Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Simone Weil Religious Thougth

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 28

SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT IN THE

LIGHT OF CATHOLIC THEOLOGY


GEORGES FRfiNAUD, O.S.B.
Solesmes, France

That the Church is holy is an article of faith proclaimed in the Nicene


Creed. Striking evidence of this privilege is provided by those souls
who are called by God to great heights of the spiritual life. In the
history of Catholicism each century has plentiful examples to offer
of this intimate contact with God, and the Church has always paid
especial attention to them, gladly recognizing in them one of the endur-
ing signs of her divine mission.
Nevertheless, the Church's joy in recording the direct and consciously
felt action of God on souls has always been tempered with prudent
reserve. The greatest saints have themselves realized and pointed out
the dangers of illusion in the higher realms of the spiritual life. Ex-
treme caution is necessary. Such experiences cannot be accepted as
authentic until they have been subjected to careful examination, and
then only the supreme authority of the Church can pronounce upon
their validity.
In this study we are not concerned with extraordinary manifesta-
tions such as visions, private revelations, and ecstasies; we are con-
cerned only with that conscious form of loving and living with God
which is the normal, albeit rare, apogee of a spiritual life raised by
divine grace to the height of perfection. There is nothing astonishing
about this sort of experience when it occurs among saints whose
whole life has been developed in the faith, for visible membership in
the Body of Christ carries with it participation in the favorable condi-
tions in which sanctity should normally flourish. Difficulties begin to
arise when the type of mystical experience we are considering appears
to be granted to a soul not belonging to the visible community of the
Catholic Church, to a soul which has not known our religion, or which
has turned from it at the very moment when it believed it was receiv-
EDITOR'S NOTE.—This article represents, with minor omissions, the text of a lecture
given by Dom Georges Fr&iaud at the Catholic University of Angers. The translation
is the work of Stephen Deacon.
349
350 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

ing the direct rays of divine light. Is such a case possible? What are
we to think about it?
There are certain facts we must accept. The existence of authentic
mystics among people entirely ignorant of the Catholic faith is nowa-
days regarded as beyond question. Missionaries from the Far East
have provided evidence which cannot easily be rejected. Be that as it
may, there is another fact, this time beyond argument, which raises
the same question—the fact that there exist among pagans quite
large numbers of souls living in a state of friendship with God but
without any apparent link with the Church of Christ. Though they
cannot know it, these souls do receive their spiritual riches through
the mediation of the Church, whose prayers and Eucharist have a
mystical influence far beyond her visible boundaries.
The existence of a life of grace in souls making no external profession
of the Catholic faith raises the fundamental difficulty familiar to apolo-
gists—that of the salvation of unbelievers. The addition of mystical
experiences does not raise a new problem; it merely emphasizes the
degree of sanctity attainable by souls in involuntary ignorance. This
is the extremely difficult case of Simone Weil. The recent publication
of her notes, essays, and letters, too hastily made available to a very
wide public, has made known the extraordinary life of this "agnostic-
atheist" Jewess. She was a woman of exceptional intelligence and cul-
ture, familiar with Catholic doctrine, heroic in her faithfulness to the
precepts of evangelical morality, favored, it would seem, with numerous
mystical experiences, yet determinedly unbelieving about several es-
sential articles of faith, and for that reason unable, right up to the
time of her death, to receive baptism. She did not hesitate, moreover,
to show an aggressive hostility towards certain of the Church's atti-
tudes and teachings. She denied the Church's right to impose beliefs
on the faithful. Finally, she propounded the notion, based on her
personal supernatural experiences, that the easiest way to achieve
unity with God was to refrain from any explicit act of faith and even
from any intellectual affirmation about His existence.
Such an attitude is a serious matter—more serious than people seem
to think. If Simone did have mystical experiences—which would prove
that she enjoyed a life of grace—she constitutes the most difficult
possible case of the problem of the salvation of unbelievers. Nor is
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 351

this a mere academic problem. Simone's writings are not solely a


personal testimony; from this testimony is developed a spiritual doc-
trine which is in direct opposition to the Church's teaching on several
fundamental points. How can we reconcile the spiritual life of Simone
Weil with the serious deficiencies in her faith and the wilful errors
contrary to the Church's teaching to which she admitted?
i
We cannot be content with the completely negative answer, reached
by disposing of the problem with an adverse judgment—a judgment
which in any case no one in this world has the right to give. It could
be said that Simone Weil had, by her wilful and culpable refusal, cut
herself off from eternal life; that, as an "infidel" in the true sense of
the word, she remained all her life in a state of sin; that her mystical
experiences were no more than illusion. Nothing would remain to her
credit but genius, a highly refined aesthetic sense, prodigious learning,
natural virtues apparently unflawed, and above all complete sincerity,
while on the debit side there would be certain eccentricities and
exaggerations and a touch of intellectual pride. Such a solution, apart
from being overly simple and intolerably unjust, would involve the
risk of depriving us of a testimony which, if it really has any element
of the divine, is a gift of Providence we are not permitted to spurn.
There is a second solution, still negative but less radical. This would
admit as probable the state of grace and supernatural virtues of Simone
Weil but would dismiss her mystical experiences as illusory. Simone
would have believed, in good faith, that she had been in direct touch
with God but she would have been mistaken or deceived. There is no
lack of reasons to support such an idea; one need look no further than
Simone's own psychology. There is an unmistakable tendency to re-
gard intellectual intuition as divine inspiration. Her famous attitude of
"waiting," of which we shall speak again later, predisposed her to
accept as supernatural sudden and unexpected perceptions which
were by no means necessarily of divine origin. Above all, the devil
himself, whose intervention in the lives of even the greatest saints is
not rare, would have had the most powerful motives to cheat this
soul (deprived as it was of the support given by an explicit faith) of
the sacramental life and of the guidance of an enlightened spiritual
352 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

director. A diabolic illusion would in her case be an excellent means


of preventing her from turning to a fully explicit faith by making her
believe that she had achieved a mystical union with God by means of
religious beliefs which were for the most part wrong. The terrible
consequences of this illusory mysticism would probably be even greater
among readers who, in all good faith, accepted her testimony. Many
of them might be tempted to see in her mystical union with God the
confirmation of her ideas (wrong as they were) on faith and the spiri-
tual life.
But there are serious reasons for discounting this solution. When
the devil intervenes in matters like these, he always leaves unmistak-
able traces of his activity. There is no apparent sign of them in Si-
mone's writings, and the evidence of people who knew her, and who
observed her closely and at length, unreservedly confirms the impres-
sion of complete uprightness, of purity, and even of profound humility.
Certainly there was error, and even a certain amount of obstinacy in
error, but it seems that this was previous to and independent of her
mystical experiences.
The account of her contacts with God which appears in the auto-
biography addressed to Fr. Perrin plainly confirms this interpretation.
Its extreme soberness and its pure and radiant transparency are a
reflection of the divine. Listen to her own words:
I t was during one of these recitations [of George Herbert's poem, Love] that, as
I told you, Christ himself came down and took possession of m e . . . . Moreover, in
this sudden possession of me by Christ, neither my senses nor my imagination had
any part; I only felt in the midst of my suffering the presence of a love, like that
which one can read in the smile on a beloved face.1

