Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

01 Callahan

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

BRITISH INTER-UNIVERSITY CHINA CENTRE

Tianxia, Empire and the World:


Soft Power and China’s Foreign Policy Discourse in the 21st Century

William A. Callahan
University of Manchester

BICC WORKING PAPER SERIES, No. 1

May 2007

The BICC Working Paper Series is the official scholarly forum of the British Inter-University
China Centre (BICC), a joint project between Oxford, Bristol, and Manchester Universities.
BICC has been awarded a grant of £5m from the Higher Education Funding Council for England,
the Economic and Social Research Council and the Arts and Humanities Research Council with
the aim of making it Britain's leading centre for research and teaching on China and Chinese
language. The BICC Working Paper Series aims to publicise and disseminate original research
carried out by scholars with interest in China worldwide. The BICC Working Papers are only
available online and are free for downloading; we however request that when used for the
purpose of research they are appropriately acknowledged. The papers published in this series do
not necessarily appear in their final form, and can be revised and submitted to another forum.

1
Tianxia, Empire and the World:
Soft Power and China’s Foreign Policy Discourse in the 21st Century

Abstract
China’s recent ‘charm offensive’ is captivating the world stage. Although there has been a
thorough cataloguing of China’s soft power assets in terms of the effectiveness and limitations of
the PRC’s public diplomacy, much less attention has been paid to how the normative aspect of
China’s growing soft power will set the world agenda. This essay will examine the concept of
‘Tianxia’ to understand Chinese visions of world order. Tianxia is interesting both because it was
key to the governance and self-understanding of three millennia of Chinese empire, and also
because discussion of Tianxia is becoming popular again in the twenty-first century as an
alternative world order that is universally valid. Firstly, the paper will examine Tianxia tixi [The
Tianxia System], a popular book that discusses an all-inclusive world order that aims to solve the
globe’s problems with a world institution that embraces difference through a ‘magnanimous’
system of governance. Then it will examine some of the philosophical and historical problems
posed by this romantic understanding of Tianxia, in particular how its approach to ‘Otherness’
encourages a ‘conversion’ of difference, if not a conquest of it. The essay thus examines how
Tianxia has been redeployed in ways that blur the conceptual boundaries between empire and
globalism, nationalism and cosmopolitanism. It concludes that Tianxia is a strong example of
how domestic and international politics overlap and inform each other as part of a broader
struggle over the meaning of ‘China’. Soft power thus works not just in international influence,
but also can tell us about the identity politics of national image in domestic politics. Hence rather
than guide us towards a utopian world order that will solve global problems, Tianxia is an
example of how some in China are working to re-center Chinese understandings of world order
as a patriotic activity. This essay thus 1) critically describes a non-western worldview as an
example of soft power, and 2) examines how ideas get put into play in Chinese foreign policy
discussions.

Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the Centre for Chinese Studies at the University of Manchester and the
British Academy/Chinese Academy Social Sciences visiting fellowship for funding fieldwork in
China. Comments from the following people were very helpful: Sumalee Bumroongsook, Elena
Barabantseva, David Blaney, Paul A. Cohen, Mustapha Kamal Pasha, Chih-yu Shih, Wang
Yizhou, and the participants at the World Economics and Politics Institute seminar where I
presented this essay.

Biography
William A. Callahan is Chair of International Politics at the University of Manchester. He is also
the Research Director of Manchester’s Centre for Chinese Studies and Co-Director of the British
Inter-university China Centre. He has published articles on East Asian politics in journals
including International Organization, Alternatives, Asian Survey, Journal of Contemporary
China, and his most recent books are Contingent States: Greater China and Transnational
Relations (Minnesota, 2004) and Cultural Governance and Resistance in Pacific Asia
(Routledge, 2006).

2
Tianxia, Empire and the World:
Soft Power and China’s Foreign Policy Discourse in the 21st Century

I. Introduction: Soft power, utopia and politics in China


In the past two decades many concepts have been floated to understand post-Cold War
international politics, ranging from ‘the end of history’, to ‘the clash of civilizations’,
‘globalization’, and new understandings of ‘empire’.1 With the rise of anti-Americanism around
the world in the wake of the Iraq War, the concept of ‘soft power’ has taken on new relevance.
Indeed, although Joseph Nye introduced this concept to rationalize a decline of US hard power in
the early 1990s, in 2003 he felt it necessary to clarify and systematize the soft power concept at
the height of US hard power. Nye’s purpose in the 2000s thus was different, namely to warn the
American leadership of the hazards of ‘going it alone’ as the sole superpower in the twenty-first
century.2 But while American soft power has experienced a dramatic decline in the past five
years, the soft power of the concept itself has increased: ‘soft power’ has now spread beyond
analyses of US influence to understand the non-coercive power of the European Union, Japan
and other states.3
Most recently, the concept of soft power has been employed to understand the rise of
China beyond its growing military power and economic clout. Rather than acting as a
revolutionary power that challenges the international system, Beijing has been engaging in a
‘charm offensive’ to convince the world of its peaceful status quo intensions. Scholars thus have
been busy analyzing the People’s Republic of China (PRC)’s growing soft power in terms of
state policies that have successfully spread China’s culture, language, development model and
peacekeeping troops around the world.4
One of the most important aspects of soft power is the ability of a state to set the agenda
of international politics and use its values to define not only world problems, but also define the
range of solutions to these problems.5 Although there has been a thorough cataloguing of China’s
soft power assets in terms of their effectiveness and limitations, much less attention has been
paid to the normative aspect of soft power. If the predictions about China overtaking the United
States to be the dominant superpower in the next few decades are true, then how would China
run the world?
Investigation of Chinese visions of world order are not new – in 1968 the doyen of
American Sinology, John King Fairbank, edited the seminal text on this topic: The Chinese
World Order: Traditional China’s Foreign Relations. 6 Fairbank’s idealized description of a
hierarchical Sinocentric world order with the Chinese empire at the core and loyal tributary states
and barbarians at the periphery has generated considerable debate over the past four decades.7

1
Fukuyama 1989; Huntington 1993; Held, et al. 1999; Hardt and Negri 2000; Harvey 2003.
2
Nye 1991; Nye 2003; Nye 2004; Leheny 2006. Although Nye coined the term, the concept of soft power
draws on earlier international politics theorists such as Hans J. Morgenthau, Ray S. Cline, Klaus Knorr,
Richard N. Rosecrance, Robert Cox and sociologists such as Steven Lukes (see Nye 1991, 29-35, 266).
3
Nye 2004, 73-89; Haine 2004; Leheny 2006.
4
Gill and Huang 2006; Ramo 2004; Kurlantzick 2006; Pan 2006; Joseph S. Nye, ‘The Rise of China’s
Soft Power’, Wall Street Journal Asia (29 December 2005). Chinese officials and scholars have also been
discussing the PRC’s growing soft power (see Embassy of the People’s Republic of China in the United
States of America, ‘Soft power, a new focus at China’s “two sessions”’, (14 March 2007); Pang 2006;
Pang 2005; Wei 2005).
5
Nye 2004, 7.
6
Fairbank 1968b.
7
Fairbank 1968a; Rossabi 1983; Mancall 1983; Cohen 1986; Hevia 1995; Kang 2003; Liu, LH 2004.
Hevia (1995:7-15) summarizes much of this debate. Fairbank’s view also informs understandings of

3
But what is most interesting is that while prominent western experts have concluded that China
is status quo power that is unlikely to challenge the international system,8 this idealized version
of China’s imperial past is now inspiring Chinese scholars’ and policy-makers’ plans for China’s
future – and the world’s future. Rather than simply provide suitably Chinese parallels to
‘international’, ‘security’ or other mainstream international relations concepts, many public
intellectuals in Greater China have been promoting the ancient concept of ‘Tianxia’ (天下) to
understand Chinese visions of world order in ways that go against China’s official policy of
peacefully rising within the international system.
Tianxia is interesting both because it was key to the governance and self-understanding of
three millennia of Chinese empire, and also because discussion of Tianxia is becoming popular
again in the twenty-first century. In April 2005 a prominent philosopher at the Chinese Academy
of Social Sciences (CASS), Zhao Tingyang, published Tianxia tixi: Shijie zhidu zhexue daolun
[The Tianxia System: A Philosophy for the World Institution] to describe a Chinese model of
world order that is universally valid.9 The Tianxia System became a best-seller in China because
it caught a wave of interest in Chinese-style solutions to world problems, and especially an
interest in how the traditional concept of Tianxia combines the seemingly contradictory
discourses of nationalism and cosmopolitanism. Tianxia thus has become a topic of conversation
not just among public intellectuals and IR scholars, but also in much the broader arenas of
popular culture and state policy: Zhang Yimou’s recent film Hero was not just an international
blockbuster, it also promoted the notion that heroism involves sacrificing everything for
Tianxia. 10 Likewise, Chinese president Hu Jintao’s new ‘harmonious world’ foreign policy
narrative draws on concepts similar to Zhao’s Tianxia system.11 Discussion of Tianxia also has
spread beyond China’s borders: the premier historian of overseas Chinese, Wang Gungwu, chose
‘Tianxia and Empire’ as the topic for the inaugural Tsai Lecture at Harvard in 2006, while
Chinese-American academic Fei-Ling Wang warned of the influence of concepts like Tianxia in
the International Herald Tribune, as did Geneva-based Xiang Lanxin in Singapore’s United
Morning News [Lianhe zaobao].12 Hence in the past few years, there has been a Tianxia buzz not
just in China, but also among the Chinese diaspora, as part of a lively debate over whether
Tianxia constitutes ‘China’s contribution’ to world civilization. While Chinese scholars have
been employing traditional concepts – including Tianxia – to explain current domestic and
foreign policies for over a decade, 13 Zhao’s plan for a Chinese-inspired world utopia
dramatically shifted these discussions from the margins to the mainstream as a sort of patriotic
cosmopolitanism. In this way, the Tianxia system is the current answer to the perennial question
that transfixes policy elites in China: what is China’s proper role in the world?
Discussions of cosmopolitanism in the past few decades have often sought to decenter
power and knowledge relations, and question hierarchical modes of governance. Yet recent
trends among Chinese intellectuals are going in a different direction: ‘decentering’ has been the
problem for Chinese intellectuals; their key goal for past century has been to ‘re-center’ China as
the focus of world politics.14 In terms of its economic strategy, China certainly is ‘going global’

China’s traditional foreign policy among many current international relations scholars in the PRC (see
Qin 2006; Yan 1995; Dan 2005).
8
See Shirk 2007; Shambaugh 2006; Johnston and Ross 2006; Shambaugh 2004/05; Johnston 2003.
9
Zhao 2005.
10
Zhang YM 2004.
11
See Hu 2005.
12
Wang GW 2006; Fei-Ling Wang, ‘Heading Off Fears of a Resurgent China’, International Herald
Tribune, (11 April 2006); Xiang Lanxin, ‘Jieyan quqi, shenyan hexie’ [Give up talking about [China’s]
rise, be careful discussing [world] harmony], Lianhe zaobao (Singapore), (26 March 2006).
13
See Dan 2005, 23-38; Li 1999; Sheng 1995; Liu 1992.
14
See Tu 1994; Tu, et al. 1992.

