Critiquing Cultural Relativism
Critiquing Cultural Relativism
Critiquing Cultural Relativism
2013
Recommended Citation
Kanarek, Jaret (2013) "Critiquing Cultural Relativism," The Intellectual Standard: Vol. 2: Iss. 2, Article 1.
Available at: http://digitalcommons.iwu.edu/tis/vol2/iss2/1
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Ames Library, the Andrew W. Mellon Center for Curricular and Faculty
Development, the Office of the Provost and the Office of the President. It has been accepted for inclusion in Digital Commons @ IWU by
the faculty at Illinois Wesleyan University. For more information, please contact digitalcommons@iwu.edu.
©Copyright is owned by the author of this document.
The Intellectual Standard
I. INTRODUCTION
Cultural relativism is the ever-popular theory claiming that, "any
set of customs and institutions, or way of life, is as valid as any other:'l
In its appeal to tolerance-the seemingly incontrovertible "virtue" of the
modern era-it has gained wide appeal amongst myriad disciplines, most
notably in the social sciences.2 However, the theory is destructive in both
theory and practice. In theory, cultural relativism emphatically denies rea
son and objective reality.3 In practice, it sanctions the worst manifestations
of violence and oppression.
"A man's volition is outside the power of other men. What the unal
terable basic constituents are to nature, the attribute of a volitional
consciousness is to the entity 'man: Nothing can force a man to think.
Others may offer him incentives or impediments, rewards or punish
ments' they may destroy his brain by drugs or by the blow of a club,
but they cannot order his mind to function: this is in his exclusive,
sovereign power:'
beliefs, often breaking entirely with the dominant thought of their respec
tive eras. Aristotle, against the backdrop of centuries of mysticism, offered
the first rational philosophy in recorded history. Sir Isaac Newton rejected
the scientific theories of his time and fundamentally redefined physics and
the methods by which science was conducted. Our nation's founding fa
thers created a political system unlike that of any realized in their time.
All of these great men were unprecedentedly radical for their time,
somehow overcoming the supposed beliefs "ingrained into them:' Barring
volition, such feats would be neither possible nor explainable. In most of
the cases, the prevailing cultural attitude was fundamentally opposed to
the ideas and achievements of these men. If the notion of enculturation
held true, what would give rise to these unprecedented and radical men?
How and why did these men do what they did? The thoughts and actions
of these men were revolutionary in their respective eras, and it is doubtful
that some abstract cultural phenomenon necessitated these achievements.
For example, pre-Aristotelian philosophy condemned the material
world as illusory, instead praising the mystic realm of Forms (as Plato did),
or some other transcendental world, as the true and supreme reality.21 The
world had little knowledge or awareness of a non-mystic philosophy prior
to that of Aristotle's, and there was hardly any significant cultural impetus
for a philosophy of his kind. It was Aristotle's choice to think, evaluate, and
reject the dogma of his time that made his achievements possible.
Of course, the cultural relativist could claim that X or Y cultural
factor gave rise to these achievements, but such a claim is non -falsifiable
it is neither testable nor open to empirical investigation. To prove encul
turation, it would be necessary to provide a method by which a causal
relationship between generally held views and the specific content of an
individual's mind could be empirically shown. Such a method is not yet
possible, and even if it were, the cultural relativist would have to denounce
it as just another "culturally biased way of thinking that is no different from
magic or witchcraft:'
Not only that, but enculturation is an empirical delusion. The no
tion that moral rules, beliefs, values, and practices are "involuntarily" in
grained into the minds of individuals is absurd. Even the most susceptible
minds, such as those of children, do not operate in this way. Simply im-
mersing a child with moral rules and the like will neither garner their ac
ceptance nor ensure their practice. Instead, the child must actively seek to
understand and apply them by choice. As Rand observed about the learn
ing process:
This view is far from controversial. A child will not learn by osmo
sis if he is placed amidst other children in a classroom. At most, the child
may be able to parrot a concept of which he has no understanding, but he
will learn nothing without seeking to understand the content of the lesson
being taught. The fact that so much focus is placed on trying to get kids
interested in learning is evidence enough to prove this point. If children
simply absorbed knowledge presented to them with no volitional effort on
their part, their interest in learning would not be an issue.
