Heidegger and The Aesthetics of Living
Heidegger and The Aesthetics of Living
Edited by
Vrasidas Karalis
All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,
or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or
otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner.
Contributors............................................................................................. 228
VRASIDAS KARALIS
and intersubjectivity. The eyes meet on the television set and the new
divinities of history emerge from their osmosis.
Hence, his critique of the modern always misses the point of what
precisely makes modernity another form of being-ness and not a condition
of being that has meaning solely by contrast to older, mainly Greek,
conceptions, practices and experiences. In a sense, Cornelius Castoriadis’
suggestion that the task of philosophy is to enhance human autonomy
against the pervasive heteronomy imposed by societal structures and
human creativity is itself a Heideggerian idea never envisaged by
Heidegger. Yet in order to understand the implications of such a
suggestion one must consider the importance of the human subject itself as
existing, and hence must have reflected on the anthropic as a principle of
being-ness. There are thus many philosophical ‘elements’ missing from
Heidegger’s thought. His early rejection of psychology shows a profound
misprision of the nature of language as collective creation and its function
within semantic fields of cultural and trans-cultural validity. Indeed, one
could argue that despite its international eminence, Heidegger’s
philosophy is equally important for what it omits, passes over in silence
and conceals and that, in a sense, his own critique of modernity, rationality
and humanism is also a critique of his own philosophical enterprise. The
most important task of a new approach to his works is to see what is not
and cannot be reduced to the individual and what can become a cultural
hypothesis of wider validity. Heidegger’s work already suffers from an
ever-growing industry of commentaries which, instead of elucidating the
presuppositions and the consequences of his work, concoct an obscure
mythology around his name and about his philosophy. The only fair way
to assess his work is to see it within its limitations and explain what
transcends them and what can be conducive to different forms of thinking
by expanding the limitations of their semantic structures.
As with every philosopher we must try to focus on the consequences of
their questions and not the accuracy of their answers. Furthermore we
must try to understand the interplay of meanings that made such questions
possible and thereby to locate their explanatory value, indeed – one might
say: their anthropic value. For, even within his critique of humanism,
Heidegger’s thinking can be extremely humanistic in its implications and
highly provocative in regard to its anthropological underpinnings. Indeed,
one could claim that anthropological reflection was impossible within his
thinking because he never addressed the question of the tragic as a
dimension of self-understanding and self-articulation. Historically it is
interesting that even the collapse of Germany, or the Holocaust, or the
destruction of Europe were never understood by Heidegger as tragic
xvi Introduction
GIANNI VATTIMO
1
An earlier version of this article appeared in the journal Micromega under the
title “Heidegger filosofo della democrazia”, vol. 5, 2003.
2 Heidegger and the Philosophy of Emancipation
not truth but authority makes the law – has always been subject to
rationalist criticism inspired by metaphysics, even when this was
motivated by the best revolutionary intentions.
Everywhere we are faced with “truth” in politics, the danger of
authoritarianism begins, precisely that “closure” that Popper stigmatizes in
his work. Now, what Heidegger calls “metaphysics” is exactly the idea
that being is an order - objectively given once and for all. This is also the
substance of Nietzsche’s criticism of Socrates, when he sees in him the
inceptor of modern decadence, guilty of having killed the great tragic spirit
of the ancients. If being is a stable structure given once and for all, there is
no possible openness in history nor any freedom.
Obviously, such a vision is much more reassuring than the tragic one
which – so we assume – characterized the pre-Classical Greeks; but any
such reassurance, we suggest, is particularly meaningful for those who are
already secure in the prevailing order, and who, for this reason above all,
recognise it as rational and worthy of remaining valid forever. (Here, I
call your attention not only to Nietzsche but also to Benjamin’s theses on
the philosophy of history.) I remind you that, in the first pages of the
lecture on the end of philosophy I mentioned previously, Heidegger cites,
in immediate proximity to the name of Plato, that of Karl Marx, as one
who has – well before Nietzsche – already overturned metaphysics and
thus also Platonism.
By pointing this out, I do not want to say that it is possible to bridge
the gap between the Marxist overturning and that “overcoming”
(Überwindung), for which Heidegger tries to prepare the way by his work.
But it is not entirely arbitrary, in our view, to recall Marxist ideas on the
origin of alienation in the social division of work when we try to
understand – with Heidegger – why and how metaphysics has established
itself in such a radical way in the history of our world. Here I leave aside
the debate on the “historical” or “eternal” nature of metaphysics in the
thought of Heidegger, which would probably lead us to invoke his
dependence on the biblical myth of Original Sin, a myth he could never
completely get rid of.
Although the notion of metaphysics is meant by Heidegger in a rather
peculiar way, I think that the analogy with Popper – even if it is
paradoxical – could clarify the sense in which it is also shared by much
contemporary philosophy; obviously, it should not be difficult to
recognize it in Wittgenstein (“Die Welt ist alles was der Fall ist.”
“The world is everything that is the case”: Tractacus, 1), and, of course,
in the context of pragmatism and neopragmatism. I know some
philosophers are still talking about metaphysics in a way that is concordant
Gianni Vattimo 3
arguable, it simply accords with the new conditions of our time. Compared
with the epoch in which Heidegger and Popper wrote their works, the
world of today is much more strongly “rationalized” and “scientifically
organized”. The phenomenon of the end of philosophy and the
schizophrenia of the specialized sciences and technologies, with the
possible consequence of a new authoritarianism – I am thinking of Bush’s
America, of course, but not exclusively – is infinitely more visible and
pervasive.
When I propose the thesis of the relatively paradoxical nearness of
Heidegger to Popper, I am not claiming that this is the definitive truth, I
am just trying to offer an interpretation that corresponds with present
events, to the concrete situation in which I think we live.
Following Heidegger and Marx, maybe not Popper as well (although I
could argue this case for him also), the task of thought in this situation is
to think what remains hidden in the “everyday presentation” of what
usually happens. For Marx what matters is the dialectic concreteness of
the interrelations which are concealed by the false consciousness of
ideology; for Heidegger, the truth as alétheia, the basic openness of a
horizon – (we might speak of a paradigm) – which makes possible all truth
meant as correspondence to the state of affairs, be it a verification or a
falsification of propositions. As I said, it is not immediately clear that this
effort to think what remains hidden in the everyday presentation of the
world also corresponds to Popper’s idea of the task of philosophy; I don’t
want to pursue this problem further here.
As far as Heidegger and Marx are concerned, the question is: may we
talk of the hidden alétheia which Heidegger has in mind as if it were
identifiable with the concreteness of the economic and social interrelations
of Marx’s materialism? In other words: how shall we imagine the task of
thought in the epoch in which philosophers no longer (believe that they)
have a privileged access to an eternal truth, on the basis of which they
would be entitled to govern society or to be the advisors of the sovereign?
If we followed Marx exclusively, we would return to a metaphysical and
rationalistic historicism, in which the task of the philosophers would be to
express the definitive truth of history – something known clearly only by
the proletariat, which also makes it real in the form of revolution. If, on the
contrary, we had to follow exclusively Heidegger, we would find
ourselves entangled in that “groundless mysticism, bad mythology,
dangerous irrationalism” (grundlose Mystik, schlechte Mythologie,
verderblicher Irrationalismus: Zur Sache des Denkens, ibid.) which he
sees as a risk related to his theory.
6 Heidegger and the Philosophy of Emancipation
In order to avoid these risks, which are not only Heidegger’s, but those of
several contemporary philosophies as well – certainly of those which are
unwilling to become merely harmless complements of the specialized
human sciences – one has to step forward on the path of the “urbanization
of the Heideggerian province” (I call your attention here to Habermas’
famous definition of Gadamer’s hermeneutics). This means, for me, to go
back to a undeveloped passage of Heidegger’s lecture on “The Origin of
the Work of Art” (1936).
On a page of that essay, Heidegger – as you know – defined the work
of art as the “putting into work of the truth”, in other words as the place in
which the event of being happens, opening up an epoch, etc. From that
moment on, Heidegger developed his “ontology” mainly, if not
exclusively, on the basis of this idea of the event: he tried again and again
to catch the event of being by listening to the inaugural words of poetry, of
the ancient wisdom (for example: Der Spruch des Anaximander), etc. But
in the essay of 1936 he also named, without further explanations, other
ways of the opening of truth, i.e. of the event of being. Among them, also
“the foundation of a state”, or politics. It is very likely that an additional
reason he did not develop his meditation on this point was his unhappy
adventure with Nazism. For me, it is nevertheless important to recall this
allusion to politics as a possible place for the event of being, because what
I want to suggest is that, in the epoch of democracy, the inaugural event of
being might no longer be the work of art, but, in some sense, the political
agorà.
It was in the epoch of metaphysics that the event of being happened in
those privileged moments which were the great works of art; not forgetting
that the great works of art have always had something to do with the
power of the sovereigns (painting, architecture, theatre, music; even
poetry, in many senses). In those privileged expressions, being speaks still
in the form of an “essential” truth which still entitles, or claims to entitle,
the philosopher to sovereignty.
My provisional conclusion would then be that, if we want to
“correspond” to the event of being in our specific historical situation, we
should try to discern its voice in something which has much more to do
with politics than with art, or with any kind of profound invisible
announcement. I have ventured the proposal that we describe this kind of
thought with a term of the late Foucault, “ontologie de l’actualité”,
ontology of the immediate present, as it were. The event of being to which
thought is challenged to correspond in the epoch of democracy is the way
in which being gives itself, from time to time, in collective experience.
What is hidden and tends to remain un-thought in the specialization of the
Gianni Vattimo 7
sciences is the “on he on”, being as being, the wholeness of the individual
and social experience. This wholeness is to be liberated from
technological schizophrenia and not to be allowed to relapse into
authoritarian social discipline. If one still speaks here of ontology,
entrusting once more the task to the philosophers – no longer as
sovereigns or as advisors of the sovereign – it means that one has to
imagine a new and still undefined social role of the “intellectual”, closer to
that of the artist and of the priest than to those of the scientist and of the
technologist. At any rate, it should be a priest without a hierarchical
church, or else a street artist. In a less picturesque way, we might describe
this role as that of a historian and a politician – somebody who does
ontology insofar as he helps in connecting current experience with those of
the past and with those of other cultures and societies, building and
rebuilding a continuity which is the very meaning of the term logos, dis-
course. (I think again of the idea of the philosopher as a Dolmetscher, a
“translator”, proposed by Habermas). Does all this have anything to do
with “being”, one might ask. But: is being anything different, more
profound and hidden, than this, its “event”?
CUTTING POETS TO SIZE –
HEIDEGGER, HÖLDERLIN, RILKE
ANTHONY STEPHENS
From the outset I must make it clear that I am writing here not as a
philosopher, but as a scholar of German literature. This implies that all the
texts I treat will be seen as having literary status, regardless of any other
claims implicit in them or claims made for them. This impinges on
Heidegger’s tendency to accord a special privilege to certain poetic texts,
especially the late poems of Hölderlin. Few scholars writing in English on
Heidegger show any awareness that Hölderlin’s late poetry did not
become accessible to the general reader until the publication of the fourth
volume of Norbert von Hellingrath’s edition in 1916 and that Heidegger
was making a radical departure from the customary reading of Hölderlin’s
late work by taking a hagiographical approach to precisely this phase of
his creativity. He has given this a theoretical basis in numerous places,
notably in the essay Der Ursprung des Kunstwerks (The Origin of the
Work of Art) of 1935-1936. From a literary perspective, however, this
often results in his lifting segments of text from their origins, in effect:
decontextualising them. A great deal of writing on Heidegger in English
simply accepts this practice without enquiring into what implications this
change of status may have. It has resulted in the reception of Hölderlin by
Heidegger and Heideggerians constituting a separate preserve, isolated
from the mainstream of scholarship on the poet both in Germany and
elsewhere. My intention in the following is to restore something of the
literary perspective. For the sake of consistency and accuracy, all
translations into English in this essay are my own. References to
Heidegger and other authors are to texts in the original language.
Taking this approach means suspending the special privilege
Heidegger accords to certain poems. Hence all such texts as may be seen
as having a claim to other than fictional status, including philosophical
writing, will be discussed as fictions. To cite one example of this
approach, Robert Alter’s The Art of Biblical Narrative contains a chapter
called “Sacred History and the Beginnings of Prose Fiction” in which
Anthony Stephens 9
An echo of the times is audible in the word Heidegger uses for “coming to
power”, Ermächtigung, since the law giving Hitler dictatorial powers was
the Ermächtigungsgesetz of 23 March 1933. Here Heidegger also touches
on the enigma of the “history of Being”, and I shall return to this puzzle
later. What Heidegger’s focus on a small number of texts from about five
years of Hölderlin’s productive life achieves is to make Hölderlin appear
much less typical of his own age than is the case. Hölderlin’s artistic
development is steeped in German Hellenism and German Idealism, with
all that implies in terms of metaphysics. It was no coincidence that
Hölderlin received his higher education in the Tübinger Stift, a protestant
seminary, in the company of Hegel and Schelling and that they together
composed a text, since called Das Älteste Systemprogramm [des deutschen
Idealismus] (The First Systematic Program [of German Idealism])
(Hölderlin, 1969: 2, 647-49). The draft manifesto, a fragment of which is
preserved in Hegel’s handwriting, was composed in the years 1795-97
(Kreuzer, ed., 2002: 38ff.).
Heidegger was more willing to admit Hölderlin’s congruity with the
metaphysics of his age in 1934-35 than he was later:
But history is always the unique history of the people in question, in this
case of the people to which this poet belongs, the history of Germania.
Now and to the extent we know who this man is in his essence, we have
attained that which we were seeking: the metaphysical locus of Hölderlinic
poetry. That is the centre of Being itself, the Being of the demigods, the
Being of the man, of our poet. We recall what the latter says of himself
[...]: “But now day breaks! I waited, saw its coming,/ And let what I saw,
the Holy, be my word” (Heidegger, 1980: 288).
What Rilke terms “the Open”, principally in the eighth of his Duino
Elegies, has nothing but the sound of the same words in common with
what the thinking of the essence of DOKTHLD comprehends in the term “the
Open”. A brief explanation of what Rilke means by “the Open” can assist
us to form a more stable concept and to be ready for a more clarified
contemplation of what is thought in the essential realm of DOKTHLD by
means of a resolute differentiation from the Rilkean word. [...] It is
necessary only to point out unambiguously, that Rilke’s naming of “the
Open” is different in every respect from what is conceived concerning “the
Open” in its essential relation to DOKTHLD and from what is to be
conceived in terms of a conceptual question (Heidegger, 1982: 227).
This is a topic to which he will return in his essay of 1946 on Rilke, Wozu
Dichter?, in the essay collection Holzwege – an essay that allegedly set
out to commemorate the 20th anniversary of Rilke’s death – but, by and
large, recurs to the strictures of the lectures on Parmenides. In point of
fact, what Heidegger claims as his “discoveries” with regard to the relation
of poetic language to the world of objects and common experience had
already been anticipated in print by Rilke in his essays on aesthetics
between 1898 and 1903 (Stephens, 1976: 94-114), and Rilke, essentially,
had done no more than draw his own original conclusions from the
questions already posed by French Symbolism. Heidegger appears to have
been blissfully ignorant of them – a sine qua non of his denigration of
Rilke. Had Heidegger taken the trouble to read Mallarmé, then he could
have scarcely presented his essentially old-fashioned poetics with the
panache he does. But then, he had, quite arbitrarily, selected Hölderlin’s
latest poetry as the apogee of Western poetic achievement, and in this
template there was no room for what European poetry had accomplished
since Baudelaire. The hagiography that has attached itself to Heidegger’s
poetics has no defence but wilful ignorance.
I have retranslated the poem by Rilke, Wie die Natur die Wesen
überläßt […], that Heidegger discusses at length in Wozu Dichter?, since
the translation by Julian Young and Kenneth Haynes in Off the Beaten
Track makes the German syntax of the closing lines very ambiguous, and
quite unnecessarily so:
In Off the Beaten Track the “it” which ends the translation of this poem
offers a choice of antecedents: “law”, “the open”, “our defenselessness”
(Young and Haynes, eds., 2002: 207). The real antecedent in the original
text is “Schutzlossein”, which I have rendered at that point as “exposure”
to avoid a repetition of the more literal, close synonym “unprotectedness”
earlier in the text. This is an untitled poem written on 4.6.1924, and not
published in Rilke’s lifetime, as a dedication in a copy of Rilke’s novel
Die Aufzeichnungen des Malte Laurids Brigge (begun 1904, published
1910). The copy was sent on behalf of Rilke’s wife Clara to Hellmuth
Freiherr Lucius von Stoedner. In this poem, written more than two years
after the eighth Duineser Elegie, there is nothing to say that Rilke is
working with the same understanding of “the Open” that he develops
there, where it is used as a conjectural foil to bring out the limitations of
human perception of the world, which is evoked – in opposition to what
animals may experience – as being “closed” in various senses (Stephens,
1972: 178ff.; Engel, ed., 2004: 380ff.). Indeed, the third last line suggests
human consciousness may here indeed have some access to “the Open”,
which the text of the eighth Duineser Elegie emphatically denies.
However that be, underlying all Heidegger’s strictures on Rilke is the
assumption that Rilke, like Hölderlin, strove to reflect in his work one
unified world-view. In the tradition of German Idealism, Hölderlin did for
as long as he was able. Rilke did not, and this is one of the oldest
conundrums of scholarship on Rilke.
But to you, you splendid one, to you, you conjurer, a whole life was given
to feel as an urgent image, when you spoke it out,
each line closed like destiny, death was
even in the gentlest, and you entered it; but
the god who preceded you led you out and above it
Since this poem was published in the same volume as the dedicatory
poem, Wie die Natur die Wesen überläßt [...], on which Heidegger did
comment in detail, the fundamental difference between the two poets had
been clearly spelled out by one of them in a book Heidegger read, but
Heidegger simply chose to ignore the fact. Why?
I suggest that it stems from a fiction Heidegger terms “the history of
Being”, whose strong agenda makes it necessary for Rilke’s poetry to
“remain back behind that of Hölderlin on the course of the history of
Being as far as rank and position are concerned” (Heidegger, 1950: 276)
The word Heidegger uses for course, Bahn, implies linear movement, in
time since it occurs in the German words for race-track, ghost-train, tram-
line and, of course, Autobahn. Does this “history of Being” run backwards
in time? It appears so in Heidegger’s essay on Rilke, Wozu Dichter?. Here
Hölderlin is called the “precursor” whom “no poet of our age can
overtake”. Why? “The precursor does not [...] disappear into a future, but
he arrives from the future in such a manner that it is only in the arrival of
his word that the future achieves presence” (Heidegger, 1950: 320).
My answer to this puzzle is that Heidegger posits two different
“histories of Being”, and that one of them does reverse time-sequences.
For Heidegger pulls the same trick on Nietzsche in 1935, as he does on
Rilke in 1946. At the conclusion of his lectures on Der Rhein in 1935,
Heidegger states:
What Hölderlin here sees as the essence of historical being, the emotional
intensities in conflict between what is an endowment and what is a task,
was rediscovered by Nietzsche and termed the Dionysian and Apollonian,
but not in such simplicity and purity as Hölderlin; for in the intervening
time Nietzsche had had to traverse all those fatal circumstances that are
denoted by the names Schopenhauer, Darwin, Wagner, and the term
Anthony Stephens 15
“founding years” [of the German Empire]. [...] The hour of our history has
now struck. [...] The force of Being must now once more and in reality
become a question for our powers of comprehension (Heidegger, 1980:
294).
signally failed. Since Hölderlin envisages the future return of the gods, the
dominance of a radiant future over present and past does not have to be
abandoned. His installation of Hitler as the authority that guarantees the
future in the letter to Elisabeth Blochmann of 30 March 1933 – “So I
experience the present wholly in terms of the future” (Heidegger, 1990:
60) – stands in clear parallel to his subjection of the present to
Hölderlin’s poetry in the introduction to his lectures on Germanien and
Der Rhein: “We do not wish to make Hölderlin accord with our own age,
but, on the contrary: we wish to subject ourselves and those to come to the
measure of the poet” (Heidegger, 1980: 4).
The only problem is that, between Heidegger’s own era and the few
years at the start of the 19th century when Hölderlin wrote the poems
Heidegger refers to endlessly, there is a kind of temporal trough of about
140 years into which the achievements of Nietzsche and Rilke fall. Both
have to fail in comparison with Hölderlin, because Hölderlin’s only true
peers are the Pre-Socratics. Thus, from 1934 onwards, Heidegger becomes
more and more critical of Nietzsche, and, in 1946, Rilke, whose prestige in
Germany as a poet in the 40’s rivalled that of Hölderlin, has to be again
put down and presented as a Hölderlin manqué, although Heidegger had
access to all that was needful for him to avoid this distortion of Rilke’s
work – most of all the poem quoted above in which Rilke himself is both
unstinting in his admiration of Hölderlin and perfectly clear as to the
fundamental difference between their two poetic projects. Instead, he still
quibbles as to the right understanding of the concept of “the Open”, so as
to show Rilke as being helplessly entangled in “present-day metaphysics”,
hence lagging behind Hölderlin.
I suggest therefore that Heidegger’s portrayal of Hölderlin and Rilke
is dictated by the fictional structure of that alternative “history of Being”
that is subordinated to a vision of future salvation. The poets are thereby
cut to size in the sense that they are shaped to fit a pattern that has its
origins outside the work of either of them. At its most basic, Heidegger’s
doubling of the “history of Being” can be seen as an oscillation within his
apocalyptics. When he wishes to accent the positive, soteric aspect,
Hölderlin’s poetry is necessary as an anticipation of the world to come,
and this means that time has to be rearranged so that Hölderlin is “the
precursor” who “arrives from the future” (Heidegger, 1950: 320), thus
assigning to the poet the same role Hölderlin himself had assigned to
Christ in his great elegy Brod und Wein (Bread and Wine). What this
might have to do with philosophy in the 20th century eludes me, but it is a
standard pattern in German Romantic visions of an ideal futurity, which,
in turn, revive early Christian eschatology. When Heidegger’s
18 Cutting Poets to Size – Heidegger, Holderlin, Rilke
apocalyptics lack the soteric dimension and are weighed down by his
pessimism as to the increasing dominance of technology in history, then
they rather follow the Old Norse pattern of history degenerating into the
Fimbulvintr, the Great Winter presaging the end of the world, with no
redemption and no prospect but catastrophe. This variant leaves
chronology unscathed.
The esoteric history of Being has staying power. In the interview with
Der Spiegel in 1966 Heidegger insists: “only a god can save us”. We can
see this “history of Being” as a sublimation of the hopes he had initially
placed in Hitler’s regime. When he states late in his life: “Hölderlin is for
me the poet who points into the future, who awaits the god” (Thomä, ed.,
2003: 214), then Hölderlin has had transferred onto him the whole burden
of futurity – but at what cost?
Ultimately none, since most recent writing on Heidegger seems to live
happily with two different “histories of Being”. As for the poets, only
those readers who approach them solely through Heidegger’s texts will
face grossly selective, exaggerated or distorted versions of their work. The
question is rather: what does it say about a philosophy that it depends on
dual versions of the same “history” and that one of them is anchored by an
irrational conception of part of the achievement of one poet?
Heidegger’s impact on the reception of both poets in Germany was
greatest in the 50’s and early 60’s of the 20th century and diminished
sharply with the swing to the left of the “1968 generation”. Once the short-
lived Marxist dominance in German literary scholarship was over, there
was no return to Heideggerian positions and terminology. Recent German
scholarship on the topic of Heidegger and Hölderlin tends to cast a cold
eye on Heidegger’s glorification of the poet. Thus Kathleen Wright states
in the recent Heidegger-Handbuch:
Heidegger explicitly makes a hero of Hölderlin – indeed both during and
after the Hitler-era, by assigning the leading role to Hölderlin and poetry
(and only to Hölderlin’s poetry) in the drama in which the destinies and
the future of Germany and Europe unfold. At the same time he magnifies
himself since he gives his own thought (and only his own thought) the
only important minor role in the same unfolding drama (Thomä, ed., 2003:
214).
Rilke had made the acquaintance of Norbert von Hellingrath, the editor of
the pioneering Hölderlin edition, in 1910 and was in contact with his
Anthony Stephens 21
editorial project from 1911 onwards. It may thus be the case that lines in a
poem finished by Rilke in 1912, Perlen entrollen (Pearls are spilled) is an
early reminiscence of Brod und Wein with none of the later connotations
of the concept in the eighth Duineser Elegie at all: “O wie ein Golf hofft
ins Offne/und vom gestreckten Leuchtturm/ scheinende Räume wirft [...]”
(“Oh, as a gulf hopes towards the Open/ and from its stretched
lighthouse/throws luminous spaces [...]” (Rilke, 1996: 2, 38). The sea-
imagery and the evocation of vast spaces seem to establish a connection to
Hölderlin, but one looks in vain for the epistemological concerns of the
eighth Duineser Elegie. This illustrates how careful one must be in dealing
with Rilkean concepts from poem to poem.
Heidegger was not careful at all, and so, as Agamben must
acknowledge (Agamben, 2004: 57ff.), he comes to represent Rilke, in his
lectures on Parmenides, as an ignoramus: “Rilke knows and suspects
nothing of DOKTHLD; he knows and suspects as little as does Nietzsche.
Accordingly Rilke is entirely confined within the borders of the traditional
metaphysical definition of human and animal” (Heidegger, 1982: 231).
But Rilke continues to be read and esteemed – as does Heidegger, for all
that he knew and suspected nothing of the nature of poetic fictions.
Bibliography
Agamben, 2004
Giorgio Agamben, The Open. Man and Animal. Trans. Kevin Attell.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Alter, 1981
Robert Alter, The Art of Biblical Narrative, London & Sydney: Allen
and Unwin.
Angehrn, 2003
Emil Angehrn, “Kritik der Metaphysik und der Technik. Heideggers
Auseinandersetzung mit der abendländischen Tradition”. In
Heidegger-Handbuch. Leben – Werk – Wirkung, ed. Dieter Thomä:
268-279: Stuttgart & Weimar: Verlag J.B Metzler.
Barash, 2003
Jeffrey Arnold Barash, Martin Heidegger and the Problem of
Historical Meaning. 2nd. rev. ed.. New York: Fordham University
Press.
Betz, 1938
Maurice Betz, Rilke in Frankreich. Erinnerungen, Briefe, Dokumente.
Wien: Reichner Verlag.
22 Cutting Poets to Size – Heidegger, Holderlin, Rilke
Buchheim, 2002
Iris Buchheim, “Heidegger. Hölderlin als 'Geschick'”. In Hölderlin-
Handbuch. Leben – Werk – Wirkung, ed. Johann Kreuzer: 432-438.
Stuttgart &Weimar: Verlag J.B.Metzler 2002.
