04-Պատմության Տեսություն-2017-2
04-Պատմության Տեսություն-2017-2
04-Պատմության Տեսություն-2017-2
Albert A. Stepanian
Introduction
The western canon implied rational perception of history with a purpose formulated
still by Herodotus as follows - to find out how, when and why (pw~§, potev, dia; tiv) hap-
pened important events of history [Herod., I, 1, 1].1 Efforts of Herodotus and his close
contemporaries reformed the logographic genre of storytelling in an area of rationalistic
study and explanation of the past. In accordance with this approach, the term iJstoriva was
coined for denoting investigation in its proper sense.2 From this time, the image of histori-
ans gained a particular social significance since the investigation of the past (despite pure
curiosity) pursued practical interests.
During centuries, rationalistic approach gave birth to numerous genres of historical
writing, from chronicles and annals to ethno-geographic descriptions and biographic
sketches, from local and global histories to moral and philosophical reflections on events
of the past.3 Such transmissions were particularly effective within cultural context of Hel-
lenistic age. It affected different historical traditions in different ethnic, social and cultural
circumstances.
As it is established, Hellenistic elite culture was effectively introduced in Greater Ar-
menia by around the middle of the third century BC.4 It represented a combination of
Greek, Zoroastrian and native Armenian traditions5 in various areas of intellectuality and
38
practice - religion beliefs and rituals, administration system and court etiquette, literature
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
and rhetoric, theater and philosophy. Scholars on the base of literature and archeological
material have studied the process.6 My task is to trace this syncretism in historiography.
Aspects of this approach have already been discussed7 and now it seems necessary to en-
rich and systematize them in the light of modern approaches.
In Greater Armenia, the two genres of Hellenistic historical writing seem to deserve
peculiar attention – pragmatic history and tragic history. They marked the process of
introduction of western tradition in Armenian intellectual environment and make up the
focus of the present investigation of the problem.8
citizen if he cannot follow how, why or by what process every event has developed”
[Polyb., III, 7, 5].
Pragmatic history was thought as effective only in the case of a balanced combination
of these opposite approaches. Many intellectuals of the II -I centuries BC. – particularly
civilisations plus anciennes […]”. Dan, 2014, 52.
6 From numerous studies of this problem, We should like to put out those of the three eminent scholars:
Eremyan, 1948, 33 – 46; Sargsyan, 1966, 12 – 14; Tiratsyan, 1988, 116 – 121.
7 Sargsyan, 1969, 107-126; Stepanyan, 1991, 121-139.
8 Stepanyan, 1991, 116.
9 Malitz, 1982, 257 - 259.
10 The two eminent representatives of the pragmatic history (pragmatikhv iJstorivav) were Thucydides and
Polybius. It was believed that the term denoted: “[…] a formal approach to study of the past based on cur-
rent methods in the practical sciences”. Herchenroeder., 2010, 72.
11 Walbank, 1972, 40 – 43.
39
Posidonius, Diodorus Siculus, Timagenes, and Strabo – adopted this assumption of histo-
ry.12 Eminent Metrodorus of Scepsis was among them: “[…] a man of agreeable speech
and wide learning” [Plut., Luc., 22, 2]. It is attested that he graduated from the Athenian
Academy and soon became celebrated in political philosophy and logic, rhetoric and law
theory, geography and history.13 However, evidences about his concrete ideas and con-
cepts are very scarce and fragmentary wherefore we found it reasonable to juxtapose three
important texts concerning him – life-course, semantic code of works (corpus), and some
global ideas of the treaty “On Tigranes”.
The first text implies a common sight to the biography of the philosopher in the light
of the renowned concept that the life of a creative individuality is a more or less exact
embodiment of his beliefs and ideas, perceptions and concepts.14 In other words, despite
simple people, he lives within his own reverse perspective.
In 75 BC., Metrodorus graduated from Academy, the scholarch of which (from about
79 BC.) was the outstanding philosopher Antiochus of Ascalon who crucially changed the
content of academic curriculum and research strategy. Particularly, he denied the Skepti-
cism paving a path for compiling important values of Old Academy with those of Peripa-
tetic and Stoic Schools. Due to that, the rationalistic assumption of world and human be-
ing was recognized as a guiding principle of contemplative and practical modes of life.15
We are going to demonstrate the adherence of Metrodorus to this assumption. An adher-
ence, which continued to lead his mind, will and social activity throughout all his creative
life.
Through prestigious marriage, the philosopher acquired citizenship of Chalcedon, the
most prosperous city of Troas. Here, during the Third Mithridatic War (73 – 71 BC.), he
met Mithridat VI Eupator, the king of Pontus. He took the side of the king with great en-
thusiasm and began to pursue a public career in the royal court. In other words, he aban-
doned pure philosophy to practice political life (ejk tou~ filovsofou metabeblhvkw§ ejpi;;
to;n; bivon praktikovn) [Strabo, XIII,1, 55]16. Soon, he gained an exceptional honor and influ-
ence being appointed to supervise all the affairs of state justice (ta;; peri;; dikaiodosiva§). In
addition, he was granted with the title of king’s father and his authority and power reached to
an incontestable height so that nobody could appeal against his decisions [Ibid.].
It is also important to outline the essential perspective of this phase of Motrodorus’
life. For this purpose, the Stoic ethic theory seems most appropriate. It prompted that a
genuine philosopher (sovfo§) had to step down from his pure contemplations to the level of
appropriate actions (ta;; kaqhvkonta) becoming a practicer (ajskhthv§).17 The principal care
12 Stepanyan, 2014, 196.
13 Fuchs, 1938, 34 – 36. Sometimes, scholars confuse him with another intellectual of the same name, Me-
trodorus of Scepsis, a pupil of the Carneades. They neglect the account of Cicero: “[…] aequilem fere meum
ex Academia rhetorem nactus Metrodorum illum.” [Cic., De orat., III, 20, 75]. See Scullard, 1992, 685.
14 Foucault, 1969, 181 – 182. J. Barnes applies the same approach in his interpretation of the speculative
system of Antiochus of Ascalon. Barnes, 1989, 52 – 55.
15 On the new start of Academy under leadership of Antiochus see in detail Merlan, 1967, 53 – 57; Barnes,
1989, 67 – 78; Polito, 2012, 31 – 54.
16 The problem of transition from speculative wisdom (sofiva) to practical wisdom (frovnhsi§) is formulated
by Aristotle as follows: “The end of theoretical knowledge is the truth (ajleqeiva), while that of practical
knowledge is action (to; ejrgovn) […] practical men study not eternal principle but the relative and immedi-
ate application” [Arist., Met., II, 993b, 20]. The Stoics adopted this concept. Rist, 1977, 108 – 111. Philo of
Alexandria proceeded from the same concept speaking about his endeavor to abandon the contemplative
life for a political life [Philo, De spec. leg., III, 1 - 6]. Cf. Runia, 2000, 362.
17 Stoic philosophy was introduced in Rome in the 2d century BC., and the central figure of this adoption
40
of the latter was to bridge the social order with universal Order. This task seemed to be
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
vital for the kingdom of Pontus consisting of numerous social and ethnic unities - from
nomadic tribes and agricultural communities to industrious Greek cities - different lan-
guages, cultures and customs. Royal authority intended to bring them together through
rational justice, law and administration. In Metrodorus, Mithridat Eupator (and his en-
lightened proximi) saw an adequate figure to carry out this paramount program.18
Soon, however, this idyll came to end. Relations between the king and philosopher
soured sharply. The king secretly even planned to put him to death. According to Strabo,
the philosopher “[…] incurred the enmity of men less just than himself” [Strabo, XIII, 1,
55]. Supposedly, they represented the conservative local (tribal) nobility longing to en-
large its traditional autonomy. This faction gained the upper hand in the second phase of
the Third Mithridatic War when the king began to suffer defeats from Lucius Licinius
Lucullus and lose control over his kingdom.19 In his turn, the king, probably, tried to de-
pict the philosopher as a scapegoat of all his failures.
For averting the catastrophe, the Pontiac king strived to involve Greater Armenia into
ly put him to death [Plut., Luc., 22, 3 - 4]. Metrodorus was about forty years old.
Parallels with Plato are obvious. Like the great philosopher, Metrodorus tried to pat-
was Panaetius. The Stoic moral terms were transformed into the essential Roman values – gravitas, decorum,
officium. See Morford, 2002, 22 – 32; Schofield, 2003, 242 – 246.
18 Stepanyan, 2014, 197 – 198; The subject “philosopher in the court” has a principal significance in stud-
ding of elitism and governing ideology in the Hellenistic age. Erksine, 2011, 181.
19 Olshausen, 1974, 160 – 166. The dichotomy of Hellenized and Conservative (local) branches of the elite
was typical for Greater Armenia as well. Cf. Stepanyan, 2012, 142 – 157.
20 In other words, Tigran and his entourage, like the eminent Hellenistic courts, were ready to learn from
philosophers. Erskine, 2011, 179.
21 “Metrodorus Scepsius qui cognomen Romani nominis odio inditum est […]” [Plin. Nat. hist., XVIII, 3].
22 Stepanyan, 2012, 98.
23 On the category of intellectual royal friends in the Hellenistic courts, see Strootman, 2011, 74 – 76.
24 Reinach, 1890, 362 – 363; Olshausen, 1972, 812- 813.
41
tern his life-way in accordance with his social ideal. It is well attested, during all his long
life, Plato did his best to incorporate his project of the ideal state in Syracuse.25 However,
he failed and at last gave up. Nearly the same is traceable in Metrodorus’ life: he tried to
bring about his theory of social order and justice in Pontus and Greater Armenia. How
ever, in both cases, he failed and (in spite of Plato) paid for that with his life.
