Individual and Corporate Social Responsibility: Byr B Wandj T Z
Individual and Corporate Social Responsibility: Byr B Wandj T Z
Individual and Corporate Social Responsibility: Byr B Wandj T Z
doi:10.1111/j.1468-0335.2009.00843.x
Society’s demands for individual and corporate social responsibility as alternative responses to market and
distributive failures are becoming increasingly prominent. We draw on recent developments in the
psychology and economics of prosocial behaviour to shed light on this trend and the underlying mix of
motivations. We then link individual concerns to corporate social responsibility, contrasting three possible
understandings of the term: firms’ adoption of a more long-term perspective, the delegated exercise of
prosocial behaviour on behalf of stakeholders, and insider-initiated corporate philanthropy. We discuss
the benefits, costs and limits of socially responsible behaviour as a means to further societal goals.
INTRODUCTION
Economists’ view of how society should be organized has traditionally rested on two
pillars. The invisible hand of the market, described in Adam Smith, harnesses consumers’
and corporations’ pursuit of self-interest to the pursuit of efficiency. The state corrects
market failures whenever externalities stand in the way of efficiency, and redistributes
income and wealth, as the income and wealth distribution generated by markets has no
reason to fit society’s moral standards. In industrialized democracies, much of the
political spectrum has converged on this division of labour, albeit with some sharp
divergences of opinion as to the relative roles of the market and the state.1
Textbook economics has thus long embraced the shareholder-value approach, which
posits that firms should be controlled by profit-maximizing shareholders while other
stakeholders are protected by contracts and regulation. Stakeholders’ insulation from
managerial decisions operates through fixed nominal claims (wages and severance pay,
fixed debt repayment combined with priority and collateral, etc.) and exit options
associated with general training, flexible labour markets and short-term debt maturities.
The state is supposed to step in only when satisfactory contracting solutions would
involve high transaction costs or require more symmetry in the information held by the
parties; cases in point include environmental taxation, anti-trust, prudential regulation,
and the regulation of network industries. The state also controls redistributive taxation.
In a nutshell, following Pigou (1920), the state, and not citizens or firms, is in charge of
correcting market failures and income or wealth inequality.
Yet society’s and law-makers’ demands for individual and corporate social
responsibility as an alternative response to market and redistributive failures have
recently become more prominent.2 Certainly, calls for people to contribute time and
money to good causes have existed throughout history and in all societies, from
Antiquity3 to, say, eighteenth century Quakers’ and Mennonites’ refusal to invest in
weapons and slavery. But the movement is gaining momentum, especially with the
empowerment of civil society (non-governmental organizations or NGOs) and the
equitable-trade/responsible-investment movement. A variety of factors probably
combine to account for this trend: (i) social responsibility is likely to be a normal good;
(ii) information about companies’ practices throughout the world has become much more
accessible and quick to travel; (iii) the scope of environmental and social externalities
exerted by multinationals in less developed, more laxly regulated countries is likely to
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
2 ECONOMICA [JANUARY
have expanded in pace with globalization; (iv) the long-run cost of atmospheric pollution
(e.g. global warming), or at least the public’s awareness of it, has risen significantly.
Responding to such demands, business leaders, governments and academics are now
also emphasizing the notion of corporate social responsibility (CSR). A standard definition
of CSR is that it is about sacrificing profits in the social interest. For there to be a sacrifice,
the firm must go beyond its legal and contractual obligations, on a voluntary basis. CSR
thereby embraces a wide range of behaviours, such as being employee-friendly, environment-
friendly, mindful of ethics, respectful of communities where the firm’s plants are located, and
even investor-friendly. Sometimes, the call for duty extends beyond the corporation’s
immediate realm and includes supporting the arts, universities and other good causes.
Why do citizens and corporations empower themselves and substitute for elected
government? A first and clearly relevant motivation is that government may itself fail.
Government failures have multiple origins:
Capture by lobbies and other interest groups. Governments under influence may fail to
correct externalities as Pigovian principles would recommend, or bend to wealthy
constituents’ opposition to redistributive policies.
Territoriality of jurisdiction. For instance, one cannot rule against child labour in a
distant, sovereign country, and an outright import ban may be infeasible due to
international trade agreements or other policy constraints. Consumer boycotts and
investor activism then become the outlet through which citizens can express their
opposition to these practices.
A combination of inefficiency, high transaction costs, poor information and high
delivery costs. The state thus has a comparative disadvantage in policing minor
nuisances such as a lack of respect for employees or conspicuous consumption by
executives, or in directing resources to very local needs. ‘Appropriate’ behaviours in
such contexts are instead enforced through the pressure of social norms and popular
demands that firms be socially responsible.4
A second important motivation is that economic agents may want to promote values
that are not shared by law-makers. Because preferences are heterogeneous, it is inevitable
that some consumers’, investors’ or workers’ values will not be fully reflected in policy.
They, or organized groups acting on their behalf, will then become activists.5
Despite its growing importance, little is known about the economics of individual and
corporate social responsibility. This paper draws on recent developments in psychology
and behavioural economics to shed some light on the new trend, its future and its limits.
It considers the benefits and costs of socially responsible behaviour (SRB), and asks
whether it is a viable model for the achievements of social goals. This work is still at an
early stage and the paper can thus primarily help us to organize our thinking on these
issues. Subject to this caveat, the take-home message is that SRB holds real promise,
provided that we understand its motivations and limitations.
The paper is organized as follows. Section I discusses individual social responsibility,
and Section II discusses corporate social responsibility. Section III concludes with a
summary and some open questions.
