Cohen 2
Cohen 2
Cohen 2
• John Barry Memorial Lecture, University of Melbourne, 30 September, 1992. The research referred to
in this lecture is funded by a grant from the Ford Foundation International Human Rights Programme.
flnstitute of Criminology, Faculty of Law, Hebrew University, Jerusalem 91905, ISRAEL
98 STANLEY COHEN (1993) 26 ANZJ Crim
rights. My case does not need the standard PhD opening: everyone has ignored the
subject except me. What I am saying, is that the subject has often been raised and
then its implications conveniently repressed. This is a process strangely reminiscent
of my substantive interest in the sociology of denial: how information is known but
its implications are not acknowledged.
The first significant confrontation with the subject came in the early phase of
radical criminology in the late sixties. That favourite debate of the times - "who are
the real criminals?" - naturally turned attention from street crime to white
collar/corporate crime and then to the wider notion of "crimes of the powerful". The
particular context of the Vietnam War, pushed our slogans ("Hey, hey LBJ! How
many kids have you killed today?") explicitly in the direction of "crimes of the state".
In criminology, this sentiment was expressed in the much cited paper by the
Schwendingers (1970) entitled "Defenders of Order or Guardians of Human
Rights?" Looking back at this text, it appears a missed opportunity to deal with the
core issues of state crime.
Quite rightly, the Schwendingers saw themselves going in the same direction, but
a step further than Sutherland by invoking the criterion of social injury to define
crime. In the case of white collar crime, this mandated us to go beyond criminal law
into the areas of civil and administrative law. The Schwendingers then noted that if
Sutherland had consistently followed what they rightly call his "ethical" rather than
legal categorisation, he should also have arrived at those other socially injurious
actions which are not defined as either criminal or civil law violations. So far, so
good. But their argument then goes awry.
Firstly, they cite as examples of other socially injurious action (their only
examples) "genocide and economic exploitation". Now, besides the fact that these
are hardly morally equivalent categories, genocide is crucially different from
economic exploitation. It is recognised in current political discourse as crime by the
state; it is clearly illegal by internal state laws; and since the Nuremberg Judgements
and the 1948 UN Convention Against Genocide, it is a "crime" according to
international law. Genocide belongs to the same conceptual universe as "war
crimes" and "crimes against humanity". By any known criteria, genocide is more self
evidently criminal than economic exploitation.
The Schwendingers make no such distinctions nor try to establish the criminality
of human rights violations. Instead they launch into a moral crusade against
imperialistic war, racism, sexism and economic exploitation. We might agree with
their ideology and we might even use the term "crime" rhetorically to describe
racism, sexism and economic exploitation. This type of sixties rhetoric indeed
anticipates the current third and fourth generation "social rights". A more restricted
and literal use of the concept "state crime" however, is both more defensible and
useful. If we come from the discourse of human rights, this covers what is known in
the jargon (for once, not euphemistic ) as "gross" violations of human rights -
genocide, mass political killings, state terrorism, torture, disappearances. Ifwe come
from the discourse of criminology, we are talking about clear criminal offences -
murder, rape, espionage, kidnapping, assault.
I don't want to get into definitional quibbles. Enough to say that the extension of
criminology into the terrain of state crimes, can be justified without our object of
study becoming simply everything we might not like at the time. Let us see what
happened after that mid-sixties to mid-seventies phase when questions about state
crimes and human rights were placed on the criminological agenda by the radicals.
HUMAN RIGHTS AND CRIMES OF mE STATE: THE CULTURE OF DENIAL 99
What mostly happened was that the human rights connection became lost. In the
discourse of critical criminology, the putative connection between crime and politics
took two different directions, both quite removed from the idea of state crime.
The first was the short-lived notion of the criminal as proto-revolutionary actor
and the extension of this to all forms of deviance. This whole enterprise - referred
to as the "politicisation of deviance" - was soon abandoned and eventually
denounced as naive, romantic and sentimental. 1 The second connection - which
turned out the more productive - was the focus on the criminalising power of the
state. This led to the whole revisionist discourse on the sociology of law, social
control and punishment that has remained so salient and powerful.
But neither direction leads anywhere near towards talking about state crimes. The
subject simply faded away from criminological view in the mid-seventies to
mid-eighties. By the time left realist criminology appeared, we move entirely from
"crimes of the state" back to the "state of crime." Today, the subject has re-appeared
from two contexts, one external to the discipline, the other internal.
The external context is the incremental growth of the international human rights
movement itself. Emerging from the United Nations Charter and the great
declarations and conventions of the next decade, from international governmental
organisations such as UNESCO and the Council of Europe, from fledgling pressure
groups such as Amnesty International to the vast current list of national and
international non-governmental organisations, the human rights movement has
become a major institutional force. Pushed by the rhetorical use of "human rights"
by the Carter Adminstration about Latin America and its critique of the Soviet
Union, the ideal of human rights took on a powerful life of its own. It has become a
secular religion.
