Body - and - World - in - Merleau-Ponty - and - Deleuze 2 PDF
Body - and - World - in - Merleau-Ponty - and - Deleuze 2 PDF
Body - and - World - in - Merleau-Ponty - and - Deleuze 2 PDF
PHENOMENOLOGICA
Romanian Journal for Phenomenology
Vol. II I 2012
•
HUMAN ITAS
BUC H ARE S T
Cover
ANGELA ROTARU
Body nd World
in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze1
Cory Shores
Universiy ofLeuven
I. Inroducion
s Joe Hughes obseves, there is "not much consensus in the current
critical literature when it comes to the question of Deleuze's relationship to
phenomenology."2 On the one hand, Deleuze is oten explicitly critical of
Husser!, Merleau-Ponty, nd phenomenology in generl, and many commen
tators have regarded those critiques s expressing an anti-phenomenological
tendency in Deleuze's thinking.3 Other scholrs acknowledge the tensions
1 May I thank Rolnd Breeur, Ullrich Melle, nd Nicolas de Warren of the Husser! Archives
pp. 15-34; D. Okoski, Dee and theuin fpresnaio, Berkely: Uvesiy of Cifoia
Press, 1999;L. awlor, hinking throughrnchPhiosopy: heBeing of thesio, Bloomington:
Indiana UnivesiyPrss, 2003; D. Olkowski, "Phlosophy of Sure, Phlosophy of Event De
lee's Criique ofPhenomenolo," ChmiIntion/13 (2011), pp. 193-216; nd . Monte
bello, " Ddee, ne nti-phenomenoloie?" ChsmiIntaioall3 (2011), pp. 315-325.
4 See, or mple, C. Bons, "Trnslator's Inroducion: Ddee, Empicism, nd the Sug
le for Subjeciit;" n G. Delee, Empiism andSujeiviy: n ssay onHumes heoy fHuan
Naure, English rns. by C. Bonds, New York: Columbia University Prss, 1991, pp. 1-19;
]. ynols nd J. Rofe, " Deleze nd Melau-Pony: mmnence, Univocity nd Phenomenol
oy," joual f the Bish Soiy or Phnomnooy 37.3 (2006), pp. 229-251; H. Somers-Hll,
" Ddee nd Merleau-Pon: Astheis of Dfence," n C. Bons (e.), Deze: heIntive
eduio, London: Continum, 2009, pp. 123-130;]. Hughs, op. it.;]. Wmbacq, " Depth nd
me n Melau-Pony nd Deleze," ChmiInaioal13 (2011), pp. 327-348;]. Wmbacq,
" Maice Melau-Pony nd Gils Delee s Intepreters ofHeri Bergson," nA.Tieniecka
(d.), rascenenalm Ovune: FromAbsolue Powr of Cosiones unil theForcs of Comic
Archieonis aea Hssraa 108), Dorrecht: Springer, 2011, pp. 269-284; nd J. Wm
bacq, " Maurice Merlau-Pon's Criicism on Bergso's hoy ofTne Seen hroh the Work of
Glls Delee," Sa Phnomnooica11 (2011), pp. 309-325.
5 See, for mple, C. Colebrook, Gilles Deze, London: Routledge, 2002; L. Byant,
Dfference and Givenness: Dezs ranscenental Empiicism and the Ontoloy of Immanence,
Evnston: Northwestern University Press, 2008.
6 A. Beaieu, GilesDeleuze et a phinominooie, Mons: Sils Maria, 2004.
30 (2000), p. 68.
Body and ord in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze 183
2. Phenomenal Interation
his red patch which I see on the carpet is red only in virtue of a shadow which
lies across it, its quality is apparent only in rdation to he play oflight upon it,
and hence s n element in a spatil coniguration. Moreover the colour cn
be said to be there only if it occupies an rea of a certain size, too small an rea
not being describable in these terms. 9
We are also misled into thinking that there is a "point-by-point" constant cor
respondence between the prts of what we see and the parts of our "elemen
tary perception."10 Certain optical illusions disprove this thesis.
enooy ofPercepion, English rns. by C. Smith, London: outledge, 1 962, pp. 34. Hence
fonh abbreviated s P, with French/English page numbers.
9 P, p. 1 0/4.
10
P, p. 1 4/7.
1 84 Cory Shores
Consider for example the above portion of the Miller-Lyer optical illusion
[igure 1]. We see two equal lines. Now, view the remaining pieces [igure 2].
hen we put them together [igure 3], we do not see them combined into
two equal lines with inverted arrow-ends.
Rah�r, the horizontal lines now apper as bering iferent lengths, on account
of their integrated relations wih the ngled pieces. Hence, what we sense is not
the immediate efect of he prts making one-to-one impressions on us:
11
P, pp. 16/9, 18/11.
Body and orld in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze 185
announces something else which it does not include, that it exercises a cogni
tive unction, and that its parts together mke up a whole to which each is re
lated without leaving its place. Henceforth the red is no longer merely there, it
represents something for me, and what it represents is not possessed s a "real
part" of my perception, but only aimed at s an "intentional part".12
Notice how the man in the foreground holds out his arm, which casts a shad
ow on the man standing next to him [igures 5 and 6].
