2012 Filosofie Internationala Subiecte 3
2012 Filosofie Internationala Subiecte 3
2012 Filosofie Internationala Subiecte 3
In this essay I will reflect on the human-nature relationship: Today, the dominating perspective
on this “dualistic” bond is characterized by approaches to nature, based upon so-called human-
centered assumptions. These approaches, which henceforth will be referred to as anthropocentric,
account for a position in the ecological philosophy that considers humans either a morally
superior being – or more radically – the only moral subject. However, this hegemonic position
relies on an insufficient body of arguments. As Peter Singer, representing the patocentric
position, writes: “If [an animal] suffers, there can be no moral justification for disregarding that
suffering, or for refusing to count it equally with the like suffering of any other being”. Other,
more radical, positions in the ecological philosophy question too the anthropocentrism and raise
argument for a broader definition of moral value and rights.
As the topic is very comprehensive it must be broke down in smaller parts: First I will discuss
the topic of animal rights, starting with Peter Singer’s patocentristic views. Secondly, I will go a
step even further and argue for the moral integrity of all life. Finally, using a dialectical attitude, I
seek to combine the ecological positions into coherent principles of a bio-centered ethical
approach to nature and the integrity of life in general.
The first question that I will address is: Why do humans have moral worth, if animals do not? As
Peter Singer argues in his book Animal Liberation, there can not be any moral justification for
refusing to count the suffering of a man to the suffering of another being. One of the first points
on the subject raised in the anthropocentric tradition is that human beings are more intelligent,
master the commands of languages and has a perception of moral, whereby they are morally
superior. There are, nevertheless, many counterarguments to be articulated against this reasoning.
The first is that we do not use intelligence as an “ethical” measure in our everyday life, nor our
skills in language or our moral sense: For example we do not consider an intelligent man more
morally valuable than a child, simply because he is more “intelligent”. In the same way our
current principles of moral are independent of how many languages we speak or how “morally”
we act. Another counterargument originates from the is/ought problem, also known as Humes
Law or the naturalist fallacy. Basically David Hume asserts that man can only come to know
how things are, applying descriptive scientifically methods, but not how things ought to be,
because that is concerning moral which is a metaphysical phenomenon. For these reasons, the
argument that humans are morally superior to animals because of their “talents” is invalid.
This leads to the central argument of Singer’s thesis: If animals have a “consciousness” and the
ability of experiencing “pleasure and pain”, then they should be regarded moral beings. Singer
here extends the principle of equality, which only applies to humans within the anthropocentric
position, and combines it with an utilitarian approach: If a being is able to suffer (or enjoy) then
it must have an interest, which should be respected in ethical terms, no matter if that being is a
human or another animal. Additionally he claims that if we do not accept this argument, we are
“speciesists”, meaning that we only grant humans ethical right because we favour our own
species in the same way that the white man defended the slavery of the black man by referring to
racial difference.
To sum up: According to Peter Singer we must either acknowledge the moral value of feeling
(patocentric) beings or acknowledge ourselves as speciesists.
Now I shall move on to my next inquiry, which is arguing that not only feeling animals should be
entitled moral rights, but the entire biosphere as well. However, it is a fundamental supposition
in the following chain of reasoning that moral, by definition, is a metaphysical subject, and
therefore it cannot be “proven” empirically.
In the last part of Singer’s quotation, he states that “if a being is not capable of suffering, or of
enjoyment, there is nothing to take into account.” As Singer uses a utilitarian approach in his
argumentation it is an axiom that a being with no interest (unable to experience pain or pleasure)
has no moral rights. This assumption, however, is problematic: What moral rights should be
granted to a senile elderly, a disabled person or an embryo (not to say a new-born child)? The
very dramatic consequence of Singer’s solely focus on the interest of the being, and not the
matter of life itself, is that he must conclude, for instance, that we have a somewhat duty to kill
(un)born disabled children if we estimate that their lives would contain more “pain” than
“pleasure”. It is thus a consequence that the “quality of life” is at some point above the right to
live: The value of a human life is accordingly relative to its (potential) “qualities”.
Another way to perceive the integrity of life is from an absolutistic perspective. The reason to do
so is because it seems that we, emotionally and in discourse, consider human life to be sacred.
For instance it says in the American Declaration of Independence “that we declare these truth to
be self-evident…”, whereas a list of (human rights) follows. Nonetheless, if we accept that
human life has an absolutistic, “self-evident”, intrinsic value, we will have difficulties arguing
that all life forms do not. One argument is based upon the awe-of-life, which is an extension of
the integrity of human life to cover all forms of life, seeing that the similarities between human
and non-human life (animals, plants and bacteria) share significant similarities. This argument is,
though, strongest in connection with Singer’s patocentric position, since the similarities in life
patterns between humans and animals grow rapidly larger in a like comparison between humans
and plants. Therefore, a stronger argument for the moral rights of all life forms is still needed.