4
by seeking to create a set of successful ‘Chinese’ global consumer brands, as well as developing
its own set of global technical standards. 15 This essay will explore how Chinese state
intellectuals likewise have been involved in developing universal standards of civilization for a
Chinese-style world order.
To explore the normative aspects of emerging China’s soft power politics, this essay will
examine Zhao’s discussion of how the all-inclusive Tianxia system would solve the world’s
problems with a world institution that embraces difference through a ‘magnanimous’ system of
governance. Since Zhao (as we will see below) is looking to the positive aspects of Chinese
thought, the first section will sympathetically summarize his argument.16 Then the next section
will examine some of the theoretical and historical problems posed by this romantic
understanding of Tianxia, in particular how its approach to ‘Otherness’ encourages a
‘conversion’ of difference, if not a conquest of it that transforms all difference into the (Chinese)
self.
The essay thus examines how Tianxia recently has been redeployed by China’s
intellectuals of the state and public intellectuals among the Chinese diaspora in ways that blur the
conceptual boundaries between empire and globalism, nationalism and cosmopolitanism. It
concludes that Tianxia is a strong example of how domestic and international politics overlap
and inform each other as part of a broader struggle over the meaning of ‘China’. Soft power thus
works not just in international influence, but also can tell us about the identity politics of national
image in domestic debates. The power of Tianxia comes less from the sophistication of its
theoretical argument than from its strategic placement in China’s discursive networks of power.
Rather than guide us towards a utopian world order that will solve global problems, Tianxia is an
example of the workings of soft power in the sense that it re-centers Chinese understandings of
world order as a patriotic activity in domestic politics. The popularity of Zhao’s very peculiar
book therefore helps us understand how discussions of ‘soft power’ often tell us more about a
state’s internal identity politics than about its role in international society. In other words, it
shows how worldview, national image and soft power are intimately linked in discussions of
foreign policy.17

II. The Tianxia system


The problem in international politics today, according to Zhao, is not ‘failed states’ but a ‘failed
world’.18 Indeed, he declares that our world is actually a ‘non-world’.19 Here Zhao is appealing
Chinese philosophy’s guiding normative logic: while ‘world’ should refer to a peaceful order,
what we have is a disordered world of chaos. While many would see world disorder as a political
or an economic problem (that would be solved by a better political or economic system), Zhao
feels that world chaos is a conceptual problem: ‘to order the world we need to first create new
world concepts which will lead to new world structures’.20 Since western concepts (especially

15
Ramo 2007; Zhang YJ 2005; Suttmeier, et al. 2006.
16
This is more difficult than it may appear. The book contains three long chapters that utilize many of the
same arguments and examples in sometimes contradictory ways. In a way, this book was not written as a
single narrative, but is a collection of Zhao’s musings on Tianxia. Moreover, the book is transnational in
form as well as content – two of the three chapters were first written and presented in English (see Zhao
2006a), and only later translated into Chinese in a more detailed and polemical style (Zhao 2005, 34, 110).
It is necessary to describe the Chinese version because the Chinese book is the text that informs broader
debate over soft power and foreign policy in the PRC.
17
See Wei 2005; Ramo 2007; Wang HY 2003; Embassy of the People’s Republic of China in the United
States of America, ‘Soft power, a new focus at China’s “two sessions”‘, 14 March 2007.
18
Zhao 2005, back cover.
19
Ibid, 21, 110.
20
Ibid, 1.

5
those from the Westphalia system) have gotten us into this mess, Zhao boldly states that only the
Chinese concept of Tianxia – literally translated as a All-under-heaven – can properly order the
world. Throughout his discussion, he plays with the definition of this ancient and often vague
term, sometimes reading Tianxia as ‘the World’, and other times understanding it as ‘Empire’.
Either way, Tianxia is presented as a legitimate world order that is very different from western
imperialism. This new way of thinking of global problems on a global scale presents a utopia
that orders political relations in quite different ways from popular understandings of
globalization and cosmopolitanism. 21 But this is a utopia that will set the analytical and
institutional framework necessary to solve the world’s problems – in other worlds, Tianxia is
presented as a utopia that has practical applications.

Tianxia: three interwoven meanings


In its most basic sense, Tianxia is a geographical term. Tianxia is actually one of the few
classical Chinese concepts that uses two characters: tian and xia. Tian is the heavens, the sky,
and what is on top, while xia is an indexical term meaning below, lower, inferior.22 Tianxia thus
refers to everything below the sky, and thus is commonly used in classical texts to refer to the
earth or to the (Chinese) world.
But Zhao argues that in addition to this material and geographical sense, Tianxia also
contains two other important meanings that are not just descriptive, but normative: a) Tianxia
referring to all the people, the people’s heart (minxin 民心), the people’s will, and b) Tianxia as
the world institution.23 Each of these three meanings of Tianxia – geographical, psychological,
and institutional – is necessary and interdependent in Zhao’s normative world. They are
indivisible; otherwise ‘Tianxia-the world’ would be ‘destroyed’.24 Here Zhao is elaborating on
Chinese thought – Tianxia is actually not the focus of contemporary or historical debate in
Chinese philosophy – and directing his arguments at a much wider audience to tackle problems
not just in political philosophy, but in political science.25 In this way Zhao seeks to unify not
only the world, but the world of thought as well.26

1. Tianxia as ‘the World’ geographically


Zhao argues that world chaos comes from using the improper perspective to view the world,
conceptualize its problems and thus formulate solutions. Arguing that a world order based on
national interests leads to conflict – including wars – Zhao tells us that we need to think about
world order in terms of a truly world view. The world’s problems are too big for any one nation,
superpower, region or international organization. Although the United Nations and the European
Union are good ways of thinking beyond the state that come from good intentions, Zhao feels
that they are still limited by their reliance on the analytical framework of international relations
that is based on thinking from the nation-state.
To counter this mainstream way of framing ‘the international’, Zhao looks to an ancient
passage from Lao zi’s Daode jing (Ch. 54) that instructs us to ‘use the world [Tianxia] to
examine the world [Tianxia]’. Zhao uses this important passage to argue that Tianxia is more
than a place: it is a method for looking at world problems and world order from a truly global
perspective – thinking through the world rather than thinking about the world from an inferior
national or individual perspective. While existing theories provide a ‘view from somewhere’,
21
Ibid, 35.
22
See Xu 1981, 1, 2.
23
Zhao 2005, 41, 123-24.
24
Ibid, 42.
25
Ibid, 32.
26
Ibid, 30. For a historically informed discussion of the unity of world and the world of thought in China
see Bøckman (1998, 310-46).

6
Zhao’s Tianxia presents a holistic ‘view from everywhere’.27 Likewise, to have world order, we
need to measure the world according to a world standard, rather than according to national
interests.
By thinking through the world with a view from everywhere, Zhao argues that we can
have a ‘complete and perfect’28 understanding of problems and solutions that is ‘all-inclusive’.
With this all-inclusive notion of Tianxia, there is literally ‘no outside’ (wuwai – 无外). Since all
places and all problems are domestic, Zhao says that ‘this model guarantees the a priori
completeness of the world’.29 World unity thus leads to world peace and world harmony.

2. Tianxia as ‘all the people’


The all-inclusive nature of Tianxia is more than geographical. Zhao uses it to define the second
notion of Tianxia as ‘all the people’. Here he underlines how a proper Tianxia system does not
have an ‘outside’ either geographically or ethically.30 While the present world system is defined
according to the competing needs of nation-states, Zhao highlights how Chinese thought stresses
political philosophy, especially ethics and human relations. Zhao looks to Carl Schmitt to argue
that the west organizes political life according to distinctions between friends and enemies,31
which inevitably leads to division and conflict. He constrasts this with Chinese philosophy’s all-
inclusive nature, where difference is not converted into absolute Otherness. While the west
organizes human relations around the idea of ‘tolerance’, according to Zhao China looks to the
practice of being ‘magnanimous’ (dadu 大度) to difference: ‘Those who come are not rejected,
resulting in very beneficial and good things’. Citing Derrida’s argument that we ‘only have to be
tolerant toward intolerable things’, Zhao feels that tolerance is only necessary when we basically
promote our own values. While China can have a ‘tolerant heart’, it doesn’t have ‘tolerant
thought’; rather China has ‘magnanimous thought’ that doesn’t reject ‘the Other’.32
In China’s all-inclusive Tianxia system, then, distinctions between inside and outside,
and even friends and enemies are more relative than absolute.33 While the west divides the world
according to racial distinctions, Chinese thought unites it according to an ethical logic that is
cultural. 34 The goal of the Tianxia system is ‘transformation’ (hua 化 ): the aim of this
‘comprehensive model’ is to change the self and the Other, and thus normatively order ‘chaos’
by transforming the ‘many’ into ‘the one’.35 While Schmitt defines politics as the practice of
publicly distinguishing between friends and enemies, Zhao tells us that ‘Tianxia theory is a
theory for “transforming enemies into friends,” where “transformation” seeks to attract people
rather than conquer them’.36
Thus Tianxia as ‘the world’ includes ‘all peoples’. Zhao glosses the famous classical
passage ‘Tianxia is shared’ (Tianxia wei gong) to argue that ‘Tianxia is the people of Tianxia’s
Tianxia. The people of Tianxia all think in terms of Tianxia. Of course this is the superior
ideal’. 37 Likewise, Zhao quotes another famous classical passage, ‘Tianxia is one family’
(Tianxia yi jia) to argue that the world is one family.38

27
Zhao 2005, 108.
28
Ibid, 40.
29
Ibid, 51.
30
Ibid, 14, 30.
31
See Schmitt 1996.
32
Zhao 2005, 13.
33
Ibid, 51.
34
Ibid, 53-4.
35
Ibid, 13.
36
Ibid, 33.
37
Ibid, 30.
38
Ibid, 41, 77.