Buddeberg, 1956
Else Buddeberg, Denken und Dichten des Seins. Stuttgart: Verlag J.B.
Metzler.
Engel, 2004
Manfred Engel, ed., Rilke-Handbuch. Leben – Werk – Wirkung.
Stuttgart & Weimar: Verlag J.B.Metzler.
Gumbrecht, 2004
Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht, Production of Presence. What Meaning
Cannot Convey. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Haar, 1994
Michel Haar, La Fracture de l’Histoire. Douze essais sur Heidegger.
Grenoble: Editions Jérôme Millon.
Hamburger, 1966
Käte Hamburger, Philosophie der Dichter. Stuttgart: Ernst Klett
Verlag.
Heidegger, 1950
Martin Heidegger , “Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes (1935/36)”. In
Holzwege: 1-74: Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
Heidegger, 1950
Martin Heidegger, “Wozu Dichter?”. In Holzwege: 248-320: Frankfurt
am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
Heidegger, 1990
Martin Heidegger, Elisabeth Blochmann, Briefwechsel 1918-1969, ed.
J. W. Storck, Marbach am Meckar: Deutsaches Literaturarchiv.
Heidegger, 1980
Martin Heidegger, Hölderlins Hymnen "Germanien" und "Der Rhein".
Gesamtausgabe, vol. 39, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
Heidegger, 1950
Martin Heidegger, Holzwege. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio
Klostermann.
Heidegger, 2002
Martin Heidegger, Off the Beaten Track [Holzwege]. Trans. and ed.
Julian Young and Kenneth Haynes. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2002.
Heidegger, 1982
Martin Heidegger, Parmenides. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 54, Frankfurt am
Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
Anthony Stephens 23
Hölderlin, 1969
Friedrich Hölderlin, Werke und Briefe, eds. Friedrich Beißner and
Jochen Schmidt, Frankfurt am Main: Insel Verlag.
Kreuzer, 2002
Joachim Kreuzer, ed., Hölderlin-Handbuch. Leben – Werk – Wirkung.
Stuttgart and Weimar: Verlag J.B. Metzler.
Mason, 1964
Eudo C. Mason, Lebenshaltung und Symbolik bei Rainer Maria Rilke,
Weimar, 1939. 2nd ed.. Oxford: Marston Press.
Phillips, 2005
James Phillips, Heidegger’s Volk. Between National Socialism and
Poetry. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Rilke, 1931
Rainer Maria Rilke, Briefe und Tagebücher aus der Frühzeit. Leipzig:
Insel Verlag.
Rilke, 1996
Rainer Maria Rilke, Werke, vol. 2, Gedichte 1910-1926, eds. Manfred
Engel and Ulrich Fülleborn. Frankfurt am Main & Leipzig: Insel
Verlag.
Risser, 1999
James Risser, ed., Heidegger. Toward the Turn. Essays on the Work of
the 1930s. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press.
Stephens, 1972
Anthony Stephens, Rainer Maria Rilke’s "Gedichte an die Nacht". An
Essay in Interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stephens, 1976
Anthony Stephens, "Ästhetik und Existenzentwurf beim frühen Rilke".
In Rilke heute [II], eds. Ingeborg H. Solbrig and Joachim Storck: 95-
114. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag.
Stephens, 2003
Anthony Stephens, “Duineser Elegien”. In Rilke-Handbuch. Leben –
Werk – Wirkung, ed. Manfred Engel: 365-384. Stuttgart & Weimar:
Verlag J.B.Metzler.
Thomä, 2003
Dieter Thomä, ed., Heidegger-Handbuch. Leben – Werk – Wirkung.
Stuttgart & Weimar: Verlag J.B Metzler.
Wolin, 1990
Richard Wolin, The Politics of Being. The Political Thought of Martin
Heidegger. New York & Oxford: Columbia University Press.
24 Cutting Poets to Size – Heidegger, Holderlin, Rilke
Wolin, 1991
Richard Wolin, ed., The Heidegger Controversy. A Critical Reader.
Cambridge, Mass. & London: The MIT Press.
Wright, 2003
Kathleen Wright , “Die 'Erläuterungen zu Hölderlins Dichtung' und die
drei Hölderlin Vorlesungen (1934/35, 1941/42, 1942). Die
Heroisierung Hölderlins”. In Heidegger-Handbuch. Leben – Werk –
Wirkung, ed. Dieter Thomä: 213-230. Stuttgart & Weimar: Verlag J.B:
Metzler.
GEOGRAPHY, BIOLOGY AND POLITICS:
HEIDEGGER ON PLACE AND WORLD
JEFF MALPAS
I.
Heidegger claimed that one of the unique features of his thinking in the
1920s was his discovery, or rediscovery, of the problem of world. The
concept of world figures prominently in Part One, Division One, of Being
and Time, but Heidegger remained dissatisfied with his treatment of the
matter there, frequently returning to the problem in his work in the period
immediately following the publication of Being and Time – most
obviously in the 1929 lectures on The Fundamental Concepts of
Metaphysics. In those lectures Heidegger responds to the problem at issue
by exploring the difference between the mode of being proper to the
animal and the human, and, in so doing, he draws upon a range of
biological and zoological studies from the previous forty years or so
including the work of figures such as the experimental embryologist
Wilhelm Roux, the Czech biologist Emmanuel Radl, the neo-vitalist
biologist Hans Driesch, and the pioneering ethologist, Jakob von Uexküll.
The way Heidegger draws upon these scientific sources, and who he
draws upon (most of these figures form part of the anti-materialist
movement in German science that is the subject of Anne Harrington’s
excellent Reenchanted Science1), is itself of interest for what it tells us
about Heidegger’s knowledge of the scientific thinking of his time. In his
own more recent examination of the relation between the human and the
animal, the essay, The Open, Giorgio Agamben discusses von Uexküll’s
work, in particular, with specific reference to Heidegger, but he also
connects that work, both that of von Uexküll and Heidegger, with the work
of two prominent geographical theorists, Paul Vidal de la Blanche and
Friedrich Ratzel. Agamben writes:
1
Anne Harrington, Reenchanted Science: Holism in German Culture from
Wilhelm II to Hitler (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999).
26 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
The studies by the founder of ecology follow a few years after those by
Paul Vidal de la Blanche on the relationship between populations and their
environment (the Tableau de la géographie de la France is from 1903),
and those of Friedrich Ratzel on the Lebensraum, the ‘vital space’ of
peoples (the Politische Geographie is from 1897), which would
profoundly revolutionize human geography of the twentieth century. And
it is not impossible that the central thesis of Sein und Zeit on being-in-the-
world (In-der-Welt-sein) as the fundamental human structure can be read
in some ways as a response to this problematic field, which at the
beginning of the century essentially modified the traditional relationship
between the living being and its environment-world. As is well-known,
Ratzel’s theses, according to which all peoples are intimately linked to
their vital space as their essential dimension, had a notable influence on
Nazi geopolitics. This proximity is marked in a curious episode in
Uexküll’s intellectual biography. In 1928, five years before the advent of
Nazism, this very sober scientist writes a preface to Houston
Chamberlain’s Die Grundlagen des neunzehnten Jahrhunderts
{Foundations of the Nineteenth Century}, today considered one of the
precursors of Nazism’.2
2
Giogio Agamben, The Open: Man and Animal, trans. Kevin Attell (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2004), pp.42-43.
Jeff Malpas 27
connection with the main theme of this volume explicit: the aesthetics of
dwelling that we find in the later Heidegger, and that is already prefigured
(although in a less than integrated fashion) in elements of the earlier
thinking, has to be understood in terms of the centrality to Heidegger’s
thinking of a concept that is also central to cultural-geographic thought,
namely, the concept of place or ‘geographic’ space – topos, Ort,
Ortschaft3. Agamben’s comments highlight this connection through their
juxtaposition of Heidegger’s philosophy with the geographical thought of
Ratzel and Vidal de la Blanche (which is not to ignore the important
connection with von Uexküll). In so doing, however, Agamben also
indicates the way in which it is precisely the connection between, as we
may put it, the philosophical and the geographical that can be seen as
reinforcing the politically problematic character of Heidegger’s thinking.
Yet not only is the manner in which Agamben draws this connection
highly misleading in this regard, but it also neglects any real consideration
of what might be at issue in the centrality of the ‘geographical’, or better,
the topological, in Heidegger’s thought. Indeed, notwithstanding
Heidegger’s own personal political engagement, there is reason to think
that the role played by the concept of place in his thought actually runs
counter to the associations that are often taken to belong with it.
II.
One of the important developments within cultural geography in the
last quarter of the twentieth century has been the rise of a movement often
referred to as ‘humanistic geography’ that draws heavily on the work of
Husserl as well as Heidegger, and that has given a special emphasis to the
concept of place as a central and determining notion in geographical
inquiry. The key figures in this development include writers such as Yi-Fu
Tuan, 4 Edward Relph,5 Anne Buttimer and David Seamon,6 and their
3
For a more detailed account of the topological character of Heidegger’s thinking
see my Heidegger’s Topology: Being, Place, World (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press, 2006).
4
See, for instance, Yi-Fu Tuan, Space and Place: The Perspective of Experience
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1977).
5
Relph’s Place and Placelessness (London: Pion, 1976) is a particularly
influential text in the area.
6
See, amongst other works, Anne Buttimer and David Seamon (eds.), The Human
Experience of Space and Place (London: Croom Helm, 1980); also David Seamon
and Robert Mugerauer (eds.), Dwelling, Place, and Environment: Towards a
Phenomenology of Person and World (New York: Columbia University Press,
28 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
work has not been restricted in its influence to geography alone. Indeed,
humanistic geography has come to be allied with a mode of place-oriented
environmental thinking that encompasses writers in a wide range of
disciplines from sociology to psychology, from anthropology to
architecture. Within this broad field, Heidegger’s ‘Bauen Wohnen
Denken’ (‘Building Dwelling Thinking’)7 has often appeared as a key text.
Moreover, that tradition is also one that can be seen to connect up with,
and draw upon, the work of Vidal de la Blanche – a point that might be
thought to confirm the associations suggested by Agamben. Yet, in fact,
the way in which Vidal de la Blanche plays a role here is itself indicative
of the need for a certain degree of caution in attempting to delineate the
connections and lines of influence that might be thought to be at stake,
since the Vidalian tradition as it appears within American geography is
itself often counter-posed to Ratzelian thinking rather than being allied
with it – and this so in spite of the Ratzelian influences on Vidal de la
Blanche himself. Moreover, humanistic geography draws heavily on
phenomenology, on Husserl as much as Heidegger, as well as on writers
such as Bachelard and Merleau-Ponty. How are we to situate that broader
phenomenological tradition, within which the idea of a close connection
between human being and space or place is also a recurrent theme
(especially as developed in the work of Bachelard and Merleau-Ponty), in
terms of the problematic set of connections sketched out by Agamben?
As Agamben presents matters, Heidegger, von Uexküll, Ratzel and
Vidal de la Blanche all share the same basic commitment to a conception
of human being as essentially bound up with its environment or world – in
Heideggerian terms, human being is being-there (Da-sein) which is being-
in-the-world. Such a commitment, as I indicated a moment ago, is also one
1985). For an excellent survey of recent articles on humanistic geography see Paul
Adams, Steven Hoelscher and Karen E Till (eds), Textures of Place: Exploring
Humanist Geographies (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2001). It
should be emphasized, however, that this is not the only route through which
Heidegger’s influence has been felt in contemporary geography. Heidegger has, of
course, had a major impact on geographic thinking simply in virtue of the
enormous impact he has had on twentieth century thought in general, but
Heidegger’s specific focus on concepts and space and place has also had, in
addition to the immediate effect of essays such as ‘Bauen Wohnen Denken’, a
significant indirect impact through its effect on key thinkers as Foucault and
Lefebvre – see, especially, Stuart Elden, Mapping the Present: Heidegger,
Foucault and the project of a spatial history (London: Continuum, 2001).
7
In Vorträge und Aufsätze (Stuttgart: Günther Neske Verlag, 1954); the English
translation appears in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New
York: Harper and Row, 1975).
Jeff Malpas 29
8
Troy Paddock, ‘Gedachtes Wohnen: Heidegger and Cultural Geography’,
Philosophy and Geography 7 (2004), p.237-8.
9
In this respect, the comments in Paddock’s reply seem to be rather weaker, and
certainly less clear, in the connection they assert between Heidegger, Ratzel and
30 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
Nazism, than those to be found in his original article – see Paddock, ‘In Defense
of Homology and History: a Response to Allen’, Philosophy and Geography 7
(2004), pp.257-8.
10
Paddock, ‘Gedachtes Wohnen’, p.248.
11
See, for instance, Charles Bambach’s discussion of the role of the idea of
‘rootedness’ (Bodenständigkeit), and associated notions, in Heidegger’s writings
and speeches form the 1930s in Heidegger’s Roots: Nietzsche, National Socialism,
and the Greeks (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003), pp.12-68. Bambach
argues that the preoccupation with rootedness and autochthony is present
throughout Heidegger’s thinking, not only in the 1930s, and that these notions are
always marked by the logic of exclusion.
Jeff Malpas 31
resignation from the Rectorate in 1934, and so at a time after his attempt to
establish himself as the intellectual leader of a National Socialist Germany
had clearly failed, that such a conception, as developed explicitly in terms
of place, seems to become much more important.
There is certainly a clear shift in Heidegger’s thinking that first occurs
in the ‘thirties, and intensifies around the late ‘forties, towards an explicit
concern with place and related concepts – concepts that include those of
‘dwelling’, the ‘Fourfold’ and, I would also argue, of the Event (das
Ereignis) – my own view is that this shift towards the ‘geographic’ or
‘topological’ is itself closely tied to the famous ‘Turning’ or ‘Reversal’ in
Heidegger’s thought12). There is good reason to suppose that this shift is
itself connected to Heidegger’s own failed engagement with Nazism, not
in the sense that it derives from Nazi ideology, but is instead formed in a
reaction to it.13 Significantly, it is in his engagement with Hölderlin in
1934-35, immediately after his resignation of the Rectorate, that ideas of
place and dwelling that lie at the heart of the ‘geographic’ conception of
space that concerns Paddock begin to emerge more explicitly (though still
in a relatively undeveloped form) as a focus for Heidegger’s thinking.
Thus one finds, at the same time as Heidegger’s thought orients itself more
towards ‘geographic’ or ‘place-based’ conceptions, a shift away from, and
sometimes direct criticism of, key elements of associated with Nazi
ideology. One might argue, of course, that this shift is simply a result of
the failure in Heidegger’s own political ambitions, and so to treat it as a
kind of ‘sour grapes’ response, and while there may be some truth in this
from a biographical perspective, it should not be allowed to obscure the
philosophical issues that are nevertheless also involved. Indeed, as we
shall see shortly, there is a deep tension between ‘geographic’ modes of
thinking and the type of thinking that is characteristic of Nazi ideology,
and this tension becomes apparent, not only in Heidegger’s thinking, but
also in the work of Ratzel and Vidal de la Blanche.
12
See my discussion of this in Heidegger’s Topology, chapter four.
13
One might argue that such a reading can be drawn, in part, from James Phillips’
argument in Heidegger’s Volk: Between National Socialism and Poetry (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2005), although Phillips focuses more on the idea of
‘the people’ and the role of poetry in Heidegger’s thinking in this period, than on
place as such (see, however, Phillips’ discussion of the ‘uncanny homeland’ –
‘unheimliche Heimat’ – on pp.169-217).
32 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
III.
Just as a closer examination of Heidegger’s own involvement with
Nazism complicates the attempt to discern a simple line of connection
between Heidegger’s own fascist politics and his thinking of space and
place, so too does a closer examination of the intellectual history that
involves Heidegger, Ratzel, Vidal de la Blanche and von Uexküll lead to a
more complex picture than that which Agamben implies. To what extent
Heidegger’s concept of ‘being-in-the-world’ is actually indebted to or
influenced by von Uexküll’s concept of Umwelt seems to me debateable –
nowhere have I seen any evidence that would demonstrate any direct
influence from one to the other as opposed to some convergence of what
were otherwise independent lines of thought, although Harrington, for
instance, speculates on the possibility of such influence. Heidegger was
certainly familiar with von Uexküll’s work at the time he wrote The
Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, and, as Harrington points out, von
Uexküll himself drew attention to apparent similarities between his
thought and that of Heidegger in a 1937 paper.14 Yet while the exact
nature and extent of any influence of between von Uexküll on Heidegger
may be uncertain,15 there can be no doubt of the connection between von
Uexküll and Chamberlain. Indeed, what Agamben omits to tell us,
somewhat surprisingly perhaps, is that not only did von Uexküll write a
14
See Harrington, Reenchanted Science, pp.53-4; Harington refers to Uexküll `Die
neue Umweltlehre. Ein Bindeglied zwischen Natur- und Kultur-Wissenschaft’, Die
Erziehung: Monatschrift für den Zussamenhang von Kultur und Erziehung im
Wissenschaft und Leben 13 (1937), p.199.
15
My own view is that the influence is likely, if it exists at all, to be at a fairly
general level simply because of the neo-Kantian subjectivism – which I discuss
further below – that is such a central element in Uexküll’s thinking, and which
Heidegger clearly attempts to avoid, if not entirely successfully, even in Being and
Time. Heidegger and Uexküll may have both accept a holistic construal of the
relation between the human, or animal, and the world, but they differ significantly
in the way that holistic relation is understood (the analogy between ‘being-in-the-
world’ and the idea of the animal in its ‘umwelt’ is thus somewhat superficial, even
though both can be seen as exemplifying a similar holistic tendency). The interest
in Uexküll that is evident in the lectures that make up Heidegger’s The
Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics seems to be underpinned partly by
Heidegger’s desire to connect his own thinking with contemporary biological
thought, and especially with the holist and anti-mechanist tendencies in that
thought, and partly, as I discuss below, by the problem that is presented by
Uexküll’s talk of the animal as having a world at all – talk that seems in conflict
with Heidegger’s own account of the animal as ‘poor in world’.
Jeff Malpas 33
16
Letter to Chamberlain, April 10, 1921; quoted in Harrington, Reenchanted
Science, p.60.
17
The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, p.264.
34 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
18
‘The Origin of the Work of Art’, in Off the Beaten Track (English translation of
Holzwege), trans. Julian Young and Kenneth Barnes (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002), p.55.
19
Contributions to Philosophy, trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999), p.208; see also the comments in
’’European Nihilism’, in Nietzsche, trans. David Farrell Krell (San Francisco:
Harper & Row, 1979-87), Vol IV (Nihilism), p.141.
Jeff Malpas 35
constructed in all its details. Everything [about the beech] that I see, hear,
smell or feel are not qualities that exclusively belong to the beech, but
rather are characteristics of my sense organs that I project outside of
myself’20 The same subjectivism is also clearly evident in von Uexküll’s
published work – for instance, in his 1934 book, A Stroll Through the
Worlds of Animals and Men, von Uexküll invites us to:
…first blow, in fancy, a soap bubble around each creature to represent its
own world, filled with the perceptions which it alone knows. When we
ourselves then step into one of these bubbles, the familiar meadow is
transformed. Many of its colourful features disappear, others no longer
belong together but appear in new relationships. A new world comes into
being. Through the bubble we see the world of the burrowing worm, of the
butterfly, of the field-mouse; the world as it appears to the animals
themselves, not as it appears to us. This we may call the phenomenal
world or the self-world of the animal.21
20
Quoted by Harrington, from Uexküll’s unpublished autobiographical notes, in
Reenchanted Science, p.41.
21
‘A Stroll Through the Worlds of Animals and Men’, in Claire H. Schiller (ed.),
Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a Modern Concept (New York:
International Universities Press, 1957p.5.
22
Thus Ludwig Clauss writes in Die nordische Seele: Eine Einführung in die
Rassenseelenkunde (The Nordic Soul: An Introduction to Racial Psychology), that
“The manner in which the soul reaches out into its world fashions the geographical
area of this world into a ‘landscape’. A landscape is not something that the soul
alights upon, as it were, something ready-made. Rather it is something that it
fashions by virtue of its species-determined way of viewing its environment” –
Clauss, Die nordische Seele: Eine Einführung in die Rassenseelenkunde (Munich:
J.F. Lehmanns Verlag, 1932), p.19.
36 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
IV.
It has been common to assimilate racialist thinking of the sort
exemplified in Uexküll, with its emphasis on the difference between the
racial types associated with different regions or ‘spaces’ to Ratzelian
geographic ‘determinism’. In fact, Ratzel stands quite apart from writers
such as von Uexküll, and other racial theorists in general, simply on the
basis of his very different understanding of the nature of the connection at
issue here. It is indeed as an environmental or geographic determinist –
one who puts the emphasis on the human as determined by the
environment or geography – that Ratzel has been most commonly read, if
not entirely accurately, within English-speaking circles; and it is notable
that Ratzel also placed himself in clear opposition to the racist doctrines
that were common in the latter half of the nineteenth century. He thus
writes that ‘The task of ethnography is …to indicate, not in the first
instances the distinctions, but the points of transition, and the intimate
affinities which exist; for mankind is one though very variously
cultured’.23 Ratzel’s notion of Lebensraum, living space, was an
expression of his commitment to the idea that the forms of human
organisation were always bound to their own geographic space, and could
not be understood in separation from that space. As Robert Dickinson
writes:
Ratzel…thought of the anthropogeographic unit as an areal complex
whose spatial connections were needed for the functioning and
organisation of a particular kind of human group, be it the village, town or
state. The concept of lebensraum deals with the relations between human
society as a spatial (geographic) organisation and its physical setting.
Community area, trade area, milk-shed and labour-shed, historical
province, commercial entity, the web of trade between neighbouring
industrial areas across state boundaries – these area all subsequent
variations of the concept of the ‘living area’.24
23
Ratzel, History of Mankind, trans. A. J. Butler from 2nd German edn., 3 vols
(London: Macmillan, 1896-8), p.4.
24
Robert E. Dickinson, The Makers of Modern Geography (London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1969), 71.
Jeff Malpas 37
25
See J. Nicholas Entrikin and Vincent Berdoulay, ‘The Pyrenees as Place:
Lefebvre as guide’, Progress in Geography 29 (2002), p.143
38 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
others like him. It also marks, of course, a key point of differentiation from
Nazi ideology, and, in this respect, Heidegger must also be positioned
alongside Ratzel and Vidal de la Blanche. Moreover, it is not just the
emphasis on the role of the geographic (although what is meant by that
will also require some further examination) as opposed to the biologistic
that is at issue here. What characterises the work of von Uexküll, as well
as Nazi racial theorists, is the tendency to understand the nature of the
animal or human ‘world’ as based in certain general forms of species-
nature, ‘racial stock’ or racialised ‘soul’. Such a tendency is already one
that diminishes the significance of geographic space or place – it is the
general type that is important in such thinking, in contrast to which the
thinking that is oriented toward place typically gives emphasis to the
regional and the local.
This latter issue turns out to be a crucial point of difference when one
looks to the way Nazi ideology is related to the German ‘Heimat’
tradition. The idea of ‘Heimat’ – a term usually translated as ‘Homeland’
(though the translation does not capture the richness of the original
German) – is connected with ideas of one’s place of origin, the place in
which one belongs, not only in the sense of the region from which one
comes, and in which one may still dwell, but also in the sense of one’s
childhood home. In its academic form, the focus on Heimat and
Heimatskunde, was part of the same orientation towards an understanding
of human life and culture as it stood in relation to space, and so to region
and landscape, as is evident in Ratzel and Vidal de la Blanche. Thus
Ratzel’s Deutschland: Einführung in die Heimatkunde,26 which was a
standard text in German schools in the early part of the twentieth century,
essentially consisted in a regional ethnography of Germany. Elements of
the Heimat tradition were themselves appropriated by the Nazis appearing
in Nazi propaganda and rhetoric as well as in work of racial psychologists
such as Clauss – elements of local and regional tradition and culture could
be seen as a reflection of the racial stock associated with that locale or
region. Yet the emphasis here is not on the local and regional as such, but
rather on the local and the regional as they stand in relation to the racial
and the national. The totalising politics of the Nazi state was not about
strengthening local or regional associations and culture, but rather about
the creation of a political apparatus geared to the satisfaction of a set of
universalising desires and ambitions.27 It is thus that Nazism, for all its
romantic anti-modernist elements, can also be seen as the instantiation of
26
F. Ratzel, Deutschland. Einführung in die Heimatkunde (Leipzig: Grunow
1898).
27
See Heidegger’s Topology, pp.25-6.
Jeff Malpas 39
V.
It is often claimed that to take human being as standing in an important
relation to place or geographic space is already to presuppose a
homogeneity of culture and identity in relation to that place, as well as to
exclude others from it. This the core of the argument that is often used to
demonstrate the supposed politically dangerous character of ‘geographic’
28
For an exploration of some of the complex network of issues that is at stake
here, with particular, but not exclusive, reference to the Australian context, see
Linn Miller, Being and Belonging (PhD dissertation, University of Tasmania,
2006), and also, though from a somewhat different perspective, Peter Read,
Belonging: Australians, Place and Aboriginal Ownership (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000).
40 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
thinking (an argument that appears, for instance, in Levinas,29 but is also
assumed, apparently as self-evident, in many other writers). Yet this claim
is usually only advanced in specific instances – it is frequently directed
against Heidegger, for instance, but is seldom deployed against indigenous
forms of thought that similarly prioritise place or geographic space – and
typically depends on already construing ‘geographic’ thinking in a way
that assumes its problematic political associations rather than exhibiting or
proving them (and seldom delves too deeply into the actual historical and
philosophical details that might be relevant here). What the work of
thinkers such as Heidegger, as well as of Ratzel and Vidal de la Blanche,
and the broader tradition of humanistic geography, brings to prominence is
the very question of place or geographic space as such.
In Heidegger’s work the questionability of place is already evident, if
indirectly, in Being and Time, in terms of the problematic status accorded
to spatiality within the structure of ‘being-in-the-world’ at the same time
as ideas and images of space and place constantly emerge as central
elements within the overall analysis (in, for instance, the very idea of
‘being-in’, as well as the notion of the ‘Da’, the ‘There’, of Dasein).30
Much of Heidegger’s later thinking can be seen as itself a sustained
attempt to elucidate the nature of place or topos, hence Heidegger’s own
characterisation of his thinking as a ‘topology’ of being.31 In his thinking
of place, Heidegger can also be seen as urging a re-thinking of space.
Thus, in the very late essay ‘Art and Space’ (written in conjunction with
the Basque sculptor Eduardo Chillida whose contributions was in the form
of series of lithographs), Heidegger urges an understanding of space, in
terms, not of the ‘physical-technological’ space of ‘Galileo and Newton’,
but rather of ‘clearing away’ (Räumen) – the sort of ‘clearing away’ that
opens up a region for settlement and dwelling.32 While space is that which
Galileo and Newton theorise, it is also, that clearing away and opening up,
29
See Levinas, ‘Heidegger, Gagarin and Us’, in Difficult Freedom: Essays on
Judaism, trans. Seán Hand (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1990), pp.