This discourse, of course, is very dense, complex and contradictory (Social Justice,
1989). "Human Rights" has become a slogan raised from most extraordinary
different directions. Progressive forces and organisations like Amnesty can enlist
famous rock stars to perform in defence of international human rights. Right wing
pressure groups in the USA can unseat politicians and defeat Supreme Court
nominations by invoking the human rights of the unborn foetus. Civil liberties
groups defend pornography on the grounds of freedom of speech and the women's
movement attack this freedom as an assault on the human rights of women. Nations
with the most appalling record of state violence and terror can self-righteously join
together in the UN to condemn other nations for their human rights violations.
Some human rights activists are awarded the Nobel Peace Prize, others are jailed,
tortured, have disappeared or been assassinated. The human rights of one group are
held sacred, the rights of another totally ignored ... and so on.
But whatever the concept of human rights means, it has become a dominant
narrative. Arguably, with the so-called death of the old meta-narratives of marxism,
liberalism and the cold war, human rights will become the normative political
language of the future. I have no time to go into its conceptual ambiguities - the
difference between civil and human rights, the relationship between political and
human rights work, the tension between universalism and cultural relativism. Nor
can I raise the numerous policy issues of policing, enforcement and international
law. One of the most salient issues for criminologists, raised dramatically by the
current horrors in the former Yugoslavia, is the long-proposed establishment of an
international criminal tribunal.
So this is one way - from the outside - that criminologists as citizens who read
the news, must have become aware of the subject of human rights violations and
crimes of the state. Not that you know about this awareness if you just read
100 STANLEY COHEN (1993) 26 ANZJ Crim
criminological texts. There is, however, one intemal way in which the subject has
been registered in criminology. This is through the growth of victimology.
There are many obvious echoes of human rights issues in victimologicalliterature
- whether in the feminist debate about female victims of male sexualised violence;
in talking about children and children's rights; in the concern about victims of
corporate crime, ecological abuse, etc. Some students (Karmen, 1990) find these
echoes only in "radical" rather than "conservative" or "liberal" victiminology. The
conservative tendency is concerned with victims of street crime, making offenders
accountable, encouraging self reliance and advocating retributive justice. The liberal
tendency includes white collar crime, is concerned with making the victim "whole"
and advocates restitution and reconciliation. Only the radical tendency extends to all
forms of human suffering and sees law and the criminal justice system as implicated
in this suffering.
This distinction, though, between conservative, liberal and radical tendencies is
not always clear. And in the context of one crucial subject - what happens to state
criminals such as torturers after democratisation or a change in regime - the
distinction breaks down altogether. Here, it is the "radicals" who call for
punishment and retributive justice, while it is the "conservatives" who invoke ideals
such as reconciliation to call for impunity."
In any event, these external and internal inputs are slowlymaking their way into
criminology. In the mainstream, this can be seen in recent standard textbooks which
explicity deal with the subject of state crime, and others which consider the human
rights definition of crime.
In the radical stream, there is Barak's recent (1991) volume Crime By the Capitalist
State. The editor makes a strong case for including state criminality in the field of
criminology - both on the grounds that the consequences of state crimes are more
widespread and destructive than traditional crime and because this would be a
logical extension of the already accepted move into the field of white collar crime.
The overall tone of the volume, though, is too redolent of the sixties' debates:
general ideas about discrimination and abuse of political and economic power, the
focus only on capitalism and the disproportionate attention on worldwide low
intensity warfare by the USA (CIA, counter-insurgency etc).
Despite this recent interest, major gaps in the criminological discourse remain:
(a) First, there is little understanding that a major source of criminalisation at
national and international levels draws on the rhetoric of human rights. Significant
waves of moral enterprise and criminalisation over the last decade are derived not
from the old middle-class morality, the Protestant ethic nor the interests of
corporate capitalism, but from the feminist, ecological and human rights
movements. A major part of criminology is supposed to be the study of law making
- criminalisation - but we pay little attention to the driving force behind so many
new laws: the demand for protection from "abuses of power". The radical slogans of
the sixties have become the common place of any government and inter-government
forum. Alongside our standard research on domestic legislatures and ministries of
justice, we should see what our foreign ministries are doing - at the Council of
Europe, the United Nations, etc.