7
The philosophical and political problem, for Zhao, is how to represent the interests of the
people of Tianxia as a truly world interest. He argues – at length – that democracy is illegitimate
for representing the world interest because 1) it is based on individual desires, which are
manipulated in both elections and surveys, and 2) although democratic institutions may work in
domestic politics they don’t (and he argues can’t) work on a global scale.39 Because of these
problems and contradictions, democracy is judged to be an ‘erroneous’ way of determining the
people’s will.
Because ‘the masses always make the wrong choices’, Zhao reasons that the people’s
general will needs to be determined by a ‘careful observation of social trends’. These ‘careful
and sincere observations’, Zhao tells us, ‘can better detect the truth and come to a better
reflection of public choice than do democratic elections’.40 Since the masses are easily misled,
only the elite can think through the world and have a ‘view from everywhere’.41 Moreover, since
‘most people do not really know what is best for them, but that the elite do [sic], so the elite
ought genuinely to decide for the people’.42 Zhao thus concludes that majority rule needs to be
guided by the rule of the majority of the Tianxia people’s ‘elite’. 43 Indeed, Zhao states that
democratic elections have led to the ‘disasters’ of Hitler’s Germany and America’s ‘new
imperialism’.44 Therefore the elite task of representing the people’s heart is more important than
popular democracy.45 The criteria to judge the people’s heart thus is not ‘freedom’ but ‘order’ –
which is one of the main themes of Chinese thought (i.e. order/chaos – zhi/luan 治/乱). Tianxia,
Zhao reminds us, refers to the greatest and highest order.46

3. Tianxia as the world institution


Since the Tianxia system is defined by order, Zhao argues that this alternative world order needs
to be established and maintained through a world institution. As he concludes the book: ‘Tianxia
theory is the core philosophy … that provides the deepest theoretical plan for the world
institution’.47 Because Tianxia refers to the greatest order, its structure as the world institution
has fundamenental legitimacy.48 Again, Zhao tells us that although the EU and the UN seem to
be super-state regional and world institutions, they are limited by a worldview that is based on
nation-states.49
While the west organizes political life in terms of the three levels of ‘individual,
community and nation-state’, Zhao tells us that Chinese political thought looks to the levels of
‘Tianxia, state, and family’. While the western world prioritizes the individual and works in
terms of the nation-state, the Tianxia system starts at the largest level, Tianxia, and orders
political and social life in a top-down manner.50
The legitimacy of the Tianxia world system does not come from procedural measures
such as those that define liberal democracy (i.e. elections or the outcome of rational debate in
civil society), but from two substantive criteria: universal effectiveness and complete

39
Ibid, 19.
40
Zhao 2006a, 31.
41
Zhao 2005, 108.
42
Zhao 2006a, 32.
43
Zhao 2005, 28-9, 57.
44
Ibid, 152.
45
Ibid, 28; also see Zhao 2006b.
46
Zhao 2005, 31.
47
Ibid, 160.
48
Ibid, 31.
49
Ibid, 151-55.
50
Ibid, 17.

8
transitivity.51 Thus the political rules and ethical judgements that apply at one level need to apply
effectively at all levels: remember that democracy is an ‘error’ because it applies only at the
domestic level of the state, but not at the world level of Tianxia. To argue these points about
effective transitivity, Zhao uses a famous passage from the Confucian ‘Great Learning - Daxue’
that links pacifying Tianxia, governing the state and properly ordering families.52 He argues that
this logic shows the ‘priority and primacy of world governance by a world institution’ with order
‘descending down to states and families’.53 In this hierarchy, both ends of this continuum are
important – but for different reasons: while Tianxia provides political order for ‘inferior’ levels,
family (jia 家) morality sets the ethical standard for superior levels.54 As a way of shifting our
attention away from state-centric views of order and world politics, Zhao stresses that the family
and Tianxia are the two pillars of his world institution.
Zhao concludes one of the core chapters of The Tianxia System with a comparative
analysis of historical empire systems, arguing that the Tianxia system is the most appropriate for
the twenty-first century.55 The Roman empire, the British empire, and America’s new empire all
have fatal flaws. The Roman empire was a universal empire that expanded its territory through
military conquest, and thus had no natural borders. The British empire, on the other hand, is an
example of modern imperialism that is based on the logic of the nation-state, which integrated
the illegitimate ideas and practices of nationalism, imperialism, and colonialism. This conjuction
of capitalism and imperial colonialism resulted in an unbalanced world system that followed the
divisive logic of the nation-state by imposing territorial borders between peoples. America’s
‘new empire’ of globalization has transformed modern imperialism’s direct control into a more
hidden domination of the world’s politics, economics and culture. This globalization of
American values means that the US not only plays the game, but sets the rules as well – which
Zhao feels is ‘disastrous’.56
Lastly, Zhao presents the ‘Tianxia model’ as the solution to both modern imperialism and
new imperialism.57 While previous empires have taken a particular nation-state as the model and
universalized its particular values, criteria and standards, Tianxia is the only system that thinks
through the world. When we take Tianxia as an a priori and complete concept for the world
institution, then we can distinguish a positive globalism from a negative globalization.58 Still,
Zhao stresses that he is not advocating the resurrection of ancient China’s imperial practice; his
objective is to sketch out a utopia, with Tianxia theory providing only a ‘theoretical plan’ that
utilizes the resources of China’s tradition thought.59 Indeed, he spends the bulk of this five page
description of Tianxia criticizing other people and other places: the US-led Iraq War,
Habermas’s communicative rationality, Nye’s soft power, Hardt and Negri’s new understanding
of empire, the international politics of human rights, the limits of liberalism, and so on.60
Hence Zhao doesn’t dwell on the details of how the world institution would work in the
twenty-first century, or how we would get from the present international system to his utopian
Tianxia system, except to note that participation is voluntary.61 At other times, Zhao states that
while Tianxia institution is shared, each locality would be independent economically, politically

51
Ibid, 19.
52
See Confucius 1971, 357-59.
53
Zhao 2006a, 8.
54
Ibid.
55
Zhao 2005, 102-09.
56
Ibid, 102-05.
57
Ibid, 105-09.
58
Ibid, 105.
59
Ibid, 106.
60
Ibid, 106-09.
61
Zhao 2006a, 36.

9
and culturally as sub-states in the Tianxia system rather than autonomous nation-states in the
Westphalian international system.62 Indeed, on the last page of the book Zhao opines that ‘What
we have discussed here is merely limited to the philosophical questions of Tianxia theory, and
the realization of the future’s world institution model certainly poses very complicated questions,
which philosophy cannot yet answer’.63
To sum up, Zhao tells us that the world has serious political problems that need to solved
first conceptually, and then institutionally. Zhao’s arguments grow out of a more general feeling
among Chinese intellectuals that China’s ethical system of domestic and international order was
destroyed by the violent tendencies of selfish (Western) nation-states that operated in the
Westphalian world system that continues to order the world. Zhao provides the Tianxia system
as the solution to the world’s problems, arguing that we need to think through the world to
understand it, and thus effectively and legitimately govern it. Tianxia is a hierarchical system
that values order over freedom, ethics over law, and elite governance over democracy and human
rights. It is literally a ‘top-down’ prescription for the world’s ills. Employing a mixture of
tradition and modernity, the book uses ancient texts to propose a very modern solution to the
very modern problems of world order. Tianxia is presented as the proper all-inclusive master
narrative of world order that will solve all the world’s problems through a single master
institution that has ‘no outside’ and operates according to a ‘view from everywhere’. Rather than
being like contemporary philosophical debates that often question such master narratives, Zhao’s
reasoning is like popular strands of theoretical physics that seek the final ‘theory of everything’.

III. Philosophical and Historical Criticism


Before proposing the Tianxia system as the solution to the world’s problems in the body of the
book, in his ‘Introduction’ Zhao needs to clear the scholarly terrain of rival theories from both
China and the west. He quickly goes through the history of contemporary Chinese thought,
arguing most strongly against a group of scholars who give a robustly self-critical view of
China’s struggles with modernity and the west.64 Zhao feels that this obsession with ‘digging up
skeletons’ from China’s past and looking to the west for answers makes the Chinese people lose
hope, and thus damages China’s ‘social cohesion and unity’. 65 He quotes Foucault’s
power/knowledge argument,66 but argues that ‘at the same time we also must stress the relations
of “knowledge/responsibility” as the theoretical meaning of knowledge’. He concludes that ‘truth
is not the highest judgment, for truth must be good, truth must be responsible, because in the end
what humanity needs is life, not truth’.67
Zhao’s project thus is to ‘transcend the historical limits’ of Chinese tradition in order to
explore the theoretical possibilities offered by Chinese thought for dealing with contemporary
problems.68 Rather than dwelling on ‘past mistakes’, Zhao very deliberately takes what he calls a
‘positive view’ of Chinese tradition: ‘Simply put, we must discuss the positive meaning of the
concept of “China”’.69 In this way, Zhao is able to revive an 3000 year old (and unachieved)
ideal like Tianxia by looking to ‘its conditions of possibility’ and ‘potential beyond history’.70

62
Zhao 2005, 78.
63
Ibid, 160.
64
For an interesting discussion of debates in contemporary Chinese thought see Wang Hui (2003, 140-
187).
65
Zhao 2005, 4-5.
66
See Foucault 1980.
67
Zhao 2005, 5-6.
68
Ibid, 16.
69
Ibid, 3.
70
Ibid, 46.

