MethodologyPoliticalTheory PDF
MethodologyPoliticalTheory PDF
MethodologyPoliticalTheory PDF
Political theory is a long-established field. Its questions have animated thinkers since
Classical Antiquity. Consequently, the methods of theorizing and substantive
conclusions are diverse. In this article, we review the methodology of a core branch of
contemporary political theory: the one commonly described as “analytic” political
theory.
Given space constraints, we are not able to cover the history of political thought, the
study of ideologies, the comparative study of political thought across cultures, and
“continental” political theory, including “hermeneutic”, “post-structuralist”, and
“post-modernist” approaches (for a more comprehensive discussion, see Leopold and
Stears 2008). Nonetheless, the label “analytic” should not be interpreted narrowly. It
is meant to refer to an argument-based and issue-oriented, rather than thinker-based
and exegetical, approach that emphasizes logical rigour, terminological precision, and
clear exposition. The term “analytic” is not intended to refer only to the logical and
linguistic traditions of philosophy associated with the Vienna Circle and philosophers
in Oxford and Cambridge in the first half of the 20th century. Contemporary analytic
political theory goes well beyond conceptual analysis. At least since the publication of
*
We are most grateful to Kimberley Brownlee, Emanuela Ceva, Johannes Himmelreich, Mathias
Koenig-Archibugi, Joseph Mazor, Florian Ostmann, Mike Otsuka, Miriam Ronzoni, and Kai
Spiekermann for extensive and helpful written comments.
2
One clarification about the nature of this review is needed. Although we cover
established ground, we do so from an angle that will be somewhat unfamiliar to at
least some political theorists – namely an angle inspired by the philosophy of science.
We have chosen this angle with a view to systematizing the activity of analytic
political theorizing so as to make its connections with other fields of philosophy and
positive science more transparent. This seems appropriate in the context of a
handbook on philosophical methodology.
To demarcate the scope of political theory, it is helpful to distinguish it from its most
closely related neighbouring fields: political science, moral philosophy, legal theory,
normative economics, and social ontology. We also offer some comments on the use
of the label “political theory”, as opposed to “political philosophy”.
Political theory can easily be distinguished from (positive) political science. Political
science addresses empirical and positive questions concerning politics and society
(for an overview, see Goodin 2009). It seeks to describe and explain actual political
phenomena, such as elections and electoral systems, voter behaviour, political-
opinion formation, legislative and governmental behaviour, the interaction between
the legislative, executive, and judicial branches of the state, and the stability or
instability of different forms of government. Political theory, by contrast, addresses
conceptual, normative, and evaluative questions, such as what a democracy is, how
we ought to organize our political systems, and how to evaluate the desirability of
policies.
Political theory and political science can complement each other. Normative
recommendations and evaluations of policies or institutional arrangements often rest
on empirical premises. It is hard to arrive at a blueprint for a just society, for example,
without understanding how society actually works, since normative recommendations
may have to respect feasibility constraints (e.g., Gilabert and Lawford-Smith 2012).
Thus political theory requires political science and the social sciences more generally.
Similarly, when political scientists investigate, for instance, whether democracy
promotes economic development or whether free societies are more politically stable
and less corrupt than unfree ones, they need to know what counts as a democracy or
how to define freedom. These questions require the conceptual input of political
theorists. Finally, among the large number of empirical questions that political
3
scientists could investigate, some are undoubtedly more interesting, relevant, and
pressing than others, and political theory can help shape the research agenda.
While there is a natural division of labour between political theory and political
science, the distinction between political theory and moral philosophy is subtler.
Some scholars view political theory as a subfield of moral philosophy, in which the
concepts and principles from moral philosophy are applied to political – and, more
broadly, social – problems. If one views political theory in this way but also does not
want it to collapse completely into moral philosophy, one must give a clear criterion
of when a problem counts as “political”.
Consider, for instance, gender relations in civic life or in the workplace, which many
people regard as a political issue. The question of whether, and how, a distinction
between the private or personal domain and the political or social one can be
meaningfully drawn is controversial. Some feminist thinkers have famously
challenged the possibility of drawing any such distinction and have endorsed the
slogan “the personal is political” (for an overview, see Baehr 2013). In sum, if one
wanted to distinguish political theory from moral philosophy by referring solely to the
substantive domain of problems addressed, one could at best use some heuristic
criterion to capture a conventional distinction, but this would yield no principled line.
Another way to distinguish political theory from moral philosophy is to invoke the
conditions of theorizing in each field. The aim of moral theorizing, one might say, is
to come up with the correct solution to any given moral problem simpliciter – the
solution that, based on the theorist’s comprehensive moral view, is right. The aim of
political theory, one might argue, is different. The political theorist, at least under
modern conditions, is engaged in problem solving under a particular constraint: the
presence of pluralism and disagreement about how to solve the problem at hand (see
Rawls 1996; Waldron 1999). Thus any compelling solution to the problems of
political theory, such as how to define justice or how to design a legitimate procedure
for collective decision-making, must appeal to people with a variety of (reasonable)
viewpoints, precisely because those solutions are meant to apply to, and be acceptable
in, pluralistic societies.
We now turn to the relationship between political theory and legal theory. The two
overlap, and it is difficult to draw a sharp distinction between them. We might again
arrive at a rough distinction by using some heuristic criterion to identify what counts
as “legal” or “related to the law”. As with the attempt to distinguish the “political”
from the “private” or “personal”, however, we cannot expect any such criterion to
yield a definitive distinction.
More generally, one might say that the deontic concepts used in legal theory, such as
legal permissibility, legal rights, and legal obligations, are different from their
counterparts in political or moral theory and therefore require a different analysis.1
Still, political theory and legal theory are best seen as overlapping fields of enquiry.
Political theory also overlaps with normative economics, especially with social choice
and welfare theory. Social choice and welfare theory is the formal, but also normative
and evaluative, study of (i) collective decision-making procedures, (ii) mechanisms
for allocating benefits and burdens in society, and (iii) methods by which a social
planner, policy maker, or institutional designer can assess the goodness or desirability
of different social states, policies, or institutions. Normative economists investigate
these – (i), (ii), and (iii) – by introducing desiderata that any reasonable procedure,
mechanism, or method is required to satisfy and then asking which procedures,
mechanisms, or methods, if any, satisfy the given desiderata. (For a survey, see List
2013.)