In the standard dictator game experiment, for instance, many subjects are willing to
make at least a small sacrifice in their own payoff to benefit others. This is prima facie
evidence of the existence of altruistic, other-regarding preferences. The real picture is
more complex, however, as a clever experiment by Dana et al. (2007) demonstrates. As
these authors show, when given the opportunity not to know whether their actions
actually hurt others, many people take advantage of this ‘moral wriggle room’ to make
selfish choices. Their main experiment contrasts two variants of a dictator-like game, with
anonymous players. In a first, ‘known’ condition, subjects choose between a selfish option
A that delivers 6 to them and 1 to someone else, and a fair option B delivering 5 to each.
In conformity with many previous such experiments, about three-quarters of subjects
choose B. In a second, ‘uncertain’ condition, subjects can again choose either 6 (option A)
or 5 (option B) for themselves, but they do not know what the other player will receive in
each case. They are told only that there are two versions of the game, drawn at random
with equal probabilities, that they could be playing. In version 1, the payoffs to A and B
are as above, namely (6, 1) and (5, 5), creating the same trade-off between material gain
and generosity. In version 2, there is no trade-off: A leads to (6, 5) and B to only (5, 1).
Subjects are also given the opportunity to find out, immediately and at no cost, which of
the two versions of the game they have randomly drawn and will be playing. According to
standard decision theory, truly generous individuals should strictly prefer to learn the
state of nature, as this would allow them to choose B in state 1 and A in state 2. Yet half
of the subjects choose not to know and proceed to select option A, presumably seizing the
(false) excuse that they may not be hurting the other. This behaviour, akin to crossing the
street to avoid passing near a beggar, shows how subtle we are when we play games with
ourselves. We understand (probably not even consciously) that our memory is imperfect
and that creating a ‘cloud of smoke’ around whether we are actually selfish can thus
provide a self-excuse for pursuing our own interests.
Other experiments, sometimes involving even more transparent self-deception, lead
to similar results and conclusions. Dana et al. (2006) thus show that many people who
would voluntarily share $10 with an anonymous other in a dictator game prefer to just
take $9 for themselves and not face that choice. In a related vein, Hamman et al. (2009)
show that many subjects who would otherwise behave generously in a dictator game will,
given the opportunity, delegate the sharing decision to a third party who has acquired a
reputation for being biased in favour of delegating principals. Put differently, economic
agents are eager to delegate the ‘dirty work’ that they would not want to do themselves;
somehow, not directly choosing the selfish action seems to exonerate them from what
would be the logical damage to self-esteem.
All these experiments point to the idea that self-signals play an important role.
Accordingly, one would expect the cost to self-esteem incurred from selfish actions to be
magnified when these become more salient or memorable. Indeed, Mazar et al. (2008) find
that subjects who can cheat (for money) on a task without any risk of detection, cheat less
when they are first made to read the Ten Commandments or their university’s honour
code. Such reminders of moral precepts should, according to the standard economic
model, be irrelevant. In fact, by making transgression of these precepts more salient, they
reduce the ambiguity on which self-deception relies, inducing more honest behaviour.
(a) The efficacy of publicizing people’s good and bad deeds is, in a sense, self-limiting. As
publicity is scaled up, people discount the meaning of prosocial acts, attributing their
motivation more to image-seeking and less to altruism. This form of ‘over-justification
effect’ implies a partial crowding out of the incentive provided by publicity (see Bénabou
and Tirole 2006a for a formal analysis). The implication is that the more ‘advertised’
socially responsible investments (SRIs) are, the more they will be discounted.
(b) Another cost relates to individuals’ choice of signals. Giving is heavily distorted
toward the more visible or memorable targets: Americans, for instance, donate
substantial amounts to Harvard, Yale, Princeton and other well-known alma maters,
but far less to primary and secondary schools. Similarly, giving to concert halls and
museums has much greater ‘glamour’ and networking value than giving to the poor.9
A similar point applies to green investment by households: as Ariely et al. (2009)
note, buying a hybrid car or installing solar panels buys more social prestige than
insulating one’s house or buying an energy-efficient furnace. While the latter
investments are in fact more ecologically virtuous, they are also invisible to others,
and after a while even to oneself.
(c) The quest for social prestige or the enhancement of self-image is, in itself, a zero-sum
gameFin the parlance of sociologists, a positional good. The buyer of a hybrid car
feels and looks better, but makes his neighbours (both buyers and non-buyers of
hybrid cars) feel and look worseFa ‘reputation stealing’ externality. In the limit,
when everyone behaves in a socially responsible way, no one gets credit for it.
Figure 2 depicts what happens when participation in a prosocial activity increases.
Individuals with intrinsic motivation (altruism) above some threshold receive the
honour attached to participation, while those below it abstain and suffer stigma.
When participation increases, the honour involved decreases (prosocial behaviour
becomes more common) and the stigma for not participating increases (only the ‘very
bad apples’ do not participate).
Evidence that the quest for social prestige is a zero-sum game (or at least is
perceived to be) is provided by Monin (2007) and Monin et al. (2008). In a series of
experiments, these authors document a frequent backlash against ‘moral rebels’ such
as vegetarians or subjects who refuse to play along in an ethically questionable
scenarioFpeople who in principle should restore our faith in human nature, but in
practice make us feel morally inadequate. Outside the laboratory, moreover, such
adverse reactions to ‘do-gooders’ are socially costly: they will be ostracized,
threatened or harmed, creating a welfare loss.
