Srinivas Rao: 'Advaita: A Critical Study', Jnana Bharati, Bangalore.
88 pp. Rs. 25.
It is a tempting thing to try and philosophize like Wittgenstein did:
dealing with problems in a series of pointillistic statements of inquiry and analysis, which go to compose a canvas of balanced if enigmatic composition, and mind-blowing sweep. Srinivas Rao has not resisted this temptation, which I think a great many professional philosophers feel but dare not succumb to. The chances of an imitation working out do not seem high; depressingly, that is the case here. Writing in the terse, aphoristic style of the Tractatus or the Philosophical Investiga- tions is not, to put it mildly, an easy thing to carry off. The central thread of the critique concerns the rope-thread super- imposition. And things start unravelling from there on. For polemical purposes, the superimposition performs as an analogy; in a more pervasive way, one should properly look at it as a metaphor -- for perception, epistemic grasp and the definition of metaphysical exis- tence. Even as an analogy, its power is severely circumscribed -- it is no proof of the Advaitic doctrine. Treat it as a literal appeal to draw logical consequences for a metaphysical theory, and it blows up in your face. Why, asks Rao, are only false snakes and not real ones sublated. A fine touch of wry humour perhaps. An attempt to make an ironic metaphysical inquiry, and it becomes an illustration of taking a metaphor literally -- a cardinal sin, that. In consequence of this over- extended analysis, a confusion emerges between 'sadasadvilakdana'/ 'anirvacaniya' and 'asat'. Unless I am mistaken, Advaita does not hold the barren woman's son (from the empirical point of view) as analogous to the world (from the transcendental state), as the author seems to claim [5.4]. Rather, the whole point of the 'inexplicable' nature of the world is that it does not fall under either the category of the existent or the non-existent (in effect, the existential statement being neither true nor false, 'sat' nor 'asat'). If this is correct, then surely there is just this confusion in Rao's account with regard to the ontological status of the world. It is this unfortunate obfuscation that leads to talk of the world as 'non-existent' in the favoured Indian style of 'false' (i.e.,
Journal of Indian Philosophy 1 "7:101 - - 1 0 4 , 1 9 8 9 .
logically false). But actually, there is good reason to wonder if the
concept of 'mithya' (or terms used with roughly the same intent) is not a qualified doctrine which claims something other than transparently bivalent expression. What sets Advaita apart from psychologistic or perceptual idealism is precisely this notion of the ambiguity of the world's ontological status, given the conceptual tension between 'sat' and "asat'. It is from this that the whole mimicry of realism is possible in the 'vyavah6ra' realm, in the form of objective experience. In the light of Advaita's challenge to bivalent statements regarding existential notions (in the form of "sadasadvilak~ana' and 'anirvacaniya'), the author's whole project of exploiting the 'atman'-'anatman' distinction in terms of existence and non-existence becomes questionable. Which is a pity, because the argument as such about the incoherence of relating the 'andtman' and the transcendental '6tman' is quite nicely dealt with. I confess too that I do not see how Frege's puzzle of the Morning Star and Evening Star serves as a paradigm for the "reality-Reality" (i.e., world-Brahman) distinction [10.7--10.11], whether it be Hiriyana's original analogy or the retelling here. Reference itself is the problematic concept in the case of Brahman and the world. It is Advaita's point that the 'sense' in which we talk of the world fails to refer, going by the 'sense' in which Brahman is "Real". As the scare quotes imply, the convoluted and misread nature of the analogy becomes apparent. On the other hand, if it is an epistemological point that is being made (as in the Jastrow 'Duck-Rabbit Head'), the author only states the obvious fact that aspect-change does not change the object whose aspect changes. So too, Rao goes on, with the rope and the snake; and, he adds blithely, "this applies equally to 'reality' and 'Reality'". Since the whole thrust of the Advaitic argument is the incommensurability of world and Brahman, transition here as a parallel instance must be carefully explained; for that would in itself show a radically different interpretation of the Advaitic position regarding the relative natures of the world and Brahman. It should not be thrown in as self-evident. From a more traditional Indian metaphysical line, one wonders why Rao repeatedly talks of 'point of view' from 'Brahm6nubhdva" (trans- lated as 'transcendental experience'), not indeed as a conventional verbal device, but as if it were a metaphysical state. I would tend to think that the Advaitin would hold just that there is no such 'point of
THE POWER OF MIND: The Power of Concentration, The Key To Mental Power Development And Efficiency, Thought-Force in Business and Everyday Life, The Inner Consciousness…
(The Journal of Asian Studies 1962-Aug Vol. 21 Iss. 4) Review by - Alex Wayman - Advaita and Viśi Ādvaita - by S. M. Srinivasa Chari (1962) (10.2307 - 2050947) - Libgen - Li