10
The goal thus is not criticize China (whose problems are all figured as in ‘the past’ rather than
the present), but to ‘rethink China’ in order to deal with the world’s future.71
Beyond his general rhetorical style, Zhao’s presentation of the Tianxia system raises a
number of issues for both classical Chinese philosophy and contemporary social theory. I will
first examine the problems of his use of classical Chinese texts, and then consider the problems
of his engagement with contemporary social theory.

Chinese philosophy
Zhao is certainly not the first Chinese scholar to look to tradition for answers to contemporary
problems. This was the task of New Confucian movement of the twentieth century, which was
revived in the 1980s-90s on mainland China by overseas Chinese scholars such as Harvard’s Tu
Weiming. Curiously, recent philosophical and social science investigations of Chinese thought
rarely discuss ‘Tianxia’ as a global idea. 72 Rather they look to Confucian ethics to see how
Chinese culture can help us better understand social relations in terms of human interactions on a
very inter-personal scale, or look to tian to explain China’s immanent and anthropomorphic
spirituality.73 The closest they come to Zhao’s work is in trying to shift discussions of human
rights from legalistic ‘rights talk’ to concentrate more on ‘human dignity’ figured as the product
of human relations, which includes obligations to society. 74 Thus rather than explore the
possibilities of Tianxia system, this diverse group of scholars is more interested in ‘Confucian
humanism’. More to the point, although many contemporary scholars are also interested in
Confucianism as a universally valid philosophy, it is common to distinguish ‘Confucian
humanism’ from the historical legacy of ‘imperial Confucianism’ as an authoritarian state
practice. Hence most authors consciously avoid talking about Tianxia as part of the
contemporary potential of Chinese thought.75
While Zhao is certainly striking out in a new direction by exploring the theoretical
possibilities of Tianxia, his argument is based on a cavalier use of a few key passages from
Chinese thought, which upon closer consideration actually don’t support his Tianxia worldview.
Zhao’s argument for thinking through the world is based largely on his reading of Chapter 54 of
Lao zi’s Daode jing: ‘use the world [Tianxia] to examine the world [Tianxia]’. This passage is
cited numerous times in each chapter, but Zhao usually takes it out of context. The larger passage
is ‘use the self to examine the self, use the family to examine the family, use the neighbourhood
(bang 邦) to examine the neighborhood, use the world to examine the world. How do I know that
the workings of the world [Tianxia] are like this? From this’.76 Thus while there is nothing in this
passage that prioritizes Tianxia over other spaces of activity – and actually suggests that we start
with the self, not with the world – Zhao reads it as a top-down hierarchy: ‘while you can’t easily
sacrifice the needs of units at one level for the interests of a unit at another level, at the same
time, it also signifies that the superior levels have to exist, and that common interest comes from
them more than from the units at the inferior levels’. 77 Quoting Lao zi to support a world
institution also goes against the general tenor of the Daode jing, where utopia is presented as
suspicious of grand ordering projects and even thinking beyond one’s village (see chapters 60,

71
Ibid, 10-11.
72
See Tu, et al. 1992.
73
Tu 1989; Hall and Ames 1998, 235-44; Tu el al. 1992.
74
Ames 1997; Rosemont 1988; Zhao 2005, 22-25, 98, 109; Zhao 2006b.
75
Also see Xiang Lanxin, ‘Jieyan quqi, shenyan hexie’ [Stop talking about [China’s] rise, be careful
discussing [world] harmony], Lianhe zaobao (Singapore), (26 March 2006).
76
Translation based on Ch’en 1981, 241-42; Chen 1985, 273-75. For a different interpretation see Ames
and Hall (2003, 160-62).
77
Zhao 2005, 62.

11
80). Thus, Zhao is disingenuous in his use of the Daode jing to support his argument for a
hierarchical world order that thinks through the world and acts through world institutions.
Zhao likewise plays fast and loose with other key classical Chinese texts. Throughout the
book, Zhao employs the phrases ‘Tianxia is shared – Tianxia wei gong’ and ‘Tianxia is a family -
Tianxia yi jia’ to support his argument that Tianxia is the highest and best perspective, and that it
works like a family.78 But, once again, these phrases come from a key classical text – the Book of
Rites (Liji)’s ‘Great Harmony’ – the full passage of which actually calls into question Zhao’s
arguments.79 A closer consideration of the Great Harmony passage shows how these two phrases
are going in opposite directions: while ‘Tianxia is shared’ is the utopian goal, ‘Tianxia is a
family’ refers to the failure of Great Harmony. It is neither the norm nor the objective; ‘Tianxia
is a family’ is something to be avoided, or perhaps only tolerated.
Is Zhao’s presentation of Tianxia a productive ‘misreading’80 of the Chinese tradition that
opens up theoretical possibilities? Perhaps. In many ways, Tianxia is an empty or negative term
– it refers to everything but the heavens – that needs to be explained and interpreted. While other
contemporary scholars stress the need to actively interpret Chinese thought,81 Zhao appeals to
‘tradition’ for authority while also using a more positivistic style of stating ‘facts’ and criticizing
‘errors’. I am not arguing that Zhao’s Tianxia system is ‘a lie’, ‘wrong’, ‘erroneous’ or a
‘mistake’, so much as suggesting that on philosophical grounds his use of Chinese texts is not
very persuasive. Rather than a productive misreading of the tradition, Zhao seems to be more
interested in selecting a few phrases to use as slogans to brand his new Tianxia system: ‘use
Tianxia to examine Tianxia’, ‘Tianxia is shared’, ‘Tianxia is a family’.

Social theory
In discussing the benefits of the Tianxia system, Zhao employs contemporary social theory’s
concept of self/Other relations to compare how analytical borders are drawn in China and the
west. Here he is following thinkers like Levinas and Bachelard in seeing social relations and
space as ethical and normative practices.82 Connolly and Walker applied this mode of analysis to
international relations to question how foreign policy emerges when the national self performs its
identity as a mode of exclusion of the Other as a foreign enemy.83 The critical aim of these
theorists is to resist the urge to convert difference into Otherness, and thus let diverse modes of
life exist.
Zhao’s most important argument, then, is that Chinese thought and the Tianxia system
provide a productive form of self/Other relations that does not alienate difference to the outside.
But upon scrutiny, Zhao’s argument that China has no outside or Others runs into problems. His
argument concentrates on how the west has absolutely excluded otherness, and has dealt with
difference through conquest. Yet Todorov’s analysis of early European-American encounters
shows how violent conquest is only one mode of dealing with difference: conversion to the
conqueror’s worldview is the other technique of imperial violence.84 In other words, although
exclusion is an important issue recent feminist analyses of patriarchal societies, for example,
have shown how it is important to examine how self/Other relations work to include difference
in hierarchical ways. Thus although Zhao’s all-inclusive Tianxia system may not have an outside,
its institutionally-backed ‘self’ utilizes both absolute exclusion and hierarchical inclusion to
control three social groups: the west, the people, and other nations along China’s frontier.

78
Zhao 2005, 30, 63, 65.
79
See de Bary 1960, 176.
80
See Bloom 1975.
81
Liu 2006; Tong 2006.
82
Levinas 2000, 75-88; Bachelard 1994.
83
Connolly 1991, 36-63; Walker 1993.
84
Todorov 1984.

12
1. Excluding ‘the west’
Zhao’s master narrative is based around a fundamental and absolute distinction between a moral
China and an immoral west, whose individualist thought system and Westphalian world system
he feels need to be transcended. Although Zhao is very interested in how analytical frameworks
set the terms of debate,85 he is going in a different direction from scholars such as Wang Hui
who argue that it is essential to question such absolute distinctions to understand China: ‘So, just
what are China’s problems? Or, what methods or even language should be used to analyze
them? … [since] the binaries of reform/conservatism, the West/China, capitalism/socialism, and
market/[state] planning are still hegemonic concepts … problems can hardly be brought to
light’. 86 Hence even though Zhao is very critical of how western thought employs absolute
binaries, he uses the same analytical framework of China/west to construct and exclude ‘the
west’ as the Other.
Although he cites numerous modern and contemporary western thinkers – including Kant,
Marx, Husserl, Schmitt, Habermas, Foucault, Rawls, Derrida, Hardt and Negri – Zhao does not
explore their views at any length. Rather he describes western thought in terms of an absolutist
version of Christianity that is intolerant of ‘heresy’, and violently excludes unbelievers as
‘pagans’.87 In this way, Zhao ignores the vibrant explorations of cosmopolitanism since Kant
revived this discussion in the late eighteenth century. Indeed, one Chinese word to describe
cosmopolitanism is Tianxia-ism (tianxia zhuyi).88 Perhaps Zhao overlooks current discussions of
cosmopolitanism because their focus on ‘cosmopolitan democracy’ 89 and ‘actually existing
cosmopolitanisms’ 90 runs against his Tianxia system’s unitary world institution governed by
elites. Zhao is more interested in critiquing ‘mainstream’ thought, so he likewise treats
international relations theory as nothing but state-centric realism, and thus does not consider how
post-positivist IR theory is self-critically considering many of the same questions that interest
him. In other words, Zhao is not interested in critically understanding western thought so much
as creating an Occidentalized west as the Other, so as to reaffirm the identity of Tianxia as the
all-inclusive self.
In a broader sense, Zhao is mixing up ‘is’ and ‘ought’ by using his utopian Tianxia model
to criticize the faults of historical empires. This is especially significant because China actually
has a 2500 year history of empire(s), and thus a wealth of historical experience in world
ordering.91 Moreover, each empire has had its own utopian ideal – Pax Romana, the civilizing
mission, white man’s burden, manifest destiny, free world, and so on – to inspire its governance
regime. In other words, all of the ‘western’ empires discussed in The Tianxia System have
likewise argued that they are best for the world as the manifestion of an altruistic philosophical
project that is not only just, but inevitable. In this sense, Zhao’s Pax Sinica mission is quite
similar to that of the western imperial scholars who he criticizes; he is likewise aiming to
integrate culture and power,92 in what some now call China’s ‘yellow man’s burden’ of using
China’s ethical mode of governance to pacify and civilize the world.93 As Friedman summarizes:

85
Zhao 2005, 1, 7.
86
Wang Hui 2003, 146.
87
Zhao 2005, 14, 49, 51-54, 59, 77, 99.
88
The more common Chinese word for cosmopolitism is world-ism (shijie zhuyi).
89
See Archibugi & Held 1995.
90
See Cheah & Robbins 1998.
91
See Wang GW 2006.
92
See Said 1978, 2; Said 2000, 346.
93
See Nyiri 2006, 106; Ren 2006, episode 12.