12
P, p. 20/13.
13 P, P· 9/4.
14M. Merleau-Pon, 'Tel et !'esprit," in C. Lefort (ed.), Euvres, Pris: Gllimrd, 2010,
p. 1599; "Eye and Mind," English trans. by C. Dallery, in]. M. Edie (ed.), he Primay of
Perception and Other Essay s, Evnston: Northwestern Universiy Press, p. 167. Henceforth ab
breviated s OE, with French/English page numbers.
15 s image nd the following details: Rembrndt, De Nachwacht, Wneia Comons,
hp://commons. imedia.org/wki/File:Rembrandt_nighwatch_large.jpg,accessed1 4-Dec-2011.
186 Cory Shores
We do not merely see his arm from just our perspective; we also see it s if we
were looking from his right side at the ngle of the light source, because the
shadow we see from our perspective presents to us the apperance of his rm
from the sun's perspective.
his illustration will help us grasp the sort of pnoptic vision we have even
rom our glance at one viepoint. Consider also when we stand beween a set
of railroad tracks and look down their straight extent into the distance. hey
seem to converge very fr of. But this tells us they must be still parallel all the
way in the distnce, because they would instead appear prallel rom here only
if they continually diverged s they progressed. In a way, seeing the conver
gence is to indirectly stnd far down the tracks nd view them being parallel. 16
Yet, this means we are implicitly tking the perspective of horizonally implied
objects related to the one in focus:
every object is the mirror of ll others. hen I look at the lmp on my table,
I attribute to it [ . . ] the qualities [ . ]which the chimney, the walls, the table
. . .
can "see"; but back of my lamp is nothing but the face which it "shows" to
the chimney. I can therefore see an object in so fr s objects form a system
or a world, nd in so far as each one treats the others round it as spectators
of its hidden spects [ . . ].Any seeing of n object by me is instntaneously
.
IG
OE, P· 1624/187.
17 P, pp. 82-83/68.
Body and Wold in vferleau-Pony and Deleuze 187
the water produces. Yet reall, the loor, as the appearance that it happens
to be, is seeable only because it is given to us through he rippling water. We
should not assume there is such a thing as an object seen in itsel£ ll things
are sensed in their intermeshment with everything else. Even the water we
mentioned is not contained only there in the pool. hen we raise our eyes
to he trees above the water, we see the webbed play of the water's relections.
The tree foliage has its particular appearance only because the water below it
"sends into it, upon it its active and living essence."18
Yet, because these horizonal objects are indeterminate and ambiguous, we
are motivated to turn our attention toward them, which then makes hem
determinate. To better understand this process, Merleau-Ponty refers us to the
way that children acquire the abiliy to perceive distinct colors. At irst, hey
can only distinguish colored things from non-colored things. hen, they dif
ferentiate warm and cool shades of colored regions. Finally, they can discern
diferent colors. he psychologist mistkenly thinks that the child originally
perceived the diferent speciic colors in their determinacy, except the child
was merely unaware of the colors' identities. So according to this psychologicl
interpretation, children irst can see he redness of he red, with its diference
to the blueness of blue, but they just have not yet learned the corresponing
names and concepts for the color. Merleau-Ponty says hat instead he colors
were originally seen in an indeterminate form, and only gradually does the child
come to constitute hem distinctl. In other words, he child sees diferent colors
but not so much the distinctions between them, although these diferences hng
implicitly on the horizon of her awareness.19 here re relations, then, beween
the colors hat re seen, alhough they apper only implicitl. So, when children
early on see neihboring things bering diferent colors, they have a vaue sense
that the visual apperances difer in some signiicnt way. ter later learning
how to detect the diferences beween he colors, they then see them determi
nately nd uniquely. Because the colors began indeterminately, their becoming a
determinate appearance was merely on the horizon of the child's awareness. We
might here notice nother sort of horizon. he determinate forms were there
inirectly in he beginning stage. Yet, heir arrival to the cild's consciousness is
pening; in a wa, it hangs on a sort of temporal horizon too, being at he edge
of the grsp of he present intentions.
he parts of our phenomenl world are given so pre-integrated that even
when he world suddenly appears to us quite diferently than the moment
before, in a way we were already anticipating the alteration.20 He depicts a
scene to illustrate. We walk along a shoreline. Before us is a ship run aground
in the beach. Behind it is a forest, and he ship's masts blend in with the trees,
preventing us from initilly noticing them as belonging to the ship. Yet, here
18
OE, p. 1616/182.
1 9 P, p. 38/29-30.
20
P, p. 23/15.
188 Cory Shores
will come a moment when we feel that the look of some of the trees is on the
verge of ltering. Before even seeing the masts as distinct from the forest, we
felt some sort of tension in their appearance, just as "a storm is imminent
in storm clouds."21 Even when originally mistken, we still perceived all the
distinguishing qualities of the masts, and they told us indirectly they were
not trees. So from the beginning we had a "vague expectation" that there was
something more to be understood in the appearance of the forest:
21
P, p. 24/ 1 7.
22
P, p. 25/ 1 7.