Later, during an attentive recitation of the Our Father, the experi-


ence is renewed:
At times the very first words tear my thoughts from my body and transport it
to a place outside space where there is neither perspective nor point of view. The
infinity of the ordinary expanses of perception is replaced by an infinity to the
second or sometimes the third degree. At the same time, filling every part of this
infinity of infinity, there is silence, a silence which is not an absence of sound but

l
Simone Weil, Waiting for God, trans. Emma Craufurd (New York: Putnam, 1951),
p. 69.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 353

which is the object of a positive sensation, more positive than that of sound.
Noises, if there are any, only reach me after crossing this silence.
Sometimes, also, during this recitation or at other moments, Christ is present
with me in person, but his presence is infinitely more real, more moving, more
clear than on that first occasion when he took possession of me.2

It should be noted that in the first case quoted above Simone ex-
pressly excludes participation by the senses and imagination. Her ex-
periences seem to be strictly limited to the domains of pure intelli-
gence and love. Now theological teaching is that in these domains
the devil cannot act directly on the soul. Without being decisive, that
is one very good reason for discounting the theory of diabolic illusion.
Besides, descriptions like that are not imagined and everyone who
knew her agrees that Simone was incapable of lying. In any case, the
bare admission in this second possible solution that Simone Weil
enjoyed a supernatural life of grace and charity poses in all its force
the problem of reconciling such a life with her errors in matters of
faith. The mystical experiences add nothing essential to the problem
and there is therefore no a priori reason to reject them.
There remains, therefore, only one acceptable way of stating the
problem: to admit as probable (for there is no certainty in these mat-
ters, except perhaps in the case of canonized saints) that Simone, in
spite of her doctrinal shortcomings, lived, at least during the time she
had her mystical experiences, a lofty supernatural life, since she did
attain at times to a union of love with God. What then are we to make
of her errors?
One is tempted to reduce them to the inoffensive minimum, a
simple historical mistake about the Jewish people and the Catholic
Church and a failure to grasp the doctrine of the constitution of that
Church. All the rest could be written off as unimportant misunder-
standings. According to his preface to Gravity and Grace, this is the
stand taken by Gustave Thibon, who prudently disclaims any preten-
sions to theological competence.3 On the whole, a quick reading of
the aphorisms which make up this book confirms such a judgment.
Unfortunately, one is apt to forget that these thoughts were selected
and arranged by M. Thibon. When one compares them with the works
* Ibid., p. 72.
8
Cf. Simone Weil, Gravity and Grace, trans. Emma Craufurd (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1952), Introduction, p. xxix ff.
354 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

later published over her name, one is struck by the sharply different
impression they give. The highest motives impelled M. Thibon to make
a selection from the loose notes he received and to arrange them me-
thodically. One gets the impression that the selection, guided by a
very praiseworthy prudence, has unintentionally attenuated what
might otherwise have been a little too much for the faithful to swallow.
A more detailed study would perhaps show us that the editor has used
this means to give us a truer and more intimate picture of Simone. We
shall soon see that all that is most profound and true in her lies hidden
in the rough ore of error. Only someone who knew her and whose com-
petence is beyond question has the right or the means to separate the
gold from the dross.
Not being in the privileged position of M. Thibon, I believe we
must confine our attention in the main to her writings as she herself
left them in her notebooks and as they have recently been made
public. Despite the veil of so much error which hides the best in them,
they remain transparent enough for us to discern the supernatural
riches of a soul which, in spite of its shortcomings, undoubtedly received
signal favors from God. We shall devote the second part of this study
to the difficult task of making the distinction between the obvious
serious errors which swarm (I do not think the word is too strong)
from the pen of Simone Weil and the nucleus containing the precious
germ which, once isolated, has the most magnificent lights and re-
flections. For the moment we shall limit ourselves to admitting and,
as far as possible, explaining the antithesis between Simone's genuine
interior life and her denials of fundamental matters of faith.
According to traditional Catholic theological teaching, no super-
natural life is possible without a minimum of objectively explicit faith
in the existence of God and His rewarding providence. Now Simone
Weil has declared on several occasions that before her experience of
union with Christ she had always maintained a complete abstention
from any intellectual judgment on the existence of God. "As soon as I
reached adolescence, I saw the problem of God as a problem the data
of which could not be obtained here below, and I decided that the
only way of being sure not to reach a wrong solution, which seemed to
me the greatest possible evil, was to leave it alone."4
4
Waiting for God, p. 62.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 355

During the whole of her life she continued to believe that for a soul
which has not yet experienced contact with God, the attitude most
favorable to this contact is one of complete agnosticism with regard
to the intellectual problem of God. She herself on several occasions
referred to this intellectual position (which was for so long her own
and which, according to her, is the ideal position for beginners),
denominating it "atheistic agnosticism.''
She emphasized it particularly in her autobiography in terms which
leave no room for doubt: "I was brought up by my parents and my
brother in complete agnosticism and never made the slightest attempt
to get away from it. And, rightly in my opinion, I never had the slight-
est wish to do so." We shall come back to this "atheism" later, but it
is important first of all to fix Simone's attitude towards the problem
of faith as it is presented by the teaching of the Catholic Church. To
her the Church's teaching seemed neither rational nor useful; on the
contrary, it appeared to be an obstacle to union with God.

But to add dogma to this conception of life [the Christian conception], without
being forced to do so by indisputable evidence, would have seemed to me like a
lack of honesty. I should even have thought I was lacking in honesty had I con-
sidered the question of the truth of dogma as a problem for myself or even had I
simply desired to reach a conclusion on this subject.5
The special function of the intelligence requires total liberty, implying the
6
right to deny everything
He who has not heard this word [the word of God in the secrecy of the soul],
even if he adheres to all the dogmas taught by the Church, has no contact with
truth.7
. . . my vocation imposes upon me the necessity of remaining outside the Church,
without so much as engaging myself in any way, even implicitly, to her or to the
8
dogmas of Christianity
. . . that my thought should be indifferent to all ideas without exception, includ-
9
ing for instance materialism and atheism

She taxes with totalitarianism the Catholic idea of faith, which


she describes in the following terms: "Unconditional adherence to the
Church. That is what St. Thomas, as well as the Catechism of the
Council of Trent, calls faith."10 A few pages later she calls this faith
7
* Ibid., p. 66. • Ibid., p. 78. Ibid., p. 80.
8
Ibid., p. 85. • Loc. cit.
10
La connaissance surnaturelle (12th ed.; Paris: Gallimard, 1950), p. 79.
356 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