The second text concerns the semantic code of Metrodorus’ works. For such analysis,
we decided to proceed from the titles of his treatises, which are unfortunately lost. At first
sight, they represent an unbound series – “On Gymnastic Training”, “On Herds”, “A Con-
tour [of World]”, “On Customs” “On History”, “On Rhetoric”, “On Tigranes” etc.26 Non-
theless, an experienced glance is able to trace some important common features uniting
them.
Stoic theory attributes a support to speak about these features more exactly. The latter
was based on a concept stating that an overwhelming sympathy integrated all elements of
the universe making them to live in accordance with the Order of Nature.27 The Stoics
denoted this creative principle by different terms – reason, fire, breath, governing princi-
ple, god, logos etc. (nou~§, pu~r, pneu~ma, to; hJgemonikovn, qeov§, lovgo§). They considered
its emanations (ejkpuvrosi§) to be aimed at the global cosmic determinism covering stars
and planets, animals and men. 28 Order, justice and harmony of this imagined universe
gave grounds to compare it with an ideal Commonwealth (City) securing welfare and hap-
piness for its partisan-citizens.29
Human being was depicted as the mediator of the cosmic justice and
harmony in earthly circumstances. His body was thought to function due to
the association of its different parts. It was believed that the most important
function of men was to reproduce the cosmic balance in themselves through
skillful gymnastic instruction.30 The same was true about the partner relation-
ship between creatures living with communal life (koinoniva) - from families,
tribes to various forms of city communities, political associations and em-
pires. It was held that laws (expressions of the overwhelming Universal Law)
would guide various forms of social partnership. This was estimated as the
principal condition for earthly communities to imitate their heavenly pattern
consisting of stars, planets and pure spirits.31 In this regard, fatalism was
considered as the most important feature of the Universe.
Besides this fatalism, the Stoics, however, recognized also the personal responsibility
of men to learn the cosmic Order and to act in accordance with it.32 For this purpose, they
25 It is well attested, the philosopher undertook three voyages to Syracuse (389 – 388, 367 – 361, 361 – 357
BC.) to educate and turn the tyrants into beneficent philosopher-kings. Huard, 1976, 109 – 110.
26 This presumptive list of the titles is extracted from the primary sources on the life and intellectual activity
of the philosopher [FGrH, 184, 204, 205; Apoll. Rhod., Scholl., IV, 133; Athen., XIII,14; Strabo, XVI, 3, 6; 4, 7].
27 Cicero defined this isomorphism very exactly: “Just as there is no part of our body which is not of less
value than we ourselves are, so the cosmos as a whole must be of more value than any part of it” [Cic., De
nat. deorum, II, 32].
28 Zeller, 1886, 243 – 244; Hankinson, 1999, 531 – 534; White, 2003, 136 – 138.
29 Stanton, 1968, 183 – 195; Tsolis, 2000, 336 - 343; Brown, 2009, 357 – 364.
30 Schofield, 1999, 760 – 768; Evans, 2008, 108 – 109. On the cosmic character of human nature, see
Inwood, 1999, 682 – 683.
31 Mitsis, 1999, 155 – 177.
32 The maxim of the Middle Stoa displayed this assumption entirely: volentem fata ducunt, nolentem tra-
42
were obliged to commit appropriate actions (ta; kaqhvkonta) which made up the focus of
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
the intellectual and spiritual development of the advanced and selected men.33 In this light,
it is worth to remind that the Greek mentality and practice traced parallels between the
body training and rhetoric instruction believing that the both were built on the same cru-
cial values – proportion (kaivro§) and craft-wisdom (mh~ti§).34
With the extension of these principles, the dwelled world (oijkoumevnh) would pass
over all kinds of diversities. It would have a real chance to incorporate the cosmic Com-
monwealth building harmony of its ethnic and religious, cultural and moral, social and
political aspects. The Stoics worked out a theory of global citizenship.35
Perhaps, the close attention of Metrodorus to various tribes and peoples dwelling in
the area from India to Caucasus, Asia Minor and Greece, Italy and (even) Germany must
be discussed in the context of this approach [Plin. Hist. Nat., III, 20; VIII, 14; XXVIII, 23;
XXXIV, 16; XXXVII, 15].36Though logical, this assumption stays still hypothetical and
cannot pretend to unquestionable trustworthiness. Nevertheless, it draws a path in world-
view system of Metrodorus.
43
The first fragment belongs to Gn. Pompeius Trogus, an author of the 1st century B.C.,
whose narrative of world history - Historiae Philippicae – is credited to be composed on
trustworthy primary sources. Telling about subduing of Seleucid Syria by the army of Ti-
gran II, he records:
After the kings and kingdom of Syria had been exhausted by continual
wars, occasioned by the mutual animosities of brothers, and by sons succeed-
ing to the quarrels of their fathers, the people began look for relief from for-
eign parts, and to think of choosing a king from among the sovereigns of
other nations. Some therefore advised that they should take Mithridates of
Pontus, others Ptolemaeus of Egypt, but it being considered that Mithridates
was engaged in war with the Romans, and Ptolemaeus had always been an
enemy to Syria, the thoughts of all were directed to Tigranes king of Armenia,
who, in addition to the strength of his own kingdom, was supported by an al-
liance with Parthia, and by matrimonial connection with Mithridates. Ti-
granes accordingly, being invited to the throne of Syria, enjoyed a most tran-
quil reign over it for seventeen years (per XVII annos tranquilissimo regno
potitus est), without having occa-sion to go to war either to attack others or
to defend himself [Just., Epit., XL, 1, 1 - 4]41.
This seems to be a description of a popular assembly with a well-elaborated scenario
to vindicate Tigran’s peaceful conquest of Syria as a great benefaction. As the main
achievements of the king, order and peace (pax) have been pointed out which, however,
continued only seventeen years (83 – 66 BC.). This idealistic vision of the events, of
course, was far from the historical truth because other sources relate about resistance of
the Syrians to Tigran’s invasion [Strabo, XI, 14, 15; App., Syr., 48; Plut., Luc., 14, 5,
10]42. Some scholars are inclined to trace in this fragment a citation from On Tigranes by
Metrodorus of Scepsis. A treatise targeted at the legitimation and propaganda of the king’s
empire.43 Without tangible risk of error, one can even state that the fragment contains in-
formation about the concept of pax Armenica.44
The second fragment, which belongs to Plutarch, seems to continue the same concept
on the new ideas and considerations. At first sight, it contains Tigran’s boastful self-esti-
mation:
Above all else, the spirit of the king himself had become pompous and
haughty in the midst of great prosperity. All the things which men most covet
and admire, he not only had in his possession, but actually thought that they
existed for his sake (dij aujtovn gegongevnoi) [Plut., Luc., 33,3].
However, a close concern leads to the conclusion that the Armenian sovereign spoke
in accordance with his hypostasis of а savior. We have noticed, according to the common
41 The key term of the fragment pax (peace), according to the Hellenistic and (particularly) Roman political
theory, made up the essence of every genuine government. Parchmani, 2009, 31 – 58;.
42 Mommsen, 1867, 46 – 47; Bevan, 1902, 261 – 263; Errington, 2008, 277. For balanced assessment of the
situation, some scholars find that the two approaches must be combined. Cf. Asdourian, 1911, 34, Manan-
dyan, 1943, 49 – 50; Garsoïan, 1997, 65.
43 Castiglioni, 1928, 629; Liebman-Frankfort, 1969, 896 – 898.
44 Stepanyan, 2012,
44
Hellenistic assumption, an eminent king accomplished this function through a (real or rit-
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
ual) act of conquest and occupation of his own land. Therefore, in official documents, his
realm often was named a land obtained by spear (cwvra dorivkthto§).45Such concept em-
phasized his absolute authority over his subjects. 46In other words, the grotesque gesture,
ascribed by the author to the king, was nothing else than a norm of the Hellenistic political
theory and practice. In this case also, without significant risk of error, one can accept this
text as a cornerstone of Metrodorus’ assumption of Tigran’s Empire.47
The third fragment again belongs to Plutach and seems to contain elements of the Ro-
man counter-propaganda based on nearly the same ideas and values as in the case of Ti-
gran II. It states: “Lucullus, after filling Asia full of law and order, and full of peace (polh`§
me;;n eujnomiva§, polh`§ dj eijrhvn§), did not neglect the things which minister to pleasure
and favour [...]” [Plut., Luc., 23, 1]. Strictly speaking, the Roman general ascribed himself
the same function of the savor of Asia. Was the target of his ideological attack Metrodorus
the hater of Rome? It is hard to assert because we have no direct account about that, and
the answer may only be sought in logical constructs and probabilities.
modern scholarship50, whereas there is a direct testimony of Trogus on this account. Relat-
45 This concept had two various aspects. The first denoted the king’s mythological creative function. As
to the second aspect, it represented the same concept reshaped, however, into a legal norm aimed at the
regulation of real social relations. See Goodenough, 1928, 68 – 72; Mehl, 1980/1981, 174 – 190; Hahn, 2010,
458 - 464.
46 Cf. Dvornik, 1966, 262 – 263.
47 This Hellenistic concept is still traceable in the text of Moses Khorenatsi: “For the frontiers of the brave
[…] are their weapons; as much they act, that much they hold” [Khor., I, 8, 4].
48 On this concept of world history, see in detail, Swain, 1940, 4 – 9.
49 On Hellenistic prophesies see in detail Cumont, 1931, 79 – 88. Two oracles also aroused spiritual enthusi-
asm in this transitive age - Oracula Sibyllina and Oracula Hystaspis. See, Parke, 1988, 125 - 135; Suderman,
2012, 606 – 609.