23 P, p. 38/30.
24 Ibid.
Body and orld in Mer!eau-Pony and De!euze 189
3. Synaesthetic Interation
I do not trnslate the "data of touc'' "into the language of seein'' or vice versa-I
do not bring togeher one by one the pas of my body; s trnslation nd this
uication re performed once and for llin me: they re my bod, itsel£30
nother way to articulate this sense-integration is that all sense-data are syn
aesthetic. He has us consider patients who lost the ability to visualy perceive
color qualities. Even without this capacity, they were still able mny times to
25 P, p. 39/30.
26
P, p. 272/23 5.
27 P, p. 48/38.
28 P, p. 174/149.
29 Ibid.
30 P, p. 175/ 1 50.
190 Cor y Shores
determine the colors shining upon them, on account of how it was perceived
in its mixture with the other senses. hey might for exmple know it is yellow
when their body responds as if feeling something stinging it; one patient said,
"I clenched my teeth, and so I know that it is yellow."31 Of course even when
we do visually perceive color qulities, we also sense them in these other ways
as well. It is not that we irst see red and then our body responds by enlivening
itself; rather, just as soon as we see red, our body is enlivened at the same time,
because seeing red is pardy a tactile sensation felt throughout our bodies. 32
"Synaesthetic perception is the rule," he writes, nd
He has us consider that although we have two eyeblls with each one giving us
diferent streams of visual data, we still have a uniied view of one phenomenal
world. He thinks that the visul quality of sounds and audible properties of
colors come about through the same sort of synthesis of sense-data. Because
ll our senses are pre-integrated in this way, he says that their unity is an 'a
prioi truth."34 Our body is "not a collection of adjacent organs, but a syner
getic system"; their unctions re lllinked together in our actions.35
hen a child reaches out for something, from the beginning she feels her
self a part of the world around her, because on that basis she knows that her
body could move mong the things around her and take them into her grasp.
Our integration with the world, then, is evident from the way our senses al
low our body to immediately move around and interact with all the other
parts of the world.36 In fact, we even take up the objects around us and make
them extensions of our own sensibility. Merleau-Ponty's famous exmple is
the blind man wlking with a stick. hen irst beginning to use it, he might
feel the stick making contact with his hand. Yet ter a while, it becomes as
though the end of the stick is his new point of contact wih the objects round
him. He no longer feels the contact between his hand and the stick but instead
31 P, p. 244/211.
32 P, p. 245/211 .
33 P, p. 265/229.
34 P, p. 255/221 .
35 P, p. 270/234.
36 OE, p. 1594/162.
Body and ord in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze 191
between the stick and the ground or other things his stick is "feeling."37 We
are inherently gered to be organically integrated with the objective world
around us. he blind person's awareness wants and tries to extend into its sur
rounding world. We use telephones to extend our voices and ears into distant
places. Our gaze, Merleau-Pony writes, is anlogous to the blind man's stick:
like his cane, our vision feels out the world in an interrogative way, ranging
over objects and dwelling on them. his is "the organic relationship between
subject and world, the active transcendence of consciousness, the momentum
which carries it into a thing and into a world by means of its organs and
instruments."38
Our body's immersion in the world is evident as well in its sympathetic
relationships with it. Consider how when we her a sound, part of our ear ap
paratus vibrates at the same frequency, in sympathy with the air's vibrations.
It is as though there were a place of crossing-over beween the world and our
body: "In the same way I give ear, or look, in the expectation of a sensation,
and suddenly the sensible takes possession of my ear or my gze, and I sur
render a part of my body, even my whole body, to this particular manner of
vibrating and illing space known as blue or red."39 He also has us think of the
holy sacrament of communion. he bread is not only something sensible. s
well, it is believed that when we ingest it, it communicates into us the "real
presence of God." Sensation is like his too. We are not only given an impres
sion of the world around us, but enter into communion with the world by
means of the sympahetic relation of that sensation.40 hen our hands are
about to feel something smooth, they take up a certain "degree," "rate," and
"direction of movement" appropriate for feeling that ind of surface, instead
of the sorts of motion and readiness needed to feel something roughY he
smooth thing called out to our hands to tell them how it needed to be felt, so
that even before making physical contact, the smooth thing in a sense placed
itself upon our hands. So, we cannot say that we are the toucher performing
the action, and the smooth thing is something passive receiving our action.
he smooth object acts on us just as much as we act on it. he thing we sense
begins as a "vague beckoning" whose call to us allows us to "synchronize" with
it.42 We "interrogate" the object "according to its own wishes," which places us
into a "pre-established harmon'' and "kinship" with it, an a piori sort of pre
condition of organic integration with the world, necessary for us being able
37 P, p. 1 77/ 1 52.
38 P, p. 1781 1 52-1 53.
39 P, p. 245/2 12.
40 P, pp. 245-246/2 12.
4 1 M. Merleau-Pont, Le visible et !'invisible, in C. Lefort (ed.), Euvres, Pris: Gllimrd,
20 1 0, p. 1 759; he Vsibe and theInvsible, C. Lefort (ed.), English trns. by A. Lingis, Evan
ston: Northwestern University Press, 1 9 86, p. 1 33. Henceforth abbreviated s I, with French/
English page numbers.