231-34 – in this essay Levinas writes, for instance, that 'One's implementation in a
landscape, one's attachment to Place, without which the universe would become
insignificant and would scarcely exist, is the very splitting of humanity into natives
and strangers. And in this light technology is less dangerous than the spirits of
Place.'
30
See Heidegger’s Topology, chapter three.
31
See ‘Seminar in Le Thor 1969’, Four Seminars, trans. Andrew Mitchell and
François Raffoul (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2004), pp.41 & 47.
32
Martin Heidegger, ‘Art and Space’, trans. Charles Seibert, Man and World 1
(1973), p.4; from ‘Die Kunst und der Raum’ (St Gallen: Erker Verlag, 1969), p.6.
Jeff Malpas 41
that ‘spacing’, that allows for the possibility of appearance, and that occurs
always and only in relation to specific places. It is this sense of space,
itself closely associated to geographic rather than purely geometric space
(to use Paddock’s contrast) that turns out to be so important in the later
Heidegger’s meditative thinking on the happening of the Fourfold, and
with it the ‘aesthetics’ (we might also say, with an eye to the place of ethos
here, the ‘ethics’) of dwelling.
The space and place at issue here is not, however, a space or place
already determined by, nor simply determinative of, human being. Instead,
it is that within and on the basis of which human being is itself brought to
articulate and meaningful appearance. Thus, in the account of the Fourfold
in essays such as ‘Bauen Wohnen Denken’, place is that which is
established in and through the gathering together of earth and sky, gods
and mortals, in the thing, while it is also that within and on the basis of
which the thing itself appears, as it is also that which allows the
appearance of the elements of the Fourfold as such – the sky is that very
sky which arches above us, and the earth that which lies beneath our feet,
here, now, in this place, and it is also here, in ‘this’ place, and only here,
that the encounter between mortals, and between mortals and gods
(whether in their absence or presence) also occurs. Mortals thus play a role
in the coming to be of places, although not exclusively so, and places
themselves play a role in the appearing of mortals. On this basis, place
might be viewed in terms somewhat reminiscent of Plato’s conception of
the chora (a term sometimes equated with space, but also with place) as
the very matrix of becoming – although unlike Plato’s chora,33 which
remains always indeterminate, place itself comes to appearance, and so
appears in a singular and determinate form (as just ‘this’ place) in the
happening, the Ereignis, of place that is also the happening of the
Fourfold.34
Although there has sometimes been a tendency within humanistic
geography to treat place is ways that sometimes assume a certain
‘subjectivism’ in relation to place – place is thus viewed as a function of
human experience (a tendency that is sometimes evident in, for instance,
Tuan’s work35) – there is nevertheless a complexity and indeterminacy that
has also merged as a key element in the geographical understanding of
place as that has developed over the last century or so, particularly in the
line that derives from Ratzel and Vidal de la Blanche, and that
33
See Plato, Timaeus, 48E-52D
34
For a more detailed account see Heidegger’s Topology, chapter six.
35
See my brief comment on this in Place and Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999), p.30 n.33.
42 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
36
See Entrikin, The Betweeness of Place: Towards a Geography of Modernity
(London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990).
37
See Doreen Massey, ‘Power-geometry and a progressive sense of place’, in Jon
Bird, Barry Curtis, Tim Putnam, George Robertson and Lisa Tickner (eds),
Mapping the Futures (London: Routledge, 1993), pp.64-67.
38
See Massey, Space, Place and Gender (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1994), especially pp. 117-72.
Jeff Malpas 43
sense.39
VI.
Agamben’s juxtaposition of Heidegger with von Uexküll and, perhaps
more importantly, Ratzel and Vidal de la Blanche, turns out to be
significant for reasons rather different from those that Agamben himself
may have had in mind. It not only directs attention to the complexities of
the intellectual connections that we may trace out between Heidegger and
39
Heidegger, Parmenides, trans. André Schuwer and Richard Rojcewicz
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992), p.117.
40
‘Letter on “Humanism”’, Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp.257-58. See, once again, James Phillips’
discussion of this idea of the ‘uncanny homeland’ (‘unheimliche Heimat’) in
Heidegger’s Volk, pp.169-217.
44 Geography, Biology and Politics: Heidegger on Place and World
other thinkers, but also to the way in which Heidegger’s thought connects
up with a number of important elements in geographic thought that centre
on notions of ‘geographic’ space, and to the complexities that surround
those notions. One of the core questions that emerges here is not merely
whether the idea of a connection between human being and place is itself
politically problematic, but just how that connection should be understood.
Is it a matter, as von Uexküll, Chamberlain or Clauss would have it, that
place and space, and so also world, are themselves functions of the
biological, of a racially determined human nature, of a certain sort of soul?
Or is it rather that the world is itself worked out in and through place, and
that place provides the proper and only frame within which the animal and
the human can come to appearance, within which they appear as animal
and as human?
This latter question can be seen to bring us back within the ambit of
Agamben’s original comments, since they return us to the question of the
relation between place and world, as well as the relation between the
human and the animal, but they place the issue of place, and of space, at
the centre of that discussion, whereas it remains relatively peripheral in
Agamben. There is, in fact, good reason to suppose that we cannot begin
to understand the being of the human or of the animal unless we can first
address the relation between world and place. In that case, and contrary to
the position developed by Agamben, the open does not name that which
stands between the animal and the human, but rather the open, but
bounded, space, the place, within which an encounter between the human
and the animal is itself possible. Agamben has his own reasons, of course,
for wanting to shift the concept of the open in the way that he does, but in
so doing he shifts the discussion away from the very question that he also
opens up through the associations that he suggests between Heidegger,
von Uexküll, and the geographical tradition that includes Ratzel and Vidal
de la Blanche.
HEEDING HEIDEGGER’S WAY:
QUESTIONS OF THE WORK OF ART1
ELIZABETH M. GRIERSON
Edvard Munch and The Scream (1893) has just hit the headlines. “Outrage
at ease of Scream theft” announces yet another art heist from a public
museum. “No alarms rang as the robbers threatened a security guard with
a gun, forced people to lie down, and removed the painting, worth about
$80 million” (The New Zealand Herald, 24 August, 2004: B1). In the
report the work of art is described as “one of art’s best-known treasures”;
“one of the most instantly recognisable images in art”; one of “four
versions of The Scream which was part of a series called The Frieze of
Life”; a “howling figure”; and “the world’s most famous and most
frequently reproduced painting”. Each of these statements acts as a mode
1
This essay has been developed form an earlier version that appeared in ACCESS:
Critical Perspectives on Communication, Cultural & Policy Studies, 22 (1 & 2),
2003.
46 Heeding Heidegger’s Way: Questions of the Work of Art
2
Art historian Meyer Schapiro disputes Heidegger’s statement that the shoes
painted by Van Gogh are indeed peasant shoes. Although the shoes play a central
role in Heidegger’s arguments regarding the “equipmental being of the equipment”
as dwelling in the time of being and belonging to the earth, Schapiro wrote to
Heidegger in 1965 to point out that he (Heidegger) had overlooked Van Gogh’s
own concerns for painting the shoes as a “sacred relic” of his own life. (See
discussion in Berman, 1996). Clearly Schapiro approaches the shoes with the art
historian’s search for historical accuracy and truth to the artist’s intentions and
subjective presence, whereas Heidegger has allowed the shoes to enter the realms
of his heuristic unfolding of a philosophical argument. Two different discourses
are thus at work with the “peasant” shoes as the problematised signifier.
Elizabeth M. Grierson 55
origin of the work. The work is the origin of the artist. Neither is without
the other” (Heidegger, 1999c: 143), and circled through questions of
“Thing and Work” (Heidegger, 1999c: 146-165), “Work and Truth”
(Heidegger, 1999c: 165-182), “Truth and Art” (Heidegger, 1999c: 182-
203) (following his three lectures), ending with an Epilogue referring to
“the riddle of art” and noting that his foregoing reflections “are far from
claiming to solve the riddle. The task is to see the riddle” (Heidegger,
1999c: 204). So what sort of riddle, what sort of “disclosure” is taking
place here? For the reader there has been no easy solution, no
correspondence in questioning the question of truth. The reader has been
set to work as the truth is set to work in the work of language and thought.
What happens, in Heideggerian terms, through the work of art, as in
the writing and reading of the text, is an unconcealment of questions of
concealment, “where alëtheia, truth, happens”. The relations of reader and
viewer, writer and artist, text and image, are inflecting each other when
brought into relations through language as a way of being. For Heidegger
the work of art is neither “present-at-hand” nor “ready-to-hand” as the
entities in Being and Time. As Smeyers explains (Smyers, 2002: 82), “The
work of art is neither of these but rather an entity through which the truth
of beings is disclosed – it has a privileged relation to Being, similar only to
that accorded to Dasein”. Krell writes of Heidegger’s later thoughts on this
relation in “Building Dwelling Thinking” (1951):
To the thing as technological component and as scientific object
Heidegger opposes the thing as the place where the truth of Being,
disclosedness, happens. In the work of art such disclosedness is
compellingly experienced – perhaps most of all in the work of poetry
(Krell, 1999: 344).
with a “sickness” of the modern world with its calculative thinking and
“extinction of ‘the divine radiance’” (Young, 2002: 35). What is at stake
here? Heidegger (Heidegger, 1977a: 33) puts it this way:
The coming to presence of technology threatens revealing, threatens it
with the possibility that all revealing will be consumed in ordering and
that everything will present itself only in the unconcealedness of standing-
reserve. Human activity can never directly counter this danger. Human
achievement alone can never banish it.
at hand, indeed to stand there just so that it may be on call for a further
ordering […]. We call it the standing-reserve [Bestand]”.
So by these diagnoses man in the generalised sense is a sorry state in a
world of over-technologised “standing-reserve” which is the danger and
the destitution; and from there Heidegger proposes a “saving power” that
could be accessed through the work of art in its revealing of
spatial/temporal relations beyond its mere “object-being”. “The whole art
industry, even if carried to the extreme and exercised in every way for the
sake of works themselves, extends only to the object-being of the works.
But this does not constitute their work-being”, says Heidegger (Heidegger,
1999c: 166) as he turns to a particular work of art to show more clearly the
“work” of “disclosure”: Van Gogh’s painting of peasant shoes, which are,
according to Heidegger, “a pair of peasant shoes and nothing more. And
yet” (Heidegger, 1999c: 159).1 He then shows, by his way of working
through his text, that the painting “is the disclosure of what the equipment,
the pair of peasant shoes is in truth. This work-being emerges into the
unconcealment of beings, alëtheia” (Heidegger, 1999c: 161). In this
section of his essay he makes clear that we must not just settle for seeing
or imagining “a pair of shoes in general, or simply look at the empty,
unused shoes as they merely stand there in the picture” (Heidegger, 1999c:
159). What we are seeking to discover is “what the equipmental being of
the equipment in truth is” (ibid.). So the being, Dasein must be interpreted
in its moment of time and being as it brings the relations of time and being
into proximity as a mode of “belonging”. This has a sense of dwelling in
the time of being as a way of living in the world. “From out of this
protected belonging the equipment itself rises to its resting-within-itself”
(Heidegger, 1999c: 160).
He presents the exemplar of “the old wooden bridge” (in Heidegger,
1977a: 16; and Heidegger, 1999e: 354) spanning the river from bank to
bank, which “brings stream and bank and land into each other’s
neighbourhood” (Heidegger, 1999e: 354), as belonging in and with itself
and gathering all into earth. The bridge “dwells” thereby in the relations of
its being rather than dominating technologically as object in the landscape.
Heidegger speaks also of the relational quality of the Greek temple that
“makes visible the invisible space of air” as it “illuminates also that on
which and in which man bases his dwelling” – that is earth, “the sheltering
agent” (Heidegger, 1999c: 168). The Temple reveals a relational space of
being: “The temple-work, standing there, opens up a world and at the
same time sets this world back again on earth” (ibid.); and he takes this to
the work of art and asks, “what, then, does the work-being of the work
consist?” (Heidegger, 1999c: 169); and brings us to see a work of art that
Elizabeth M. Grierson 61
This essay has been questioning as it seeks to disclose something about the
work of art and education, something about presencing in the work-being
of work, something about being in time, in and with the world. There is
something very temporal about this discussion in the process of its writing
and reading. It appeals to no sense of transcendental hope that it will be
grabbed and disseminated as the ultimate answer for a new approach to
art, education or living. If there is a “heeding [of] Heidegger’s way” in the
process of its writing and reading, then a process of “revealing and
concealing, in which the coming to presence of truth, comes to pass”
(Heidegger, 1977a: 33) may be at work.
Heidegger said, “the work erects a world which in turn opens a space
for man and things” (Heidegger, 1999c: 141). If there is a clearing, an
opening, through which “the truth of beings has set itself to work”
(Heidegger, 1999c: 162) in the “workly” character of work, then
technology might be at work here as “no mere means” but as “a way of
revealing”. We are reminded by Heidegger (Heidegger, 1977a: 33) that,
“The coming to presence of technology threatens revealing, threatens it
with the possibility that all revealing will be consumed in ordering”. So it
would seem there is something here to heed. “If we give heed to this, then
another whole realm for the essence of technology will open itself up to
us. It is the realm of revealing, i.e., of truth” (Heidegger, 1977a: 12).
If the work-being of the work of art, and the work of writing, can open
up spaces for unconcealment of relations in the world, as a horizon of
disclosure of both the “danger” and “saving power”, then we may seek a
similar mode of unconcealment in our work of being in the world. We
62 Heeding Heidegger’s Way: Questions of the Work of Art
may set ourselves to work as the “setting forth” of being and disclosure in
the horizons of our labour.
We may thus set ourselves to work as a work of art in Heidegger’s
sense. In art, as in education, we may then open spaces “not to listen to a
series of propositions but rather to follow the movement of showing”
(Heidegger, On Time and Being, 1972). Then we might find a way to
dismantle the pre-suppositions embedded in our metaphysicality of
thinking, being and doing in Western frames of knowing the world. Rather
than the Enframing of such correspondences in the world of work and
living, we might heed Heidegger’s way of throwing light upon the
fundamental limitations of subject-object separations as a way of being in
and with the world. Then, hearing Heidegger, we might set ourselves to
work in such a way that exposes those limits and “in the sense of poiësis,
lets what presences come forth into appearance” (Heidegger, 1977a: 27).
And here lies the project of this discussion, to “pay heed to the way” as a
“way of thinking” (Heidegger, 1977a: 3), and to reveal something of “the
constellation of truth after which we are questioning” (Heidegger, 1977a:
35) in the time of poiësis in our work-being.
Bibliography
Berman, 1996
M. Berman, M, "Meyer Schapiro: The presence of the subject", New
Politics, 5 (4) (new series), whole no. 20. Retrieved March 31, 2007,
from the World Wide Web:
< http://www.wpunj.edu/newpol/issue20/berman20.htm>
Bischoff, 1990
U. Bischoff, Edvard Munch, 1863-1944. Köln: Benedikt Taschen.
Dickie, 1997
G. Dickie, Introduction to Aesthetics: An Analytic Approach. Oxford:
OUP.
Grierson, 2000
E. M. Grierson, The Politics of Knowledge: A Poststructuralist
Approach to Visual Arts Education in Tertiary Sites. Unpublished
Doctor of Philosophy thesis, University of Auckland, Auckland.
Heidegger, 1972
M. Heidegger, On Time and Being. Trans. J. Stambaugh. New York:
Harper Colophon Books.
Heidegger, 1973
M. Heidegger, "Metaphysics as History of Being". In The End of
Philosophy, trans. J. Stambaugh: 1-54. New York: Harper & Row.
Elizabeth M. Grierson 63
Heidegger, 1977a
M. Heidegger, "The Question Concerning Technology". In The
Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William
Lovitt: 3-35. New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, 1977b
M. Heidegger, "The Age of the World Picture". In The Question
Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt: 115-
154. New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, 1991
M. Heidegger, Nietzsche, Vols. I & II. Trans. David Krell. San
Francisco: Harper & Collins.
Heidegger, 1999a
M. Heidegger, Ontology: The Hermeneutics of Facticity. Lecture
Course from the Summer Semester of 1923. Trans. John van Buren.
Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1999b
M. Heidegger, "On the Essence of Truth". In Basic Writings, ed. David
Krell: 111-138. London: Routledge.
Heidegger, 1999c
M. Heidegger, "The Origin of the Work of Art". In Basic Writings, ed.
David Krell: 139-212. London: Routledge.
Heidegger, 1999d
M. Heidegger, "Modern Science, Metaphysics, and Mathematics". In
Basic Writings, ed. David Krell: 267-305. London: Routledge.
Heidegger, 1999e
M. Heidegger, "Building Dwelling Thinking". In Basic Writings, ed.
David Krell: 343-363. London: Routledge.
Krell, 1999
D. Krell, "General Introduction. The Question of Being". In Basic
Writings, ed. David Krell: 1-35. London: Routledge.
Lovitt, 1977
W. Lovitt, "Introduction". In The Question Concerning Technology
and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt: xiii-xxxiv. New York: Harper
& Row.
Roberts, 1966
D. Roberts, Existentialism and Religious Belief, ed. Roger Hazelton.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Smeyers, 2002
P. Smeyers, "The Origin: Education, Philosophy, and a Work of Art".
In Heidegger, Education, and Modernity, ed. Michael Peters: 81-101.
Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
64 Heeding Heidegger’s Way: Questions of the Work of Art
PETER MURPHY
I.
The Greeks were the first historical people. At least Heidegger thought
so. They were the first to create themselves in time, the first to break the
rule of the habitual, the first to be original. The title of Heidegger’s 1935
lecture on “The Origin of the Work of Art” sums up in three words—
origin, work and art—the emergence of an historical people.1 The “work”
of the work of art is to open up a world. The “origin” of the work of art is
the beginning, the advent in time, of such a world. This emergence in time
is historical. “Art’s” work is to create a world historical people.
The first historical people, the Greeks, were the beginning of all
beginnings. Their beginning lay in the art of the Greek temple. This art
work opened up a “world” (Heidegger, 1971: 41-43). This act of world
creation was both an act of art and an act of nature. This aesthetic nature
was the self-generating creating coming forth of things for the first time.
“The Greeks”, Heidegger muses, “called this emerging and rising in itself
and in all things phusis” (Heidegger, 1971: 42).
As we’ll see, this is both true and untrue. But, for the moment, let us
just continue to follow Heidegger along.
“To be a work means to set up a world” (Heidegger, 1971: 44). To set
up means to open up. To open up means to “to come forth for the very first
time” (Heidegger, 1971: 46). The work of art opens a world by bringing
forth all the fundamental distinctions of things—the remoteness and
nearness, the scope and limits, of things. The rockiness of rocks, the
glimmer of metals, the spaciousness of space, the colour of things—in
short, the qualities of things, the self-subsistence of things, their is-ness,
their being, originates when art opens a world. All of this comes forth
1
See “The Origin of the Art of Work” in Heidegger, 1971.
66 The Pitch Black Night of Human Creation: Calling Heidegger’s
Philosophy of Terror to Account
enemies are friends and friends are enemies. When Heidegger asks Pilate’s
cynical question—“what is truth?”—he answers it simply enough: truth is
untruth (Heidegger, 1971: 60). Openness is concealment. That is simple
enough. But how does Heidegger get to that point?
Well, Heidegger says, the Greek word for truth, alƝtheia, means the
unconcealedness of being (Heidegger 1971: 36, 51, 59). For the present,
let us not worry that it means nothing of the kind. Greek truth, alƝtheia,
was not revelation but the overcoming of oblivion. Truth was the
antipodes of the mythical Hades and its river of Lethe, the source of
deadly sleep. Greek truth negated the negation of the lethal soma because
it stood aside, apart, from the birth and death of things in time. Greek truth
signified what was imperishable or immortal.
Still, we should not argue about this, not yet anyway. Let us for the
moment simply accept Heidegger’s declaration at face value: Truth is un-
concealment. So how then can truth also be concealment?
The sting in the tail, Heidegger declares—and Heidegger is a master of
declaration—is that un-concealment was, for thought, the most concealed
thing in Greek existence. The middle term of this conundrum was art. The
work of art—which originates worlds, bringing them forth by opening
them up—manages in this act of un-concealment to bring forth
concealment. To explain this, Heidegger draws an analogy. Un-
concealment is like a clearing in the midst of being. Thanks to this
clearing, beings are revealed. But this has the effect that beings are
concealed as well. Heidegger notes, and quite reasonably so, that
everything we encounter, every presence we meet, always withholds itself
(Heidegger, 1971: 53). This is the “curious opposition” of presence. Every
time a being opens up, it also hides, obscures and conceals itself. It
conceals, it denies, it dissembles (Heidegger, 1971: 54-55). Truth is
untruth.
There is something in this. Revelation is not pretty. When we insist on
the truth, when we demand that someone “tell me the truth”, we often
expect the worst. We expect something bad—sometimes something
terrible—to be revealed. “Truth time” exposes bad things. We hide bad
things. Truth exposes what has been hidden.
II.
Enough, for the moment, about truth—what about art? Art is a work
that brings forth a world. The work is the bringing forth. Bringing forth is
creation (Heidegger, 1971: 58). That which is created is the being that
grows out of its own nature by its own accord. Creation is phusis—that
68 The Pitch Black Night of Human Creation: Calling Heidegger’s
Philosophy of Terror to Account
III.
In all of this, there are some things to agree with Heidegger. Yes, art is
world making. Yes, acts of creation are paradoxical. Yes, there are a
handful of societies that have managed to install paradox at their heart.
Yes, the ancient Greeks and the Modern European West would be
included in this cluster. It is doubtful, however, if the Middle Ages would
make the grade—and, even if Heidegger would protest it, Rome and
America also belong in this cohort, possibly Japan as well. All of these are
societies driven by deep, deep paradoxes, sometimes almost unfathomable
70 The Pitch Black Night of Human Creation: Calling Heidegger’s
Philosophy of Terror to Account
paradoxes, and all them thus capable of acts of world making not seen, and
more to the point not possible, in other less ambidextrous societies.
But, as for Heidegger’s account of creation, I’d take issue with that in
almost every aspect. What Heidegger offers is a philosophy of “creation
out of nothing”. The beginning that interrupts history, which starts and re-
starts it yet without repeating it, is a disclosure of Nothing. Creation brings
forth the something that is nothing, or the nothing that is something. I
happily accept that this is not per se nonsensical or rather it is a non-sense
that makes sense. Creation and creativity rely on the force of paradox. This
force might be thought of as the engine of creation. Paradox is essential to
the nature or phusis of creation. What is at issue is not this generality, but
rather the specific creationist paradox of the “creation of something out of
nothing”—the creation of determinations out of indetermination.
To see where the creationist paradox leads Heidegger, let us turn our
attention to the lecture series that he gave in the winter semester of 1941
(Heidegger, 1993). There, in those lectures, we begin to see clearly the
menace of the idea of creation out of nothing, and the ominous
implications of creation forged in the battle of the unfamiliar with the
familiar amidst the strife of truth at war with itself.
This is the battle of a truth that is untruthful. It is war and, in war,
warriors deceive. They survive on cunning and ruse. So creation out of
nothing in the first instance is the hiding of truth that begins things by the
un-concealing of them. Un-concealment, alƝtheia—that which for the
Greeks had been the overcoming of the oblivion of death of the river lethe,
the a-lethal act—in Heidegger’s account hides the truth. Hiding the truth,
lying, is the work of art. It reveals first by hiding a (dreadful) truth—the
truth of obliteration that is the essence of Being. To this end Heidegger
invokes Nietzsche: “One who tells the truth ends by realizing that he
always lies” (Heidegger, 1991: 215). Thus “we have art so that we do not
perish from the truth” (Heidegger, 1991: 216). “We need the lie in order
that we achieve victory over this reality […] in order to live” (Heidegger,
1991: 217). Still rehearsing Nietzsche, Heidegger says of art: it is the will
to semblance. It is illusion, deception, and untruth. Art lies. The art of war
is the art of lying. The lie of Nietzsche’s artist, however, is not just
strategic in nature. Its rationale is not just to attain victory over the enemy.
More fundamentally the lie hides what is shocking, namely the works of
lethe. It shelters us from the experience of its horror. It shields us from
seeing what is dreadful. The lie is necessary so that we do not look into the
abyss. We cannot cope with the unimaginable concealed in the abyss.
Heidegger, though, is not Nietzsche. For just as much as Heidegger
admits to the power of the aesthetic lie, he also doesn’t (really) believe in
Peter Murphy 71
2
This comes from Heidegger’s 1942 lectures on Hölderlin’s Hymn “The Ister”.
The translation is taken not from the standard English language translation,
Heidegger (1996), but from Ward (Ward, 1995: 192).
72 The Pitch Black Night of Human Creation: Calling Heidegger’s
Philosophy of Terror to Account
its homely self in the drive for what is in-habitual and extra-ordinary. The
“un” is not just a negation but an overpowering of things. This
overpowering, this uncanny power, towers above humanity, revealing
itself in horror and terror. In order to create, this power must annihilate.
IV.
In works of fiction, horror is left to the imagination. In the works of
uncanny bestiality, however, the horror is unimaginable. It can be
prosaically reported and meticulously recorded but the imagination is
repelled by it. Take for instance the recorded works of that attentive
student of Hitler and Stalin, the Baath Party leader and psychopath
Saddam Hussein. Even professionals collecting evidence on Saddam’s
torturers find the videos of their deeds almost impossible to watch.3 To
watch means having to imagine unimaginable horror. It means having to
imagine the endless repetition of such horror. The human mind flinches
and turns away from such thoughts. The imagination shudders, in
revulsion, as the video clip:
opens amid Saddam’s elite troops, Saddam Fedayeen, chanting ‘With
blood and spirit we will redeem you Saddam.’ The Fedayeen stand barking
and clapping in a courtyard. A blindfolded prisoner, forced to his knees
and held in position, has his arm outstretched before him along a low
concrete wall. A masked member of the Fedayeen raises high a three-foot-
long blade and ferociously slams down on the man’s hand, slicing through
his fingertips. The victim is wailing, screaming in agony. The swordsman-
torturer, not sufficiently satisfied with his first effort, raises the sword
again and drives down once more on the man’s immobile hand. This time
he severs the fingers closer to the knuckles as the blood spurts from his
hand spilling over and down the concrete slab. The victim emits a wail I
have never heard—could never imagine hearing—from a grown man, this
time louder, harder than the first (Shawcross, 2005).
3
The following is drawn from the account by the great reporter and broadcaster,
William Shawcross (2005). The quotes are from the documentary producer Nick
Schulz who recounts how he was “unable to sit through these clips at first, having
to turn away several times[...]”.