50 The Parthian claim was based on the ideology tracing blood relations between the Arsacids and Achae-
menids. Neusner, 1963, 45 - 48; Dąbrowa, 2010,130 – 131. As to Mithridates VI Eupator, he set up his claim
45
ing about subjugation of Syria by Gn. Pompey’s in 64 BC., he records that one of the last
Seleucids, Antiochus XIII, visited the general and raised a claim to regain his ancestral
throne. But he was sharply denied: “[...] he (Pompey) would not give Antiochus what he
himself had yielded to Tigranes (ita quo cesserit Tigrani) and what he would not know
how to defend” [Just., Epit., XL, 4]. In this way, the Roman general underlined the fact
that he had taken over the Eastern legacy from the hands of Tigran II signing the Artaxata
treatise in 66 BC. On these grounds, he began to reorganize Syria into a Roman prov-
ince.51
In other words, the right interpretation of the Artaxata treatise has a principal signifi-
cance for the claim of Greater Armenia on world dominance. It is a renowned fact that,
after ebbs and flows of wars and internal strives, the Armenian king of kings gave up and
decided to come to terms with the Romans.52 The sides elected to settle the problems at
the meeting of the two leaders. Receiving Tigran II at the Roman camp, Pompey solemnly
“[...] spoke words of encouragement, telling him among other things that he had not lost
the kingdom of Armenia, but had gained the friendship of the Romans” [Dio Cass., XXX-
VI, 52, 4].53 In other words, Greater Armenia abandoned the occupied territories and the
status of the great empire. By the next step, it was recognized as a Roman partner of high
rank - amicus populi Romani, which meant its acknowledgement the Roman suzerainty in
the East.54
However, soon the Roman propaganda forgot about the Tigran’s empire. Usually,
Rome was more tolerant and flexible in the similar situations.55 But the case under consid-
eration was extraordinary because Roman intellectuals intended to solve an important
ideological problem convincing the world that only their empire was the rightful heir of
the Seleucid super-state. This perception found its full expression in the narrative of Vel-
leius Paterculus:
The Assyrians were the first of all races to hold world power, then the
Medes, after them the Persians, and then the Macedonians. Then through the
defeat of Kings Philip and Antiochus, of Macedon origin […] the world pow-
er passed to the Roman people (summa imperii ad populum Romanum perve-
nit)[Vel. Pat., I,6,6]56.
Coming back to the quest of Greater Armenia to the status of super-state, the follow-
ing becomes clear: the impulse proceeded from the brain center of the court of Tigran II.
on blood relations with both the Achaemenids and Seleucids. Rubinsohn, 1993, 7 – 8.
51 Jones, Syrig, 1992, 1030.
52 The last test of the lot was the rebellion of the crone-prince Tigran the Young who tried to usurp the
throne with the Parthian support but failed. He decided to offer his services to Pompey but the general
preferred to build relationship with Tigran II. On these grounds, his relations with Pompey were spoiled and
he ended life in Roman captivity. See Gray, 1992, 1073.
53 Minasyan, 2009, 94 – 101; Stepanyan, Minasyan, 2013, 26 – 27.
54 Gn. Pompey settled Roman East as a rather complicated system of relations beginning from provinces
and ending with allies and friends. It supplied the Romans with facility to govern this great territory (full
of ethnic, social and cultural diversities) with appropriate flexibility. See Downey, 1951, 149 – 163; Gruen,
1984, 668 – 670; Sherwin-White, 1984, 209 – 226; Ball, 2002, 33 – 34.
55 Braund, 1984, 81- 82.
56 Later, however, the Romans began to consider the Parthians as their equals. Relating about the meeting
of the August’s heir Gaius Caesar with the Parthian king Fraataces, Velleius states: “[…] while two eminent
leaders not only of the empires they represented but also of mankind (hominum) thus met in conference –
truly a notable and memorable sight” [Vel. Pat., II, 51, 2].
46
In this regard, its concern with Metrodorus of Scepsis seems most probable.
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
On these grounds, bringing together the results of our discussion, we can tentatively
point out the crucial concepts of the treatise “On Tigranes” as follows: a. Tigran’s empire
was based on the principle of persuasion (h[qo§) but not on bare coercion (kravto§) and it
was aimed at peace, order and justice; b. the empire was a result of the king’s creative ef-
forts: he had built it as a savior and benefactor of all his subjects; c. the empire occupied a
honorable place in the string of super-states representing glory and destiny of the East,
beginning from Assyria; d. the treatise “On Tigranes”, probably, was composed as an es-
say of world history focused, however, on the deeds of the king of kings and his ances-
tors57.
Certainly, this narrative axis was complemented with numerous historical events and
facts (ta;; pravgmata) but their consideration is beyond the limits our reach. We can only
guess about them.
Epigraphic data comes from archeological site of Armavir, the capital of Eruandid
Armenia (6th – 3d centuries BC). Two basalt boulders (I, II) were discovered with Greek
letters in 1911 and 1927. Scholars trace on them seven inscriptions – three on the first
boulder and four on the second. They are fragmentary and sometimes poorly preserved,
which makes their transcription, translation and interpretation extremely difficult. Despite
57 It is well known that compiling the recent period of Armenian history, Strabo had on hand an extend
work and tried to sketch it in main features (ejn kefalaivw/) [Strabo, XI, 14, 15]. Departing from this fact,
some scholars found it possible to trace in this primary source the treatise of Metrodorus or Artavazd II. Cf.
Sargsyan, 1969, 119 – 120.
58 In spite of ritualized rural life, in the Hellenistic cities (and especially in the courts), life was apparently
theatricalized. See Chaniotis, 1997, 219 – 221.
59 Sreedharan, 2004, 33.
60 Walbank, 1985, 68 – 69.
47
the efforts of scholars - J. Smirnov, A. Boltunova, H. Manandyan, C. Trever and J.-P.
Mahé - our knowledge about their content is still ambiguous. Nevertheless, scholars are
still unanimous about the character and (even) the content of some inscriptions [Arm., I, 1
– 3; II, 1, 4].61
However, it is not the purpose of the present investigation to discuss the epigraphic,
orthographic, stylistic or literary peculiarities of the Armavir inscriptions. Our focus is the
semantic cod of the fourth inscription of the second boulder [Arm., II, 4] in A. Boltuno-
va’s restoration and H. Manandyan’s interpretation.62It seems more trustworthy and sup-
posedly contains a fragment of an unknown tragedy:
In its information, H. Manandyan traced the events of 201 BC., when the las king of
Eruandid dynasty, Eruand the Last, challenged by Young Artashēs, was murdered in a
battle. As to Philadelphus, supposedly, she was the priestess of the temple of Artemis/Ana-
hit connected with the late king with sacred marriage ties (iJerogamiva/), a religious experi-
ence and ritual reflecting the unity of basic cosmic and social elements in a sacred com-
monality.64
The starting point of this interpretation is the fragment of Moses Khorenatsi record-
ing in detail about the conflict of Eruand with Young Artashēs.65 The king is depicted as an
evil tyrant who has usurped the royal throne and dignity massacring the house of his pre-
decessor, the king Sanatruk. As to Artashēs, he is the only offspring of the late king who
has escaped the destiny of his brothers and sisters. His tutor prince Smbat Bagratid saves
him and brings up in the Parthian court.
Artashēs’ pretention to his paternal throne is quite legitimate, wherefore he is depict-
ed as a personification justice and law. In a cruel battle, Eruand is defeated; abandoned by
his soldiers and close entourage, he tries to find refuge in the palace of the royal capital
Eruandashat: “However, one of soldiers entered and struck off Eruand’s head with a saber,
scattering his brains over the floor. From such blow he died, having held the throne for
61 On the details of discovery, transcription, translation and study of Armavir inscriptions see Trever, 1953,
104 – 148; Movsisyan, 2003, 124 – 137.
62 Manandyan, 1946, 9 – 17. This interpretation was accepted by Robert, 1952, 181 - 185; Habicht, 1953,
251 - 156; Mahé, 1994, 571 - 573.
63 Th~i Filadevlfwi Noumhvnio§ [eij]pe [fo]neovei
tou`t’ e[po§, ajmeivbw d’ oujde;n e[cwn ajkleev§.
jAlla; min oJploforo[u`nta] livpen q[u]mov§ ...
... kainavpolin cw~ron jArmenihn kat[ivc]en ...
64 H. Manandyan even found her to be the sister of Eruand the Last. Manandyan, 1946, 16. On the sacred
marriage, see Frazer, 1914, 70 – 72; Koester, 1995, 171 – 177; Avagianou, 2008, 150 – 156.
65 Ruling sometimes as Achaemenid satraps, sometimes as independent sovereigns of Armenia, the Eruan-
dids linked the Post-Urartian period with that of the Artaxiads (6th – 3d centuries). See Tiratsyan, 1958,
53 – 72; Toumanoff, 1963, 277 – 285.
48
twenty years” [Khor., II, 46].66
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
Classic sources (especially Strabo and Plutarch) provide records, which come to com-
plete the lifecourse of Artashēs as the founder of Artaxiad dynasty (180 BC. – 52 AD.)67.
As it was demonstrated before, the new king first of all restored the territorial integrity of
Greater Armenia establishing social peace and consensus. After that, he built a splendid
new capital, Artaxata, the embodiment of the new social order. Let us underline again,
scholars trace in his reformation the crucial event of history of Hellenistic Armenia.68
The legitimation of the authority of the new dynasty was one of the most important
problems of Artashēs I. Its echo is clearly traceable in the inscription under consideration:
despite Khorenatsi, it portrays the last Eruantid king as a valiant and brave warrior who
died “with a weapon in his hand”. This approach seems quite explainable: the political
propaganda of the new dynasty tried to show the blue blood of its predecessor. It was well
attested by the fact, that the Eruandids traced their origin from Achaemenids, the dynasty
whose heritage continued to be desirable for centuries.69 Subsequently, the next step of le-
gitimation was to connect the Artaxiads with the Eruandids through ties of consanguinity.
