Architecture, Critique, Ideology PDF
Architecture, Critique, Ideology PDF
Architecture, Critique, Ideology PDF
Critique,
Ideology
sven-olov
wallenstein
Architecture, Critique, Ideology
© Copyright 2016 Sven-Olov Wallenstein and Axl Books.
Axl Books
www.axlbooks.com
info@axlbooks.com
ISBN 978-91-86883-13-3
Architecture, Critique, Ideology
Writings on Architecture and Theory
sven-olov wallenstein
axl books
Contents
This book gathers together essays written over the course of the
last decade, all of which in one way or another deal with the tra-
dition of critical theory, and with the fate of such a theoretical
enterprise within architectural discourse. For some, this tradi-
tion has increasingly come to seem problematic, although the
criticisms are not all of a piece: on closer inspection, it is clear
that they are comprised of several contradictory and incompat-
ible strands, some of which involve the rejection of the idea of a
critical theory altogether, others of which call for a redefinition
and rethinking of some of its basic parameters and assumptions.
This book situates itself among those strands of thought that
defend the legacy of critical theory, although it also argues that
such a defense must remain open to contemporary challenges,
theoretical as well as practical.
The referent of the very term critical theory is by no means
obvious. Historically, the term generally refers to the Frankfurt
School, and the legacy of Adorno and Benjamin in particular; in
a larger timeframe it also denotes the philosophical tradition that
begins with Kant’s Critical Philosophy and continues—more like
a constantly broken and twisted line than a straight one—through
Hegel, Marx, and beyond. My proposal here involves understand-
ing the term as freely as possible, so that it also intersects with
vii
architecture, critique, ideology
viii
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
forces that transcend and condition it. This divide between the
generality of concepts and the particularity of practices is obvi-
ously not of recent vintage, but it has acquired a particular in-
tensity in the present, where singularity and difference are the
battle cries of the moment, while all things on another level melt
into air precisely because of their maximal interconnectedness. If
all things are singular, local, and specific, and seem to resist the
generality of theories, it is precisely because they form part of a
network that in turn operates by continually differentiating itself,
and in this exerts a systemic power that remains opaque to those
who inhabit its singular points. These two sides must be thought
together without reducing one to the other, which is why there is
no one answer to the problem of the relation between theory and
practice: they call upon each other in specific situations, and the
movement neither proceeds from top to bottom, which is how
one, rightly or wrongly, tends to understand the great idealist sys-
tems (with the possible, partial exception of Hegelianism), nor
from the bottom up, as in the attempts to create a physiological
aesthetic to succeed idealism in the second half of the eighteenth
century, which today find an echo in many claims that aesthetic
issues are fundamentally to be dealt with in cognitive science,
evolutionary theory, or even empirical biology. Instead, this rela-
tion is brought to life from both ends, by works that question their
own status as well as the categories we use to apprehend them,
and by a thought that seeks other determinations than those of-
fered by a seemingly self-enclosed sphere of concepts.
The subtitle of this book, “Writings on Architecture and
Theory,” seeks to point to this indeterminacy, or rather this
quest for singular determinations—which perhaps was what
Adorno, following Benjamin, once aspired to in the idea of con-
stellations.1 The “and” indicates the need for an articulation, or
1. See Adorno, Negative Dialektik, Gesammelte Schriften (Frankfurt am
Main; Suhrkamp, 1997), vol. 6, 164–169; Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B.
ix
architecture, critique, ideology
Architecture
In order for such a theory to become productive, it cannot re-
fer exclusively to buildings, bricks, and mortar, nor, by simply
Ashton (London: Routledge, 1973), 162–166.
2. The outer limit of this trajectory was perhaps signaled by his “Per
una critica dell’ideologia architettonica” (first published in Contropi-
ano 1969; trans. Stephen Sartarelli in Hays, Architecture Theory Since
1968 [Cambridge, Mass: MIT, 1998]), and the methodological preface
to La sfera e il labirinto, “Il progetto storico” (1980), trans. Pellegrino
d’Acierno and Robert Connolly in Tafuri, The Sphere and the Labyrinth:
Avant-Gardes and Architecture from Piranesi to the 1970s (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT, 1990), where the self-reflexivity of the very language
of critique strikes back almost with every step at the methodological
assurance of the 1969 essay. If the first text wants to confront architec-
tural discourse with the material contradictions of a reality to which it
offers only imaginary solutions, the “real problem,” Tafuri states in the
second text, “is how to project a criticism capable of constantly putting
itself into crisis by putting into crisis the real.” (9)
x
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xi
architecture, critique, ideology
4. See Hegel, Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik, Werke, eds. Eva Moldenhauer
and Karl Markus Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1986), vol.
14, 270; Hegel’s Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, trans T. M. Knox (Ox-
ford: Clarendon Press, 1975), 633, and my discussion of this transition
in “Hegel and the Grounding of Architecture,” in Michael Asgaard and
Henrik Oxvig (eds.), The Paradoxes of Appearing: Essays on Art, Architec-
ture, and Philosophy (Baden: Lars Müller Publishers, 2009).
xii
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xiii
architecture, critique, ideology
Critique
The obvious relation of the term critique to a whole tradition
running from Kant and Hegel through Marx up to Benjamin and
Adorno has already been noted, as has the general sense in which
the term is understood here, such that it comes to include posi-
tions that not only deviate from the legacy of dialectical critique,
but also would appear to stand opposed to it. What is at stake is
the sense of critique as reflection on our historical present that
attempts to excavate conditions, possibilities, and limitations of
aesthetic production, which on the one hand is inevitably in-
scribed in the structures of the current world, and on the other
hand takes issue with it, attempts to go beyond it, or at least taps
into its contradictions so as to set congealed structures in motion.
In order to do this, critique cannot retreat to positions that have
already been absorbed, which is why the broader understanding
of critical theory corresponds to the necessity of rethinking the
concepts that were at the basis of its earlier forms: subjectivity,
experience, contradiction, negation, form, autonomy, nature—all
of which have been subjected to fundamental transformations
both in philosophy and the arts since the 1960s.
Such a rethinking of the basic tenets of critical theory has
been underway for some time within the Frankfurt School it-
self, specifically in Habermas and his followers. In their line of
reasoning, the concept of mimesis—which Adorno understands
not as simple imitation and duplication of some given reality in
artistic form, but as an archaic form of merging with the object
that survives inside representation, as an inner subversion of
identity thinking—must be rejected, since it allegedly sets itself
xiv
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xv
architecture, critique, ideology
xvi
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
Ideology
In the most far-reaching sense of the term, ideology would take
us all the way back to the beginnings of philosophy, to Plato’s
theory of forms, which is a logos of the idea or eidos, and as such
the first ideo-logy (which incidentally also holds for the more
restricted sense of the term, as comes across in the necessity of
“noble lies” in The Republic). Most contemporary uses of term
however draw on the model proposed by Marx in The German
Ideology, i.e., the camera obscura that gives us an inverted picture
of the world, so that ideas and not material processes come to be
seen as the determining factors. Against this, Marx suggests that
it is only determined individuals who produce determined social
relations, and what is decisive is not how they represent their
life process to themselves, but how it actually occurs, in what
way they are active and produce material objects. The produc-
tion of ideas, law, metaphysics, religion, etc., is thus inextricably
tied to the material production process, and with the interac-
tion (Verkehr) that it involves, and consciousness (Bewusstsein)
is finally never anything other than conscious being (bewusstes
Sein), i.e., a kind of being-aware that arises directly out of the
actual life process.7 But this direct reflection is nevertheless an
7. “Das Bewusstsein kann nie etwas Andres sein als das bewusste Sein,
und das Sein der Menschen ist ihr wirklicher Lebensprozess. Wenn in
der ganzen Ideologie die Menschen und ihre Verhältnisse wie in einer
Camera obscura auf den Kopf gestellt erscheinen, so geht dies Phän-
omen ebensosehr aus ihrem historischen Lebensprozess hervor, wie die
xvii
architecture, critique, ideology
xviii
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
spirit produces new substances both on the left and the right.