74 The Pitch Black Night of Human Creation: Calling Heidegger’s
Philosophy of Terror to Account
In the works of the unimaginable, when deeds such as this are repeated an
incalculable numbers of times, there is an unmistakable strain of social
necrophilia. When the power of the unimaginable became explicit, for the
first time, in the Terror of the French Revolution, death is transformed in
status from a violent political means to a necrotic social end. Death’s
works are enacted on an all-consuming social scale.
The germ of this necrotic strain threaded its way for centuries through
the Faustian art-culture and art-religion of the European West. It mutated
from the Gothic era via the Baroque to Romanticism. But it is not until the
French Revolution that the threshold between grisly imagination and the
unimaginable is finally crossed over. What made the difference? Most
crucially, the all-devouring overpowering of state and society found a
justification—in the act of creation.
As Heidegger later put it, creation cannot abide structure and order,
statute and limit because creators must create all of this. The radicalism of
Heidegger is evident when he quotes from a letter that Hölderlin wrote to
his brother (Heidegger, 1993: 62). Hölderlin puzzles about whether the
assault of Nothing on society and humankind should be opposed?
Heidegger’s answer to this question is a mocking rhetorical counter-
question. What if the Nothing that horrifies man and displaces him from
his usual dallying and evasions were the same as Being? If this was the
case, Heidegger reasons, then Being would have to announce itself as
something horrifying and dreadful. For anything else is an avoidance of
Being. There is no doubt that Heidegger thinks that the time has come for
this announcement. It is too late for any more equivocation.
So no wonder that disclosure, un-concealment and truth function to
hide, cover up and conceal something dreadful. This is the secret of
nihilation that ordinary humanity, sensibly, evades. To be shaken from this
Peter Murphy 75
4
That Heidegger’s philosophy should have become a court philosophy for Iran’s
theocratic state should not surprise us. The messianic death fixation of that regime,
which sacrificed hundreds of thousands of its subjects in the apocalyptic primitive
slaughter of the Iraq-Iran War, has uncanny parallels with Germany in the 1930s.
When Jurgen Habermas made his 2002 sojourn to Iran, he observed: “During the
1990s, Martin Heidegger and Karl Popper provided the key terminology for a
debate between Reza Davari Ardakani on the one side and Abdolkarim Sorush on
the other. Davari is now president of the Academy of Sciences and classed with the
‘postmodernists’. The latter were particularly drawn to the analysis of the ‘nature
of technology’ in Heidegger’s later writings and linked it to the Iranian critique of
Western modernity. Sorush, meanwhile, who is currently spending a semester as
guest lecturer at Harvard, personally tends toward a mystical branch of Islam, but,
as a Popperian, is a resolute adherent of a cognitive division of labor between
religion and science. If I understood it correctly, during this dispute Davari rose to
the status of philosophical spokesman of the Shiite orthodoxy, while Sorush
76 The Pitch Black Night of Human Creation: Calling Heidegger’s
Philosophy of Terror to Account
V.
The refrain of those who march to the tune of “evil but not immoral” is
that what begins, ends, and what ends, begins. In both cases, the end is
annihilation and only the time of destruction can give birth to worlds.
Time casts a deep shadow across the body of Heidegger’s philosophy. The
conjugation of “being and time” is the most powerful leitmotif of his
work. Historical time is the midwife of precocious acts of creation. These
acts are undetermined. Nothing, nihil, “causes” them. They are
unmediated. These miraculous beginnings in time are preceded by nothing
and are destined to expire in nothing. Nothing is the emptiness that is
filled up with the pure difference of “un”. Time creates through “un”-
doing. The “un”-doings of historical time precede and postdate creation.
The constant alteration of time’s “un”-doings is the only constant left us. It
is the only (ironic) trace of the metaphysical.
Heidegger repeatedly and insistently attributes creation, creation out of
nothing and into nothing, to the Greeks. But Greek nature or phusis, the
coming forth or originating of something out of itself, was not ever, and
could not ever be, creation out of nothing. The notion of an emergence out
of nothing is shaped by the theistic creation mythology of the Middle East.
It underpins the biblical account of genesis. The Greeks had no interest in
genesis thinking. For the Greeks, phusis implied durable, imperishable
form. Creation, which was usually understood as a kind of making,
occurred when the material stuff of self, society and nature was molded by
form, reason or spirit. From the Pre-Socratics through Plato, Aristotle, the
Stoics and the Epicureans, there were lively arguments about the nature of
this nature. But mostly it was agreed that phusis was a kind of self-
propelling morphology. Whatever was said in these debates, no one ever
equated the morphology of form, reason or spirit with nothing—whether
this was the nothing of birth or the nothing of extinction.
Heidegger understood the morphological nature of Greek phusis
perfectly well. In the first volume of his Nietzsche lectures, he gives a very
fine account of Platonism (Heidegger, 1991: 162-199). He describes how
the Greek phusis brings forth form or morphe, the limit or the boundary,
the configuration of a being. He also describes how one’s delight in art
arises from logical, mathematical feelings—from the feeling for letting
one’s mood be determined by order, boundary and overview. Yet, for
Heidegger, the lure of destruction, change and becoming, or rather their
Bibliography
Carroll, 2001
J. Carroll, The Western Dreaming: The Western World Is Dying For
Want Of A Story. Sydney: HarperCollins.
Habermas, 2002
J. Habermas, “The Unrest is Growing: Habermas in Iran Interview
with Juergen Habermas on his visit to Iran”, Public Theology, reprinted
from the June 18, 2002 issue of Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung at:
http://www.pubtheo.com/page.asp?pid=1073 Accessed June 2006.
Heidegger, 1971
M. Heidegger, Poetry, Language and Thought. New York: Harper and
Row.
Heidegger, 1991
Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche, vol. 1. San Francisco: Harper.
Heidegger, 1993
M. Heidegger, Basic Concepts. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana
University Press.
Heidegger, 1996
M. Heidegger, Hölderlin’s Hymn “The Ister”. Trans. William McNeill
and Julia Davis. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Murphy and Roberts, 2004
P. Murphy and D. Roberts, Dialectic of Romanticism. London:
Continuum.
Shawcross, 2005
W. Shawcross, “Saddam Removal: Why the U.S. had no alternative”,
The American Spectator, September 2005, reprinted at:
http://www.williamshawcross.com/
Ward, 1995
J. F. Ward, Heidegger’s Political Thinking. Amherst: University of
Massachusetts Press.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER AND THE PHILOSOPHY
OF NEGATIVITY
PAOLO BARTOLONI
1.
The reflection on language as “the house of Being” permeates Heidegger’s
work from “Letter on Humanism” [1946] (1993) onwards. Heidegger
returns insistently to this reflection, especially with regard to poetic
language, and the affinities between poetic language and thinking.
Heidegger is said to believe that philosophy does not begin with thought,
but with astonishment, surprise, errancy (Safranski, 1998: 1); in a word,
with poetry. And in fact, the entrance into philosophy through poetry
gradually becomes Heidegger’s favourite route to thinking and for
thinking. It is no accident, then, that his attention and investigation of
poetry increase dramatically from the mid 1930s, especially from the
1934-1935 lectures on Hölderlin’s hymns to Germany and the Rhein
(1980). It is in the poetry of Hölderlin first, and later in that of Rilke,
George and Trakl that Heidegger looks for that unique trigger to his
thought. It does not come as a surprise either if, in the same period, also
known as Kehre, Heidegger’s dealings with pre-Socratic thought,
especially Parmenides, Heraclitus, Anaximander, assume the character of
poetic readings. It is also perhaps because of Heidegger’s penchant for
poetry – and of course, because of his “poetic” style of philosophising –
that some commentators have labelled him, and not always favourably, a
poet rather than a philosopher (Megill, 1985; Gottlieb, 1990).
In the collection of lectures/essays delivered in 1957-1958 and brought
under the title of On the Way to language (Unterwegs zur Sprache) we
find a text which is of particular interest in the discussion of the relation
between poetry and thinking. I am referring to “Words” (Das Wort). This
lecture is a close reading of a poem by Stefan George, “The Word” (Das
Wort). It is also a further attempt on the part of Heidegger to think the
80 Martin Heidegger and the Philosophy of Negativity
2.
And, in fact, this is not the place. If one looks at the German edition of
Unterwegs zur Sprache (1975), one soon realizes that Das Wort is
preceded by Das Wesen der Sprache (“The Nature of Language”) and
followed by Der Weg zur Sprache (“On the Way to Language”). This is
the original order of the three lectures, which has been radically altered in
the English translation for reasons that one can only speculate about. Was
it perhaps thought that “The Nature of Language” and “Words” were too
similar, the latter being almost a repetition of the former? Would perhaps
the reader in English object less to the book, should the uncanny
similarities between “the Nature” and “Words” be mitigated by
interspersing them with “On the Way”?
In “The Nature of Language” Heidegger sets the tone for the three
lectures on language, which he considers as individual parts of a whole. In
“The Nature of Language” he expressly says that the purpose of these
lectures is to “undergo an experience with language” (Heidegger, 1982:
57) which might be “helpful to us to rid ourselves of the habit of always
hearing only what we already understand” (Heidegger, 1982: 58).
Heidegger wishes to experience, and perhaps write, a language, whose
relation with him is different from the one he has with traditional – one
might be tempted to say metaphysical – language. In other words,
Heidegger intends to experience a meeting with a language which,
remaining the same, says things differently. It is in this sense that the
preposition “a” before language is strictly incorrect. This is not another
language, it is instead the same language that relates to us, and us to it,
differently. Heidegger explains this further: “In experiences which we
undergo with language, language itself brings itself to language. One
would think that this happens anyway, any time anyone speaks. Yet at
whatever time and in whatever way we speak a language, language itself
never has the floor” (Heidegger, 1982: 59).
As we now see, in Heidegger’s terminology “a language” is not
language. Language is that which speaks “itself as language”. When does
this happen? “Curiously enough”, answers Heidegger, “when we cannot
82 Martin Heidegger and the Philosophy of Negativity
find the right word for something that concerns us, carries us away,
oppresses or encourages us” (ibid.).
As an example of the coming of language to itself, Heidegger
discusses Stefan George’s poem Das Wort, whose final line reads: “Where
words breaks off no thing may be.” What is at stake here is precisely what
Heidegger draws attention to when he refers to the breaking of words in
the face of “something that concerns us”.
This is the place from where Heidegger can continue his analysis of
George’s poem, together with his investigation of thinking and poetry. As
Heidegger tells us, Stefan George first published “Words” “in the 11th and
12th series of “Blatter fur die Kunst” in 1919”. (Heidegger, 1982: 140) He
later included it “in the last volume of poems published in his life-time,
called Das Neue Reich (ibid.).
George’s poem is about the poetic journey, and the experience of
confronting the mystery of life, in the hope of giving this mystery
concreteness through language. But this hope is destined to remain
unfulfilled since not even the depth of poetry, its magic and inspiration,
can say the unsayable. So while the poet holds the mystery in his hands,
waiting for poetic language to transform the mystery into the reality of a
presence, the mystery slips away, as the poet learns that there is no word
that can “enfold these depths.” The last two stanzas read: “And Straight it
vanished from my hand,/ The treasure never graced my land…/ I then
sadly learned renunciation:/ Where word breaks off no thing may be (So
lernt ich traurig den verzicht:/ Kein ding sei wo das wort gebricht).”
Heidegger’s investigation focuses on the last two lines, and especially
on the notion of renunciation (verzicht). The question and the
philosophical problem that Heidegger engages with is whether this
renunciation simply leaves the poet empty handed, and sadly melancholic
in the face of negativity and emptiness.
What takes place in the following pages is a great feat of rhetorical and
philosophical bravura through which Heidegger turns the notion of
renunciation from negative into positive. This reversal of fortune might
not say very much about George’s poem, but may say a great deal about
Heidegger’s philosophy and its insights into ontology. In other words,
while the connection between philosophy and literature remains here
ambiguous and not totally convincing, the conclusions at which Heidegger
arrives are striking and of outmost importance, especially in relation to a
philosophical trend characterising the second half of the twentieth century,
including the work of Blanchot and Agamben.
Paolo Bartoloni 83
3.
One might wish that Heidegger had chosen a more consonant poem for his
discussion. One that comes straight to mind is the “Buried Harbour” by
Italian poet Giuseppe Ungaretti. This poem was written in 1916, only
three years before George’s Das Wort. It reads: “The poet goes there/ then
returns to the light with his songs/ and scatters then/ Of this poetry there
remains to me/ that nothing/ of inexhaustible secrecy” (Ungaretti, 1990:
26). George’s and Ungaretti’s poems are similar. They both present a
journey into other lands from which the poet returns with precious
treasures which, however, soon turn into nothingness. And yet the
nothingness in Ungaretti “remains” present as “inexhaustible secrecy”.
Heidegger would very likely equate this secrecy with a near remoteness.
But let us quote Heidegger on this very crucial point. “As a mystery,” he
writes glossing George’s poem, “the word remains remote. As a mystery
that is experienced, the remoteness is near. The perdurance of this
remoteness of such nearness is the nondenial of self to the word’s
mystery. There is no word for this mystery, that is, no Saying which could
bring the being of language to language” (Heidegger, 1982: 154).
And yet the mystery is not gone, is not negative. It is rather present
through its withdrawing. It remains located in the space between poetry
and thinking; and from where we are we can try to listen to it by thinking
with poetry and through poetry. I have just paraphrased the last paragraph
of Heidegger’s lecture Das Wort, which reads: “In order that we may in
our thinking fittingly follow and lead this element worthy of thought as it
gives itself to poetry, we abandon everything which we have now said to
oblivion. We listen to the poem. We grow still more thoughtful now
regarding the possibility that the more simply the poem sings in the mod
of song, the more readily our hearing may err” (Heidegger, 1982: 156).
Besides, “singing” and “songs”, these two concepts so central to
Heidegger’s discussion of George’s Das Wort, are also vital to Ungaretti’s
“The Buried Harbour”. Let us remember that in Ungaretti the poet returns
to light with his “songs” (canti).
For Heidegger it is not, however, a matter of choosing the right poem
since he is not interested in engaging with a process of exegesis, whose
aim is to illustrate and elucidate the meanings of a given poem. Rather,
Heidegger is interested in using the poem as the preferred path to an
experience with language. Strictly speaking, he is not so much reading the
poem as listening to it.
Heidegger’s interpretations of Hölderlin, George, Rilke, Trakl are not
literary interpretations in the conventional sense of the word. There is not
84 Martin Heidegger and the Philosophy of Negativity
4.
But how is it that “renunciation” becomes positive, and therefore
ontologically relevant and consubstantial to Heidegger’s mode of
thinking? The key to this question must be looked for in the verb that
accompanies renunciation in George’s poem: “to learn” (So lernt ich
traurig den verzicht). According to Heidegger the poet in Das Wort is not
simply renouncing, he has learned renunciation (Heidegger, 1982: 143).
To Heidegger the difference between “renounciation” and “learning
renunciation” is of paramount importance. To him learning means “to
become knowing” (ibid.), that is, to enter a process of active engagement
with thinking, and, in this particular case, with language. This process
Heidegger equates with a journey, and with a movement of discovery. The
subject places himself underway through the action of learning. But what
is it that the poet learns? He learns renunciation. For Heidegger, this
renunciation translates into the active affirmation of the predisposition to
experience language as language. While it is true that the thing remains
unsaid, it is also true that it remains close to language, adhering to
language unsaying. Heidegger’s punch line comes a little later in the essay
when, as already discussed, he argues that language’s Saying resides
precisely in its non-saying:
Because this renunciation is a genuine renunciation, not just a rejection of
Saying, not a mere lapse into silence. As self-denial, renunciation remains
Saying. It thus preserves the relation to the word. But because the word is
shown in a different, higher rule, the relation to the word must undergo a
transformation. Saying attains to a different articulation, a different melos,
a different tone. The poem itself, which tells of renunciation, bears witness
to the fact that the poet’s renunciation is experienced in this sense – by
singing of renunciation (Heidegger, 1982: 147).
5.
This is, as Gianni Vattimo has argued, the Heidegger who has been
interpreted as the philosopher who experiences Being by withdrawing
Being – as opposed to the Heidegger who chases Being in order to
reconnect with it (Vattimo: 1994).
But exactly what is this renunciation; is it the romantic celebration of
losing oneself in contemplation? It might very well sound like a mystical
experience in which, paraphrasing a romantic Italian poet, Giacomo
Leopardi, the shipwrecking of the subject in the mystery of life becomes
sweet. And yet in Heidegger this sweetness is not so much romantic as
phenomeno-ontological. As early as the beginning of the 1920s, at the
time when he was considered the “child of phenomenology”, Heidegger
was lecturing about the need to place oneself before the world (Heidegger,
1987: 113), which meant to resist, and indeed abolish, reified and
culturally institutionalised attitudes to things. He preached the
philosophical significance of looking at things as such in order to regain
them to their “worldiness” (Heidegger, 1987: 71-72). In the lecture Das
Wort, Heidegger uses a similar term, “bethinging” (die Bedingnis), which
becomes the higher rule of the word “which first lets a thing be as thing.”
(Heidegger, 1982: 151) In reality Heidegger never let his
phenomenological education to wander too far off from him.
Renunciation, suspension, destruction and errancy will recur again and
again throughout Heidegger’s work with the same meaning, that is,
opening oneself, unconcealing oneself to a higher experience of the world.
It is in this sense, for instance, that the philosophical potency of
destruction in What is Philosophy [1956] (1963), resembles the discussion
of renunciation: “Destruction does not mean destroying, but dismantling,
putting to one side the merely historical assertions about the history of
philosophy. Destruction means – to open our ears, to make ourselves free
for what speaks to us in tradition as the Being of being. By listening to this
interpellation we attain the correspondence” (Heidegger, 1963: 73).
While here destruction initiates a correspondence with the origin of
philosophy, in Das Wort renunciation introduces a correspondence with
86 Martin Heidegger and the Philosophy of Negativity
6.
Those who follow Heidegger and interpret and study his work have long
been dealing with this indeterminacy in the attempt to bring it to fruition.
Again, it useful here to remember Vattimo’s distinction between the
interpretations of Heidegger from the left and those from the right.
Vattimo places himself on the left, especially if one considers the
significant philosophical project known as pensiero debole (weak
thought). In pensiero debole Vattimo investigates the affirmative and
potentially constructive elements of what has also been termed the
negative existentialism of Heidegger.
Another Italian philosopher on the “left” of Heidegger is Giorgio
Agamben. Agamben’s articulation of biopolitcs is informed by ontological
and aesthetic issues which can be traced back to Heidegger’s discussion of
potentiality as the renunciation or suspension of Being. As we now know
this renunciation does not give Being up, it rather clings to Being by
thinking of a higher ontological event.
Paolo Bartoloni 87
7.
In those lectures Heidegger states his concept of the open in relation to
and against Rilke’s poetisation of it in the eight Duino Elegy. For
Heidegger, Man is in the open – which also means face to face with Being
– when Man frees himself from reified and constructed possibilities in
order to come closer to the original possibility, which in this renunciation
remains near despite its spatial and temporal remoteness. Boredom, argues
Heidegger, is one instance in which this experience might take place. In
those instances, that is, in which life loses its conventionality and opens
itself to a possibility of worldiness, and life as such. Agamben adheres
closely to Heidegger’s open, locating the area of indeterminacy between
humans and animals in the space of boredom. Agamben also calls this
space the zone of désœuvrement (unemployment/worklessness),
borrowing a term coined by Maurice Blanchot. In other words, Agamben
appears to use two affirmative philosophical processes, Heidegger’s and
Blanchot’s – we will come to Blanchot’s work shortly – to describe an
event of great vulnerability and danger.
Things, however, are not really that simple. At the end of The Open
this event of indeterminacy is cited as a possible alternative to the aporia
Paolo Bartoloni 89
8.
It is hard to conceptualise, let alone imagine, what kind of society this
might be. The problem is compounded by Agamben’s conspicuous silence
on this matter. He might retort that the task of philosophy is not so much
that of giving answers as that of generating questions. And yet this
philosophical stance – which again resembles very much the one taken by
Heidegger – leaves Agamben’s philosophy vulnerable to similar criticism
as those articulated with regard to Heidegger’s. Let us take for instance
the intelligent and balanced book, Heidegger’s Estrangements: Language,
Truth, and Poetry in the Later Writing, by Gerald Bruns. Towards the end
of Bruns’ book we find this comment, which is also a methodological
reservation, that might be easily extracted to describe Agamben’s work:
The folly of trying to follow closely Heidegger’s thinking […] comes out
very forcefully when you try to stop, because there is no natural stopping
place, no place of arrival where everything falls into place and you can
say, ‘Well now that’s done: and I’m glad it’s over.’ Instead, the movement
you get into is that of going back over what has been said in order to pick
up on what is missing or what has been left out of account. So you are
always starting over with something familiar, and then going astray as you
try to finish or complete what you think you have in hand. This is why,
after a while, repetition and confusion are likely to appear the distinctive
features of anything you have to say about Heidegger (Bruns, 1989: 174).
9.
In Blanchot désœuvrement is synonymous with renunciation. This is
certainly the way in which Agamben appears to understand it. Blanchot’s
worklessness is at once action and no-action. Its emergence decrees an
insubordination, a stop a “suspension” in which “society falls apart
completely. The law collapses: for an instant there is innocence; history is
interrupted” (Holland, 1995: 250). The similarities between Agamben and
Blanchot are obvious, as obvious is the way they have arrived at this
postulation by following Heidegger beyond Heidegger. The stop Blanchot
refers to is something that must be learned and enacted deliberately.
Should this action which refuses action be embraced by the community,
then the law will collapse and history (the anthropological machine) will
grind to a halt. Innocence, for which one could very well replaced
nakedness, will emerge and triumph.
The 1960s, and also a section of the Italian operaismo in the
1960s/1970s were an explicit attempt to bring about a dramatic change in
society by way of renouncing accepted values and norms. While
innocence was at the core of the hippy movement, insubordination as
political and social struggle was the driving force of theoretical and
practical activism in Italy. Let us think for instance of the writing of Mario
Tronti and Antonio Negri in the 1960/1970s. Their idea of politics was
nothing other than a politics of withdrawal. On this point is worth quoting
at length from an essay by Brett Neilson:
The fundamental move of these Marxist intellectuals whose work
provided the theoretical backbone for a whole generation of protest
movements in Italy, was to reverse the classical relationship between
labour and capital. By arguing that capital is essentially a social power
that requires productive labour, and which evolves through a series of
attempts to control or co-opt workers, they introduced the notion that the
withdrawal of labour and/or refusal to collaborate with capital in the
organization of labour (e.g., by making demands that could not be
possibly be met) would function to destroy the capitalist system. And, in
so doing, they invented a new form of politics that considered the denial
of action or, as Tronti (1966) famously called it, “the strategy of refusal.”
(2006: 131-132).
Paolo Bartoloni 91
10.
In The Writing of the Disaster [1980] (1986) Blanchot distinguishes
between two types of refusal or renunciation. The first he calls a deliberate
and voluntary refusal, which “expresses a decision”. This refusal,
according to Blanchot, “does not yet allow separation from the power of
consciousness” (Blanchot, 1986: 17). Next to this conscious refusal
Blanchot speaks of a refusal “which is not so much a denial as, more than
that, an abdication” (ibid.). The ultimate example of this latter refusal is
Bartleby. Blanchot states that Bartleby’s abdication is in reality a
“relinquishment of identity” (ibid.), leading to a loss of being and thought.
With Bartleby, intimates Blanchot, “we have fallen out of being, outside
where, immobile, proceeding with a slow and even step, destroyed men
come and go” (ibid.).
Blanchot’s distinction is of considerable significance. Firstly it tells us
that renunciation can be either positive affirmation (an example of which
might be operaismo) or passive nakedness (Bartleby). Secondly, it appears
to announce a problem that might very well be the central one engaging
Agamben’s thought; that is, renunciation as consciousness and
renunciation as nakedness. While in the first instance renunciation works
within the context and the framework of the status quo in order to subvert
it, in the second one renunciation abdicates, insubordinate, yet deferent to
the status quo. It is in this sense that the act of conscious renunciation
might destabilize society and history (the anthropological machine), and
yet retain it as its guiding principle. The other possibility (Bartleby), is
abdication as the bringing forward of an existence without being, whose
individual sacrifice might be born out only at the level of the individual,
like in the case of Bartleby and his employer.
Clearly, Agamben operates within a different contextual framework.
He is aware that acts of conscious renunciation, as those experienced in
92 Martin Heidegger and the Philosophy of Negativity
the 1960s and the 1970s, are improbable in today’s society, given the deep
structural and technological changes undergone in the last thirty years.
Abdication of life, the other side of the coin, is precisely what Agamben
regards as the extreme danger of contemporary societies, and the very
cause for the implementation and success of the state of exception.
What is left to think is a nakedness that does not abdicate, but which,
through a suspension of history, introduces not so much, and not only a
political struggle, as an ethical and philosophical turn the outcome of
which might as well fall into a mystical and messianic heap or into
constructive ethical practices, as, for instance, those announced by Gianni
Vattimo in his essay “Heidegger and the Philosophy of Emancipation”.
Bibliography
Agamben, 2005
Giorgio Agamben, State of Exception. Trans. Kevin Attell. Chicago:
Chicago University Press.
Agamben, 2004
Giorgio Agamben, The Open: Man and Animal. Trans. Kevin Attell.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Agamben, 1999
Giorgio Agamben, “Bartleby, or on Contingency”. In Potentialities:
Collected Essays in Philosophy. Trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen: 243-
271. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Agamben, 1998
Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer. Ed. and trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Agamben, 1993
Giorgio Agamben, The Coming Community. Trans. Michael Hardt.
Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press.
Agamben, 1993
Giorgio Agamben, Infancy and History: The Destruction of
Experience. Trans. Liz Heron. London and New York: Verso.
Agamben, 1991
Giorgio Agamben, Language and Death: The Place of Negativity.
Trans. Karen E. Pinkus and Michael Hardt. Minneapolis and London:
University of Minnesota Press.
Blanchot, 1986
Maurice Blanchot, The Writing of the Disaster. Trans. Ann Smock.
Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Paolo Bartoloni 93
Bruns, 1989
Gerald L. Bruns, Heidegger’s Estrangements: Languages, Truth, and
Poetry in the Later Writings. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Gottlieb, 1990
Anthony Gottlieb, “Heidegger for Fun and Profit”. New York Times
Book Review, January 7.
Heidegger, 1993
Martin Heidegger, “Letter on Humanism”. In Martin Heidegger: Basic
Writings, ed. David Farrell Krell: 213-265. London: Routledge.
Heidegger, 1992
Martin Heidegger, Parmenides. Trans. André Schuwer and Richard
Rojcewicz. Bloomington and Indianapolis, Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1987
Martin Heidegger, Zur Bestimmung der Philosophie. Mit einer
Nachschrift der Vorlesung “Uber das Wesen der Universitat und des
akademischen Studiums”. Gesamtausgabe, band 56/57, ed. Bernd
Heimbuchel. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.