13
‘To be a Chinese patriot is to be an ethical being committed to a better future for the human race
in an authoritarian, hierarchical, China-centered world.’94

2. Guiding the masses


As noted above, Zhao’s main argument against democracy is that the world’s masses are
incapable of thinking through the world, and thus cannot be trusted to act in a truly world interest.
He goes on at length to criticize common people as ‘blind followers, selfish, irresponsible,
foolish, and vulgar’. Zhao likewise worries about the legitimacy of a society that is dominated by
‘swindlers, petty people, whores, idiots, and scoundrels’. 95 In this sense Zhao is following a
Maoist line of using the category ‘the people’ not inclusively to embrace all persons, but in a
restrictive sense that hierarchically organizes people according to the distinction of ‘the people’
and ‘non-people’.96 Zhao’s solution thus is not to totally exclude the people, but to include them
in a hierarchical way that is guided by the elite.

3. Conquering and Converting Other Nationalities


Zhao does not give much historical evidence for the utility of the Tianxia model. As we saw
above, he is more interested in the possibilities of pure thought than in the messy experience of
history. Even so, at times Zhao does elaborate on what he means by an all-inclusive Tianxia that
seeks to transform enemies into friends. But rather than stress how inside and outside are
‘intimately’ interwoven, 97 Zhao argues that Tianxia describes a place that is all part of the
normatively good ‘inside’, and thus lacks an outside (wuwai). Within the all-inclusive Tianxia,
there are distinctions between inside and outside (nei/wai 内/外), including in international
relations. 98 Yet Zhao feels that these relations are not of absolute Otherness, but of relative
cultural difference. Zhao thus uses imperial China’s ‘tribute system’ as the guiding model for the
effective integration afforded by Tianxia. He cites the example of inner and outer zones (neifu
and waifu) in the Sinocentric imperial order to explain how difference co-exists in the Chinese
system which was not organized around clear territorial borders. Rather imperial China and the
Tianxia system order the world through a series of concentric circles with the civilized imperial
capital at the center flowing out to embrace the various ‘barbaric’ peoples at the periphery. This
differentiation between inner and outer led to imperial China’s ‘civilization/barbarism
distinction’, where ‘[a]ccording to Chinese concepts, barbaric lands and tributary states became
beneficial competitors’ for Chinese civilization.99
While Zhao stresses that these were not racial distinctions, this is a moot point. If we
accept that ‘race’ is a pseudo-scientific concept deployed to explain cultural differences, then the
category of ‘racism’ did not exist before modern science and social Darwinism. When Zhao says
that the benefit of this ‘civilization/barbarism’ interaction was an ‘objective discussion of the
long term advantages and disadvantages of different cultures’, it certainly sounds like a hierarchy
of cultures analogous to modern racism and the PRC’s current concern with the ‘population
quality’ of its ethnic minorities.100 More to the point, these hierarchical cultural relations where
the goal is to transform enemies into friends follows the logic of the other technique of empire
discussed above: conversion.101 The workings of conversion are clear in this important passage
from the key Confucian text, The Mencius, which later became a slogan for a dominant strand of
94
Friedman 2007, 8.
95
Zhao 2005, 27.
96
See Schoenhals 1994.
97
Bachelard 1994, 217-18.
98
Zhao 2005, 53.
99
Ibid, 53, 59-61; also see Dan 2005, 25-39; Hevia 1995, 7-15; Fairbank 1968a.
100
Zhao 2005, 54; Jiang 1999, 8, 10, 12; Dikötter 1992; Kipnis 2006; Nyiri 2006.
101
See Todorov 1984.

14
Chinese frontier policy: ‘I have heard of the Chinese converting barbarians, but not of their being
converted by barbarians’. 102 While Zhao suggests that we need to transform peoples by
‘improving their interests’, Shapiro reminds us that community-building always entails
community-destroying.103
In current discussions of world order, it is popular to see traditional China as a benevolent
empire that provided peace and stability for centuries before the arrival of western imperialism in
the nineteenth century. 104 This narrative is now often used in international relations texts to
explain why China is not a threat to world order in the twenty-first century. 105 Yet this
comparison of a war-mongering Westphalian Europe with a peace-loving imperial China that
didn’t wage war for centuries employs a very narrow definition of ‘war’ as an inter-state
phenomena.106 Actually, the Chinese state was constantly engaged in violent interactions with
states and semi-states along its frontiers. In its first century, the Qing dynasty (1644-1911)
expanded massively in the west, including a struggle over the northwest frontier with Czarist
Russia and the Mongolian Zunghar state that lasted into the 1770s. Rather than being a case of
western imperial incursion into China, (as it is presented in Chinese modern history textbooks),
this episode is better understood as a violent struggle between three empires – the Manchu Qing,
Czarist Russia, and the Mongolian Zunghar – which resulted in the annihilation of the Zunghar
as a people.107 A key classical phrase that Zhao does not mention is instructive: ‘The Tianxia is
united’ [Tianxia yitong] describes ‘uniting the tianxia through conquest’.108 This reflects how the
Chinese empire had a para bellum policy where, as Johnston argues, war was a constant
occurrence in a zero-sum game that employed both pure violence and absolute flexibility.109
Violent conflict along China’s borders is down-played in Beijing’s official record
because this narrative was written by imperial officials from the center who engaged in what
Giersch calls ‘textual incorporation’: they told Beijing that the empire was in control of frontier
areas, when in fact it wasn’t.110 Indeed, new analyses of China’s borderlands are able to contest
the romantic view of China as a benevolent empire because they use sources from outsiders who
were subject to China’s often violent imperial control. Curiously, such research is not common in
China itself, where the Chinese empire is rarely seen as an example of imperialism (which
following Lenin is defined as a western capitalist phenomenon). Wang Hui explains that while
postcolonialism is popular in Chinese academia, it focuses on a critique of western imperialism,
thus making it ‘often synonymous with a discourse of [Chinese] nationalism’. Because imperial
China is distinguished from modern imperialism, there is ‘not a single Chinese postcolonial
critique of Han [Chinese] centrism from the standpoint of peripheral culture’.111
Hence Zhao’s argument that Tianxia is all-inclusive seems to miss the point that not
everyone wants to be included. China’s imperial and contemporary history in Tibet, Taiwan and
Xinjiang is instructive for what happens to difference that prefers to stay outside and not be
transformed into a ‘friend’ – it is redefined as a terrorist separatist threat that warrants military
action. China’s legal claim to these territories is strong, but Zhao’s point is to stress the ethical
legitimacy of the Tianxia model, which is sorely lacking. The main question then is not whether

102
Mencius 1970, 3A/4; Dikötter 1992, 18.
103
Zhao 2006c,1; Shapiro 2004, 126.
104
See Fairbank 1968a; Zhao 2006a, 36.
105
Li 1999; Zhang, YJ 2001.
106
See Kang 2003, 65-66.
107
See Perdue 2005, 256-89. For a description of similar – but less successful – wars in the Ming dynasty
see Johnston (1995).
108
Wang GW 2006, 3; also see Bøckman 1998, 310-46.
109
Johnston 1995, 249-54.
110
Giersch 2006, 12.
111
Wang 2003, 170; also see Dutton 1998.

15
China has a pattern of self/Other relations that is similar to the west (or not),112 but how the
Tianxia system addresses difference. Because Zhao figures his Tianxia system as ‘all-inclusive’,
any difference risks being converted into the sameness of the overarching (Chinese) self.
Zhao’s The Tianxia System is not a one-off; it is popular because it taps into China’s
current zeitgeist. The PRC’s official policy is to peacefully rise as a status quo power within the
international system. But many Chinese take for granted that the current Westphalian system is
immoral, legalistic and encourages war. Imperial China’s Sinocentric hierarchical world order
thus is seen as the solution rather than the problem. Since Chinese culture is taken to be superior,
many feel that it is the duty of patriotic Chinese to spread Chinese values, language, and culture
not just in Asia, but around the world.113 Hence, in the twenty-first century to be cosmopolitan is
to be patriotic, and vice versa. But this popular foreign policy of patriotic cosmopolitanism often
goes against the PRC’s official foreign policy of peaceful rising, in a ‘nationalist’ struggle that is
seldom seen outside Chinese-language texts.
To sum up, this section has shown how Zhao’s Tianxia utopia has serious theoretical
problems both in terms of its cavalier reading of classical Chinese texts and its odd use of
contemporary social theory’s vocabulary of ethical relations in a way that promotes ‘conversion’
rather than ‘conquest’. Lastly, it is necessary to point out the irony of one of Zhao’s main
arguments. He understandably criticizes the west, and America in particular, for universalizing
its particular worldview at the considerable expense of other worldviews. But is Zhao doing
anything different? Isn’t he trying to universalize the very particular Chinese concept of Tianxia
in order to apply it to the world? And doesn’t Zhao’s Pax Sinica risk creating the very problems
of an intolerant world order that he seeks to solve?
This leads us to the next section’s argument that the real meaning of the Tianxia system is
not found in its novel world order, but in its role in contemporary Chinese politics. In this way,
Tianxia is a strong example of how domestic and international politics overlap and inform each
other as part of a broader struggle over the meaning of ‘China’. Qin Yaqing put it simply when
he stated that the main issue for the PRC’s engagement with the international system is not the
institutional politics how will China fit into multilateral organizations, but the identity politics of
answering the question ‘Who is China?’ 114 Once again, worldview, national image and soft
power are intimately related in discussions of foreign policy.

