Preview
Preview
Preview
The second edition of Strategic Studies: A Reader brings together key essays on strategic
theory by some of the leading contributors to the field. This revised volume contains
several new essays and updated introductions to each section.
The volume comprises hard-to-find classics in the field as well as the latest scholar-
ship. The aim is to provide students with a wide-ranging survey of the key issues in
strategic studies, and to provide an introduction to the main ideas and themes in the
field. The book contains six extensive sections, each of which is prefaced by a short
introductory essay:
Overall, this volume strikes a balance between theoretical works, which seek to discover
generalizations about the nature of modern strategy, and case studies, which attempt to
ground the study of strategy in the realities of modern war.
This new edition will be essential reading for all students of strategic studies, security
studies, military history and war studies, as well as for professional military college
students.
‘This superb volume provides an essential primer for any student of strategic studies.’
Theo Farrell, Kings College, London
‘By a wide margin this is the premier Reader in the field of strategic studies. For research
as well as teaching, it is an invaluable resource.’ Colin S. Gray, University of Reading
‘An essential text for anyone interested in the development of strategic ideas.’
Stephan Fruehling, Australian National University, Canberra
‘The new volume makes an excellent contribution to the study of strategy, and to the
ongoing debate on the complexity of strategy and the connection between security and
strategy. It is also a great and highly recommended teaching tool for advanced course on
strategic studies.’ Mohiaddin Mesbahi, Florida International University
Strategic Studies
A Reader
Second Edition
R Routledge
Taylor & Francis Group
LO N D O N A N D N E W YORK
First published 2008 by Routledge
This edition published 2014
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2014 selection and editorial material, Thomas G. Mahnken and Joseph A. Maiolo;
individual chapters, the contributors
The right of the editors to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of
the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with
sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in
any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter
invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data has been requested
Typeset in Baskerville
by RefineCatch Limited, Bungay, Suffolk
Contents
Acknowledgements viii
General introduction 1
PART I
The uses of strategic theory 5
Introduction 5
PART II
Interpretation of the classics 49
Introduction 49
PART III
Instruments of war, intelligence and deception 127
Introduction 127
PART IV
Nuclear strategy 203
Introduction 203
PART V
Irregular warfare and small wars 261
Introduction 261
PART VI
Future warfare, future strategy 339
Introduction 339
22 From Kadesh to Kandahar: military theory and the future of war 392
MICHAEL EVANS
Index 447
Acknowledgements
The publisher would like to thank the following for permission to reprint their
material:
Oxford University Press, for Freedman, Lawrence, “Strategic Studies and the Problem
of Power,” from War, Strategy, and International Politics (1992), edited by Lawrence
Freedman et al., pp. 279–294.
Naval War College Press, for Fuller, William C., Jr., “What is a Military Lesson?,” from
Strategic Logic and Political Rationality: Essays in Honor of Michael I. Handel (Frank Cass,
2002), edited by Bradford A. Lee and Karl-Friedrich Walling, pp. 38–59.
National Defense University, for Gray, Colin S., “Why Strategy is Difficult,” Joint Force
Quarterly (summer 1999), pp. 6–12.
The United States Naval War College, for Handel, Michael I., “Who is Afraid of Carl
von Clausewitz?: A Guide to the Perplexed” (summer 1999).
University of California Press, for Liddell Hart, Basil, The Decisive Wars of History (1929),
reprinted as Strategy: The Indirect Approach (London: Faber and Faber, 1954), extracted
in Gerard Chaliand, ed., The Art of War in World History: From Antiquity to the Nuclear Age
(Berkeley, University of California Press, 1994), pp. 927–931.
University of California Press, for Schelling, Thomas C., Arms and Influence (New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press, 1966), pp. 1–34, extracted in Gerard Chaliand, ed., The
Art of War in World History: From Antiquity to the Nuclear Age (Berkeley, University of
California Press, 1994), pp. 1013–1022.
MIT Press, for Byman, Daniel L. and Waxman, Matthew C., “Kosovo and the Great
Air Power Debate,” International Security, 24 (4) (spring 2000), pp. 5–38. © 2000 by the
President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of
Technology.
Acknowledgements ix
Taylor and Francis, for Jervis, Robert, “What’s Wrong with the Intelligence Process?,”
International Journal of Intelligence and CounterIntelligence, 1(1) (1986), pp. 28–41.
Taylor and Francis, for Maiolo, Joseph A., “Deception and Intelligence Failure: Anglo-
German Preparations for U-boat Warfare in the 1930s,” Journal of Strategic Studies,
22(4) (1999), pp. 55–76.
Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, for Brodie, Bernard (ed.), The Absolute Weapon: Atomic Power
and World Order. © 1946 by Yale Institute of International Studies. Copyright ©
renewed 1974 by Yale Concilium on International and Area Studies. Used by permis-
sion of Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company. All rights reserved.
Foreign Affairs, for Wohlstetter, Albert, “The Delicate Balance of Terror.” Reprinted
by permission of Foreign Affairs, 37(2), pp. 211–234. © 1959 by the Council on Foreign
Relations, Inc. www.ForeignAffairs.com.
Taylor and Francis, for Kreps, Sarah and Fuhrmann, Matthew, “Attacking the Atom:
Does Bombing Nuclear Facilities Affect Proliferation?,” The Journal of Strategic Studies,
34(2) (April 2011), pp. 161–187.
Taylor and Francis, for Neumann, Peter R. and Smith, Michael L.R., “Strategic
Terrorism: The Framework and its Fallacies,” The Journal of Strategic Studies 28(4)
(August 2005), pp. 571–595.
National Defense University, for Hoffman, Frank G., “Hybrid Warfare and Challenges,”
Joint Force Quarterly (2009), pp. 34–48.
MIT Press, for Mahnken, Thomas G., “Weapons: The Growth and Spread of the
Precision-Strike Regime,” Daedalus, 140 (3) (summer 2011), pp. 45–57. © 2011 by the
American Academy of Arts and Sciences.
Taylor and Francis, for Newmyer Deal, Jacqueline, “The Revolution in Military Affairs
with Chinese Characteristics,” The Journal of Strategic Studies, 33(4) (August 2010),
pp. 481–504.
Taylor and Francis, for Bukkvoll, Tor, “Iron Cannot Fight: The Role of Technology in
Current Russian Military Theory,” The Journal of Strategic Studies, 34(5) (October 2011),
pp. 681–706.
x Acknowledgements
The United States Naval War College, for Evans, Michael, “From Kadesh to Kandahar:
Military Theory and the Future of War,” Naval War College Review, 56(3) (summer
2003), pp. 139–147.
Taylor and Francis, for Rid, Thomas, “Cyber War Will Not Take Place,” The Journal of
Strategic Studies, 35(1) (February 2012), pp. 5–32.
Taylor and Francis, for Strachan, Hew, “The Lost Meaning of Strategy,” Survival (2005),
pp. 33–54.
Every effort has been made to contact copyright holders for their permission to reprint
material in this book. The publishers would be grateful to hear from any copyright
holder who is not here acknowledged and will undertake to rectify any errors or
omissions in future editions of this book.
General introduction to the
second edition
Events since the publication of the first edition of this Reader have only emphasized the
relevance of war and strategy in the modern world. The wars in Iraq, Afghanistan,
Georgia and Libya; territorial disputes in the South China and East China seas, as well
as the continuing possibility of conflict on the Korean Peninsula, in the Persian Gulf and
across the Taiwan Strait, all demonstrate that force remains an instrument of statecraft
and emphasize the importance of strategic thought and action.