(d) Our moral standards are challenged along multiple dimensions and in repeated
instances. Good behaviour in one context may ‘justify’ more mediocre behaviour in
another, and people who have recently ‘done good’ in one dimension may feel
immunized against negative (social or self) inferences, and thus later on act less
morally constrained. Monin and Miller (2001) document this ‘moral credentializing’
in experiments on gender or ethnic stereotyping: subjects who were previously given
Abstain Participate
v:altruism
Stigma cut -off v* Honour
FIGURE 2. Honour and stigma. (Source: Bénabou and Tirole 2006a.)
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
2010] INDIVIDUAL AND CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY 7
Amending Pigou This simple policy prescription raises several issues. First, image values
may not always be easy to measure, although there are implicit markets for items such as
a named building, a plaque or a university chair. Second, and relatedly, one would want
to know when the correction can be significant and when it is likely to be negligible. In
this respect, we have already seen that image concerns are influenced by visibility:
efficient furnaces may need to be subsidized more than hybrid cars.
Perhaps more subtly, image concerns depend endogenously on the prevalence of the
behaviour in question. Provided that the distribution of altruism in the population is
unimodal (as in Figure 2), one can show (see Bénabou and Tirole 2010) that for a given
social cost of the externality, the optimal subsidy varies non-monotonically with the
proportion of people choosing the socially responsible option: see Figure 3, which depicts
this correction to Pigovian taxation. Intuitively, ‘admirable’ actsFthose that very few
individuals in society perform (or would perform without considerable incentiviza-
tion)Fcarry substantial social prestige, and should therefore command only modest
material incentives. At the other extreme, ‘respectable’ actsFthose that ‘any decent
person’ would engage in (absent exceptional constraints or inducements)Fare such that
failing to perform them entails enormous stigma; so here again, material incentives
should be low. ‘Modal acts’, which are neither admirable nor merely respectable, are
those for which Pigovian precepts apply best and extrinsic incentives should be strongest.
Crowding out and the over-justification effect The observation that the image value of
different behaviours is endogenous (determined together with the equilibrium behaviour
of the whole population) has another important implication: the level of material
incentives will affect this attribution problem, and therefore the (self-) reputational return
to prosocial acts. This is illustrated in Figure 4, drawn from Bénabou and Tirole (2006a).
This figure depicts a population’s average contribution a to a public good (say,
donating blood) or conformity to some socially desirable behaviour, as the material
reward y for doing so (or, conversely, the penalty for failing to) increases.10 In the
absence of image concerns, aggregate behaviour confirms the representation of Homo
Economicus in Econ 101: a higher reward elicits increased supply. As image become more
important, an unusual phenomenon occurs: over some interval, the supply response to
incentives flattens out, and eventually becomes downward-sloping. This violation of
basic price theory results from what psychologists call the over-justification effect, and
economists call a signal-extraction problem. When there is no or little reward, a prosocial
act is interpreted as genuine altruism. As material incentives become more substantial,
the ‘meaning’ of the act changes: it becomes more difficult to know to what extent it is
motivated by altruism or by greed (since people also differ along both dimensions). The
signalling value of prosocial behaviour thus weakens, offsetting or even reversing the
direct effect of higher incentive. Of course, when rewards become sufficiently large,
supply eventually recovers its standard upward-sloping nature, but such levels of
payments could be very costly.
Figure 4 and the more general analysis underlying it have other testable implications
besides the possibility of crowding out. First, prosocial contributions increase when their
visibility, and therefore their impact, on social esteem, increases. Second, the power of
incentives is weaker (or even negative) when image concerns are large. Ariely et al. (2009)
provide empirical validations of these predictions. In their experiments, subjects
performed tasks to earn money for charitable causes under two conditions. In a ‘private’
condition, only the individual observes his effort and amount earned (only his self-image
can be at stake). In the ‘public’ condition, all subjects, and possibly some other peers,
aggregate supply
37.5
incentive: y
–2.5 0 2.5 5 7.5 10 12.5 15
FIGURE 4. The overjustification effect. (Source: Bénabou and Tirole 2006a.)
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
2010] INDIVIDUAL AND CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY 9
observe each person’s choices (so both self- and social-image are involved). The first
observation, which corroborates many earlier findings (e.g. Freeman 1997), is that
contributions are larger when they are public. The second observation is more striking: in
conformity with the theoretical prediction, the impact of material incentives weakens
considerably (or even reverses) when they are public. Moreover, this change in slope
occurs only when the task is performed for a good cause: it is absent when it is known
that subjects are simply earning money for themselves, or for an organization that most
observers disapprove of. These results are consistent with the idea that subjects in the
public condition seem worried that the presence of rewards may cause their prosocial
behaviour to be attributed to greed more than to altruism. Moving beyond the
laboratory, such findings provide a further rationale for subsidizing efficient furnaces
more than hybrid cars.