"social idolatry."11 She copies word for word a paragraph on faith


from the Catechism of the Council of Trent and adds the abrupt
and brutal comment, "Bad!"12
It is therefore not only the content of the Catholic faith which she
rejects but our whole concept of faith and the manner in which we
exercise it. She rejects all idea of a submission of the intelligence to a
divine authority exercised by the Church. To my mind this attitude
constitutes the most powerful argument against the reality of authen-
tic supernatural life in the case of Simone Weil. The deviation—
rather, the opposition—is found right at the basis of her concept of
the religious life; this deviation shows up on every page of her work,
even on the most moving ones. Quite often also, on account of this
permanent undertone, certain passages which seem perfectly good to
us (because we interpret them in a Catholic context) have actually
quite a different, and in fact erroneous, meaning.
Faced with this "black list," in which we have made no attempt to
minimize anything which adds to the difficulty of our problem, we
are strongly tempted to give up the attempt and to leave to God alone
and His infinite mercy the task of solving a problem towards the solu-
tion of which the available data give us no lead. It is certain that all
Simone's assertions which we have just quoted on the subject of
atheism and the Catholic faith are errors which we are bound to re-
ject. However, the writings of Simone are so transparent that it does
not seem completely hopeless to try to discover therein indications of
the action of grace and of the private dispositions which made it pos-
sible. Let us come back, first of all, to Simone's "atheism." M. Thibon
has given us on this subject a text which even by itself can calm some
of our fears:
A case of contradictory truths. God exists: God does not exist. What is the
problem? I am perfectly certain that there is a God in the sense that I am certain
that my love is not an illusion. I am perfectly certain that there is no God in the
sense that I am certain that there is no real being resembling the conception I
have when I use the word God. But that which I cannot conceive is not an il-
lusion.13

I believe St. Thomas Aquinas might have put his name to such a
formula of "atheism," though he would have noted at the same time
11 18
Ibid., p. 82. ^ Ibid., p. 164. Gravity and Grace, p. 103.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 357

that there was nothing really contradictory about it. It is true that
Simone gives it a meaning which St. Thomas would not have accepted,
since for her nothing real, absolutely nothing, corresponds to what
we conceive under the appellation God, whereas in Christian philos-
ophy our concepts allow us not only to reach certainty about the
existence of God but also to have some imperfect yet objective knowl-
edge of Him.
In the text which M. Thibon quotes immediately afterwards, Si-
mone remarks that there are "two atheisms, of which one is a purifica-
tion of the notion of God."14 But St. Thomas also recognized the need
for a "way of negation" to purify any assertion we make about God.
When we have said that God exists, we must always add that He does
not exist in our way of thinking of existence. It is a part of our approach
to transcendence, which affirms the existence of a God greater than
anything we can conceive of Him. Undoubtedly, Simone exaggerated
the negative side of this concept and did not see beyond it on the plane
of conceptual intelligence. This extreme position is based on a false
notion of knowledge and certainty, which in her view can only result
from a real and immediate contact with the object. She held that to
rise above atheism one must experience God, and said on several
occasions that only mystics had ceased to be atheists.
But Simone has revealed the existence in herself of a psychological
act, or rather a permanent attitude, which implies, without any ver-
bal expression or clear-cut formulation, a profound belief—nay, a
faith—in the reality which she considered as conceptually unknow-
able, the reality we call God. This belief of hers has an experimental
basis; it is the recognition of her own misery, her own impotence,
what in philosophy we should call her contingency (i.e., the fact of ex-
isting without having any inherent right to exist).
Moreover, from the start of her spiritual life Simone really believed
that she had a call, a vocation, an obligation which required her to
adopt an attitude basically Christian. She submitted to it immediately
and unreservedly.
. . .1 never hesitated in my choice of an attitude; I always adopted the Chris-
tian attitude as the only possible one. I might say that I was born, I grew up,
and I always remained within the Christian inspiration. While the very name of
u
hoc. cit.
358 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

God had no part in my thoughts, with regard to the problems of this world and
this life I shared the Christian conception in an explicit and rigorous manner,
with the most specific notions it involves.16

From the start she had a feeling of obligation which was not only
moral but also religious, in the sense that she saw herself as required
to perform actions impossible for human nature alone. Only a superior
strength, a supernatural strength, would allow her to perform them.
She placed herself thus unmistakably in a supernatural perspective.
Everything she did, in fact, implied the existence of an Absolute, a
Creator of the material world and of souls, who gives to the latter the
feeling of having a supernatural duty and (in the measure that they
submit, wait, and consent) the supernatural means necessary to carry
it out. This certainty, finding concrete expression in a submission
which aimed at being complete and absolute, was by no means
hindered by her awareness of her own misery. On the contrary, it was
her misery which seems to have given divine supernatural aid (soon
to be called love) its great opportunity. In this attitude it is pos-
sible to recognize, implicit but real, an imperfect form of the initial
movement of the soul towards faith and justification described by
the Council of Trent (Session VI, Chapter 5).16 There is a certain
faith in God and His supernatural providence in the attitude of "wait-
ing on God" which is the primary and fundamental attitude of Si-
mone's soul. No one had a greater sense of God's mercy. Later on we
shall have to make considerable reservations in the matter of her
exclusion of the idea of merit and reward; even so, she believed in a
rewarding Providence which gives to each faithful soul what it has
caused it to desire.
How is it that this attitude did not lead Simone to &fidesex auditu,
the intellectual adherence accorded to an explicit revelation, which
would have broadened into a profession of the Catholic faith? The rea-
son is that there was the obstacle of an intelligence at one and the
same time extremely alert and yet hindered in its objective develop-
ment by a mass of faulty prejudices and, most of all, by a wrong con-
cept of knowledge. This was an obstacle all the more insurmountable
18
Waiting for God, pp. 62-63.
16
Denziger-Bannwart-Umberg, Enchiridion symbolorum (ed. 24-25; Barcelona: Herder,
1948), n. 797.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 359