At the same time, war appears to be taking new forms. Since the early 1990s, theorists
and practitioners have been arguing that we are in the early phases of a Revolution in
Military Affairs (RMA) brought on by the development and diffusion of precision-strike
weaponry. Moreover, recent years have seen growing debates over the effects and effective-
ness of cyber operations. The Chinese military has embraced both precision-guided weap-
onry and information operations, and both figure prominently in Chinese writings on
future warfare. In addition, Russia’s increasing reliance on nuclear weapons, China’s
nuclear modernization, North Korea’s demonstration of its nuclear capability, and
continued suspicion that Iran would like to follow suit, demonstrate that nuclear weapons
(and nuclear strategy) remain a concern.
In a world in which so much about the character and conduct of war appears to be
changing, an understanding of the theory of war reminds us that the nature of war does
not change. Moreover, an understanding of the enduring nature of war can help us
focus on its changing character and conduct.
Theory offers the student of strategy a conceptual toolkit to analyse strategic prob-
lems. An understanding of theory equips the student with a set of questions to guide
further study. As Carl von Clausewitz wrote, the purpose of theory is not to uncover
fixed laws or principles, but rather to educate the mind. As he put it:
In other words, we study strategic theory in order to learn how to think strategically.
Because the stakes in war are so high, strategy is a supremely practical endeavour.
The most elegant theory is useless if it lacks practical application. Strategic theory thus
succeeds or fails in direct proportion to its ability to help decision makers formulate
sound strategy. As the twentieth-century American strategist Bernard Brodie put it,
“strategy is a field where truth is sought in the pursuit of viable solutions.”2
On strategy
Because strategy is about how to win wars, any discussion of strategy must begin with an
understanding of war. As Clausewitz famously defined it, “war is thus an act of force to
compel our enemy to do our will.”3 Two aspects of this definition are notable. First, the
fact that war involves force separates it from other types of political, economic and mili-
tary competition. Second, the fact that war is not senseless slaughter, but rather an
instrument that is used to achieve a political purpose, differentiates it from other types of
violence.
Strategy is, or rather should be, a rational process. As Clausewitz wrote, “No one
starts a war – or rather, no one in his senses ought to do so – without first being clear
in his mind what he intends to achieve by that war and how he intends to conduct
it.”4 In other words, success in war requires a clear articulation of political aims and
the development of an adequate strategy to achieve them. Clausewitz’s formulation
acknowledges, however, that states sometimes go to war without clear or achievable
aims or a strategy to achieve them. As Germany demonstrated in two World
Wars, mastery of tactics and operations counts for little without a coherent or feasible
strategy.5
Successful strategy is based upon clearly identifying political goals, assessing one’s
comparative advantage relative to the enemy, calculating costs and benefits carefully,
and examining the risks and rewards of alternative strategies. The purpose of strategy is
ultimately to convince the enemy that he cannot achieve his aims. As Admiral J.C. Wylie
wrote,
the primary aim of the strategist in the conduct of war is some selected degree of
control of the enemy for the strategist’s own purpose; this is achieved by control
of the pattern of war; and this control of the pattern of war is had by manipulation
of the centre of gravity of war to the disadvantage of the opponent.6
If the successful operations against Islam’s enemies and the severe damage inflicted
on them do not serve the ultimate goal of establishing the Muslim nation in the
heart of the Islamic world, they will be nothing more than disturbing acts, regardless
of their magnitude, that could be absorbed and endured, even if after some time and
with some losses.
Notes
1 Carl von Clausewitz, On War, edited and translated by Michael Howard and Peter Paret (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), 141.
2 Bernard Brodie, War and Politics (New York: Macmillan, 1973), 452–3
3 Clausewitz, On War, 75.
4 Ibid., 579.
5 David Stevenson, 1914–18: The History of the First World War (London: Penguin Books, 2005); Karl-
Heinz Frieser, The Blitzkrieg Legend: The 1940 Campaign in the West (Annapolis, MD: Naval Institute
Press, 2005).
6 J.C. Wylie, Military Strategy: A General Theory of Power Control (Annapolis, MD: Naval Institute Press,
1989), 77.
7 Andrew F. Krepinevich, Jr., The Army and Vietnam (Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University
Press, 1986); Piers Mackesy, The War for America, 1775–1783 (Rutgers: University of Nebraska Press,
1993).
8 Clausewitz, On War, 4.
Part I
Introduction
The three essays in Part I offer readers an important point of departure for the explora-
tion of strategic studies. All three authors share the view that strategy is more than the
practical application of a few common-sense rules of thumb about the use of military
means to achieve political ends; that strategy should be studied methodically and that it
has a place among the scholarly pursuits; and that useful strategic knowledge demands
that present-day theorists think rigorously about “the lessons” of past wars and history
more generally.
In the first essay reproduced in Part I, Sir Lawrence Freedman of King’s College
London draws on insights from political science and sociology to examine the most
fundamental underlying concept of strategic studies: namely, the concept of “power”.
Although power is often measured in terms of assets (men, money, hardware, etc.),
power should be understood as a relationship between opposing wills. As Freedman
defines it, “power is the capacity to produce effects that are more advantageous than
would otherwise have been the case”. To illustrate, Freedman turns to deterrence
theory: A deters (or exercises power over) B, when B modifies its behaviour in response
to A’s threats. As anyone familiar with international relations knows, however, deter-
rence relationships are in practice never straightforward. B may not perceive the threat
or respond in the way intended by A. The complexities of politics and psychology
conspire to frustrate the exercise of power, especially when it requires the continual
application of force. Put simply, B will always seek ways to subvert A’s control. Although
for these reasons any exercise of power is inherently unstable, power at its most stable is
achieved when B accepts A’s will in the form of authority. What Freedman’s analysis
suggests is that an understanding of power relevant to strategic studies must encompass
more than “control” through “force”. Strategy, he writes, is “the art of creating power
to obtain the maximum political objective using available military means”.
While Freedman offers insights into the methodology of strategic studies and the
central concept of power, the second essay reproduced here examines the way in which
strategic thinkers have used and abused history. William C. Fuller, Jr. of the US Naval
War College disputes the accepted wisdom that armed forces routinely ignore the
“lessons” of prior wars. Even the most cursory survey shows that nations and their armed
forces have constantly striven to learn from past experience. The real problem, as Fuller
6 The uses of strategic theory
sees it, is not a lack of interest in historical lessons, but instead the problem of knowing
what “the lessons” are and how to embrace them. He sets out the typical styles of
extracting military lessons and the pitfalls associated with them, specifically the fallacies
of the “linear projection” and the “significant exception”. Strategists fall for the first of
these by rigidly predicting future military outcomes from those of the immediate past;
strategists fall for the second when they explain away prior military experiences that do
not conform to the existing model of war as “significant exceptions”. These two fallacies
occur because military organizations prefer steady incremental change to radical trans-
formation, and because they often prefer to prepare for the wars they want to fight
instead of the ones that they may actually be more likely to fight. What Fuller’s analysis
shows is that the whole concept of a “military lesson” is dubious and potentially
dangerous. Although military organizations can learn much from wars of the past, useful
“military lessons” are short-lived because of the interactive nature of war. After
all, future adversaries may find a way to creatively exploit a strategy based on prior
experience, or may simply learn precisely the same lesson, and so produce a frustrating
strategic stalemate.