(b) Another important defect in recent literature is its American focus. It is
pre-occupied with "exposures" - of the CIA (eg, drug running in Vietnam), FBI
surveillance methods, the global drug wars, international arms dealing, etc. This
results in a certain ethnocentrism, but also allows the derivative subjects (political
economy, globalisation, state propaganda, illegal clandestine operations, counter
intelligence) to be denied as being "normal politics" (like the white collar crime
HUMAN RIGHTS AND CRIMES OF THE STATE: THE CULTURE OF DENIAL 101
issue allowed the denial of "normal business"). For my purposes here, I want to
stress not the politicality of the subject but its criminality. For this, we don't need
theories of the state, we need merely to pick up the latest Amnesty Annual Report.
(c) If we have missed something about law making, we have ignored even more
the facts of victimisation. Again, there is a ritualistic acknowledgement of the
damage, harm and violence that are the obvious consequences of state crime - and
then we return to easier topics. It is as if we don't want to face these facts; as if - to
anticipate the substance of the second part of my lecture - we have denied their
implications. I am aware that phrases such as "crimes of the twentieth century"
sound bombastic - but for vast populations of the world, this is a fair
characterisation of those "gross violations of human rights": genocide, mass political
killings, disappearances, torture, rape by agents of state,"
This terrible record is known but (as I will show) simultaneously not known. Take
genocides and mass political killings only: the Turkish genocide of at least a million
Armenians; the Holocaust against six million Jews and the hundreds of thousands of
political opponents, gypsies and others; the millions killed under Stalin's regime; the
tribal and religious massacres in Burundi, Bengal and Paraguay; the mass political
killings in East Timor and Uganda; the "autogenocide" in Cambodia; the "ethnic
cleansing" in Bosnia; the death squads and disappearance in Argentina, Guatamala,
El Salvador. Or take torture - a practise supposedly eradicated from Europe by the
beginning of the 19th century and now routinely used in two thirds of the world.
To add up the deaths, injuries and destruction from all these sources and then
compare this to the cumulative results of homicide, assault, property crime and
sexual crime in even the highest crime countries of the world, is too tendentious an
exercise, too insulting to the intelligence. One cannot calibrate human suffering in
this way.
But criminologists do, after all talk about offence "seriousness". The standard
literature in this area - and allied debates on culpability, harm, responsibility and
the "just desserts" model - already compares street crime with white collar crime.
A current important contribution (von Hirsch and Jareborg, 1991) tries to gauge
criminal harm by using a "living .standard analysis". Von Hirsch and his colleague
have argued ingeniously that criminal acts can be ranked by a complicated scale of
"degrees of intrusion" on different kinds of legally protected interests: physical
integrity; material support and amenity; freedom from humiliation; privacy and
autonomy.
What von Hirsch calls "interests" are strikingly close to what are also called
"human rights". His examples, however, come only from the standard criminological
terrain of citizen against citizen. Including corporate crime would extend the list to
(business) organisations against citizen. This is certainly an interesting and
worthwhile exercise. It allows, for example, the ranking of forcible rape by a stranger
as very grave because this is so demeaning and gross an attack against the "freedom
from humiliation" interest; therefore rape at gun point becomes more serious than
armed robbery; date rape comes lower on the cumulative scale on grounds that
threat to bodily safety is eliminated, and so on.
But neither crimes of state nor the wider category of "political crime" are
mentioned. There is no logical reason why the identity of the offender should be
assumed to be fixed as citizen against citizen, rather than state agent against citizen
when talking about, say, murder, assault or rape. In fact, there are good moral
reasons why any grading of seriousness should take this into account - in particular,
the fact that the very agent responsible for upholding law, is actually responsible for
the crime. And there is a good empirical reason: that for large parts of the world's
102 STANLEY COHEN (1993) 26 ANZJ Crim
population, state agents (or para military groups, vigilantes or terrorists) are the
normal violators of your "legally protected interests".
I don't want to oversimplify the many conceptual objections and obstacles that
criminologists will legitimately raise to my glib appeal to include state crime in our
frame of reference. Most such objections fall under two categories:
First, there are the equivalent arguments to those used in the field of corporate
crime - that the state is not an actor and that individual criminal responsibility
cannot be identified. For corporate crime, this objection has been disposed of often
enough, most recently (and to my mind convincingly) by Braithwate and Fisse
(1990). The corporation engages in rational goal seeking behaviour; it can act; it can
have intentions; it can commit crimes. This is just as (though more complicatedly)
true for the state.
The second objection (again paralleled from Sutherland onwards in the case of
corporate crime) is that the resultant action is not "really" crime. Here, the
counter-arguments are complicated and come from a number of different directions:
(i) an appeal to international law and conventions on such concepts as "war crimes"
or "crimes against humanity"; (ii) a demonstration that these acts are illegal by
domestic criminal law and fit all criteria of "crime"; (iii) and even if the acts in
question are legal by internal state jurisdiction, then the question arises of how this
legal legitimation occurs. We have to remember (perhaps by inscribing this on our
consciousness each morning) that state crimes are not just the unlicenced terror of
totalitarian or fascist regimes, police states, dictatorships or military juntas. And in
even the most extreme of these regimes, such as Nazi Germany, the discourse of
legality is used (Muller, 1991).