66 In various religious systems, the sacred marriage personified the cause of cosmic and social harmony.
Kramer, 1969, 22 – 26. The concept was adopted by the Christianity in the form of the marriage of Christ
with the Church. Klein J., 1992, 868-869.
67 We proceed from the idea that all the holders of the Armenian throne of the 1st half of the 1st century
AD. – Tigran V, Zenon-Artashēs, Iberian princes (Mithridat and Rhadamist) Tigran VI, based their claims on
the fact that they were Artaxiads by maternal line. Cf. Toumanoff, 1963, 81; Stepanyan, 2012, 28 – 68.
68 Sargsyan, 1976, 521 – 553; Adonts, 2009, 445 – 455. About the metaphysical aspects of Artaxata see
Stepanyan, 2014, 209 – 225.
69 Boyce, 1983, 427; Daryaee T., 2006, 494 – 497.
70 More than twenty Aramaic inscriptions are found in modern Armenia, in which the king names himself
Eruandakan. Perikhanian, 1966, 17 – 29; Perikhanian, 1971, 5 – 11.
71 Barret, 2002, 38 – 55.
72 The intellectual stance was characteristic for the Greek theater spectators: “In the Greek theater the
spectators had to do much of the work themselves, to imagine places and settings, important information
and relationships from the mythical tradition visualise in their minds the events occurring off-stage and
narrated by others”. Storey, Allan, 2005, 52.
49
In this light, summing up the results of the discussion, the following assumption ap-
pears more appropriate: the inscription under consideration displays a fragment of an un-
known tragedy. Scholars have come to the same conclusion, proceeding from semantic,
stylistic and metric peculiarities of the text. Some of them even find (of course, tentative-
ly) that its author is the king Artavazd II (55 – 34 BC.) renowned by his literary, rhetoric
and historical works.73
Combining this interpretation with that of H. Manandyan, we come up to a proposi-
tion that the fall Eruandid dynasty made up the content of a tragic plot which has not
come down to us in its initial form. Continuing this logic, one could conclude that, in Hel-
lenistic Armenia, historical past was staged in accordance with the canons of theatrical
theory.
To what extent this proposition is true. For answer, we must explain another important
question: are there more distinct evidences about the genre of tragic history in Hellenistic
Greater Armenia? In other words, were there intellectuals enough acquainted with Aristo-
telian poetry which states particularly: “Poetry, therefore, is more philosophical and higher
than history: for poetry tends to express the universal, history the particular” [Arist., Poet.,
1451b, 4-5].
50
des for treachery” [Plut., Crass., 19,3].77 The Roman general was unable to appreciate the
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
situation and make adequate decisions. On the contrary, he led his legions through water-
less steppes and deserts of the North Mesopotamia heading to Seleucia-on-Tigris.
To meet Crassus, the Parthian king equipped a new army under the eminent nobleman
Surena. Thе latter pursued the traditional Parthian war tactics which demanded to come up
to a general battle after exhausting the enemy forces through a series local scrambles. Im-
plementing this tactics, Surena surrounded the Roman army at Carrhae and forced it to
surrender. More than 20 000 Roman legionaries were killed. Many were captivated and
lived in slavery during long years. As to Crassus, he was captured and beheaded: “And the
Parthians, as some say, poured molten gold into his mouth in mockery […]” [Dio Cass.,
40, 27, 3]. His head and right hand were sent to Artaxata, the capital of Greater Armenia,
to Orodes II and Artavazd II, who had already stopped military actions and come to terms
[Plut., Crass., 33, 2 ].78
This unprecedented military crash left indelible mark in the memory of generations. The
principal opponents estimated it from opposite points of view. The Romans saw in it the in-
proceeded from the fact that his addressee was well acquainted with Greek language, lit-
77 Following “the letter and spirit” of Artaxata treaty, signed by Gn. Pompey and Tigran II (66 BC.), the king
Artavazd II counted himself an amicus populi Romani whereas Crassus demanded from him duties of a socius
populi Romani obliged to support Rome with all his resources. About similar situations, see Braud, 1984,
72 – 76.The fact is that, in the last period of The Republic, the Roman generals began to treat the partner
states: “[...]in a traditional and almost feudal form of clientship”. Konstan, 1997, 3, 128 - 131.
78 Asdourian, 1911, 60 – 61; Ziegler, 1964, 34 – 35. Among the main causes of the disaster, modern scholars
often point out the low level of the awareness of the Romans about the Parthians. Cf. Campbell, 1993, 216.
79 The procession represented a set of pictorial fragments to express the low passions and avarice of the
enemy. Its plot was patterned on the Old Iranian world-view system well attested by numerous bas-reliefs
of the Achaemenid and Sasanid ages – Behistun, Naqgh-i Rostam, Bishpur, Taq-i Bostan etc. See in detail,
MacDermot, 1954, 76 – 80; Herman, 2000, 35 – 40; Canepa, 2010, 582 – 584.
80 Stepanyan, 2015, 114.
51
erature, rhetoric and everyday mode of life.81 According to Plutarch, it was true particu-
larly about the two kings. This fact makes to think that the reverse perspective of the audi-
ence was active and ready to play an important role in the forthcoming performance.82
The wedding party was held in the banquet-hall (tw~/ ajndrw~ni) of the Artaxata court
and comprised two phases. The first phase represented the traditional banquet (ejstiavsei§
te kai; povtoi) [Plut., Crass., 33, 1]. The kings and their close entourage (fivloi kai;
suvntrofoi) took a separate seat. From time to time, they invited an eminent guest to hon-
or him with a drink or gift. In its profound essence, these (and similar) actions were de-
signed to reestablish the elite hierarchy and re-consolidate it around the royal authority.83
The first phase ended, and the servants removed the tables. The second phase of the
party started which, like old Greek symposia, contained a literary component as well.84
According to tradition, the choice and interpretation of the piece depended on the artistic
and philosophical taste of the head of the banquet (sumposiavrco§) [cf. Plato, Symp.,
176a].85 In this regard, it must be added that such banquets were considered as private en-
terprises, and were most popular in the Hellenistic age. For example, Alexander the
Great’s symposia as a rule included dramatic and literary performances with the objective
of illustrating the essence of contemporary events. Theatricality emerged as a prevailing
mode of public behavior within decision-making procedure; and current events were inter-
preted in accordance with the archetypes of old myths and tragedies.86
In our case, the head of the banquet also preferred to uncover the meaning of current
events by means of tragedy87. Presumably, he adhered to a tragic understanding of history
which appeared among members of the Peripatetic school in response to the Aristotelian
concept of the strict opposition between history and tragedy (poetry) [Arist., Poet., 1451b,
4 - 5].88They believed in the possibility of a genre of historical writing aimed at expressing
universal meanings through concrete events and characters.89
Following this perception, the director of the Artaxata performance stopped his choice
on the Bacchae of Euripides as a model of his interpretation of the event of the day. Sup-
posedly, he departed from the idea that “[…] tragedy is an imitation of an action that is
serious, complete, and of certain magnitude” [Arist., Poet., 1449b, 12]. As it is obvious
from ensuing text, it was first of all implemented with an intention to define an action
which is complete and whole. In its turn, “A whole is that which has a beginning, a mid-
dle, and an end”[Arist., Poet.,1450b, 27].90 For tracing this, we must restore the plot of the
81 Hellenism was an elite cultural phenomenon having its specific particularities in each concrete country.
See, Traina, 2002, 22 – 23.
82 The eminent theologian and philosopher P. Florensky as a specific method of perception work out the
theory of the reverse perspective when the inner space of an audience actively implements the content and
meaning of a piece of art. See Florensky, 2006, 218 - 221.
83 Cohen, 2001, 115 – 118. The tradition of the like banquets was vivid at the Achaemenid court. As to the
Seleucid court, it combined the Greek and Iranian traditions. Cf. Brosius, 2011, 41 – 44; Murray, 1996, 22 – 24.
84 Wecowski, 2014, 28 – 33.
85 Murray, 1990, 5.
86 Borza, 1983, 47 – 48; Chaniotis, 1997, 224 – 226.
87 On the problem of the Hellenistic theater in Hellenistic Greater Armenia see, Goyan, 1952, 79 – 103;
Traina, 2010, 95 – 102; Stepanyan, 2015, 115 – 118.
88 Vernant, 1990a, 245 – 246. The following fact is very indicative: Polybius the greatest critic of tragic
history could not remain indifferent to its principal perception, and viewed the performance (qevama) Tyche
in world history. Cf. Walbank, 1985, 225.
89 Marincola, 2013, 78 – 80.
90 Butcher, 1920, 334 – 336; Ackrill J., 1977, 595 – 601; It must be underlined that modern narrative
52
tragedy in brief:
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
It begins with the comeback of Dionysus from the East to Thebes to take
avenge on the royal house refusing to recognize and worship him. He also
desires to vindicate his late mother, Semele, disgraced by the Thebans. God
drives the Theban women into ecstatic madness and sends them on the top of
Mount Cithaeron to commit orgies. They are turned into maenads and are led
by Agave - the sister of Semele and mother of the young Theban king Pen-
theus. Dionysus meets with Pentheus disguised as a Stranger and enchants
him as well. He convinces him to put on woman’s clothing and go to Cithaer-
on to watch the orgies. But maenads catch him and in wild rush tear to piec-
es. In their mad imagination, Pentheus looks like a young lion. More active is
Agave who holds the lion’s head above her head solemnly leading the mae-
nads to Thebes. She is in ritual delight but the trance soon wears off. She
comes back to reality understanding that she has killed her beloved son. The
mother’s grief is limitless, and nobody can condole with her. The vengeance
ognize Dionysus’ divinity. The second fragment began with the song preparing the ent-
rance of Agave. The participants likely had to restore the connection of the two fragments
by memory proceeding from the text of Euripides.
theory proceeds just from this Aristotelian idea. See White, 1984, 3- 5.
