Notes of The Cvetacvatara The Buddhacarita
Notes of The Cvetacvatara The Buddhacarita
Notes of The Cvetacvatara The Buddhacarita
Early
Journal
Content
on
JSTOR,
Free
to
Anyone
in
the
World
This
article
is
one
of
nearly
500,000
scholarly
works
digitized
and
made
freely
available
to
everyone
in
the
world
by
JSTOR.
Known
as
the
Early
Journal
Content,
this
set
of
works
include
research
articles,
news,
letters,
and
other
writings
published
in
more
than
200
of
the
oldest
leading
academic
journals.
The
works
date
from
the
mid-‐seventeenth
to
the
early
twentieth
centuries.
We
encourage
people
to
read
and
share
the
Early
Journal
Content
openly
and
to
tell
others
that
this
resource
exists.
People
may
post
this
content
online
or
redistribute
in
any
way
for
non-‐commercial
purposes.
JSTOR
is
a
digital
library
of
academic
journals,
books,
and
primary
source
objects.
JSTOR
helps
people
discover,
use,
and
build
upon
a
wide
range
of
content
through
a
powerful
research
and
teaching
platform,
and
preserves
this
content
for
future
generations.
JSTOR
is
part
of
ITHAKA,
a
not-‐for-‐profit
organization
that
also
includes
Ithaka
S+R
and
Portico.
For
more
information
about
JSTOR,
please
contact
support@jstor.org.
Notes on the S7vetdgvatara, the Bfuddiacarita, etc.-By E.
WASHBURN IJIOPKINS,Professor in Yale University, New
Haven, Conn.
L The 1vetAqvatara.
system, for otherwise, "if the author had known the Sfamkhya
system and recognized the system as opposed " (als gegnerisches
System, p. 291), "his work would not have contained passages
which could be, and actually have been, interpreted as if Kapila
were the highest sage and the Sihhkhya the way of salvation."
Logically accurate as this view may appear, it is in fact erro-
neous. That it is held by the scholar whose specialty is the his-
tory of Hindu philosophy shows how necessary it is for the San-
skritist not to ignore the most important record of the phases of
Hindu thought subsequent to the chief Upanishads. Professor
Deussen's view is that "VedAnta was distorted into Samikhya
and thereby destroyed." In accordance with this opinion he
interprets Kapila and Sduhkhya at v. 2 and vi. 13, as "the red
being " and "testing," respectively, despite the fact that, in the
latter passage, Sdrhkhya-Yoga is a (necessary) deistic means of
salvation:
tat kdrancaT &anhkhya- Yogd-dhigamyana
jinatva devam nmucyate sarvapddi4h,
translated as
"Wer dies Ursein durch Prufung und Hingebung
Als Gott erkennt, wird frei von allen Banden,"
to be translated,
" On recognizing as (a personal) God, attainable by the Sduh-
khya-Yoga (system), that (apparently impersonal) First Cause,
one is freed from all bonds."
The whole argument is deistic and it is stated in the phraseol-
ogy familiar to students of the epic, where ihah kdranamn is
urged, as, for example, in xiii. 14. 230, and in 222-23, where exactly
the same idea is expressed: 9iva is the lord known as the kdranan,
First Cause, who is worshipped by Yogins with Yoga (and other
forms of worship). There is a first cause, but salvation requires
that one should recognize it as God, as consistently taught not by
the atheistic Sdhhkhya system but by the Sdhhkhya-Yoga, which
is deistic.
Ignoring the historical use of the word, Professor Deussen con-
cludes that the word aarnchkya as here used proves that the
author did not know it " as the name of the system opposed by
him"; whence his grand conclusion that the Saimkhya system
was developed from tendencies which may be seen in the Upani-
Vol. Xxii.] The 97vetavatara, etc. 383
shad, and conversely that the Samikhya system was not the base
of the Upanishad.