The substantive questions addressed in social choice and welfare theory are similar to
some of those addressed in political theory. For example, questions such as how to
distribute benefits and burdens are addressed by political theorists and normative
economists alike. Indeed, Rawls’s Theory of Justice was, in part, influenced by the
normative works of economists such as Kenneth Arrow (1951), John Harsanyi (1955),
and Amartya Sen (1970). Similarly, normative economists frequently draw on moral
and political theory. For example, John Roemer’s (1998) formal work on distributive
1
Of course, even within legal theory, one can distinguish between what is legally permissible
according to a specific set of laws (e.g., those of a particular country) and what the standard of legal
permissibility should be.
5
justice is influenced by G. A. Cohen’s (1995) work in political theory; and the work
on variable-population social choice by Charles Blackorby, Walter Bossert, and
David Donaldson (2005) is influenced by Derek Parfit’s (1984) work on population
ethics.
Arguably, the main difference between political theory and social choice and welfare
theory is not a substantive one (although the former is broader than the latter), but a
methodological one. Mainstream political theory is a non-formal discipline, making at
most limited use of formal methods from mathematics, logic, and economics, while
social choice and welfare theory is predominantly formal.
A less well-known but growing field in the neighbourhood of political theory is social
ontology. Social ontology investigates the nature of phenomena such as joint
intentions, collective actions, social norms and conventions, group agency, and
institutions (e.g., Gilbert 1989; Pettit 1993; Searle 1995; Bratman 1999; Tollefsen
2002; Tuomela 2007; List and Pettit 2011). Its central question, roughly speaking, is:
What are the building blocks of the social world, and how are they related to one
another, to the individuals involved, and to the physical world?
The substantive questions in social ontology are distinct from those in political theory
and in some respects prior to them. Social ontology is primarily a positive and
explanatory field rather than a normative or evaluative one. Its relevance to political
theory lies in the fact that political theory cannot get off the ground unless we are
clear about what entities and properties exist in the social world. For example, before
we can answer questions about rights, obligations, and responsibilities, we need to
know what entities can be the bearers of rights, obligations, and responsibilities. Are
these restricted to individuals, or do they also include certain collectives? Should we
regard the state as an agent, as a mere collection of individuals, or as some kind of
special fiction? Similarly, before we can answer the question of what is or is not
socially desirable, we need to know what the possible objects of value might be. It is
difficult to determine, for instance, whether there should be any cultural rights or state
subsidies for cultural activities unless we can give at least a partial answer to the
question of what we mean by “culture”.
Although some scholars distinguish between political theory and political philosophy,
this is mainly a conventional distinction. It refers, roughly, to the different styles of
political theory conducted in political science and philosophy departments,
respectively, especially in North America. (In the UK, much of what is conventionally
called “political philosophy” is traditionally conducted in political science
departments.) Arguably, “political theory” is the slightly more inclusive and
interdisciplinary label, referring not only to philosophical work but also to a variety of
6
The analysis of political concepts is relevant not only to normative theory building
(e.g., any theory of liberalism must employ some concept of liberty) but also, as
already noted, to positive work in political science. Thus conceptual analysis is, in
some sense, the least normative or evaluative part of political theory.
Of course, when we analyze concepts such as freedom and democracy, we are usually
interested in the kinds of freedom and democracy that we find valuable or
normatively required. Hence the ultimate motivation for our analysis may well be a
normative or evaluative one: we may wish to clarify these concepts in order to
express normative or evaluative principles in terms of them. Logically, however, the
question of how to understand freedom and democracy is distinct from the question of
whether freedom and democracy so understood are valuable. Indeed, political
scientists may sometimes be interested primarily in whether freedom or democracy
can serve as independent variables in explanations of political phenomena (e.g., when
they investigate whether freedom promotes prosperity or whether democracies are
less prone to fighting wars against one another), irrespective of any considerations of
value.3 In this section, we introduce some key ideas relevant to the analysis of
political concepts.
2
For a classic work on political concepts, see Oppenheim (1981).
3
Of course, political scientists may also consider freedom or democracy as dependent variables, such
as when they ask which social and economic conditions promote each. Think, for instance, of the
literature on the transition to, and consolidation of, democracy (e.g., Linz and Stepan 1996). In such
studies, considerations of value may plausibly affect our choice of interpretation of the relevant
concepts.
4
We here cannot discuss the ontological status of concepts, on which there are several rival views in
philosophy. Instead, we rely on a relatively simple characterization of concepts, emphasizing the fact
that we use concepts to categorize or classify objects and that they serve as ingredients in the activity of
political theorizing. For a broader discussion of concepts as the constituents of thoughts, see Margolis
and Laurence (2012). For a cognitive-science treatment of concepts as locations or regions within
“conceptual spaces”, see Gärdenfors (2000).
7
For the purposes of this article, we assume that any concept has a domain of
application. This is the set of objects of which it is meaningful to ask whether they
fall under the given concept or not. We might say, for example, that the domain of the
concept democracy is the set of all systems of government or decision-making. For
any object in that set – i.e., any system of government or decision-making – we can
meaningfully ask whether it is democratic or not. By contrast, for objects outside that
domain, it is not meaningful to ask whether they are democratic or not. It makes no
sense to ask, for instance, whether an equilateral triangle or a mountain is democratic
or not (cf. Dworkin 1986, 75). Note that the domain of the concept democracy – or
justice, or freedom, and so on – can be variously specified; we return to that point
below.
Philosophers are divided over the extent to which concepts in general have defining
conditions (for a review, see, e.g., Margolis and Laurence 2012). Many of our
common-sense concepts arguably lack such conditions. We may be able to pick out
some paradigm instances (or “prototypes”) of redness or beauty, but may be unable to
arrive at clear-cut necessary and sufficient conditions that an object must satisfy to be
red or beautiful (for a related discussion, see Dworkin 1986, chap. 2). By contrast, in
theoretical work, it is usually desirable to look for concepts with defining conditions.