because it concerned an intelligence sincerely and unyieldingly at-


tached to what it considered to be the basic and immutable laws of
thought. On account of this prejudice, faith was to her something
that could be neither visualized nor expressed and, more serious still,
something which could never be acquired by external instruction. If
this attitude had implied any ill-will or culpability on Simone's part,
it would have constituted an obstacle to any spiritual life. However,
it seems that in fact she did not incur this responsibility in the initial
disaster which closed her mind to the reception of any divine revela-
tion conveyed by the verbal and conceptual teaching of a human
intermediary.
By contrast, in her innermost soul there was complete submission
to everything that was recognized as a call or a duty coming from a
transcendent other world, in itself unknown. Such submission is partly
natural: submission to those circumstances of our life which are beyond
our control (acceptance of the laws of the universe and the expressions
of the divine will which we call "necessities")* absolute submission to
the natural moral law and to the obligations imposed by social condi-
tions. But there is also something of the supernatural in this submis-
sion when the soul is aware of an interior inspiration within itself of
which it recognizes the absolute value without explicitly knowing its
origin. Simone often describes this inspiration in the form of an at-
traction exercised by an absolute supernatural good, which for her is
the only good. Later she gives it its true name of supernatural love,
which she conceives to be not so much the love of the creature for
God as the love of God Himself informing the creature in order that
the creature may share in its own motion. The submission of the
natural faculties (understanding and will) to this absolute good, to
this supernatural love, is what constitutes faith for her. This submission
is "waiting," desire and love; it is based on one absolute certainty,
that a real desire for the real good is never in vain. In other words,
God never refuses Himself to anyone who, by reason of grace, consents
to desire Him: those who ask for bread are not given stones. To end
with, we must quote from her American Notebooks a passage which
gives the most recent expression of her thought on this matter.
That God is goodness is certain. It is a definition. That in some way—unknown
to me—God is reality, that too is certain. These are not matters of faith. But to
360 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

believe that each thought by which I desire the good brings me nearer to it, that
is faith. I cannot know this except by faith. And even when I have known it, it
still is not a matter of established fact but remains a matter of faith.
Since the possession of goodness consists in desiring it, the object of the article
of faith in question—and it is the sole article of true faith—is the self-multiplica-
tion of every desire for the good.
The mere fact that a soul desires this goodness purely, truly, and exclusively
with a part of itself, means that at some later time it will desire it with a greater
part of itself . . . unless it refuses its consent to this transformation.
To believe that is to have faith.17

Do not let us misunderstand the meaning of this desire: it is the


desire for a real good and therefore, for Simone, the desire for super-
natural good, and cannot be achieved without supernatural aid. The
passage quoted gives a very elevated view of the intimate personal
aspect of faith.
We must, however, recognize that this personal aspect is only a part
of it. To make this concept of faith the sole guiding principle of one's
whole spiritual life is to destroy the foundations of Christianity and
open the door to illuminism. It is, unfortunately, to render oneself
inaccessible to all external apostolic action. Religion is reduced to pure
mysticism without any exterior control or guidance. The soul can
only be moved from within by God Himself and rejects in advance
any step which it does not feel a supernatural interior call to take.
The whole attitude of Simone, right up to her death, stems from this
initial lack in her.
This lack did not, however, have for Simone all the disastrous effects
which it might have had. Since it was the result of an intellectual ob-
stacle which did not involve any wilful fault, it did not constitute an
absolute barrier to divine grace. In spite of this imperfection, which
had no taint of sin, God took the initiative in a work of grace. In
effect, He gave to Simone's innermost soul the first impulse, the first
attraction, which she welcomed without knowing its source, knowing
only that it did not derive from her own will but from a transcendent
otherness to which she owed absolute submission. This divine initiative
is all the more outstanding in her case on account of the deficiency
in intellectual light which, in the ordinary way, would be rendered
supernatural by explicit faith and would have accompanied the grace.
La connaissance surnaturdle, p. 275.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 361

Simone was faithful to this first grace; by its help she did all that it
was possible for her to do, and God continued to give her interior guid-
ance to make up for what is normally the work of the mind and of
explicit faith. We have two indications, which it would be difficult
to refute, that this (too exclusively) interior faith of Simone's did
implicitly embrace the mystery of Christ. The first of these is the fact
that from her first contact with the Gospels Simone recognized that
her interior life had been, unknown to her, a really Christian life.
The second is that Christ revealed Himself to this soul in a mystical
experience of love. In spite of so many deficiencies, there was at the
root of Simone's spiritual life an element of faith sufficient, with God's
grace making up for what was lacking, to allow her to make the act
of supernatural charity necessary to purify her soul and place her in a
state of friendship with God. That is, we must believe, the only explana-
tion of how this soul could have attained the mystical union of love
which marks the approach to supernatural perfection.
Let us conclude this first study with a brief recapitulation. Simone's
case remains an exceptional one and one that can never be regarded as
a normal example of Christian life. The path she followed was valid
for her alone, taking into account all her circumstances. It would be
false and dangerous for others to imagine that their circumstances are
the same. Any sincere unbelievers or non-practicing Christians who
think to find comfort in her example must first satisfy themselves that
their prejudices and their ignorance are really invincible and that there
is no taint of culpability. They must be able to say, like Simone, that
they have been faithful to interior grace to a heroic degree. Lastly,
they must see whether they have followed her example in adopting a
Christian attitude which has done more than merely make them be-
have like well-brought-up people. This attitude should also have led
them to a practice of continuous asceticism, renunciation, perfect
charity, daily meditation on the Gospel, attentive attendance at Holy
Mass and the Divine Office (like that of Simone at Solesmes in 1938
when "the thought of Christ's passion entered into her once for all
time"), and lastly to that intense love of the Blessed Sacrament which
is perhaps the most reassuring thing about the last phase of Simone's
life. Most people who managed to keep pace with her that far would
find no difficulty in embracing explicitly the entire beliefs of the Church.
362 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

There is one other reason for not allowing Christians to take Simone
as a model of the spiritual life: that is the initial error which closed
her mind to explicit belief in the Church and in the long run influenced
all her religious thinking. Perfect sincerity, genius, even supernatural
love, cannot make truth out of falsehood. In the second part of this
study we shall see the striking contrast her errors make with the
treasure of goodness and beauty which constitute the only acceptable
part of her most moving testimony.
H

It is not without a certain hesitation that one approaches Simone


Weil's work with the object of setting its content alongside the funda-
mental truths of philosophy, and one has even greater scruples about
confronting it with the teachings of the Catholic faith. Simone herself
would have been the first to disallow such a comparison. Was she not
constantly setting her conception of intellectual liberty against any
a priori compulsion or doctrinal authority? Moreover, in confronting
her writings with a system of teaching from which she deliberately
remained aloof, is one not running the risk of forcing them into a
rigid framework which will distort and falsify them? The great danger
here lies in taking ideas having their origin and development in an
atmosphere of phenomenological psychology and placing them in a
content of ontological realism inspired by Aristotelian philosophy.
The difference between these two systems is not just one of vocabulary;
the whole thought content is different. To avoid misrepresentation
one would have to translate one into the terms of the other, and even
then one would risk being led astray by a faulty translation.
We shall therefore not waste time on the impossible and useless
task of making a literal comparison between Simone Weil's texts and
the theses of theology or Christian philosophy. We shall deal only with
certain fundamental points in her thought and try to see the extent
to which they can be reconciled, not with a scientifically elaborated
philosophic system nor even with the canons of a Council, but with
the primary self-evident truths of common-sense and with what the
Church has received from Christ's own lips. For it was in the name
of truth and of Christ that Simone, too, purported to speak.
Straightway Simone brings us up short—she is a mystic directly
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 363