One of the clearest and most eloquent texts for understanding these symbiotic
issues of responsiblity and criminality, is the 1985 trial in Argentina of the former
military junta members responsible for the mass killings, atrocities, disappearances
of the "dirty war". Reports of this trial (eg, by Amnesty International) should be on
all criminology reading lists.
The reasons why we don't make these connections are less logical than
epistemological. The political discourse of the atrocity is, as I will soon show,
designed to hide its presence from awareness. This is not a matter of secrecy, in the
sense of lack of access to information, but an unwillingness to confront anomalous or
disturbing information. Take the example of torture. Democratic-type societies -
the French in Algeria (Maran, 1989); the British in Northern Ireland; the Israelis in
the Occupied Territories (Cohen, 1991) - could all proclaim their adherence to
international conventions and domestic laws against torture. This called for a
complex discourse of denial that what they were doing constituted torture. No, it was
something else, "special procedures" or "moderate physical pressure". So something
happened - but it was not illegal. In more totalitarian societies (with no
accountability, no free press, no independent judiciary) denial is simpler - you do
it, but say you do not. Nothing happened.
The standard vocabulary of official (government) denial weaves its way - at times
simulaneously, at times sequentially - through a complete spiral of denial. First you
try "it didn't happen". There was no massacre, no one was tortured. But then the
media, human rights organisations and victims show that it does happen: here are
the graves; we have the photos; look at the autopsy reports. So you have to say that
what happened was not what it looks to be but really something else: a "transfer of
population", "collateral damage", "self defence". And then - the crucial subtext -
what happened anywaywas completely justified - protecting national security, part
of the war against terrorism. So:
HUMAN RIGHTS AND CRIMES OF 11-IE STATE: 11-IE CULTURE OF DENIAL 103
Note that unlike most societies where gross human rights violations occur, the
facts are both private and public knowledge. Nearly everyone has direct personal
knowledge, especially from army service. These are not conscripts or mercenary
soldiers drawn from the underclass; everybody serves (including the middle class
liberals) or has a husband, son, cousin or neighbour in reserve duty. There is a
relatively open press, liberal in tone, which regularly and clearly exposes what is
happening in the Occupied Territories. No one - least of all the group which
interests me - can say those terrible (though, as I will show, complicated) words "I
didn't know."
It is way beyond my scope to discuss the special reasons in Israel for denial,
passivity or indifference. These are part of a complex political history - of being
Jewish, of Zionism, of fear and insecurity. I mention this case only because it led me
to comparisons, to looking for similarities and differences in other societies. I went
back to my experience of growing up in apartheid South Africa. More fatefully, 1
turned to the emblematic events of this century: the Holocaust "texts" about the
good Germans who knew what was happening; the lawyers and doctors who
colluded; the ordinary people who passed by the concentration camps everyday and
claimed not to know what was happening; the politicians in Europe and America
who did not believe what they were told. Then from this one historical event, I went
to the contemporary horrors reported every day in the mass media and documented
by human rights reports - about Bosnia, Peru, Guatamala, Burma, Uganda ...
All this - and the relevant social scientific literature - led me back to versions of
the same universal question. This is not Milgram's famous question of how ordinary
people will behave in terrible ways, but rather how ordinary, even good people, will
not react appropriately to knowledge of the terrible. Why, when faced by knowledge
of others' suffering and pain - particularly the suffering and pain resulting from
what are called "human rights violations" - does "reaction" so often take the form
of denial, avoidance, passivity, indifference, rationalisation or collusion?
I have mentioned the official state discourse: the pure denials (it didn't happen,
they are lying, the media are biased, the world community is just picking on us) and
the pure justifications (deterrence, self defence, national security, ideology,
information gathering). But my concern is not the actor but rather (back, in a
curious way, to labelling theory!) the audience. In the triangle of human suffering so
familiar to criminologists - the victim, to whom things are done; the perpetrator,
who is activelycausing the suffering; the observer who sees and knows - my interest
lies in this third corner: the audience, the observers, the bystanders.
For my purposes here, I want to consider a specific group of obselVers - not
those whose avoidance derives from (crudely speaking) their support for the action.
If they see nothing morally wrong or emotionally disturbing in what is happening,
why should they do anything? In this sense, their denial or passivity is "easy" to
explain. My interest is more in the subgroup who are ideologically predisposed to be
against what is happening, to be disturbed by what they know. How do they react to
their knowledge of the terrible?