The final essay takes strategic studies to the level of its application. As Colin S. Gray
of the University of Reading points out, much of what appears to be wise and even
prudent in theory is often unhelpful to the hapless military officer who is tasked with
drawing up a feasible strategy and then executing it. Strategy is difficult to put into prac-
tice because it is neither policy making nor combat. Talent in one or the other field, as
Gray writes, does not make one a good strategist. Good strategists, Gray suggests, are
born rather than trained. Strategy is difficult because war itself is an extraordinarily
complex activity in which everything that can go wrong will. Even the most high-tech
communication and intelligence systems, for instance, cannot dispel what Clausewitz
(see Michael Handel’s essay in Part II) called the fog and friction of war, or anticipate
how a foe will act to frustrate even the most brilliantly conceived and executed strategy.
Study questions
1 What is strategy?
2 What is “power”? And how does the definition offered by Freedman shape your
understanding of strategy?
3 Is strategy an “art” or a “social science”?
4 Are historical “lessons” a reliable guide for future strategy?
5 Why is strategy difficult?
Further reading
Betts, Richard K., “Is Strategy an Illusion?”, International Security 25, no. 2 (2000), 5–50.
Brodie, Bernard, “Strategy as a Science”, World Politics 1, no. 4 (1949), 467–488.
Brodie, Bernard, Strategy in the Missile Age (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1959).
Fearon, James, “Rationalist Explanations for War”, International Organization (summer 1995), 317–414.
Fischer, David Hackett, Historians’ Fallacies (London: Routledge, 1971).
Gat, Azar, A History of Military Thought: From the Enlightenment to the Cold War (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2002).
The uses of strategic theory 7
Gooch, John, “Clio and Mars: The Use and Abuse of History”, The Journal of Strategic Studies 3, no. 3
(1980), 21–36.
Howard, Michael, The Causes of War (London: Ashgate, 1983).
Lanir, Zvi, “The ‘Principles of War’ and Military Thinking”, The Journal of Strategic Studies 16, no. 1
(1992), 1–17.
McIvor, Anthony D., ed., Rethinking the Principles of War (Annapolis, MD: US Naval Institute Press,
2005).
This page intentionally left blank
1 Strategic studies and the
problem of power
Lawrence Freedman
I
‘The strategic approach’ is . . . one which takes account of the part played by force,
or the threat of force in the international system. It is descriptive in so far as it
analyses the extent to which political units have the capacity to use, or to threaten
the use of armed force to impose their will on other units; whether to compel them
to do some things, to deter them from doing others, or if need be to destroy them as
independent communities altogether. It is prescriptive in so far as it recommends
policies which will enable such units to operate in an international system which is
subject to such conditions and constraints.1
Michael Howard has throughout his career served as one of the most eloquent and lucid
exponents of the strategic approach. He was outlining his own creed when he described
classical strategists as
the thinkers who assume that the element of force exists in international relations,
that it can and must be intelligently controlled, but that it cannot be totally
eliminated.2
II
Although the intensive political science debate on this nature of power has been much
more extensive and sophisticated than that in strategic studies it has still reached a dead
end. This is not the place to survey the massive literature on power, but it is worth noting
some features.
Much of the difficulty stems from the fact that the starting-point for most analyses of
power—in political theory as much as strategic studies—is that it is an expression of the
subject’s will. This is reflected in different ways in three of the classic definitions of power:
Thomas Hobbes, ‘man’s present means to any future apparent good’;12 Max Weber,
‘the probability that one actor in a social relationship will . . . carry out his own will’;13
and Bertrand Russell—‘the production of intended effects’.14
One of the key questions is whether power is only realized through conflict. Talcott
Parsons, for example, sees power as a generalized capacity to seek group goals, and he
stresses the extent to which these goals can be consensual and achieved by an accepted
authority.15 Those who disagree insist that this neglects the inherently coercive and
conflictual dimensions of power. They are concerned that insufficient stress is given to
the ‘power over’ questions as opposed to the ‘power to’.16
There are many problems with the analysis of power in terms of ‘power over’. Pluralist
theorists, such as Dahl, sought to measure power by looking at the processes of decision-
making and tended to discover that no one group had a monopoly of power in terms of
Strategic studies and the problem of power 13
being able to get their way. This was vulnerable to the sort of critique developed by the
more radical theorists such as Bachrach and Baratz, who pointed to the importance of
successful non-decisions, that is the ability to get a set of interests enshrined in the
unspoken and unchallenged consensus, as a critical indicator of power.17 Power can be
exercised by the creation of social and political institutions which ensure that only the
most innocuous second-order issues ever come forward for decision. If the major ques-
tions relating to the distribution of resources and values in a society are successfully kept
from political consideration then this is an effective exercise of power. So what is meas-
ured may not be very interesting.
Others have argued that power can be measured by looking at the distribution of
resources and values, but that is open to the objection that the distribution may not have
been intended and so cannot truly be said to be an exercise of power. Looking at the
political hierarchy in search for ‘power élites’ also has its limitations, in that one élite
may not always win on all issues, and that those in an apparently subordinate position
may not be dissatisfied with the outcomes of the political process. Thus is it really an
exercise of power if the effects were not intended? At the very least must one show that
its exercise has made a difference?
Those who are most keen to find the sources of power have been those most anxious
to seize them. The strategists with the most sensitive theories of power have been
Marxist-Leninists because their theorizing has been closely linked with political action
(praxis). Marxist theory has taken as its starting-point the existence of a conflict of interest
between the ruling and working classes and seen its strategic task as being one of creating
a consciousness of class oppression rather than using its own awareness of this to analyse
inequality.
The difficulties of doing this have given Marxists a sense of the great variety of means
by which people can be kept down. Concepts like hegemony, which are now so useful in
understanding international relations, were first applied systematically by activist-
theoreticians such as Gramsci18 who were anxious to discover how it was that ruling
groups could ensure passivity and compliance among the masses. The problem of seizing
control of the state in conditions when all the odds were stacked in favour of the ruling
group stimulated sustained strategic debate.
Marxists were least interested in decision-making in a bourgeois democracy, which
they saw as part of the pretence by which ruling groups hid the realities of power from
the masses. Rather they were interested in the processes by which mass consciousness
became clouded by the ability of the ruling class to influence the way they saw political
reality, and, at the other extreme, those historic, revolutionary moments when the
masses rise to the challenge and attempt to take power.
From a variety of perspectives other political theorists have considered the relation-
ship of power to authority on the one hand and force on the other. This link between
power and authority is an important issue in much political theory, according to whether
the two are considered to be exclusive or extensions of each other.19 There is little doubt
that the peaceful exercise of authority is much more satisfactory than the violent exercise
of force when it comes to getting one’s way. But how is that to be achieved? The trick of
the powerful is to rule by encouraging the ruled to internalize the ruler’s own values and
interests.
14 Lawrence Freedman
III
Can strategists make a contribution to this debate? Strategic studies itself is not rich
in theory. It appeals to the practical and the pragmatic. Much of the fascination of
strategy is that it is concerned with politics at its most pure and raw—the pursuit of
interests even where they conflict with those of others, the problems of anticipating the
decisions of competitors or rivals when taking one’s own, the attempt to manipulate and
shape the environment rather than simply becoming the victim of forces beyond one’s
control.
As such it has long intrigued students of politics—Machiavelli is considered to be one
of the founding fathers of modern strategy.20 Arguably, it should be acknowledged as
one of the central branches of political theory. Yet a preoccupation with strategy has
often been considered slightly improper, perhaps because it requires regarding political
life too much through the eyes of the practitioner. Academic political theory has been
dominated by questions of order and justice. Even the study of power has often been
about whether to exercise it can be moral, rather than how the concept can be refined
to aid our understanding of the dynamics of political life.21
From a moral perspective strategy appears as subversive: it illuminates the means by
which the drive for order is thwarted and the unjust can triumph. Meanwhile, more
contemporary political analysis has sought to identify patterns and regularities in polit-
ical systems that tend to deny the importance of the active element in political life.