Heidegger, 1985
Martin Heidegger, Phänomenologische Interpretationen zu Aristoteles
/ Einführung in die Phänomenologische Forschung. Gesamtausgabe,
band 61, ed. Waler Bröker and Käte Bröker-Olmanns. Frankfurt:
Vittorio Klostermann.
Heidegger, 1982
Martin Heidegger, On the Way to language. Trans. Peter D. Hertz. San
Francisco: Harper and Row [Unterwegs zur Sprache. Stuttgart: Verlag
Günther Neske Pfullingen, 1975].
Heidegger, 1980
Martin Heidegger, Hölderlins Hymmen "Germanien" und "Der Rhein.
Gesamtausgabe, band 39, ed. Susanne Ziegler. Frankfurt: Vittorio
Klostermann.
Heidegger, 1963
Martin Heidegger, What is Philosophy? Bilingual edition. Trans. W.
Kluback and J. T. Wilde. London: Vision.
Holland, 1995
Michael Holland, ed., The Blanchot Reader. London: Basil Blackwell.
Megill, 1985
Allan Megill, Prophet of Extremity: Nietzsche, Heidegger, Faucault,
Derrida. Berkeley: University of California Press.
94 Martin Heidegger and the Philosophy of Negativity
Neilson, 2006
Brett Neilson, “Cultural Studies and Giorgio Agamben”. In New
Cultural Studies: Adventures in Theory, eds. Gary Hall & Clare
Birchall. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Safranski, 1998
Rüdiger Safranski, Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil. Trans.
Ewald Osers. Cambridge & London: Harvard University Press.
Ungaretti, 1990
Giuseppe Ungaretti, The Buried Harbour. Trans. Kevin Hart.
Canberra: Leros Press.
Vattimo, 1994
Gianni Vattimo, Oltre l’interpretazione. Roma/Bari: Editori Laterza.
THE INTERPRETATION OF DA-SEIN
AS A TRANSFORMATIVE, POETIC
AND ETHICAL BEING
JANE MUMMERY
[M]any times, even ad nauseam, we pointed out that this being qua Dasein
is always already with others and always already with beings not of
Dasein’s nature (Heidegger, 1984: 19).
1
As Frederick Olafson puts it, Da-sein is “the kind of entity that eksists in the
sense that it transcends its own spatiotemporal envelope and can thus be said not
only to be in but to have a world” (Olafson,1998: 97).
2
Heidegger writes in History of the Concept of Time that “When we ask about this
entity, the Dasein, we must at least ask, Who is this entity?, and not, What is this
entity?” (Heidegger, 1992: 237).
96 The Interpretation of Da-sein as a Transformative, Poetic
and Ethical Being
the world always takes place from a situatedness within, which is also a
disclosure of, the world. Overall, Heidegger argues that Da-sein is our
way of being, a way that is not separable from the world, instead marking
a “disclosive weddedness to the world” (Thiele, 1995: 45).
Exploring some of the implications of Heidegger’s depiction of Da-
sein is thus the aim of this paper. To begin with, as I will demonstrate, Da-
sein’s way of being, in escaping categorization in terms of any particular
‘what’, points instead to a ‘how’ and an open and transformative
potentiality, a potentiality that is best exemplified by a certain mode of
being-with. This, however, has implications broader than just the
transformation of our understanding of Da-sein’s way of being-in-the-
world. Specifically, I suggest that it is this understanding of Da-sein’s
potentiality that not only mirrors but underpins and enables Heidegger’s
later delineations of the ethical and aesthetic potentiality of thinking itself.
Like Da-sein, or perhaps due to Da-sein, thinking is depicted as being able
to escape its traditional or common forms and constraints. These
possibilities, however, raise in their turn a series of important questions
with regard to the very possibility of thinking – in particular, questions
concerning whether we do in fact need to dwell in order to think. Such
questions, as I will show, have some interesting implications with regard
to the possibility and efficacy of ethical thinking.3
3
Of course, in using the Heideggerian project to assess ethical thinking, I am going
against the tenor of Heidegger’s own argument. As Silvia Benso puts it, it is “well
known” that Heidegger saw his thought as needing to be “free of any practical
concern” (Benso, 1994: 159). In Heidegger’s words, his thinking – given that it is
of Being rather than beings – “has no result. It has no effect. It satisfies its essence
in that it is” (Heidegger, 1998: 272). Nonetheless, as a range of thinkers have
stressed, Heidegger’s project has important implications for attempts to develop
non-systematised ethics (see, for instance, Benso, 1994; Caputo, 1993a; Gasché,
2000; Hodge, 1995; Lewis, 2005; Olafson, 1998).
Jane Mummery 97
4
It is important to realize that Heidegger is not making value judgements with
regards to the modes of being-in-the-world of authenticity and inauthenticity.
Indeed, it is fair to say that inauthenticity and authenticity simply describe whether
Da-sein’s life is its own in any real sense. That is, they are descriptive rather than
prescriptive terms.
98 The Interpretation of Da-sein as a Transformative, Poetic
and Ethical Being
5
“The term ‘ecstatic’ has nothing to do with ecstatic states of mind and the like.
The common Greek expression ekstatikon means stepping-outside-self. It is
affiliated with the term ‘existence’. It is with this ecstatic character that we
interpret existence” (Heidegger, 1982: 267). Heidegger also designates this ecstatic
stepping-beyond as the non-absolute transcendence constitutive of Da-sein’s
existence as Da-sein: “the being that we ourselves in each case are, the Dasein, is
the transcendent” (Heidegger, 1982: 298; cf. Heidegger, 1998: 108).
6
Heidegger suggests this in his infamous comparison of the business of
concentration camps with that of agriculture: “agriculture is now a motorized food
Jane Mummery 99
being-with, Heidegger states, for example, that “even the Rhine itself
appears as something at our command […] the river is dammed up into the
power plant. What the river is now, [is] namely, a water power supplier”
(Heidegger, 1977: 16).
Similarly, we can see this sort of model of being-with played out in
Da-sein’s inauthentic relationship with the “they”. Specifically, the “they”
are also perceived by an inauthentic Da-sein in terms of their use-value.
The “they”, after all, are useful insofar as they provide an answer to the
question of Da-sein’s being. The “they” frames Da-sein, keeping it from
anxiety and/or boredom, keeping it busy and involved and without the
chance of reflecting, except complacently, upon its being-in-the-world. As
Heidegger puts it, the “supposition of the ‘they’ that one is leading […] a
full and genuine ‘life’, brings Dasein a tranquility” (Heidegger, 1995a:
222; Heidegger, 1996: 166). Da-sein is as such reassured by simply being-
with the “they”. Further, such being-with the “they” provides Da-sein with
a sense of certainty with regards to how to approach and understand
everything and everyone else. Through “idle talk”7, in particular, Da-sein
sees itself as gaining a general understanding of everything, an
understanding that is authoritative simply because it is commonplace.
Nevertheless, in contrast to this mode of being-with that perceives the
world and things in terms of their possible usages, Heidegger says that Da-
sein can also disclose the world by “dwelling” in it, where dwelling in no
way implies ownership or control. Rather it suggests a transformative
relation with the world, others, and things. In other words, insofar as it
dwells, Da-sein is in the world differently. Not only does dwelling
disclose the world differently, but it changes the way in which Da-sein as
being-with is with others. This mode of being-with is also described by
Heidegger as a matter of ethos, where ethos both describes and suggests a
transformation of “the open region in which the human being dwells”
(Heidegger, 1998: 269). Ethos, we could say, is and suggests relations of
“releasement” and “letting be” (Gelassenheit)8, where Da-sein is able to
“[l]et the Others who are with it ‘be’ in their ownmost potentiality-for-
Being, and to co-disclose this potentiality in the solicitude which leaps
forth and liberates” (Heidegger, 1995a: 344; Heidegger, 1996: 274). In this
case, then, Da-sein’s being-with marks a disclosure of the world in terms
of a possible mode of belonging together that does not desire or descend
into either unification or mastery. That is, such a dwelling being-in-the-
world is a recognition of the point that Da-sein’s own needs and interests
are not, in fact, necessarily paramount. The modesty of this form of world
disclosure is additionally stressed by Heidegger when he describes this
being-in-the-world in terms of the belonging together of the fourfold –
a.k.a. the “earth and sky, divinities and mortals” (Heidegger, 1971: 149) –
where what matters is first Da-sein’s recognition of itself as not being “the
lord of beings” (Heidegger, 1998: 260), and, second, Da-sein’s recognition
of the importance of letting things be. Dwelling, then, itself marks a
significant transformation of Da-sein’s mode of being-with, where things,
others and the world – and, of course, Da-sein’s own being – cannot
simply be delineated in terms of use-value.
All of this, however, encompasses and implies far more than simply
reminding us of the range of worldly possibilities open to Da-sein.
Certainly this outline of our possible depictions of the relation between
self and other, along with Heidegger’s subsequent affirmation of an
authentic being-with, can be recognized in any number of self-help books,
but Heidegger is making some much more basic points here. For a start,
we need to remember that this possibility of dwelling is inextricable from
Da-sein’s potential for authenticity. Da-sein as dweller in the world is the
Da-sein who resolutely chooses itself, “deciding for a potentiality-for-
Being, and making this decision from one’s own self” (Heidegger, 1995a:
313; Heidegger, 1996: 248). That is, Da-sein as dweller is the Da-sein
who withdraws from absorption in the they, thereby demonstrating that the
possibility of dwelling, and thereby of ethos, is tied to that of authenticity.
More on this later. The second basic point that Heidegger makes here is to
remind us that the way we understand Da-sein to be will also give us a
picture of how we expect thinking to be. Indeed, I would suggest that it is
Da-sein’s possible transformative attunement to its own potentiality
through anxiety or boredom that makes Heidegger’s ongoing project re the
transformation of philosophy and thinking itself possible, a transformation
that can furthermore be seen to have implications for ethical and aesthetic
thinking. The question, however, is how exactly?
Jane Mummery 101
9
Heidegger stresses that the aim of his destruktion is positive (see Heidegger,
1995a: 44; Heidegger, 1996: 20). This point is reiterated by Caputo, who writes:
“The recovery of the meaning of Dasein, and ultimately of Being itself, cannot be
effected without deconstructive violence, even as deconstructive violence is not to
be undertaken except in the service of a positive program of retrieval” (Caputo,
1987: 65). Although I concur with Caputo’s point here, there is of course an oft-
cited problem with describing Heidegger’s notion of destruktion as a form of
(Derridean) deconstruction which has to do with what each of these terms makes
possible: destruktion, a sort of gathering or enabling; deconstruction, more of a
disabling. Derrida, of course, discusses this issue in his Of Spirit: Heidegger and
the Question.
10
Hodge has argued that Heidegger’s readings of the philosophical tradition
“demonstrate the contribution of these previous thinkers, then show their
limitations and then seek to break elements of their work free to be used in the
[his] new formation. It is the overriding importance of developing this new form of
thinking which for Heidegger justifies his impositions onto the texts of Kant, of
Leibniz, or indeed Aristotle” (Hodge, 1995: 149).
Jane Mummery 103
language that would preserve or translate into our discourses its world-
disclosive properties as opposed to its objectifying tendencies” (Ziarek,
1995: 384). Poetic thinking, in other words, is disclosive thinking, able to
go beyond the metaphysical methodology of enframing things to one of
releasing them, letting them be.
And it is this that reminds us again that these conceptions of
questioning and dialogic interpretation, and poetic and meditative
thinking, are very much inextricably tied up with Da-sein’s actual being-
in-the-world11. For a start Heidegger emphasizes that it is only through an
“analytic of the Dasein” (Heidegger, 1995a: 37; Heidegger, 1996: 14) that
the problematic of philosophical questioning can be reopened as a
question and re-attuned from calculative to meditative thinking –
philosophical questioning, after all, only has meaning as a “human
activity” (Heidegger, 1995b: 19). To put this another way, we could say
that the horizon of the problematic of philosophical questioning can
necessarily only be Da-sein itself. And, further, that the only way to
develop this problematic “still more radically”, and to let these “ancient
fundamental questions spring forth anew”, is to ground it and them in a
rethought human existence (Heidegger, 1995b: 359, 350). This point is, I
think, also demonstrated by Heidegger’s realization of the necessary
interconnectedness of the “what” and the “how” of his methodology. As
he puts it in his conversations with Nietzsche:
Our reflections make it clear that in thinking […] what is thought cannot
be detached from the way in which it is thought. The what is itself defined
by the how, and, reciprocally, the how by the what (Heidegger, 1991: 119).
11
For instance, note how Heidegger draws on Da-sein’s experiences of facticity in
his essays in Poetry, Language, Thought.
12
In full, Heidegger writes: “[T]he question of being, is in itself, correctly
understood, the question of man. Yet, the important thing is to raise the question of
man in view of the problem of being […]. This fundamental philosophical question
about man remains prior to every psychology, anthropology, and characterology,
but also prior to all ethics and sociology” (Heidegger, 1984: 17, my italics).
Jane Mummery 105
For a start, as the above quote suggests, Heidegger sees ethics quite
differently to what we commonly associate with ethical thinking. Most
simply, he describes the usual understanding of ethics as just one more
example of calculative thinking, specifically concerned with prescribing
and calculating rules for living, mores, and appropriate levels of praise and
blame. Such calculations, he argues, are dissociated from what really
matters which is ethos, and Da-sein’s potential for being-in-the-world in
terms of dwelling and letting be. Finally, of course, Heidegger suggests
that this potential for dwelling is itself played out in meditative and poetic
thinking, thinking which can also be seen as a sort of revitalized ethical
thinking highlighting the practices of letting be, releasement, and waiting.
It is at this point, however, that I want to go back to an issue I flagged
earlier, that of the relation between dwelling, ethos, ethical thinking, and
Da-sein’s authenticity. That is, is Heidegger suggesting that only authentic
Da-sein can dwell and think ethically? And if so, is this problematic?
To begin with, I would argue that Heidegger does seem to quite
explicitly connect authenticity with ethos, dwelling and thinking. For
instance, in his rectoral address of 1933, “The Self-Assertion of the
106 The Interpretation of Da-sein as a Transformative, Poetic
and Ethical Being
13
Note that whilst Heidegger did of course infamously identify this figure of
thinker with a determined historical person, such identification is not, in fact,
necessary or inevitable.
14
Benso makes this point clearly in ‘On the Way to an Ontological Ethics’ (see
Benso, 1994: 165-166).
Jane Mummery 107
Now in the above quote Heidegger can of course be seen as developing his
argument as to Da-sein’s role in the revealing-concealing of Being – a role
also delineated by him through his discussions of thinker as shepherd
and/or poet. Da-sein as thinker in both of these cases is in effect the
medium by which Being comes to the world15, and the realization of this
stands for Da-sein’s ownmost potential. In other words, ethos stands for
and describes Da-sein’s potential essential being-in-the-world. Thinking
ethically for Heidegger, then, is thinking Da-sein’s essential being, or,
putting this otherwise, it simply describes Da-sein’s dwelling being-with.
This, of course, brings us right back to the beginning where Heidegger
argues that what matters in understanding our being is that we realize that
our being is as a “how” as opposed to a “what”.
Finally, then, there is one more point that I wish to make that is
resultant from some of the ideas I’ve put forward here. That is, I would
15
More specifically, the language of Da-sein as thinker is this medium. Far from
being mere communication or speech, language “is the house of Being, which is
propriated by Being and pervaded by Being” (1998: 254).
108 The Interpretation of Da-sein as a Transformative, Poetic
and Ethical Being
Bibliography
Benso, 1994
Silvia Benso, "On the Way to an Ontological Ethics: Ethical
Suggestions in Reading Heidegger", Research in Phenomenology,
XXIV: 159-188.
16
To mention only two key texts, Caputo critiques Heidegger’s project in terms of
its mythologizing “tendencies” in his aptly named Demythologizing Heidegger
(Caputo, 1993b: 1); whilst Derrida engages critically and productively with
Heidegger in his Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question (Derrida, 1989).
Jane Mummery 109
Caputo, 1993a
John D. Caputo, Against Ethics. Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana
University Press.
Caputo, 1993b
John D. Caputo, Demythologizing Heidegger. Bloomington &
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Caputo, 1987
John D. Caputo, Radical Hermeneutics. Bloomington & Indianapolis:
Indiana University Press.
Derrida, 1989
Jacques Derrida, Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question. Trans.
Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby. Chicago & London:
University of Chicago Press.
Gasché, 2000
Rodolphe Gasché, "Toward an Ethics of Auseinandersetzun". In
American Continental Philosophy: A Reader, eds. Walter Brogan and
James Risser: 314–332. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana
University Press.
Heidegger, 1998
Martin Heidegger, Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Heidegger, 1996
Martin Heidegger, Being and Time. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. Albany:
State University of New York Press.
Heidegger, 1995a
Martin Heidegger, Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and
Edward Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell.
Heidegger, 1995b
Martin Heidegger, The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics. Trans.
William McNeill and Nicholas Walker. Bloomington & Indianapolis:
Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1993
Martin Heidegger, Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings. Trans. David
Farrell Krell. New York: HarperCollins.
Heidegger, 1992
Martin Heidegger, History of the Concept of Time. Trans. Theodore
Kisiel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1991
Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche, Volumes I and II.. Trans. David Farrell
Krell. San Francisco: HarperCollins.
110 The Interpretation of Da-sein as a Transformative, Poetic
and Ethical Being
Heidegger, 1990
Martin Heidegger, "Der Spiegel Interview". In Martin Heidegger and
National Socialism, eds. Günther Neske and Emil Kettering, trans. Lisa
Harris: 41-66. New York: Paragon House.
Heidegger, 1985
Martin Heidegger, "The Self-Assertion of the German University:
Address, Delivered on the Solemn Assumption of the Rectorate of the
University Freiburg". Trans. Karsten Harries. Review of Metaphysics
38: 470-480.
Heidegger, 1984
Martin Heidegger, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic. Trans.
Michael Heim. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1982
Martin Heidegger, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology. Trans.
Albert Hofstadter. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1977
Martin Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology and Other
Essays. Trans. William Lovitt. New York & London: Garland.
Heidegger, 1975
Martin Heidegger, The End of Philosophy. Trans. Joan Stambaugh.
London: Souvenir Press.
Heidegger, 1971
Martin Heidegger, Poetry, Language, Thought. Trans. Albert
Hofstadter. New York: Harper and Row.
Heidegger, 1969
Martin Heidegger, Identity and Difference. Trans. Joan Stambaugh.
New York: Harper and Row.
Heidegger, 1966
Martin Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking. Trans. John M. Anderson
and E. Hans Freund. New York: Harper and Row.
Heidegger, 1958
Martin Heidegger, "The Question of Being". In The Question of Being,
trans. Jean T. Wilde and William Kluback: 32-109. New Haven,
Conn.: College and University Press.
Hodge, 1995
Joanna Hodge, Heidegger and Ethics. London & New York:
Routledge.
Lewis, 2005
Michael Lewis, Heidegger and the Place of Ethics: Being-With in the
Crossing of Heidegger’s Thought. London & New York: Continuum.
Jane Mummery 111
PETER WILLIAMS
1
Damasio claims that “[b]rains can have many intervening steps in the circuits
mediating between stimulus and response, and still have no mind, if they do not
meet an essential condition: the ability to display images internally and to order
those images in a process called thought” (Damasio, 1994: 89).
2
First introduced by C.D. Broad (1933). Broad’s ideas were taken up by Vincent
Nowlis (1963) who suggested that moods are higher-order dispositions and
emotions lower-order dispositions. Moods therefore, according to this view, are
dispositions to have emotions. Griffiths points out, however, that moods pre-
dispose us not only to emotions, but also to actions.
114 Moods That Matter: Heidegger, Affect and Wallace Stevens’
“Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird”
3
First published in Enclitic 2, 1978: 5-33.
Peter Williams 115
terms, like “[a] stone [that] has instantly withdrawn again into the same
dull pressure and bulk of its fragments” (Heidegger, 1971: 46-47); I am
pressing downward and manifesting my heaviness. My mood has
positioned me, and for me to live authentically I must embrace the ethics,
the mode of existence, of my “stoneness” which, like the earth itself,
“shrinks from every disclosure and constantly keeps itself closed up”
(Heidegger, 1971: 47).
When I ground my existence in my mood, when I submit to my
“stoneness”, I open myself to a strange but compelling doubleness. One
aspect of my consciousness observes myself from the outside, becoming
appalled at how I have surrendered myself to a situation in which the ego
loses its autonomy and renounces its active, willing powers. Yet from
within my mood, from my inhabiting of the mood, such reflective or
ethical judgements seem almost small, irrelevant and certainly gross
because they fail to comprehend and contain the immense expansiveness
that moods afford. Moods overcome us and cause global changes in
propensities to occupy other affective and behavioural states and to
respond to external stimuli and sensory provocations.
I feel that by embracing and expanding my “stoneness” I stand in the
same relation to Heidegger as Heidegger stands to poetry. The nature of
this relationship could be called “estrangement”. Accompanying this
feeling of estrangement is a certain amount of anxiety, a primordial mood
and an overwhelming affect with which Heidegger is inevitably
concerned. Anxiety, a mood that has no object and no propositional
content (as opposed to an emotion like fear that has a particular source and
object, usually “within-the-world”) functions for Heidegger as a reminder
of our “throwness” into the world, and that our life and death, our Being,
must be confronted. In the mood of anxiety, for example, “one feels ill at
ease” (Heidegger, 1977: 101), and nothing in particular is the source of
this feeling. It is perhaps Heidegger’s interest in the “nothing” that, in its
everyday usage and in its metaphysical context, connects his earlier and
later works. “The nothing” names the source of all that is perhaps dark and
troublesome in existence, that which seems to rise from nowhere and
return to it, but it also expresses the disclosure of Being as such and the
illumination surrounding whatever this disclosure brings to light. In this
sense, anxiety is not just negative and empty, but also positive and full.
Nothingness is fullness. Nothing is the characteristic of Being and is what
Heidegger terms “equiprimordial” which implies fullness because without
the originary revelation of the nothing there would be, according to
Heidegger, “no selfhood and no freedom” (Heidegger, 1977: 103).
116 Moods That Matter: Heidegger, Affect and Wallace Stevens’
“Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird”
Rather than a rationalist metaphyics Vico, and perhaps also Heidegger for
whom knowledge and rational opinions are only one kind of disclosure, at
least the Heidegger of “Holderlin” and “What Are Poets For?”, proposes
an imaginative metaphysics that becomes all things by not understanding
them. Vico says, “for when man understands he extends his mind and
takes in all things, but when he does not understand he makes things out of
himself and becomes them by transforming himself into them” (Vico,
1961: 156).
The power of poetic language thus derives from its ability to say
something by not saying it, or to say it by pointing to something else, or
even by its indicating the opposite of what the poet intends to say as found
in rhetorical figures such as metaphor and metonymy. And if we return to
the primordiality of anxiety, we could say that the poet’s anxiety results
not from influence, as proposed by Harold Bloom, but from the
subjugation of the guts, the seat of the aesthetic dimension according to
Nietzsche4, to the rules of an external reality. Nietzsche emphasises the
physicality of the poet when he says that artists, “if they are any good, are
(physically as well) strong, full of surplus energy, powerful animals,
sensual; without a certain overheating of the sexual system a Raphael is
unthinkable” (Nietzsche, 1967: 421). For Heidegger, however, the poet
penetrates and communicates with the reader by dwelling within the
“spirit of the words” which awakens in the reader his or her own
imaginative universals. This spirit is a reference to the essential dimension
of language itself which is as original a structure of being-in-the-world as
mood, and the language of poets discloses Being as least as authentically
as the language of thinkers. Yet poeticizing and thinking, as demonstrated
by Heidegger’s poem (above) are not the same.
In his later work, “The Origin of the Work of Art”, Heidegger goes on
to state that “Self-assertion of nature, however, is never a rigid insistence
upon some contingent state, but surrender to the concealed originality of
the source of one’s being. In the struggle, each opponent carries the other
beyond itself” (Heidegger, 1971: 49). This description of the opposition
between earth and world reminds us of the Kantian sublime and the leap-
frogging struggle, triggered by imagination, between understanding and
reason in which the sublime ultimately reminds us of the incompatibility
of rational ideas and sensory presentation. The sublime’s end is to lead us
to feel a purposiveness in ourselves that is independent of nature, and to
discover a faculty of resistance that encourages us to measure ourselves
4
Nietzsche claims that aesthetics is “physiology”, perhaps again aligning cognitive
states with visceral patterns more than even he would acknowledge.
Peter Williams 119
against the apparent omnipotence of nature. For Kant, then, the sublime is
a movement or a migration – a displacement from a threatening nature to
the capacity of reason and thinking to rise above the threat of extinction.
By emphasising a similar struggle, Heidegger seems to be moving us
towards more heterogenous notions, such as the multi-dimensional nature
of the conflict between world and earth that stands behind his
estrangement. This conflict, he says:
is not a rift (Riss) as a mere cleft that is ripped open; rather it is the
intimacy which opponents bring to each other. This rift carries the
opponents into the source of their unity by virtue of their common ground.
It is a basic design, an outline sketch that draws the basic features of the
rise of the lightening of beings. This rift does not let the opponents break
apart; it brings the opposition of measure and boundary into their common
outline. (Heidegger, 1971: 63. Emphasis mine).
It may be in the intimacy of this rift between earth and world, in the
tear and the sketch that, while feeling the downward weight of my
“stoneness”, I also feel the rising lightness of my acknowledged,
contingent state of being. The establishing of a world and the setting-forth
of the earth belong together in the unity of a poem’s or an artwork’s being;
the two, like my own weightiness and lightness, are essentially different to
one another yet never separate. And yet this same rift manifests in a work
of art as something itself primordial, like a mood or an atmosphere,
through which the artwork or poem comes radically into its own – when it
becomes so solitary or singular that we as beings feel like we loosen our
connection with it5. Think of the language of Joyce’s Finnegan’s Wake or
the recalcitrance and withdrawal of minimalist artworks that mirror
nothing we can recognise except, perhaps, a reconfigured reflection of our
own selves. This singularity is manifested in the work’s originality,
materiality and absoluteness, and we cannot forget Adorno in this respect
when he says: “If it is essential to artworks that they be things, it is no less
essential that they negate their own status as things, and thus art turns
against art. The totally objectified artwork would congeal into a mere
thing, whereas if it altogether evaded objectivism it would regress into an
impotently powerless subjective impulse and flounder in the empirical
world” (Adorno, 1997: 175).
5
The distinction between “artwork” and “poem” is probably unnecessary.
Heidegger claims in “The Origin of the Work of Art” that “[…] all art is in essence
poetr,” (Heidegger, 1971: 73). He also says that “the nature of art is poetry”
(Heidegger, 1971: 75).