instructed by God. Her experience is therefore infallible and beyond


all human question. Has God not the right, if He so wishes, to speak
in a language different from that which He used to express the public
revelation confided to the Church? By what token has the latter any
right to pronounce upon the intimate confidences Christ makes to
His friends?
Let us first of all dispose of the basic error of this plea in bar. God
does not speak in different languages to mystics and to the Church,
for in real mystical experiences (we are not talking of visions and proph-
ecy) God uses no language at all. He manifests Himself in a contact
of pure love in which there are neither words nor images nor, it seems,
ideas. Words and thoughts are the means used by the mystic when
trying to analyze and express the experience. Normally, therefore, the
mystic when expressing himself will make use of ideas and words which
are familiar to him.
It goes without saying that these words and ideas are not necessarily
taken from the ecclesiastical vocabulary of Christian dogma. Never-
theless, so long as the words used remain close to the experience they
describe, they cannot expound notions of the Divine Being contrary
to those taught by the Church. The Church is not merely the first
of all mystics, receiving her revelation from the lips of the Word
Incarnate; she is also the infallible mouthpiece for the transmission
of this revelation and is guaranteed from error by the perennial sup-
port of the Holy Spirit. She cannot be mistaken in matters of faith.
By contrast, other mystics (we exclude the sacred authors), even
after entirely authentic experiences, are not infallible and can be mis-
taken in their account of their experience and still more in the rational
interpretation of their relations with God. Only the Divine is infallible;
anything added by man runs the jisk of deviating from the truth, and
the more personal thought man gives to it, the greater is the risk of
deviation. An absolutely direct, simple, and unornamented account
has a very good chance of being true. Deductions, attempts to explain,
a great deal of thought and imagery, all tend to open the door to error.
What verification can there be of these accounts, then, except by
putting them alongside some certain knowledge, either that of natural
reason when all the relevant facts are knowable, or that of the Church
when it is a matter within the scope of her infallibility?
364 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

One does not, of course, reject the evidence of a mystic just because
he does not use the same vocabulary as the theologians. We are not
concerned with the words themselves but with what they are intended
to convey. It is perfectly possible that private revelation may make
known something which is not embodied in the explicit teaching of
the Church. The over-all perspective of collective revelation is a very
different thing from the intimate personal point of view engendered by
an intimate union of love in the depths of the soul. Nevertheless, any
divergences between the two revelations can never amount to real
contradictions. God is absolute truth and, whatever Simone Weil may
have had to say about it, truth in its singleness and perfect simplicity
never contradicts itself. Not even the most unfathomable mysteries
of the faith contain any real and serious contradiction; the occasional
appearance of contradiction is entirely due to the limitations of our
understanding.
From the above considerations we can draw the following conclusion
of capital importance. Every time a real contradiction between the
evidence of a mystic and the teaching of the Church is apparent, we
must admit either that the mystical experience was illusory and had
nothing of the divine in it, or that the mystic has added some human
error to the evidence of authentic experience. It is not always easy to
decide between these two alternatives: only an experienced spiritual
director, wise in the interpretation of souls, could prudently give judg-
ment. Based on my faith in just such a judgment, I have accepted the
probability that Simone's experiences were genuine. We are then
faced with the second alternative each time her thought comes into
conflict with the truth as taught by the Church.
We need not be surprised if we are constantly coming upon this
situation in her writings. Simone was not only a mystic; she was also
a great reasoner who never ceased turning her thoughts over from one
day's end to another. Unfortunately, her philosophy rests on an in-
trinsically unsound foundation. It is therefore to be expected that,
even after a genuine mystical contact with God, she would be unable
to express her experience, even less to relate it to the rest of her intel-
lectual life, without a generous admixture of error.
One remarkable fact in her writings seems to confirm the point we
have just made. Throughout her work, in the midst of page after page
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 365

of writings more or less contaminated, one comes across one which is


purer and full of light and freshness. For the moment, the imperfections
of the interpreter are lost and the highest part of the soul is allowed to
find expression with so true an accent and so perfect a transparency
that it is difficult not to recognize the evidence of God's presence.
Though it is by no means infallible, a sign like this taken in conjunction
with a life of asceticism and heroic charity is almost unchallengeable.
That being so, how are we to answer Simone's plea that the Church
was not competent to judge? We can make her one concession—the
divine, transcendent element of mystical experience, when it is genu-
ine, is not subject to the judgment of the Church. But it is for the
Church, if she thinks fit, to recognize or deny the genuineness. More,
the conceptual and verbal expression given to the experience, and the
interpretations and deductions made from it, are human actions into
which error can easily slip. These are therefore properly subject to
the verification and judgment of the Church.
The idea that an individual who has reached the height of mystical
union with God can put the divine favor forward as a guarantee for
all his thoughts and philosophical, moral, and spiritual teachings is
quite unacceptable. We can, therefore, even while we do not neces-
sarily reject all the mystical value of Simone's testimony, draw a line
in her writings between the truths, which may have resulted from an
intimate relation with God, and the errors, which certainly came from
some other source.
A thing that is most noticeable in Simone's writings is the consider-
able space devoted to a sort of perpetual contradiction in her thoughts,
her actions, and her attitudes. A portrait of her would be just an
assemblage of contradictions. She was atheistic yet mystic; a Jewess
yet passionately anti-Semitic; attached to the Catholic Church yet
very hard on it; an artist of genius yet careless how she presents her-
self and of her personal appearance. Her intelligence was unceasingly
at work, yet she underestimated the value of reason; passionately
devoted to humility and renunciation, she obstinately refused the guid-
ance of friends and the services of a spiritual director.
She also seems to have had a mania for contrariness. In almost all
problems she seems instinctively to have chosen the answer contrary
to the general consensus. Her original interpretations of Scripture
366 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

show up this trait in high relief; one has only to look at her reading
of the story of Noah's three sons or her interpretation of the parable
of the prodigal son.
It is no mere chance that this motif occurs throughout her work.
She herself saw contradictions everywhere. One is tempted to say
that she went out looking for them—or, if that is not quite the right
word to apply to her, that she "waited'' for them and never let one
pass unnoticed. Even more, confronting a direct contradiction was,
to her way of thinking, the best possible thing for the human intelli-
gence, just as a completely insurmountable obstacle was the best
thing for spiritual development. In this connection one should read
the two chapters of Gravity and Grace called "The Impossible" and
"Contradiction."18 Here, in any case, are some of her statements:
"Human life is impossible."19 "Our life is impossibility, absurdity."20
"The contradictions the mind comes up against—these are the only
realities: they are the criterion of the real."21 "All truth contains a
contradiction."22 A passage from the American Notebooks gives us
the origin of this tendency: "Plato's scale of cognition [from perception
to dialectic] has this significance alone: to prepare the intellect to rise
to the point where it can grasp the simultaneous truth of contradic-
tions."23
What result can be expected from this philosophy of the absurd?
Nothing, apparently, save scepticism. But that is not Simone's idea.
For her, the absurdity which is an obstacle in our way of thinking
and acting is a lever by which the soul is to be raised to a higher plane.
It puts us in a position of having to "wait" for an infinitely greater
transcendent force or light which will resolve the contradiction or the
impossibility. This light or force constitutes the supernatural, which
is essentially love (love of God, she specified later). And it is a divine
gift which we can neither procure nor attain to on our own; God alone
can give it to us. So long as we are without it, all that is real seems
absurd to us and all good is illusory and vain; real good can be seen
by us only as something unattainable by our own unaided powers.
This would be the gift made to Simone, "agnostic atheist" as she was,
18 19
Cf. Gravity and Grace, pp. 86-93. Ibid., p. 86.
21
™Loc.cit. Jta*.,p.89.
22 u
Loc. cit. La connaissance sumaturelle, p. 50.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 367

