Wendt 1992 PDF
Wendt 1992 PDF
Wendt 1992 PDF
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to International
Organization.
http://www.jstor.org
46, 2, Spring1992
IntemationalOrganization
? 1992bytheWorldPeace Foundationand the MassachusettsInstituteofTechnology
Yet some liberals want more. When Joseph Nye speaks of "complex
learning,"or RobertJervisof "changingconceptionsof selfand interest,"or
RobertKeohane of "sociological"conceptionsof interest,each is assertingan
importantrole for transformations of identityand interestin the liberal
researchprogramand,byextension,a potentially muchstrongerconceptionof
processand institutions in worldpolitics.6"Strong"liberalsshouldbe troubled
bythedichotomousprivileging ofstructure overprocess,sincetransformations
of identityand interestthroughprocess are transformations of structure.
Rationalismhas littleto offersuch an argument,7 whichis in partwhy,in an
importantarticle, FriedrichKratochwiland John Ruggie argued that its
ontologycontradictedtheintersubjectivist
individualist epistemologynecessary
forregimetheoryto realize itsfullpromise.8Regimescannotchangeidentities
and interestsifthe latterare takenas given.Because of thisrationalistlegacy,
despiteincreasingly numerousand richstudiesof complexlearningin foreign
policy,neoliberalslack a systematictheoryof howsuchchangesoccurand thus
must privilegerealist insightsabout structurewhile advancing their own
insightsaboutprocess.
The ironyis thatsocial theorieswhichseek to explainidentitiesand interests
do exist.Keohane has called them"reflectivist";9because I wantto emphasize
theirfocuson the social construction and minimizetheirimage
of subjectivity
problem,followingNicholas Onuf I will call them "constructivist."" Despite
importantdifferences, cognitivists, standpointand postmod-
poststructuralists,
ern feminists,rule theorists,and structurationists share a concernwiththe
basic "sociological" issue bracketed by rationalists-namely,the issue of
identity-and interest-formation. Constructivism's potentialcontribution to a
strongliberalismhas been obscured, however,by recent epistemological
debates betweenmodernistsand postmodernists, in whichScience disciplines
Dissent for not defininga conventionalresearch program,and Dissent
celebratesitsliberationfromScience.1"Real issues animatethisdebate,which
"Reading Dissidence/Writing the Discipline: Crisis and the Question of Sovereignty in Interna-
tionalStudies,"IntemationalStudiesQuarterly 34 (September1990),pp. 367-416. For an excellent
criticalassessmentof these debates, see Yosef Lapid, "The Third Debate: On the Prospectsof
InternationalTheoryin a Post-PositivistEra," IntemationalStudiesQuarterly 33 (September1989),
pp. 235-54.
12. The factthat I draw on these approaches aligns me withmodernistconstructivists, even
thoughI also drawfreelyon thesubstantive workofpostmodernists, especiallyRichardAshleyand
Rob Walker.For a defenseof thispracticeand a discussionof its epistemologicalbasis, see my
earlier article,"The Agent-Structure Problemin InternationalRelations Theory,"Intemational
Organization41 (Summer 1987), pp. 335-70; and Ian Shapiro and Alexander Wendt, "The
DifferenceThat Realism Makes: Social Science and the Politics of Consent," forthcoming in
Politicsand Society.Amongmodernistconstructivists, myargumentis particularly indebtedto the
published work of Emanuel Adler, FriedrichKratochwil,and John Ruggie, as well as to an
unpublishedpaper by Naeem Inayatullahand David Levine entitled"Politics and Economics in
Contemporary InternationalRelationsTheory,"SyracuseUniversity, Syracuse,N.Y., 1990.
13. See ViktorGecas, "Rekindlingthe SociologicalImaginationin Social Psychology," Joumal
fortheTheory ofSocial Behavior19 (March 1989),pp. 97-115.
Anarchyand powerpolitics
14. Kenneth Waltz, Man, the State,and War (New York: Columbia UniversityPress, 1959),
p. 232.
15. Ibid.,pp. 169-70.
16. Ibid., p. 232. This pointis made byHidemi Suganamiin "BringingOrder to the Causes of
War Debates," Millennium19 (Spring1990),p. 34, fn.11.