It will be seen at once that the whole difficulty lies in Deus-
sen s insistence on the (quite incorrect) idea that Samikhya-Yoga
implies atheism, or, in other words, that it is identical with bare
Samikhya. Reasoning in this way, he cannot admit that an ideal-
ist would applaud a realistic system, and so on through his three
antitheses, monism-dualism, theism-atheism, idealism-realism. The
sufficient answer to this is that the deistic interpretation of Sdira-
khya, which is implied in Sdufkhya-Yoga, does away with all these
antitheses. Sdihkhya-Yoga is monistic, theistic (i. e. deistic), ideal-
istic. What force there is in his argument is thus lost. His view
is based on a misinterpretation of a philosophical expression.
Strangely enough, while arguing as to the views men could not
have reconciled, Deussen overlooks the palpable fact that what
he assumes to have been an impossibility actually existed. And
not only did this (reconciliation of views) exist, but it existed as
the result of the constant attitude of great bodies of religious
philosophers, who employed exactly the same terms and meant
exactly the same thing as did the author of the Upanishad. They
were monists, theists, idealists, but to them the divine sage above
all sages was Kapila, the system they named as such and
expounded was the Safakhya-Yoga (in full), Yoga or Siaikhya
(for short). So in the Upanishad. There is no such opposition
as fills Deussen with incredulous distrust. The system is not (as
he thinks must be the case if s5dhkAya means Samikhya) first
lauded and then implicitly repudiated, because the " system " is
not what Deussen assumes it to be. He gives a meaning to Sami-
khya-Yoga which, so far as history shows, it never had.
The objection to Deussen's view may be formulated as follows.
It is unhistorical because it misinterprets the data of philosophi-
cal phraseology in three points:
1) The use of (dAydna)yoga at i. 3 is a factor in the argu-
ment intended to prose both that (Siihkhya) yoga at vi. 13
is merely Hbigebung and that the latter cannot refer to the
system later called Sdikhya-Yoga. The epic parallels refute
this. Not only do we find yogadhdrand and jftd-nayoga in
Gita viii. 12, and xvi. 1, respectively, but the very term of
the IUpauishad, dhydnayoga, at Gitd xviii. 52, and in xii.
195. 1, where dhya-nayoga is fourfold; but
384 E W. Hopkins, [1901
compared the two statements at xii. 350. 65 and xii. 218. 9, which
declare, respectively, that the Yoga system was promulgated by
Hiranyagarbha and that the Sarhkhyas call Kapila "Prajapati,"
whereas in the Upanishad he is "seer :" yam &huh Kapilam'
Shkhy(h paramarsim Prjajpatim. So of Kapila in the Bud-
dhacarita, xii. 21, it is said, Prajfrpatir iho 'cyate, when he is
introduced as the founder of the system. His regular epic title
is seer or great seer, mahign rpp ca Kapilah, for example, in xiii.
4. 56, where (like Yd-jfiavalkhya, 51) he is said to be of Ksatriya
descent, though elsewhere an incorporate divinity.
It is to be observed, moreover, that the Upanishad, in mentioning
Kapila as a great seer without directly ascribing to him the doc-
trine of the tract, is quite on a par with the Buddhacarita, where
the teaching is suddenly interrupted in its metaphysical flow by
the intrusion of " Kapila with his pupil," without any direct
statement that Kapila's doctrine is here set forth: (20) "Those
who think about the soul call the soul ksetraj'a-(21) Kapila
with his pupil, as the tradition goes, became awakened (illumi-
nated) here on earth; and he, the awakened, with his son is here
called Prajdpati-(22) What is born and grows old and is bound
and dies is to be known as vyaktam." On the other hand,'the
epic formally recognizes Kapila as divine seer, and ascribes to
him the Sdhkhya-system, interpreted as Yoga. In this regard it
represents an advance on the vaguer connection between Kapila
and the SAfhkhva (Yoga) doctrines of the Upanishad and Carita.
In the last, indeed, the stanza naming Kapila looks like an inter-
polation.
part of the usual equipment, and laghu for fine, beautiful, is well
known. Compare, for example, Mbh. viii. 19. 48 (58. 31), where
bolsters and blankets, apexastara, adorn horses. Another name
for the horse-blanket is kuth&. Horses ornamented with trap-
pings, camaras, and kuthas, and having khalinas, are described
at viii. 24. 64. The natural meaning of upagitdha, too, is
"covered." The khalina is the bridle (bit) of the later epic,
though it does not there (as here) "fill the mouth."