Before presenting some lines of enquiry into this subject, let me note an important
distinction which I won't have time to follow through. In talking about the denial of
atrocities or human rights violations, there is a world of difference between reacting
to your own government's actions as distinct from what might be happening in a
distant country. My response, say, as an Australian, to newspaper revelations about
the treatment of Aborigines in custody, follows different lines from my response to
sitting in Melbourne and reading a human rights report about death squads in
EI Salvador.
HUMAN RIGHTS AND CRIMES OF THE STATE: THE CULTURE OF DENIAL 105
I have only just started work on this subject and can present you with not much
more than my original research proposal. First, I will list some of the more useful
bodies of literature which deal - directly, but more often obliquely - with the
general phenomenon of denial. Then I will give a preliminary classification of the
major forms of denial. Finally, I will note a few questions from my fieldwork on
human rights organisations. Through interviews, analysis of publications,
educational material advertisements and campaign evaluations, I am trying to
understand how human rights messages are disseminated and received.
This last part of the work is a study in communication. The sender is the
international human rights community (directly or through the mass media). The
audience is our real and metaphorical bystanders. The message is something like this
(to quote from an actual Amnesty International advert in Britain in 1991):
Brazil has solved the Problem ofhow to keep kids off the street. Kill Them.
What bodies of literature might be of relevance?
(1) The Psychology ofDenial
Orthodox psychoanalysis sees denial as an unconscious defence mechanism for
coping with guilt and other disturbing psychic realities. Freud originally
distinguished between "repression" which applies to defences against internal
instinctual demands and "denial" (or what he called "disavowal") which applies to
defences against the claims of external reality.
With a few exceptions, pure psychoanalytic theory has paid much less attention to
denial in this sense than repression (but see Edelstein, 1989). We have to look in the
more applied fields of psychoanalysis (or its derivatives) for studies about the denial
of external information. This yields a mass of useful material. There is the rich
literature on the denial of knowledge about fatal disease (especially cancer and
more recently, AIDS) affecting self or loved ones. More familiar to criminologists,
there is the literature on family violence and pathology: spouse abuse, child abuse,
incest etc. The concept of denial is standard to describe a mother's reaction on
"discovering" that her husband had been sexually abusing their daughter for many
years: "I didn't notice anything". In this case, the concept implies that in fact the
mother did "know" - how could she not have? - but that this knowledge was too
unbearable to confront.
The subject of denial has also been dealt with by cognitive psychology and
information theory. Of particular interest is the "denial paradox": in order to use the
term "denial" to describe a person's statement "I didn't know", you have to assume
that he or she knew or knows about what it is he or she claims not to know
(otherwise the term "denial" is inappropriate).
Cognitive psychologists have used the language of information processing,
selective perception, filtering, attention span etc, to understand the phenomenon of
how we notice and simultaneously do not notice (Goleman, 1985). Some have even
argued that the neurological phenomenon of "blindsight" suggests a startling
possibility: that one part of the mind may know just what it is doing, while the part
that supposedly knows, remains oblivious of this.
We are all familiar, from basic social psychology, with the notion of cognitive bias:
the selection of information to fit existing perceptual frames. At the extreme,
information which is too threatening to absorb is shut out altogether. The mind
somehow grasps what is going on, but rushes a protective filter into place, steering
information away from what threatens. Information slips into a kind of "black hole
of the mind" - a blind zone of blocked attention and self deception. Attention is
106 STANLEY COHEN (1993) 26 ANZJ Crim
thus diverted from facts or their meaning. Thus, the "vital lies" sustained by family
members about violence, incest, sexual abuse, infidelity, unhappiness. Lies continue
unrevealed, covered up by the family's silence, collusion, alibis and conspiracies
(Goleman, 1985).
Similar processes have been well documented outside both the social psychology
laboratory and intimate settings like the family. The litany by observers of atrocities
is all too familiar: "we didn't see anything", "no one told us", "it looked different at
the time"."
In addition to psychoanalytical and cognitive theory, there is also the tradition in
philosophical psychology concerned with questions of self knowledge and self
deception. The Sartrean notion of "bad faith" is of particular interest in implying -
contrary to psychoanalytical theory - that the denial is indeed conscious.
doing my duty, just a cog in the machine. (For individual offenders like the
ordinary soldier, this is the most pervasive and powerful of all denial
systems).
• condemnation of the condemners - here, the politics are obviously more
explicit than in the original delinquency context. Instead of condemning the
police for being corrupt and biased or teachers for being hypocrites, we
have the vast discourse of official denial used by the modern state to protect
its public image: the whole world is picking on us; they are using double
standards to judge us; it's worse elsewhere (Syria, Iraq, Guatamala or
wherever is convenient to name); they are condemning us only because of
their anti-semitism (the Israeli version), their hostility to Islam (the Arab
version), their racism and cultural imperialism in imposing Western values
(all Third World tyrannies).