The debate within political science on the concept of power which raged during the
1960s and 1970s22 barely caused a ripple in the study of international politics, let alone
strategic theory. Graham Allison’s discovery of the limitations to rational decision-
making in Essence of Decision mirrored without reference many of the arguments used by
pluralist writers in their battle with the élite theorists.23
Yet there was a relevant intellectual tradition which influenced those coming to these
questions from the broader study of international politics. Those working within the
realist tradition had ‘power’ as the central concept and in general have defined it along
established lines, stressing causation and the production of intended effects, and identi-
fying it in terms of power over resources.24
Let us consider Hans Morgenthau’s concept of power.25 There is, with Morgenthau,
as is often noted, a tension between his understanding of power as a means to ultimate
ends, and power as an end in itself.26 It must be to be some extent an end in itself. Unless
one exercise of power is always different from another according to the ends being
sought, the acquisition of power as a general capacity which can serve a variety of ends
is a natural activity.
Power is directly related to political processes. Anything that can be achieved by
natural means does not require power. Excluded from consideration are non-
controversial interactions, such as extradition treaties. Morgenthau’s concept of politics
is thus very narrow—too narrow for most modern tastes. It is even more circumscribed
in domestic affairs, where much more activity is shaped by non-political factors. In inter-
national affairs, without the social cement, much more is left to politics.
Yet while Morgenthau’s understanding of politics is too narrow, his definition of
power is intriguing:
Strategic studies and the problem of power 15
When we speak of power, we mean man’s control over the minds and actions of
other men . . .
Thus the statement that A has or wants political power over B signifies always
that A is able, or wants to be able, to control certain actions of B through influencing
B’s mind.
Thus the concept of power stresses ‘the psychological element of the political relation-
ship’. As such, it works through an expectation of benefits or a fear of disadvantage, or
‘respect or love of a man or an office’. It involves orders, threats, and persuasion but also
a recognition of authority or prestige, an aspect of international politics Morgenthau
considered too often neglected.
This is distinguished from the actual exercise of physical violence. The threat of this
violence is an intrinsic element of international politics, but when violence becomes an
actuality, it signifies the abdication of political power in favour of military or pseudo-
military power. Yet Morgenthau cannot separate the application of force from power
because war has a political objective. War is a non-political means to a political end—
the accumulation of power. ‘The political objective of war itself is not per se the conquest
of territory and the annihilation of enemy armies, but a change in the mind of the enemy
which make him yield to the will of the victor.’ Note here too the identification of real-
izing one’s will as an expression of power.
There are obvious problems with the distinction between physical force and psycho-
logical power. The only time when one can truly enforce one’s will is when one has
achieved physical dominance. This is a problem to which I shall return.
What interests me for the moment is the consequence of the presumption that power
is exercised through the mind of the target—it is in the mind of the beholder. This is a
useful starting-point for any analysis of power, yet its immediate impact is to undermine
two of the common assumptions with which many analyses start, and with which
Morgenthau is often associated—that power is an asset to be accumulated and is
achieved to the extent that one’s will can be realized.
Once it is recognized that power can only be exercised through its impact on the
subject’s mind then it is accepted that it is relational and dependent upon the mental
construction of political reality by the subject.
IV
This problem can be taken further by a consideration of deterrence theory, which, for
strategic studies, has been the most thoroughly considered power relationship.27 A
standard definition is employed by George and Smoke: ‘Deterrence is simply the persua-
sion of one’s opponent that the costs and/or risks of a given course of action he might
take outweigh its benefits.’28 The definition makes it clear that the idea is to dissuade the
opponent from initiating action rather than to compel him to do—or undo—something
against his will, which distinguishes it from a more general definition of power.29
However, it is by no means clear that the ‘something’ in question threatens the deterrer
directly. The deterred may decide not to act in a particular way, even though this may
have no direct bearing on the interests of the deterrer. The definition acknowledges that
16 Lawrence Freedman
the success of deterrence depends on the opponent being persuaded. No matter how
sincere the deterrer might be in his conditional threats, if the opponent does not take
these threats seriously then deterrence will fail.
If deterrence is in the eye of the beholder then the opponent may simply misappre-
hend the message that he is being sent and fail to act accordingly. The problem with
designing deterrence strategies has therefore been to find ways of ensuring that the
opponent receives the threat, relates it to his proposed course of action, and decides as a
result not to go ahead as planned. The use in the definition from George and Smoke of
the phrase ‘costs and/or risks’ recognizes that the opponent need not be convinced that
the costs will definitely be imposed, only that there is a significant probability of this
being so.
This peculiar quality of deterrence, with the opponent being persuaded not to do
something, makes it very difficult to know whether in practice a deterrence relationship
is in being. If the opponent is inactive this may be because he has no inclination to act,
or, if he has been persuaded not to act, then this may be for reasons quite unconnected
with the deterrer or from the particular character of deterrent threats.
This is often discussed as a problem for the deterrer. Is he wasting his time by making
an effort to deter something that cannot be deterred or does not need deterring? How
can he make his threats sufficiently credible to penetrate the mind-set of his opponent?
Does this credibility depend on really being prepared to carry out the threat or merely
conveying a sufficient probability that he just might?
But it is also a problem for the deterred. Is he missing an opportunity because of
mythical fears about the possible consequences? The condition of paranoia, which is
much discussed in the deterrence literature, is an obvious example of being influenced
by fear of another which has little basis in reality. A deterrer can remain innocent of his
influence on an opponent’s calculations without the opponent losing his grip on reality.
It is possible, indeed quite normal, to be persuaded against a particular course of action
by the thought of how the target might respond. Prudence might dictate caution without
the potential target being aware that he had ever been at risk. A would-be aggressor may
thus be effectively deterred by an accurate assessment of the likely form of his potential
victim’s response without the victim having to do very much.
The phrase ‘self-deterrence’ is sometimes used to denote an unwillingness to take
necessary initiatives as a result of a self-induced fear of the consequences. But all deter-
rence is self-deterrence in that it ultimately depends on the calculations made by the
deterred, whatever the quality of the threats being made by the deterrer. So while much
of the discussion of deterrence revolves around the problem of adopting it as a strategy,
analytically it is important to recognize that it is as interesting to examine it from the
perspective of the deterred as much as the deterrer.
Moreover, deterrence can seem far less problematic when we start from the point of
view of the deterred. Once certain courses of action have been precluded through fear
of the consequences should they be attempted, this conclusion may be institutionalized.
It requires little further deliberation.
I noted earlier the focus of strategic studies on military means rather than political
ends. The political ends are normally described in terms of obtaining conformity to the
‘will’ of the political unit. With unconditional surrender at the end of total war this may
Strategic studies and the problem of power 17
be achieved, but with many conflicts where force is employed the outcome is much more
messy and confused than this decisive objective would anticipate. Much of the strategic
theory developed by such figures as Kahn and Schelling has discussed strategy in terms
of an incomplete antagonism, by which elements of common interest can be influential
even during the most intensive conflict, and has considered the conduct of the key
players during the course of a conflict in terms of bargaining.
A bargain normally means an adjustment to ends. A less than perfect outcome is
achieved but it is still the most that can be achieved. How then does this fit in with defi-
nitions of strategy which discuss it in terms of the search for appropriate means to achieve
given ends—such as the much-used definition developed by Basil Liddell Hart, ‘The art
of distributing and applying military means to fulfil the ends of policy.’30
It is possible to discuss either military means or political ends in isolation from each
other. That is what happens in much strategic studies, which turns into the most micro-
scopic examination of means unrelated to any serious discussion of what ends might be
served. Equally, many discussions of political ends are on a macroscopic scale and
discussed without any consideration of whether they are at all feasible in practice.