the day that God, in response to her "waiting," came down and filled
her with His supernatural light.
What are we to make of such a philosophy and of such a method of
disposing of the absurdities which baffle our reason? One's first instinct
is to reject out of hand a construction based on a premise which is
irreconcilably opposed to reason, does away with all possibility of
thinking or doing, and is the negation of the principle of non-contradic-
tion, first law of realism and rational thought.
We must be chary, however, about such a drastic judgment. To do
justice to Simone's method, we must put ourselves in her position.
She maintained (and this is where she really goes wrong) that human
intelligence, by its natural limitations, is incapable of knowing any-
thing beyond the material actualities of the physical world in which
it lives. Now God is outside this material sphere. Therefore, for any-
one capable of knowing only the finite realities perceptible by the
senses, one must admit that the whole world is a contradictory enigma:
it is something which exists but has no right or reason to do so. If
everything real is contingent, then everything real is absurd. To escape
this absurdity, sound reasoning leads one to posit a necessary Being,
a God, who is the raison d'etre of everything. This approach, however,
will not do for Simone. It would be a verbal, a conceptual solution
without any real value, and in her view we must therefore resign our-
selves loyally to the absurd and admit that our reason cannot explain
it away.
We can escape it, however, if we know how to desire and to "wait."
For what? That one does not know; if one did, there would be no prob-
lem. To "wait" without knowing whether there is anything to wait
for, to wait naked and without object, that, without our knowing
anything about it and vastly to our surprise, will give us God. The
mere action of desiring Him, in fact, will give Him to us because,
clearly, if He did not exist there could be no such desire. But if we
remain faithfully "waiting," He will reveal Himself clearly, He will
show us that this desire, this love which causes us to wait, is no work
of ours but is His doing; it is His own love which passes into us, for
God alone can love God. To be aware of this love is to make a genuine
contact with God, and thereby we shall resolve the contradictions
which our intellect has confronted.
368 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

This method is not without its defects and its dangers; it is not,
however, the complete tissue of contradictions that it at first appears.
It seems that for Simone at any rate, who followed it with faithful
heroism, it brought results. She does seem to have attained actual
knowledge of God through supernatural love. We must beware, how-
ever, of accepting this process as normal or general and we must bear
in mind that the results are not really certain. In most cases it would
result in utter failure. It would open the door wide to pseudo-mysti-
cism. For Catholics, it would entail disregarding the teaching of the
Church and would jeopardize our faith. Modernism itself would be
at home in this system.
Moreover, though Simone's supernatural knowledge enabled her
to resolve the contradictions which human reason could not, she was
only to find herself faced on a higher plane with new ones just as
insoluble. She believed that the mysteries of the faith were strictly
contradictory. It is true—and we are constantly compelled to come
back to this—that she judged purely the appearances of things, the
phenomenon as psychologically perceived. Even from that angle,
however, it is a mistake to assume an absolute and evident contradic-
tion between the natural and the supernatural, between reason and
faith. The Vatican Council has solemnly proclaimed that there is no
disharmony between revelation and the natural truths accessible to
mankind. When Simone, therefore, accuses all who try to reconcile
reason with faith of being heretical, she is completely on the wrong
track. The heresy would be to explain away the mystery, to show posi-
tively that there is no contradiction; by contrast, the task of the Catho-
lic theologian is to show, negatively, that the apparent contradictions
of our religion are never clear or certain and that there is a means,
unknown to us, of resolving them.
There is another point in Simone's thinking which, like the last, is
heavy with consequences—the psychological structure of the human
soul. Considering no more than spiritual activity in this sphere, Simone
distinguishes three faculties; two of them are natural—understanding
and will; the third is "supernatural love." There is material for a
whole book to be written about this keystone of Simone's spiritual
doctrine, her concept of supernatural love (which would have been a
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 369

much more suitable title for her book than Connaissance surnaturelle,
supernatural knowledge), but we shall have to confine ourselves here
to a few short remarks.
Simone separates and contrasts "love" and "will." That is to say,
for her real love (supernatural love) is not something achieved by our
souls but an act of God in us; all we do is to receive it. The whole
function of our understanding and will consists solely in submitting
to it.24 She frequently repeats that only God can love God. Our natural
faculties are therefore entirely passive in relation to this love. This is a
grave error which, despite Simone's remarkable asceticism, tends to-
wards quietism, and this in turn does away with merit and with all
true supernatural life.
Simone herself has several ways of looking at this love. Sometimes
she makes it a constituent part of the soul (its fine pointe); sometimes
she describes it as an act of God which must pass through the soul
as through a sort of tube whose perfection would lie in offering no
resistance to its passage. She also identifies this love with God Him-
self substantially present in the soul.
Any reader with the slightest knowledge of the Church's spiritual
teaching will recognize in these inexact concepts a certain measure
of truth, enough to lend to one aphorism or another an often very
profound orthodox meaning. But caution is imperative. In a form of
words which is perfectly accurate as we understand it, Simone man-
ages to express an entirely different and much less acceptable idea.
Against all these affirmations of Simone we must oppose the cer-
tain truth that the love of God is always an act of our souls—or rather,
of our will reinforced by divine grace and the infused virtue of charity.
Once we have grasped this point, we can admit that in the highest
forms of mystical experience the human understanding is no longer
conscious of anything but God's uncreated love working on the soul,
or more precisely, of the effects produced in the soul by the divine
love. From the psychological standpoint, everything that happens in
the soul is the action of God. Let me repeat that this is the attitude
which Simone consistently adopts. But in fact, even in these conditions,
the soul itself is also active; the understanding is aware of what is
24
Cf. the essay, "The Love of God and Affliction," in Waiting for God, pp. 117-36.
370 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

happening and the will returns love for love. Now that is action, that
is life; it is, in fact, the highest form of life here below. There is noth-
ing higher but the beatific vision of eternity.
We find another curious mixture of truth and error in the concept
that Simone, now a mystic, has of creation. The point is relevant since
it is, as it were, the ontological basis of the mistakes of her thinking.
On God's part creation is not an act of self-expansion but of restraint and re-
nunciation. God and all his creatures are less than God alone. God accepted this
diminution. He emptied a part of his being from himself. He had already emptied
himself in the act of his divinity; that is why St. John says that the Lamb has
been slain from the beginning of the world. God permitted the existence of things
distinct from himself and worth infinitely less than himself. By this creative act
he denied himself, as Christ has told us to deny ourselves. God denied himself for
our sakes in order to give us the possibility of denying ourselves for him.25

