Ibn Khaldun'S Philosophy of History: The Rise and Fall of States and Civillzations
Ibn Khaldun'S Philosophy of History: The Rise and Fall of States and Civillzations
Ibn Khaldun'S Philosophy of History: The Rise and Fall of States and Civillzations
'
,. This lecture was delivered on January 5, 1984 at the Faculty of politicaı Science,
Ankara University.
" ....1;
. .A.. . ~.• ..a•. " .l.,.":
186 BAR.BARA STOW ASSER
powerful force in the crcation of a civilization and its laws are the most
effective instruments for preserving it.
..•.
becomes subject to diseasf~and plague. The state begins to disintegrate.
From the outlying regions, princes, generals, dissatisfied kinsmen, and
foreign conquerors snatch pieces of territory from the control of the state.
The state is divided and subdivided into smaIl provinces. Even in the ca-
pital, the military and the bureaucrats engage in intrigues to wrest the
actural authority form the ruler, leaving him only with the insignia of
his office and the name. Finally, an outside invasion by a young, healthy
group may put an end to the life of the state, or it may decline further
and further until it wither;~ away "like a wick dying out in a lamp whose
oil is gone."
Not every conquest has to mark a new beginning. Civilization is
attractive to the primitiye conquerors and so they try to imitate the cus-
toms and practices that thi~y find when they arriye. The mastery of each
craft or science, no matter how difficult, tends to become a habit, and
therefore can be taught to others, provided that the proper methods of
instructionare known and that. the political upheaval is not too drastic
and destructive.
And so all political life and all eultural life moves in never--endlng,
always repeated eycles. There is no progress from one eycle to the next.
The notion of progress aetually is laeking altogether İn Ibn Khaldun's
philosophy, as it is in all of Arab medieval thought.
As he depiets the rise and fall of dynasties and states and eultures
in purely seeular terms, Ibn Khaldun gives a much more aeeurate aecount
of what happened in the Islamie world beforeand during his own time
than those PlOUS lawyer-theologians who tried to deseribe the Islamie
Middle Ages in the terms of the early Islamic theocraey. And yet, Ibn
Khaldun was asincere' belif!\'er and that early theocracy was as important
to him as it was to those pious writers who struggled to keep th'eir utopia
alive. How then does Ibn Khaldun deal with the beginnings of Islam? He
does so at an aıtogether different leveL.Things were not always this grim,
he says, the movement of rise and decline was not always this ineseapable.
Both the establishment of Islam and its very early history represent a
direct divine interventian in' human affairs. For a few generations, group
feeling was nothing and submission to the will of God was everything.
The periods {n which religion was thernain force of motivation were the
orthodox ealiphate (632-661),the very early years of the Umayyad king-
dom, and then again the very early years of the Abbasid empire. During
these periods, the eommunity flourished and eonquered. But then the
experience paled and its initial tremendous impact was lost. Islam eeased
to be the sole source of unity and agreement, and the old mysterious
eohesive power of natural group feeling had to eome to the füre again.
IBN KHALDUN'S PHILOSOPHY 189
And man who was too weak to keep the original faith experience aliye
had to revert to the inescapable grimness of cyclical existence. Here the
Islamic community could have escaped the cycle: by holding fast to the
laws of God and the new religion, and by avoiding materialism and greed
and corruption. Their sinful failure- to do so resulted in their loss of free-
dom and their inevitable dedine.
Before i ı:onclude with some remarks on the question of the "secu-
larism" and hence the whole q:uestion of the "modernity" of Ibn Khaldun,
let me say that Ibn Khaldun's ideas were in some ways too realistic and
hence revolutionary for the intellectually stagnant society in which he
lived and worked. There is very little evidence that he had any impact
on Arab thought in the Iate 14th or early 15th centuries. it was only in
the 16th and particularly in the 17th centuries that an Ibn Khaldun re-
discovery got underway, and the. people who rediscovered and read and
commented upon him were the Ottoman Turks. The Ottomans, as you
know, concentrated much of their intellectual interest upon historyand
political thought, and they were fascİnated with Ibn Khaldun. In the
16th, 17th, and 18th centuries, the study of Ibn Khaldun constituted an
important segment of Turkish intellectual history. it was only in the
19th century that Europa joined the Turks in reading Ibn Khaldun.
You will agree with me that, as ıbn Khalc;un grasps that fundamental
and specific element which constitutes political reality, he comes across
as arealist. In his description of the rise and fall of Islamic societies and
cultures, in his analysis of Islamic states, this political realism, this in-
terest in the concrete manifestations of social and political entities give
his work a much more "modern" flavor than is to be found even with
many present-day Muslims writers who are generally -more theocı:atic/
utopian in their- id~as. Yet, when it comes to the relationship of religion
and politics, there is a tremendous distance between Ibn, Khaldun's poli-
tical pragmatism and, let's say, Machiavelli's political philosophy. As
Machiavelli ponders the rise and fall of nations and cultures in his Dİs-
courses and in The Prİ'ııce, he also relies on religion as the main source
for social solidarity. Paradoxically, he actually does so to an even higher
degree than Ibn Khaldun. Without religion, says Machiavelli, nations
cannot develop "virtue" (political strength and cohesiveness) since it is
only on the basis ıof observed religion that good institutions can be estab-
lished which then restrain individual selfishness and thus ensure th2
supremacy of the common good. In other words, Machiavelli sees religion
as political1y useful. However, he is not concerned with religion as God-
given Truth and Law, not does he seethe corruption of religion as a
resu1t of human weakness, and sin. Both the rise and fall of religion to
.,
J;A
190 BARBARA STOW ASSER
Thus, I contend that J1)n Khaldun did not develop, nor did he seek
to develop, a truly s'ecular philosophy of history or a truly secular scienee
of politics' and society. Lately it has been fashionable to claim that he
did. Yet just as Ibn Khaldun never reeognized the idea of government
as an autonomous seeular activity so also did he not develop the idea of
the state as independent from religion that derives its legitimacy from
other sources and is fit to make its own morality. To/my mind, therefore,
Ibn Khaldun remained essentially and devoutly within the mainstream
of orthodox Islamic political philosophy, and his philosophy of history
reflects his conviction that -"vhileit is neeesary to know the exaet nature
of man and society, both social and politieal, such knowledge is not
possible "without knowing the true end of man and society." The notian
of division and separation of religion and politics, wlıich has gained
ground in the West to a pOİ!ıt where, in most peoples' opinion, political
developments is "inversaly related to religion in politics" -this notion has
its roots in Western thought or, more specifieally, in the Western Re-
naissance. Whether, of eourse, it has meant pure blessing or pure harm
or something in betwee~ for our own 'civilization is anather matter. But
the id'eal itself was not iornıulated by Ibn Khaldun, who is classical Is-
lam's seemingIy most pragmatic, seemingIy most seeular thinker. Under-
neath his pragmatism, Ibn Khaldun lets us pereeive his deeper convie-
tion: the conviction that adlıerence to the true religion can and should
insure the creation of God's Kingdom on Earth, an everlasting Golden
Age. it and when this is achieved, he tells us, civilizations, need not and
will not rise nar fall again.