Seen in context, these remarks are not so much general claims
about ideology as a settling of accounts with Marx’s own left-
Hegelian past—which in turn raises the question to what extent
he remains a Hegelian, whether there is a break between the
young and the mature Marx, if the concept of alienation in the
Paris manuscripts remains pertinent for the systemic analysis
developed in Capital, and many other related questions. The
central issue here, however, is that of the subject as the bearer
of ideology: is there a way of overcoming ideology that would
not simply discard the “phrases of consciousness” as belonging
to the element of warped reflections, but rather inscribe subjec-
tivity as a complex figure of openings and closures, both condi-
tioned and conditioning?
It was precisely these problems that motivated Althusser’s
new take on ideology as a structure that does not belong to a
subject’s way of representing the world, but rather is constitutive
of subjectivity as such.9 While the general theoretical framework
that underpins these claims has probably crumbled beyond re-
pair—specifically the idea of pure theory or science that breaks
with the empirical object just as much as with the subject, and
installs itself in a “void”10—it may be useful to return to some of
its details, since, surprisingly enough, they might have a produc-
tive relation to architecture in particular. For Althusser, ideology
9. See “Idéologie et appareils idéologiques d’État. (Notes pour une recher-
che)” (1970), reprinted in Althusser, Positions (1964–1975) (Paris: Les
Éditions sociales, 1976); trans. Ben Brewster, in Althusser, Lenin and
Philosophy and Other Essays (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971) as
well as the more developed argument in Sur la reproduction (Paris: PUF,
1995).
10. While such a void, as a particular experience of the limit of subjectiv-
ity, is not without interesting philosophical implications, it seems too
difficult to claim that it could warrant the authority of theory over
ideology. For a reading of the motif of the void, see François Matheron,
“La récurrence de vide chez Louis Althusser,” in Matheron (ed.), Lire
Althusser aujourd’hui (Paris: L’Harmattan, 1997).
xix
architecture, critique, ideology
xx
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxi
architecture, critique, ideology
xxii
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxiii
architecture, critique, ideology
xxiv
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxv
architecture, critique, ideology
xxvi
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxvii
architecture, critique, ideology
xxviii
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
18. See Martin, Utopia’s Ghost: Architecture and Postmodernism, Again (Min-
neapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2010). In Martin’s analysis,
the architecture of postmodernism appears as an integral part of the
spatial or “territorial” ordering of capitalism itself, and rather than
just a symptom or cipher for other forces, it is itself one of their crucial
agents. Architecture produces a powerful tool for the implementa-
tion of capital, and it is precisely its immanence in power that blocks
it from perceiving power other than in the distorted mirror of its own
autonomy. Its various modes of acting and representing, its thinking
in the widest sense, thus also amounts to an active unthinking of other
possibilities, above all the idea of utopia, which then returns, spectrally,
in the form of enclaves and divisions inside social space. For a further
discussion of Martin’s analysis, see chap 4 below.
19. See the interview with Raymond Bellour and François Ewald, on
the occasion of the publications of Le Pli: Leibniz et le baroque, “Sur la
philosophie,” Pourparlers (Paris: Minuit, 1990), 212: “On Philosophy,”
Negotiations, trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1995), 155.
xxix
architecture, critique, ideology
***
The first chapter, “Manfredo Tafuri and the End of Utopia,” lo-
cates a starting point in the work of Manfredo Tafuri, and more
generally, the Venice School, which during a period of intense
activity and debate constituted the focal point of the debates on
the legacy of Marxism and the possibility of a “critique of archi-
tectural ideology,” as was the title of one of Tafuri’s program-
matic essays, published in 1969.
Tafuri has an enduring and even haunting presence in con-
temporary architectural discourse. To some, his type of Marxist
analysis, deeply embedded in the conflicts of the Italian left in
the 1970s, would today seem simply outdated—or at least this is
what many would wish. The question of the ideological role of
modern architecture—which Tafuri and his colleagues studied
in great depth, drawing on analyses of architecture and urban
planning in the Soviet Union, in the social-democratic state of
the Weimar Republic, and in American capitalism—however re-
mains just as pertinent today, and the impasse with which this
analytical work has left us, in the guise of the divide between a
critical and an operative reading of history, remains a crucial is-
sue, no matter how much we would like to mitigate and even re-
press it. In fact, the idea of the Metropolis as the essential site of
capital, developed by Tafuri and Massimo Cacciari, is still very
much alive today, although approached from the opposite angle,
most famously in the writings and projects of Rem Koolhaas,
who can be understood as a rebellious disciple of Tafuri. The
question remains to what extent this type of reworked avant-
garde sensibility—to analyze the structures of the emergent as
opposed to the residual, and then declare an unconditional sup-
port for the new—intends to simply identify with the aggres-
sor, or to what extent it can be understood as a more fluid and
flexible way to deal with the present. Tafuri’s critical analysis
xxx
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxxi
architecture, critique, ideology
xxxii
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxxiii
architecture, critique, ideology
xxxiv
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxxv
architecture, critique, ideology
xxxvi
Introduction: Architecture,
Critique,
Ideology
xxxvii
architecture, critique, ideology
xxxviii
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
1
architecture, critique, ideology
2
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
3
architecture, critique, ideology
4
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
5
architecture, critique, ideology
6
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
7
architecture, critique, ideology
any other concept that would denote a going beyond, but rather comple-
tion; see Gregotti, “The Architecture of Completion,” Casabella, op. cit.
To this it must be added that while Tafuri never suggests that moder-
nity could be overcome or left behind, there is still, and specifically in
the work that emerged at the time of the book on Italian architecture, a
kind of transgression and disruption of unity in the reading of the past,
which lies at the basis of his idea of a “historical project” as presented in
the introduction to La sfera e il labirinto.
10. For a sustained analysis of this idea, see the introduction in Biraghi, Pro-
getto di crisi, 9–53.
8
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
9
architecture, critique, ideology
10
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
Towards a critique of
architectural ideology
The work that established Tafuri as a central reference in ar-
chitectural discourse, Teorie e storia dell’architettura (1968),15
launches a fundamental attack on what he calls “operative criti-
cism.” By this he means an analysis that scans history in search
14. I borrow the expression “out of architecture” from Reinhold Martin,
Utopia’s Ghost: Architecture and Postmodernism, Again (Minneapolis: Uni-
versity of Minnesota Press, 2010). For more on this, see chap. 4, below.
15. Obviously, Teorie e storia does not appear ex nihilo, but came to be after a
decade of work on both Renaissance and modern architecture. For this
background work, see Giorgio Ciucci, “The Formative Years,” Casabella,
op. cit., the interview with Luisa Passerini, “History as Project,” Any
25–26 (200), and Andrew Leach, Manfredo Tafuri: Choosing History. This
period however remains peripheral to my question here.
11
architecture, critique, ideology
12
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
13
architecture, critique, ideology
14
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
15
architecture, critique, ideology
16
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
une histoire,” in Casabella, op. cit., 53. Some of Tafuri’s own statements,
where he totally rejects the idea of a “critique” that would mediate his-
torical writing and practice seem exaggerated and philosophically naive,
and to be contradicted by his own work, which is far more fluid; see the
interview with Richard Ingersoll, “There is no Criticism, only History,”
in Casabella, op. cit.