Occasionally, however, some theoretical concepts may be regarded as undefined
“primitives” or as characterizable only through “prototypes”.
Finally, a concept’s extension is the subset of the domain consisting of precisely those
objects that fall under the concept (“that satisfy it”). If the concept has defining
conditions, these determine the extension. The extension of the concept democracy is
the set of all those systems of government or decision-making that, according to the
concept, count as democratic. More generally, there can be “non-binary” concepts,
which do not subdivide objects into those falling under the concept and those not
falling under it, but which instead classify objects on one or several dimensions that
may each admit of degrees. For example, equality and welfare are non-binary
concepts. The level of equality or inequality in a particular distribution of goods is a
matter of degree, and different interpretations of equality give us different accounts of
when one distribution counts as more equal than another (see, e.g., Sen 1980).
Similarly, a person’s welfare is a matter of degree and, on some accounts, even given
by a vector of multiple attributes, representing different dimensions or aspects of
welfare. Sen (1987) has argued for the “constitutive plurality” of the concept standard
of living; there are multiple dimensions on which a person’s standard of living can be
categorized.
For practically any salient concept in political theory, there are debates about what the
domain of application is, what the defining conditions, if any, are, and which objects
belong to the concept’s extension and which do not. Just think of the many different
8
ways in which the concept democracy may be understood. The domain of application
may be specified in a variety of ways: for example, as a set of voting procedures, as a
set of decisions, or as a set of entire political systems. Similarly, we may be divided
over the defining conditions that determine whether something is democratic or not:
for example, do only formal, constitutional features of the political system matter, or
are features of actual political practices relevant as well, and if so, how? And is
democracy precisely definable at all? In consequence, we may end up with different
extensions of the concept democracy (see, e.g., Christiano 2008; List 2011). Similar
considerations also hold for other key political concepts, such as justice, freedom,
equality, and legitimacy. Indeed, many political concepts are what political theorists
call “essentially contested” (Gallie 1955).
Political theorists, following Rawls, who in turn follows H.L.A. Hart, sometimes
distinguish between concepts and conceptions (Rawls 1971/1999, 5). Concepts, in
that terminology, are less fully specified than conceptions. For example, we may have
a broadly outlined concept of freedom as the absence of constraints on agents’
actions, which still leaves open what kinds of constraints, agents, and actions matter
(MacCallum 1967). A full specification of those constraints, agents, and actions
yields a precise conception of freedom. Different conceptions can thus be compatible
with the same broad concept.
We can translate the distinction between concepts and conceptions into our earlier
terminology by defining a conception exactly as we defined a concept in the last
section, where the domain, defining conditions (if any), and extension are fully
specified, and redefining a concept as a broader family of such conceptions, with
some aspects of the domain, defining conditions, or extension left open.
Having defining conditions that are neither too “thick” nor too “thin”: Even when
we have settled the domain of a given concept (e.g., we focus on a concept of freedom
whose domain is a set of acts, as opposed to a set of agents or institutional
arrangements), we might still be divided over the concept’s defining conditions. In the
case of freedom, a huge variety of different defining conditions have been proposed
(for overviews, see Carter 2012; Lovett 2013). To narrow down the range of
possibilities, we might require that the defining conditions be neither too “thick”, nor
too “thin”: they should not refer to any “irrelevant” facts about the objects to be
categorized, but refer to all “relevant” facts. There can then be debates about which
facts are or are not relevant and what counts as too “thick” or too “thin”. For example,
a concept is moralized if its defining conditions refer to some normative or evaluative
facts. A concept is non-moralized otherwise.5 Nozick’s above-mentioned concept of
freedom as the absence of rights-violating interference is moralized in this sense.
Political theorists are often divided over which concepts in political theory should be
moralized. Similarly, a concept is modally demanding if its defining conditions refer
not only to facts about the actual world but also to facts about other possible worlds –
i.e., facts about what would be or might be, not merely about what is. A concept is
modally undemanding otherwise. Pettit, for instance, argues that freedom is modally
demanding: a slave with a benevolent, non-interfering master still counts as unfree,
because there is a nearby possible world in which the master interferes (Pettit 1997).
Similarly, concepts such as security and peace are arguably modally demanding,
referring not only to the absence of relevant harmful actions or military conflicts in
5
The definition of moralized and non-moralized concepts requires suitable adjustments if there are no
evaluative or normative facts.
10
the actual world but also their continued absence in a range of nearby possible worlds.
Political theorists are divided over which, if any, concepts should be modally
demanding (see, e.g., Pettit 2011; Southwood 2013).
Concepts should not be confused with principles or theories – the topic of Sections 3
and 4. In particular, principles and theories have propositional content and may be
true or false, while concepts, by themselves, cannot be true or false. They only
categorize objects and, in doing so, can be more or less useful, more or less plausible,
and more or less in line with established use or with our considered judgments.6 To
give a simple illustration from outside political theory, the concepts red, green, or
triangular are neither true nor false. Only statements in which they occur can have
truth-values, such as “tomatoes are red” (true), “snow is green” (false), and
“rectangles are triangular” (false).
Still, people sometimes say things such as “freedom as non-interference is the true
conception of freedom”. Assertions of this kind are best interpreted as abbreviations
for claims such as “freedom as non-interference is the conception of freedom that is,
in some relevant sense, most appropriate”, which, in turn, could mean that it best
captures our established use of freedom or alternatively our considered judgments
about what counts as free. Literally, however, the claim that one concept of freedom
is the true one is not meaningful, since only things with propositional content can
have truth-values. Concepts do not have propositional content: the extension of a
6
Recall that the defining conditions of any concept simply specify when an object falls under the
concept, not whether the concept is true or false.
11
concept is not a set of possible worlds (which is what the extension of a proposition
is), but a set of objects.7
While analytic political theory until the early 1970s was primarily concerned with the
analysis of concepts, John Rawls’s Theory of Justice (1971/1999) invigorated the
quest for theories and the principles underlying them. Rawls formulated some
principles of justice, which are the basis of his theory of how we should organize the
“basic structure of society”, namely its main political, legal, and economic
institutions.