• appeal to higher loyalty - the original subdued "ideology" is now total and
self-righteous justification. The appeal to the army, the nation, the volk, the
sacred mission, the higher cause - whether the revolution, "history", the
purity of Islam, Zionism, the defence of the free world or state security. As
the tragic events of the last few years show, despite the end of the cold war,
the end of history and the decline of meta narratives, there is no shortage of
"higher loyalties", old and new.
Let us remember the implications of accounts theory for our subject. Built into the
offender's action, is the knowledge that certain accounts will be accepted. Soldiers
on trial for, say, killing a peaceful demonstrator, can offer the account of "obeying
orders" because this will be honoured by the legal system and the wider public. This
honouring is, of course, not a simple matter: Were the orders clear? Did the soldier
suspect that the order was illegal? Where in the chain of command did the order
originate from? These, and other ambiguities, make up the stuff of legal, moral and
political discourses of denial.
I have no time here to apply each of these theoretical frameworks -
psychoanalysis, cognitive psychology, bystander theory, motivational accounts etc -
to my case study of reactions to knowledge of human rights violations and state
crimes. (There are obviously also many other relevant fields: political socialisation
and mobilisation, mass media analysis, collective memory). For illustration only, let
me list some elementary forms of denial which these theories might illuminate.
I will distinguish three forms of denial, each of which operates at (i) the individual
or psychic level and (ii) at the organised, political, collective or official level.
issue (such as torture or the death penalty)? And which countries or which issues?
Are some techniques of confronting denial - for example, inducing guilt or
representing the horrors more vividly - counter-productive? Is there competition
for the human rights message within the same audiences (for example, from the
environmental movement)? ...
Conclusion
It is difficult to find a conclusion for one lecture of this type, even harder for two. My
first lecture was an attempt to nudge criminologists to be interested in state crimes
and human rights violations. My second lecture was a sketch for a sociology of
denial. In both cases, all I have done is to place familiar issues in different packages.
Instead of a conclusion, let me instead end with two footnotes. One raises - dare
I say - some meta-theoretical issues; the other introduces a little optimism into an
otherwise bleak story.
(1) Meta Theory
I mentioned the strange neglect of these issues by new realist criminologists and
suggested that what is at stake is their sense of reality. But "reality" is not a word
used too easily these days - or if used, only politically correct in inverted commas.
This is the legacy of post structuralism, deconstructionism and post modernism.
There are a number of trends in post modernist theory which - usually unwittingly
- impinge on the human rights discourse. Let me mention a few such meta issues:
First, there is the question of moral relativism. This is the familiar claim - now
supposedly finally vindicated - that if there is no universal, foundational base for
morality (the death of meta-narratives), then it is impossible to stake out universal
values (such as those enshrined in human rights standards). Then comes the
derivative claim that such values and standards are Western, ethnocentric,
individualistic, alien and imposed.
Now, whatever the historical record, this claim has some strange political
implications. The standard and age-old government denials of the applicability of
international human rights norms - we are different, we face special problems, the
world doesn't understand us - now acquire a new philosophical dignity. And
further, the condemners are condemned for being ethnocentric and imperialist.
A similar problem comes from the assertion that local struggles for human rights
lose their meaning because they are informed by the very universal foundations and
master narratives now so thoroughly discredited or tarnished. This is again a
complex debate; I side with those who argue that no amount of deconstructive
scepticism should deny the force with which we defend these values. It is surely a
bizarre sight for Western progressives to be telling human rights activists from the
Third World or Eastern Europe that their struggle is, after all, not worth the candle.
A second problem is posed by the proclaimed end of history. This is the current
round of the old "end of ideology" game: the collapse of international socialism
finally proving the triumph of Western democratic capitalism. Besides the poverty of
the case itself, it can make little sense for those still living between death squads,
famine, disease and violence. For them, history is not over. But even if one meta
narrative has won and there is nothing left for "history" in the industrialised world,
then how does this world react to what is happening elsewhere? Why - if not
because of racism, selfishness, greed, and the type of denial I've talked about - do
the victors not devote more resources to achieve these values elsewhere?
A third post modernist theme is even more directly relevant to my subject here -
and potentially even more destructive. This is the attack on all modes of rational
112 STANLEY COHEN (1993) 26 ANZJ Crim
enquiry which work with positivist categories of reality. The human rights movement
can live without absolute, foundational values. But it cannot live with a theory which
denies any way of knowing what has really happened.' All of us who carried the
anti-positivist banners of the sixties are responsible for the emergent
epistemological circus.