17
architecture, critique, ideology
18
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
19
architecture, critique, ideology
20
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
21
architecture, critique, ideology
22
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
23
architecture, critique, ideology
24
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
25
architecture, critique, ideology
26
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
27
architecture, critique, ideology
28
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
29
architecture, critique, ideology
30
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
31
architecture, critique, ideology
nuity from the basic cell to the city in its totality, so that they
in the end appear as the two endpoints of a single chain. The
Metropolis is one big machine, where the basic unity lies on
this side of traditional form, and the unity to be created lies
beyond it, which means that the single edifice no longer consti-
tutes a privileged or even interesting object, only a relative and
mobile cut in a more encompassing structure. Place and space,
nuances and exceptions must disappear in the Metropolis,
Hilberseimer argues, and with them all of architecture’s tradi-
tional dimensions. The strict reduction to cubic and geometric
shapes, which in a sense are scale-less because of the erasure of
all natural models, takes us away from the experiencing subject,
or, more precisely, takes us in the direction of a transformed
experience in which exchangeability and uniformity can be af-
firmed as such.
Hilberseimer thus states with cold precision, more clearly
than any of his contemporaries— Taut, Gropius, or Mies—what
modern capitalism needs. The architect as a producer of objects
belongs to the past, and the real task is to organize the city as
a cycle of production and to invent organizational models. In
this Großstadtarchitektur, there is simply no more crisis of the
object, Tafuri notes, since the object has already disappeared.
Consequently, Hilberseimer no longer understands architec-
ture as an instrument of knowledge, and the conflict between
Objectivity and the expressionism of architects like Poelzig and
Häring signals in a precise manner this divide between the cog-
nitive and the technological, with no possibility of an exchange
between them. The expressionist arrière-garde could in one
sense have been able to play a critical role in relation to the re-
ductive program of Objectivity, Tafuri suggests, but they were
unable to propose true alternatives on the same level of techno-
logical objectivity, precisely because they depended on a model
that belonged to the residual and not the emergent.
32
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
33
architecture, critique, ideology
34
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
35
architecture, critique, ideology
36
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
37
architecture, critique, ideology
38
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
39
architecture, critique, ideology
40
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
41
architecture, critique, ideology
42
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
43
architecture, critique, ideology
44
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
45
architecture, critique, ideology
46
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
42. The “paradox worthy of Kafka” no doubt refers to the short story
“Das Schweigen der Sirene,” where Kafka presents us with a series of
interpretations of the encounter of Ulysses and the sirens. In Homer,
Ulysses ties himself to the mast and blocks the ears of his oarsmen with
wax in order for them to escape the deadly seduction of the song and
keep working, while he is able to enjoy it without fear of being lured
into acting. This is a division that Adorno and Horkheimer famously
understand in Dialectic of Enlightenment as an archaic model for the
genealogy of aesthetic disinterest, both in terms of a division of labor
and as the origin of the traces of a first nature that subsists in art, to
the effect that all singing henceforth has remained internally broken.
Kafka inverts the story, and suggests that what is truly deadly is rather
the silence of the sirens, and that while some may have escaped their
song, no one has escaped their silence, which in the case of Ulysses was
prompted by the look of happiness on his face upon seeing them. In
Kafka, it is thus Ulysses who blocks his ears with wax, which prevents
him from noticing their silence. At the end Kafka proposes another pos-
sibility, that Ulysses in fact knew that the sirens were silent, but faked
not to notice this (“in a certain way held this appearance as a shield
against the sirens and the gods,” Kafka writes) in order not to receive
divine punishment because of his victory. Finally, he suggests that this
mystery is beyond human comprehension.
43. For a reading that follows Adorno, which also picks up the motif of the
siren song, although in the version of Dialektik der Aufklärung, and leaves
out the reference to Kafka’s inversion of the story, see K. Michael Hays,
“Odysseus and the Oarsmen, or, Mies’ Abstraction once again,” in The
Presence of Mies, ed. Detlef Mertins (New York: Princeton Architectural
Press, 1994).
47
architecture, critique, ideology
48
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
49
architecture, critique, ideology
50
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
part been the object of much criticism, specifically for the rigid
application of the Athens Charter, and it constitutes one of the
few actual tests of the feasibility of his urbanist vision. What
Tafuri and Dal Co see, is buildings that “call to each other across
the distances” in an “unattainable colloquy” (MA 323), remain-
ing alone and isolated, and an emphasis on the intervening
space that no longer connects but disconnects. In many of these
late projects, Tafuri and Dal Co conclude, hermetic symbols be-
come the residential model, withdrawn from productive reality,
and the “present becomes manifest as space that ruptures all
relations between processes of economic valorization and au-
tonomy of the word,” to the effect that “‘Speaking’ is possible
only by taking onto oneself the burden of such trauma.” If ar-
chitectural language here finds itself in a checkmate, it realizes
that it can only speak by taking refuge in mystic spaces, “with-
drawing from the metropolitan reality that it had mistakenly
believed could be reconciled with itself.” (ibid.)
As a kind of coda to the more grandiose battles with the im-
possible staged by Mies and Corbusier, Frank Lloyd Wright,
the final of the masters, pursued the quest for his imaginary
Usonia, and gradually came to identify with his own myth.
Rooted in eighteenth-century anarchism with its visions of
universal harmony, Wright’s vision of a “great peace” coincid-
ing with maximum mobility became increasingly remote from
the existing city, and the mythical spiral that pervades many of
his later works operated as a symbol of the interpenetration of
nature and artifice, as a spiritual principle that would establish
a “link between the contingent and the infinite” (MA 328).
Yet rather than a purist asceticism, Wright’s geometry, like
technology, is only “an obstacle to be overcome,” in the end
“indicating the possibility of transcending the civilization of
labor”—a gesture of romantic anti-capitalism that however re-
mained powerless in the face of reality, and had to have recourse
51
architecture, critique, ideology
52
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
53
architecture, critique, ideology
perceive the difference between world and thing, i.e., how archi-
tecture refuses to be subsumed under the social and historical
universe of which it is nonetheless a part. There is an irreduc-
ible “estrangement” or “distancing” (MA 364) that governs
contemporary work, Tafuri and Dal Co suggest, which opens
“new lines of conduct” that must be acknowledged and made
into a poetic based on difference and renunciation—obviously
echoing the claims earlier made on behalf of Mies—that would
dispel the myth of unitary origins and unidirectional historical
genealogies.
Surveying a wide spectrum of responses to the demise of the
modern movement, from the flight to technological objectiv-
ism (Piano and Rogers), returns to nature (van Eyck), formal
experimentations that draw on architectural history (Stirling),
nostalgic claims for an architecture that aspires to retrieve classi-
cal monumentality (Kahn) or the commercial flow of Las Vegas
(Venturi), Tafuri and Dal Co detect a surrender of all hope of
seizing control over the city, of which the isolated super-sky-
scraper is the most telling indication. As “isolated monsters”
whose own “inflexible organization acts as surrogate for the or-
der lacking in the city itself” (MA 372), they constitute new
forms of publicity, or as in the case of works by Roche and
Dinkeloo, “a screen on which the images of surrounding life
are projected, but without the ‘renunciation’ of Mies.” (ibid.)48
The resulting divide has cut off the avant-garde from the real,
spawning an infinite series of attempts at recapturing what has
been lost. And yet, Tafuri and Dal Co conclude, this is by no
means an end: “If this book aims to demonstrate anything, it is
precisely the impossibility of writing the word finis at any point
in history.” (392) The figure of the end remains operative, al-
54
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
55
architecture, critique, ideology
50. The Sphere and the Labyrinth: Avant-Gardes and Architecture from Piranesi to
the 1970s, trans. Pellegrino d’Acierno and Robert Connolly (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT, 1990), 9. Henceforth cited as SL with page number.