120 Moods That Matter: Heidegger, Affect and Wallace Stevens’
“Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird”
therefore is not only the art of poetry, but also that primordial quality in
which all forms of art find their essence in the poetic coming-to-presence.
Stevens himself seems to give a similarly circumscribed role to
imagination that is not quite Heideggerian but that also reflects the idea
that imagination has its sources and dependencies in things outside of and
external to the self. Instead of the idea of the imagination as autonomous
and self-constituting, Stevens also emphasises the contingency and
dependence of imagination when he says in a 1936 letter, “Imagination
has no source except in reality, and ceases to have any value when it
departs from reality. Here is a fundamental principle about the
imagination; It does not create except as it transforms[…]. Thus reality =
the imagination, and the imagination = reality. The imagination gives, but
gives in relation” (Stevens, 1972: 364). Stevens’ claims about imagination
here align well with Heidegger’s own when he says: “[…] it becomes
questionable whether the nature of poetry, and this means at the same time
the nature of projection, can be adequately thought of in terms of the
power of imagination” (Heidegger, 1971: 72-73). Both would reject the
view that imagination realises a distinctive content, symbolically charged
with visionary meanings or composed to generate moral effects.
In his “Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird” (Stevens, 1990: 20-
22), Stevens predisposes us to “let things be” by moving us away from the
symbolic valencies of imagination and representational thinking and
towards imaginative processes as the apprehension of estrangement. Under
the auspices of mood, imagination then breaks open a space, a “clearing”,
in which language brings into being primordial scenes in which things
come into their own for the first time as things in all their singularity, in all
their self-possession.
The poem’s opening tercet is a still scene, the minimalist quiet of a
primordial “coming into existence” or an oriental painting brushed with
haiku and imagist delicacy:
This opening could be read or even viewed as synecdoche for the activity
of the reader/viewer and a metaphor for the work of the poet where the
moving eye signifies the initial impulse for the thirteen ways of looking. It
is important to recognise, however, the way that the movement of the
entire poem is propelled by the indecipherability of mood as articulated in
Stanza VI:
122 Moods That Matter: Heidegger, Affect and Wallace Stevens’
“Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird”
Each sense of the blackbird, marking “the edge/ Of many circles” defines
a new perspective on “blackbirdness” that holds only until the blackbird
crosses its next horizon, when the reader broaches the next stanza of the
poem. Horizons are, according to Nietzsche, what “[w]e measure the
world by” and “within which our senses confine each of us”. Thus a
“concentric circle is drawn around every being” (Nietzsche, 1903: 122) in
much the same way that Stevens’ blackbird traverses the stanzas of his
poem and crosses the horizons of its own forms of being.
My original “stoneness” relates to my authenticity of mood. Mood is a
fundamental way in which my Dasein is aware of its being-in-the-world,
and it is not reason that gives Dasein its basic access to being, but moods6.
The authenticity or inauthenticity of my mood is determined by whether it
discloses the truth of my Dasein or conceals the truth. Authenticity is
resoluteness and resoluteness demands for Heidegger the willingness to
have a conscience. My mood of anxiety before Heidegger disclosed my
Dasein and in anxiety Dasein is brought before itself and so my
authenticity is understood. Heidegger says:
6
Nietzsche asks, “How did reason come into the world? As is fitting, in an
irrational manner, by accident. One will have to guess at it as at a riddle”
(Nietzsche, 1976: 81).
124 Moods That Matter: Heidegger, Affect and Wallace Stevens’
“Thirteen Ways of Looking at a Blackbird”
Bibliography
Adorno, 1997
T. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, eds. Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedemann.
Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press.
Broad, 1933
C. Broad, Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Peter Williams 125
Damasio, 1994
A. Damasio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human
Brain. New York: Quill.
Derrida, 1978
J. Derrida, “Retrait of Metaphor”, trans. F. Gasdner, B. Iginla, R.
Madden and W. Best. Enclitic 2: 5-33.
Griffiths, 1997
P. Griffiths, What Emotions Really Are. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Heidegger, 1962
M. Heidegger, Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarie and Edward
Robinson. New York: Harper and Row.
Heidegger, 1971
M. Heidegger, Poetry, Language, Thought. Trans. Albert Hofstadter.
New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, 1977
M. Heidegger, Basic Writings, ed. David Krell. New York: Harper
Collins
Merleau-Ponty, 1968
M. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible. Evanston:
Northwestern University Press.
Nietzsche, 1903
F. Nietzsche, Dawn of Day. Trans. Johanna Volz. New York:
MacMillan.
Nietzsche, 1967
F. Nietzsche, The Will To Power. Trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J.
Hollingdale. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson.
Nietzsche, 1968
F. Nietzsche, The Portable Nietzsche. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New
York: Viking.
Stevens, 1990
W. Stevens, The Palm at the End of the Mind, ed. Holly Stevens. New
York: Vintage.
Vico, 1961
G. Vico, The New Science. Trans. Thomas Bergin and Max Fisch. New
York: Anchor.
TERRENCE MALICK’S THE THIN RED LINE
AND THE QUESTION
OF HEIDEGGERIAN CINEMA
ROBERT SINNERBRINK
whether we can talk of a “Heideggerian cinema,” and to ask what such talk
might mean. Another is whether we should describe The Thin Red Line as
“Heideggerian Cinema”, as some recent critics have argued, and to
examine what this might mean. Along the way I discuss two different
approaches to the film, a “Heideggerian” approach that takes it to be
unquestionably an instance of Heideggerian cinema (Furstenau and
MacEvoy, Kaja Silverman), and a “film-as-philosophy” approach, which
argues that, while the film is philosophical, we should refrain from
grounding the film in any specific philosophical framework, even that of
Heidegger (Simon Critchley). In conclusion, I offer some brief remarks on
how the film can indeed be regarded as a case of “Heideggerian cinema”,
not because we need to read Heidegger in order to talk about our
relationship to mortality, authentic existence, or to Being, but because
Malick’s film performs a cinematic poesis, a technological revealing of
mortality and world through image, sound, and time.
the fact that the Japanese world is filmed at all, “captured and imprisoned
at all within the objectness of photography”, that makes Rashomon an
example of the process Western techno-rationalisation (Heidegger, 1982:
17). Regardless of the film’s undoubted aesthetic qualities, “the mere fact
that our world is set forth in the frame of a film forces that world into the
sphere of what you call of objectness” (Heidegger, 1982: 17). And this
“objectification” of world through the technological media of photography
and film is “already a consequence of the ever wider outreach of
Europeanization” (Heidegger, 1982: 17). The Inquirer (a stand-in for
Heidegger, one presumes) thus begins to understand his interlocutor’s
concern: far from presenting the “enchantment of the Japanese world”,
Kurosawa’s Rashomon shows us the incompatibility between this non-
Western sense of world, still replete with a sense of Being, and the
Westernised, “technical-aesthetic product of the film industry” that suffers
from a loss of the sense of Being (Heidegger, 1982: 17). In short,
cinematic art intensifies, rather than reverses, the process of
"objectification" of beings that is symptomatic of the Western forgetting of
Being.
While intriguing, particularly for its implicit criticism of Western
"orientalism", this passage is hardly a promising start for thinking about
the relationship between Heidegger and cinema. Indeed, it suggests that
there is little to be said other than that cinema is a pernicious manifestation
of Western technological enframing. It is also a disappointing discussion
of Kurosawa’s work, given the latter’s explicitly hybrid character, fusing
Japanese with Western literary traditions (Shakespeare), and its
revitalization of the Western action genre by combining it with martial
aspects of Japanese drama1. Given Heidegger’s evident skepticism
concerning film, what are we to make of the frequent talk of
"Heideggerian cinema" that Malick’s work seems to provoke?
For some viewers of Malick there is no real question here to ponder.
According to a recent essay by Marc Furstenau and Leslie MacEvoy,
Malick’s The Thin Red Line is clearly an instance of “Heideggerian
cinema” (Furstenau and MacEvoy, 2003). This follows firstly, they
suggest, from the biographical facts of Malick’s career. Malick studied
philosophy as an undergraduate with Stanley Cavell, and briefly taught
philosophy at the MIT, even teaching courses for Hubert Dreyfus. Malick
1
As Julian Young notes, "Kurosawa, who had studied Western painting, literature,
and political philosophy, based Yojimbo on a Dashiell Hammett novel, Throne of
Blood on Macbeth, and Ran on King Lear. He never pretended otherwise than that
his films were cultural hybrids" (Young, 2001: 149).
Robert Sinnerbrink 129
2
See Critchley (2005: 138) for a succinct resume of Malick’s fascinating
biography.
130 Terrence Malick’s The Thin Red Line and the Question
of Heideggerian Cinema
anxiety, the encounter with nonbeing at the heart of our finite temporal
existence. Malick’s concerns are in any case philosophical rather than
conventionally narratological (Silverman, 2003: 324), which explains the
perplexity many critics and viewers experienced when confronted with
Malick’s idiosyncratic version of the war film genre3.
Indeed, Silverman too regards Malick’s film as philosophy, a vision
that is very much grounded in Heidegger’s account of authentic being-
toward-death (as explored in Being and Time, Division II) and the
encounter with “the Nothing” (examined in “What is Metaphysics?”).
Indeed, Heidegger’s being-toward-death, as Silverman remarks, is less an
account of a limit to existence than a way of existing in the world as finite,
as grounded in the Nothing (Silverman, 2003: 334); it is less a way of
embracing death than a way of affirming life by "living toward" death.
Malick’s exploration of this theme, moreover, invokes what Silverman
calls a singular affectivity, a simultaneous negativity and affirmation:
“both a darkness verging on total eclipse and a radiance brighter than the
sun’s return” (Silverman, 2003: 324). The film subjects us to the shattering
experience of an almost unbearable negativity that permeates both our
psychic core and our bodily being (Silverman, 2003: 324).
Indeed, The Thin Red Line, Silverman suggests, takes phenomenology
to a place where Heidegger himself was not capable of bringing it: “the
battlefield” (Silverman, 2003: 326). It is precisely here, as Heidegger
hints, that we encounter finitude in its rawest sense; the experience of “the
nothing” that dissolves our spurious independence, our generic das Man-
Selbst subjectivity, and thereby reveals to us our "groundless" mortality4.
To be sure, one hears echoes here of the "existentialist" theme of war as an
authentic encounter with mortality, the Front-Erlebnis celebrated by
writers such as Ernst Jünger. Far from exulting in negativity and violence,
however, Malick’s explorations of mortality and the meaning of authentic
Being-toward-death are oriented by philosophical, ethical, even spiritual
concerns. Private Witt’s journey is one towards Being, the Nothing, that
transpires through an authentic affective relationship to his own mortality,
his “confrontation with the nonbeing that grounds him” (Silverman, 2003:
331). This is a confrontation that is manifested through his affective
relationship with death, that is, through his calm, or what the later
3
One film critic notoriously gave the film a rating of four question marks; not an
inappropriate rating for such a "Heideggerian" work!
4
See Heidegger’s enigmatic remark in Being and Time that Da-sein can attain its
authenticity as anticipatory resoluteness by “running under the eyes of death”; in
so doing, it can “take over completely the being that it itself is in its thrownness”
(Heidegger, 1996: §74, 350).
132 Terrence Malick’s The Thin Red Line and the Question
of Heideggerian Cinema
his mother’s death but seeing nothing glorious in it) (Silverman, 2003:
328). The sequence, with its gently singing bird and silent poetic gestures,
ends with the camera panning up towards the roof, giving way to the blue
of the sky, which “becomes part of the sea, land, and oceanscape of the
Solomon Islands” (Silverman, 2003: 328). “‘Openness to the world’”, as
Silverman observes, “is the dominant trope invoked by these last images”
(Silverman, 2003: 328). Another important observation is that Witt’s
utopian-romantic vision of the harmonious life of the Melanesian
community is his subjective fantasy, rather than Malick’s orientalising
naivety, a fantasy shattered by the violence of war and the reality of
domination, disease, and discord. There is no question that Silverman’s
emphasis on Witt’s “journey toward Being”, his decision “to live
‘toward’” his finitude through his early meditation upon his own death,
enriches our cinematic and philosophical understanding of the film,
particularly Malick’s decision to make Witt the central character, and to
turn the manner in which Witt faces his own death into the film’s narrative
climax (in James Jones’ novel, Witt is a minor character, ignorant and
racist, and he certainly does not die).
At the same time, however, Silverman’s approach presupposes that we
can talk about Malick’s cinema, and The Thin Red Line in particular, as
"Heideggerian" in a straightforward sense. Although they emphasise
different aspects of Heidegger’s thought, Furstenau, MacEvoy, and
Silverman all assume that the film can be subsumed within a philosophical
framework that would explain its thematic content and aesthetic style. This
strongly "Heideggerian" approach applies philosophy to film or reads film
in light of a given philosophical framework, without, however, raising the
question of the relationship between philosophy and film, which is what a
reading in the spirit of Heidegger’s thought, I would suggest, might be
expected to do.
5
Critchley thus discusses the ways in which Malick departs from James Jones’
gritty 1963 novel and the 1964 film version by Andrew Marton.
136 Terrence Malick’s The Thin Red Line and the Question
of Heideggerian Cinema
of war, finding amidst the violence and brutality the possibility of selfless
sacrifice; he seeks an encounter with "the glory", with the moment of
immortality that arrives in facing one’s death with calm.
Their relationship thus takes on the character of a philosophical
disputation, Welsh’s “nihilistic physicalism”, as Critchley describes,
clashing with Witt’s “metaphysical panpsychism” (Critchley, 2005: 141).
Welsh’s assertions are confounded by Witt’s questions: “What is this war
in the heart of nature?” “Where does this evil come from?” “Maybe all
men got one big soul, that everybody’s part of—all faces are the same
man, one big self”. Welsh’s dispirited resignation is contrasted with Witt’s
affirmative spark: Witt survives the war, but is deadened; Witt dies but in
an enlivened state, calmly sacrificing himself for his fellows. Who is
"right" about the metaphysical truth of war? There can be no answer to
this question, the ambivalence of the experience of war, as a confrontation
with mortality, being precisely Malick’s point: it "poisons the soul" but
also "reveals the glory".
These metaphysical reflections on truth, mortality, and humanity, are,
for Critchley, what makes Malick’s film a philosophical work. The key to
the film and to Malick’s work generally, he suggests, is calm: the calm
acceptance of death, of this-worldly mortality, a calmness present not only
as a narrative theme but as a cinematic aesthetic. Malick’s male
protagonists, as Critchley observes, “seem to foresee their appointment
with death and endeavour to make sure they arrive on time” (Critchley,
2005: 142-143). Witt is one such character, recklessly putting himself in
situations of extreme danger, fascinated by the intimacy of death, but with
an anticipation of it that brings not fear but calm. Early in the film, Witt
describes his initially fearful response to his mother’s death as follows: “I
was afraid to touch the death that I seen in her. I couldn’t find anything
beautiful or uplifting about her going back to God. I heard people talk
about immortality, but I ain’t never seen it”. Witt then wonders how it will
be when he dies, what it would be like “to know that this breath now was
the last one you was ever gonna draw”. And it is here that he finds his
answer about the relation between immortality and mortality: “I just hope I
can meet it the same way she did, with the same … calm. Because that’s
where it’s hidden, the immortality that I hadn’t seen”.
As Kaja Silverman points out, however, this scene actually presents
Witt’s mother’s sense of calm, rather than Witt’s own recollection of his
mother’s death. For Witt recalls the fear he felt in seeing his mother
"going to meet God". Yet it is her moment of calm before death that gives
Witt a clue as to how to experience his own authentic being-toward-death
(Silverman, 2005: 328). Be that as it may, the thought Malick presents
Robert Sinnerbrink 137
6
Critchley also mentions Blanchot’s L’Instant de ma mort in this context.
138 Terrence Malick’s The Thin Red Line and the Question
of Heideggerian Cinema
Malick is in this respect more akin to a poet like Wallace Stevens than
to a thinker like Heidegger, though Critchley leaves the nature of this
relationship tantalizingly open. In the end it is the poet Stevens who
"frames" Critchley’s reading of The Thin Red Line, which opens with
Stevens’ “The Death of a Soldier” and closes, aptly, with a quotation from
“The Palm at the End of the Mind”—lines resonating with the final image
of a coconut shoot emerging from out of the sandy shallows. As with the
later Heidegger, we defer to the poet rather than the philosopher when it
comes to that mode of poetic revealing which exceeds the philosophical
framing of the film, or indeed the framework of philosophical discourse
itself.
Surely here, philosophically anxious viewers might exclaim, we are
talking of an experience evoking Heidegger’s Gelassenheit! For all the
care to avoid invoking a philosophical meta-text, or departing from our
immersion in the cinematic Sache, we find ourselves talking of the way
things presence, their luminous appearance, their revealing of a world that
we do not master or control; an experience that reveals the mystery of
finitude and the calm releasement towards time, death, and the mystery of
Being. Hermeneutic banana skin or not, it seems difficult to avoid talk
about Malick’s cinematic "letting be" without invoking, at least implicitly,
the Heideggerian thought of Gelassenheit, about which Critchley remains
silent. Is Critchley’s reading here not a touch "Heideggerian" after all?
Surely it reveals, in a phenomenological manner, the way the film
thematises death, finitude and our proper relationship with Being.
Interestingly, however, Critchley does not mention the theme that, in
my view, is most central to the film: the confrontation with mortality and
different attitudes towards our own finitude as mortal and finite beings.
My suggestion would be that it is the, dare one say, properly
"Heideggerian" theme of mortality that pervades the other themes of
loyalty, love, truth, and indeed our relationship to Nature, lending these a
philosophical subtlety and poetic richness. In this sense, reference to
Heideggerian phenomenology seems indispensable, since what we are
watching is nothing less than a phenomenology of mortality; one that
demonstrates the distinctive experiences of mortality—our success or
failure to confront it—in the stories of the different characters’ experiences
during the battle of Guadalcanal. This also means that the question of what
we mean by “Heideggerian cinema” presents itself once again. Whereas
Furstenau and MacEvoy’s approach threatens to subsume the film within a
"Heideggerian" framework, Critchley’s avoidance of such a framework
might be taken as another kind of avoidance of the question of the
Robert Sinnerbrink 139
A Cinematic Poesis?
In conclusion I want to offer some brief remarks suggesting an alternative
way of approaching the question of "Heideggerian cinema". As discussed
earlier, Heidegger’s thinking on film, such as it is, remains overwhelmingly
negative: film is a powerful instance of reductive technological en-framing
that only intensifies the Western obliteration of Being. We should recall
here, however, that Heidegger’s claim that en-framing or Ge-stell as the
essence of technology—the revealing and ordering of beings as a totality
of available resources—is a thoroughly ambivalent process: it not only
presents the great danger of a destructive reduction of human beings to
manipulable resources, but also presents the possibility of a "saving
power"—of a new relation of appropriation between Being, beings, and
human beings that might emerge from within the technological world
(Heidegger, 1977). What would be the artform most essential to the
technological age? Surely cinema: the technological en-framing of reality
that enables us to reveal luminous appearances in time. If we take cinema
to be the artform most appropriate to the age of technology, then such
ambivalent possibilities must also be present in cinematic art, despite the
dominance of standardised Hollywood conventions, which often do reduce
film to a "worldless" aesthetic resource.
Despite the undeniable instrumentalisation of modern experience,
technological en-framing also opens up the possibility of a new way of
revealing world, namely through film as a form of cinematic poesis. By
this I mean a revealing or bringing-forth through sound and image that
displaces the conventional representational and narrative focus on
presenting objects in their presence within the action-directed,
motivational schemas of self-willing subjects. One need only compare The
Thin Red Line with Spielberg’s Saving Private Ryan (1998) to understand
the contrast I am proposing here. Such an anti-representationalist account
of cinematic poesis could supplement the readings of Malick’s film
offered by Critchley and by Silverman, bringing these into a reflective
relationship with Heidegger’s thought without thereby reducing the
meaning of the film to a Heideggerian meta-text, or else foreclosing the
question of the relationship between Heidegger and cinema altogether.
Heidegger’s general complaint against cinema is that it remains
irreducibly "metaphysical" in the sense of only ever being able to present
beings in their massive presence. It is beholden to a metaphysical realism
140 Terrence Malick’s The Thin Red Line and the Question
of Heideggerian Cinema
7
My thanks to the participants of the Heidegger and the Aesthetics of Living
Conference, University of Sydney, December 12-14, 2005, and to Daniel Ross for
his many thoughtful comments.
Robert Sinnerbrink 141
Bibliography
Cavell, 1979
Stanley Cavell, “Foreword to the Enlarged Edition”. In The World
Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Critchley, 2005
Simon Critchley, “Calm: On Terrence Malick’s The Thin Red Line”. In
Film as Philosophy. Essays on Cinema after Wittgenstein and Cavell,
ed. R. Read and J. Goodenough: 133-148. Basingstoke and New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Furstenau and MacEvoy, 2003
Marc Furstenau and Leslie MacEvoy, “Terrence Malick’s
Heideggerian Cinema: War and the Question of Being in The Thin Red
Line”. In The Cinema of Terrence Malick: Poetic Visions of America,
ed. H. Patterson: 173-185. London: Wallflower Press.
Heidegger, 1977
Martin Heidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology”. In The
Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. W. Lovitt:
3-35. New York: Harper and Row.
Heidegger, 1982
Martin Heidegger, “A Dialogue on Language between a Japanese and
an Inquirer”. In On the Way to Language, trans. P. D. Hertz: 1-54. San
Francisco: Harper and Row.
Heidegger, 1993
Martin Heidegger, “What is Metaphysics?” In Basic Writings. Revised
and Expanded Edition, ed. D.F. Krell: 93-110. San Francisco: Harper
and Row.
Heidegger, 1996
Martin Heidegger, Being and Time. Trans. J. Stambaugh. Albany: State
University of New York.
Silverman, 2003
Kaja Silverman, “All Things Shining”. In Loss: The Politics of
Mourning, ed. D. L. Eng and D. Kazanjian: 323-342. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Young, 2001.
Julian Young, Heidegger’s Philosophy of Art. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
REFLECTIONS ON HEIDEGGER’S SAYING:
“THE WAY WHAT IS QUESTIONED
ESSENTIALLY ENGAGES OUR QUESTIONING
BELONGS TO THE INNERMOST MEANING
OF THE QUESTION OF BEING”
GEORGE VASSILACOPOULOS
I. Introduction
For Heidegger thinking is “the historical process in which a thinker arises,
says his word, and so provides to truth a place within a historical
humanity” (Heidegger, 1998: 7) and, of course, in his own case this
historical process begins with the question of the meaning of being. Parvis
Emad (2002) has recently argued that for the most part commentators have
neglected the guiding significance of this question in their appropriations
of Being and Time. He offers an analysis of the structure of the question
with two purposes in mind: the first is to show how commentators have
misunderstood Heidegger and the second is to show how the structure of
the question of the meaning of being “guides and reaches into Heidegger’s
hermeneutic efforts which distinguish his fundamental-ontology and
being-historical thinking from traditional pre-occupation with being”
(Emad, 2002: 15). Whether we take Heidegger’s central focus to be the
question of being or instead “what brings about being” (Sheehan, 2001: 5),
an appreciation of the way in which Heidegger’s philosophical project is
activated calls for careful consideration of what “belongs to the innermost
meaning of the question of being” (Heidegger, 1996: 7). Emad makes the
point that “when Heidegger stresses the need for an exposition and
conceptualization that are peculiar to being and its meaning he alludes to
the language of being”. Moreover, “this shows that as early as the analysis
of the structure of the question of being Heidegger ‘speaks’ that language
of being” (Emad, 2002: 15). My focus in this paper is to ask: what
precisely is it to “speak” this language in an analysis of the structure of the
George Vassilacopoulos 143
II.
Heidegger's contention is that his thinking deals with what is fundamental.
Dealing with what is fundamental suggests a fundamental encounter with
it. The encountering is never simply a result of the coming together of
already self-sufficient beings. It is there from the very beginning; or rather
it is itself the beginning. What is encountered and the agent of the
encounter are made sense of in terms of the encounter itself. This is why
144 Reflections on Heidegger’s Saying
in his most important statement about the question of being – the question
being the form of the encounter between being and Da-sein – Heidegger
draws attention to the interrelation between the asking and the asked
about:
[...] there is a notable "relatedness backward or forward" of what is asked
about (being) to asking as a mode of being of a being. The way what is
questioned essentially engages our questioning belongs to the innermost
meaning of the question of being. But this only means that the being that
has the character of Da-sein has a relation to the question of being itself,
perhaps even a distinctive one (Heidegger, 1996: 7-8).
Let us begin by noting that these insights not only emerge within the
dynamics of the question of being but they merge with the question. That
is, in giving shape to the question they allow the question to emerge and
unfold. Heidegger’s statement should not be read as an externally derived
description but as part of the question’s essential engagement of the
questioned with the corresponding questioning. Accordingly, from the
point of view of the thinker there is nothing, so to speak, beyond the
question, since it is through asking and as asking that “the being that has
the character of Da-sein” becomes an issue. Everything, including the
question as a whole, becomes an issue through the question. Moreover,
there is in the question a kind of spontaneity that determines a theoretical
vision which is made sense of in terms of the dwelling of the thinker “in”
being, that is, according to the challenge that being poses in and through
the question of its meaning.
So, the thinker emerges as a thinker insofar as he or she realises that
within the framework of the question this challenge is not simply to think
in an external and conventional manner. Rather, thinking is determined by
the willingness of Da-sein to dwell in the question of being, thus allowing
the asking to be fully determined by what already determines it, namely
being as the asked about. Heidegger thus draws our attention to the radical
nature of asking, a radicality that emanates exclusively from the encounter
with being. In the question of being, asking “loses” its status as a formal
faculty of a subject already present to itself and indifferently applied to
any “object”. In other words, the questioned as questioned is not passive
or indifferent to a questioning that exclusively belongs to the subject who
might activate it at will. On the contrary, within the framework of the
question of being the asking seems to be passive only in the sense that it
appears as the “mode of being” of Da-sein that emerges through its
dwelling in the question of being and its association with being as the
asked about. As Heidegger puts it, “asking this question, as a mode of
George Vassilacopoulos 145
to the question of being via the fact of its appearance. Accordingly, the
challenge for the thinker is in the enactment of the question out of the
reality of an understanding of being. This means that the thinker must
remain alert to the guidance of being within the framework of the question
of being. Ultimately, it is only through enacting the question in this sense
that the formality of the question may be overcome in order to enable Da-
sein concretely to deal with its mode of being as questioner. More
specifically, being’s double act of referring directly both to its implicitness
and to its disclosure makes possible Da-sein's corresponding double act.