91 The two persons make up the main opposition of tragic plot - Dionysus and Pentheus (anti-Dionysus).
The first embodies the polarities of vitality: life and death, joy and sorrow, wisdom and violence. As to the
second, he is tyrannous, lawless and selfish. See Vernant, 1990b, 403.
92 In other words, the director of the performance was an adherent of the genre of the tragic history.
About the problems of the genre see, Walbank, 1985, 227 – 229; Marincola, 2013, 82. It is well traceable
in the works of Plutarch. De Lacy, 1952, 159 – 171; Zadorojny, 1997, 169 – 182; Mossman, 1998, 83 – 93.
93 On the structure and functions of these associations (tecni~tai Dionusiakoiv) see Sifakis, 1967, 99 – 103;
Evans, 2008, 114 – 116.
94 The similar practice was well known at Hellenistic courts. See Borza, 1983, 171; Chaniotis, 1997, 232.
53
The deviation from Euripides plot began in the third fragment. A messenger of the
general Surena came up to the door of the banqueting-hall: “[…] and after a law obeisance
cast the head of Crassus into the center of the company” [Plut., Crass., 33, 2]. He brought
information about offstage events. From this point on, a new tragedy plot began on the con-
ventional scene of the hall. With applause and shouts of joy, the audience accepted the main
idea of the director about the identity of Pentheus and Crassus.95 In this light, the Roman
general looked as tyrannous, lawless and selfish antihero whose evil destiny was inevitable.
Meanwhile, Jason of Tralles continued in this vein, discarded the costume of Pen-
theus: “and assuming the role of the frenzied Agave, sang these verses as if inspired”:
We bring from the mountain
A tendril fresh-cut to the palace,
A wonderful prey” [Eur., Bacch., 1170 – 1172, Plut., Crass., 33, 3].
Following Euripides’ plot, the audience would come back to the image of the unhappy
mother who had killed her son. In the case of Crassus, Mother-Rome would have been
imagined in the role of Agave. According to this logic, the ideology of the tragic perfor-
mance would have coincided with that of the ritual procession in which Rome represented
the pole of evil. As it is shown above, the procession reflected the Parthian official inter-
pretation formulated in the ideological center of the king of kings.96 However, such expec-
tations did not come to pass. The deviation from the standard plot continued, and Agave
came up to her renowned dialogue with the chorus:
“Who slew him? (Chorus)
Mine is the honour”. (Agave) [Ibid.].
Suddenly, one of the Parthian grandees, Pomaxathres97: “[…] sprang up and laid hold
of the head, feeling that it was more appropriate for him to say this than for Jason” [Plut.,
Crass., 33,3]. On this occasion, the new interpretation of the plot became apparent: Moth-
er-Rome had no part in the murder of Crassus. The author of this tragic incident was a
Parthian grandee. In Plutarch’s words, the Parthian king was delighted and endowed both
Pomaxathres and Jason with rich gifts. Supposedly, this interpretation was a surprise for
him.
The author of the new plot had a task to legitimize the alteration through the previous
course of actions of the antihero. He would have to make it in accordance with the canon
of tragic plays, looking particularly for the point when the change of fortune occurred.98
Keeping in mind the fact that tragedy represented a complete action, he would have to
come back to the beginning of the Parthian expedition of Crassus.99
The beginning of Crassus’ expedition, according to Plutarch’s narrative, was marked
with dramatic events. In 54 BC, Crassus held consulship with Pompey, and Syria fell to
him for the forthcoming five years by lot.100 He accepted this with great exaltation and
95 Stepanyan, 2015, 121.
96 On this center and its activity see in detail: Neusner, 1963, 58; Dąbrowa, 2008, 25 – 31;
97 Most probably the name derived from Nomoxavqrh§ (= Av. Nāmōxšathra). Cf. Justi, 1895, 254.
98 According to the canon of the classical tragedy, this point (to; metabolei~n) was designed to reveal the
essential motives and movements of the plot. de Romilly, 1970, 17; Wiles, 1997, 134 – 135.
99 Cf. Smith, 1968, 10 – 14.
100 It was an imitation of the common practice of the sortation of provinces between consuls (sortiri pro-
vincias). Cf. Badian, 1992, 891 -892.
54
began thinking: “[…] he would not consider Syria nor even Parthia as the boundaries of
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
his success, but thought to make the campaigns of Lucullus against Tigranes and those of
Pompey against Mithridates seem mere child’s play, and flew on the wings of his hopes as
far as Bactria and India and the Outer Sea” [Plut., Crass., 16, 2].
Crassus boasted in this manner among the intimate circle of his friends but the rumor
was soon spread in Rome, and the enemies initiated attacks against him. The plebeian tri-
bunes101 were more active: invested with sacred power of veto in the borders of the City,
they did their best to stop the expedition. They motivated their denial by divine and hu-
man justice: “[…] and a large party arose which was displeased that anyone should go out
to wage war on men who had done the state no wrong (oujde;n ajdikou~sin), but were in
treaty relations with it (ajll j ejnspovndoi§)” [Crass., 16, 3]102. They particularly pointed out
the fact that: “[…] in the decree which was passed regarding his mission there was no
mention of a Parthian war” [Ibid.]. Caesar and Pompey, on the contrary, supported and
encouraged Crassus.
On the day of the departure, the multitude was summoned by the plebeian tribunes to
101 The collegium of plebeian tribunes was probably established in 494 BC. It contained ten members who
were charged with the defense of the lives and property of the Roman citizens (ius auxilii). The person of the
tribunes was sacrosanct, and nobody could insult them without sever punishment. If unanimous, they could
excise a veto (ius intercession) against the acts of magistrates, laws, election and senatus consulta. They could
also hold comitia tributata and pass decries. The authority of the tribunes was valid in the borders of the City.
See Abbott, 1901, 195 – 198; Momigliano, 1992, 1092; Lintott, 1999, 30 – 32; North, 2011, 264 – 266.
102 The procedure of the allotment of provinces usually resulted with a Senate decree designating the main
tasks of the governor’s future mission. Cf. Lintott, 1999, 102.
103 Pompey understood that the campaign was fraud with great dangers that could cause it to end in disas-
ter. However, he supported Crassus since such an outcome would not contradict his own plans. Supposedly,
the same was true about Caesar’s support.
104 The walls and gates of the City spatially limited the power of the plebeian tribunes. At the same time,
it was valid if all the member of the collegium (ten tribunes) were unanimous. Momigliano, 1992, 1092.
55
state” [Plut., Crass., 14, 5].105In other words, the Mother herself was in great danger and
was not responsible for the evil actions of her son.106 From this perspective, the beginning
and the end of Crassus’ life-tragedy seemed to be equivalent narrative units107.
According to such interpretation, Rome was no longer assessed as the pole of evil,
and the Parthian expedition of Crassus appeared as an unfortunate accident implemented
by his personal avarice and vainglory. Consequently, with the catastrophe and murder of
the antihero, the restoration of peace and harmony could now be quite possible. This mes-
sage to Rome was uttered in the Armenian court through the deviation from the plot of the
Bacchae of Euripides.108
The correspondence of this message with the policy of Tigran II in last
years of his reign was obvious. It implied friendly relations (amicitia) of
Greater Armenia with both Rome and Parthia.109 In other words, the strategy
demanded from the country to support none of the conflicting super-state
against the other. In this light, we can tentatively reconstruct Artavazd’s argu-
mentation as well: he had supported neither Crassus against Parthia nor
Orodes II against Rome. His strategy implied a neutral position - beyond
alienation and hatred, victory and defeat - to endorse a compromise, the
equivalent of the existential and moral mean (to; mevson).110 In semiotic per-
ception, the situation could be defined through the formula “neither… nor”.111
The symmetric correspondence of the beginning of Crassus’ Parthian campaign with
his tragic end performed in the Armenian court suggested that they may have composed
the crucial elements of a tragic history which may have made up one of important primary
sources of Plutarch’s narrative about Crassus’ eastern campaign.
We now come up to the last point of the present investigation concerning the author-
ship of the performance in the Artaxata court. Indeed, who directed the semantic develop-
ment of the historical play and skillful deviation from the plot of the Bacchae? The answer
to his question can only be tentative and based on common logic of the situation, which,
as demonstrated above, was that the palace performance and the artistic representation of
the exoneration of Rome sought the restoration of the policy of friendship of Greater Ar-
menia with both super-states. The text of Plutarch may help point us in the right direction
as it contains a rather transparent allusion to the authorship of the performance.
Embellishing the portrait of Artavazd II, the author pinpoints the fact that he “actually
composed tragedies, and wrote orations and histories” [Plut., Crass., 33, 2]. It is well
105 Some could even have interpreted this approach as an indication of the sympathy of the director to
the old Roman Republic. However, I find it too bold in view of the fact that we have no direct accounts of
it in our primary sources.
106 Usually, the Romans vindicated their military setback by the will of omnipotent Destiny. However, the
case of Crassus was an exception: in time, the Roman public opinion formed a steady belief that his disaster
resulted from his avarice and vainglory. See Traina, 2010, 209 – 212.
107 This equivalence makes up the narrative mainstream of numerous literary genres. Cf. Smith, 1968, 10 – 14.
108 Stepanyan, 2012, 183 – 186.
109 It was after Artaxata treatise of friendship with the Romans (66 BC.), Tigran II came to terms with the
Parthian king Phraates II: “For they both well understood that whichever of them should conquer the other
would simply help along matters for the Romans and would himself become easier for them to subdue. For
these reasons they were reconciled” [Dio Cass., 37, 7, 4]. Cf. Stepanyan, 2012, 138 – 139.