56
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
51. Via Giulia: Un’ utopia urbanistica del ‘500 (Rome: Staderini, 1975).
52. The term “monad” is not used by Tafuri, but the logic of the argument
draws him close to Adorno’s understanding of the term: the monad
concentrates the world within itself, and in this it lets us understand
the contradictions of the world in a condensed form. For Adorno on
the monadic structure of the work, see Aesthetic Theory, trans. Robert
Hullot-Kentor (London: Continuum, 1997), 237–239.
57
architecture, critique, ideology
53. The meaning of terms like “left” and “right” is far from obvious. Ta-
furi’s formulation might be taken in the sense that the “left” would un-
derstand the symbolic order as historical through and through, whereas
the “right” would uphold a more emphatically structural view that sees
historical transformations of language as mere fluctuations, ripples that
can never shake the great Law of the Father and the Signifier. A bit
further on, Tafuri cautions us that the “privilege attributed by Lacan to
the pure materiality of the signifier” should not be identified with any
“infantile attempts at reconstructing a lost fullness for disenchanted
words” (SL 6), but he leaves the positive meaning of this materiality
unexplained. K. Michael Hays has attempted to formulate a systematic
theory of architecture on the basis of the Lacanian symbolic, but only
with a general reference to Tafuri’s negative view of the resurgence of
the “language problem” in the sixties; see Hays, Architecture’s Desire:
Reading the Late Avant-Garde (Cambridge, Mass.; MIT, 2010), 1–21, on
Tafuri 3–4.
58
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
59
architecture, critique, ideology
60
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
61
architecture, critique, ideology
62
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
63
architecture, critique, ideology
64
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
65
architecture, critique, ideology
66
1. Tafuri and the
end of utopia
67
architecture, critique, ideology
68
Rodchenko, Corbusier, and others: a history of planning that
goes beyond the architect, and shows how the avant-gardes have
been transformed into techniques. This means to undo the tradi-
tional role of the architect, and, seen in this light, the proposals of
Progetto e utopia were less a series of statements of end and closure,
and more an invitation to pursue the task of linking architecture
(understood in a broad sense that includes technologies, models
of organization and planning), critique (as the project of a history
that would be able to decompose and recompose the elements of
the trajectory of modernism in a way that cuts across disciplin-
ary borders), and ideology (as the element of thinking and acting
that includes illusions and well as partial truths, and does not al-
low for a thought that would simply see reality at is, since this re-
ality its itself made up of subject and object positions that include
the historians own). What this analysis can offer, Tafuri writes, is
“an intermittent journey through a maze of tangled paths, one of
the many ‘provisional constructions’ obtainable by starting with
these chosen materials. The cards can be reshuffled and to them
added many that were intentionally left out: the game is destined
to continue.” (SL 21)
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
71
architecture, critique, ideology
72
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
73
architecture, critique, ideology
74
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
75
architecture, critique, ideology
76
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
77
architecture, critique, ideology
the entire process that leads from the singular element to the
city-totality, within which the individual object is dissolved in
a cycle that also mobilizes the user and lays claims to displace
older forms of aesthetic experience. This is displayed in Ludwig
Hilberseimer’s manifesto Großstadtarchitektur (1927), which
proposes a reading of the city as a continuous chain where no
link has priority, and where eventually the moment of groß takes
precedence over Stadt. The issue is no longer the Metropolis as a
bounded place with a specific identity, the “mother city”—thus
severing the “metro-” from its Greek root meter, mother—but
the Metropolis-machine, whose basic habitat unity is the sin-
gular cell, while the edifice, and eventually the city, ceases to
be a basic form. Just as place and space, nuances and exceptions
must disappear for this Metropolitan logic to unfold, and with
them all of architecture’s traditional dimensions, so too the
new scaleless architecture takes us away from the experiencing
subject and its identification with an affective environment, or
more precisely, opens up the possibility of a subjective percep-
tion whose anonymity constitutes a moment of inescapable
truth condensed in the image of the assembly line.
Significantly enough, this loss of place, which extends from
the disruption of the image of the city, to use Kevin Lynch’s
expression, to the violent displacement of the phenomenologi-
cal space-time coordinates of the perceiving subject, could also
be reinterpreted as a kind of emancipatory nihilism, as was the
case in the writings of Massimo Cacciari, whose early work de-
veloped in close connection to Tafuri’s. Cacciari takes his cues
partly from Heidegger, and somewhat surprisingly argues that if
modernity does not allow for dwelling as that which Heidegger,
in most traditional readings, would appear to mourn,7 then the
lesson to be drawn from his work is that this condition is not
78
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
79
architecture, critique, ideology
Controlling space
The problem of how architecture and urban planning could
seize control over the forces and dynamisms of the Metropolis
had been closely connected to the emerging social sciences at
the turn of the century, as can be seen in the writings of Ger-
man sociologists such as Weber, Simmel, and Sombart, and in
80
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
81
architecture, critique, ideology
16. As comes across in his earlier Teoría del enlace del movimiento de las vías
marítimas y terrestres (1863), written as a companion to project for an
intermodal freight transportation system for the port of Barcelona.
82
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
83
architecture, critique, ideology
84
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
85
architecture, critique, ideology
86
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
87
architecture, critique, ideology
88
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
89
architecture, critique, ideology
in search of its own style must also include and project a new
lifestyle, that it must be able to influence everyday behavior,
generate a distinctive look, and fashion desirable objects, if it
is to seize hold of the general public and become desirable. The
utopian moment in modernism is in this way an integral part
of a new visual culture and the system of media and image dis-
tribution that had already begun to emerge in the middle of
the nineteenth century—the age of mechanical reproducibility,
as Benjamin said with reference to photography and cinema,
although he, too, though more obliquely, references architec-
ture—and it has as one of its main objectives the production of
a desiring subject that itself exists as an agent of consumption,
first and foremost precisely of the image of modernity.
This is why it can arguably be deemed superficial simply
to reject the problem of style as superficial; instead it must be
thought as an element belonging to the very substance of archi-
tecture, if the latter is understood as a means of persuasion and
identification through form and image, which it can and must
be. This issue had been raised sharply by Schinkel, as a ques-
tion of what could be accepted as the organic expression of the
contemporary moment, which in his case meant to oppose the
imminent threat of fashion as a severing of form and content.
In 1826, returning to Berlin from his journey to England, where
he had encountered the technological marvels of industrialism,
he notes “the modern age makes everything easy, it no longer
believes in permanence, and has lost all sense of monumental-
ity.” This is an epoch, he continues, “in which everything be-
comes mobile, even that which was supposed to be most du-
rable, namely the art of building, in which the word fashion
becomes widespread in architecture, where forms, materials,
and every tool can be understood as a plaything to be treated as
one wants, where one is prone to try everything since nothing
is in its place (weil nichts an seinem Orte steht), and nothing seems
90
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
91
architecture, critique, ideology
reaches perfection.
Corbusier’s understanding of modern architecture as a
mass medium that must utilize the most sophisticated tech-
niques of publicity, which has been analyzed in detail by Beatriz
Colomina,28 does not contradict the search for classical per-
fection; it is precisely its modern condition of possibility. His
editorial work with Esprit nouveau as well as his own publica-
tions show his command of marketing and visual techniques,
and how eternal values can only be realized through a strategic
intelligence that employs all the tricks of a new trade. The one
and unique style, embodying not taste but universal necessity—
and which thus may present itself as non-style—can then, on the
level of affective impact, be understood as yet another image,
just as functionalism in order to impose itself as a desirable look
need not function better than anything that preceded it, only
project the image of modernity and progress in a convincing
way.29
When early modernism is viewed in this perspective, the
idea of an overcoming of a “great divide” between avant-garde
and mass culture as the basis of the shift between the postmod-
ern and the modern becomes tenuous.30 The image of such a di-
vide was perhaps for the first time visible in the debate between
Benjamin and Adorno in the thirties, where we in Benjamin
would find an affirmation of new reproduction technologies,
the decay of the aura, and the entry of the artwork into the
28. See Beatriz Colomina, Privacy and Publicity: Modern Architecture as Mass
Media (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1994).