In this section, we discuss the notions of principles and theories. Although these are
widely used in political theory, they are seldom carefully defined. We hope, therefore,
that our discussion will be clarifying.
Classic examples of normative principles are the Ten Commandments from the Bible,
the Golden Rule (“You should treat other people in the way in which you would like
them to treat you”), Bentham’s principle of utility (“An action is right if it maximizes
total utility”), and more recently Rawls’s principles of justice. Roughly speaking,
these state that each person is entitled to the most extensive system of individual
7
Note that the extension of a statement or proposition is the set of those possible worlds in which the
statement or proposition is true.
12
liberties, compatible with a similar system for everyone else (the “equal-liberty
principle”); and socio-economic inequalities are permissible if and only if they are
compatible with a system of fair equal opportunities (the “fair equality of opportunity
principle”) and benefit the least well-off members of society (the “difference
principle”) (Rawls 1971/1999).
The propositional content of a principle is the set of all its implications. Sometimes
this propositional content may depend on auxiliary assumptions. As already noted,
their having propositional content sets principles apart from concepts, which merely
offer categorizations.
The word “theory” is commonly used in two distinct senses. First, it can refer to an
entire academic field or area of enquiry, such as when we speak of “political theory”
or “economic theory” as general areas to which curricula or scholarly journals are
devoted. Second, the word can refer to a specific theory within such an area, such as
Rawls’s theory of justice, the theory of the firm in economics, or Newton’s theory of
physics. Our focus here is on theories in this second, specific sense. Surprisingly,
there exists no canonical definition of a theory in that sense in political theory.
Although loose and abstract, this definition has some merits. First, it allows us to view
positive theories (in the sciences) and normative or evaluative theories (in moral
philosophy or political theory) as instances of the same general category. Second, it
makes transparent the differences between them. For example, the roles played by
theories can range from descriptive, explanatory, and predictive (in the case of
positive theories) to evaluative and prescriptive (in the case of evaluative or
normative theories). Third, the definition allows us to identify the special challenges
that arise when we construct and assess normative or evaluative theories.
8
We here follow broadly what is often called the syntactic approach to defining theories (where a
theory is defined as a set of sentences/propositions with certain properties); it is arguably the most
conventional approach. For a classic exposition, see Quine (1975). It is also worth exploring the rival
semantic approach (where a theory is defined as a set of models with certain properties), but given
space constraints, we set this aside here (see van Fraassen 1980). For an introduction to the philosophy
of science, see Okasha (2002).
13
projects as travelling to the moon and safely back. Rawls’s theory is the set of all
statements entailed by Rawls’s principles of justice, perhaps together with some
empirical premises about relevant social conditions. It can play a prescriptive or
normative role, guiding us in the design of social institutions (for an earlier discussion
of the relationship between normative and positive theories, see McDermott 2008).
For our purposes, the biggest structural difference between Newton’s and Rawls’s
theories is that one is positive and the other normative. Indeed, the principles
underlying Newton’s theory are positive principles, while those underlying Rawls’s
are normative ones. Generally, a theory is positive if it has no evaluative or normative
content; it is evaluative or normative if it has such content. Evaluative theories that
offer evaluations of “goodness” or “betterness” are also called axiological.
While Newton’s and Rawls’s theories are paradigmatic instances of our definition, a
theory need not be self-consciously theoretical. A set of rough and informal principles
describing how ordinary objects behave when pushed, dropped, or thrown can
constitute a “folk” theory of motion that is predictively useful in everyday contexts.
Similarly, a set of basic principles describing how animals respond to noise,
movement, and the presence of humans may constitute a simple predictive theory of
animal behaviour that members of hunter-gatherer societies might have used to guide
their actions. We also routinely employ normative theories without self-consciously
doing so. For example, a set of simple principles specifying how we should or should
not treat others may constitute a simple “folk” theory of personal ethics.
Our simple definition of a theory is silent on whether the theory is true, useful, or
good in some sense. A theory that is false, irrelevant, or superseded still counts as a
theory. Describing something as a theory carries no assessment of its truth or
acceptability. Thus the most far-fetched and implausible conspiracy theory – for
example, in science or in history – still qualifies as a theory.
An important distinction is that between a theory and what is offered in its support. A
theory, as we have defined it, is distinct from any arguments, evidence, or justification
given for it. For example, Newton’s actual or hypothetical experiments – such as how
an apple fell onto his head (though supposedly a myth) – are not part of his physical
theory itself; they are part of the evidence he had for that theory. Similarly, Rawls’s
14
There are two kinds of criteria that we may use to assess – especially to justify or to
criticize – principles and theories: “internal” and “external” criteria. The former
concern the way the principles or theory are formulated and their internal logical
structure. Criteria such as consistency and parsimony fall into this category. The latter
concern the relationship between the principles or theory and what these are “about”:
their normative or evaluative content, in analogy with the empirical or descriptive
content of a scientific theory. Criteria such as truth or normative adequacy (in analogy
with truth or empirical adequacy in science) fall into this second category. In this
section, we discuss the two kinds of criteria (“internal” and “external”) in turn.
Throughout this discussion, we focus on theories, rather than principles, as the units
of assessment. This is no loss of generality. We are usually interested, not in
individual principles in isolation, but in sets of principles that we wish to assess
together. If we wish to assess a principle by itself, we can view it as a special case of a
theory, namely a theory that consists just of the principle and its implications.
Although we have kept our definition of a theory deliberately thin, defining it simply
as a set of statements that may play some theoretical or practical role and that is,
ideally, derivable from some underlying principles, we usually want theories to satisfy
some further requirements. We now discuss several common criteria for assessing a
theory’s internal structure. Like our definition of a theory, they are inspired by the
sciences, but apply to normative and evaluative theories as much as they apply to
positive ones. Some of the criteria are so obvious that they are often left
unacknowledged; nonetheless, it is useful to make them explicit.
both “p” and “not p”, is of little use, whether for explanatory, predictive, evaluative,
or prescriptive purposes. By entailing everything, it is too indiscriminate.9
9
Sometimes we may be prepared to lower the bar of consistency, by admitting some “contained” or
“local” inconsistencies, as in so-called “paraconsistent” logics. Even then, we usually impose some
weakened variant of a consistency requirement, to rule out those inconsistencies that are too global to
preserve a theory’s usefulness.
