view has since been expressed by H. L. A. Hart. It is possible, that author
maintains, to define a term such as right not by substituting for it other words describing some quality, process, or event, but only by indicating the conditions necessary for the truth of a sentence
of the form You have a right. Hart, Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence, 70 L.Q. REV. 37, 41-42, 45-49 (1954).

[FN7]. The discussion was conducted in the Scandinavian legal reviews Tidsskrift for Rettsvitenskap and Svensk Juristtidning in the years 1945 to 1950.

[FN8]. I have tried elsewhere to show how the concept of rights can lead to errors and dogmatic postulates if it is wrongly taken, not merely as being the systematic unit in a set of legal rules, but as
being an independent substance. Ross, op. cit. supra note 5, at 189-202.
70 Harv. L. Rev. 812

END OF DOCUMENT
2014 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.

You might also like