IV. Conclusion: The soft power of rethinking China & rethinking the world
Although Zhao doesn’t discuss it, the meaning of Tianxia is even more complex than the
Empire/World dynamic. According to classical and modern dictionaries, Tianxia also means
‘China’. This is one reason why Zhao’s book is so popular: Tianxia is about China, and China’s
role in the world in the twenty-first century – which are very hot topics in the PRC and among
overseas Chinese. According to many scholars, imperial China’s Tianxia system of governance
worked very well – until it was challenged by western imperialism. Thus in modern times China
was forced to build a modern nation-state to defend itself from these foreign challenges. The
question that many Chinese scholars are now asking is whether it is time for China (which is
now a strong nation-state) to engage in promoting, establishing or constructing Tianxia – not just
for China’s benefit, but for the world.115 Indeed, Zhao quotes another public intellectual who
feels that after China’s recent economic success the world will ask China about its contribution
to world civilization, especially with theories of world order.116

112
See Shih 2007.
113
See Friedman 2007, 7-8; Nyiri 2006, 106.
114
Qin 2006, 13.
115
Chen 2006; Wang GW 2006; Wang YW 2006, 3; Sheng 1995.
116
Zhao 2005, 11.

16
In this way, ‘Tianxia’ discourse is a good example of how ‘soft power’ takes shape as the
romanticization of a particular national culture into ‘universally desireable values’. Following
this line of argument with the Japanese case, Leheny feels that the concept of soft power ‘has
less value as a tool for evaluating Japan’s regional importance than it does as a heuristic device
for grasping how Japanese policymakers now see their regional role’. 117 Likewise, Tianxia
provides us with a heuristic device for understanding how Chinese elites view their role in the
world, and the world itself. Moreover, the rise of Tianxia discourse in China can also help us
grasp the soft power of soft power: how Tianxia has become a dominant way of understanding
the future Chinese world order. Zhao’s The Tianxia System is meaningful not just as a
philosophical or an academic text. It is a bestseller that generates broad discussion about the
meaning of ‘nationalism’ and ‘globalization’ in China. Its power emerges not necessarily from
its arguments – which as we saw above are quite broad and vague – but from its position in a
network of debates among public intellectuals, state intellectuals and political leaders about
China’s role in the world as a major power.118
Among public intellectuals, the Zhao’s Tianxia theory thus is embedded in China’s
political culture that on the one hand has an enduring anxiety about unity and disunity (including
order and chaos), and on the other has a strong tradition of utopian thought that seeks to address
these perennial issues with the ‘complete and perfect world’.119 Zhao thus is not alone in looking
to the past for China’s future strengths: Zhang Yimou’s film Hero concludes with the assassin
being transformed into a hero (i.e. enemy transformed into friend) when he decides not to kill the
emperor. The lesson drawn from this historical parable is that the individual has to sacrifice
himself and his kingdom for the greater good of the Tianxia empire, because as the hero reasons,
‘Only the King of Qin can stop the chaos by unifying Tianxia [through conquest]’.120 Indeed, the
subtitles translate Tianxia into English simply as ‘Our Land’. The Chinese television
documentary series on ‘The Rise of Great Powers’ from Portugal to the US that captivated the
PRC in 2006 applies this historical lesson to China’s future as a major power.121 ‘The Rise of
Great Powers’ is popular because like The Tianxia System it appeals to a common feeling among
Chinese people that it is China’s turn (again) to civilize and harmonize the world. Indeed, in
early 2007 the same directors travelled to Japan, Europe and North America to conduct
interviews for the sequel: ‘China’s Road’.122
Hence Zhao’s book is part of the broader discussion of how China will be a world power:
his ‘Introduction’ of The Tianxia system is called ‘Why we need to discuss China’s worldview’.
Zhao feels that to be a true world power, China needs to excel not just in economic production,
but in ‘knowledge production’.123 Contemporary Chinese thought, Zhao tells us, is sorely lacking
because Chinese scholars are captivated by western theory. To be a knowledge power, China
needs to stop importing ideas from the west, and exploit its own indigenous ‘resources of
traditional thought’. Thus the aim of his book is to ‘rethink China’ so as to ‘restructure China’.
But because China’s problems are the world’s problems, we then need to rethink and restructure
the world in terms of Tianxia.

117
Leheny 2006, 223.
118
For a fascinating analysis that uses a similar method to understand how ‘nationalism’ is produced in
China’s discursive networks see Hughes (2005).
119
Zhao 2005,40; Hua 2001; Hua 2005; Callahan 2004; Tu 1994.
120
Zhang YM 2004.
121
Zhou, 2006. This popular documentary series was broadcast twice on China’s national television
network (CCTV) in late 2006. It has also generated a series of nine best-selling books (see Daguo jueqi
2007; Author’s interview with a director, 6 May 2007 in Manchester).
122
Author’s interview with a director, 6 May 2007 in Manchester. ‘China’s Road’ is scheduled for
broadcast in late 2007.
123
Zhao 2005, 1.

17
Here Tianxia is embedded in an important debate about how China can fit into the world
system as a ‘responsible great power’ that has emerged through a network of liberal Chinese IR
scholars in the past decade.124 China is trying to prove to the world (especially the west) that it is
no longer a revolutionary state that challenges international order, but is a ‘responsible’ member
of international society. 125 The PRC has demonstrated this by pursuing a more multilateral
foreign policy that includes expanding its membership in international organizations at both the
regional and the global level. Zhao’s ‘Introduction’ also talks about China’s ‘responsibility’ to
the world, but he adds a theoretical twist to argue that China will become a responsible great
power not merely in economic or military terms, but in terms of concepts and structures:
Bearing responsibility for the world, and not just for one’s own country,
this is China’s philosophical perspective. In practice it provides totally
new possibilities, especially if we use ‘Tianxia’ as the primary analytical
unit for understanding political/economic benefits. When we use Tianxia
to understand the world, then we can use ‘the world’ to analyze problems,
and transcend the western mode of thought that relies on nation/state, and
then we will be able to take responsibility for the world as our own
responsibility, and thus create new world concepts and new world
structures.126
Here the notion of a ‘responsible China’ shifts dramatically from that of a conservative state that
is responsible to the present world order to Zhao’s Tianxia that is responsible for creating a
totally new world order. Rather than the China problem being a world problem, the ‘world
problem’ is now ‘China’s problem’.
While ‘responsible China’ appealed to a network of liberal IR scholars in China, a group
of IR theorists is also very interested in Zhao’s Tianxia system. This network is engaged in
promoting a ‘Chinese style’ of international relations theory.127 The ‘China school’ of IR theory
thus follows an academic trend that expands from Deng Xiaoping’s formulation in the mid-
1980s that the PRC needed ‘to build socialism with Chinese characteristics’, to build sociology,
history, law (and so on) ‘with Chinese characteristics’. Deng was not interested in reviving
Chinese tradition, which he criticized as ‘feudal ideology’; he concentrated on the ‘socialism’
side of the formulation to protect his market-based reforms from leftist criticism.128 But since the
1990s, Chinese scholars have much more interested in the ‘Chinese characteristics’ side of the
formulation, as a way of carving out space in a transnational academic market for their own
unique research.129 Thus many key IR scholars are hailing Zhao’s Tianxia system as a way to
create space for a ‘China school’ of international studies in an intellectual marketplace that is
dominated by western IR. 130 Indeed, the editors of China’s top international studies journal,
World Economics and Politics, invited Zhao to write the editorial page essay for their September
2006 issue.131 But again, Zhao is doing more than contribute to this debate which sees the ‘China
school’ as an assertion of cultural sovereignty that protects China’s unique way of understanding
the world. Zhao is interested in transcending this chaotic (and nationalist) intellectual scene by
unifying the world of thought under the banner of the Tianxia system.

124
See Wang 1999; Xia 2001; Shih 2005.
125
See Shirk 2007, 105-39; Shambaugh 2004/05; Johnston 2003; Medieros & Fravel 2003.
126
Zhao 2005, 3.
127
See Liang 1997; Song 2001.
128
Deng 1987.
129
See Shi 2006; Li 2002.
130
See Qin 2006; Wang YW 2006.
131
Zhao 2006c. Zhao was invited to speak to an international politics group at the Institute of World
Economics and Politics in March 2007, where he was well-received, especially among younger scholars
(Author’s interview with Wang Yizhou in Beijing, 12 April 2007).