10
A set of statements is deductively closed if it contains all its implications.
11
The deductive-closure requirement also highlights, once more, why consistency matters. Since an
inconsistent set of statements entails everything, deductive closure would force such a theory to consist
of everything that can be expressed in the relevant language, which would amount to a completely
uninformative theory. Again, if we were to use a paraconsistent logic, we might weaken the
requirement of deductive closure but still retain some less demanding requirement in a similar spirit.
12
See also Quine (1975). Note that any axiomatizable theory is deductively closed. Note, further, that
logicians sometimes replace the “finiteness” requirement with a weaker “formal decidability”
requirement; we set these technicalities aside.
13
Although axiomatizability of a theory in terms of some easily expressible principles is one of the
marks of parsimony, axiomatizability is not a sufficient condition for parsimony.
14
In his discussion of why his principles of justice are preferable to utilitarian principles, Rawls says
that “reasonable risk aversion may be so great, once the enormous hazards of the decision in the
16
and may also depend on what the theory is about. We usually want to find the
simplest theory able to account for its subject matter. To be illuminating, the theory
ought to be simpler, for example, than the target phenomenon it seeks to account for,
as well as simpler than its rival theories. A scientific theory, for instance, should be
simpler and more succinct than an enumeration of all the empirical facts it seeks to
explain; otherwise it cannot play any explanatory role. Likewise, a good normative
theory should be simpler than an enumeration of all case-specific normative
judgments. The relevant bar of simplicity may be adjusted depending on the theory’s
subject matter.
The present list of criteria for the internal assessment of theories is only illustrative,
not exhaustive, but given space constraints, we now move on to external criteria.
What exactly a given theory is intended to represent needs to be spelt out further. In
the case of a physical theory, the answer is relatively straightforward, especially if we
accept “scientific realism”: it is intended to represent certain physical facts about the
world, such as facts about how physical objects behave in response to each other (see,
e.g., Chakravartty 2013). In the case of a normative or evaluative theory, the picture is
more complicated. If we are realists about normative or evaluative matters, we may
say that the theory is intended to represent some theory-independent moral facts. If
we are not realists about normative or evaluative matters, it is harder to specify what a
normative or evaluative theory is intended to represent (on moral realism and anti-
realism see, respectively, Sayre-McCord 2011; Joyce 2009).
Yet the very idea of a theory breaks down unless we assume that there is something
potentially representable by it, however observer-dependent or socially constructed it
might be.15 If we were nihilists, to take an extreme example of the denial of any
normative or evaluative facts, we would not be able to engage in normative or
evaluative theorizing in earnest.
Thus, in this section, we assume that normative or evaluative theories are truth-apt: it
makes sense to ask whether they are true – or, some might prefer to say: correct or
externally valid. We thus accept a form of “cognitivism” about such theories. This
original position are fully appreciated, that the utilitarian weighting may be, for practical purposes, so
close to the difference principle as to make the simplicity of the latter ... decisive in its favour” (Rawls
1999, 144 emphasis added).
15
A constructivist might take a theory to represent certain constructed facts. This is consistent even
with the view that the theory itself is the “vehicle” by which those facts are being constructed. To
develop that view further, one might draw, for instance, on parallels with Searle’s analysis of
declarative speech acts (which – roughly – bring certain facts into existence by representing them). See
Searle (1995).
17
assumption is still compatible with a variety of views about the “meta-ethical” status
of normative or evaluative judgments. We return to some of these issues in Section 6.
Granting, then, that there is some standard of correctness by which we can assess
normative or evaluative theories (an ontological assumption), we still need to know
how to do this assessment (an epistemological question). We now review several
methods of testing a theory for external validity.
Taking intuitive judgments as strict evidence: According to this method, the test for a
normative or evaluative theory is whether it fits our intuitive judgments about the
relevant normative or evaluative matters. On this approach, our intuitive judgments
have the same status as empirical observations in science. In science, a theory is
empirically adequate if it entails the correct observation statements (see, e.g., Quine
1975; van Fraassen 1980). Similarly, in moral and political theory, we might call a
theory normatively or evaluatively adequate if it entails the correct normative or
evaluative statements. According to the strict-evidence method, these are precisely the
normative or evaluative statements supported by our intuitive judgments (cf. the
discussion in Dworkin 1975). Although simple and analogous to familiar scientific
methods, this method has some problems. First, while we may be confident in some
of our normative or evaluative judgments, other judgments may be more tentative,
and in some cases – especially when the issue is less familiar – we may not have any
firm intuitions at all. Second, our intuitive judgments may be subject to biases and
framing effects, which may cast further doubt on their reliability. Third, our
normative or evaluative judgments may not be consistent with one another, or they
may entail other judgments that we reject on reflection; in such cases, the strict-
evidence method provides no guidance at all.
sometimes speak of “narrow” reflective equilibrium in the first case, and “wide”
reflective equilibrium in the second (Daniels 2013). Similarly, we may take different
views on which kinds of judgments – especially whose judgments – should serve as
input to this method; more on this below. Although the reflective-equilibrium method
is consistent with the idea that we arrive at our normative or evaluative theories
through careful deliberation, we may be worried about the possible arbitrariness of its
outcome, since there may not always be a unique equilibrium. In some cases, we may
not be able to reach any equilibrium at all (the non-existence problem), such as when
we theorize about genuine moral dilemmas and vacillate between different theories
that each fit only some of our judgments while conflicting with others. In other cases,
there may exist more than one equilibrium, in that we can arrive at different
“packages” of revised theories and judgments that each have the required “mutual fit”
(the non-uniqueness problem). Arbitrary factors such as framing effects or the order
in which we consider different implications of the theory may then affect which
reflective equilibrium we end up with (the path-dependence problem).