Its apotheosis was reached a year ago. On 29 March 1991, shortly after the
cessation of hostilities in the Gulf War - just as thousands were lying dead and
maimed in Iraq, the country's infra-structure deliberately destroyed by savage
bombing, the Kurds abandoned to their fate - the high priest of post-modernism,
Jean Baudrillard, published an article entitled "The Gulf War Has Not Taken
Place" (Baudrillard, 1991b). The "true belligerents" he argued, are those who thrive
on the ideology of the truth of this war.
He was only being consistent with an article he wrote a few days before the war
(Baudrillard, 1991 a) in which he predicted that it would never happen. The war
existed only as a figment of media simulation, of imaginary scenarios that exceeded
all limits of real world facticity. The war, Baudillard had solemnly declared, was
strictly unthinkable except as an exchange of threats so exorbitant that it would
guarantee that the-event would not take place. The "thing" would happen only in the
minds of its audience, as an extension of the video games imagery which had filled
our screens during the long build up. Dependent as we all were - prime time
viewers as well as generals - on these computer generated images, we might as well
drop all self-deluding distinctions between screen events and "reality".
Given this "prediction", it was unlikely that Baudrillard would be proved wrong if
the war really did break out. So indeed the "war" - a free floating signifier, devoid
of referential bearing - did not happen. To complain that he was caught out by
events only shows our theoretical naivete, our nostalgia for the old truth-telling
discourses.
What does one make of all this? I take my cue from Christopher Norris (1992)
who has devoted a splendid polemical book to attacking Baudrillard's theses on the
Gulf War. Norris is by no means a philistine critic or an unregenerated "positivist".
He is the author of altogether sympathetic studies of Derrida and
deconstructionism. And he concedes that Baudrillard makes some shrewd
observations about how the war was presented by its managers and the media: the
meaningless statistical data to create an illusory sense of factual reporting, the
absurd claims about "precision targeting", and "clever bombs" to convince us that
the mass destruction of civilian lives were either not happening (literal denial) or
were accidental (denial of responsibility).
But Norris is now appalled by the precious nonsense to which the fashionable
tracks of post modernism have led. What disturbs him is how seriously these ideas
were taken, "... to the point where Baudrillard can deliver his ludicrous theses on
the Gulf War without fear of subsequent exposure as a charlatan or of finding these
theses resoundingly disconfirmed by the course of real-world events". (Norris, p 17)
It is beyond my scope and competence to consider Norris's explanation for how
these ideas emerged and just where they lost their plausibility. He places particular
importance on the curious ascendancy of literary theory as a paradigm for other
areas of study. There is the bland assumption that because every text involves some
kind of narrative interest, therefore there is no way to distinguish factual, historical
or documentary material on the one hand from fictive, imaginary or simulated
material on the other. With no possible access to truth or historical record, we are
asked, Norris shows, to inhabit a realm of unanchored persuasive utterances where
HUMAN RIGHTS AND CRIMES OF THE STATE: THE CULTURE OF DENIAL 113
rhetoric goes all the way down and where nothing could count as an argument
against what the media or governments would have us currently believe.
This re-definition of history finds strange echoes, as Norris notes, among the right
wing revisionist historians of the holocaust, "... those for whom it clearly comes as
good news that past event can only be interpreted according to present consensus
values, or ideas of what currently and contingently counts as 'good in the way of
belief" (Norris, p 21). In the case of current events, like the Gulf War, we are left
with no resources to deal with the obvious contradictions between official
propaganda and personal witness (for example, about the bombing of the Amiriyah
civilian air raid shelter). The cult following of these ideas by some intellectuals
reflects, as Norris suggests, their lack of desire to make any political judgement, their
cynical acquiescence in the war. If the war was so unreal, so completely beyond our
competence to judge as informed observers, then we can say nothing to challenge
the official (media sponsored) version of events.
My point in raising this example is simple. If the Turkish government can deny
that the Armenian genocide happened; if revisionist historians and neo-Nazis deny
that the Holocaust took place; if powerful states all around the world today can
systematically deny the systematic violations of human rights they are carrying out -
then we know that we're in bad shape. But we're in even worse shape when the
intellectual avant garde invent a form of denial so profound, that serious people -
including progressives - will have to debate whether the Gulf War actually took
place or not.
(2) Acknowledgement
I promised a more optimistic second footnote. This is not to cheer you up, but just to
be honest. Denial has it opposites. What has to be understood are the conditions
under which denial does not occur, in which the truth (even if this concept is
disappearing down the post modern black hole) is acknowledged, not just its
existence but its moral implications.