In the American Notebooks she wrote again: "God is not omnipo-


tent, since He is Creator. Creation means abdication. But He is omnipo-
tent in the sense that His abdication is voluntary. He knows the results
of it and wills them."26 Further on in the same book we come to the
climax of these astonishing assertions: "Creation and original sin are
but two facets, different to us, of a unique act of abdication by God."27
"What from God's point of view is creation, is sin from the creature's
point of view."28
How can we attempt to justify these paradoxes? We cannot help
asking ourselves if their author is not just deliberately misconstruing
the most self-evident truths. To start with, there is.a completely false
idea of creation, which Simone sees as a sort of pantheistic emanation.
God transforms a part of His substance into each creature; this would
entail a degradation of the divine Being. There is also a sort of mathe-
matical misconception: God, who occupies all space, has to diminish
Himself in order to make room for His creatures. All this is very far
removed from the Catholic doctrine of creation, and it is easy to see
how in Simone's conception this divine action constitutes the impos-
sible realization of a perfect contradiction.
Onto this primary error there are grafted many others which we
26
Waiting for God, p. 145.
26
La connaissance surnaturelle, p. 67.
27
/taf.,p.91. **Ibid.,p. 168.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 371

can only note in passing. Creation, which would be a sin for the crea-
ture, is an absolute necessity for God. Without it He would not have
been able to become man, and without the Incarnation there could
have been no God the Son. Thus, for Simone the supreme mystery of
the Trinity is the result of the Incarnation, original sin, and creation.
And since this mystery is necessary, it follows that its causes are as
well.
It also happens sometimes, as we have had occasion to note, that
Simone Weil associates with her fallacious notions certain truths of
which she became directly aware in the course of the development of
her interior life. It is on her false concept of creation as renunciation
that she bases her ascetic doctrine of self-denial by the creature. The
soul makes a space within itself to allow room for God and permit
its own divinization. Many moving pages are devoted to asceticism
and total renunciation, pages which, read in the context of Catholic
doctrine, have a truth and beauty worthy of the great spiritual masters.
But replace them in the framework of Simone's doctrine and they show,
if not error, at least some serious lack. We have already remarked how,
with her, asceticism lacks the positive and supernatural element which
gives it its efficacity. There is wanting the real supernatural love of the
creature for its God.
Attached to this doctrine of creation is an opinion, also sadly defec-
tive, on the final destiny of the human soul. Simone conceived the soul
as an amalgam of two elements—one natural, the understanding and
the will; the other divine, supernatural love, which could only really
exist in the souls of mystics or of those on the path to mysticism. What
happens at death? The animal part disappears and nothing is left
but the supernatural love, which is not a created being but God Him-
self. Nothing of the individuality of the soul, therefore, survives death.
For a clear definition of this tragic and hopeless opinion we must
refer to the American Notebooks. It is obviously useless to try to
reconcile this notion with the Catholic teaching on man's last end.
The error is absolute: it is pantheism and the denial of all personal
immortality of the soul.
The consequences of this idea are equally serious. There is no finality
in human activity; God is not an end for us; He exists for His own good
alone. Our only joy and our sole perfection is to be aware by mystical
372 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

union of the existence of pure joy in Him who alone is happy. Such
thoughts foster a high philosophy of perfect disinterestedness, but on
account of sublimation all contact with reality is lost.
What happens to the theological virtues in this scheme of things?
We spoke of faith in the first part of this study and found that it
remained implicit. Hope, too, loses its principal object, final happiness.
There is nothing left but hypomone, the waiting upon a God who is
unknown and who will reveal Himself only to allow His confidant to
lapse once more into nothingness.
Charity remains. Here we are in an immense field which would
involve ranging over all of Simone's works. We should have to read
all that she has to say in Waiting for God on implicit charity and un-
conditional love. Our personal love cannot be directed towards God,
it can only bear upon created objects which can be loved uncondition-
ally, such as "Beauty of the World" and "Religious Practices." After
we have received the graces of mysticism, this love develops into the
higher plane of benevolent contemplation, becoming the love of God
Himself exercised in us and through us for the whole of His creation.
Here once more we must pick out certain pages rich with truth and
beauty from the rest where errors pullulate. It is in these passages
where she hymns the love of God that Simone's nobility and incompar-
able art are revealed. To cite only one example, consider these closing
lines from a meditation on love in La connaissance sumaturelle: "God
loves, not as I love but as an emerald is green. He is 'I love.' If I
were perfect, I, too, would love as an emerald is green."29
There is another theme which runs throughout Simone's works,
that of Christ and the redemption. It occupies the leading place in
her thoughts and by its realism and austerity corrects a tendency in
her to replace mysticism with aestheticism. One can never tire of
reading her notes on redemptive suffering, on the suffering of the inno-
cent. But here again beautiful conclusions are based on faulty or too
fragile foundations. Her most moving words are those devoted to the
mystery of the cross. She is constantly meditating upon Our Lord's
cry, "My God! My God! Why hast Thou forsaken me?" There are
times when she twists this beautiful text out of recognition, but at
others she derives great truths from it.
M
IWtf.,p. 77.
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 373

The tragic, almost pessimistic, side of the redemption obscures for


her the other aspects of the mystery; the cross overshadows the resur-
rection, the ascension, Pentecost, and the Church. How could Simone
have felt all this if heaven existed for God alone, if the survival of the
soul, and still more of the body, were radically impossible? On this
point, which is essential, she completely distorts the authentic message
of Christ.
We can no longer be astonished to find that she understands nothing
of the doctrine of the Mystical Body based on our real and present
union with the body and soul of the risen Christ, instrument of all
grace. Her conception of the sacraments, too, reduces them to mere
symbolism. True, she talks about the real presence in the Eucharist
in terms reminiscent of the Church's teaching, but when she goes on
to say that the presence is purely conventional, like God's presence in
pagan idols, we can see how far she still is from the truth.
I have spoken of the Church and it is to the Church that I come back
now after a far from complete exploration of the forest of Simone's
works, a forest liberally interspersed with impenetrable undergrowth.
Simone devoted several passages to the Church which reveal quite
clearly how little she really knew of its greatness and beauty. We
shall not discuss her criticisms of the Church, which bordered on
calumny and blasphemy. These attacks were not inspired by what was
beautiful and pure and perhaps even divine in her interior life; they
were the evil results of a terrible error, an error all the more corrupting
because it was invested in the guise of truth. The last notes written
by Simone and published in The Need for Roots and La connaissance
sumaturelle are the most painful.30 Simone, whose view was sometimes
so lofty and so wide, was here unable to rise to the level of a reality
which is itself also a divine work. The Church Triumphant which she
denies, and the Church Militant which she wished to limit to the
European races, are precisely the catholica, the Universal, which gathers
to its maternal breast all who live in true charity.
Some recently published articles have tried to find in Simone's
criticisms of the Roman Church evidence of her being spiritually akin
to the Catharists. These notions, based on certain phrases detached
30
Cf., for example, The Need for Roots, trans. Arthur Wills (New York: Putnam,
1952), p. 277 ff.; La connaissance surnaturelle, pp. 67, 82, 265.
374 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