As we noted earlier, a second form of the over-justification effect arises from the fact
that people also differ in the intensity of their image concerns. Some are literally obsessed
with social esteem, while others care about it much less. When good deeds are very visible
(by their nature or by policy design), they will then be ‘discounted’ as being likely to
reflect a strong desire to ‘buy’ admiration. This discount, in turn, will dampen the
signalling incentive to act prosocially, and this even when image seeking is not frowned
on per seFit just reduces the attribution of good behaviour to genuine altruism. This
effect never fully crowds out the impact of an increase in the publicity of actions (medals,
citations, wall of shame, etc.), but can substantially dampen it.11
Such ‘concerns about not looking image-concerned’ resonate, as they are present in
our everyday lives. Most people hesitate to boast about their good actions and would
much rather have third parties advertise these acts for them. This follows naturally from
the logic of inference: someone who brags about his good deeds signals that he is image-
concerned and creates a suspicion about the extent of his true altruism.
can also result from well-designed schemes. First, monetary incentives often put more
weight on short-term than on long-term performance. Although the recent crisis has
brought more widespread recognition of the hazards that short-term-oriented
compensation schemes create for corporations and society, some dependence on current
or recent firm performance is inevitable. Second, decisions by boards and shareholders
about whether to keep current management, change it or alter the scope of its activities
are also necessarily based in part on recent observation (even if some of the long-term
impact of managers’ actions may filter through long-term indicators such as the stock
price12). Thus career concerns also generate some short-term biases.
In practice, short-termism often implies both an intertemporal loss of profit and an
externality on stakeholders. That is, managers take decisions that increase short-term
profit, but reduce shareholder value and hurt workers or other constituencies. For
example, a firm may renege on an implicit contract with its labour or suppliers so as to
reduce costs, thereby damaging goodwillFmaking it more difficult to attract motivated
workers in the future, or to induce suppliers to make relationship-specific investments
(e.g. Krueger and Mas 2004). Alternatively, a firm could economize on safety or
pollution control; this also increases short-run profits, but creates contingent liabilities
down the roadFrisk of future lawsuits, consumer boycotts and environmental clean-up
costs. In such cases, the ‘win–win’ argument makes clear sense.
The upshot is that in this first vision, CSR is about taking a long-term perspective to
maximizing (intertemporal) profits. This suggests that socially responsible investors
should position themselves as long-term investors who monitor management and exert
voice to correct short-termism.
In the same vein, but with much more ambiguous welfare consequences, ‘strategic
CSR’ (to use a term coined by Baron 2001) consists in taking a socially responsible
stance in order to strengthen one’s market position and thereby increase long-term
profits. For instance, CSR could be a means of placating regulators and public opinion
to avoid strict supervision in the future, or to attempt to raise rivals’ costs by
encouraging environmental, labour or safety regulations that will particularly handicap
competitors.
Vision 2: Delegated philanthropy (the firm as a channel for the expression of citizen
values) For the reasons discussed in Section I, some stakeholders (investors, customers,
employees) are often willing to sacrifice money (yield, purchasing power and wage,
respectively) so as to further social goals. Put differently, stakeholders have some
demand for corporations to engage in philanthropy on their behalf. The corresponding
CSR profit sacrifice is then passed through to stakeholders at their demand.
Note that one needs to explain why people would want corporations to do good on
their behalf, rather than doing it on their own or through charitable organizations,
churches, etc. Information and transaction costs are clearly important here. In theory,
consumers could send money to directly supplement the income of workers in the coffee
plantations supplying Starbucks. But they would have to be informed about the
occurrence of individual trades and contracts, and their financial transfers would involve
enormous transaction costs. Somehow, philanthropy must thus be delegated. It could
perhaps be entrusted to some charitable organization, but transaction costs are still likely
to be much lower if delegation goes through the corporation, which already is involved in
a financial relationship with the workers.
Another argument for asking corporations to behave prosocially is that the desired
actions are often not about transferring income to less-favoured populations, but about
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
2010] INDIVIDUAL AND CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY 11
refraining from specific behaviours, such as polluting the environment; here there is no
substitute for asking the firm to behave well when the state does not impose constraining
regulations. A related case is when a firm draws on its technical expertise or exploits
complementarities to deliver goods and services to those in need more efficiently than
governments or other philanthropic ‘intermediaries’ could. Examples include a giant
supermarket chain organizing relief convoys to a zone hit by a hurricane, or a large
water-treatment utility setting up a programme of digging water wells for poor, remote
villages in a developing country.
Many examples come to mind: Starbucks increases its demand by buying fair-trade
coffee and tea. Other firms advertise heavily that their clothing is made from organic
cotton, or is the product of fair trade. Some corporations provide incentives for employee
engagement in community service, thereby boosting public relations with the local
communities and attracting motivated employees (Besley and Ghatak 2005; Brekke and
Nyborg 2008). The view that corporations engage in socially responsible behaviour
(SRB) on behalf of stakeholders is also supported by the observation that ‘sin stocks’
(tobacco, alcohol, casinos) exhibit higher returns (Hong and Kacperczyk 2009).13 On the
other hand, and as we will later discuss, other empirical research fails to demonstrate a
link between CSR behaviour and a lack of profitability.
The idea that firms exercising CSR are responding to consumer and investor demand,
that they ‘do good’ on their behalf, is consistent with the greater prevalence of such
practices among firms that are large, are profitable, produce final goods and are
scrutinized by NGOs. Visibility with respect to stakeholders demanding SRB thus
incentivizes firms to engage in such behaviour.14
As with individuals, the image concerns of corporations also have their darker side,
taking here the form of ‘greenwash’: disseminating a misleading picture of environmental
friendliness or other SRB, or one that is accurate in some dimensions but serves to
obscure less savoury ones. Thus Enron was a huge corporate giver, particularly to the
Houston area, and one of the most impressive ‘glossy brochures’ documenting the
multiple facets of a firm’s CSR benevolence is the one issued in 2007 by the American
International Group.15
Vision 2 of CSR does not raise any specific corporate governance issue: management
caters to demand and maximizes profit. As with the long-term perspective, profit
maximization and CRS are consistent.
institutions are eligible for tax-deductible contributions. So, while it has very imperfect
control over the allocation, it at least keeps control over the identity of recipients.