110 According to Aristotle, the mean marked the desirable middle of two extremes of the same quality. It
corresponded to virtue excellence and beauty [Arist., Nic. Eth., 1106b, 19 - 29].
111 Stepanian, 2013, 32.
56
known that the king had been tutored under the supervision of the Greek intellectuals who
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
had found refuge in the court of Tigran II.112 Among them the philosopher Methrodorus of
Scepsis and the orator Amphicrates of Athens were most renowned [Plut., Luc., 22, 10].
Moreover, Plutarch states that some of the works of Artavazd II were still preserved
(wnJ~ ei[nai diaswvzontai) [Plut., Crass., 33, 2]. The eminent biographer and moral philos-
opher was writing his Parallel Lives in Greece more than a hundred years after the events
under consideration, and it would not be exaggeration to state that the works of the Arme-
nian king continued to hold the interest of Greek intellectuals. Does Plutarch’s statement
indicate that he had actually used Artavazd’s works? An absolute answer again remains
tentative; nevertheless, there is a high degree of probability that he did that.113
In this regard, a synopsis of the lost historical work attributed to the king Artavazd
could presumably have looked as follows:
The three most influential politicians of Rome, Caesar, Pompey and
Crassus, set up triumvirate to subdue the Republic. They occupied all the
power and divided the empire between themselves. By lot, Crassus obtained
of his narrative was to transform the crucial events of the past and present into historical
narrative.116 This experience is to be viewed in the context of the first attempts of introduc-
ing the western canon of historiography in Armenia.
112 They made up an intellectual center operating under the patronage of the queen of queens Cleopatra.
Stepanyan, 2012, 320 – 322.
113 It is fair to underline that G. Goyan had already come to the belief that the Artaxata performance was
directed by Artavazd II. See Goyan, 135- 148.
114 The director, obviously, departed from the idea that the form and context of the performance of a trag-
edy made the audience: “[…] to view the same characters and circumstances in a consciously constructed
drama that pointed to a world beyond the theater”. Rehm, 1994, 46.
115 A similar arrtoach is aopted by Merkelbach, 1995, 71 - 72.
116 According to P. Ricoeur, this transformation passes through two important phases. First, it shapes events
into a novel (plot), after that reshapes it into history. Ricoeur, 1985, 214.
57
Conclusion
Summing up the sketch of the process of introducing the western historical canon in
ancient Armenia, two genres of it must be pointed out, the pragmatic and the tragic histo-
ries. They varied by research approaches and methods but pursued the same purpose to
reshape the past and present as a comprehensible narrative able to give answers to the es-
sential questions of historical investigation – how, when, and why happened this or that
crucial event. This approach, however, did not entirely replace traditional epic history, and
within time, a synthetic genre emerged aimed at the synthesis of the two genres.
The western canon of historiography was introduced as a branch of Hellenistic elite
culture concentrated in the two capitals of Greater Armenia, Artaxata and Tigranocerta. In
the royal court, lived and created a group of intellectuals - rhetors, philosophers, writers,
who set up the brain center called to perform the Greek intellectual achievements in this
remote land. Some of them even tried to interpret history of the country in accordance
with the Hellenistic perceptions. By their efforts, the mentioned genres of historiography
became prominent in Greater Armenia.
Primary sources give clear evidence about the genre of pragmatic history, associating
it with the name of Metrodorus of Scepsis, the eminent rhetor and philosopher. The main
concern his work On Tigranes was world history focused on the deeds of Tigran II. It in-
terpreted them in the light of the political theory of Hellenistic age and had a purpose to
legitimate Tigran’s empire as the personification of creative intentions of the East – both
earthly and heavenly. Supposedly, it depicted the empire as a space of absolute peace and
order led by the king to the prosperity of all ethnic and social units. The political propa-
ganda of Tigran II considered the empire in the train of the great empires of the East - As-
syria, Media, Achaemenid Iran and Seleucid Empire. It is no accident that Pompey justi-
fied the Roman dominance in Syria proceeding from the results of Artaxata treaty.
As to the second genre, the tragic history, it was associated with the name of Artavazd
II. There is reason to believe that the king used the plots of eminent Greek tragedians to
pattern the historical events of the past and present in order to uncover their profound
metaphysic essence. Tragic history concerned the poetry of history and was ready to an-
swer the question “what might happen” in this or that concrete situations. Applying the
tools of tragic history, Artavazd II gave his interpretation of the Parthian campaign of
Crassus, the insane son who caused a great trouble, against the will of his mother (Rome).
In this light, Artavazd’s authorship of the renowned Armavir inscription receives a new
share of probability.
Of course, all these constructions are of assumptive character. However, in every case,
this quality was formed in accordance with numerous (though indirect) accounts and con-
jectures. A fact that bestows our restorations with a higher degree of probability.
Bibliography
Sources
Aristotle, 1902, The Poetics. Translation by S.H. Butcher (London, Macmillan & Co.).
Aristotle, 1926, Nicomachean Ethics. With an English translation by H. Rackham (Cambridge
(Ma), London, Harvard Univ. Press).
Cassius Dio Cocceianus, 1961, Roman History, v.3 – 4, With an English translation by E. Cary
58
(Cambridge (Ma), London, Harvard Univ. Press).
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
Cicero M.T., 1942, De oratore, book III. With an English translation by H. Rackham (Cambridge
(Ma), Hervard Univ. Press).
Cicero M.T., 1967, De natura deorum, books I – II. With an English translation by H. Rackham
(Cambridge (Ma), Hervard Univ. Press).
FHGr, 1848, Fragmenta historicorum graecorum, ed. C. et Th. Mülleri, t. II – III (Parisis, Ambrosio
Firmin Didot).
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ
Iustinus, 1976, Trogi Pompei Historiarum Philippicarum Epitoma (Lipsiae, ed. Teubner).
Moses Khorenatsi, 1978, History of the Armenians. Translation and commentary on the literary
sources by R. W. Thomson (Cambridge (Ma), London, Harvard Univ. Press).
Paterculus Velleius, 1955, Roman History, v. 1 – 2, With an English translation by F.W. Shipley, in:
Compendium Historiae Romae (Cambridge (Ma), Harvard Univ. Press).
Philo of Alexandria, 1993,The Works of Philo. Complete and Unbridged. New Updated Version.
Trans. by C.D. Yonge (Peabod (Ma), Hendrickson Publ.).
Pliny, 1949 – 1954, Natural History, in 10 v. With an English translation by H. Rackham, W.H.
Jones, D.E. Eichholtz (Cambridge (Ma), London, Harvard Univ. Press).
Plutarch, 1914 – 1916, Parallel Lives, v.2 -3. With an English translation by B. Perrin (Cambridge
Rome).
Arnold E.V., 1911, Roman Stoics (Cambridge, UP).
Asdourian P., 1911, Die politischen Beziehungen zwischen Armenien und Rom von 190 v.Chr. bis
428 n. Chr.(Venedig, Mechiteristenbuchdruckerei).
Avagianou A., 2008, Hieros Gamos in Ancient Greek Religion: The Human Aspect of a Sacralised
Ritual, in: Sacred Marriages: The Divine-Human Sexual Metaphor from Sumer to Early
Christianity, ed. by M. Nissinen & R. Uro (Winona Lake (In), Eisenbraus), 145 – 172.
Badian E., 1958, Alexander the Great and the Unity of Mankind, Historia, 7, 425 – 444.
Badian E., 1992, Crassus Marcus Licinius, The Oxford Classical Dictionary, 295.
Baldry H. C., 1965, Unity of Mankind in Greek Thought (Cambridge, UP).
Ball W., 2002, Rome in the East. The Transformation of an Empire (London, New York, Rout-
ledge).
Barnes J., 1989, Antiochus of Ascalon, in: Philosophia Togata. Essays on Philosophy and Roman
59
Society, ed. by M. Griffin and J. Barnes (Oxford, Clarendon Press), 51 - 96.
Barret J., 2002, Staged Narrative. Poetics and Messenger in Greek Tragedy (Berkeley, Los Ange-
les, London, Univ. of California Press).
Belikov, A.P., 2001, Parthian Campany of Crassus, Para Bellum (Military-Historical Journal), 12,
[Беликов А.П., Парфянский поход Красса, Para Bellum (Военно-исторический
журнал), 12], 103 - 119.
Bivar A.D.H., 2006, Political History of Iran under the Arsacids, in: Cambridge History of Iran,
v.3/1, ed. By E.Yarshater (London, New York, Cambridge Univ Press), 21 – 99.
Borza E.N., 1983, The Symposium at Alexander’s Court Text (1983), Ancient Macedonia, 3, (Thes-
saloniki), 45-55.
Bosworth A.B., 1980, Alexander and the Iranians, The Journal of Hellenic Studies, 100, 1 – 21.
Botsford G.W., 1922, Hellenic History (New York, Macmillan Co.).
Boyce M., 1983, Achaemenid Religion, Encyclopaedia Iranica, ed. by E. Yarshater (New York,
Mazda) v.1/4, 426 – 429.
Braund D., 1984, Rome and the Friendly King. The Character of the Client Kingship (London,
New York, St. Martin’s Press).
Bringmann K., 1993, The King as Benefactor: Some Remarks on Ideal Kingship in the Age of Hel-
lenism, in: Images and Ideologies. Self-definition in the Hellenistic World, ed. by E.