In other words, when being discloses itself as concealed in the form of the
asked about its intimate relation to Da-sein in the mode of being of asking
also makes Da-sein’s disclosing possible and necessary. At the same time,
being’s state of concealment that is identified by being’s “backward”
relatedness to Da-sein makes possible and necessary Da-sein’s
concealment. Somehow the thinker dwells at one and the same time in
both the question of being, which is a form of being’s disclosing, and in
the concrete reality of concealment, that is the reality of an understanding
of being. The thinker becomes a thinker by withstanding this tension.
So far I have drawn attention to the mutually informing state of
concealment that the relation of being and Da-sein discloses within the
framework of the question. Following Heidegger we can read the question
of the precise nature of this mutually informing state of concealment as a
matter of how to gain the appropriate access to Da-sein:
[…] the first concern in the question of being must be an analysis of Da-
sein. But then the problem of gaining and securing the kind of access that
leads to Da-sein truly becomes crucial. Expressed negatively, no arbitrary
idea of being and reality, no matter how “self-evident” it is, may be
brought to bear on this being in a dogmatically constructed way; no
“categories” prescribed by such ideas may be forced upon Da-sein without
ontological deliberation. The manner of access and interpretation must
indeed be chosen in such a way that this being can show itself to itself on
its own terms. And furthermore, this manner should show that being as it
is initially and for the most part-in its average everydayness (Heidegger,
1996: 14-15).
III.
What is the meaning of being as the asked about and what is the
corresponding meaning of the asking? Turning to the first part of this
question note that by asking it we register an interest in providing a formal
answer to the formal question of the meaning of being. That is to say, we
register an interest in being’s formal meaning that is already presupposed
in so far as being performs the role of the asked about. Posed more
precisely, the first part of our question is: what is the meaning of being
insofar as being makes its meaning an issue within the framework of the
question of being?
One obvious strategy in response is to analyse the role that being
performs as the asked about. We know that being makes itself an issue as
the asked about – being is disclosed as concealed – through engaging with
the asking incorporated in the question of being. In other words being is
disclosed as questioned in the disclosing provided by the corresponding
questioning. Simultaneously, however, and through a reversal of roles due
to the mutual informing of the questioned and the questioning, as
1
On Parvis Emad’s analysis of the structure of the question of being we move
from the discovery that the being to be interrogated is situated in an understanding
of being to the “conjoined appearance of questioning and understanding of being”
and from this we see that being essentially determines questioning and the
questioner as the mode of being of a being (Emad, 2002: 20). However, it is not
clear from Emad’s discussion how he thinks that the structure of the question
renders this visible.
150 Reflections on Heidegger’s Saying
disclosed in the disclosing that asking is, the asked about is transformed
into a disclosing in which asking is disclosed. Consequently, both the
asked about (being) and the asking (Da-sein) function as disclosing and
disclosed. The asked about is the asked about and it also engages with the
asking only if, by being disclosed in asking, it discloses what discloses it,
namely asking. Being incorporates into itself the asking by becoming the
disclosing of the asking and, as a result, itself becoming the asked about as
disclosed.
It follows from this line of thinking that, immanent to being, there is a
differentiation: being is both disclosed as concealed and disclosing. What
is the significance of this? Since it belongs to the essence of the asked
about to be disclosed in the disclosing of the asking by engaging with its
own disclosing of the asking, what is asked about in the asking, or what is
questioned in the question, is disclosing. It is disclosing that, as the
disclosing of the asking in the question of being, withdraws and thus
transforms itself into the undisclosed disclosing, that is into formal, or
empty disclosing. As disclosing of the asking and thus as disclosed in the
asking, the asked about that is being as concealed is both as disclosing and
as remaining undisclosed in its own disclosing. It is the disclosing that
discloses the questioning of itself. Being’s self-relation then is a self-
withdrawing, a self-emptying. Heidegger refers to the “nothingness of
being” (Heidegger, 1996: 6, ft) and to the question of being as the “most
universal and the emptiest” (Heidegger, 1996: 35). Below, when we
discuss the meaning of the asking we will see precisely how the formality
of disclosing is manifested. Here, the point to note is that the disclosing
that the asked about is – in disclosing the asking that makes it disclosed as
undisclosed – shows itself to be disclosed as undisclosed disclosing.
So, the question of the meaning of being is the question of the meaning
of disclosing which disclosing makes itself an issue through its own
formality, or the active emptying out of itself. The disclosing in question
here is pure disclosing, disclosing as such for the reason that, as the asked
about, being directly engages with the asking, insofar as it functions as the
disclosing of its own questioning. It becomes what it is by actively
incorporating into itself what makes it what it is, namely asking. In other
words the asked about is the asked about as such, or the concealed as such.
As questioned, being belongs to itself, so to speak, and not to something
else that might somehow qualify it as questioned through an independent
questioning. Because of this, the undisclosed disclosing is disclosing as
such, or as I suggested above, formal disclosing. Here then disclosing
itself is the asked about. In other words, being engages with questioning
because being is disclosing and disclosing, as the asked about in the
George Vassilacopoulos 151
In the asking of the question of being, and as the asking, Da-sein discloses
its being as disclosing. But whereas being’s disclosing happens as its
“nothingness”, Da-sein’s disclosing involves Da-sein’s being as a whole.
As the questioner that belongs to what is questioned, Da-sein is posited as
the most disclosing, as the disclosed disclosing. Here, in the mode of
152 Reflections on Heidegger’s Saying
IV.
Although we have moved some way toward the point of activation of the
concrete phenomenological process of the analytic of Da-sein, our
elaboration of the question of being has not yet brought us to this point of
departure. Even though, as that from which its meaning will be extracted
in a self-interpreting manner, Da-sein’s being manifests the withdrawing
of the question out of which the question “grows”, this manifestation is not
George Vassilacopoulos 153
yet radical enough because it does not capture what the question of being
demands, namely, the withdrawing of Da-sein’s being as a whole. If this is
indeed required, a further step that would lead us to the state of
withdrawing, not just of Da-sein’s meaning but of Da-sein’s being as well,
is warranted here. Let us consider where and how this withdrawing is
manifested.
We know from our analysis of Da-sein's encounter with being in the
asking of the question of the meaning of being that Da-sein's being is
disclosing. Bearing in mind that Heidegger refers to Da-sein as self-
concern given that Da-sein’s being is always “mine” (Heidegger, 1996:
35) we can ask: what precisely is involved in this disclosing for the being
whose essence it is to be concerned with its being in its being? Now the
characteristic of Da-sein’s concern is that it contributes ontologically to
that about which it is concerned. From this it follows, rather dramatically,
that Da-sein withdraws in its concern as concern when its concern is
directed to something other than Da-sein, in a way that Da-sein’s concern
with it directly contributes to this other’s being. Here Da-sein's concern
needs to be directed elsewhere than to Da-sein. This calls for an object to
which Da-sein is related in a way that takes one beyond the metaphysics
of the subject/object dichotomy. This non-metaphysical encounter must
disclose the being of the object in and through Da-sein's concern. That is
to say, it must disclose it, not as something that pre-exists its encounter
with Da-sein, but as something that takes shape in the very act of Da-
sein’s concern.
In and as this act of concern the object's being is made explicit as no-
concern. No-concern and concern thus merge into a mutual non-reflective
belonging. The object's being becomes an issue through the non-
becoming of an issue of Da-sein's being. In such an encounter Da-sein is
concerned, without however encountering its concern in the sense of
coming back to itself, so to speak. Consequently, in its concern with
beings other than itself, Da-sein's whole being is involved without Da-sein
being its whole. Da-sein's being is completely withdrawn, or “absorbed”,
in Da-sein’s concern with beings other than itself. It is withdrawn in that
its withdrawing is itself withdrawn. Here, of course, we can refer to Da-
sein’s preoccupation with the handiness of handy things and to the
instrumentality of the instrument (Marion, 1991: 237) forming part of
being-in-the-world, and whose analysis marks the initial developmental
stages of Being and Time. Accordingly, the thinker begins the analytic of
Da-sein with Da-sein’s dealings with equipment, not because this is what
is most obviously and naturally observable around him or her, but because
154 Reflections on Heidegger’s Saying
Da-seins might ask the question of being. Yet actually asking it requires
radicalising Da-sein’s individuality by transcending the state of the “they”
in the way that Heidegger attempts in Being and Time.
If our analysis so far has merit, it follows that in the developmental
momentum of the thinker’s engagement with being-in-the-world, the next
radical step is the liberation of Da-sein's being from its “absorption” in the
world (Heidegger, 1996: 51). This raises the question of how one moves
from a perspective internal, so to speak, to the withdrawing of Da-sein's
being as concern in its dealings with entities, to concern itself? The task
that the question of being dictates here is for Da-sein to return to itself by
ridding itself of its being's withdrawing that is registered in the encounter
with beings other than Da-sein. This task has two aspects or moments:
Da-sein needs to liberate itself and, at the same time, to locate from within
the site of its liberation the fundamentals of its being. Given Da-sein’s
radical “absorption” in the world, such liberation could only be achieved
through an equally radical crisis. This crisis would need to be powerful
enough to disconnect Da-sein's being from this association with the world
by turning violently against its withdrawing in the world. This can be
achieved only if it is possible for Da-sein to incorporate into itself the no-
concern that belongs to the being of entities and to associate this with its
concern. In other words, Da-sein must be in a position to liberate its being
from entities as the being that it is by showing that this being is the no-
concern of concern. Consequently, it must make its being withdraw as a
precondition for being disclosed as disclosing from within itself. The no-
concern of concern is expressed by Angst whose radicality, as Heidegger
suggests, is expressed in the fact that it has no particular object. For this
reason Angst introduces a fundamental change of direction in the
development of Being and Time, one that is more radical than that between
“Division One” and “Division Two”.
I have argued that for its initial and fundamental disclosing Da-sein is
guided by being and being guides itself through what it provides to Da-
sein since asking emanates from the asked about which asked about comes
to be in the enactment of the asking. This appearance of being in the form
of the asked about, and its role in the question of being, is what Being and
Time, and for that matter the whole of Heidegger’s project, requires for its
activation. Precisely because we gain access to being as that which is
asked about through the question of the meaning of being it is the formal
structure of the question that reflectively situates us in an understanding of
being and in being’s guiding significance.
156 Reflections on Heidegger’s Saying
Bibliography
Emad, 2002
Parvis Emad, “The question of being: Foremost hermeneutic pre-
condition for interpreting Heidegger”, Enrahonar 34: 11-29.
Heidegger, 1996
Martin Heidegger, Being and Time. Trans. J. Stambaugh. Albany:
SUNY Press.
Heidegger, 1998
Martin Heidegger, Parmenides. Trans. A. Schuwer and R. Rojcewicz.
Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Marion, 1991
Jean-Luc Marion, “L’Interloque”. In Who Comes after the Subject?,
ed. E. Cadava, P. Connor, J.-L. Nancy: 236-245. New York and
London: Routledge.
Nicolacopoulos and Vassilacopoulos, 1999
Toula Nicolacopoulos and George Vassilacopoulos, Hegel and the
Logical Structure of Love: An Essay on Sexualities Family and the
Law. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Richardson, 1963
William J. Richardson, Heidegger Through Phenomenology to
Thought. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Sheehan, 2001
Thomas Sheehan, “Kehre and Ereignis: A Prolegomenon to
Introduction to Metaphysics”. In A Companion to Heidegger’s
Introduction to Metaphysics, eds. R. Polt and G. Fried: 3-16. New
Haven and London: Yale University Press.
ART, TRUTH AND FREEDOM: CONTEMPLATING
HEIDEGGER’S CATEGORIAL VISION
COLIN HEARFIELD
A. Categorial Vision
Categorial vision may seem a strange, if not erroneous way of naming the
manner in which Heidegger discloses the ontological essence of art, truth
and freedom. For with Heidegger, the term "categorial" pertains solely to
the ontological characteristics of things present-at-hand (Heidegger,
1962a: 79); that is, things which remain categorially distinct from the
temporal structures or "existentialia" of Dasein. Furthermore, categorial
vision is usually associated with Husserl’s scientifically nuanced
phenomenology concerning the intuited revelation of objective essences
beyond the psychological relativism of subjectively constituted facts. Yet
Heidegger’s ontology of Being, despite its more poetic, hermeneutic mode
of thinking, is nonetheless closely modeled on Husserl’s anti-idealist
attempt to overcome the intractable dualism of subject/object relations
through the categorial vision of pre-reflective essences. Both are
concerned with dismantling the transcendental conditions of categorical or
conceptual identity, what Heidegger refers to as the metaphysics of
presence dominant since Plato.
The aporia of a finitely constituted yet infinitely constituting
transcendental subject blocks the path to an intuitive, categorial vision of
the truth of what is. Accordingly, for both Husserl and Heidegger, what is
imperative in this process is to allow what is other, the things themselves,
to speak for themselves. This becomes possible, at least for Heidegger, in
an appreciation of the ontological difference between being and not-being,
in the fact that what is is rather than is not. Now insofar as the vision of
the essential truth of being emerges from this unprovocative letting-be of
what is and gives it projective expression then it is categorial. This claim
may be set in relief by way of brief reference to Kant’s transcendental
schematism. Without delving into the imagistic complexities of these
158 Art, Truth and Freedom: Contemplating Heidegger’s Categorial Vision
thus remains unable to think the essential truth of art as the historical
shaping of community. Heidegger, however, also perceives signs of a
distinctly non-aesthetic, non-metaphysical approach to art in both Plato
and Kant; and it is precisely this attempt to clarify what might constitute a
non-aesthetic approach to art which motivates "The Origin" essay
(Bernstein, 1992: 131).
Heidegger’s account of the happening of truth in the Greek temple is
prefaced on Plato’s view of the beautiful. And Heidegger interprets Plato’s
view of the beautiful in the following manner; he states:
[t]he beautiful is what advances most directly upon us and captivates us.
While encountering us as a being, however, it at the same time liberates us
to the view upon Being. The beautiful is an element which is disparate
within itself; it grants entry into immediate sensuous appearances and yet
at the same time soars towards Being; it is both captivating and liberating.
Hence it is the beautiful that snatches us from oblivion of Being and grants
the view upon Being (Heidegger, 1979-1987: 196).
This now gives us an initial glimpse into our earlier unanswered question
as to how truth sets itself to work in the Greek temple. Indeed "the lighting
projection of truth" (Heidegger, 1971: 73) occurs precisely as those
categorial schemata present in the work, namely "the setting up of a world
and the setting forth of earth" (Heidegger, 1971: 48).
Setting up a world is the opening of a clearing, which grants passage to
an understanding of beings we are not and of our own essential being. This
opening or "lighting" is in varying degrees an unconcealing of the
historical scope of a people’s destiny. For a work to set up a world,
however, it must do so through earthly materials, which, whether stone,
wood, pigment or linguistic utterance, all pertain to the setting forth of
earth in the work. In setting forth the earth, the work sets itself back on the
self-dependent yet self-secluding character of earth. As self-secluding,
earth remains in some measure a concealing of both itself and what we
encounter in the world opening before us. This concealing concerns a limit
or refusal of knowledge beyond the historical clearing opened by the work
as well as a dissembling of truth where what appears in the clearing is at
times deceptive or obscured by other beings in the clearing. Without being
wholly reduced to untruth, earth is nevertheless the source of untruth.
Insofar as setting up a world is dependent on the setting forth of earth, then
this double concealment is itself a condition and limit of the unconcealing
happening in the work. The manner in which truth sets itself to work in the
great work of art now reveals itself as a constant striving of earth and
world against the other; a battle between what is concealing and
unconcealing, between the absence and presence of truth.
The question, however, of how truth establishes itself or makes itself
known in the "primal conflict" (Heidegger, 1971: 60) of world and earth
remains unanswered. Truth is established or brought forth, Heidegger
indicates, when earth and world "move apart because of [their conflict]"
(Heidegger, 1971: 61). What is brought forth in this opening is the specific
createdness of the work; a truth which itself engenders the conflict of earth
and world and which stands fixed in the figure or shape of that conflict as
the work’s createdness. The schematic image of this establishment of truth
as the createdness of the work is articulated as rift.
This rift carries the opponents into the source of their unity by virtue of
their common ground. It is a basic design, an outline sketch, that draws the
basic feature of the rise of the lighting of beings. This rift does not let the
opponents break apart; it brings the opposition of measure and boundary
into their common outline (Heidegger, 1971: 63).
162 Art, Truth and Freedom: Contemplating Heidegger’s Categorial Vision
The rift, then, establishes the intimate belonging together of earth and
world within their difference. As the schematic image of a work’s self-
appropriating createdness, the rift "must be set back into the earth"
(Heidegger, 1971: 64). For only in this way, Heidegger continues, will the
work’s createdness stand out from what is created in the work. The rift-
design, as Bernstein indicates, is Heidegger’s displacement of the
potentiality for the schemata of world and earth away from the
transcendental imagination of Kant’s genius-artist to the work of art itself
(Bernstein, 1992: 122). Indeed the schemata of world and earth made
possible by the rift-design are the categorial transfiguration of Kant’s
transcendental aesthetic schemata of form and matter (Bernstein, 1992:
118). While both situate the hidden origin of this schematic design in
earth/nature, for Heidegger it does not manifest in the transcendental
imagination of the artist but rather in the createdness of the work itself
(Heidegger, 1971: 70).
Bibliography
Adorno, 1940
T. W. Adorno, "Husserl and the Problem of Idealism", The Journal of
Philosophy 37(1): 5-18.
Adorno, 1973
T. W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics [1966]. Trans. E. B. Ashton. New
York: Continuum.
Bernstein, 1992
J. Bernstein, The Fate of Art: Aesthetic Alienation from Kant to
Derrida and Adorno. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Heidegger, 1962a
M. Heidegger, Being and Time [1927]. Trans. J. Macquarie and E.
Robinson. New York: Harper and Row.
Heidegger, 1962b
M. Heidegger, "Letter on Humanism" [1947]. Trans. E. Lohner, in
Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, eds. W. Barrett and H. Aiken, 4
vols., vol. 3: 271-302. New York: Random House.
Heidegger, 1979-1987
M. Heidegger, Nietzsche [1961]. Trans. D. F. Krell, 4 vols., vol. 1. San
Francisco: Harper.
Heidegger, 1971
M. Heidegger, "The Origin of the Work of Art" [1936]. Trans. A.
Hofstadter, in Poetry, Language, Thought: 15-86. New York: Harper
and Row, 1971.
THE WORK AND THE PROMISE
OF TECHNOLOGY
JOHN DALTON
1
Though according to Young, despite Heidegger’s general disdain for modern art
as intergrated into the destitution of modern techno-science, he is said to have had
a “great love” and high esteem for Le Corbusier, alongside a range of other
modern artists and figures. At any rate, an examination must await another
occasion. See Julian Young, Heidegger’s Philosophy of Art (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001).
2
Technics and technology are not synonymous. Technics (Techne, “la technique”,
“die Technik”) refers to the meaning or Wesen of technology, while technology
refers to artefacts or domains of technical action (industry, science, linguistics,
cyberspace, digital media, etc). These objects or domains need not be mechanistic,
digital, etc., but are formed or structured by a logistics that is “technical” (e.g.,
analytic language). However, this model of technics is derived from technology.
The thinking of technics here is technics as repetition/iteration, and so does not
166 The Work and the Promise of Technology
the question of how to form and judge oneself as a “who” among a “we”?
Already too late, the aesthetic saves itself by way of a recursive fixation
with its own epistemological crisis. Aesthetics becomes critique of
aesthetics, sustaining itself in the dialectic of judgement wherein art and
literature become the apologists for philosophy’s (Idealism’s) finitude.
Aesthetics figure the redemptive unity of art and life for which it
prophetically longs, yet interminably defers. For the Heidegger of The
Origin of the Work of Art, aesthetics forecloses its own ontological
dimension. The end of art is the loss of art as a historically meaningful
way of being. The frame for the later thinking of art and technics can be
found as early as the 1936-1938 Beiträge (as well as the Nietzsche
lectures, which cannot be addressed here). The decision for art becomes
again one of historical necessity and recovery—“whether art is an
exhibition for lived experience (Erleben) or the setting-into-work of truth”
(Heidegger, 1999: 63).
As a reflective judgement in search of its concept, the aesthetic
signifies the form of finality apart from the representation of an end. Yet
the contrary is affirmed. Art becomes a moral-politics insofar as it
assumes the legislative form of judgement. As a “philosophy” of art,
aesthetics is concerned with the condition of the possibility and the limits
of the concept of “art”. We are immediately engaged in the Kantian
problematic. Human reason, Kant insists, is by nature architectonic. If the
schematism should translate categories of understanding into forms
intuitable by sensibility, the architectonic falters on the very Idea of the
subject. The subject is but the regulative Idea of the unity of its own
representations. The Kantian aesthetic is rather the crisis of the
presentation of the Idea of the subject. Art gives an adequate presentation
of the Idea only on the basis of the relation between judgement and
transcendental imagination (Einbildungskraft). Yet aesthetic judgement
lacks a concept. Understanding and sensibility can only achieve a unity
through the external form of consensus—through the Idea of nature as
purposive yet represented by the form of a historical community. The
aesthetic is a formative work, and thereby, technical (this, it should be
noted, leads into Romanticism and the themes of aesthetic education and
the state as a work of art)4. Art becomes the ergon of the unique and
redemptive expression of life or matter. As the technical prothesis of
redemption, aesthetics becomes the via negativa of representation, the
figure of alienated modernity. Another thinking of technics may, on the
4
To pursue these themes in the detail they require, see J.M Bernstein, The Fate of
Art (University Park, Pa: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992).
168 The Work and the Promise of Technology
5
It is not possible to offer a detailed or historico-philosophical account here of
Heidegger’s relation to Aristotle—rather, certain general or structural features of
both early and later Heidegger can be addressed. For good accounts of Heidegger’s
relation to Aristotle, see Ted Sadler, Heidegger and Aristotle: the Question of
Being (London and New Jersey: Athlone, 1996) and Walter A. Brogan, Heidegger
and Aristotle (Buffalo: State University of New York Press, 2006).
John Dalton 171
6
For a more precise account see Thomas Sheehan, “Heidegger’s Philosophy of
Mind,” Contemporary Philosophy: A New Survey, ed G. Floistad, vol. IV,
Philosophy of Mind: 237-318 (Nijhoff: The Hague, 1984).
172 The Work and the Promise of Technology
7
Space prohibits the valuable exploration of Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition.
John Dalton 173
And further:
In enowning, the history of being has not so much reached its end, as that it
now appears as history of being. There is no destinal epoch of enowning.
Sending is from enowning (Das Schicken ist aus dem Ereignen)
(Heidegger, 2003: 61).
8
We cannot assume that ancient Greek technology did not engage the violence we
associate with modern industralization, etc. Here, Young makes the point that for
Heidegger, modern technology constrains objects and beings to appear as nothing
but resource. As will be argued presently, this depends upon the priority of poeisis
over techne. See Julian Young, Heidegger’s Later Philosophy: 37-62 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2002).
174 The Work and the Promise of Technology
9
We should note the etymological connection between Machenschaft and Macht
(power), as well as Heidegger’s reading of Nietzsche’s Wille zur Macht as the
apotheosis of the “nihilistic will-to-will”.
John Dalton 175
All that is needed is a ready and willing glance into our atomic age in order
to see that if God is dead, as Nietzsche says, the calculated world still
remains and everywhere includes humans in its reckoning inasmuch as it
reckons everything to the principium rationis (Heidegger, 1991: 101).
10
In the 1962 essay Überlieferte Sprache und Technische Sprache, Heidegger
admonishes the “violence” against language in the form of linguistics,
functionalism, and analytic symbolism. Language becomes “information” spoken
by the Sprachmaschine (language-machine). Martin Heidegger, “Traditional
Language and Technological Language,” trans. Wanda Torres Gregory, Journal of
Philosophical Research, 23 (1998).
178 The Work and the Promise of Technology
perhaps only for that brief but magnificent time? Why did art bear the
modest name techne? Because it was a revealing that brought forth and
hither, and therefore belonged within poiesis. It was finally that revealing
which holds complete sway in all the fine arts, in poetry, and in everything
poetical that obtained poiesis as its proper name (Heidegger, 1977: 34).
11
“[...] the object of scientific knowledge is necessary. Therefore it is eternal,
because everything that is necessary, without qualification, is eternal, and what is
eternal does not come into being or cease to be.” Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics:
1139b.
180 The Work and the Promise of Technology
that opens itself in the work can never be verified or derived from what
went before. In its exclusive reality, what went before is refuted by the
work. What art founds, therefore, can never be compensated and made
good in terms of what is present and available for use. The founding is an
overflowing, a bestowal (Heidegger, 2002: 47).
A work, by being a work, allows a space for that spaciousness. “To allow a
space” here means, in particular: to make free the free of the open and to
install this free place in its structure [...]. As a work, the work holds open
the open of a world (Heidegger, 2002: 23).
Heidegger clarifies his thinking at the very end of the Artwork essay.
He will not, at any point, mention Aristotle by name. He will, instead,
convict the translation of Greek into Latin: the forma of beauty that takes
it light from Being takes from a Being already thought as eidos. Form, or
morphe, is already predicated of the organon (work). In turn, actuality
becomes veritas, objectivity, lived experience and representation. And
finally, aesthetics.
But art and the work of art are not the formless. Art is not chaos. The
work of art is gathered into the ontological fold as presenting the very
difference or strife between being and beings, between world and earth. In
an extraordinary passage, Heidegger writes:
This strife which is brought into the rift-design, and so set back into the
earth and fixed in place, is the figure (Gestalt). The createdness of the
work means: the fixing in place of truth in the figure. Figure is the
structure of the rift in its self-establishment. The structured rift is the
jointure (Fuge) of the shining of truth. What we here call “figure” is
John Dalton 181
The Riss brings world and earth, being and beings, into a shared
outline (Umriss). This shared outline cannot be thought any other way
than as the form of a relation, the structure or fundamental design
(Grundriss) of the ontological difference.
The truth of the difference, or the thinking of the being as a being, the
disclosure of the being in its ontological-eidetic meaning as the factical
implication of a historical world, is a placement or a framing of the very
method and logic of Heidegger’s ontology. At issue then is the technics of
originary thinking, its design or figuration of an “event” that makes
possible ontology itself. The very placement and framing of the Riss as
ontological difference is the framing (the placement and the form) of the
thinking of the origin itself, and in turn, Ereignis. Both the ontological
difference and the event may be read as a technics that sets-into-work a
kinetic poiesis as an ontologised techne.
Originary Technics?
A technics addressed as a setting-into-work of truth is a technics
thought ontologically and ethically. By thinking facticity as ethos,
technology is always already within a horizon of responsibility. What is
unique about modern technology, however, is that as a figure of futurity,
technology exceeds and so positions our horizon of responsibility. For this
reason, technology is the very “thing” that responsibility must bear upon.