Thought experiments and intuition pumps: Whether we opt for the strict-evidence
method or the reflective-equilibrium method, we may sometimes wish to sharpen or
clarify our intuitions or judgments. Thought experiments and real-world cases can
serve as useful “intuition pumps” (Dennett 2013; Brownlee and Stemplowska
forthcoming). Here, we consider some hypothetical or actual scenario that prompts
strong normative or evaluative judgments. In the much-discussed “trolley problems”,
for example, we are asked to judge what actions, if any, would be permitted to
prevent a run-away trolley from crashing into, and killing, a larger group of people, at
the expense of leading it to crash into, and kill, a smaller group (Thomson 1985). We
then use these judgments to test our relevant normative or evaluative theories,
following either the strict-evidence method or the reflective-equilibrium method. The
usefulness of intuition pumps, especially ones involving highly idealised,
counterfactual scenarios has recently been the object of considerable controversy in
political theory (Elster 2011). We return to this issue in Section 5.
The relevant judgments: Both the strict-evidence method and the reflective-
equilibrium method raise the question of which kinds of judgments, and whose
judgments, to use in testing our theories. Should we test our theories on the basis of
relatively spontaneous judgments or on the basis of suitably “filtered” judgments, and
how should that filtering take place (Rawls 1999, 42)? And should we use the
political theorist’s judgments (which might be affected by his or her ideological
views) or society’s (which might similarly be affected by biases), and in the latter
case, which society should we focus on (Miller 1992; Walzer 1983)? For example,
while the Rawls of A Theory of Justice arguably followed the former approach
(relying on the political theorist’s judgments), the Rawls of Political Liberalism
subscribed to the latter (looking at society) (Rawls 1971/1999; Rawls 1996).
Specifically, the later Rawls re-interprets his theory of justice as an articulation of the
ideas implicit in the public culture of liberal democratic societies. The building blocks
of his account of justice are explicitly “drawn” from, and supposed to be widely
acknowledged within, the society for which that account is designed. Relatedly,
political theorists disagree about whether the judgments to which they appeal in
theory testing should “fit” the particular practice the theory is meant to regulate. If the
answer to this question is positive, then the exercise of theory construction is best
seen as an attempt to offer what Ronald Dworkin calls a “constructive interpretation”
19
In political theory, as well as in other disciplines, theories are often abstract and/or
idealised in certain respects. In this section, we explain what this means and discuss
some methodological issues raised by abstraction and idealization.
Broadly following Onora O’Neill (1996, chap. 2), we say that a theory is abstract
with respect to an issue – represented by a set of statements – if it is silent on that
issue; formally, it has no implications at all for the given statements, implying neither
any of these statements nor any of their negations. Newton’s theory of physics, for
example, is abstract with respect to the colours of the physical bodies whose motion it
represents. A theory is idealized with respect to an issue – again represented by a set
16
The distinction between practice-dependence and practice-independence is complex and much
debated. Due to space constraints, we are unable to explore this complexity here.
20
Since theories are meant to simplify the world, most political theorists agree that
abstraction is virtually unavoidable in theory construction, and an innocuous
intellectual exercise (O’Neill 1996, chap. 2; see also the discussion in Stemplowska
2008). Idealization, unlike abstraction, is looked at with greater suspicion in political
theory and is considered potentially problematic (O’Neill 1996, chap. 2).
The “danger of idealization” in political theory has been discussed primarily in the
debate on “ideal versus non-ideal theory” (for an overview, see Valentini 2012). The
debate is largely animated by the worry that resort to simplifying assumptions and
idealized thought experiments or intuition pumps – which are common in
contemporary political theory – will adversely affect the validity of the ensuing
theories (see, e.g., O’Neill 1996, chap. 2; Farrelly 2007; Mills 2005). For instance,
John Rawls develops his theory of justice assuming full compliance with the resulting
principles. This makes critics wonder whether we can trust Rawls’s principles to
deliver correct and action-guiding prescriptions for the real world, where many people
fail to abide by the demands of justice.
In assessing this worry, two points are worth making. First, like abstraction, some
degree of idealization in our theories – in the form of simplifying assumptions – may
play an important, and justified, heuristic role. Again, Newton’s theory of physics
does not appear to be significantly undermined by its assuming friction away,
especially to the extent that information about friction can potentially be re-introduced
in refinements or applications of the theory. This suggests that, rather than reject
idealizations as problematic from the outset, we must ask whether a theory contains
the “right” idealizations, given its purpose (Robeyns 2008; Valentini 2009).
Second, to answer the question of which idealizations are “right” and which are not,
we need to distinguish between three possible loci – or levels – at which idealizations
can occur: (1) the theory itself, (2) the conditions of application of the theory’s
prescriptions (where those prescriptions are of the form “if such-and-such conditions
hold, then such-and-such follows”), (3) the justification of the theory. Crucially,
idealization at any one of these levels need not entail idealization at any of the others.
Rawls’s theory of justice, as described earlier, consists of the “equal liberty” (X), “fair
equality of opportunity” (Y), and “difference” (Z) principles and their implications.
The theory itself would be idealized – a level (1) idealization – if and only if these
principles entailed false statements about their subject matter – for instance, if the
statement “we ought to re-arrange the tax system so as to benefit the worst off as
much as possible” were false. Note, however, that the often-criticized “idealized”
21
assumption of full compliance is not made within the theory itself, but occurs as part
of the justification that Rawls offers for the theory. It is one of the assumptions made
by the parties in the original-position thought experiment. So, it is an idealization at
level (3). Rawls’s principles, which generate his theory, do not imply any false claims
about full compliance; hence we have no idealization at level (1) here. Nor do the
prescriptions following from these principles presuppose full compliance for their
applicability; hence we have no idealization at level (2) either (see Simmons 2010, 9–
10 for discussion).