17. KennethWaltz,Theory Politics(Boston: Addison-Wesley,1979).
ofIntemational
Anarchy,self-help,and intersubjectiveknowledge
Waltz definespoliticalstructure on threedimensions:orderingprinciples(in
thiscase, anarchy),principlesof differentiation (whichhere dropout), and the
distributionof capabilities.19
By itself,thisdefinitionpredictslittleabout state
behavior.It does not predictwhethertwo stateswill be friendsor foes,will
recognizeeach other'ssovereignty, willhave dynasticties,willbe revisionistor
status quo powers, and so on. These factors,which are fundamentally
intersubjective,affectstates' securityinterestsand thusthe characterof their
interactionunderanarchy.In an importantrevisionofWaltz's theory,Stephen
Waltimpliesas muchwhenhe arguesthatthe"balance ofthreats,"ratherthan
the balance of power, determinesstate action, threatsbeing socially con-
structed.20Put more generally,withoutassumptionsabout the structureof
identitiesand interestsin the system,Waltz's definitionof structurecannot
predictthe contentor dynamicsof anarchy.Self-helpis one such intersubjec-
tivestructureand, as such,does the decisiveexplanatoryworkin the theory.
The questionis whetherself-helpis a logicalor contingentfeatureof anarchy.
In thissection,I develop the conceptof a "structureof identityand interest"
and showthatno particularone followslogicallyfromanarchy.
A fundamentalprincipleof constructivist social theoryis that people act
towardobjects,includingotheractors,on the basis of the meaningsthatthe
withthecommunity
states'identification varies,fromthelimitedformfoundin
"concerts"to thefull-blown formseen in "collectivesecurity"arrangements.34
Dependingon howwell developedthe collectiveselfis, itwillproducesecurity
practices that are in varyingdegrees altruisticor prosocial. This makes
collectiveaction less dependent on the presence of active threatsand less
prone to free riding.35 Moreover, it restructureseffortsto advance one's
objectives,or "power politics,"in termsof shared normsratherthan relative
power.36
On this view, the tendencyin internationalrelationsscholarshipto view
power and institutionsas two opposing explanationsof foreignpolicy is
thereforemisleading,since anarchyand the distribution of power onlyhave
meaningforstateactionin virtueof the understandings and expectationsthat
constituteinstitutionalidentitiesand interests.Self-helpis one suchinstitution,
constituting one kind of anarchybut not the only kind. Waltz's three-part
definitionof structurethereforeseems underspecified.In order to go from
structureto action,we need to add a fourth:the intersubjectively constituted
structure ofidentitiesand interestsin thesystem.
This has an importantimplicationforthewayinwhichwe conceiveof states
in the state of naturebeforetheirfirstencounterwitheach other.Because
statesdo not have conceptionsof self and other,and thus securityinterests,
apart fromor priorto interaction,we assume too much about the state of
nature if we concur with Waltz that, in virtue of anarchy,"international
political systems,like economic markets,are formedby the coaction of
self-regardingunits."37We also assume too muchifwe argue that,in virtueof
38. See Waltz,Man, theState,and War; and Robert Jervis,"Cooperation Under the Security
Dilemma," WorldPolitics30 (January1978),pp. 167-214.
39. My argumenthere parallels Rousseau's critiqueof Hobbes. For an excellentcritiqueof
realistappropriationsof Rousseau, see Michael Williams,"Rousseau, Realism,and Realpolitik,"
Millennium18 (Summer1989), pp. 188-204. Williamsargues thatfarfrombeing a fundamental
startingpointin the stateof nature,forRousseau the staghuntrepresenteda stage in man's fall.
On p. 190,WilliamscitesRousseau's descriptionofman priorto leavingthestateof nature:"Man
onlyknowshimself;he does not see his own well-beingto be identifiedwithor contraryto thatof
anyoneelse; he neitherhates anythingnor loves anything; but limitedto no more than physical
he is no one, he is an animal."For anothercritiqueof Hobbes on the stateof naturethat
instinct,
parallelsmyconstructivist readingof anarchy,see Charles Landesman,"Reflectionson Hobbes:
Anarchyand Human Nature,"in Peter Caws, ed., The Causes of Quarrel(Boston: Beacon, 1989),
pp. 139-48.