Another approach is based on the teleological argument in which it is claimed that all life
contains a so-called telos – that is a “final cause”. The term was originally invented by Aristotle,
who said that the “the seed has the full-grown plant as its telos”. This argument is, in the same
way as Singer’s patocentric argument, an extension of the values of human purposes as it is
claimed that the intrinsic value of the purpose does not depend on the specific form of life, but
lies within the purpose itself. All life forms have, according to the argument, thus an inherent
value due to their final cause, which could be growth, reproduction or diversity.
Another more radical position in the ecological philosophy is the Deep Ecology Movement led by
Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess and later also American George Sessions. In the deep
ecology, the Earth is, ideally, considered a harmonic ecosystem with no distinction between
human and nature. Every living being, also accounting the “life of an ecosystem and its single
component” (here also inorganic materials: Rocks, mountains, rivers and valleys) have an
inherent value. Naess and Sessions have articulated the following principles of the deep ecology,
in which they sum up the basic metaphysical axioms of their philosophy:
1. The well-being and flourishing of human and non-human life on Earth have value in
themself (synonyms: intrinsic value, inherent value). These values are independent of the
usefulness of non-human life for human purposes.
2. Richness and diversity of all life forms contribute to the realization of these values and
are also values in themselves.
3. Humans have no right to reduce this richness and diversity, except to satisfy vital needs.
(Freely adapted from: Deep Ecology: Living as if Nature Mattered, Sessions and Dewall).
Naess and Session thus construct a new perspective of nature, inspired by Eastern religion, Zen-
Buddhism and Spinoza’s theory of one substance (being God), from which they can deduce the
holistic argument. It asserts that humans can not be separated from nature, seeing that they are an
inseparable part of nature as an ecological system. Moreover, the consequence is that our
superior intellect does not release us from the bonds of nature, it actually rather impose us to
secure (and restore) the balance or harmony of life in the ecosystem.
In this last section of the essay I attempt to combine the views of anthropocentrism and
biocentrism using a dialectical approach. Here anthropocentrism is regarded the dominating
thesis and the biocentrism (and the deep ecology movement) appears as an antithesis. The aim is
to construct a synthesis or ethical approach to nature which can be proposed in some basic
biocentrical principles.
First, nonetheless, I will present my critique of Naess’ and Sessions’ deep ecological perspective
and the holistic argument in defence of the anthropocentrism. It is assumed in the holistic
argument as a consequence of the deep ecology world view that man is inseparable from nature.
On the one hand, an objection could be that culture together with the invention and advancing
development of technology is a symbol or “proof” of man’s detachment from nature. On the
other hand, it could be reasoned that the richness and diversity of culture, the exploration of
science, and the development of new technology is a realization of human life and therefore also
a value cf. the second principle of deep ecology.
In attempt to combine these two opposing perspectives into an approach we will thus have to
take consideration of the absolute value of life, on the one side, and the value related to the
realization of life, on the other side. Nevertheless, the value of life and the value of the telos
related to every living being must be equally respected, and hence the right of realization for one
life is limited by the equal right of another life. In keeping with that thought, I propose the
following three basic principles of biocentrical ethics:
1. All life has an inherent value, which can not be reduced by either human or technological
power.
This first principle emphasizes that all life, in this approach defined as organisms build up by
complex and functioning cell structures, have an inherent value as argued earlier. Moreover, this
right or value is not relative to human interests or power, seeing the values are absolutistic and
irreducible for consumptive (human) purposes.
1. Humans should seek an ecological balance or harmony where the value of all life forms
are respected and their vital needs can be satisfied.
The principle proclaims that our “industrialized” relation to nature must end. Instead of viewing
nature as a resource and the goal of every intercourse to gain economical profit on behalf of
nature, we should seek to modify this relation so that our needs can be satisfied and the respect
for life is still restored.
Basically this principle is a compromise where the right for humans to realize their life through
the development of technology is accepted on the condition that technology shall not reduce the
inherent value or realization of other life forms, if not to fulfil vital needs.
In conclusion: I have argued for a reconstruction of the ecological order, focusing on the ethical
integrity of all life, and proposed three basic principles for a biocentrical ethics, which is
adaptable with human culture and technology. It relies on the metaphysical axiom that all life has
an inherent value in itself, no matter if it a human, an animal or a plant, which should at least be
recognized as a moral worth.
As a last reflection on Singers thesis it could be argued that, from a biocentrical perspective, his
definition of “suffering” and “interest” is too narrow. If the assumption of a metaphysical value
of life is recognized, it is reasonable to claim that all life has an interest (or enjoyment) of
flourishing. Any obstruction of that interest would then be considered suffering, which can only
be ethical, conditioned by the respect for life and the balance within nature.