Unlike the citizen-delegation view, the view of corporate philanthropy as manage-
ment-initiated raises substantial corporate governance issues. Indeed, if investors simply
demand the highest possible return (implying no tolerance for SRB if they do not benefit
from it), managers and the board must be somewhat entrenched in order to be able to
practise corporate philanthropy on a large scale (Cespa and Cestone 2007). The notion of
the mission of management being broader than just maximizing shareholder value
necessarily involves some cost to corporations, making it more difficult for them to raise
funds from investors.17 It may also weaken managerial accountability by creating
multiple objectives and performance criteria; at the extreme, too many missions amount
to no mission at all (Dewatripont et al. 1999).
In practice, the dividing line between the different notions of CSRFlong-term
perspective (vision 1), delegated philanthropy (vision 2) and insider-initiated corporate
philanthropy (vision 3)Fmay be elusive. Consider, for instance, the increasingly popular
practices of nominating someone with a good external reputation as a Corporate
Sustainability Officer, or of turning to reputable NGOs for advice and help. Do firms hire
a Corporate Sustainability Officer to serve as an advocate against short-termismFa kind
of environmental risk manager, in effectFwithin the firm? Or is this executive meant to be
a voice for costly prosocial behaviour demanded by stakeholders? Similarly, consider the
introduction of monetary incentives based on environmental performance. Are they meant,
say, to encourage divisional managers to install carbon-free equipment that is currently
unprofitable due to the world’s lax attitude toward climate change, but will reduce future
costs when carbon dioxide is taxed at a more reasonable level? Or is a genuine desire to do
good a better interpretation of green incentives than the long-term perspective view? In the
latter case, are these ‘green incentives’ the object of intense communication to shareholders
(suggesting vision 2) or a confidential policy (suggesting vision 3)?
In sum, we see that, as with individual consumers and investors, corporate ‘socially
responsible behaviours’ often carry much ambiguity as to their exact motivation.
Do the data help us to tell these theories apart? Empirical studies often relate corporate
profitability with socially responsible behaviour.18 There seems to be, overall, no or a
slightly positive correlation between socially responsible behaviour and corporate
returns; see Orlitzky et al. (2003), Margolis and Elfenbein (2007) and Margolis et al.
(2007) for meta-analyses, Heal (2005) and Reinhardt et al. (2008) for further discussions.
The interpretation of empirical analyses is, however, subject to three difficulties.
The first difficulty concerns which CSR theory is being tested. We observed that
visions 1 and 2 both predict a positive correlation between CSR and profits,19 while
vision 3 predicts the reverse. In practice, CSR is likely to involve a mix of all three across
the corporate sample, so it is unclear what specific channel is being tested.
The second difficulty pertains to the empirical strategy. On the causal-inference front,
SRB and profitability are clearly both endogenous variables, raising the usual issue of
what are the exogenous drivers (equivalently, what would be appropriate instruments)
underlying the observed correlation patterns. If managers differ exogenously in their
individual time horizons, for instance, then a positive correlation is to be expected (from
vision 1). If they differ in the private value that they derive from being associated with a
firm known to act well toward its employees, consumers or the environment, then (from
vision 3) one might expect a negative relationship. There could also be reverse causation,
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
2010] INDIVIDUAL AND CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY 13
for instance if the most profitable firms are the best able to afford the cost of CSR or, as
suggested by Margolis and Elfenbein (2007) and Margolis et al. (2007), have the most
incentive to engage in it.20
An empirical strategy must also choose between operating performance and stock
market returns to measure ‘corporate returns’. Both involve different problems. For
operating performance (e.g. return on assets), the empirical challenge is the following: if
one believes that CSR increases the mean profit by limiting rare disasters (vision 1), then
one needs very large samples to see that significantly in the data. Most studies look
instead at stock returns. This raises the issue of whether CSR companies have different
systematic risk exposures (either due to their resilience in periods of crisis or because they
face a specific CSR risk factor), in which case they command different risk premia, and
therefore have different expected returns. As Andries (2008) notes: ‘New laws and
regulations are typically introduced when things go wrong . . . Socially responsible
investors would simply be the ones with higher risk aversion to a deterioration of the
‘‘state of the world’’.’
Another issue is whether financial markets are still learning about CSR. Some people
have in mind (implicitly or explicitly) that the stock market has been undervaluing the
‘true importance’ of CSR, so that virtuous companies have positive abnormal returns
(they keep surprising the market positively, in contradiction to market efficiency). An
intermediate story is a ‘slow repricing’, whereby environmental and social factors are
gradually becoming recognized as relevant price factors for valuing a company; virtuous
firms experience high returns during this recognition period, but should experience lower
ones once the repricing is completed.
The third unknown involves extrapolation. Socially responsible investment has, so
far, mostly been a marginal phenomenon, and there is no reason why profitability should
remain the same as its prevalence increases. A key issue here is which types of socially
responsible activities involve decreasing or, conversely, increasing returns. For instance, a
small number of environmentally concerned investors can always invest in the existing
clean companies; it is therefore likely that CSR has had little impact on stock prices in the
past. As SRI popularity increases, other firms may have to start incurring higher
abatement costs in order to attract funding, depressing yields.21 Consistent with this idea
of an increasing CSR discount, Andries (2008) finds, in the cross-section of S&P 500
firms and after controlling for industry and firm characteristics: (i) no significant
relationship between asset returns and CSR over the 1991–2006 period; (ii) an emerging
negative relationship for some criteria related to negative screening (tobacco, alcohol,
gambling, nuclear power) over the more recent 2000–06 period.