A key aspect of strategy is the interdependence of decision-making. This does not only
refer to the need to take the goals and capabilities of opponents into account. It must
take in the need to motivate one’s own forces by appealing either to their very personal
goals of survival/comfort/honour or to their broader values, as well as the need to
appeal to allies to throw in their lot with you. Equally, with allies, there is co-operation
to achieve the overriding goal of the containment or defeat of the enemy, but as with the
grand alliance during the Second World War, this can be combined with confrontation
over the shape of the post-war settlement or competition for the hearts and minds of
the liberated territories. Again, this requires some adjustment of both means and ends.
In practice, strategic relations are all mixtures of co-operation, confrontation, and
competition.
The interdependence of the decision-making means that effective strategy is based on
a sound appreciation of the structure of the relationships involved and the opportunities
it provides the various actors. It is necessary to anticipate the choices faced by others and
the way that your action shapes those choices.
V
Where does this leave us with the analysis of power and strategy? The view that strategy
is bound up with the role of force in international life must be qualified, because if force
is but one form of power then strategy must address the relationship between this form
and others, including authority.
The analysis of power has been dominated by a sense of hierarchy, as a relationship
between a super-ordinate and a sub-ordinate. This seems to be accepted in strategic
theory yet it is contradicted by the anarchic character of the international system and the
lack of a supreme locus of power. If power resources are decentralized then power rela-
tionships cannot be simply hierarchical. It is further assumed that the atomized nature
of the system produces regular clashes between individual units which, because they are
not mediated through a complex social structure, are more likely to be settled through
18 Lawrence Freedman
force. While this Hobbesian view of the international system has been properly contra-
dicted,31 it does provide a contrary tendency to that in domestic politics in modern states
with an authoritative government and many effective constraints against the regular use
of force to settle conflicts.
It is hard to get away from a view of power as a capacity to produce effects. In my
view, if it is insisted that these effects be ‘intended and foreseen’32 then in practice this is
too restrictive. My definition of power is the capacity to produce effects that are more advanta-
geous than would otherwise have been the case. How might this work as a concept?
A can oblige B to modify his behaviour through a successful application of force. In
this case B’s range of choice is physically restricted and his perceptions of A’s power are
reinforced through superior strength. However, it is normally preferable for A to
encourage B to modify his behaviour through coercive threats (and also inducements).
Best of all for A is if B does his bidding without question because he accepts A’s authority.
With all exertions of power other than force majeure, A’s objective is to persuade B to
change his preferred pattern of behaviour. In these cases an appreciation of power must
start with B’s understanding of his relationship with A.
Theorists normally give short shrift to the idea that power is an asset. Although we
talk of the powerful, in practice we are talking of power resources. There is nothing
automatic in their application: they can be squandered or exploited brilliantly. There is
an art to politics. Yet if by looking at great strength we act cautiously with A then A has
exerted power. So power is a capacity that exists to the extent that it is recognized by others. It is a
perceived capacity that cannot be independent of what is perceived.
This does not require a distinction between power and brute force. Force is not some-
thing different, merely the most extreme case when recognition of A’s power becomes
inescapable. Nor does power dissolve into authority at the other extreme. Authority is a
form of power. If people do what you want because of awe or respect then that is the best
form of power.
The perception of B may bear scant resemblance to the intention of A. The identifica-
tion of power with the ability to achieve a desired effect, that is with will, ignores the
problem that many of the effects involved are unintended or partial. It is one thing to
demonstrate mastery over nature—quite another to demonstrate mastery over other
wilful beings. It is rare in any social system for an actor to be able to disregard pressure
of one sort or another, positive and negative, from all others, which would imply a
complete monopoly of power. Even when A is in an unassailable position vis-à-vis B,
B may still have potentials that cause A to modify his behaviour. There is a fundamental
difference between the exertion of ‘power over’ nature or physical objects, and over
other individuals or groups who also have a capacity of sorts.
In most social systems, even those marked by a high degree of conflict, individual
actors participate in a multiplicity of political relationships. B does not simply need to
modify his behaviour because of A but also because of C and D as well. Most decisions
are complex and involve a variety of considerations involving other actors. The more dense
and complex the social structure the more difficult the exertion of power because B cannot attend only to
the pressures from A.
The greater the coherence within a political community the more likely it is that
power will be exercised through authority. In modern, complex structures this will mean
Strategic studies and the problem of power 19
that it has been institutionalized. For reasons that are familiar this is extremely difficult
in international society but it has been achieved in some areas—for example Western
Europe and North America. Conflict will develop within a political community to the
extent that institutional forms leave one group feeling disadvantaged, and to the extent
that it sees itself to be a distinct community on its own. This is the natural state of the
international community. But it is moderated by awareness of a shared fate resulting
from the costs of conflicts and the benefits of interdependence.
The two-way character of most political relationships and the complex character of
most political systems mean that any exercise of power is manifestly unstable. It is,
however, possible to go further and argue that any exercise of power is inherently unstable.
Let us examine this last point more fully. The ideal type towards which most discus-
sions of power tend is of A wholly controlling B’s fate. Suppose that A has captured B.
A’s most complete exercise of power would be to execute B immediately. But then the
power relationship would cease to exist. Let us assume that A wishes only to imprison B.
To start with B may be hopelessly cowed. Gradually he may find ways of not doing A’s
bidding. This may be no more than time-wasting. He may become aware that he is
something of a prize for A and that A will eventually wish to exhibit him in a reasonable
physical condition. He will also know that A cannot cope with a complete challenge to
his authority and so he will begin to seek the limits of A’s tolerance.
All this may be quite trivial and petty. In essential terms it may not matter. Despite all
the irritations imposed on his captors, B is still taken and displayed. But multiply this
relationship and the individual assertions of freedom at the margins can have a cumula-
tive effect. A cannot provide a warden for every prisoner. The fewer he has, the greater
the opportunity for conspiracies and acts of defiance. If control is lost completely then
there might be a mass break-out.
Absolute control requires a continual application of force. It needs continual renewal.
While for hard cases this may be found when necessary, in practice a more relaxed rela-
tionship will often be sought. Occupying forces will seek to do bargains with the victim
populations—material goods, respect for religious symbols, etc. That is, they seek to
reduce the coercive aspects of the relationships and seek to develop durable structures
which soften the impact of conflict.
VI
This analysis may be able to help clarify the character of strategic activity.
The focus of strategic thinking must be the ability of a state to sustain itself. Much
writing on strategy and international politics distinguishes the problems of the state in its
external relations from the requirements of internal order. This is a false dichotomy. A
state with problems in internal order is more vulnerable to external pressure—it is a
supplicant, requiring powerful friends to put down insurgency and provide economic
assistance. It is vulnerable to an unfriendly opponent stirring the pot a little.
Often problems of internal order at most require local police action. The complexity
of social interactions in a modern society ensures a coherence that in itself deters seces-
sionists and insurrectionists. However, this is by no means always the case. Many modern
states are still at an early stage of development and are not based on any natural social
20 Lawrence Freedman
cohesion. They are agglomerations of nationalities or tribes who feel their greatest
loyalty to the group rather than society at large.
We can thus distinguish between hard and soft states according to the degree of social
cohesion and popular legitimacy which they enjoy. Hard states can be vulnerable exter-
nally. But strong national feeling is an important source of political strength.