29. See, for instance, Jean Baudrillard, Pour une critique de l’économie politique
du signe (Paris: Gallimard, 1972), 229–255, and the concluding discus-
sion in Reyner Banham, Theory and Design in the first Machine Age (Lon-
don: Architectural Press, 1960), 320–25.
30. I borrow this expression from Andreas Huyssen, After the Great Divide:
Modernism, Mass Culture, Postmodernism (Bloomington: Indiana Uni-
versity Press, 1987). Many other similar discussions could be cited,
although Huyssen seems to me to formulate it in the most concise and
systematic fashion.
92
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
93
architecture, critique, ideology
(1966) and Learning from Las Vegas (1972, co-authored with De-
nise Scott Brown and Steven Izenour), are replete with negative
judgments about the past, they can also, and more positively,
be seen as the beginning of an American tradition of cultural
studies32 that emerges from a dialog with pop art, attempting to
map the experience of the commercial landscape as a different
type of order: “Some of the vivid lessons of pop art, involving
scale and context,” Venturi writes in the conclusion to the first
book, “should have awakened architects from prim dreams of
pure order,” and henceforth it is “perhaps from the everyday
landscape, vulgar and disdained, that we can draw the complex
and contradictory order that is valid and vital for our architec-
ture as an urbanistic whole.”33
Not without irony, Venturi presents Complexity and
Contradiction as a “gentle manifesto,” and, in the introductory
sections, he manipulates his historical references with subtle
displacements, reinterpreting rather than simply rejecting the
modernist legacy. His examples are drawn from the whole of
architectural history from the Renaissance to Le Corbusier,
Aalto, and Kahn, in order to delineate a different take on tradi-
tion than the one championed by predecessors like Pevsner and
Giedion. The examples are widely separated in space and time,
not in order to point to eternal principles, but rather to provide
a kind of counter-historical thrust to the linear narratives of
progress.34 Just as the images in Complexity and Contradiction still
32. See Fredric Jameson, The Seeds of Time (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1994), 141. In this sense there is a straight line leading from Ven-
turi to Koolhaas; see the comments on Venturi in The Harvard Guide to
Shopping (Cologne: Taschen, 2001).
33. Robert Venturi, Complexity and Contradiction in Architecture (New York:
The Museum of Modern Art, 1966), 104. Henceforth cited in the text
as CCA.
34. On one level there is no fundamental methodological difference
between Giedion and Venturi: both of them mobilize different ele-
ments from the past to justify current production, and from Tafuri’s
perspective they are equally operative. What Venturi opposes is rather
94
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
95
architecture, critique, ideology
the case of Learning from Las Vegas, the aim is that we should
suspend our value judgment, at least temporarily, in order to
transform the very ideas of value and judgment, thus making
possible a mode of perception that thrives on precisely those
values that had been eradicated from the canon of modern ar-
chitecture. Irony, ambiguity, and polysemy are the weapons
wielded against the imperatives of modernist utopianism, and if
architecture is a mode of communication on all levels, it should
not insulate itself as a utopian counter-image against the messi-
ness of the historical city, or as a semiotic surplus in relation
to its contemporary, commercial, and low descendant: in short,
learning from Las Vegas means to learn how to take a new look
at, and take on the look of, everyday life.38
Complexity and contradiction in architecture for Venturi
result from its necessary participation in an equally complex
and contradictory social and communicative urban form; its
language is inevitably that of a multiplicity of styles and lay-
ers that need not be reformed on the basis of some radical new
grammar.39 If we are to reinstall the social function of archi-
ties: Photograph, Cinema, and the Post-Apocalyptic Ruin,” Site 7–8
(2004).
38. In the most systematic interpretation of Venturi and Scott Brown’s
work so far, Aron Vinegar stresses that we should not reduce the book
to a precursor to the subsequent debate on postmodernism, or to a
mere apotheosis of consumer culture, as is often the case, but rather un-
derstand it as a new take on everyday life. Drawing on Stanley Cavell’s
distinction between skepticism and the ordinary, Vinegar proposes that
the proposal is that we should strive to attain a different mood, open to
the ambiguities of perception and sensibility, rather than to settle for a
choice between the modern and the postmodern. See Vinegar, I Am a
Monument: On Learning from Las Vegas (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 2008),
and Aron Vinegar and Michael J. Golec (eds.), Relearning from Las Vegas
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2009).
39. As we will see in chap. 4, other readings are possible. As Reinhold
Martin suggests, Venturi and Scott Brown’s ideas may be understood
less in terms of a plea for populism and the dissolution of the high–low
distinction than as a normalization, i.e., an adjustment of architecture’s
language through the methods of social science, drawing through the
models of Levittown and Las Vegas.
96
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
97
architecture, critique, ideology
98
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
99
architecture, critique, ideology
tion,” the new reference to the city also entails a return to semantics
(without the term being used), even though of very different nature; see
chap 6, below.
100
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
101
architecture, critique, ideology
44. The initial article was published in Architectural Forum (March 1968),
and reprinted in Nesbitt, Theorizing a New Agenda. The text cited here
is the later version in Learning from Las Vegas. There are also important
differences in terms of layout and the use of images from the first edi-
tion 1972 and the second 1977; see Vinegar, I Am a Monument. The texts
cited in the following however remain the same.
102
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
103
architecture, critique, ideology
104
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
46. As Denise Scott Brown suggests, “New analytic techniques must use
film and videotape to convey the dynamism of sign architecture and the
sequential experience of vast landscapes; and computers are needed to
105
architecture, critique, ideology
106
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
107
architecture, critique, ideology
108
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
109
architecture, critique, ideology
110
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
111
architecture, critique, ideology
53. Rossi emphasizes the varying senses of the term: it can mean a block,
a neighborhood, a residential district (the English translation uses
district and residential district), but it can also be used as a translation, “as
imprecise as it is useful” (AC 97/81), of the German Siedlung.
112
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
54. In some passages Rossi comes close to the expanded idea of monument
launched by Alois Riegl. For a discussion of Riegl on monuments, see
Thordis Arrhenius, The Fragile Monument: On Conservation and Moder-
nity (London: Artifice, 2012), 92–107.
113
architecture, critique, ideology
55. Rossi’s cosa umana draws on Lévi-Strauss’s famous proposal that the
city is “la chose humaine par excellence”; see Tristes tropiques (Paris:
Plon, 1955), 122. The analogy between a city and a poem or a sym-
phony is relevant, Lévi-Strauss says, because they are all located “in
the encounter between nature and artificiality” (121), which for Rossi
means: in the encounter between collective, i.e., non-conscious, and
conscious processes. Rossi’s persistent use of “aesthetic intentionality”
can however be confusing, since what he in fact shows is that the urban
fact in its very facticity is independent of its origin, and that the initial
intention in no way guides later overlays of new uses and senses.
114
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
115
architecture, critique, ideology
116
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
117
architecture, critique, ideology
118
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
119
architecture, critique, ideology
120
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
121
architecture, critique, ideology
122
2. 1966:
Thinking the City
68. In a passage Venturi describes the limit of the city as a total break, which
the absolute indifference to the nature: “Beyond the town, the only tran-
sition between The Strip and the Mojave Desert is a zone of rusting beer
cans. Within the town, the transition is as ruthlessly sudden. Casinos,
whose fronts relate so sensitively to the highway turn their ill-kempt
backsides toward the local environment, exposing their residual forms
and spaces of mechanical equipment and service areas.” (LLV 35)
123
architecture, critique, ideology
124
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
127
architecture, critique, ideology
3. The bridge was one of the technological icons of the time and the
subject of photographs by Germaine Krull as well as a film by Moholo-
Nagy, Marseille, Vieux Port, from 1929.