Turning now to Stiegler’s Technics and Time (it is not, to say the least,
possible to rehearse the scope, significance and innovation of this work. It
is necessary to leave aside much of the demands of exposition and pass
over the “fault of Epimetheus” and the reading of Leroi-Gourhan), we can
critically focus on the essential claim of Stiegler’s argument. Indeed,
Stiegler’s account is haunted by the very anthropology it would otherwise
deconstructively delimit. Despite the brilliance of Stiegler’s reading of
Heidegger, Stiegler pushes the ontic/ontological difference and the later
thought of Ereignis back into a metaphysical anthropologism so as to
convict Heidegger of the exclusion of technics. Stiegler’s claim is that
Heidegger fails to think the question of technics adequately in that he
forecloses the role of technical supplementarity for Dasein’s finite
temporalisation. In particular, Dasein’s individuated and disclosive
temporal being-there requires the supplement of a mnemotechnics, a
182 The Work and the Promise of Technology
history of the human and the technical as the possibility of the invention of
the new while simultaneously displacing the anthropomorphism of the
modern political citizen-subject and overcoming the philosophical
repression of technics (Heidegger included). But this reinscribes history
not as the history of difference (iteration, etc), but as constrained by the
critique of modernity and the spectre of the technologisied loss of
memory. To borrow the phrase, the thorough-going “technologization of
the life-world” assumes the thesis of a quasi-technological determinism.
Technology becomes autonomous, divorced from social agency, a source
of alienation that must be overcome. The “redoublement épochal”, the
active remembering of the default of origin, cannot be guaranteed,
however, by a revitalised or rethought technics. Technics itself does not
guarantee the intentional structure of a politics (the telos of a polis) nor
less temporality itself. Technics offers no end. Hence, a politics must also
be technical and construct a telos. Politics must affirm its technicity,
without as yet reducing itself to the category of means.
Indeed, if what is at issue is a politics that bears upon political
communities “to-come”, it is the memory of the future that is at stake—the
technological possibilities for the invention of new communities. Yet
Stiegler’s politics of memory is constrained to reinscribe the critique of
technology as the enabling frame of a new politics. To cite Stiegler from
the preface to Technics and Time:
Bibliography
Beardsworth, 2003
Richard Beardsworth, "Thinking Technicity". In Jacques Derrida, vol.
3. London: Sage Publications.
Heidegger, 1999
Martin Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy (On Enowning). Trans.
Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly. Indiana and Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Heidegger, 2002
Martin Heidegger, "The Origin of the Work of Art". Trans. and ed.
Kenneth Hayes, in Off the Beaten Track. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Heidegger, 1991
Martin Heidegger, The Principle of Reason. Trans. Reginald Lily.
Indiana and Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1977
Martin Heidegger, "The Question Concerning Technology". Trans.
William Lovitt, in The Question Concerning Technology and Other
Essays. New York: Garland Publishing.
Heidegger, 2003
Martin Heidegger, "Seminar in Le Thor 1968". Trans. Andrew
Mitchell and François Raffoul, in Four Seminars. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
Stiegler, 1998
Bernard Stiegler, Technics and Time 1: The Fault of Epimetheus.
Trans. Richard Beardsworth and George Collins. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
THE AN-DENKEN OF EXISTENTIALISM:
VATTIMO’S HEIDEGGER AND THE AESTHETICS
OF LIVING
ASHLEY WOODWARD
1
According to Rockmore this orthodoxy instituted by Jean Beaufret, is
exemplified by philosophers such as Jacques Derrida and Michel Haar, and was
exported to the Anglophone academy largely through the dissemination of
deconstruction. Rockmore characterises this French “orthodox” approach to
Heidegger scholarship with three points: the tendency to interpret his earlier
writings from the perspective of his later work, to see Heidegger’s thought as
beyond philosophy, and to minimise the significance of his involvement with
Nazism (Rockmore, 1995: 121). Rockmore contends that, like any orthodoxy, the
French Heideggarian orthodoxy is based on an uncritical fidelity to presupposed
truth claims which are rarely, if ever, tested (Rockmore, 1995: 124). In my
invocation of a Heideggerian orthodoxy here, I follow Rockmore only to the extent
that the genealogy of Heidegger interpretation he proposes explains the widespread
uncritical acceptance of Heidegger’s characterisation of Sartre in the “Letter on
humanism”. Indeed, the view that Sartre was wholly mistaken in his reading of
Heidegger is one part of the orthodoxy which Rockmore himself seems to
uncritically accept.
192 The An-Denken of Existentialism: Vattimo’s Heidegger
and the Aesthetics of Living
2
Quoted by Heidegger in Heidegger, 1993: 237.
Ashley Woodward 193
3
Unorthdox, but not unique. In fact, when Vattimo’s book The End of Modenity
(Vattimo, 1988) was translated into German, some commentators complained that
his reading of Heidegger was not original (Barbiero, 1992: 165).
194 The An-Denken of Existentialism: Vattimo’s Heidegger
and the Aesthetics of Living
4
See the explanation of Heidegger’s term Verwindung below.
5
On this point, we might recall Heidegger’s complaint, in “On the question of
Being”, that “[p]eople have tended to represent the 'oblivion of being' as though to
say it by way of an image, being were the umbrella that has been left sitting
somewhere through the forgetfulness of some philosophy professor” (Heidegger,
1998a: 314).
Ashley Woodward 195
[a]ll we can say about Being at this point is that it consists in trans-mission,
in forwarding or destiny: Ueber-lieferung and Ge-schick. The world plays
itself out in horizons constructed by a series of echoes, linguistic
responses, and messages coming from the past and from others (others
along side us as well as other cultures) […]. Being never really is but sends
itself, is on the way, it trans-mits itself (Vattimo, 1984: 157).
6
Vattimo develops this reading of Heidegger most fully in his paper “An-Denken.
Thinking and the foundation” in Vattimo, 1993.
7
This influence is unsurprising; Vattimo studied with Gadamer, and translated his
Truth and Method (Gadamer, 1989) into Italian.
8
For a concise statement of Vattimo’s reading of Gadamer, see Vattimo, 2002.
196 The An-Denken of Existentialism: Vattimo’s Heidegger
and the Aesthetics of Living
9
While Vattimo often focuses his analyses on philosophical texts, he points to
other cultural factors as contributing to this ontology of decline. Indeed, one of the
most interesting aspects of Vattimo’s work is the way he traces relationships
between the philosophical developments of thinkers such as Nietzsche and
Heidegger and developments in culture. Vattimo relates the ontology of decline to
the end of colonialism and the rise of mass media in the “Introduction” to The End
of Modernity (Vattimo, 1988). More recently (and perhaps more contentiously), he
has related this ontology to the advent and development of Christianity (Vattimo,
1999).
Ashley Woodward 197
The best in us has perhaps been inherited from the feelings of former
times, feelings which today can hardly be approached on direct paths; the
sun has already set, but our life’s sky glows and shines with it still,
although we no longer see it (Nietzsche, 1984: 137).
10
Most importantly for Vattimo, in the first essay of Heidegger’s Identity and
Difference (Heidegger, 1974). Heidegger also uses the term in the context of a
discussion of nihilism in “On the question of Being” (Heidegger, 1998a).
11
Vattimo’s most thorough analysis of the term Verwindung, on which I have
drawn here, is in Vattimo, 1988: 172-3.
Ashley Woodward 199
insofar as Ge-schick does not merely hand down Wirkungen [effects], but
also specific traces, elements that have not actually become the world: the
ruins accumulated by history at the feet of Klee’s angel (Vattimo, 1984:
163).
[…] liberation from the exclusive bond to its historical context puts Dasein
itself in a state of suspension; a suspension which touches him in his
deepest constitution as subject (and it is in this sense that I believe
Heidegger’s antisubjectivism is to be read).
What then can be said for the continuity that constitutes subjective life
(even on a psychological level), when the latter turns out to be marked in
its very structure by the discontinuity of the Ab-grund [abyss]? Are we not
in the very same situation described by Nietzsche in The Gay Science,
when he speaks in aphorism 54 about "the consciousness that I am
dreaming and that I must go on dreaming"? Nietzsche’s work clearly
shows that all this has vast implications for the mode of thinking the I as
individuality/identity (Vattimo, 1993: 128).
12
Briefly, these terms have the following meaning for Sartre. States are inert,
passive modes of consciousness, such as emotions. Actions encompass both
physical actions and psychical actions (such as doubting, reasoning, or meditating).
Qualities are potentialities for particular states or actions, such as “failings, virtues,
tastes, talents, tendencies, instincts, etc.” (Sartre, 2004: 28).
202 The An-Denken of Existentialism: Vattimo’s Heidegger
and the Aesthetics of Living
13
For example, in this lecture Sartre states: “Our point of departure is, indeed, the
subjectivity of the individual, and that for strictly philosophic reasons. It is not
because we are bourgeois, but because we seek to base our teaching on the truth,
and not upon a collection of fine theories, full of hope but lacking real foundations.
And at the point of departure there cannot be any other truth than this, I think,
therefore I am, which is the absolute truth of consciousness as it attains to
itself…outside of the Cartesian cogito, all objects are no more than probable, and
any doctrine of probabilities which is not attached to a truth will crumble into
nothing” (Sartre, 1960: 360-1).
14
Tilottama Rajan supports this view, arguing that “when Heidegger ‘corrects’
Sartre, he reduces the latter’s work metonymically to Existentialism is a
Humanism…” (Rajan, 2002: 56).
Ashley Woodward 203
[T]o say that we invent values means no more nor less than this; that there
is no sense in life a priori. Life is nothing until it is lived; but it is yours to
make sense of, and the value of it is nothing else but the sense that you
choose (Sartre, 1975: 367-8).
So how does one choose values? It is here that the aesthetic character of
living becomes evident. Drawing a parallel between the artist who paints a
canvas and the choice of moral values, Sartre writes:
As everyone knows, there are no aesthetic values a priori, but there are
values which will appear in due course in the coherence of the picture, in
the relation between the will to create and the finished work […]. We are
15
In Being and Nothingness the notion of consciousness as a transcendental field is
abandoned, but the spontaneous, transcendent nature of consciousness that it
supports is maintained and extended.
204 The An-Denken of Existentialism: Vattimo’s Heidegger
and the Aesthetics of Living
in the same creative situation […]. There is this in common between art
and morality, that in both we have to do with creation and invention. We
cannot decide a priori what it is that should be done (Sartre, 1975: 364).
[…] in this world where I engage myself, my acts cause values to spring up
like partridges (Sartre, 1956: 76).
Bibliography
Barbiero, 1992
Daniel Barbiero, “A weakness for Heidegger: the German root of il
penserio debole”, New German Critique 55: 159-72.
Benjamin, 1999
Walter Benjamin, “Theses on the philosophy of history” [1940]. Trans.
Harry Zorn. In Illuminations, ed. Hannah Arendt. London: Pimlico.
Carravetta, 1991
Peter Carravetta, Prefaces to the Diaphora: Rhetorics, Allegory, and
the Interpretation of Postmodernity. West Lafayette, Indiana: Perdue
University Press.
Fox, 2003
Nik Farrell Fox, The New Sartre: Explorations in Postmodernism.
London and New York: Continuum.
Gadamer, 1989
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method [1960]. Trans. Joel
Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. New York: Continuum.
Heidegger, 1972
Martin Heidegger, On Time and Being [1962]. Trans. Joan Stambaugh.
New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, 1974
Martin Heidegger, Identity and Difference [1957]. Trans. Joan
Stambaugh. New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, 1991
Martin Heidegger, The Principle of Reason [1955-6]. Trans. Reginald
Lilly. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1993
Martin Heidegger, “Letter on humanism” [1946]. Trans. Frank A.
Capuzzi in collaboration with J. Glenn Gray. In Martin Heidegger:
Basic Writings, ed. David Farrell Krell. New York: Harper Collins.
206 The An-Denken of Existentialism: Vattimo’s Heidegger
and the Aesthetics of Living
Heidegger, 1998a
Martin Heidegger, “On the question of Being” [1955]. Trans. William
McNeill. In Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Heidegger, 1998b
Martin Heidegger, “On the essence of ground” [1928]. Trans. William
McNeill. In Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Howells, 1988
Christina Howells, Sartre: The Necessity of Freedom. Cambridgeshire
and New York: Cambridge University Press.
Nietzsche, 1984
Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All-Too-Human. Trans. Marion Faber and
Stephen Lehmann. London: Penguin.
Rajan, 2002
Tilottama Rajan, Deconstruction and the Remainders of
Phenomenology: Sartre, Derrida, Foucault, Baudrillard. Stanford,
California: Stanford University Press.
Rockmore, 1995
Tom Rockmore, Heidegger and French Philosophy: Humanism,
Antihumanism, and Being. London and New York: Routledge.
Sartre, 1956
Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness [1943]. Trans. Hazel E.
Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.
Sartre, 1975
Jean-Paul Sartre, “Existentialism is a humanism” [1946]. Trans. Philip
Mairet. In Existentialism from Doestoevsky to Sartre, ed. Walter
Kaufmann. New York: Meridian.
Sartre, 2004
Jean-Paul Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego: A Sketch for a
Phenomenological Description [1937]. Trans. Andrew Brown. London
and New York: Routledge.
Vattimo, 1984
Gianni Vattimo, “Dialectics, difference, and weak thought”. Trans.
Thomas Harrison. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 10: 165-177.
Vattimo, 1988
Gianni Vattimo, The End of Modernity: Nihilism and Hermeneutics in
Post-Modern Culture. Trans. John R. Snyder. Baltimore: John Hopkins
University Press.
Ashley Woodward 207
Vattimo, 1993
Gianni Vattimo, The Adventure of Difference: Philosophy after
Nietzsche and Heidegger. Trans. Cyprian Blamires with Thomas
Harrison. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Vattimo, 1997
Gianni Vattimo, Beyond Interpretation: The Meaning of Hermeneutics
for Philosophy. Trans. David Webb. Stanford: Stanford University
Press.
Vattimo, 1999
Gianni Vattimo, Belief. Trans. Luca D'Isanto and David Webb.
Cambridge: Polity, 1999.
Vattimo, 2002
Gianni Vattimo, “Gadamer and the Problem of Ontology”. Trans.
Stefano Franchi. In Gadamer's Century: Essays in Honor of Hans-
Georg Gadamer, ed. Jeff Malpas, Ulrich Arnswald, and Jens
Kertscher. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER AND THE ALETHEIA
OF HIS GREEKS
VRASIDAS KARALIS
1
“I know how hard it is in Latin verse/ To tell the dark discoveries of the Greeks,/
Chiefly because our pauper-speech must find / Strange terms to fit the strangeness
of the thing” (trans. W.E. Leonard).
216 Martin Heidegger and the Aletheia of his Greeks
from within our own mental structure and philosophical conditioning. This
would not only be impossible but even undesirable. Plato is not Plato’s
Plato after Aristotle; and Plato-after-Aristotle is not the same as Plato
Christianus, or Plato Neoplatonicus, or Plato Hegelianus and so forth.
Heidegger approaches the Greeks from the vantage point of having
studied their legacy and the tradition of philosophising they established in
Europe. His perception of them finds in their name a beginning, the origin
and the source of a specific way of thinking – and irrespective of what that
specific way of thinking entails, it is still the beginning of our way of
thinking. Heidegger and indeed German philosophy since romanticism
was obsessed with the question of origins, therefore with the problem of
time. As it is well-known, the secularisation of temporality after the
French Enlightenment led to the disappearance of a providential god or of
an implied eschatology and replaced it with the idea of an endlessly open
and continuously incomplete progress. This had as a consequence the
strong sense of existing-in-time, of temporality and temporal conscience,
in order to situate the thinking subject within such infinity which abolished
all sense of a situated self. Religious temporality placed individuals within
a plan of gradual unfolding; the individual could locate his or her space
and could articulate his or her subjectivity by employing the symbolic
network of associations established by religious myths and more
specifically Christian metaphors. Post-Enlightenment thinking privileged
time because it was afraid of space: the very locus of existence became a
moment of negation and annulment, feeling was strongly internalised by
the emotive language of romanticism. In that process which was rendered
more shaky Charles Darwin’s blind contingency of humanity, or Sigmund
Freud’s destructive introspective conscience, time and temporality
emerged as interpretive principles to account for the disappearance of
space.
Heidegger continued the romantic tradition about the Greeks, despite
being fully aware of its limitations. He continues it in a rather complex
and highly controversial manner, starting with his early approaches to
Plato and then through to the gradual discovery of the Pre-Socratics. We
know of course that when Heidegger talked about the Greeks he meant
Parmenides, Heraclitus, Plato and Aristotle. Diogenes Laertius, the first
historian of philosophy, believed that all Greek philosophy culminated
with the work of Epicurus. The Pre-Socratics, Plato and Aristotle were the
stepping stones towards the completion of philosophy in his work. For
Heidegger however, the Greeks were the names and the words defined by
Hegel: “En” is the word of Parmenides; “logos” is the word of
Heraclitus”; “idea” is the word of Plato; “energeia” is the word of
220 Martin Heidegger and the Aletheia of his Greeks
Aristotle. All these words define the horizon of the word “being” in Greek
and the way that the Greek word for “being”, that is einai, is in its essence
aletheia; for Heidegger aletheia can not be found in the Latin “veritas”.
According to him, aletheia is not accuracy or truthfulness or even fidelity.
Aletheia, he translates, is “esse”, being in its originary, primordial,
essence. It partakes with all words mentioned above; en, logos, idea and
energeia but it is the foundational structure (being) of all of them. It exists
within them and within the totality of the Greek language since Greek is
the language of philosophy and thus its aletheia must or simply points
towards ousia. Now the question arises if aletheia is ousia; how are
disclosed-ness and presence-ness linked? Is aletheia the negation of
Dasein, of the historical being in its “throwness” in society? It is
interesting to remember here that when in the 60s Heidegger visited
Greece, he talked about the “increasing desolation of the modern Dasein”
(Heidegger, 2005: 44) as if the aletheia of “us today” is concealed and
subsumed under modernity and “the chains of calculatory planning”
(Heidegger, 2005: 44).
Unquestionably Heidegger has located a very serious philosophical
problem; how language, unconceals the concealed essence of being. What
then is the relation between language and mental energy? In one Ƞf his last
seminars in 1969, he reverted to Parmenides and stated that “aletheia was
visible to the Greeks in the form of IJȠ ĮȣIJȩ of ȞȠİȚȞ and İȓȞĮȚ as expressed
in the poem of Parmenides” (Heidegger, 2003: 39). Certainly this is one of
the most controversial ideas of Greek philosophy. Parmenides states that
“to gar auto noein esti te kai einai”: “For the same thing both can be
thought and can be” (Waterfield, 2000: 58); “For it is the same thing that
can be thought and that can be”; (Burnet, 1958: 173).
The sentence can be interpreted in many different ways since its syntax
is extremely ambiguous. The equation of being and thinking resulted in a
rather strong association of being with logos and then, in the Greek
context, logos with power and social authority especially with the
Sophists. Furthermore Heidegger linked aletheia with the act of revealing
in a physical sense. In the same text he stressed that “for the Greeks
ĮȜȒșİȚĮ is visible as ȜȩȖȠȢ and ȜȩȖȠȢ means, much more originally than to
'speak': to let presencing” (Heidegger, 2003: 39). This is a very important
statement but it refers again only to a limited number of philosophers.
Paradoxically it bears the ring of the Sophist’s extolment of language as
public performance and parrhesia. Logos from the Greek lego means, as
Heidegger perceptively observed, to gather around, to collect. So is made
language the locus of convergence and confluence of the potential
diversity of the phenomena. So if we associate logos with aletheia, noein
Vrasidas Karalis 221
for Socrates and Plato, aletheia was temporalised cognition, the ability to
establish formal analogies between what is understood and how it is
understood. Aletheia meant responsivity between the seer and the seen, a
relation of mutual interpenetration: the knowing subject changes its forms
of understanding as the known object is resignified. The knower is
transformed by what is known: this is the Greek understanding of aletheia.
In the Greek understanding of the word there is nothing to be un-veiled or
to be revealed; the presence of everything is the epiphany of truth. In
philosophical terms, aletheia can only be found in predication, in the
qualities of beings, not in the ineffability of their pre-formal existence (or
Being-ness). Indeed one could suggest that for the Greeks, aletheia was
the relation established between beings through their predicates. The
Greek verb to be (Eimi) means “exist as” and not “exist”; it presupposes
formal, or formless, presence, therefore predication and actuality.
Existence as such, the being-ness, comes into Greek much later, during the
semantic osmosis of Greek and Hebrew cultures in Alexandria; when in
the Septuagint, the Hebrew God’s answer to Moses is translated as “I am
the being-ness”, (in itself a peculiar syntactical form: “Ego eimai ho on”,
Exodus, 3: 14), then the notion of existence as existing without predication
emerged. (Although the masculine grammatical form is full of cultural
connotations also, something which indicates that there cannot be a
language of being without predication: beings become linguistic events
only in their qualities and connections.)
Heidegger imposed a completely different hermeneutical perspective
when he dealt with the philosophers and the poets he chose to engage
with. He relocated the idea of such epiphanic knowledge into a theological
content so his text brings within it the semantic tensions of its origins. The
tension itself culminates Heidegger’s project to offer new translating
conditions for Greek texts in a way that both infuriated and inspired many
thinkers after him. For example his translation of the Heraclitian saying
“ethos anthropo daimon” as “Man, insofar as he is a man, dwells in the
nearness of god” (Heidegger, 1998: 269); or “the (familiar) abode for
humans is the open region for the presencing of god (the unfamiliar one)”
(Heidegger, 1998: 271) is rather evocative of medieval mysticism (more
specifically of Meister Eckhart or the poet Angelus Silesius) than of the
vision of moral character being the unique fate of the individual.
If there could be a conclusion from the previous notes, it is that
Heidegger never saw the Greeks antagonistically, as if he was struggling
to establish his philosophy through an agon against them. On the contrary
through his Greeks, Heidegger antagonised the history of his era and
somehow used them as an incentive and as a weapon to fight against his
Vrasidas Karalis 225
time and yet to enrich its intellectual endeavor. Probably this paradox of
his Greeks can be explained by reference to his own intellectual adventure
through his century. Indeed, the philosopher, who never talked about
himself, can be implicitly seen in his works as he was struggling to come
to terms with the history of his time and his own position in it. Probably
the semantic dichotomy of his own aletheia can be felt in his own
paradoxical involvement with historical processes that were beyond his
philosophical reflections and could be interpreted, precisely because of
their origins, only with the discourse of politics. The fact that Heidegger
ignored that “philosophy was born in and through the polis and is a part of
the same movement which brought about the first democracies”
(Castoriadis, 1991: 15) accounts for his own very limiting understanding
of aletheia. Probably only within the institutions of political democracy
can aletheia have the un-veiling impact that Heidegger suggested.
Otherwise it cannot be invested with the psychical energy that will make it
a vital project for transformation. The incompleteness in Heidegger’s
confrontation with the Greek notion of aletheia can be attributed to his
personal inability to confront history. In his own way, he made Greek
thinking relevant again but muted its disruptive truth. By decontextulising
the forms of meaning that aletheia generates, he domesticated the concept
which in any tradition “contains the possibility of a historically effective
universality only by effecting a rupture with the world of traditional or
authoritarian instituted representations” (Castoriadis, 1991: 74). By
depriving aletheia of its most “enowing” element, by erasing the seer from
the seen, Heidegger simply deleted the first letter from the word and threw
the concept back to its pre-philosophical opacity and ineffability.
Indeed, if we may appeal to one of the most playful peculiarities of
Greek grammar, the alpha-privative may also be the alpha-cumulative,
meaning all oblivions together. Heidegger made the Greeks speak
philosophically again by transferring their linguistic representations onto a
contemporary level of significating networks. Yet, he imposed a thick
glass barrier between us and them so much so that everything they were
saying became inaudible and mythical regressing to its pre-logical origins.
Aletheia cannot exist without logos; as Parmenides would have said “for
that is not / cannot be spoken or thought”; and despite its ingenious and
imaginative interpretive translations Heidegger’s discussion of logos is
missing the point of his own innovative approach; because if, as he
explained: “ȅ ȜȩȖȠȢ, IJȠ ȁȑȖİȚȞ is the laying that gathers. [...] ȅ ȁȩȖȠȢ
then would be the Greek name for speaking, saying, and language....”
(Heidegger, 1975: 77) then it remained to be explained what is gathered
226 Martin Heidegger and the Aletheia of his Greeks
and what is said. But that was not attempted and Heidegger’s own creative
misappropriation of the Greeks left behind an unfulfilled great promise.
Bibliography
Burnet, 1958 [1st 1892]
John Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy. London: Adam & Charles
Black.
Castoriadis, 1991
Cornelius Castoriadis, Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy: Essays in
Political Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
Cleve, 1969
Felix M. Cleve, The Giants of Pre-Sophistic Greek Philosophy, an
Attempt to Reconstruct their Thoughts. 2nd edition, vol. 2. The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff.
Gallop, 1984
David Gallop, Parmenides of Elea, Fragments, a Text and Translation
with an Introduction. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Heidegger, 1972
Martin Heidegger, On Time and Being. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. New
York: Harper Torchbooks.
Heidegger, 1975
Martin Heidegger, Early Greek Thinking, The Dawn of Western
Philosophy. New York: HarperCollins.
Heidegger, 1992
Martin Heidegger, Parmenides. Trans. Andre Schuwer and Richard
Rojcewicz. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, 1995
Martin Heidegger, Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ĭ 1-3, Trans. Walter
Brogan and Peter Warnek, Bloomigton and Indianapolis: Indiana
University Press
Heidegger, 1998
Martin Heidegger, Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill. Cambridge
University Press.
Heidegger, 2000
Martin Heidegger, Introduction to Metaphysics. Trans. Gregory Fried
and Richard Polt. New Haven & London: Yale University Press.
Heidegger, 2003
Martin Heidegger, Four Seminars: Le Thor 1966, 1968, 1969,
Zahringen 1973. Trans. Andrew Mitchell and Francois Raffoul.
Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Vrasidas Karalis 227
Heidegger, 2005
Martin Heidegger, Sojourns, The Journey to Greece. Foreword by John
Sallis. Trans. John Panteleimon Manousakis. New York: State
University of New York Press.
Freud, 1984
Sigmund Freud, "A Disturbance of Memory on the Acropolis" [1936],
in On Metapsychology: the Theory of Psychoanalysis, trans. James
Strachey. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Jaeger, 1947
Werner Jaeger, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Trans.
Edward S. Robinson. London: Oxford University Press.
Murphy-O'Connor, 1968
Jerome Murphy-O’Connor, ed., Paul and Qumran, Studies in New
Testament Exegesis. London: Geoffrey Chapman.
Nida, 1969
Eugene A. Nida, The Theory and Practice of Translation. Leiden: E.J.
Brill.
Popper, 1972
Karl R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific
Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Waterfield, 2000
Robin Waterfield, The First Philosophers: the Pre-Socratics and the
Sophists. Trans. with commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wittgenstein, 1997
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations. 2nd edition. Trans.
G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
CONTRIBUTORS