Similarly, consider Rawls’s assumption that society exists under favourable historical
and social conditions. Relative to existing war-torn, or desperately poor countries, this
assumption is clearly false: it is an idealization. Rawls says explicitly that his
principles of justice may not apply to societies in which the relevant favourable
conditions are absent (Rawls 1999, 216). Does this make Rawls’s theory idealized –
an idealization at level (1) – and problematically so? Arguably, it does not, because
the favourable-conditions idealization operates at the level of the conditions of
application of the theory’s prescriptions, i.e., at level (2). The prescription that is
entailed by the theory (under a careful formulation) – namely “if favourable
conditions hold, justice demands X, Y, and Z” – is still true. Although the conditional
nature of this prescription limits the scope of application of the theory, it does not
make the theory itself idealized, by generating false prescriptions.
We suspect that, although worries about idealization in political theory are frequently
expressed as complaints about “theories being idealized”, they actually tend to target
idealizations at levels (2) and (3), rather than (1) – i.e., at the levels of the theories’
conditions of application and the justifications offered for those theories, not at the
level of the theories themselves.
Of course, idealizations at levels (2) and (3) often make the target-theories somewhat
irrelevant to the real world, by rendering them insufficiently action-guiding in real-
world circumstances. While this lack of guidance may be a genuine shortcoming, it is
not accurately captured by the claim that the theories themselves are idealized.
Rather, in the case of a level (2) idealization, the theories entail true prescriptions of
an “if-then” sort, whose antecedent conditions – the “if” clauses – do not hold in real-
world circumstances. And in the case of a level (3) idealization, the theories may be
insufficiently justified, in that the justifications offered for them – such as highly
contrived thought experiments – are too idealized to allow inferences for the real
world.
Our discussion highlights the importance of clarity about the role that idealizations
play in the defence and formulation of one’s theory. Consider a theory of justice
prescribing “p”, defended on the assumption that there is no reasonable disagreement
about justice within society, and yet formulated in universal terms: “justice always
demands that p”. This theory does indeed run the risk of being problematically
idealized, if it turns out that the presence of reasonable disagreement makes a morally
relevant difference to what justice demands. The theory, in that case, would have false
implications in a number of situations, namely those involving reasonable
22
disagreement. A true principle, by contrast, would only say: “if there is no reasonable
disagreement, justice demands that p”.
Yet, the difference between moral philosophy and political theory may be said to be
the following. In moral philosophy, we commonly (though not universally) make the
assumption that, among the many different rival normative or evaluative theories, one
is the independently correct or true theory. The task for the moral philosopher is to
identify that theory. If we conduct moral philosophy on this assumption, disagreement
is of a “merely” epistemic kind. There is a fact about what the right answer to any
normative or evaluative question is; we may just have different beliefs about that fact.
It is less clear – so the argument goes – whether the same assumption can be made in
political theory. On this picture, disagreement in political theory may be viewed, not
merely as “epistemic”, reflecting different beliefs about the same truth, but as partly
“constitutive” of the correctness conditions – or warranted assertability conditions –
of normative claims themselves. On this view, whether a normative or evaluative
theory in political theory is correct (or assertable) depends, in part, on the society in
which the theory is to be applied, and specifically on the level of reasonable
disagreement in that society; we define the notion of reasonableness below.
A key desideratum here is that our theories be, at least in principle, acceptable to
individuals holding reasonable but conflicting moral views within pluralistic societies.
What counts as a correct normative or evaluative principle in a society with little
reasonable disagreement need not always count as correct in a highly pluralistic
society, where the range of reasonable disagreement is greater. In light of this, some
23
theorists avoid using the notion of truth in political theory altogether, and prefer to
replace it with other, less loaded notions, like reasonableness or reasonable
acceptability (Rawls 1996; cf. J. Cohen 2009).
But what might justify the shift from the “epistemic” to the “constitutive” status of
disagreement in the political domain? At least two answers are possible. First, the
shift might be morally justified. On this view, a commitment to respect for persons
places a burden of “reasonable acceptability” on the principles put forward by the
political theorist, insofar as these principles may be permissibly enforced against
individuals, for instance through state action. The idea is that political theory focuses
on the development of “enforceable rules”, and these rules are normatively
appropriate – meet the relevant criterion of correctness – only if they are acceptable to
reasonable individuals to whom they apply.
The inspiration for many of the foregoing reflections can be found in John Rawls’s
second major book, Political Liberalism (1993/1996). We now offer a brief
discussion of Rawls’s treatment of the relevance of pluralism to political theorizing.
For example, a theory of justice that adjudicates all aspects of personal, and not just
political and social, life would be “comprehensive”, as would be a theory based on the
metaphysically loaded premise that human beings are morally equal because they are
created “in the image of God”. Both theories would be the object of reasonable
disagreement within a pluralistic society. By contrast, a theory of justice that focuses
on the basic structure of society and is based on a commitment to “citizens’ freedom
and equality” would count as “political”, since its domain does not “over-reach” and
its premises are entrenched in the public culture of liberal democracies and arguably
24
The notion of “reasonableness” is hard to pin down in general, and this is true in
Rawls’s case as well (for discussion, see Gaus 1996, 131–132; Gaus 1999). In
particular, the notion may be interpreted in epistemological and/or moral ways. Under
an epistemological interpretation, something is reasonable if it is consistent with a
proper use of reason in light of the evidence available. Rawls believes that, because of
what he calls the “burdens of judgment”, we should not expect agreement between the
views of different people, even when they are all developed by consistently applying
the powers of reason (Rawls 1996, Lecture 2, sec. 2). Under a moral interpretation,
reasonableness refers to a view’s compatibility with certain fundamental normative
requirements, such as respect for citizens as free and equal, or a commitment to
mutual justification (Rawls 1996, Lecture 2, sec. 3). This would make views that
reject such a commitment unreasonable.
from different such perspectives could not hope to gain sufficient support and to offer
a stable basis for social organization in pluralistic liberal democracies (Rawls 1996,
Lecture 4). The notion of an overlapping consensus operationalizes the idea that the
criterion of correctness of a “political” theory is its acceptability to individuals who
hold competing but reasonable comprehensive moral theories.
7. Concluding remarks
We have reviewed the methodology of analytic political theory from what we hope is
a somewhat novel and helpful angle. By drawing on ideas from the philosophy of
science, we have attempted to highlight the ways in which theorizing in political
theory relates to theorizing in other areas of philosophy and positive science. We have
also reviewed some recent debates and controversies within the political-theory
literature, which has only recently given greater attention to methodological
questions. Our hope is that this article will prove to be a clarifying contribution to the
growing methodological debate in political theory.
