Ayten Gundogdu
Ayten Gundogdu
Ayten Gundogdu
Ghuman’s case, while it is one of the few that received significant attention, is
by no means exceptional; this Kafkaesque world has become home to millions of
migrants in an age that is increasingly defined by extremely restrictive border policies.
Deportation without any possibility of appeal and arbitrary detention have now become
routine practices for states in managing the movement of people across borders.
Ghuman’s case demonstrates the possibility that even foreigners in relatively privileged
positions can be denied fundamental rights. Ghuman’s case is representative of the
pervasive problems encountered by millions of migrants who become vulnerable to
various forms of violence, discrimination, and abuse as they cross borders.
Arendt: The stateless were rightless in the sense that they were deprived of legal
personhood as well as the right to action and speech. Expulsion from their political
communities entailed an expulsion from humanity, as they lost not only their citizenship
rights but also their human rights. Questioning the idea that these are natural rights
inherent in human dignity, her critique highlights how the effective guarantees of
human rights rely on membership in an organized political community. Those who are
deprived of such a community can hardly be recognized as human beings entitled to
equal rights. They might be offered food and shelter as victims deserving compassion.
The stateless find themselves in a condition of rightlessness, Arendt argues, as they are
dispossessed of legal personhood, denied a political community that could render their
actions and speech relevant, and driven away from the company of other human beings.
She contends that “the concept of human rights was treated as a sort of stepchild
by nineteenth-century political thought” and was not taken up by any major political
party. Alluding to the international efforts to draft a universal declaration, she suggests
that these “best-intentioned humanitarian attempts” still remain within the confines of a
state-centric international law and fail to provide guarantees for a right to have rights. In
an essay published in 1949, before The Origins of Totalitarianism, she refers to the
declaration adopted by the United Nations and bemoans its “lack of reality.” In that
essay, she seems to catch a glimpse of hope in the emergence of humanity as a political
reality, especially when she suggests that this new development “makes the new
concept of ‘crimes against humanity,’ expressed by Justice Jackson at the Nuremberg
Trials, the first and most important notion of international law.”
With the advent of détente in Cold War, human rights concerns started to occupy
a prominent place in the agendas. The transnational advocacy networks created have
been crucial in providing informal mechanisms of enforcement and putting pressure on
governments to change those policies that are in violation of human rights. In addition,
in the mid-1970s, states also started to incorporate human rights into their foreign
policy, which meant that they could use various forms of sanctions against those states
that refuse to comply with human rights norms. There has been a sea change in our
understanding of human rights since the time Arendt completed her analysis of
statelessness; to use Louis Henkin’s phrase, ours is “the age of rights.”
Marx’s critique in the “On the Jewish Question” operates with a reappropriation
of Hegelian dialectics, whereas Arendt’s aporetic inquiry proceeds in a quite Socratic
mode (38). Whereas in the past a new body politic could legitimate its founding with
reference to divine authority, secularization leaves political actors with the problem of
finding a new authority for the laws, rights, and institutions they establish. This problem
attending the founding of any body politic in the modern era becomes especially
manifest in declarations of rights: “There is no period in history to which the
Declaration of the Rights of Man could have harkened back... [I]nalienable political
rights of all men by virtue of birth would have appeared to all ages prior to our own as
they appeared to Burke—a contradiction in terms.” Precisely because the past cannot
authorize this new conception of rights, there is the urge to find a new foundation.
Grounding rights in nature must be understood then in relation to revolutionary crises
and emergencies that initiated the search for a new “transcendent source of authority” or
“an absolute from which to derive authority for law and power.”