Gruen et al. (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London, Califprnia Univ.Press), 7 - 24
Bringmann K., 1997, Posidonius and Athenion: A Study in Historiography, in: Hellenistic Con-
structs. Esseys on Culture, History and Historiography, eds. P. Cartledge, P. Garnsey, E.
Gruen (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London, Univ. of California Press), 159 – 174.
Brosius M., 2011, New out Old? Court and Court Ceremonies in Achaemenid Persia, in: Court and
Court Societies in Ancient Monarchies, ed. by T.J.S. Spawforth (Cambridge, New York,
CUP).
Brown E., 2009, The Emergence of Natural Law and the Cosmopilis, in: The Cambridge Compan-
ion to Ancient Greek Political Thought, ed. by S. Salkever (Cambridge, UP), 331 – 364.
Brubaker R., 2004, Ethnicity without Groups (Cambridge (Ma), Harvard Univ. Press).
Bundy D., 2007, Early Asian and East African Christianities, in: The Cambridge History of Christi-
anity (CHCh), ed by A. Casiday and F. W. Norris (Cambridge UP), 118 – 148.
Bury J.B., 1909, The Ancient Greek Historians (Harvard Lectures) (London, Macmillan & Co.).
Butcher S. H., 1920, Aristotle’s Theory of Poetry and Fine Art (London, Macmillan & Co., 4 th ed.).
Campbell B., 1993, War and Diplomacy: Rome and Parthia, 31 BC. – AD. 235, in: War and Society
in Roman World, ed. by J. Rich and G. Shipley (London, New York, Routledge).
Canepa M., 2010, Technology of Memory in Early Sasanian Iran: Achaemenid Sites and Sasanian
Identity, American Journal of Archeology, 114/4, 582 – 584.
Cartledge L., 2006, Historiography and Ancient Greek Self-Definition, in: Companion to Historiog-
raphy (London, New York, Routledge, 2d. ed.), 20 – 37.
Castiglioni L., 1928, Motivi antiromani nella tradizione storica antica, in: Recordi dell’instituto
Lombardo, 61, 625 – 639.
Chaniotis A., 1997, Theatricality beyond the Theater. Staging Politic Life in the Hellenistic World,
Pallas, 47, 219 – 259.
Clarke K., 1999, Between Geography and history. Hellenistic Constructions of the Roman World
(Oxford, Clarendon).
Cumont F., 1931, La fin du monde selon les mages occidentaux, Revue de l’histoire des réligions,
103, 29 – 96.
Dąbrowa Ed., 2008, The Political Propaganda of the First Arsacids and Its Targets (From Arsaces I
to Mithradates II), in: Parthica 10 (Incontri di culture nel mondo antico), ed. A. In-
vernizzi (Pisa, Roma, Fabrizio Serra), 25 – 31.
Dąbrowa Ed., 2010, The Parthian Kingship, in: Concepts of Kingship in Antiquity, Proceedings of
the European Science Foundation Exploratory Workshop: Padova, Nov. 28 – Dec. 1,
2007 (Padova, S.A.R.G.O.N. Editrice e Libreria), 123 – 134.
60
Dan A., 2014, Les concepts en sciences de l’Antiquité: monde d’emploi (Chronique 2014 – Les
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
transferts culturels) Dialogue d’histoire ancienne, 40/1, 239 – 305.
Daryaee T., 2006, The Construction of the Past in the Late Antique Persia, Historia (Zeitschrift für
Alte Geschichte), 55/4, 493 – 503.
de Lacy Ph., 1952, Biography and Tragedy in Plutarch, American Journal of Philology, 73/2, 159 – 174.
de Romilly J., 1970, La tragédie greque (Paris, PUF).
Debevoise N.C., 1968, A Political History of Parthia, 2d ed. (New York, Greenwood Press).
Downey G., 1951, The Occupation of Syria by the Romans, Transactions and Proceedings of the
American Philological Association, 82, 149 – 163.
Dumézil G., 1938, Vahagn, Revue de l’histoire des religions, 117/2, 152 – 170.
Dvornik F., 1966, Early Christian and Byzantine Political Thought: Origins and Background (Lo-
cus Valley, New York, Dumbarton Oaks Center for Byzantine Studies).
Eremyan S. T., 1948, Principal Features of Social Order of Armenia in Hellenistic Age (Bulletin of
AS of Arm. SSR, 11) [Еремян С.Т., Основные черты общественного строя Армении
в эллинистическую эпоху (Известия АН Арм. ССР, 11)], 33 – 73.
Errington R. M., 2008, A History of Hellenistic World, 323 – 30 BC. (Oxford, Blackwell Publ.).
Erskine A., 2011, Between Philosophy and the Court: The Life of Persaios of Kition, in: Creating a
61
Heidegger M., 2009, Basic Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy, trans. by R.D. Metcalf, M.B. Tan-
zer (Bloomington, Indiana Univ. Press).
Herchenroeder L., 2010, Hellenistic Historiography and Sciences Practices and Concepts by Poly-
bius’ Histories. (A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the USG Graduate School
Univ. of Southern California).
Herman G., 2000, The Rock Reliefs of Sassanian Iran, in: Mesopotamia and Iran in the Parthian
and Sassanian Periods: Rejection and Revival, 238 B.C. – A.D. 642, ed. by V.S. Curtis
(London, British Museum Press), 35-45.
Huard R.L., 1976, Plato’s Political Philosophy. The Cave (New York, Algora Publ.).
Inwood B., 1999, Stoic Ethics, in: CHHPh, 675 – 738.
Jones A. H. M., Syrig H., 1992, Syria, The Oxford Classical Dictionary, 1030 - 1031.
Justi F., 1895, Iranisches Namenbuch (Marburg, N.G. Elwert’sche Vrlg.).
Klein J., 1992, Sacred Marriage, in: The Anchor Dictionary, v.5, ed. D.N. Freeman (New York,
Doubleday), 866 – 870.
Koester H., 1995, Ephesos in Early Christian Literature: Ephesos, Metropolis of Asia. An Interdis-
ciplinary Approach to its Archeology, Religion and Culture (Valley Forge, Trinity Press
International), 119 – 140.
Konstan D., 1997, Friendship in the Classical World (Cambridge, UP).
Kramer S. N., 1969, The Sacred Marriage Rite (Blomington, Indiana Univ. Press).
Liebman-Frankfort Th., 1969, L’istoire des parthes dans le livre XLI de Trogue Pompée. Essai
d’identification de ses sources, Latomus, 28, 894 – 922.
Lintott A., 1999, The Constitution of the Roman Republic (Oxford, UP).
MacDermot B.C., 1954, Roman Emperors in the Sassanian Reliefs, Journal of Roman Studies, 44,
76 -80.
Mahé J.-P., 1994, Moïse de Khoréne et les inscriptions gréques d’Armavir, TOPOI, Orient -
Occident, 4/2, 567 - 586.
Malitz J., 1982, Thukidides’ Weg zur Geschichtsschreibung, Historia, 31, 257 – 289.
Manandyan H. H., 1943, Tigran II and Rome: A New Interpretation Based on Primary Sources
(Yerevan, Armfan Publ.) [Манандян Я.А., Тигран II и Рим, В новом освещении по
первоисточникам (Ереван, изд. Армфан)].
Manandyan H. H., 1946, Armavir Greek Inscriptions in a New Interpretation (Yerevan, YSU Press)
[Манандян Я.А., Армавирские греческие надписи в новон освещении (Ереван, изд.
ЕГУ).]
Manandyan H. H., 1954, On the Trade and Cities of Ancient Armenia in Connection with World
Trade of Remote Times (V c. BC. – AD. XIV c.), 2d ed. (Yerevan, ESU Press) [Манан-
дян Я.А., О торговле и городах древней Армении в связи с мирoвой торговлей
древних времен (V в. До н. э. – XIV в. н.э.)(Ереван, изд. ЕГУ)].
Marincola J., 1997, Authority and Tradition in Ancient Historiography (New York, Cambridge UP).
Marincola J., 2013, Polybius, Plutarchus and Tragic History: A Reconstruction, in: Polybius and his
World, In Memory of F.W. Walbank, ed. by B.Gibson and Th. Harrison (Oxford, OUP),
73 – 90.
Marwick A., 2001, The New Nature of History. Knowledge, Evidence, Language (London, Pal-
grave).
Mauskopf Deliyanis D., 2003, Introduction, in: Historiography in the Middle Ages, ed. by D.
Mauskopf Deliyanis (Leiden, Boston, Brill).
Mehl A., 1980/1981, DORIKTHTOS CWRA. Kritische Bemerkungen zum ‘Speererwberb’ in Politik
und Völkerrecht der hellenistische Epoche, Ancient Society, 11/12, 173 – 212.
Merkelbach R., 1995, Die Trimeter von Armavir - Inschrift eines armenischen Königs?, Epigraphi-
ca Anatolica, 25, 71 - 72.
Merlan P., 1967, Greek Philosophy from Plato to Plotinus, in: The Cambridge History of Later
Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy, ed. by A.H. Armstrong (Cambridge, UP), 14 –
136.
62
Mintz A., 1996, Hurban: Responses to Catostrophe in Hebrew Literature (Syracuse, UP).
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
Mitsis Ph., 1999, The Stoic Natural Rights, in: Topics in Stoic Philosophy, ed. by K. Ierodiakonou
(Oxford, UP), 153 – 177.
Momigliano A., 1966, Time in Ancient Historiography, History and Theory, 6/6, 1 – 23.
Momigliano A., 1992, Tribuni Plebis, in: The Oxford Classical Dictionary, 1092.
Morford M., 2002, The Roman Philosophers, From Time of Cato the Censor to the Death of Mar-
cus Aurelius (London, New York, Routledge).
Mossman J.M., 1998, Tragedy and Epic in Plutarch’s Alexabder, Journal of Hellenic Studies, 108,
83 – 93.