128
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
129
architecture, critique, ideology
130
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
131
architecture, critique, ideology
132
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
133
architecture, critique, ideology
134
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
14. For the connection between Leibniz’s conception of vis plastica and
Wölfflins’s analysis of Baroque art, see Gilles Deleuze, Le Pli: Leibniz et
la baroque (Paris: Minuit, 1988), 6.
135
architecture, critique, ideology
136
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
16. Other important texts from the period include Theo van Doesburg,
Grundbegriffe der neuen gestaltenden Kunst (1925), and Moholy-Nagy,
von material zu architektur (1929). The latter concludes with a celebra-
tion of Gropius’s Bauhaus building in Dessau and Brinkmann and van
der Flugt’s Van Nelle factory in Rotterdam, both of which evince an
“illusion of spatial interpenetration of a kind that only the subsequent
generation will be able to experience in real life—in the form of glass
architecture.” Moholy-Nagy, von material zu architektur (Berlin: Gebr.
Mann, 2001), 236.
137
architecture, critique, ideology
138
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
Dialectics of transparency
Giedion’s proposals might be understood as utopian, and his
interpretations of the past were never mere records of facts,
but always were oriented toward the opening up of possible fu-
tures—they are indeed operative, as Tafuri suggested, but self-
consciously so—which is one of the reasons why his idea of a
constructive subconscious had such a massive influence on Ben-
jamin’s work on the Parisian arcades, most directly in the case
of the sections on architecture, but also as a general theoretical
model for the way in which technology impacts on structures of
consciousness and perception, in tearing open a gap in the fabric
of time that heralds a coming transformation.19
139
architecture, critique, ideology
140
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
141
architecture, critique, ideology
142
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
and values of a humanist culture, and for which the analogy with paint-
ing will be essential. For a discussion of this, see my The Silences of Mies
(Stockholm: Axl Books, 2008), 59-63.
143
architecture, critique, ideology
writes in his diary: “Everyone, once in a his life, writes his ‘mys-
tery play’; mine was the Glass House.”26
In many respects the Glass House notes are close to Eisenstein’s
working notes toward the film version of Marx’s Capital, in radi-
cally exceeding the strictures of cinematic language and even the
domain of the visual as such: it was “an impossible film,” François
Albera says, “a project destined to remain virtual.”27 But this vir-
tuality was indeed a highly productive one, and it continued to
inform much of Eisenstein’s subsequent work. The transparency
of the glass house condenses the formal and the political into
one charged image, with multiple intersecting points of view,
and where the interpenetration not just of subjects and objects,
but also of actions, generates a dialectical drama that shows the
promised transparency to be ridden with fears and tensions; it
harbors a mystery: that transparency and interpenetration on an-
other level produces opacity, confusion, and division. The ques-
tion of how to negotiate the relation between political agency and
formal complexity, how to transform the dislocation of percep-
tion into a model for social critique, traverses the avant-garde in
all of its guises, and whether the quest for transparency, material
as well as social, will help bring about this model for social cri-
tique, constitutes one of its founding problems.
Producing complexity,
or the planning of chance
When Giedion notes that “walls no longer rigidly define
streets,” and that “the street has been transformed into a stream
of movement,” his vocabulary is derived from a first machine
age discourse on energy, movement, and velocity, claiming to
dissolve all firm objects that pose obstacles to a new type of free-
26. Cited in François Albera, “Introduction,” in Eisenstein, Glass House
(Paris: Les Presses du Réel, 2009), 11.
27. Ibid, 9.
144
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
145
architecture, critique, ideology
146
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
147
architecture, critique, ideology
148
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
149
architecture, critique, ideology
among object, function, and user that allows for no further questions
because it is intuitive, evident, and transparent. See Acceptera (Stock-
holm: Tiden, 1931), 139f. “Germans” in the above quoted no doubt
refers to Walter Gropius and his introductory remarks to the 21 theses
on “Systematische Vorarbeit für rationellen Wohnungsbau,” in bauhaus
1, no. 2 (1927): “Bauen bedeutet Gestaltung von Lebensvorgängen.
Die Mehrzahl der Individuen hat gleichartige Lebensbedürfnisse. Es
ist daher logisch und im Sinne eines wirtschaftlichen Vorgehens, diesen
gleichgearteten Massenbedürfnisse einheitlich und gleichartig zu be-
friedigen.” (“Building means shaping of life processes. The majority of
individuals have similar vital needs. Thus it is logical, and in the spirit
of an economical undertaking, to satisfy these mass needs in a uniform
and similar way.”)
36. For an overview of how situationist theory engages with the legacy of
modernist architecture and city planning, see Simon Sadler, The Situ-
ationist City (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1999).
150
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
151
architecture, critique, ideology
38. “By declining labor-saving devices, devising tortuous routes through his
apartment, and fitting it with noisy doors and useless locks, Feuerstein
refused to allow his own home to become another cog in the mecha-
152
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
153
architecture, critique, ideology
154
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
tween Debord and Henri Lefebvre. For the latter, whose analy-
sis of the structures of everyday life forms the backdrop of many
situationist concepts, it is decisive that fantasy and historical
moments (with the Paris commune constituting the paradigm
for both of them) can be integrated in a systematic theory capa-
ble of accounting for the subjective dimension of history with-
out reducing it. But rather than the systemic analysis that at
the time claimed to move away from subjectivity and experience
toward the construction of a pure Theory (most obviously in the
case of Althusser and his followers), for which individual experi-
ence would be caught up in the order of the imaginary, Lefebvre
insists on the power of the subject and imagination to engage
in the concrete dialectic of everyday practice, even to the point
that he would insist on being a “romantic revolutionary” and on
the need for resuscitating the dimension of feast and carnival,
against the kind of critical analysis whose obsession with struc-
tures for him merely reflected and reinforced the technocratic
world that it aspired to overthrow. In this there is also a moment
of pleasure or enjoyment (jouissance) that is essential for theory
to be meaningful, but also belongs particularly to architecture,42
a bodily encounter with the built environment that cannot be
reduced to the particular ways in which it spatializes the social
order, but that also transgresses this order in a form dispersal
and expenditure that still belongs to the capacity of the subject,
not to its undoing.
This idea of a theory that begins in and returns to the com-
plexity of the concrete was crucial throughout Lefebvre’s work,
and it emerges in the aftermath of the Second World War43 in
42. As comes across in the recently rediscovered text, Towards an Architecture
of Enjoyment, ed. Lukasz Stanek, trans. Robert Bononno (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 2014).
43. Sylvère Lotringer notes that Lefebvre initiates his program for a
critique just after the Second World War, and the first volume is con-
temporary with the emergence of new housing programs and suburbia.
155
architecture, critique, ideology
156
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
157
architecture, critique, ideology
158
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
159
architecture, critique, ideology
160
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
161
architecture, critique, ideology
162
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
163
architecture, critique, ideology
164
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
54. In the following chapter, we will see how Reinhold Martin’s interpreta-
tion of postmodernism makes extensive use of the idea of the feedback
loop, in a way that seems consistent with Tschumi’s proposal.
55. See “Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism”
(1984), reprinted in expanded form in Postmodernism, or, The Cultural
Logic of Late Capitalism (Durham: Duke University Press, 1991. See also
chap. 4, below.