Or take the basic skill of reading. A man could spend years locked
in a library full of books, yet he would not learn to read without actively
seeking to understand what was before his eyes. If he wants to read, he
must choose to open a book, make sense of the various markings, form
the concepts of letters, sounds, words, meanings, et cetera. Man's mind is
not filled with efficacious content "involuntarily:' Learning is not a passive
process.
For a theory that is supposed to assert "an empirical truth" about
man's nature, it is inexcusable that enculturation cannot be empirically
verified and explicitly prohibits progress in doing so. That enculturation is
grounded in a blatant empirical delusion about man's volitional nature and,
subsequently, his learning process, is arguably worse.
So far, cultural relativism has been shown to be vehemently op
posed to-and be without any basis in-reason and reality. By definition, it
is a rejection of both. In its formulation, it unapologetically necessitates an
untenable contradiction and evades crucial aspects of reality, such as man's
22 Ayn Rand, Return of the Primitive: The Anti-Industrial Revolution, pp. 68.
Vol. 2- Iss. 2 - 2013 9
The Intellectual Standard Critiquing Cultural Relativism
issue. During World War II, the German Nazis believed they had a moral
and valid claim to takeover of the rest of the world. One prominent expres
sion of this belief was the Nazi's principle of Lebensraum, or"living space;'
supposedly justifying national conquest as an ordained right of the Aryan
race for the purposes of natural development. Conversely, Poland main
tained and acted on the principle of national sovereignty. Despite these
diametrically opposed principles, Germany invaded Poland under the pre
tense that it had a right to do so, while Poland staunchly denied such a
right.
In the cultural relativist framework, however, the German claim
to Poland is just as valid as Poland's claim to sovereignty. Accordingly, the
Nazi fantasy of world domination and their practice of brutal invasions
and genocide are equally as valid as the idea of sovereignty and the prac
tice of it. On what basis, then, is Poland to claim a right to its sovereignty
when claims to its enslavement are equally as valid? The result is the moral
disarmament of the innocent-Poland would be left with few, if any, means
to effectively rebut Germany 's actions and justification.
As such, cultural relativism makes cross-cultural judgments im
possible-it leaves no means by which different ideas and practices of cul
tures can be judged. The result is obvious: the innocent are left morally
defenseless against their aggressors. Its framework-if taken to be true and
applied as such-automatically disarms the victims. It does so through
its universal denial of any standard by which an idea or practice may be
judged, at least cross-culturally.
But isn't it equally possible that the Nazi's are left with no means
to challenge Poland's claims to sovereignty? Isn't cultural relativism the
theory of tolerance that supposedly prevents acts of aggression? As Frank
Hartung, esteemed professor of sociology at Wayne State University, elo
quently answers:
" The Nazi thinks that it is right for him to exterminate Jews, con
demn without trial, appropriate foreign lands and kill resisting for
eign persons, violate international law, etc. Why is it right for him to
think and act thus? Because these are the accepted value judgments
of his culture. Hence it is right for him to follow them. The Ameri
can thinks that the opposites of the above value judgments are right.
Why? Because in the United States these are the accepted value judg
ments ... Each side can legitimately, on this theory, claim it is right
and both sides can be asserting true propositions:'25
Note that the innocent are left unable to challenge the claims of the
aggressors. Also note that the means by which each conviction is granted
validity is through the fact that they are convictions. Cultural relativism,
then, can only empower the aggressors: both by disarming the innocent
and sanctioning the aggressors' actions. With no means of adjudication,
it is no wonder why this scholar concludes that "ethical disagreements are
not solved by cultural relativism ... but rather one or the other party is dis
solved, liquidated:'26 This is not necessarily always the case, but granted a
zealous aggressor, it is more than likely.
V. CONCLUSION
Cultural relativism is destructive in both theory and practice. In
its theoretical denial of reason and objective reality, it sanctions the worst
forms of violence and oppression in practice. This is unsurprising; a theory
that adamantly denies reason and reality cannot be suitable for the latter,
nor be sound according to the former.