42 P, p. 248/2 1 4.
192 Cory Shores
to sense the things around us.43 Our hands can "[open] upon a tactile world"
when we are feeling the world from within them, but this also requires that
our hands remain accessible to being lready touched by the outside world,
which informs them how to go about their touching. In this way, there is a
"crisscrossing" of the touching and the tangible. By opening themselves up in
this way, our hands incorporate themselves into the world they feel out; "the
two systems are applied upon one another, s the two halves of an orange":44
hus a sensible datum which is on the point of being felt sets a kind of mud
dled problem for my body to solve. I must ind the attitude which will provide
it with the means of becoming determinate, of showing up as blue; I must ind
the reply to a question which is obscurely expressed.45
So, we might think of ourselves togeher with the world we perceive s being
of one lesh. here is an intimacy beween us "s close as beween he sea and
the strand,"46 whle yet we re still somehow partly our own selves; we do not
dissipate into he lesh just because we are so much a part of it. Objects, he says,
do not begin s selfsme tings which we s seers come to view ater we begin
opening our attention to them. Instead we nd the objects are involved in an
intimac; s if "the gaze itself envelops them, clothes them with its own lesh."47
when we perceive colors or odors, we are perceiving nothing else but igures
and movements, but igures and movements so smll, so varied, and in such
great number, that our minds are not capable in their present states of consid
ering them singly and distinctl. s a consequence we are not aware hat our
perceptions are composed of ininitesimally small perceptions of igures nd
movements. For example, when we thoroughly mix very ine yellow and blue
powders, we perceive green; we are not aware that what we in fact perceive is
only yellow and blue, very inely mxed.48
43 I, p. 1 759/ 1 33.
4 Ibid.
45 P, p. 248/2 1 4.
46 I, p. 1 756/ 1 30-1 3 1 .
47I, p. 1 757/ 1 3 1 .
48 G . W Leibniz, "Meditationes d e Coitione, Veritate e t Ideis," i n C. I. Gerhrdt (ed.), Die
phiosophschn Schitn von Goied ilhelm Leibnz, voL , Berlin: Georg Olms, 1965, p. 426;
Body and ord in kfereau-Pony and Deleuze 193
54 G. Bateson, Mind and Naure: A Necessay Uni, London: ildwood House, 1 979, p. 1 1 0.
55 G. W Leibniz, Nouveax essais sur l'entendement humain, in C. I. Gerhatdt (ed.), Die
philosophschen Schriten, vol. 5, Berlin: Weidmann, 1 882, p. 47; New Essays on Human Un
destanding, English trans. by . Remnant and J. Bennett, Cambridge: Cmbridge University
Press, 1 981 , pp. 53-54, and see lso , pp. 1 1 6-1 17/86. Deleuze uses the exmple of a water
mill in his nalysis.
56 , p. 1 2 1 /9 1 .
57 , p. 1 1 5/87.
196 Cory Shores
in a way, the uture is already sensed now in the immediate ield of micro
perceptions. Following his waves illustration,Leibniz writes:
he loudest noise in the world would never waken us if we did not have some
perception of its stn, which is smal, just s the strongest force in the world
would never break a rope less the lest force strained it and stretched it slight
ly, even though that little lengthening which is produced is imperceptible. 58
Deleuze reads this to mean that what we perceive now gives us tiny indica
tions of what is to come.
However abruptly I may log my dog who eats his meal, the animal will have
experienced he minute perceptions of my stelhy arrival on tiptoes, my hos
tile odor, and my liing of the rod that subtend the conversion of plesure into
pain. How cold a feeling of hunger follow one of satisfaction if a thousnd
iny, elementay forms of hunger (for salts, for sugar, butter, etc.) were not
released at diverse and iniscernible rhyrhms?59
So like animals, we feel "pricklings," even though what we wil come to per
ceive is not yet clear to s. hese are tiny perceptions that "are not integrated
into present perception."60 In the following moments, more of these tiny
pricklings prove remarkable and come out as a clear and distinguished per
ceptionY hese subversive micro-perceptions "destabilize the preceding mac
roperception while preparing the following one."62 his is striingly similar
to Merleau-Pont's notion that we now are implicitly aware of the content
of our forthcoming perceptions. We shold emphasize that for Deleuze, the
basis for the implicit perception is not that uture macro-perceptions are in
tegrated with present ones, but rather that present ones are heterogeneous
mltiplicities with nti-integrational parts that overthrow former phenom
enal apperings rather than blending them together. It is only on the highest
order of synthesis, the relarizing ilter that makes perceptions regular and
homogeneous, that such a blening happens.
So recall how a macro-perception is the diferential product of sub-phe
nomena, which themselves are diferentials of yet smaller ones, all the way
to the ininitely small. We will turn now to Deleuze's explicit discussions of
phenomena in Dfference and Rpetiion, and note how his modiication of
the J.-H. Rosny energetics formula corresponds to the analysis ofLeibnizian
micro-perceptions:
58 G. W Leibniz, Nouvax essas, op. it., p. 47; Nw ssays, op. it., p. 54.
59 , p. 1 1 5/87.
60 , p. 1 1 6/87.
6' Ibi.
62 , p. 1 1 5/87.