One of the problems with taking nature as the foundation of the Rights of Man
comes to light with the modern tendency to understand this concept mostly in biological
terms. The danger of equalization on the basis of a shared biological nature is that the
Rights of Man will come to stand for the basic necessities of life. But the crisis of
statelessness reveals the problems with this position: There might be cases where people
may be provided basic necessities such as food and shelter but still lack the recognition
as rights-bearing subjects. One of the problems with taking nature as the foundation of
the Rights of Man comes to light with the tendency to understand this concept mostly in
biological terms. The danger of equalization on the basis of a shared biological nature is
that the Rights of Man will come to stand for the basic necessities of life. But the crisis
of statelessness reveals the problems with this position. The most crucial limit of taking
nature as the basis of rights comes to view, according to Arendt, with the plight of the
stateless who are “thrown back into a peculiar state of nature. The Rights of Man are
understood as “primary positive rights, inherent in man’s nature, as distinguished from
his political status.” The problems with this presupposition, implying that human rights
can exist in isolation or in the absence of a political community, become evident as soon
as we encounter those who are stripped of all political qualifications and relationships
(39). “Perhaps this is the most confounding perplexity that confronts us in thinking of
human rights as natural rights: Those who appear in their mere givenness or naked
humanity cannot be recognized as subjects entitled to equal rights. By grappling with
this problem, Arendt aims to show that human rights do not precede and ground politics
and citizenship; it is polítics and citizenship that need to be prioritized for human rights
to have any effective guarantees” (40).
If Arendt disapproves of the French for being driven by “the social question,” or
poverty, she also criticizes the Americans for their utter neglect of it. Far from justifying
the exclusion of the poor from the political realm, she in fact insists that satisfaction of
basic material needs and provision of negative liberties are not sufficient measures to
tackle poverty (69). Read in this light, the lesson to be drawn from Arendt’s account of
“the social question” is not that the politicization of the Rights of Man necessarily ends
in violence but instead that a moralistic approach to human suffering can easily turn into
an instrumentalist understanding of politics as a means (if necessary, violent means) to
achieve moral goals. This moral economy is neither inevitable nor irresistible in efforts
to address human suffering; but such efforts need to be guarded against the danger of
yielding to the demands of this moral economy, and contemporary practices and
institutions of human rights are not immune to this danger (71). Lo analiza desde
Melville.
Después de criticar la Labor Arendt hace esta afirmación: “From the revolutions
of 1848 to the Hungarian revolution of 1956, the European working class, by virtue of
being the only organized and hence the leading section of the people, has written one of
the most glorious and probably the most promising chapter of recent history” (82). [La
cuestión es: excluir la labor no es lo mismo que excluir a los laborantes: también se
podria buscar la frase en alemán]. [La gran sorpresa de los movimientos laboristas es
que convierte a los laborantes en actores políticos]. [Lo inesperado de la acción es que
tambén puede surgir de los laborantes o los refugiados: de los excluidos: pensar en
Sabbatai Zevi]. To point out the importance of political emancipation, Arendt
underscores the difference between slave labor and modern, free labor. The difference is
not simply that the slave lacks “personal freedom,” she argues, but that the modern
worker “is admitted to the political realm and fully emancipated as a citizen.” (84).
Arendt’s invocation of a right to have rights continues to puzzle her readers, and
scholarly debates have centered on the qüestions related to the status and source of this
right that is not legally codified: If this new right cannot derive its validity from any
existing legal framework, what is its foundation? And can Arendt’s political theory
offer a normative framework? Benhabib, for example, argues that Arendt’s political
theory provides no such foundation: Scholars such as Peg Birmingham and Serena
Parekh respond by locating foundations for human rights in Arendt’s political theory.
Far from being a theorist opposed to the philosophical projects of normative
justification, they argue, one of Arendt’s “primary concerns” is “the working out of a
theoretical foundation for a reformulation of the modern notion of human rights.” (165).
“Accordingly, Arendt’s call for a right to have rights can be taken as a new
beginning, which brings forth a right that was not known or given in the existing
configuration of rights and citizenship in an International order organized around the
principle of nationality. Understood in these terms, it invites us to rethink human rights
in terms of practices of political founding and draws attention to the vital importance of
declarin rights in this regard” (171). [With the 18th revolutions, what we are confronted
with is a new form of articulating and instituting rights. In Lefort’s terms: a declaration
by which human beings, speaking through their representatives, revealed themselves to
be both the subject and the object of the utterance in which they named the human
elements in one another, ‘spoke to’ one another, appeared before one another, and
therefore erected themselves into their own judges, their own witnesses (172).
Reading Arendt’s call for a right to have rights as an invitation to rethink human
rights in terms of political practices of founding (especially declaratory practices) has
three main implications. First and foremost, this reading draws attention to the crucial
role of action, especially speech, in the continuous reinvention of human rights (172).