After all, in the Milgram experiment, somewhere around 30% of the subjects
(depending on the conditions) did not push the button. In Kelman and Hamilton's
public opinion surveys, again another 30% would not obey orders to shoot innocent
women and children. In the middle of even the most grotesque of state crimes, such
as genocide, there are extraordinary tales of courage, rescuing and resistance. Acts
of altruism, compassion and pro-social behaviour are woven into the social fabric.
Above all, there is the whole human rights movement itself, which over the last three
decades has mobilised an extraordinary number of people into wholly selfless
behaviour to alleviate the suffering of others - whether by giving money, writing to
a prisoner of conscience or joining a campaign.
In my initial interviews with human rights organisations, I was surprised to hear a
sense of optimism. Yes, there are some people (referred to in the trade as the
"ostriches") who do not want to know. But most organisations were certain that their
potential pool has not been reached. I mentioned to one of my interviewees the
cynical notion of "compassion fatigue" - that people are just too tired to respond,
they can't bear seeing any more pictures of the homeless in the streets, victims of
AIDS, children starving in Somalia, refugees in Bosnia. Her response was that the
concept was a journalistic invention; what there is, is media fatigue.
This is where we return to the state of hyper-reality which post modernist theories
have so well exposed. The question is right open: Will the type of manipulation and
114 STANLEY COHEN (1993) 26 ANZJ Crim
simulation seen in the Gulf War dominate, creating indeed a culture of denial? Or
can we conceive of a flow of information which will allow people to acknowledge
reality and act accordingly?
This might seem a pretentious question for us humble criminologists to consider,
but I hope that you will allow me to get away with it.
NOTES
1 I have examined elsewhere the move in alternative criminology from "idealism" to
"realism", see Cohen (1988; 1990).
2 On the issues in bringing torturers to justice after the regime changes in Brazil and
Uruguay, see Weschler (1990).
3 On rape and sexual abuse in custody, see Amnesty International reports in 1992, especially
on India, Turkey, Philippines, Guatamala and Uganda.
4 For a nuanced historical reconstruction of the perceptions of villagers living next to the
Mauthausen concentration camp complex, see Horwitz, 1992.
5 My minor personal involvement in this debate - as the object of a radical post-modern
critique for foolishly using objective standards of knowledge (in a report on torture in
Israel) - is recorded in Cohen (1991).
REFERENCES
Barak, Gregg, (ed) (1991) Crimes By the Capitalist State: An Introduction to State Criminality,
State University of New York Press, Albany.
Baudrillard, Jean (1991, a) "The Reality Gulf' The Guardian, 11 January.
- (1991,b) "La guerre du Golfe n'a pas eu lieu" Liberation, 29 March.
Braithwaite, John and Fisse, Brent (1990) "On the Plausibility of Corporate Crime Theory",
in W. Laufer and F. Adler (eds) Advances in Criminological Theory, Vol II, Transaction,
New Brunswick. .
Cohen, Stanley (1988) Against Criminology, Transaction, New Brunswick.
- (1990) "Intellectual Scepticism and Political Commitment: The Case of Radical
Criminology", Bonger Memorial Lecture, University of Amsterdam.
- (1991) "Talking About Torture in Israel" Tikkun, Vol 6, No 6 pp 23-30, 89-90.
Edelstein, E L et al (eds) (1989) Denial: A Clarification of Concepts and Research, Plenum
Press, New York.
Goleman, Daniel (1985) Vital Lies, Simple Truths: On the Psychology of Self Deception, Simon
and Schuster, New York.
Horwitz, Gordon (1992) In the Shadow ofDeath: Living Outside the Gates ofMauthausen, Free
Press, New York.
Hovanissian, Richard G (ed) (1986) The Armenian Genocide in Perspective, Transaction, New
Brunswick.
Journal of Social Issues (1990) Special Issue on "Moral Exclusion", Vol 46.
Karmen, A (1990) Crime Victims:An Introduction to Victimology, Brooks Cole, California.
Kelman, Herbert C and Hamilton, V Lee (1989) Crimes of Obedience, Yale University Press,
New Haven.
Kuper, Leo (1981) Genocide, Penguin Books, London,
Maran, Rita (1989) Torture: The Role of Ideology in the French-Algerian War, Praeger, New
York.
Muller, Ingo (1991) Hitler's Justice: The Courts of the Third Reich, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge.
Norris, Christopher (1992) Uncritical Theory: Postmodernism, Intellectuals and the Gulf War,
Lawrence and Wishart, London.
Oliner, Samuel and Oliner, Pearl (1988) The Altruistic Personality: Rescuers of Jews in Nazi
Europe, Free Press, New York.
HUMAN RIGHTS AND CRIMES OF THE STATE: THE CULTURE OF DENIAL 115