18
Lastly, Zhao’s writings are embedded in the discursive network of China’s top political
leaders; Tianxia’s utopian themes chime with Beijing’s latest foreign policy narrative:
‘harmonious world’. Just five months after The Tianxia System was published, Chinese President
Hu Jintao outlined his four point plan for a ‘Harmonious World’ at the United Nations in
September 2005. 132 Since then, the ‘harmonious world’ formulation has dominated China’s
explanations for its responsible engagement with the world, including an important section of the
December 2005 white paper ‘China’s Peaceful Development Road’.133 Even hard-core realists
like Yan Xuetong now exuberantly use this idealistic slogan to describe China’s recent
diplomatic victories.134
The relation of scholarship and government policy – especially the ties between
philosophers and the foreign ministry – is certainly opaque in China. On the one hand, Zhao and
the editors of World Economics and Politics all work for CASS, China’s largest and most
important think-tank, which is often compared to a state ministry in terms of its size and
influence. Zhao, on the other hand, rarely refers to the Chinese state (and never to the
Communist Party) in his book. When he is criticized by other scholars for trying to use the
Tianxia system to ‘harmonize the world’ under Chinese leadership,135 Zhao demurs by saying
that he is only interested in ‘purely theoretical’ questions of world order. But then a few lines
later Zhao praises the Chinese government for ‘once again utilizing the resources of China’s
tradition thought’ in its twin policies of building a ‘harmonious [domestic] society’ and a
‘harmonious world’.136 Like with The Tianxia System, Zhao’s argument here is both ‘nationalist’
and ‘cosmopolitan’ since his form of utopian globalism is based on Chinese ideals.
Thus Tianxia is embedded in a broad discussion of Chinese visions of world order that
includes a feature film like Hero, ‘The Rise of Great Powers’ TV series, dozens of articles in
prominent IR journals, and even the Chinese president’s ‘harmonious world’ foreign policy
narrative. Zhao’s ideas are not influential in the standard sense of everyone agreeing with his
proposed Tianxia system: actually the film, the TV series, academic articles and state policy all
disagree with him on many important issues. Rather Zhao’s ideas are indirectly influential
according to the normative logic of soft power: he has been able to set the agenda, and thus
productively generate a powerful discourse that sets the boundaries of how people think about
China’s past, present and future. Zhao does this by employing familiar vocabularies: for the
general audience he talks of ‘sacrifice for Tianxia’; for liberal IR scholars he talks of China as a
‘responsible great power’; for IR theorists he discusses how China has its own ‘worldview’ that
is different from the west; and for Beijing’s political elite his ideas resonate with China’s
‘harmonious world’ policy. Zhao actually has very different understandings of these key phrases
from each of these groups, but he uses this familiar language to position himself at the center of
these core discursive networks, and thus present his contrary views as the mainstream view. By
rethinking China in this way, Zhao is also able to rethink the world, and thus set discursive
boundaries to control Chinese popular understandings not just of the past and the present, but of
the future as well.137 In this way, the Tianxia system is part of China’s assertion of normative
soft power, but in a way that complements China’s hard power of economic and military
strength.

132
Hu 2005.
133
‘Wu Jianmin: “Harmonious World” helps rebut “China Threat”’, People’s Daily, 20 March 2006;
State Council 2005.
134
Yan Xuetong, ‘China’s first step forward in its “harmonious world-oriented” diplomacy’, People’s
Daily, (19 December 2006).
135
Xiang Lanxin, ‘Jieyan quqi, shenyan hexie’ [Stop talking about [China’s] rise, be careful discussing
[world] harmony], Lianhe zaobao (Singapore), (26 March 2006).
136
Zhao 2006c, 1.
137
See Shapiro 2004, 48.

19
Although Zhao’s book was reviewed alongside Habermas’s work,138 perhaps the best way
to understand the role of The Tianxia System is to compare it to Samuel Huntington’s high
profile writings. The point is not whether (or not) Huntington’s articles are intellectually
sophisticated, or whether (or not) US policy is dictated or influenced by them. Rather the texts
are powerful as polemics that define problems in specific ways that actually serve to limit the
range of possible solutions. In this way, Huntington set the terms of the debate about post-Cold
War international politics that in turn generated a certain range of responses. Even when these
responses are critical of the clash of civilizations argument, they add to its influence by
recirculating the ‘clash of civilizations’ concept.
Zhao was already famous among intellectuals in the humanities before he put together his
thoughts on Tianxia in 2005. The Tianxia System worked to grow the market for a politically-
inflected discussion of Chinese utopia, and is provoking responses from both IR scholars and
political leaders in China. By inserting his discussion of a Chinese utopia into powerful
discursive networks, Zhao has asserted himself as the ‘mainstream’ for discussions of China’s
future – and of the world’s future. Zhao mainstreamed Tianxia not by making arguments that all
would agree with; rather Zhao was successful because he described this exotic idea in terms of
already existing vocabularies and debates. People now have to respond to his arguments, even
when they are discussing something else: nationalism, globalization, socialism, world peace, and
so on. 139 Although The Tianxia System has serious theoretical problems, the book has quite
successfully generated considerable social capital for Zhao as well as enhancing China’s soft
power as a source of universally valid model of world politics. But rather than showing how soft
power can help us to understand the international influence of China’s worldview, Zhao’s
manoeuvres show how soft power actually is better understood as an inward-looking
phenomena. It helps us understand how ideas about foreign policy – including those that chafe
with the official view – get put into play in Beijing as part of the domestic politics of China’s
national image. That the main significance of The Tianxia System.

Bibliography
Ames, Roger T. 1997. Continuing the Conversation on Chinese Human Rights. Ethics and
International Affairs no. 11: 177-205.
Ames, Roger T. and David L. Hall, translators and commentators. 2003. Dao De Jing: A
Philosophical Translation. New York: Ballantine Books.
Archibugi, Daniele and David Held. 1995. Cosmopolitan Democracy: An Agenda for a New
World Order. Cambridge: Polity.
Bachelard, Gaston. 1994. The Poetics of Space. Boston: Beacon Press.
Bloom, Harold. 1975. A Map of Misreading. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bøckman, Harald. 1998. China Deconstructs? The Future of the Chinese Empire-State in a
Historical Perspective. In Reconstructing Twentieth-Century China: State Control, Civil
Society, and National Identity, edited by Kjeld Erik Brødsgaard and David Strand, 310-46.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Callahan, William A. 2004. Remembering the Future: Utopia, Empire and Harmony in Twenty-
first Century International Theory. European Journal of International Relations 10(4): 569-
601.

138
Sun 2005.
139
See Fei-Ling Wang, ‘Heading Off Fears of a Resurgent China’, International Herald Tribune, (11
April 2006); Xiang Lanxin, ‘Jieyan quqi, shenyan hexie’ [Stop talking about [China’s] rise, be careful
discussing [world] harmony], Lianhe zaobao (Singapore), (26 March 2006). This, of course, includes the
author.

20
Cheah, Pheng and Bruce Robbins. 1998. Cosmopolitics: Thinking and Feeling Beyond the
Nation. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Chen Guying. 1985. Laozi: Zhu, yi, ji pingjie [Laozi: Text, Notes and Comments]. Beijing:
Zhonghua shuju.
Ch’en Ku-ying [Chen Guying]. 1981. Lao Tzu: Text, Notes and Comments. Translated and
adapted by Rhett Y.W. Young and Roger T. Ames. San Francisco: Chinese Materials
Center.
Cohen, Paul. 1986. Discovering History in China: American Historical Writings on the Recent
Chinese Past. New York: Columbia University Press.
Confucius. 1971. Confucian Analects, The Great Learning and the Doctrine of the Mean.
Translated by James Legge. New York: Dover.
Daguo jueqi: Jieshouci [The rise of great powers: Explanations]. 2007. Beijing: Minzhu fazhi
chubanshe.
Dan Xingwu. 2005. Liang daguoji tixi de chongtu yu jindai Zhongguo de shengcheng [The clash
of two international systems and the formation of modern China]. PhD dissertation,
Chinese Academy of Social Sciences, International Politics Department.
de Bary, W. T., ed. 1960. Sources of Chinese Tradition, Vol. I. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Deng Xiaoping. 1987. Jianshe you Zhongguo tese de shehui zhuyi [Building Socialism with
Chinese Characteristics], revised and enlarged edition. Beijing: Renmin chubanshe.
Dikötter, Frank. 1992. The Discourse of Race in Modern China. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Dutton, Michael. 1998. Streetlife China. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fairbank, John King. 1968a. A Preliminary Framework. In The Chinese World Order:
Traditional China’s Foreign Relations, edited by John King Fairbank, 1-19. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Fairbank, John King, ed. 1968b. The Chinese World Order: Traditional China’s Foreign
Relations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Foucault, Michel. 1980. Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Writings, 1972-1977, edited
by Colin Gordon. New York: Pantheon.
Friedman, Edward. 2007. Where is Chinese Nationalism? The Political Geography of a Moving
Project. Conference on Nationalism, Globalization and Regional Order in Northeast Asia,
London School of Economics, 12 May.
Fukuyama, Francis. 1989. The End of History? The National Interest. Summer.
Giersch, C. Patterson. 2006. Asian Borderlands: The Transformation of Qing China’s Yunnan
Frontier. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Gill, Bates and Yanzhong Huang. 2006. Sources and Limits of Chinese ‘Soft Power’. Survival
48(2): 17-36.
Haine, Jean-Ives. 2004. The EU’s Soft Power: Not Hard Enough? Georgetown Journal of
International Affairs 5(1): 69-77.
Hall, David L. and Roger T. Ames. 1998. Thinking from the Han: Self, Truth, and
Transcendence in Chinese and Western Culture. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. 2000. Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Harvey, David. 2003. The New Imperialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Held, David, et al. 1999. Global Transformations: Politics, Economics and Culture. Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press.
Hevia, James 1995, Cherishing Men From Afar: Qing Guest Ritual and the Macartney Embassy
of 1793. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