Second, a right to have rights marks a new beginning radically interrupting the existing
regime of human rights and introducing “a hiatus between the end of the old order and
the beginning of the new,” or “between a no-longer and a not-yet” (173). Human rights
are not simply normative constraints regulating an existing political and legal order but
also political inventions that can constitute a new order. Understood in these terms,
human rights have an “insurrectional” dimension, to use Balibar’s term, because they
can turn against the constituted political and normative order for the purposes of
founding a new one. Finally, this reading allows a different understanding of the
perplexities arising from Arendt’s call for a right to have rights; instead of seeing them
as representative of the normative deficiencies of her political thought, it takes them as
illuminating starting points for wrestling with the perplexities of new beginnings that
break with the existing order (173). [“Arendt’s argument about the American
Revolution draws attention to her unique understanding of authority. Insisting on the
etymological connection between authority (auctoritas) and augmentation (augere),
Arendt renders authority dependent on the ongoing practices of augmentation, which
involve not simply conservation but also strengthening and amendment. Accordingly,
laws and rights do not have an irresistible and incontrovertible authority derived from
an extra-political source; they are in need of an ongoing authorization in and through
political practices that reenact and augment the principle manifested in the founding”
(182)]. [Arendt’s essay “Civil Disobedience” further clarifies her Montesquieuan notion
of principle and dispels the doubt that her understanding of authority in terms of
practices of augmentation entails “a unitary and consensual” picture overlooking the
conflicts, disagreements, and exclusions that characterize political acts of founding].
Here, we can think of how the Haitian Revolution appropriated the terms of the
1789 Declaration, which had sidestepped the issue of slavery, in unpredictable and
imaginative ways to question slavery. [This last point shares similarities with
Benhabib’s proposal to understand human rights in terms of “democratic iterations” that
involve practices of contesting and redefining existing inscriptions of rights. Drawing
on and reinterpreting Jacques Derrida’s work, Benhabib suggests that such iterations do
not simply reproduce what they repeat; each iteration “transforms meaning, adds to it,
enriches it in ever-so-subtle ways]. Human rights owe their origins, guarantees, and
reinvention to political practices of declaring and enacting rights in ways that are not
fully authorized by the prevailing institutional and normative frameworks (188).
These connections become palpable in the public demonstrations of sans-
papiers. For example, in May and June 2010, hundreds camped in front of the opera
house at the Place de la Bastille in Paris. By choosing this symbolic site, sans-papiers
“claimed a place for themselves in the revolutionary and republican history in France”
(196). Sans-papiers started their demonstrations at the Church of St. Ambroise on
March 18, 1996, and that it was on March 18 of 1871 that the Paris Commune seized
power in the city. As Vincenzo Ruggiero notes, one of the slogans that sans-papiers
used at the time was “March 18, 1996, on c’est levé (we have risen).” Several scholars
proposed rethinking sans-papiers’political practices as a new form of citizenship: Sans-
papiers do lack the legal status of citizenship, but they act as if they were citizens (198).
Is the lack of prior authorization for these acts of citizenship. Sans-papiers’ struggles
reveal that human rights understood as a right to have rights ultimately depend on a type
of citizenship enacted by those who do not have a legitimate standing and yet who
thrust themselves into the public spaces from which they are excluded. From an
Arendtian perspective, these practices reenact and augment the principle of equaliberty
manifest in the eighteenth-century declarations, and they are indispensable to the
continuous reinvention of human rights. Sans-papiers’ words and deeds affirm this
principle in many respects: They demonstrate that equality and freedom are to be
understood not as inherent human attributes, but instead as political achievements that
are in need of each other. In addition, sans-papiers’ protests highlight that the subjects
of rights are not passive beneficiaries but political actors capable of declaring and
vindicating rights in struggles affirming their political and human standing (198). [It is
quite puzzling that Arendt describes The Castle as “the one novel in which Kafka
discusses the Jewish problem” or “the only one in which the hero is plainly a Jew,”
given that K. is not described as Jewish in the novel. What renders K. Jewish, according
to Arendt, is not “any typically Jewish trait,” but instead that “he is involved in
situations and perplexities distinctive of Jewish life].