165
architecture, critique, ideology
166
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
167
architecture, critique, ideology
168
3. The Pyramid and
the Labyrinth
169
architecture, critique, ideology
170
4. The Recent Past
of Postmodern
Architecture
173
architecture, critique, ideology
174
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
175
architecture, critique, ideology
Postmodernism as an interrogation
of the legacy of the Enlightenment
This was the version closely associated with Lyotard and the
debates initiated by Habermas, and it engendered a vast amount
of the misunderstandings that have circulated in the discussion
for such a long time that they have become almost unquestion-
able truths. One of the reasons for this confusion is the crucial
shift that occurs in Lyotard’s own work between an epochal and
a modal version of the postmodern. The modal version, which
is the one that he would continue to defend throughout most
of his later writings, is launched in a programmatic essay from
1982, “Answering the Question: What is the Postmodern?”
Here he proposes a curious temporal twist, when he says that
the postmodern precedes the modern as a futur antérieur, a future
that is seen from the point of view of the past:
176
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
In this sense, the question posed here about the recent past
of the postmodern can itself be taken as a continuation of the
modal version of the postmodern in its relation to the modern,
in a way that also puts the present at stake. The recent past of
the postmodern would then pose the question of what kind of
event it constituted, an event that still finds echoes in the pres-
ent, and whose conceptualization by no means needs to have
been accessible at the time, but rather reaches us in the form
177
architecture, critique, ideology
178
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
179
architecture, critique, ideology
180
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
181
architecture, critique, ideology
182
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
183
architecture, critique, ideology
184
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
185
architecture, critique, ideology
186
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
187
architecture, critique, ideology
16. The essay goes back to a radio talk from 1960, and was first published in
Arts Yearbook 1961. See Greenberg, The Collected Essays and Criticism, Vol.
4: Modernism with a Vengeance, 1957-1969, ed. John O’Brian (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1993), 85-94.
17. Reprinted in Greenberg, The Collected Essays and Criticism, Vol. 1: Percep-
tions and Judgments, 1939-1944, ed. John O’Brian (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1986).
188
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
189
architecture, critique, ideology
190
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
191
architecture, critique, ideology
192
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
28. Some attempts were made to connect minimal art to architecture, but
mostly in very general and unspecific terms. In Gregory Battcock’s
influential anthology Minimal Art (1968), only one out of the almost
thirty contributions explicitly address the connection to architecture,
Michal Benedikt’s “Sculpture as Architecture” (1966-67), but does so
in general terms, without giving any reference to actual architectural
works of the period.
193
architecture, critique, ideology
194
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
ous types eclecticism and iconicity that could lay claim to being
a “vernacular” (Venturi) or return us to a comprehensible lan-
guage of forms, often drawing on a humanist heritage. This was a
look that obviously just as quickly could be superseded by others,
and it immediately became just as dated as its predecessors, and
shot through with a kind of irony and doubly invisible quotation
marks. These markers were, it must be remembered, however
also part of the postmodernism’s own claim to dismantle ideas of
originality, authorship, and authenticity, and it appeared as if the
phenomenon postmodernism in some hyper-reflexive twist itself
immediately became postmodern.
The reason for the early and massive impact of the post-
modern in architecture must also be sought in the history of
the discipline itself. The reactions against modernism began al-
most immediately after the Second World War, and one could
even claim that architectural discourse had already entered into
a postmodern phase, even if it was not named as such, just as
the late modern formalist interpretations of the others arts were
being consolidated. The discovery of everyday life, from Aldo
van Eyck to Team X, and many other critical analyses, above all
in relation to the urban form, which would eventually lead up
to the symbolic dissolution of CIAM in 1959, predate the major
symbolic publications in the mid-sixties, Venturi’s Complexity
and Contradiction in Architecture and Aldo Rossi’s L’architettura
della città.29 A decade later these developments would be
brought together into Charles Jencks’s Language of Post-Modern
Architecture (1977),30 where the synthesis in terms of style, or
rather a plurality of styles that co-exist in a neutral availabil-
29. For more on Venturi and Rossi, see chap. 2, above.
30. Charles Jencks, The Language of Post-Modern Architecture (London:
Academy Editions, 1977. The book has since 1977 gone through many
editions, and has become a standard reference, also because Jencks is
one of the few who has consistently held on to the term “postmodern,”
in a long series of publications..
195
architecture, critique, ideology
ity, became the guiding idea, which limited the analytic value of
the concept, but also made it more useful and effective for jour-
nalistic polemics. From Jencks onward, the idea of break some-
where in the sixties had imposed itself, regardless of whether it
is described as postmodern or not, and of what its basic reasons
were supposed to have been. Ten years after Jencks, the term
“postmodern” is still retained in Heinrich Klotz’s ambitious
Moderne und Postmoderne: Architektur der Gegenwart, 1960–1980,31
while ten years further ahead, the equally ambitious anthologies
edited by Kate Nesbitt, Theorizing a New Agenda for Architecture:
An Anthology of Architectural Theory, 1965–1995,32 and K. Michael
Hays, Architecture Theory Since 1968,33 settle in their titles for
more neutral markers, “a new agenda,” or simply “since,” even
though they too in their respective ways suggest a break some-
time in the sixties after which things no longer remain the same.
Rather than to write the history of the rise and decline of
31. Klotz, Moderne und Postmoderne: Architektur der Gegenwart, 1960–1980
(Braunschweig: Vieweg & Sohn, 1984); one can note that the English
translation, published four years later, gives the title a backward-
looking inflection: The History of Postmodern Architecture, trans. Radka
Donnell (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1988). Klotz aims to avoid purely
stylistic criteria and the idea of eclecticism, and for him the postmodern
is not so much a rejection of the modern as it is an attempt to integrate
a moment of fiction in function.
32. Kate Nesbitt (ed.), Theorizing a New Agenda for Architecture: An Anthology
of Architectural Theory, 1965–1995 (New York: Princeton Architectural
Press, 1996). In the introduction, Nesbitt notes, “While only the first
chapter is so titled, postmodernism is in fact the subject and point of
reference for the entire book. I hope to make clear that postmodernism
is not a singular style, but more a sensibility of inclusion in a period of
pluralism.” (17)
33. K. Michael Hays (ed.), Architecture Theory Since 1968 (Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT, 1998). Hays notes that many point of chronological departure
could be chosen, but that “in the long run, the coupling of Marxist
critical theory and poststructuralism with readings of architectural
modernism has been what has dominated theory in the main, subsum-
ing and rewriting earlier texts; and ‘since 1968’ covers that formation.”
(xiv) In this sense, his conception of theory, unlike the one adopted
by Nesbitt, is normative, which no doubt accounts for the otherwise
bewildering absence of the term postmodernism from the introduction.
196
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
197
architecture, critique, ideology
198
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
199
architecture, critique, ideology
200
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
201
architecture, critique, ideology
202
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
203
architecture, critique, ideology
204
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
205
architecture, critique, ideology
206
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
works far apart in space and time, on the basis of what he called
an experiential immediacy, which to be sure involves an essen-
tial moment of fiction, and in this it is in some respects not so
far apart as one might think from the more strict procedures
of someone like Husserl.43 For Moore it is however not varia-
tion that gives us the essence, but memory, but as Otero-Pailos
stresses, the memory in case was in fact there in order to be
forgotten, or transformed into a creative act outside of history,
and in this sense Moore can criticize his modernist predecessors
for not being modern enough in relying on objective, pre-given
forms handed down by an equally objectified history.