Free riding Socially responsible investment, the fair-trade movement, and the desire to be
employed by a socially responsible institution all involve a private provision of a public
good. The temptation to free ride is substantial. We may be willing to pay 5% more for
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
14 ECONOMICA [JANUARY
Information In order to choose a company to invest in, buy from or work for, investors,
consumers and workers need information as to whether it really behaves prosocially.
This raises three challenges:
Data collection is itself a public good. It is therefore important that specialized rating
agencies supply the required information to the public. Of course, these agencies may
face inadequate incentives, as was demonstrated in the recent financial crisis, and there
are grounds to be vigilant. But the problem of reporting is not specific to this context,
and we have to meet the need for delegation.
Different dimensions of good corporate citizenship need to be aggregated. Firms do
well in some dimensions and poorly on others, so one of the challenges facing rating
agencies is to find a methodology for adding them up into a synthetic index (or a small
number thereof). How does one assess the closure of a plant that emits a lot of CO2 but
provides jobs to a local community? Does one view nuclear power in terms of its
definitely favourable impact against global warming, or of its long-lasting hazardous
waste? Can a multinational offset some local environmental damage by financing a
school, clinic or waste-treatment facility in the community?
Should corporate social performance be assessed in absolute or relative terms? For
example, an oil company may pollute a lot, but make substantial efforts to reduce its
pollution and be ‘best in class’. Relatedly, Landier and Nair (2008) have suggested
including relative performance within the industry as a criterion for delineating socially
responsible portfolios.
Defining what is socially responsible CSR inherits the strengths and weaknesses of the
democratic process. As is well-known, politicians often tend to follow public opinion in
order to pander to the electorate.22 Good public policy is therefore often conditioned by
a proper understanding, or at least a lack of prejudice by voters in the relevant matter. A
case in point is environmental policy. European politicians may impose a cost of over
1000 euros to economize one ton of carbon by subsidizing solar panels (most cost
estimates range from 600 to 1400 euros), when they could have economized over 50 tons
with the same money by buying out the carbon rights. (At the time of writing, the price of
a ton in the EU’s Emissions Trading System is 15 euros.) But due to poor information or
an imperfect understanding of the economics of the matter, or again the bias toward
more visible, ‘symbolic’ interventions introduced by voters’ identity concerns, there is no
electoral sanction, but actually an increase in popularity, attached to such moves.
Similarly, the challenge for a proper assessment of which firms are socially
responsible is to disincentivize rating agencies and CEOs from pandering to the biases
of their constituencies (investors, consumers and workers). The same problem arises in
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
2010] INDIVIDUAL AND CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY 15
many contexts. NGOs reselling confiscated ivory will be frowned on by the public for
behaving ‘immorally’, even when this move lowers the price of ivory and thereby
discourages poachers. A polluter may still be frowned on after a tax on the pollutant is
imposed at its Pigovian level (the polluter is then subject to ‘double taxation’). Regardless
of their own attitudes toward genetically modified organisms, most experts would admit
that popular attitudes on the subject are often driven by rather unscientific arguments
and based on little information. Finally, framing is bound to distort assessments: the
choice of presenting a firm’s rationale for locating a plant in a low-labour-cost country as
‘helping a poor country to develop’ or ‘minimizing labour cost’ is obviously not neutral.
What kind of activism? A much debated question for green or ethical funds is the nature
of their action. Should they intervene in governance or more passively vote with their
feet? In the latter case, should the fund engage in a dialogue with the firm before
excluding it from its portfolio?
Typically, green or ethical funds are informed (by lobbies, some multilateral
organizations, etc.) of an ‘incident’, i.e. a firm’s potential misbehaviour. The fund then
‘monitors’ and enters a ‘dialogue’ or ‘engagement’ with the firm to persuade it to alter its
behaviour, threatening a boycott if it does not comply. Some funds and NGOs prefer a
‘clean hands’ approach that does not involve any such dialogue, for fear of being seen as
soft on the infringer or of being led to a compromise that does not satisfy the socially
responsible investors.
Another debate relates to the choice between positive and negative screening.
Negative screening refers to the exclusion of unrepentant firms; positive screening
consists in investing only in ‘best-in-class’ corporations.
A third debate concerns whether the names of companies facing engagement, and not
only those that end up excluded, should be published. There may be a good argument for
not disclosing the names of firms involved in negotiations, so as to give them more of an
incentive to alter their behaviour. On the other hand, this may increase the risk of
collusion or capture of the NGO or fund involved.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
This paper formed the basis for the Coase lecture, delivered by Jean Tirole at the London School of
Economics on 19 February 2009. We are grateful to Francesco Caselli and Augustin Landier for
valuable comments. Bénabou gratefully acknowledges support from the Canadian Institute for
Advanced research. Jean Tirole gratefully acknowledges the funding of the chair ‘Sustainable
Finance and Responsible Investment’ by the Association Francaise de Gestion (AFG) at IDEI.
NOTES
1. On this last point, see Bénabou and Tirole (2006b) and Bénabou (2008a).
2. For instance, according to data from the Social Investment Forum Report (2007), cited in Andries
(2008), the value of assets under management in the USA that fall into the SRI category grew at annual
rates of about 12% over 1995–2005 and 18% over 2005–07; by the end of 2007, these SRI assets
accounted for 11% of total assets under professional management. Other signs of the same trend
include the proliferation of fair-trade products, carbon offsets and newly created positions such as
Corporate Sustainability Officer in many large companies.