Body and ord in au-Pony and Deuze 197
he phenomenon that lshes across this system, bringing about the commu
nication beween disparate series, is a sign. [. ]
. . Every phenomenon is com
posite because not only are the wo series which bound it heterogeneous but
each is itself composed of heterogeneous terms, subtended by heterogeneous
series which form so many sub-phenomena.65
he green lashes out as the diferential relation between yellow and blue,
which themselves are diferentil relations, nd so on to ininity. Green lashed
out phenomenally because it was remarkable in that situation, and perhaps
that is why we might call ii a sign in Deleuze's sense of the term here. he
sound of the waterfll does not representationally signiy anhing when it
lshes out, but it alerts our awareness to somehing remarkable in our phe
nomenal world.
. Bodiy Dferenias
Deleuze lso uses Leibniz's diagram when discussing Spinoz's bodily af
fection, which will allow us to explain the nti-integrative relations beween
boh our body and its world and lso those within the Deleuzin phenomenl
body itsel£ To do so, we begin with his interpretation of Spinoz's simplest
bodies so as to link his renditions of Spinozistic bodily composition and f
fective variation.
63 G . Deleuze, Dfirence et rpeition, Paris: PUF, 1968, p. 287; Dference and peiion,
English trans. by . Paton, Nw York: Columbia UniversityPress, p. 222 . Henceforth abbrevi
ated as D R, with French/English page numbers. Rosn's original formulation does not have he
third coupling e - e'. Deleuze adds it, perhaps to emphasize that the orders go on to ininity.
See J.-H. Rosny, Les sciences et le pluralsme, Paris: Felx Alcan, 1922, p. 6.
4 DR, p. 286/222.
65 Ibid.
198 Coy Shores
66 B. Spinoza, Ethica, in C. Gebhardt (ed.), Opera, voL 2, Heidelberg: Winter, 1 972, p. 97;
Ethis, English trans. by G. H. R Prkinson, Oford: Oford University Press, 2000, p. 1 26.
67 S. DuY, he Loic of pression: Quali, Quantiy and Intensiy in Spinoa, Hegel and
Deleuze, ldershor: Ashgate, 2006, p. 48.
68 B. Spinoza, Ethica, op. cit., pp. 99- 1 00; Ethics, op. cit., p. 1 28.
69 B. Spinoza, Epstoae, in C. Gebhrdt (ed.), Opera, vol. 4, Heidelberg: Wmter, 1 972, p. 1 70;
he Leters, English trns. by S. Shirley, Cmbridge: Hackett, 1 995, p. 1 92.
70 B. Spinoza, enati Des Cartes Principiorum Phiosophiae Pars 1 & Il, in C. Gebhrdt
(ed.), Opera, vol. 1, Heidelberg: Winter, 1 972, p. 1 90; he Pincples of Cartesian Philosoph,
English trns. by S. Shirle, Cambridge: Hackett, 1 998, p. 53. See also G. Ddeuz� , Spinoa et
le probleme de !'epression, Paris: Les editions de minuit, 1 968, p. 1 87; Expressionism in Phi
losophy: Spinoza, English rans. by M. Joughn, New York: Zone, 1 990, p. 204.
Body and World in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze 199
speeds determines the compound's power to afect other bodies and to sustain
its diferential composition under the inluence of detrimental afections.71
For example,
chyle is an iniite set of very simple bodies. Lmph is nother ininite set of the
very simple bodies. hat distinguishes he wo ininite sets? It is the dfferentil
relation! You have this time a dy/x which is: the initely smal prts of chyle
over the ininitely small parts of lymph, nd his diferentil relaion tends to
wrds a limit: the blood, that is to say: chyle and lymph compose blood.72
Our blood, then, is a "xed ratio" only in the sense that the lymph and chyle
maintain their continuously varying diferential relation instead of splitting
aprt and forming diferentil relations with other bodies; in other words,
their being related in a ratio remains xed, even though the value of that ratio
is under continuous alteration.
Yet, the blood will decompose under the afective inluence of arsenic,
for example. he poison's simplest bodies have a diferentil vlue that, rath
er than allowing the arsenic to combine with the blood, instead causes the
lymph and chyle to lose their co-variational relations and to then take up
relations with other simplest bodies.73 Note as well that the blood's power to
sustain itself is dependent on its diferential relation to other parts of the body.
he blood diferentially relates with other tissues to make up organs, which
themselves diferentilly co-compose to constitute the whole body. Our body
is then made of various levels of diferential composition, all the way down
to the ininitely smallest level of pure diferences without terms. So when we
are afected, our body's total level of power varies depending on whether the
afecting bodies increase or decrease the power of our compounds' abiliy to
retain their continually ltering relations. Arsenic, upon entering our body,
decomposes the blood, which then decomposes higher layers of our composi
tion, and so on, sending shock waves of disruptive afections throughout all
the levels of our body. s Spinoza writes: "I understand a body to have died
when its parts are so disposed that they maintain a diferent ratio of motion
and rest to one nother."74 s we will ind, these compositionl disruptions are
matters of continuously varying ffective intensities sweeping throughout our
bodies and ltering their power levels.