The same distinction can be applied at the regional level. Western Europe is a strong
sub-system, in that it is marked by a complex interdependence and shared values, while
Eastern Europe may be weak. The potential for conflict tends to decline with the
complexity of the social structure. None the less conflicts persist and strategy only comes
into being when there is an antagonism of which all participants are aware. It is inter-
esting to consider unconscious power relationships but they do not involve strategy.
While strategy may start with a visible conflict which will have to be decided by force
the ideal resolution may be for A to turn his advantage into authority. The institution-
alization of advantage so that it becomes reflected in consensus and procedure is the
supreme achievement of strategy. Strategists specialize in situations in which force may
be necessary, but a sole preoccupation with force misses the opportunities of authority.
Although all power is unstable, that based on authority has a much longer half-life than
that based on force.
Because in most cases, the power relationship between A and B is only one of a
number in which both actors participate, B may have a variety of options as to how to
respond to A’s threats. In order to get B to produce the required behaviour A must gain
B’s attention and shape his construction of reality. This must depend on the coercive
means at A’s disposal, but to translate these means into effective power is an art rather
than a science because of the need both to ensure that B does not use his own means to
frustrate this effort and also to influence B’s developing assessment of his own situation.
This is always the case even in war. In the movement towards the decisive clash, B may
be holding out all the time for a better peace settlement than unconditional surrender.
Force may for a moment provide complete control but the instability of such control
requires that either it is renewed continuously or else transformed, through the strate-
gist’s art, into authority.
In this sense strategy is the art of creating power. Power is unstable and subject to qualifica-
tion. It does not always produce the preferred effects, but it produces more advanta-
geous effects than would otherwise have been achieved.
Notes
1 Michael Howard, ‘The Strategic Approach to International Relations’, repr. in The Causes of Wars
(London, 1983), 36.
2 Michael Howard, ‘The Classical Strategists’, repr. in Studies in War and Peace (London, 1970), 155.
3 See in particular ‘The Relevance of Traditional Strategy’ and ‘The Forgotten Dimensions of
Strategy’, in Foreign Affairs, Jan. 1973 and Summer 1979 respectively. Both are reprinted in The
Causes of Wars.
4 Quincy Wright, The Study of War (Chicago, 1942). (Abridged version edited by Louise Leonard
Wright, Chicago, 1964.)
5 Bernard Brodie, Strategy in the Missile Age (Princeton, NJ, 1959) 21.
6 This is discussed in my The Evolution of Nuclear Strategy (London, 1981), esp. Section Five.
7 ‘The Relevance of Traditional Strategy’, in Causes, 85.
Strategic studies and the problem of power 21
8 Ibid. 86.
9 André Beaufre, Deterrence and Strategy (London, 1965), although he disagreed with Beaufre’s tendency
to extend the use of the term strategy.
10 ‘Morality and Force in International Politics’, in Studies, 235; ‘Ethics and Power in International
Policy’, in Causes, 61; ‘Military Power and International Order’, in Studies, 209.
11 W.B. Gallie, ‘Essentially Contested Concepts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955–6),
167–98. For a discussion of power along these lines see William E. Connolly, The Terms of Political
Discourse (2nd edn.; Princeton, NJ, 1983).
12 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, parts 1 and II (Indianapolis, 1958), 78.
13 Max Weber, Economy and Society, ed. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich (3 vols., New York, 1968),
53.
14 Bertrand Russell, Power: A New Social Analysis (London, 1938), 25.
15 Talcott Parsons, ‘On the Concept of Political Power’, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society,
107 (1963), 232–62.
16 See Steven Lukes, Power: A Radical View (London, 1974).
17 Robert Dahl, Who Governs? Democracy and Power in an American City (New Haven, Conn., 1961); Peter
Bachrach and Morton Baratz, ‘The Two Faces of Power’, American Political Science Review, 56
(Nov. 1962), 947–52.
18 A. Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks (London, 1971).
19 See John Hoffman, State, Power and Democracy (Sussex, 1988), pt. 2.
20 He is the first to be considered in Edward Meade Earle’s Makers of Modern Strategy (Princeton, NJ,
1962).
21 This is one of the main preoccupations of Connolly, Terms of Political Discourse. It is interesting to
note how much Howard has been preoccupied with this tension between ‘morality and force’ and
‘ethics and power’. See n. 17.
22 For collections of materials on this debate see Marvin Olsen (ed.), Power in Societies (London, 1970)
and Steven Lukes (ed.), Power (London, 1986).
23 Graham Allison, Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis (Boston, Mass., 1971). For a
critique along these lines see Lawrence Freedman, ‘Logic, Politics and Foreign Policy Processes: A
Critique of the Bureaucratic Politics Model’, International Affairs (July 1976).
24 See for example Stanley Hoffman, ‘Notes on the Elusiveness of Modern Power’, International Journal,
30 (Spring 1975); David Baldwin, ‘Power Analysis and World Politics’, World Politics, 31 (Jan. 1979);
Jeffrey Hart, ‘Three Approaches to the Measurement of Power in International Relations’,
International Organization, 30 (Spring 1976).
25 I am basing this section largely on the excerpt from Hans Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, repr.
as ‘Power and Ideology in International Politics’, in James Rosenau (ed.), International Politics and
Foreign Policy (New York, 1961), 170–2.
26 See Kenneth Waltz, Man, the State and War: A Theoretical Analysis (New York, 1959), 35.
27 This question is considered in more detail in Lawrence Freedman, ‘In praise of general deterrence’,
International Studies (Spring, 1989).
28 Alexander George and Richard Smoke, Deterrence in American Foreign Policy: Theory and Practice
(New York, 1974), 11.
29 A distinction is developed in the literature between deterrence and compellance—between ‘inducing
inaction and making someone perform’. It has been most fully elaborated by Thomas Schelling,
Arms and Influence (New Haven, Conn., 1966), 175, 69 ff.
30 Basil Liddell Hart, Strategy: The Indirect Approach (London, 1967), 335.
31 Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, NJ, 1979), 44.
32 Dennis Wrong, Power: Its Forms, Bases and Uses (London, 1988), 2.
2 What is a military lesson?
William C. Fuller, Jr.
‘Those who do not learn the lessons of the past are condemned to repeat them.’ This
hackneyed statement, popularly but erroneously ascribed to George Santayana, ought
of course to be paired with the comment of the German philosopher Hegel, which (in
paraphrase) is that the one thing we learn from history is that nobody ever learns
anything from history.1 What can we or do we usefully learn from the experience of
previous wars? This is a very important question, not least because if one contemplates
the twentieth century, one notices almost immediately that a whole variety of military
establishments compiled a dismal record at predicting the character of the next war –
that is, at correctly forecasting the nature of the conflict they were to confront next.
Consider World War 1. Almost no one in Europe, with the exception of the obscure
Polish-Jewish financier Ivan Bliokh, understood that World War I would be a protracted
war of attrition and stalemate.2 Nearly everybody else expected that the coming pan-
European war would be short and decisive, over in a matter of months, if not weeks.3 But
the predictive skills of the leaders of the major powers did not improve later in the
century. In 1940, for example, many Soviet leaders dismissed the idea that Germany
could conduct a successful Blitzkrieg against the USSR, despite Hitler’s campaigns in
Poland and France.4 Then, too, Japan, in preparing for a war against the United States
in 1941 adopted a theory of victory that was utterly bizarre, that bespoke a fatal incom-
prehension of the US system of government and the temperament of its people.5 Still
later, the United States itself failed to anticipate the Vietnam War and arguably never
grasped its essential character, even at its end.6 Thus the Soviet Union also misunder-
stood the war on which it embarked in Afghanistan in 1979, with catastrophic results.7
This list could be expanded almost effortlessly, although it would be both unedifying and
depressing to do so.