3. See, for example, Avlonas (2009) on ancient Greece.
4. See Shavell (2002) and Besley and Ghatak (2007). For example, the latter authors emphasize that for
CSR to be socially beneficial, corporations must be more efficient than the government at producing
public goods.
5. In his review of what economics has to contribute to our understanding of CSR, Kitzmueller (2008)
notes that if ethical consumers are a minority (majority), the government may under (over) regulate.
6. See Bénabou and Tirole (2007).
7. Of course there are also downsides to such shaming punishments. We leave these for future research.
8. Those reminders operate not only at the individual’s level, but also at group level. Within firms or their
boards, in particular, socially responsible investment advocates can thus act as safeguards against over-
optimistic ‘groupthink’, systematically asking management to present worst-case or disaster scenarios,
appointing devil’s advocates, protecting whistleblowers, and so on. For more on groupthink and its
prevention, see Bénabou (2008b).
r The London School of Economics and Political Science 2009
2010] INDIVIDUAL AND CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY 17
9. This applies at least domestically; giving to poor countries is somewhat different, in part because of
different attributions made for the causes of their poverty (see Bénabou and Tirole 2006b), and in part
because such giving has much greater visibility, as it takes place on a ‘global’ stage.
10. The specification of preferences underlying Figure 4 is U ¼ (va þ vyy)a þ maE[va|a,y] – C(a), where va
and vy parametrize an individual’s degree of altruism and marginal utility of income, a is his level of
contribution, C(a) is the associated cost, and y is the per-unit incentive rate. E[va|a,y] is the best estimate
of va conditional on the chosen action and its reward, and ma is the intensity of the image concern,
common to all agents for simplicity. The joint distribution of va and vy is taken to be Gaussian, and C(a)
is quadratic. The curves shown in Figure 4 correspond to different values of ma.
11. See Bénabou and Tirole (2006a).
12. On this point see, for example, Holmström and Tirole (1993).
13. A similar conclusion is reached by Geczy et al. (2005).
14. Of course, NGO scrutiny is itself endogenous.
15. See American International Group, Inc. (2007, pp. 4–5).
16. Among other instances, Jennings (2006) relates that: ‘from 1992 to 2002, while Dennis Koslowski served
as CEO, Tyco gave 35 million to charities designated by Mr. Koslowski . . . Mr. Koslowski served on
the board of the Whitney Museum of American Art, and, as a result Tyco donated 4.5 million to the
travelling museum shows that Whitney sponsored.’
17. It is interesting to note that this notion is more popular in civil-law countries, which put more emphasis
on stakeholder participation in governance and a broader duty of firms to society, than in common-law
countries, where shareholder value has primacy.
18. A recent entry in this literature is Krüger (2009), who conducts event studies on the announcement of
ratings by KLD Research & Analytics, a firm that provides environmental, social and governance
(ESG) research for institutional investors. Stock prices fall on average by 1% within a week following a
negative announcement. On the other hand, there does not seem to be an abnormal return after a
positive announcement.
19. At least up to a point. Barnea and Rubin (2006) argue that small amounts of CSR expenditures will
raise profitability, while larger amounts will not.
20. In his descriptive statistics, Krüger (2009) finds that ‘irresponsible companies’Fdefined as those for
which KLD records more events of bad behaviourFtend to have been less profitable in the past than
responsible ones.
21. In the long run, however, certain technologies (e.g. clean power more likely than reforestation) may
benefit from economies of scale and learning-by-doing, bringing costs back down and yields up.
22. See, for example, Maskin and Tirole (2004).
REFERENCES
AMERICAN INTERNATIONAL GROUP, INC. (2007). Putting Our Strength Behind Sustainability. Corporate
Responsibility Report. Available at http://media.corporate–ir.net/media_files/irol/76/76115/AIG_CRe-
port_0708.pdf
ANDRIES, M. (2008). Social responsibility and asset prices: is there a relationship? Mimeo, University of
Chicago.
ARIELY, D., BRACHA, A. and MEIER, S. (2009). Doing good or doing well? Image motivation and monetary
incentives in behaving prosocially. American Economic Review, forthcoming.
AVLONAS, N. (2009). The origins of social responsibility in ancient Greece. Mimeo, American College of
Greece.
BARNEA, A. and RUBIN, A. (2006). Corporate social responsibility as a conflict between shareholders. EFA
2006 Zurich Meetings.
BARON, D. (2001). Private politics, corporate social responsibility and integrated strategy. Journal of Economics
and Management Strategy, 10, 7–45.
BÉNABOU, R. (2008a). Ideology. Journal of the European Economic Association, 6(2–3), 321–52.
FFF (2008b). Groupthink: collective delusions in organizations and markets. Mimeo, Princeton University.
FFF and TIROLE, J. (2006a). Incentives and prosocial behavior. American Economic Review, 96(5), 1652–78.
FFF and FFF (2006b). Belief in a just world and redistributive politics. Quarterly Journal of Economics,
121(2), 699–746.
FFF and FFF (2007). Identity, morals and taboos: beliefs as assets. CEPR Discussion Paper no. 6123.
FFF and FFF (2010). Laws and norms. Mimeo.
BESLEY, T. and GHATAK, M. (2005). Competition and incentives with motivated agents. American Economic
Review, 95(3), 616–36.