So as to better understand the continuous variations of our body's overall
power or perfection, Deleuze returns to diferential calculus concepts. We will
need to conceive afections as though they are like instantaneous velocities;
71 G. Deleuze, Spinoa. Philosophie praique, Paris: Les eitions de minuit, 1981, p. 47; Spi
noa: Pracical Philosoph, English trns. by . Hurle, San Francisco: City Lights, 1988, p. 32.
72 G. Deleuze, Seminr 10/03/1981, English trns. by S . DfY, hrtp://ww.webdeleuze.
com nd htp://ww.univ-pris8. fr, accessed 14-Dec-20 11.
73 Ibid.
74 B. Spinoza, Ethica, op. it., p. 240; Ethics, op. it., p. 256.
200 Cory Shores
his path that lies at a right angle to he string would also be a tngent to
a circle's cuve at that location. For a cuve moving in a somewhat more ir
regular path, ining its tendency-toward-change is more complex, and here
is where we might use something like Leibniz's method. We create a triangle
on the basis of how the curve's dimensions extend in a certain region. hen, as
with Leibniz's tringles, we slowly diminish the two tringle legs, nd he third
diagonal side gives us the tangent, which also tells us which way the cuve is
tending at that place [igure 1 0].
So in this wa, as the triangle legs almost completely contract upon each other,
he diagonal line gives us the intensive vlue of the tendency-toward-chnge.
76 Ibi.
7 B. Spinoza, Epistoae, op. cit., p. 137; Letes, op. cit., p. 160.
78 G. Deleuze, Seminar 20/0 1 1 1 9 8 1 , op. cit.
79 Ibi.
80
G. Deleuze, Seminar 24/0 1 / 1 978, English trns. by . S. Murph, http://ww.webde
leuze.com nd http://ww.univ-paris8.fr, accessed 1 4-Dec-20 1 1 .
202 Coy Shores
8 1 Ibi.
82 Ibi.
83 G. Deleuze, "Spinoza et les trois 'ethiques'," in Criique et liniqu�, Paris: Les editions de
minuit, 1 993, pp. 1 72-173; "Spinoza and the hree 'Ethics'," in Essays Criical and Clinica,
English trns. by D. W Smith, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 1 38-1 39.
84 Ibid.
Body and orld in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze 203
neno:85 "he rain makes them howl like dogs; wih one side they screen the
other; they oten turn hemselves, the impious wretches."86 in droplets are
pelting a dmned soul, disrupting he composition of is sin at that location
and thereby sending shock waves of decompositionl forces throughout the rest
of his body. Yet, to maintain his constitution, the sol turns up a new side of his
body that is more able to sustain the afections. He is awre of how the rain af
fects him, and he thus knows how to self-afectively alter himself so to maintin
his dfferentil contact with it. Our active self-ffection nd adaptive interaction
with the world around us is what Deleuze here clls "rhythm." He also ofers
he example of swimming hrough a powerul wave. hen we colide with the
wave, its afection begins to decompose our bod. Yet, by self-afectively altering
the arrangements of our own body's prts, we may swim in conjunction with
the wave and together form a larger composite bod.87 Deleuze suggests nother
illustration to explain more clearly how afective rhythm involves couplings of
continuous afective variations. He hs s consider a dual improvisation of a vi
olin and a pino. On the one hand, each one needs to improvisationaly choose
its own development. Yet, the musicians' decisions wil inluence how the other
plays in concord with it. So, in order for both instruments to maintain their
diferential co-composition, they must make self-modiications that are difer
entilly compatible with those of the oher player.88
mains of the senses, with each one being integrated with the others in a Mer
leau-Pontian synaesthetic way; for example, when our eyes see the stomping
hooves of the bulls in Bacon's bullighting paintings, our ears seemingly hear
the noises they make. In this sense, the painter wold "mke visible a ind of
original unity of the senses." Ddeuze rejects this nd the other hpotheses, be
cause they do not take into account the "vitl power" of sensational rhchm.90
In simple sensations, he writes, rhythm "appears as the vibration that lows
through the body without organs, it is the vector of the sensation, it is what
makes the sensation pass from one levd to another."91 Recall that the "vector"
of the afect-sign is the intensity of the ffection's increase or decrease in value.
lso, these ffective intensities send shock waves of disruption throughout the
body's composition, causing it to decompose nd recompose, in accordance
wih a "rhythmic" co-variation within and between boies. So, Ddeuze's read
ing of Spinozistic ffect will now help us better characterize the phenomeno
logicl value of his body without organs, for he writes that it is "an intense
and intensive body. It is traversed by a wave that traces levds or thresholds in
the body according to the variations of its mplitude. hus the body does not
have organs, but thresholds or levels."92 In Ddeuze's Spinozistic body, these
intensive levels are precisely what causes our bodily composition to shit and
change its arrangements, and the more rhthmically our body acts, the more
it breaks down its norml organic divisions and relations to produce new
unctional relations between its prts. In other words, the rhythm of afection,
just like the rhythm of sensation, pushes our bodies to the limits of its organi
zation, tending it toward being a body without organs. We see this correlation
as well in Ddeuze's notion of the indeterminate and tempory organs of sen
sation moving from place to place in bodies without orgns. he exposed side
of the damned soul in Dante's Ineno is the point of contact where the pdting
rain distributes its decompositional afective shock waves throughout him. By
turning another side upward, he self-ffectively sends wiin himself waves of
afective lteration so to rearrange the rdations of his body, and by doing so,
he creates a new site of sensitiviy to the external waves of afection. Because
he continually twists his sides around, each new organ of sensation replaces
the prior one, ming ll of them temporay and indeterminate. Likewise,
Ddeuze writes of the body without organs:
A wave with a variable amplitude lows through the body without orgns; it
traces zones and levels on this body according to the variations ofits mplirude.