The question naturally arises: Why was this the case? What explains why the military
establishments of so many countries have been so badly wrong about the very thing that
Clausewitz declared was their most important task? After all, in one of the best-known
passages in On War, Clausewitz insisted that,
the first, the supreme, the most far-reaching act of judgment that the statesman and
commander have to make is to establish . . . the kind of war on which they are
embarking; neither mistaking it for, nor trying to turn it into, something that is alien
to its nature. This is the first of all strategic questions and the most comprehensive.8
What is a military lesson? 23
Why, then, do military establishments get it wrong? An answer proposed by some is that
the ability of the military to perceive the obvious is clouded over by an almost willful
blindness. It has, for example, been maintained that the great European military powers
contemptuously ignored the experience of the American Civil War, supposedly because,
as Moltke apocryphally said, that war was merely a matter of two ragged militias chasing
each other around a continent and consequently had no instructive value for the officers
of the professional armies of civilized countries.9 The ‘lessons’ of almost every war fought
since are said to have been stupidly disregarded by one nation or another. This view –
that military establishments have an uncanny capacity for overlooking the obvious – is
still very much with us.
Take Colonel (Ret.) John Warden of the US Air Force, an important air power
theorist of the past decade. In an influential essay he argues that:
many vital lessons have flowed from isolated events in the past. The following are
examples of lessons that should have been obvious at the time but were subsequently
ignored, with great loss of life: the effect of the long bow on French heavy cavalry at
Agincourt; the difficulty of attacking the trenches around Richmond; the carnage
wrought by the machine-gun in the Russo-Japanese War; the value of the tank as
demonstrated at Cambrai; and the effectiveness of aircraft against ships as shown by
the sinking of the Ostfriesland in tests after World War I.10
Now Colonel Warden is, of course, trying to make a case for the importance of the
lessons (or his version of the lessons) of the Persian Gulf War, which is the ‘isolated event’
to which he wants to call our attention. Yet his remarks here are problematic, not in the
least because the examples he cites are not ‘lessons’ at all, but rather empirical observa-
tions (and frequently incorrect ones) about the efficacy of various weapons.11 They are
not prescriptive and tell us nothing about what to do (or what not to do), which a lesson
by definition must. But a still greater objection can be made to Warden’s implicit allegation
that military establishments routinely ignore the experience of prior wars: it is demon-
strably false.
For instance, it is simply not the case that Europeans dismissed the American Civil
War; on the contrary, they studied it assiduously. G.F.R. Henderson’s Stonewall Jackson
and the American Civil War was a textbook at the British Staff College at Camberley for
many years.12 In Germany, there were a number of serving officers – among them
Scheibert, Mangold, and Freydag-Loringhoven – who specialized in writing about the
North American campaigns of 1861–65.13 Even in Imperial Russia, at the beginning of
the 1880s, the Tsar himself decreed a controversial (and extremely unpopular) reform of
the entire Russian cavalry arm based upon his appreciation of the operations of ‘Jeb’
Stuart and Phil Sheridan.14
If European military elites did not ignore the American Civil War, they were even
more eager to profit from the ‘lessons’ of their own recent conflicts. Consider the German
Wars of Unification. The successes of Prussia and then Germany in 1866 and 1870,
respectively, commanded the attention of the entire world. The armies of the other great
powers, and even those of the smaller powers, attempted to analyze the factors that had
produced German victory; there was an intense, even frenzied interest in studying and
24 William C. Fuller, Jr.
if possible copying the most important features of Germany’s military system. For
instance, the Prussian advantage in numbers vis-à-vis France in 1870 was clearly a func-
tion of the Prussian practice of conscription, which led to the creation of large reservoirs
of trained men. After all, Germany had been able to put 1.1 million troops into the field,
while France could initially muster no more than 560,000. One form or another of
conscription was adopted after the Franco-Prussian war by defeated France, Italy,
Holland, and Tsarist Russia. Even Britain, which recoiled from conscription as alien to
its traditions, still wanted to remain militarily competitive; the reforming Secretary of
State for War, Edward Cardwell, used fear of Prussia to ram through Parliament a series
of laws overhauling the British Army and abolishing finally the purchase of commissions
by officers.15
Indeed, the reverberations of Prussia’s victories were felt in areas of European life not
obviously connected to the performance of armies and fleets. Bismarck’s cryptic remark
that ‘the battle of Königgrätz was won by the Prussian schoolmaster’ was interpreted to
mean that efficiency in modern war depended on the intelligence and initiative of the
troops.16 It was not enough any more to have soldiers who behaved like automata, who
did exactly what they were told, and displayed neither independence nor ingenuity.
It was also believed that education could develop these traits. If it was unrealistic to
expect that every soldier would be a graduate of an elementary school, at a bare
minimum the corporals and sergeants – non-commissioned officers in general – would
have to be educated men. ‘Literate non-commissioned officers are a burning necessity
for contemporary armies’, wrote one Russian commentator in 1873.17 As a result of this
insight, governments throughout Europe took steps to make schools more numerous
and accessible. The notion that popular education was somehow indispensable to
national security put down roots, and it did so precisely because of the wars of German
unification. What was true of the American Civil War and Bismarck’s wars of unifica-
tion in the mid-nineteenth century is equally true of every major war fought since, for
military organizations have scrutinized them all in the hope of ascertaining their lessons.
Far from spurning the lessons of the past, most nations and their military establish-
ments have, by contrast, evidenced an insatiate desire to assimilate them. In the US
armed forces, for example, there are ‘lessons-learned’ databases; the army has a center
for the study of lessons learned; and there are 516 volumes in the Naval War College
Library that have the word ‘lessons’ in the title. What is true of the US military is true of
other militaries. Moreover, it has been true for an extremely long time. Once Frederick
the Great of Prussia happened to overhear some officers denigrate the value of studying
past wars and military theory, maintaining instead that personal experience was the only
source of military excellence. The king was moved to remark to them that he knew of
two mules in the army’s commissary corps that had served through 20 campaigns. ‘Yet’,
added Frederick ‘they are mules still.’18
It is hardly surprising that military organizations evince such profound curiosity about
the so-called ‘lessons’ of the past; knowledge of military history can be construed as
an inoculation against error and mistake in war, which at worst can produce defeat
and at the very best can exact an extremely high cost in blood. It was Bismarck, after all,
who observed that ‘fools say they learn from experience. I prefer to profit by others’
experience.’19
What is a military lesson? 25
There are two components to the question of military lessons. The first is the problem
of knowing what the lessons are. In Bismarck’s terms, how are we to comprehend what
are the precise elements of other people’s experience that we ought to absorb? To extract
useable lessons from the past, we have to interpret it, and interpretation can be skewed
by prejudice, pre-conceptions, and tacit assumptions. The second problem concerns the
action taken in response to this process of learning. The issue is one of receptivity – that
is, the degree to which a military organization actually embraces a lesson in practice and
alters the way in which it conducts business as a result.