21
Hu Jintao. 2005. Build Towards a Harmonious World of Lasting Peace and Common Prosperity.
Speech at the Plenary Meeting of the United Nations’ 60th Session, New York, September
15.
Hua, Shiping. 2001. Utopianism in Chinese Political Culture. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield
Publishing.
Hua, Shiping. 2005. A Perfect World. Wilson Quarterly. Autumn: 62-7.
Hughes, Christopher R. 2005. Interpreting Nationalist Texts: A Post-Structuralist Approach.
Journal of Contemporary China 14(43): 247-67.
Huntington, Samuel P. 1993. The Clash of Civilizations? Foreign Affairs 72(3): 22-49.
Jiang Zemin. 1999. Jiang Zemin lun shehuizhuyi jingshen wenming jianshe [Jiang Zemin on the
Construction of Socialist Spiritual Civilization]. Beijing: Central Committee Documents
Press.
Johnston, Alastair Iain and Robert S. Ross, eds. 2006. New Directions in the Study of China’s
Foreign Policy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Johnston, Alastair Iain. 2003. Is China a Status Quo Power? International Security 27(4): 5-56.
Johnston, Alastair Iain. 1995. Cultural Realism: Strategic Culture and Grand Strategy in
Chinese History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Kang, David C. 2003. Getting Asia Wrong: The Need for New Analytical Frameworks.
International Security 27(4): 57-85.
Kipnis, Andrew. 2006. Suzhi: A Keyword Approach. The China Quarterly no. 185: 295-313.
Kurlantzick, Joshua. 2006. China’s Charm: Implications of China’s Soft Power. Carnegie
Endowment Policy Brief, no. 47. June.
Leheny, David. 2006. A Narrow Place to Cross Swords: ‘Soft Power’ and the Politics of
Japanese Popular Culture in East Asia. In Beyond Japan: The Dynamics of East Asian
Regionalism, edited by Peter J. Katzenstein and Takashi Shiraishi, 211-33. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 2006.
Levinas, Emmanuel. 2000. Ethics as First Philosophy. In The Levinas Reader, edited by Sean
Hand, 75-88. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Li Shaojun. 1999. Lun Zhongguo wenmingde heping neihan: Cong chuantong dao xianshi: dui
‘Zhongguo weixie’ lun de huida [The Peaceful Orientation of Chinese Civilization: from
Tradition to Reality: a Response to ‘China threat’ theory]. Guoji jingji pinglun no. 19: 30-
33.
Li Shaojun. 2002. Guoji zhengzhixue gailun [An Introduction to International Politics]. Shanghai:
Renmin chubanshe.
Liang Shoude. 1997. Constructing an International Relations Theory with ‘Chinese
Characteristics’. Political Science 49(1): 23-49.
Liu Junping. 2006. The Evolution of Tianxia Cosmology and its Philosophical Implications.
Frontiers of Philosophy in China 1(4).
Liu, Lydia H. 2004. The Clash of Empires: The Invention of China in Modern World Making.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Liu Zhiguang. 1992. Dongfang heping zhuyi: yuanqi, liubian ji zouxiang [Oriental Pacificism: Its
Origins, Development and Future]. Changsha, Hunan: Hunan chubanshe.
Mancall, Mark. 1984. China at the Center: 300 years of Foreign Policy, New York: Free Press.
Medieros, Evan S. and M. Taylor Fravel. 2003. China’s New Diplomacy. Foreign Affairs 82(6):
23-35
Mencius. 1970. Mencius. translated by D.C. Lau. London: Penguin.
Nye, Joseph S., Jr. 1991. Bound to Lead: The Changing Nature of American Power. New York:
Basic Books.
Nye, Joseph S., Jr. 2003. The Paradox of American Power: Why the World’s Only Superpower
Can’t Go It Alone. New York: Oxford University Press.

22
Nye, Joseph S., Jr. 2004. Soft Power: The Means to Success in World Politics. New York: Public
Affairs.
Nyiri, Pal. 2006. The Yellow Man’s Burden: Chinese Immigrants on a Civilizing Mission. The
China Journal no. 56: 83-106.
Pan, Esther. 2006. China’s Soft Power Initiative. Council on Foreign Relations.
Pang Zhongying. 2006. Fazhan Zhongguo ruan liliang [Develop China’s soft power]. Liaowang
no. 1: 63.
Pang Zhongying. 2005. Zhongguo ruan liliang de neihan [The content of China’s soft power].
Liaowang no. 45: 62.
Perdue, Peter C. 2005. China Marches West: The Qing Conquest of Central Eurasia. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Qin Yaqing. 2006. Guoji guanxi lilun Zhongguo pai shengcheng de keneng he biran [The
Chinese School of International Relations Theory: Possibility and Necessity]. Shijie jingji
yu zhengzhi no. 3: 7-13.
Ramo, Joshua Cooper. 2004. The Beijing Consensus. London: Foreign Policy Centre.
Ramo, Joshua Cooper. 2007. Brand China. London: Foreign Policy Centre.
Ren Xue’an, director. 2006. Daguo jueqi [The rise of great powers]. Beijing: China International
Television Company.
Rosemont, Henry Jr. 1988. Why Take Rights Seriously? A Confucian Critique. In Human Rights
and the World’s Religions, edited by Leroy S. Rouner, 167-182. Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press.
Rossabi, Morris, ed. 1983. China Among Equals: The Middle Kingdom and its Neighbors, 10th-
l4th Centuries. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Said, Edward. 1978. Orientalism. New York: Vintage.
Said, Edward. 2000. Orientalism Reconsidered. In Orientalism: A Reader, edited by A.L. Macfie,
345-61. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Schmitt, Carl. 1996. The Concept of the Political. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Schoenhals, Michael. 1994. “Non-People” in the People’s Republic of China:
A Chronicle of Terminological Ambiguity. Working Paper no. 4. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
East Asian Working Paper Series on Language and Politics in Modern China.
Shambaugh, David. 2004/05. China Engages Asia: Reshaping the Regional Order. International
Security 29(3): 64-99.
Shambaugh, David, ed. 2006. Power Shift: China and Asia’s New Dynamics. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
Shapiro, Michael J. 2004. Methods and Nations: Cultural Governance and the Indigenous
Subject. New York and London: Routledge.
Sheng Hong. 1995. Shenme shi wenming [What is civilization?]. Zhanlüe yu guanli no. 5: 88-98.
Shi Bin. 2006. ‘Guoji guanxi yanjiu “Zhongguohua” de lunzheng [The Sinicization debate in
international relations research]. In Zhongguo guoji guanxi yanjiu (1995-2005)
[International Relations [Theory] Studies in China, 1995-2005], edited by Wang Yizhou
and Yuan Zhengqing, 518-45. Beijing: Peking University Press.
Shih, Chih-yu. 2005. Breeding a Reluctant Dragon: Can China Rise into Partnership and Away
from Antagonism? Review of International Studies 31(4): 755-74.
Shih, Chih-yu. 2007. The West that is not Western: Self-Identification in the Oriental Modernity.
Paper presented at the 48th annual meeting of International Studies Association, March,
Chicago.
Shirk, Susan. 2007. China: Fragile Superpower. New York: Oxford University Press.
Song Xinning. 2001. Building International Relations Theory with Chinese Characteristics.
Journal of Contemporary China 10(26): 61-74.
State Council. 2005. China’s Peaceful Development Road. Beijing, 22 December.

23
Sun Shu. 2005. Shijie, yihuo tianxia? [The world, or Tianxia?] Boyan yangshu no. 11: 4-10.
Suttmeier, Richard P., Xiangkui Yao, and Alex Zixiang Tan. 2006. Standards of Power?
Technology, Institutions, and Politics in the Development of China’s National Standards
Strategy. Seattle: NBR Special Report.
Todorov, Tzvetan. 1984. The Conquest of America: The Question of the Other. New York:
Harper Collins.
Tu Wei-ming. 1989. Way, Learning and Politics: Essays on the Confucian Intellectual.
Singapore: Institute of East Asian Philosophies.
Tu Weiming. 1994. Cultural China: the Periphery as the Center. In The Living Tree: the
Changing Meaning of Being Chinese Today, edited by Tu Weiming, 1-34. Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Tu, Weiming, et al. 1992. The Confucian World Observed: Contemporary Discussion of
Confucian Humanism in East Asia. Honolulu: The East-West Center.
Walker, R.B.J. 1993. Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Wang Gungwu. 2006. Tianxia and Empire: External Chinese Perspectives, Inaugural Tsai
Lecture. Harvard University, May 4th.
Wang Hui. 2003. Contemporary Chinese Thought and the Question of Modernity. China’s New
Order: Society, Politics, and Economy in Transition, edited by Theodore Huters, 140-187.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wang, Hongying. 2003. National Image Building and Chinese Foreign Policy. China: An
International Journal 1(1): 46-72.
Wang Yiwei. 2006. Tanxun Zhongguo de xin shenfen: guanyu minzu zhuyi de shenhua
[Exploring China’s new identity: The myth of nationalism]. Shijie jingji yu zhengzhi no. 2:
1-13.
Wang Yizhou. 1999. Mianxiang 21 shijiede Zhongguo waijiao: sanzhong xuqiude xunqiu jiqi
pingheng [Towards a Chinese diplomacy for the 21st century: Pursuing and balancing three
needs]. Zhanlüe yu guanli no. 6: 18-27.
Wei Zongyou. 2005. Quanli, ruan quanli yu guojia xingxiang [Power, soft power and national
image]. Guoji guancha no. 5: 39-45.
Xia Liping. 2001. China: A Responsible Great Power. Journal of Contemporary China 10(26):
17-25.
Xu Shen. 1981. Shuowen jiezi zhu. Shanghai: Shanghai guji chubanshe.
Yan Xuetong. 1995. Zhongguo guojia liyi fenxi [An Analysis of China’s National Interest].
Tianjin: Renmin chubanshe.
Zhang Yimou. 2004. Yingxiong [Hero].
Zhang, Yongjin. 2005. China Goes Global. London: Foreign Policy Centre.
Zhang, Yongjin. 2001. System, Empire and State in Chinese International Relations. Review of
International Studies 27(December): 43-63.
Zhao Tingyang. 2005. Tianxia tixi: Shijie zhidu zhexue daolun [The Tianxia system: A
Philosophy for the World Institution]. Nanjing: Jiangsu jiaoyu chubanshe.
Zhao, Tingyang. 2006a. Rethinking Empire from a Chinese Concept “All-under-Heaven” (Tian-
xia). Social Identities 12(1): 29-41.
Zhao Tingyang. 2006b. Yutao renquan: yizhong feixifang de pubian renquan lilun [Human rights
as credit rights: A non-western theory of universal human rights]. Zhongguo shehui kexue,
no. 4: 17-30.
Zhao Tingyang. 2006c. Guanyu hexie shijie de sekao [Some thoughts about the harmonious
world]. Shijie jingji yu zhengzhi no. 9: 1.

24

You might also like