40. Empirically,this suggestionis problematic,since the process of decolonizationand the
subsequentsupportofmanyThirdWorldstatesbyinternational societypointto waysinwhicheven
the raw materialof "empiricalstatehood" is constitutedby the societyof states. See Robert
Jacksonand Carl Rosberg,"WhyAfrica'sWeak StatesPersist:The Empiricaland theJuridicalin
Statehood,"WorldPolitics35 (October 1982),pp. 1-24.
INSTITUTIONS PROCESS
of
(2) StatesA's definition |
l the situationl
Intersubjective
and
understandings (3) StateA's action
expectations
possessed
{
ofA andB
byandconstitutive
\ ~~~(4)
State B's interpretation
\ ~~~of
A's action and
it of
B's owndefinition
\/ the situation
StateB withidentities \l
andinterests (5) StateB's action
FIGURE 1. ofinstitutions
Thecodetermination andprocess
59. On the "maturity"of anarchies,see BarryBuzan, People, States,and Fear (Chapel Hill:
University ofNorthCarolinaPress,1983).
60. A similarintuitionmaylie behindAshley'seffort to reappropriateclassicalrealistdiscourse
for criticalinternationalrelationstheory.See Richard Ashley,"Political Realism and Human
Interests,"International
StudiesQuarterly38 (June1981),pp. 204-36.
Institutionaltransformations
ofpowerpolitics
possiblein self-help
systems. The realistmightconcedethatsuchsystems are
sociallyconstructedandstillarguethatafterthecorresponding identities
and
interestshavebecomeinstitutionalized, theyare almostimpossible to trans-
form.
In theremainder ofthisarticle,I examinethreeinstitutional
transformations
ofidentityandsecurityinterest through whichstatesmight escapea Hobbesian
worldoftheirownmaking. In so doing,I seekto clarify
whatitmeansto say
that"institutions
transform identities andinterests,"emphasizingthatthekey
tosuchtransformations is relativelystablepractice.
Sovereignty,recognition,and security
In a Hobbesianstateof nature,statesare individuated by the domestic
processesthatconstitutethemas statesandbytheirmaterial capacity to deter
threatsfromotherstates.In thisworld,eveniffreemomentarily fromthe
predations ofothers,statesecuritydoes nothaveanybasisin socialrecogni-
tion-in intersubjective
understandings ornormsthata statehas a right to its
existence,territory,and subjects.Securityis a matterof nationalpower,
nothingmore.
The principle ofsovereignty transforms thissituationbyproviding a social
basisfortheindividuality and securityofstates.Sovereignty is an institution,
and so it existsonlyin virtueof certainintersubjective understandings and
expectations;thereis no sovereigntywithout an other.Theseunderstandings
andexpectations notonlyconstitutea particular kindofstate-the"sovereign"
state-butalso constitute a particular
formofcommunity, sinceidentitiesare
relational.The essenceof thiscommunity is a mutualrecognition of one
another'srightto exerciseexclusive
politicalauthoritywithin territoriallimits.
Thesereciprocal "permissions"68constitutea spatially
ratherthanfunctionally
differentiatedworld-a worldin whichfieldsof practiceconstitute and are
organizedaround"domestic"and "international" spacesratherthanaround
the performance of particularactivities.69
The locationof the boundaries
betweenthesespacesis ofcoursesometimes contested,warbeingonepractice
through whichstatesnegotiatethetermsoftheirindividuality. Butthisdoes
notchangethefactthatitisonlyinvirtue ofmutualrecognition thatstateshave
87. See Mead, Mind, Self and Society.For useful discussions of this distinctionand its
implicationsfor notions of creativityin social systems,see George Cronk, The Philosophical
Anthropology of GeorgeHerbertMead (New York: Peter Lang, 1987), pp. 36-40; and Howard,
"From ChangingSelves TowardChangingSociety."