hen the wave encounters external forces at a particular �evel, a sensation ap
pears. n organ will be determined by this encounter, but it is a provisionl
orgn that endures only as long as the passage of he wave and the action of he
force, nd which will be displaced in order to be posited elsewhere.93
his ground, this rhthmic unity of the senses, can be discovered only by
going beyond the organism. he phenomenological hpothesis is perhaps in
suicient because it merely invokes the lived body. But the lived body is still a
pltry thing in comprison with a more profound nd lmost unlivable Power
[Puissance] . We cn seek the unity of rhthm only at the point where rhythm
itsef plunges into chaos, into the night, at the point where the diferences of
level are perpetually and violently mxed. Beyond the organism, but also at the
limit of the ived body, there lies [ . . . ] the body without organs. 94
In the animal itsel, we ind representations which lack only relection and
some disinterestedness to be general ideas in the ll sense of the term: f not,
how should a cow that is being led stop before a meadow, no matter which,
simply because it enters into the category that we cll grass or meadow?96
A living being selects from a pool of diferences the parts or elements that
satisy one of its needs. hus, although each experience of grass is diferent,
they are all grouped together, because they each satisy the cow's hunger. he
cow then can dip its head mechaniclly and eat the grass, without an intense
awareness of all the meadow's variations that would distinguish one clump
from another. Bergson illustrates a sort of dephenomenalization that happens
as our bodies become more accustomed and integrated into our surroundings.
I take a walk in a town seen then for the irst time. At every street corner I
hesitate, uncertain where I m going. [ . . ] there is nothing in one atitude
.
93 FB, p. 49/34.
94 FB, p. 47/32.
95 See DR, p. 1 76/ 1 3 5 ; G. Deleuze, inma 2: L'image-temps, Paris: Les editions de minuit,
1985, p. 62; Cinema 2: he ime Image, English trns. by H. Tomlinson and R Gleta, Lon
don: Atlone, 1 9 89, p. 42.
96 H. Bergson, La pensee et le mouvant. Essas et conerences, Paris: Fex Alcan, 1 934, p. 66;
he Creaive Min, English trns. by M. Andison, Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood, 1 946,
p. 62.
206 Cory Shores
which foretells and prepares uture attitudes. Later, ater prolonged sojourn in
the town, I shall go about it mechanically, without having any distinct percep
ion of the objects which I m passing. [ . . . ] these accompanying movements
are orgnized to a degree which renders perception useless. I began by a state
in which I distinguished only my perception; I shall end in a state in which I
m hardly conscious of anything but automatism.97
Yet, suppose the cow sees what looks like grass, eats it, oly to ind that it
has the plastic taste of rtiicial turf Quite suddenly, what the cow is eating
becomes remarkable, and it comes to the forefront of its awareness. he parts
of its phenomenal world are not integrating, as its bodily domains of tasting
and seeing are forced to work simultaneously in a disharmonious way. s well,
the cow stops its habitual action of dipping its head to eat the grass and in that
way loses its integration with its world, as though the world suddenly becme
foreign to the cow. hus, eating grass stands out as a potently phenomenl ex
perience when the cow's horizons cease to integrate. "hthm" in the Francis
Bacon text is the unpredictable varying of the waves of sensation that ffect
each bodily domain diferently in such a way that the sense data cannot be
processed, regularized, recognized, and thereby dephenomenalized. hile this
use of the term "rhythm" is surely quite distinct from the Spinozistic sense, we
might note that even in this context, rhythm also seves to explin the varying
diferential relations within the body, within the world, and between the body
and the world that are at work in phenomenal experiences.
8. Conclusion
97 H. Bergson, Maiere et memoire. ssai sur a reation du cops a !'esprit, Pris: Germer Bail
Here et Cie., 1 903, pp. 1 00-1 0 1 ; Mater and Memo , English. trans. by N. M. Pal and W S.
Plmer, Mineola, New York: Dover, 2004, p. 1 1 0, emphasis mine.
Body and orld in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze 207
integrated unctioning breaks down that it comes closer to being the phe
nomenal body wihout organs. Deleuze's diference-based model, then, can
be seen as compatible with Merleau-Pon's model, as long as we distinguish
heir explanatory purposes. Merleau-Pon's theory better accounts for the
ongoing constitution of phenomenl objects, the familiar things in the world
around us, while Deleuze's theory better explains the intensiy of any given
moment of phenomenal experience. hus, although Deleuze's model in many
undamentl ways contraposes Merleau-Pon's model, we need not regard it
as a critique of phenomenology itsel, but rather as a useul contribution to
phenomenoloy's pool of theoretical ideas.