The next war will not come off distinctly under the same conditions and circum-
stances as those of recent date. Experience of war can never be applied directly
to the future. The creative mind must anticipate experience of the future. Not
the lessons that the latest wars apparently or really have taught us must we adopt
indiscriminately in the next war, but what appears to us to be the most suitable after
close investigation of the likely conditions.48
On the face of it, this is a powerful and extremely intelligent statement. But this aperçu
does not, however, provide us with much guidance. How precisely do we determine
what the most ‘suitable’ lessons of any previous war are? Which lessons are we to accept
and which are we to exclude? Obviously, the judgment will be subjective. Employing the
familiar argument of pragmatic skepticism that wars were defined by the unique proper-
ties of time and place, Bernhardi insisted that key aspects of the Russo-Japanese War
were highly unlikely to be replicated in a general European war, since, among other
things, the scale and the geography of the theater would be so different.49
Thus, if the ‘linear projectors’ started with the presumption of continuity, Bernhardi
began with a presumption of discontinuity; and this, of course, was the significant excep-
tion. Whereas in Manchuria the terrain had been rugged and the fronts extremely atten-
uated, in a general European war the terrain would be flat, and millions of men would
What is a military lesson? 33
be engaged, permitting operations and attacks in depth. He employed the same logic to
explain why the European war would be short, rather than protracted, as the Russo-
Japanese War had been. Then, too, he criticized the idea that numerical superiority had
been a key to many of Japan’s victories by observing that bold and decisive generalship
could more than compensate for inferiority in numbers. In Bernhardi’s view, the coming
European war would be a short war of maneuver. Once again, this is exactly what
World War I was not.
Why did someone as capable as Bernhardi start with the presumption of disconti-
nuity? Why was he so obsessed with limning the differences between the war of 1904–05
and a general European war? Bernhardi gives the answer away in various places in his
book: he needed to imagine a war that he thought that Germany could win.50 If that war
were a war of lengthy fronts and trenches, then it would by definition be a protracted
war, a war of attrition. He believed that in such a conflict Germany and its allies would
sooner or later lose, since they would be outnumbered by the powers arrayed against
them – France, Russia, and perhaps Britain as well. To Bernhardi, this idea was imper-
missible and defeatist; accordingly, he censored his own thinking and rejected the possi-
bility of protracted war a priori and out of hand. In other words, his own personal
intellectual desires and needs decided for him what the useful lessons of the Russo-
Japanese War would be, and what would be the significant exceptions.
This brings me to my second point about receptivity, which is that military establish-
ments often prepare to fight the wars they would prefer to fight, rather than others that
may actually be more likely. Lest anyone think that this failing is not to be met with in
recent times, let me jump ahead to the US war in Vietnam. Some scholars maintain that
William Westmoreland’s relative neglect of counterinsurgency during his tenure at the
head of Military Assistance Command Vietnam can be explained by his fear of the costs
and risks to the US Army of a massive counterinsurgency campaign. He consequently
decided that he did not want to wage one and instead planned for a large-unit war
against the regular North Vietnam Army, a war with which the US Army would be
more comfortable and for which it was better prepared.51 This, of course, is not the only
possible interpretation of his actions. However, arguably, even if the large-unit war had
been a splendid success (which it was not), without a better program of counterinsur-
gency, US victory in Vietnam was simply not possible, given the constraints imposed on
the use of force there and the value of the political object to the United States in general.
In other words, what Westmoreland may actually have done was to fight the war he
preferred rather than the one he had.
Notes
1 In his Life of Reason, Santayana actually wrote: ‘Those who cannot remember the past are condemned
to fulfil it.’ Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree (New York:
Dover Publications, 1956), p. 6: ‘peoples and governments have never learned anything from
history, or acted on principles deduced from it’.
2 Bliokh was, of course, a pacifist who wanted to demonstrate that a future general war would be so
murderous, costly, and indecisive that it could not be considered a rational instrument of policy. He
wrote different sections of this massive work in Russian, Polish, and German. The first publication
was in Russian. I. S. Bliokh, Budushchaia voina v teknicheskom, ekonomicheskom i politicheskom otnosheniiakh,
6 vols (St Petersburg: I. Efron, 1898). The complete French translation has been reprinted: Jean de
Bloch [Ivan Bliokh], La guerre future aux points de vue technique, économique et politique, 6 vols (Paris:
Guillaumin, 1898–1900; reprint: New York: Garland, 1973).
3 On the ‘short-war illusion’ see Archer Jones, The Art of War in the Western World (Urbana and Chicago,
IL: University of Illinois Press, 1987), p. 423. See also Hew Strachan, The First World War, vol. I: To
Arms (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 74, 173, 1010–13. Strachan
presents a more nuanced interpretation of the ‘short-war illusion’ than has heretofore appeared in
the historical literature. He identifies a number of European statesmen and military leaders who,
prior to 1914, evidenced some awareness that a general war might become protracted. Nonetheless,
he also shows that European military establishments had generally planned for a short war.
4 I.A. Korotkov, Istoriia sovetskoi voennoi mysli (Moscow: Izdatel’stvo ‘Nauka’, 1980), pp. 143–4. Gabriel
Gorodetsky, Grand Delusion: Stalin and the German Invasion of Russia (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 1999), p. 127.
5 Nobutaka Ike, ed. and trans., Japan’s Decision for War: Records of the 1941 Policy Conferences (Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press, 1967), p. 153.
6 Lewis Sorley, A Better War: The Unexamined Victories and Final Tragedy of America’s Last Years in Vietnam
(New York: Harcourt Brace, 1999), pp. 4–5. See also Eric M. Bergerud, The Dynamics of Defeat: The
Vietnam War in Hau Nghia Province (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1991), pp. 89–90.
7 (No name given) ‘New Evidence on the Soviet Intervention in Afghanistan’, Cold War International
History Project Bulletin, 8–9 (winter 1996/97), pp. 128–84.
8 Carl von Clausewitz, On War, ed. and trans. Michael Howard and Peter Paret (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1976), pp. 88–9.
9 Jay Luvaas, The Military Legacy of the Civil War: The European Inheritance (Lawrence, KS: University
Press of Kansas, 1988), p. 126.
10 Col. John A. Warden III, USAF, ‘Employing Air Power in the Twenty-First Century’, in Richard
H. Schultz, Jr and Robert L. Pfaltzgraff, Jr (eds), The Future of Air Power in the Aftermath of the Gulf War
(Maxwell Air Force Base, AL: Air University Press, 1992), p. 80.
11 For example, the effects of the long bow became obvious to the French cavalry at the battle of
Poitiers in 1356, that is, almost 60 years before Agincourt. The result, as one scholar has put it, was
‘great changes in armor design intended in part to make men-at-arms less vulnerable to archery’.
Clifford J. Rogers, ‘The Efficacy of the English Long Bow: A Reply to Kelly DeVries’, War in History,
vol. 5, no. 2 (April 1998), p. 241. While it is true that at Cambrai in November 1917 the use of tanks
allowed the British to make an advance of 6,000 yards, there was no break-through and the perform-
ance of the tanks was quite properly regarded as mixed. See Paddy Griffith, Battle Tactics of the Western
Front: The British Army’s Art of Attack 1916–1918 (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994),
pp. 164–5. As for the sinking of the Ostfriesland, Billy Mitchell’s bombers did destroy it, but only by
dropping ‘bombs from an unrealistically low level to ensure fatal hits’: I.B. Holley, Jr, ‘Reflections on
the Search for Airpower Theory,’ in Col. Phillip S. Meilinger (ed.), The Paths of Heaven: The Evolution
of Airpower Theory (Maxwell Air Force Base, AL: Air University Press, 1997), p. 582.
12 Brian Bond, The Victorian Army and the Staff College, 1854–1914 (London: Eyre Methuen, 1972),
p. 157. Brian Holden Reid, Studies in British Military Thought (Lincoln, NB: University of Nebraska
Press, 1998), p. 136.
13 Luvaas, Military Legacy, pp. 128–42.