88. Turner,"Role-Taking."
89. On "characterplanning,"see JonElster,SourGrapes:StudiesintheSubversion ofRationality
(Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press, 1983), p. 117. For otherapproachesto the problemof
change,see HarryFrankfurt,
self-initiated "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,"
JoumalofPhilosophy 68 (January1971),pp. 5-20; AmartyaSen, "Rational Fools: A Critiqueofthe
BehavioralFoundationsofEconomicTheory,"Philosophy and PublicAffairs
6 (Summer1977), pp.
317-44; and Thomas Schelling,"The IntimateContestforSelf-Command,"ThePublicInterest 60
(Summer1980), pp. 94-118.
Thinkingembodiessuchcriticaltheorizing.Gorbachevwantsto freetheSoviet
Union fromthe coercivesocial logic of the cold war and engage the West in
far-reaching cooperation.Toward thisend, he has rejectedthe Leninistbelief
in the inherentconflictof interestbetweensocialistand capitaliststatesand,
perhapsmoreimportant, has recognizedthe crucialrole thatSovietaggressive
practicesplayedin sustainingthatconflict.
Such rethinking paves the way for a thirdstage of new practice.In most
cases, itis notenoughto rethinkone's ownideas aboutselfand other,sinceold
identitieshave been sustainedby systemsof interactionwithother actors,the
practicesofwhichremaina social factforthetransformative agent.In orderto
changetheself,then,itis oftennecessaryto changetheidentitiesand interests
of the othersthat help sustainthose systemsof interaction.The vehicle for
inducingsuch change is one's own practiceand, in particular,the practiceof
"altercasting"-a techniqueof interactorcontrolin whichego uses tacticsof
self-presentationand stage managementin an attempt to frame alter's
definitions of social situationsin waysthatcreate the role whichego desires
alterto play.95 In effect,in altercasting
ego triesto inducealterto takeon a new
identity (and therebyenlistalterin ego's effort to changeitself)bytreatingalter
as ifit alreadyhad that identity.The logic of this followsdirectlyfromthe
mirrortheoryof identity-formation, in whichalter'sidentityis a reflectionof
ego's practices; change those practices and ego begins to change alter's
conceptionofitself.
What these practicesshould consistof depends on the logic by whichthe
preexistingidentitieswere sustained. Competitivesecuritysystemsare sus-
tainedbypracticesthatcreateinsecurity and distrust.In thiscase, transforma-
tivepracticesshould attemptto teach otherstatesthatone's own statecan be
trustedand shouldnotbe viewedas a threatto theirsecurity. The fastestwayto
do this is to make unilateral initiativesand self-bindingcommitmentsof
sufficient significancethat another state is faced with "an offerit cannot
refuse."96 Gorbachevhas triedto do thisbywithdrawing fromAfghanistan and
Eastern Europe, implementing asymmetric cuts in nuclear and conventional
forces,callingfor"defensivedefense,"and so on. In addition,he has skillfully
cast the West in the role of beingmorallyrequiredto giveaid and comfortto
the Soviet Union, has emphasized the bonds of commonfate between the
Soviet Union and the West, and has indicated that furtherprogress in
95. See Goffman,The Presentationof Self in EverydayLife; Eugene Weinstein and Paul
Deutschberger,"Some Dimensionsof Altercasting," Sociometry 26 (December 1963), pp. 454-66;
and WalterEarle, "InternationalRelations and the Psychologyof Control:AlternativeControl
Strategiesand TheirConsequences,"PoliticalPsychology 7 (June1986),pp. 369-75.
96. See Volker Boge and Peter Wilke,"Peace Movementsand UnilateralDisarmament:Old
Conceptsin a New Light,"ArmsControl7 (September1986), pp. 156-70; Zeev Maoz and Daniel
Felsenthal,"Self-BindingCommitments, the Inducementof Trust,Social Choice, and theTheory
of InternationalCooperation,"IntemationalStudiesQuarterly 31 (June1987), pp. 177-200; and V.
Sakamoto,"UnilateralInitiativeas an AlternativeStrategy,"WorldFutures,vol. 24, nos. 1-4, 1987,
pp. 107-34.
Conclusion