FFF and FFF (2007). Retailing public goods: the economics of corporate social responsibility. Journal of
Public Economics, 91(9), 1645–63.
BREKKE, K. A. and NYBORG, K. (2008). Moral hazard and moral motivation: corporate social responsibility as
labor market screening. Resource and Energy Economics, 30(4), 509–26.
BURASCHI, A. and CORNELLI, F. (2003). Donations. Mimeo, London Business School.
CARPENTER, J. and MYERS, C. (2007). Why volunteer? Evidence on the role of altruism, reputation, and
incentives. IZA Discussion Paper no. 302.
CESPA, G. and CESTONE, G. (2007). Corporate social responsibility and managerial entrenchment. ECGI
Finance Working Paper no. 157/2007.
DANA, J., CAIN, D. M. and DAWES, R. (2006). What you don’t know won’t hurt me: costly (but quiet) exit in a
dictator game. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 100(2), 193–201.
FFF, KUANG, J. and WEBER, R. (2007). Exploiting moral wriggle room: experiments demonstrating an
illusory preference for fairness. Economic Theory, 33(1), 67–80.
DELLAVIGNA, S., LIST, J. and MALMENDIER, U. (2009). Testing for altruism and social pressure in charitable
giving. Mimeo, University of Chicago.
DEWATRIPONT, M., JEWITT, I. and TIROLE, J. (1999). The economics of career concerns. II: Applications to
missions in organizations. Review of Economic Studies, 66(1), 199–217.
FREEMAN, R. B. (1997). Working for nothing: the supply of volunteer labor. Journal of Labor Economics, 15,
140–66.
FRIEDMAN, M. (1970). The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine,
13 September, 122–6.
FUNK, P. (2008). Social incentives and voter turnout: evidence from the Swiss mail ballot system. Journal of the
European Economic Association, forthcoming.
GECZY, C., STAMBAUGH, R. and LEVIN, D. (2005). Investing in socially responsible mutual funds. Working
Paper, The Wharton School, October.
GLAZER, A. and KONRAD, K. (1996). A signaling explanation for charity. American Economic Review, 86(4),
1019–28.
HAMMAN, J., WEBER, R. and LOEWENSTEIN, G. (2009). Self-interest through delegation: an additional rationale
for the principal–agent relationship. American Economic Review, forthcoming.
HEAL, G. (2005). Corporate social responsibilityFeconomic and financial perspectives. Geneva Papers, 30, 387–
409.
HOLMSTRÖM, B. and TIROLE, J. (1993). Market liquidity and performance monitoring. Journal of Political
Economy, 101, 678–709.
HONG, H. and KACPERCZYK, M. (2009). The price of sin: the effects of social norms on markets. Journal of
Financial Economics, forthcoming.
ISHERWOOD, C. (2007). The graffiti of the philanthropic class. New York Times, 2 December.
JENNINGS, M. (2006). The Seven Signs of Ethical Collapse: How To Spot Moral Meltdowns in Companies . . .
Before It Is Too Late. New York: St Martin’s Press.
KITZMUELLER, M. (2008). Economics and corporate social responsibility. Mimeo, European University Institute.
KRUEGER, A. and MAS, A. (2004). Strikes, scabs, and tread separations: labor strife and the production of
defective Bridgestone/Firestone tires. Journal of Political Economy, 112(2), 253–89.
KRÜGER, P. (2009). Corporate social responsibility and the board of directors. Mimeo, Toulouse School of
Economics.
LACETERA, N. and MACIS, M. (2008). Social image concerns and pro-social behavior. IZA Discussion Paper no.
3771.
LANDIER, A. and NAIR, V. (2008). Investing for Change: Profit from Responsible Investment. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
MARGOLIS, J. and ELFENBEIN, H. (2007). Do well by doing good? Don’t count on it. Harvard Business Review,
Social Responsibility, Special Issue on HBS Centennial, 86(1), 19.
FFF, FFF and WALSH, J. (2007). Does it pay to be good? A meta-analysis and redirection of research on
the relationship between corporate social and financial performance. Working Paper, Ross School of
Business, University of Michigan.
MASKIN, E. and TIROLE, J. (2004). The politician and the judge: accountability in government. American
Economic Review, 94, 1034–54.
MAZAR, N., AMIR, O. and ARIELY, D. (2008). The dishonesty of honest people: a theory of self-concept
maintenance. Journal of Marketing Research, 45, 633–4.
MONIN, B. (2007). Holier than me? Threatening social comparison in the moral domain. International Review of
Social Psychology, 20(1), 53–68.
FFF and MILLER, D. (2001). Moral credentials and the expression of prejudice. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 81(1), 33–43.
FFF, SAWYER, P. J. and MARQUEZ, M. J. (2008). The rejection of moral rebels: resenting those who do the
right thing. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 95(1), 76–93.
ORLITZKY, M., SCHMIDT, F. and RYNES, S. (2003). Corporate social and financial performance: a meta-
analysis. Organization Studies, 24(3), 403–41.
PIGOU, A. (1920). The Economics of Welfare. London: Macmillan.
REINHARDT, F., STAVINS, R. and VIETOR, R. (2008). Corporate social responsibility through an economic lens.
FEEM Working Paper no. 84.2008.
SHAVELL, S. (2002). Law versus morality as regulators of conduct. American Law and Economics Review, 4(2),
227–57.
SOCIAL INVESTMENT FORUM (2007) Report on Socially Responsible Investing Trends in the U.S. Available at
http://www.socialinvest.org/resources/research