Movsisyan A., 2003, Writing Systems in Pre-Mashtots Armenia (Yerevan, YSU Publ.) [Մովսիսյան
Ա., Նախամաշտոցյան Հայաստանի գրային համակարգերը (Երևան, ԵՊՀ
հրատ.)].
Munslow M., 2007, Narrative and History (New York, Palgrave Mac Millan).
Murray O., 1990, Sympotic History, in: Sympotica: A Symposium on the Symposion, ed. by O.Mur-
ray (Oxford, UP), 3 – 13.
Murray O., 1996, Hellenistic Royal Symposia, in: Aspects of Hellenistic Kingship, ed. by P. Bidle
et al. (Aarhus, UP), 15- 27.
63
Arm.SSR Publ.) [Սարգսյան Գ.Խ., Հելլենիստական դարաշրջանի Հայաստա
նը և Մովսես Խորենացին (Երևան, ՀԽՍՀ ԳԱ հրատ)].
Sargsyan G. Kh., 1969, Historiography of Pre-Mashtots Period, Historical-Philological Journal of
AS of the Arm.SSR, 1 [Սարգսյան Գ.Խ., 1969, Նախամաշտոցյան շրջանի
պատմագրությունը, ՊԲՀ, 1], 107 – 126.
Sargsyan G. Kh., 1976, Unification and Reinforcement of Armenia under Artashēs I, in: History of
Armenian People, v.1, ed. by S.T. Yeremyan et al. (Yerevan, AS of the Arm SSR)
[Սարգսյան Գ.Խ., Հայաստանի միավորումը և հզորացումը Արտաշես Ա-ի
օրոք, ՀԺՊ, hատ. I, խմբ. Ս.Տ. Երեմյան և այլք (Երևան, ՀԽՍՀ ԳԱ հրատ)],
521 – 553.
Schofield M., 2003, Stoic Ethics, in: The Cambridge Companion to Hellenistic World, ed. by G.R.
Bugh (CCS) (Cambridge, New York, CUP), 233- 256.
Scullard H.H., 1963, From Gracchi to Nero. A History of Rome from 133 BC. to 68 AD. (London
Methuen and Co. Ltd, 2d ed.,).
Scullard H.H., 1992, Metrodorus of Scrpsis in Mysia, The Oxford Classical Dictionary , 685.
Sellars J., 2007, Stoic Cosmopolitanism and Zeno’s Republic, History of Political Thought, 27/1, 1
– 29.
Shahbazi A. Sh., 1991, Carrhae, Encyclopaedia Iranica, v.5/9 – 13.
Sherwin-White A.N., 1984, Roman Foreign Policy in the East: 168 BC. – AD.1 (Norman, Univ. of
Oklahoma Press).
Sifakis G.M., 1967, Studies in the History of Hellenistic Drama (London, Athlon Press).
Smith B.H., 1968, Poetic Closure: A Study of How Poems End (Chicago, UP).
Sreedharen, 2004, A Textbook of Historiography, 500 BC. to AD.2000 (New Delhi, Orient Long-
man).
Stadter Ph. A., 2002, Historical Thought in Ancient Greece, in: A Companion to Western Historical
Thought, ed. by L. Kramer, S. Maza (Malden, Oxford, Blackwell Publ.), 35 – 59.
Stanton, 1968, The Cosmopolitan Ideas of Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius, Phronesis, 13, 183 – 195.
Stepanyan A.A.1991, Development of Historical Thinking in Ancient Armenia. Myth, Rationalism,
Historiography (Yerevan, AS of the Arm. SSR Press) [Степанян А.А., Развитие исто-
рической мысли в древней Армении. Миф, рационализм, историописание (Ереван,
изд. АН Арм ССР)].
Stepanyan A.A., 2012, Metamorphoses of History in Greater Armenia, v.1 The Age of the Artaxiads
(Yerevan, S. Khachents • Printinfo) [Ստեփանյան Ա.Ա., Պատմության կերպա
փոխությունները Մեծ Հայքում. հ.Ա Արտաշիսյան դարաշրջան, Ս.Խաչենց
• Փրինթինֆո].
Stepanyan A. A., Minasyan L. R., 2013, Greater Armenia and Euphrates Frontier in 60-s AD (Con-
flict, ideas, settlement), The Journal of Armenian Studies, of NAS of the RA, 1, 14 – 33.
Stepanyan A.A., 2014, Metrodorus of Scepsis: An Attempt of Reconstruction of Historical Concept,
in: The Trace of History: Deeds, Writings, Essence (Yerevan, Printinfo) [Ստեփանյան
Ա. Մեթրոդորոս Սկեփսացի. պատմասիրական համակարգի վերականգ
նման փորձ, Պատմության հետագիծը. Գործք, Գրույթ, Իմաստ (ՊՀ)
(Երևան, Փրինթինֆո)], 194 – 211.
Stepanyan A. A., 2015, Relations between Tragedy and Historical Experience in Plutarch (Crassus,
33), Journal of the Society for Armenian Studies, 24, 112 – 123.
Storey I.C., Allan A.A., 2005, A Guide to Ancient Greek Drama (Oxford, Blackwell).
Strootman R., 2011, Hellenistic Court Society: The Seleukid Imperial Court under Antiochos the
Great, in: Royal Courts in Dynastic States and Empires: Global Perspectives, ed. by J.
Duindam, M. Kunt, T. Artan (Leiden, Brill), 63 – 89.
Suderman W., 2012, Oracles of Hystaspes, in: Encyclopaedia Iranica, v.XII, fasc. 6, 606 – 609.
Swain J.W., 1940, The Theory of Four Monarchies: Opposition History under Roman Empire, Clas-
sical Quarterly, 35, 1 – 21.
64
Syme R., 2002, The Roman Revolution (Oxford, UP, 5th ed.).
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
Taho-Godi A. E., 1969, Hellenistic Perception of the Term “History” and Those Related to It, Prob-
lems of Classical Philology, 2 [Тахо-Годи А.Э., Эллинистическое поминание
термина “история” и подственных с ним, Вопросы Классической филологии, 2],
127 – 137.
Tarn W.W., 1948, Alexander the Great (Cambridge, UP).
Thümmel H. G., 1984, Posidonius und die Geschichte, Klio, 66, 558 - 561.
Tiratsyan G.A., 1958, Orontids in Armenia, Bulletin of Humanitarian Sciences of AS of the Arm.
SSR [Տիրացյան Գ.Ա., Երվանդունիները Հայաստանում, ՀՍՍՌ ԳԱ Տեղեկա
գիր հասարակական գիտությունների] 6, 53 - 72.
Tiratsyan G.A., 1971, Armenian in Early Hellenistic Age, in: History of Armenian People, v.1, ed.
By S.T. Eremyam, (Yerevan, AS of Arm SSR Publ.) [Տիրացյան Գ.Ա., Հայաստանը
վաղ հելլենիզմի դարաշրջանում, ՀԺՊ, հ.1, խմբ. Ս.Տ. Երեմյան և այլք,
(ՀՍՀ ԳԱ հռատ.)], 500- 520.
Tiratsyan G.A., 1988, Culture of Ancient Armenia, VI c. B.C.–A.D. III c.: According to Archeologic
Data (Yerevan AS of Arm. SSR Press) [Тирацян Г.А., Культура древней Армении, VI
в. до н.э. – III в. н.э., Ереван, изд. АН Арм. ССР].
23/1, 1 – 33.
White M., 2003, Stoic Natural Philosophy, in: The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, ed. by B.
Inwood (Cambridge, UP), 124 – 152.
White S., 2010, Stoic Selection: Objects, Actions, and Agents, in: Ancient Models of Mind. Studies in
Human and Divine Rationality, ed. by A. Nightingale and D. Sedley (Cambridge, UP).
Wiles D., 1997, Tragedy in Action (Cambridge CUP).
Yarrow L. M., 2006, Historiography at the End of the Republic. Provincial Perspectives on Roman
Rule (Oxford, UP).
Yates F.A., 1966, Selected Works, v.3, Art of Memory (London, New York, Routledge).
Zadorojni A.V., 1997, Tragedy and Epic in Plutarch’s Crassus, Hermes, 125/2, 169 – 182.
Zeller Ed., 1886, Outline of the History of Greek Philosophy (London, Longmann).
Zeller Ed., 1892, The Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics (London, Longmann).
65
Ամփոփում
Ալբերտ Ա. Ստեփանյան
ՊԱՏՄՈՒԹՅԱՆ ՏԵՍՈՒԹՅՈՒՆ
Պատմության ողբերգական և պրագմատիկ ըմբռնումները միայն դա
րեր անց, 5-րդ դարում, վերընձյուղվեցին հայոց քրիստոնեական հելլենիզ
մի մշակութային միջավայրում: Եվ ասվածի լավագույն դրսևորումը Եղիշեի
և Մովսես Խորենացու պատմական երկերն են:
Резюме
против упрощенного восприятия истории, полагая, что она способна раскрывать ме-
тафизические глубины прошлого и настоящего. Театрализацию истории они рассма-
тривали как эффективный путь достижения подобной цели. Известное представле-
ние, организованное в царском дворе Арташата (53 г. до Р.Х.) дает основание ду-
мать, что Артавазд II был преемником этого направления. Из детального анализ тек-
ста Плутарха, рассказывающего об этом, можно полагать, что его автором, вероят-
нее всего, был сам царь. Именно этим объясняется внимание историографа к его
произведениям.
Прагматический и трагический жанры историографии вновь появились в армян-
ской среде спустя лишь столетия, в 5-м веке, в контексте культуры христианского
эллинизма. Лучшими проявлениями этого стали произведения Егишэ и Мовсеса Хо-
ренаци.
67