Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

What Is Research Ethics

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 4

What is Research Ethics?

Research that involves human subjects or participants raises unique and complex ethical, legal,
social and political issues. Research ethics is specifically interested in the analysis of ethical
issues that are raised when people are involved as participants in research. There are three
objectives in research ethics. Thefirst and broadest objective is to protect human participants.
The second objective is to ensure that research is conducted in a way that serves interests of
individuals, groups and/or society as a whole. Finally, the third objective is to examine specific
research activities and projects for their ethical soundness, looking at issues such as the
management of risk, protection of confidentiality and the process of informed consent.
For the most part, research ethics has traditionally focused on issues in biomedical research. The
application of research ethics to examine and evaluate biomedical research has been well
developed over the last century and has influenced much of the existing statutes and guidelines
for the ethical conduct of research. However in humanities and social science research, different
kinds of ethical issues arise. New and emerging methods of conducting research, such as auto-
ethnography and participatory action research raise important but markedly different ethical
issues and obligations for researchers.
Research involving vulnerable persons, which may include children, persons with developmental
or cognitive disabilities, persons who are institutionalized, the homeless or those without legal
status, also raises unique issues in any research context.
Research ethicists everywhere today are challenged by issues that reflect global concerns in other
domains, such as the conduct of research in developing countries, the limits of research involving
genetic material and the protection of privacy in light of advances in technology and Internet
capabilities.

Components of Research Ethics


Principle One: Minimizing the risk of harm
Dissertation research should not harm participants. Where there is the possibility that participants
could be harmed or put in a position of discomfort, there must be strong justifications for this.
Such scenarios will also require (a) additional planning to illustrate how participant harm (or
discomfort) will be reduced, (b) informed consent, and (c) detailed debriefing.
There are a number of types of harm that participants can be subjected to. These include:
Physical harm to participants.
Psychological distress and discomfort.
Social disadvantage.
Harm to participants? financial status.
An invasion of participants? privacy and anonymity.
Typically, it is not harm that we need to think about since a researcher does not intentionally go
out to cause harm. Rather, it is the risk of harm that you should try to minimise. In order to
minimising the risk of harm you should think about:
Obtaining informed consent from participants.
Protecting the anonymity and confidentiality of participants.
Avoiding deceptive practices when designing your research.
Providing participants with the right to withdraw from your research at any time.
We discuss each of these ethical principles in the sections that follow, explaining (a) what they
mean and (b) instances where they should (and should not) be followed.

Principle Two: Obtaining informed consent


One of the foundations of research ethics is the idea of informed consent. Simply put, informed
consent means that participants should understand that (a) they are taking part in research
and (b) what the research requires of them. Such information may include the purpose of the
research, the methods being used, the possible outcomes of the research, as well as associated
demands, discomforts, inconveniences and risks that the participants may face. Whilst is it not
possible to know exactly what information a potential participant would (or would not) want to
know, you should aim not to leave out any material information; that is, information that you feel
would influence whether consent would (or would not) be granted.
Another component of informed consent is the principle that participants should be volunteers,
taking part without having been coerced and deceived. Where informed consent cannot be
obtained from participants, you must explain why this is the case. You should also be aware that
there are instances informed consent is not necessarily needed or needs to be relaxed. These
include certain educational, organisational and naturalistic research settings. We discuss these in
more detail under the section: Avoiding deceptive practices.

Principle Three: Protecting anonymity and confidentiality


Protecting the anonymity and confidentiality of research participants is another practical
component of research ethics. After all, participants will typically only be willing
to volunteer information, especially information of a private or sensitive nature, if the researcher
agrees to hold such information in confidence. Whilst it is possible that research participants may
be hurt in some way if the data collection methods used are somehow insensitive, there is
perhaps a greater danger that harm can be caused once data has been collected. This occurs when
data is not treated confidentially, whether in terms of the storage of data, its analysis, or during
the publication process (i.e., when submitting your dissertation to be marked). However, this
does not mean that all data collected from research participants needs to be kept confidential or
anonymous. It may be possible to disclose the identity and views of individuals at various stages
of the research process (from data collection through to publication of your dissertation).
Nonetheless, permissions should be sought before such confidential information is disclosed.
An alternative is to remove identifiers (e.g., vernacular terms, names, geographical cues, etc.) or
provide proxies when writing up. However, such a stripping of identifiable information may not
always be possible to anticipate at the outset of your dissertation when thinking about issues of
research ethics. This is not only a consideration for dissertations following a qualitative research
design, but also a quantitative research design [for more information, see the article: Research
strategy and research ethics].

Principle Four: Avoiding deceptive pratices


At first sight, deceptive practices fly in the face of informed consent. After all, how can
participants know (a) that they are taking part in research and (b) what the research requires of
them if they are being deceived? This is part of what makes the use of deceptive practices
controversial. For this reason, in most circumstances, dissertation research should avoid any
kinds of deceptive practices. However, this is not always the case.
Deception is sometimes a necessary component of covert research, which can be justified in
some cases. Covert researchreflects research where (a) the identity of the
observer and/or (b) the purpose of the research is not known to participants. Cases where you
may choose to engage in covert research may include instances where:
It is not feasible to let everyone in a particular research setting know what you are doing.
Overt observation or knowledge of the purpose of the research may alter the particular
phenomenon that is being studied.
Let's take each of these in turn:
It is not feasible to let everyone in a particular research setting know what you are doing
By feasibility, we are not talking about the cost of doing research. Instead, we mean that it is
not practically possible to let everyone in a particular research setting know what you are doing.
This is most likely to be the case where research involves observation, rather than direct
contact with participants, especially in a public or online setting. There are a number of obvious
instances where this may be the case:
Observing what users are doing in an Internet chat room.
Observing individuals going about their business (e.g., shopping, going to work, etc.).
Clearly, in these cases, where individuals are coming and going, it may simply be impossible to
let everyone known what you are doing. You may not be intentionally trying to engage
in deceptive practices, but clearly participants are not giving you their informed consent.
Overt observation or knowledge of the purpose of the research may alter the particular
phenomenon that is being studied
Where observations or a participants? knowledge of the true purpose of the research have the
potential to alter the particular phenomenon that you are interested in, this is a major concern in
terms of the quality of your findings.
Therefore, when you think about whether to engage in covert research and possibly deceptive
practices, you should think about the extent to which this could be beneficial in your dissertation,
not research in general; that is, everything from the research paradigm that guides your
dissertation through to the data analysis techniques you choose affect issues of research ethics in
your dissertation [see the article: Research strategy and research ethics].

Principle Five: Providing the Right to Withdraw


With the exception of those instances of covert observation where is not feasible to let everyone
that is being observed know what you are doing, research participants should always have
the right to withdraw from the research process. Furthermore, participants should have the right
to withdraw at any stage in the research process. When a participant chooses to withdraw from
the research process, they should not be pressured or coerced in any way to try and stop them
from withdrawing.
If your supervisor and/or Ethics Committee expect you to complete an Ethics Consent Form, it is
likely that you will have to let participants know that they have the right to withdraw at any time
[see the article: Ethics consent form].

Scenario about Violated Research Ethics


 You fabricate ideas
 You plagriazed ideas
 You use idea as a weapon for norms
 You use your statistics wrong

You might also like