from their context or on a misunderstood letter, are not only entirely


gratuitous; they are diametrically opposed to the basic orientation of
the whole of Simone's thought. The sympathy which she shows for
Manichean, Gnostic, and Albigensian traditions is not more than she
shows for Buddhists or Pythagoreans. She could never have adhered
to these sects, which were even more circumscribed and narrow than
her view of Catholicism. The consolamentum reserved for the perfect
would have been as repugnant to her as baptism. Her sympathy for
dissident sects, far from constituting a rejection of Roman Chris-
tianity, was in her case aimed at embracing them all in a religion which
she wished to be even more universal. She was never able to under-
stand that the Catholic Church, while refusing to incorporate error,
has always recognized as members those who, through no fault of
their own, are in invincible ignorance yet live in a state of grace and
friendship with God.
What conclusion can we reach from these rapid glances over a work
which premature death and the abnormal circumstances of her life
left uncompleted? There is no lack of valuable material in this work,
and it is too precious to be allowed to slip into oblivion, but the work
as a whole is too unbalanced and too dangerous to be placed in every-
one's hands. Simone's works can only benefit those souls which are
capable of picking out the truth and beauty without danger of being
seduced by her mistakes, mistakes which are unfortunately very wide-
spread today. Like so many of her contemporaries, Simone underesti-
mated the power of the intellect; like them, too, she advocated a
religious indifferentism and a syncretism fundamentally opposed to
reason and faith. It has been said that some unbelievers have been
drawn towards the faith by her testimony. That is not impossible:
God's grace can make use of defective instruments. But it is by no
means sure that, even while effecting this rapprochement, Simone's
example may not at the same time have made more difficult the final
step, the one step which floods the intellect with true supernatural
light.
Above all we must warn readers against expecting to find in Simone's
writings the doctrinal nourishment to sustain and guide a religious
life unassociated with dogma or religious observances. As we observed
SIMONE WEIL'S RELIGIOUS THOUGHT 375

at the end of the first part of this study, to do this would be contrary
to the example of the author herself, who well understood the need for
a religious and sacramental life, even though some of the riches to be
found therein were unknown to her.
Finally we must remember that, in spite of the sincerity of her
interior life and the heroic degree of her asceticism, Simone remains an
abnormal and exceptional case. She cannot be put forward as an ex-
ample to be followed. Her very achievement is entirely a personal one
and in any case remains uncertain. Christ's Church has authentic
saints whom she canonizes and sets up as examples for us in sufficient
numbers for there to be no need to look elsewhere for our models. The
preference for people who have reached their goal by an uncertain and
roundabout way is an eccentricity of our time, in which true saints
seem dull, uninteresting, and old-fashioned.
These important reservations do not prevent us from admiring all
that God achieved in the way of greatness and beauty in Simone.
Grace can triumph over all obstacles; only obstinacy in sin renders it
powerless, and there is abundant reason to believe that this condition
was not present in the case of Simone Weil, who considered sin the
greatest of all evils. In these days when the great wave of materialism
sweeping over the world threatens to engulf us, Simone's testimony,
though itself lacking in balance, acts as a counterweight (sometimes
even by reason of its own excesses) to the more dangerous tendencies
of our time. Her reactions to the theories of evolutionism and progress-
ism, and even to the sort of humanism which tends to absorb the super-
natural, offer us pertinent food for thought.
In her writings, and even more by her personal example, she reminds
us of the primordial necessity for the elementary moral virtues which
so many young revolutionaries are inclined to forget. Her sense of
purity is a complete rejection of the disintegrating tendencies of modern
literature. Her meticulous delicacy and search after perfection stand
as a condemnation of the indifference and mediocrity that are some-
times very near to serious negligence. Her reflections on devotion and
almsgiving are an expression of a profound sense of real purity of
intention. In this connection it is appropriate to quote the magnificent
words in which she gives full value to the grandeur and dignity of
376 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES

misfortune when the sufferer knows "that he can be the means of


earning for his benefactor the thanks of Christ."81
Simone often insisted—perhaps too often—on disinterestedness. She
condemned all seeking for recompense and did not see the formal re-
buttal of her position contained in Christ's words, "Your reward will
be superabundant in Heaven." Nevertheless we must recognize the
greatness, the beauty, and the nobility of her attitude of waiting,
silence, recollection, and patience expressed by the untranslatable
word hypomone. All young people should have read to them the "Reflec-
tions on the Right Use of School Studies with a View to the Love of
God" found in Waiting for GodP Some details need modification but
the reflections are basically sound and constitute a magnificent vindica-
tion of the true contemplative spirit. She insisted on divorcing even
our conception of heroism from the glory with which we tend to sur-
round it; she was well aware that virtue does not consist in a passing
action, however spectacular, but in a habitual disposition which in-
forms and modifies our whole nature. A virtuous man is one who na-
turally and spontaneously does the right thing.
This anxiety for profound realism in the life of virtue caused Simone
to ponder throughout her life the problem of pain and human suffering.
She wanted to experience it herself so that she could feel a genuine
"compassion." Her sense of suffering is deeply moving. The fact that
she did not understand the Christian mystery meant that her thoughts
on the subject were incomplete; but they can at least help us to realize
the falsity of our own fear of difficulties, of our tendency to flee any-
thing liable to interfere with our pleasures, of our being scandalized
by the sufferings of the innocent. As a result of her meditations on the
mystery of the cross, Simone came to see quite clearly that this appa-
rent injustice was in fact the greatest gift of a merciful love.
Lastly and most important, Simone exalted the place of God in the
life of man, emphasizing thereby the value of the passive virtues of
humility, renunciation, and obedience'. Her works can help us to ac-
quire the sense of God.
Without forgetting all the defects in her work, we can well believe
that God in His infinite mercy may, by the gift of a light that is shadow-
less, have revealed to a soul in love with beauty and perfection the
innermost secrets of love for all eternity.
La connaissance surnaturelle. * Cf. Waiting for God, pp. 105-16.

You might also like