References
Arrow, Kenneth Joseph. 1951. Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: John
Wiley & Sons.
Baehr, Amy R. 2013. “Liberal Feminism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Winter 2013.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/feminism-liberal/.
Baker, Alan. 2013. “Simplicity.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited
by Edward N. Zalta, Fall 2013.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/simplicity/.
Blackorby, Charles, Walter Bossert, and David J. Donaldson. 2005. Population Issues
in Social Choice Theory, Welfare Economics, and Ethics. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Bratman, Michael. 1999. Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and
Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brownlee, Kimberley, and Zofia Stemplowska. forthcoming. “Trapped in an
Experience Machine with a Famous Violinist: Thought Experiments in
Normative Theory.” N/A
Carter, Ian. 2012. “Positive and Negative Liberty.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2012.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/liberty-positive-negative/.
Chakravartty, Anjan. 2013. “Scientific Realism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Summer 2013.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/scientific-realism/.
Christiano, Thomas. 2008. “Democracy.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Fall 2008.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/democracy/.
Cohen, G. A. 1988. History, Labour, and Freedom: Themes from Marx. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
———. 1995. Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
———. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
26
———. 2009. Why Not Socialism? Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Cohen, Joshua. 2009. “Truth and Public Reason.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 37 (1):
2–42.
Daniels, Norman. 2013. “Reflective Equilibrium.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Winter 2013.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/reflective-equilibrium/.
Dennett, Daniel C. 2013. Intuition Pumps And Other Tools for Thinking. New York:
W. W. Norton.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1975. “The Original Position.” In Reading Rawls: Critical Studies
on Rawls’s A Theory of Justice, edited by Norman Daniels, 16–52. Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press.
———. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Elster, Jakob. 2011. “How Outlandish Can Imaginary Cases Be?” Journal of Applied
Philosophy 28 (3): 241–258.
Fabre, Cécile. 2012. Cosmopolitan War. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Farrelly, Colin. 2007. “Justice in Ideal Theory: A Refutation.” Political Studies 55
(4): 844–864.
Gallie, W. B. 1955. “Essentially Contested Concepts.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 56 (1): 167–198.
Galston, William A. 2010. “Realism in Political Theory.” European Journal of
Political Theory 9 (4): 385–411.
Gärdenfors, Peter. 2000. Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Gaus, Gerald F. 1996. Justificatory Liberalism : An Essay on Epistemology and
Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 1999. “Reasonable Pluralism and the Domain of the Political: How the
Weaknesses of John Rawls’s Political Liberalism Can Be Overcome by a
Justificatory Liberalism.” Inquiry 42 (2): 259–284.
Gerring, John. 1999. “What Makes a Concept Good? A Criterian Framework for
Understanding Concept Formation in the Social Sciences.” Polity 31 (3): 357–
393.
Gilabert, Pablo, and Holly Lawford-Smith. 2012. “Political Feasibility: A Conceptual
Exploration.” Political Studies 60 (4): 809–825.
Gilbert, Margaret. 1989. On Social Facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Goodin, Robert E. 2009. The Oxford Handbook of Political Science. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Harsanyi, John C. 1955. “Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal
Comparisons of Utility.” Journal of Political Economy 63 (4): 309–321.
James, Aaron. 2005. “Constructing Justice for Existing Practice: Rawls and the Status
Quo.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (3): 281–316.
Joyce, Richard. 2009. “Moral Anti-Realism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Summer 2009.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/moral-anti-realism/.
Larmore, Charles. 2013. “What Is Political Philosophy?” Journal of Moral
Philosophy 10 (3): 276–306.
Leopold, David, and Marc Stears. 2008. Political Theory: Methods and Approaches.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Linz, Juan J., and Alfred Stepan. 1996. Problems of Democratic Transition and
Consolidation: Southern Europe, South America, and Post-Communist
Europe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
27
List, Christian. 2011. “The Logical Space of Democracy.” Philosophy & Public
Affairs 39 (3): 262–297.
———. 2013. “Social Choice Theory.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
edited by Edward N. Zalta, Winter 2013.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/social-choice/.
List, Christian, and Philip Pettit. 2011. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and
Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lovett, Frank. 2013. “Republicanism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
edited by Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2013.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/republicanism/.
MacCallum, Gerald C. 1967. “Negative and Positive Freedom.” The Philosophical
Review 76 (3): 312–334.
Margolis, Eric, and Stephen Laurence. 2012. “Concepts.” In The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Fall 2012.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/concepts/.
McDermott, Daniel. 2008. “Analytic Political Philosophy.” In Political Theory:
Methods and Approaches, edited by David Leopold and Marc Stears, 11–28.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Miller, David. 1992. “Distributive Justice: What the People Think.” Ethics 102 (3):
555–593.
———. 2002. “Two Ways to Think About Justice.” Politics, Philosophy &
Economics 1 (1): 5–28.
Mills, Charles W. 2005. “‘Ideal Theory’ as Ideology.” Hypatia 20 (3): 165–183.
Mouffe, Chantal. 2005. “The Limits of John Rawls’s Pluralism.” Politics, Philosophy
& Economics 4 (2): 221–231.
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.
O’Neill, Onora. 1996. Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of
Practical Reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Okasha, Samir. 2002. Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Oppenheim, Felix E. 1981. Political Concepts: A Reconstruction. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Otsuka, Michael. 2003. Libertarianism Without Inequality. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Pettit, Philip. 1993. The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and
Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 1997. Republicanism. A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
———. 2011. “The Instability of Freedom as Noninterference: The Case of Isaiah
Berlin.” Ethics 121 (4): 693–716.
Quine, W. V. 1975. “On Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World.” Erkenntnis 9
(3): 313–328.
Rawls, John. 1985. “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical.” Philosophy and
Public Affairs 14 (3): 223–251.
———. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
———. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2008. “Ideal Theory in Theory and Practice.” Social Theory and
Practice 34 (3): 341–362.
28