Corry Shores
Vlierbeeklaan 38
3 0 1 0 Kessel-Lo, Belgium
corry.shores@hiw.kuleuven.be
Wors Cited
Bateson, G., Mind and Nature: A Necessay Uni, London: Wildwood House, 1 979.
Beaulieu, A., Gilles Deleuze et a phenomenoloie, Mons: Sils Maria, 2004.
Beistegui, M. de, "Toward a Phenomenology of Diference?" Research in Phenomenol
oy 30 (2000) , pp. 54-70.
Bergson, H., Matiere et mmoire. Essai sur a reaion du cops a !'espri, Paris: Germer
Bailliere et Cie. , 1 903; Matter and Memor, English trans. by N. M. Paul and
W S. Palmer, Mineola, New York: Dover, 2004.
- , La pemee et e mouvant. Essas et conerences, Paris: Felx lcn, 1 934; he Creaive
Min, English trans. by M. Anison, Westport, Conneticut: Greenwood, 1 946.
Boundas, C., "Translator's Introduction: Deleuze, Empiricism, and he Struggle for
Subjectivity," in G. Deleuze, Empiricsm and Subjeciviy: An Essay on Humes
heoy of Human Naure, English trans. by C. Boundas, New York: Columbia
University Press, 1 9 9 1 , pp. 1-1 9.
Bryant, L., Dference and Givenness: Deleuzes ranscendenal Empiricsm and the On
toloy ofImmanence, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2008.
Colebrook, C., Gilles Deleuze, London: Routledge, 2002.
Dante, he Ineno of Dante Alighieri, English trans. by J. Carlyle, London: J. M.
Dent, 1 900.
Deleuze, G., Dtrence et rpetiion, Paris: PUP, 1 968; Dference and Repeition, Eng
lish trans. by . Patton, New York: Columbia University Press, 1 994.
-, Spinoa et e probleme de !epression, Paris: Les editions de minuit, 1 968; pres
sionsm in Phiosophy: Spinoa, English trns. by M. Jougin, New York: Zone, 1 990.
- , Spinoa. Philosophie praique, Paris: Les editions de minuit, 1 98 1 ; Spinoza:
Practical Philosoph, English trns. by R. Hurley, San Francisco: City Lights, 1988.
- , Cinema 2. L'image-temps, Pris: Les editions de inuit, 1 985; inema2: he ime
Image, English trns. by H. Tomlinson nd . Galeta, London: Athlone, 1989.
208 Coy Shores
Duy, S . , he Loic ofpression: Quali, Quaniy and lntemiy in Spinoa, Hegel and
Deleuze, ldershot: shgate, 2006.
Foucault, M., "heatrum Philosophicum," in D. Bouchard (ed.) , Language, Counter
Memo, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews, English trans. by D. Bouchard and
S. Simon, Ihaca: Cornell University Press, 1 9 77, pp. 1 65- 1 96.
Hughes, J., Deleuze and the Geness ofRepresentaion, London: Continuum, 2008.
Lawlor, L., "he End of Phenomenology: Expressionism in Deleuze nd Merleau
Ponty," Coninental Philosophy Review 3 1 . 1 ( 1 998), pp. 1 5-34.
-, hinking through French Philosophy: he Being of the Quesion, Bloomington:
losophschen Schiten von Goied ilhelm Leibniz, voL 4, Berlin: Georg Olms,
1 965 , pp. 422426; "Relections on Knowledge, Truth, nd Ideas," in Monad
oloy and Other Philosophical Essays, English trans. by . Schrecker and A. M.
Schrecker, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrll, 1 965, pp. 3-1 0.
Body and ord in Merleau-Pony and Deleuze 209
Spinoza, B., Epstoae, in C. Gebhardt (ed.) , Opera, vol. 4, Heidelberg: Winter, 1 972,
pp. 1-342; he Leters, English trans. by S. Shirle, Cmbridge: Hackett, 1 995.
-, Ethic, n C. Gebhrdt (ed.), Opr, voL 2, Heidelberg: Wmter, 1 972, pp. 4 1-308;
Ethics, English trans. by G. H. R. Parinson, Oford: Oxford University Press,
2000.
-, Renai Des Cartes Pincpiorum Philosophiae Pars l & II, in C. Gebhrdt (ed.),
Opera, vol. I, Heidelberg: Winter, 1 972, pp. 1 23-230; he Princples of Cartesian
Philosoph, English trns. by S. Shirley, Cambridge: Hackett, 1 998.
Wambacq, ]., "Depth and Time in Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze," Chiasmi Intena
ional 1 3 (20 1 1 ), pp. 327-348.
-, "Maurice Merleau-Ponty nd Gilles Deleuze s Interpreters of Henri Bergson,"
in A. Tymieniecka (ed.) , ramcendenalsm Overtuned: From Absolute Power of
Consciousness unil the Forces of Cosmic Architectonics (Anaecta Husserliana 1 08),
Dordrecht: Springer, 20 1 1 , pp. 269-284.
- , "Maurice Merleau-Pont's Criticism on Bergso's heory of Time Seen rough
the Work of Gilles Deleuze," Studia Phaenomenoloica 1 1 (20 1 1 ), pp. 309-325.