Escaping from the modernist box also implied a stance
against the political McCarthyism of the time and a defense of
the irreducibility of individual experience, and Moore’s projects
for additions to existing buildings, such as fountains at signa-
ture works like the Lever House and the Seagram building, pro-
vide a sense of breaking out. But as Otero-Pailos demonstrates,
Moore’s fascination for decoration and superficiality ultimately
had in fact more to do with his understanding of the interior,
which is the space of the human mind as such, with its layers of
fantasy and memory, and here too his poetics of space comes
close to Bachelard.44 The aedicule became the vehicle for the
43. See, for instance, Husserl, Ideas I, § 70, where fantasy (Phantasie) is
understood as the basis for the method of eidetic variation, and thus
as the “vital element” (Lebenselement) of phenomenology. For Husserl
fantasy takes us away from the singularity of experience toward the
essence, whereas in Moore, it is the overlay of memory that reduces he
immediacy of the thing.
44. Bachelard’s Poetics of Space is almost exclusive dedicated to places that
we once loved, to the exploration of “topophilia.” His topo-analysis
provides us with a profound account of intimacy and of the path to the
house that takes us back in time, a regressive route that mobilizes a fan-
tasy essentially predicated upon memories that are “housed” in our soul.
We inhabit houses just as much as they inhabit us, Bachelard says, but
in terms of tradition and memory, not as a transformation and opening
toward something new. The house is our first universe, and Bach-
elard emphatically rejects those philosophers that “know the universe
207
architecture, critique, ideology
before they know the house, the far horizon before the resting-place.”
(Bachelard, The Poetics of Space trans. Maria Jolas [Boston: Beacon Press,
1969], 5) All subsequent worlds and spaces—and not least the city, which
for Bachelard seems to have only a negative function as an agent of the
dissolution of the house—are inscribed into this first non-geometric,
non-objective space, and to this extent it can only be given to us as a
remembered, or even dreamt space: “the house we were born in is more
than the embodiment of home, it is also an embodiment of dreams […]
there exists for each of us an oneiric house, a house of dream-memory,
that is lost in the shadow of a beyond of the real past. I called this oneiric
house the crypt of the house that we were born in.” (15). In this, the
protective enclosure plays a decisive role, and in many detailed and
intriguing reflections on secret spaces (closets, drawers), non- or proto-
human dwellings (nests, shells) that already point in the direction of
minute and intimate slices of space (corners, nooks), Bachelard wants to
show how the “phenomenology of the verb to inhabit” (xxxiv) means to
live intensively, to be in an enclosure; further on, he speaks of the “hut,”
whose truth derives from “the intensity of its essence, which is the
essence of the verb ‘to inhabit.’” (32) Bachelard here obviously comes
close to Heidegger’s essay on “Building Dwelling Thinking,” although
his own references are mostly negative remarks on the idea of “thrown-
ness” in early Heidegger. In accordance with Bachelard’s amalgamation
of oblivion and modernity, this world is however always one that is on
the verge of disappearing, it is a rural sphere threatened by modernity’s
disruption of interiority. If the world described by Bachelard is a crypt,
it is also a melancholy introjection that would require a “working-
through” or “perlaboration,” a Durcharbeiten in the Freudian sense, and
needs to ask the question whether we must take leave of the topophilia
that chains us to the lost thing. Nothing would at first sight be more op-
posed to Bachelard’s spatial poetics than Corbusier’s vision of transpar-
ency, where the subject must take up a new relation to the thing and to
visibility as such. Uwe Bernhardt, discusses Corbusier’s housing project
Citè Frugès, Pessac, and interestingly suggests that the changes eventu-
ally introduced by the inhabitants can be understood as attempts to
“reestablish the dimension of ‘dream’ advocated by Bachelard in dwell-
ing.” See Berhardt. Le Corbusier et le projet de la modernité: La rupture avec
l’intériorité (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2002), 105.
208
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
209
architecture, critique, ideology
210
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
211
architecture, critique, ideology
212
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
for the first time, as a name for places saturated with objects that
provide direction and centrality, ranging from the minute size
of the hand to entire urban structures and landscapes, between
which there is a continuity that architecture has to respect, al-
low to spring forth, and eventually concretize through its own
artifacts.
Otero-Pailos provides a detailed analysis of how this con-
clusion is conveyed to the reader by means of a visual imagery,
which gives a persuasive visibility to an order assumed to it-
self be derived from an invisible essence. Composing his books
both as textual and photographic essays, Norberg-Schulz gave
the final words to the images that provided the synthesis of the
argument, but as such they were deprived of context, so that
textual and visual rhetoric supplemented each other’s lack. As
Otero-Pailos notes, there is something deeply paradoxical in
this photographic strategy, given Norberg-Schulz’s dependence
on Heidegger, for does not the latter’s analysis of how the world
become a “picture” (Bild) from Cartesian philosophy onward,
and even more so when combined with his later analysis of
modern technology as “framing” (Gestell), quite simply render
any claim that photography—together with cinema a specifi-
cally modern art form, whose profound impact on the aura, aes-
thetics, subjectivity, space-time, desire, fetishism, etc. has been
detailed by an infinity of theorists at least from Benjamin on-
ward—might be “aletheic” in the sense suggested by Norberg-
Schulz wholly impossible?
While such claims about the aletheic image are no doubt un-
tenable, and belong to a historically dated phase of art theory—
as Otero-Pailos rightly notes, it seems impossible to deny that
the interpretation of any such image is always mediated through
subjectivity as well as a set of historically specific conventions—
Norberg-Schulz’s issues with Heidegger perhaps lie elsewhere,
which is also where the conflicted heritage of phenomenology
213
architecture, critique, ideology
214
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
215
architecture, critique, ideology
216
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
This quest for origins was however always marked by the sus-
picion—perhaps even promise, at least in its later versions—that
it would be infinite. This was already the case in Husserl’s search
for the depths and recesses of experience, and his understanding
of transcendental subjectivity as necessarily embodied not just
in a physical side, but also in intersubjectivity and history; in
Heidegger, the quest for foundations is rejected in the early thir-
ties, and yet returns in constantly new guises, one of which un-
doubtedly would be mythologically tinted “Fourfold” (Geviert)
that organizes his understanding of world in the later texts, and
is operative throughout the interpretation of Trakl. The tension
between these two motifs, or better this tension between two
sides of the same motif, cannot be resolved, and in fact should
not be: it is constitutive of phenomenology as such, which is
why any appeal to it as a figure of philosophical authority to
be applied to another discipline necessarily involves a moment
of deception, and even more so when it is called upon to de-
liver a normative aesthetic agenda, as is undoubtedly the case in
Norberg-Schulz. This need obviously not be intended, rather it
belongs to the phenomenological tradition as such, and beyond
this undoubtedly to any philosophical tradition that eschews the
search for empty generalities and pursues the exchange with art-
works at the kind of depth where the issue is their truth, their ca-
pacity to reveal something hitherto unknown to thought, which
is why it can be taken neither as an objection nor as a defense of
phenomenology (or any other philosophical tradition), only as
a constant temptation that must be accounted for.
For Kenneth Frampton, the last case studied by Otero-
217
architecture, critique, ideology
Pailos, these issues have become key elements for reflection, and
the necessity of a historical meditation inherent in any ground-
ing can be taken as the pivotal theme of his mature theory of
critical regionalism and tectonics. The notion of experience, or
“experiential surplus,” here functions as the guiding thread, and
Otero-Pailos follows it through Frampton’s early engagement
with Art and Crafts ideals, and traces the sustained importance
he gives to manual labor and practice throughout his work, for a
long time conceptualized under the rubric of “constructivism,”
until it eventually ushered in the vocabulary of critical regional-
ism and tectonics from the early eighties onward.
For Frampton too, the power of the image was important,
which he developed during his year as en editor of Architectural
Design (1962–65). But instead then seeking for “aletheic” imag-
es that would disclose a hidden topology, Frampton’s editorial
strategy, strongly influenced by Ernesto Rogers’s Casabella,50
was to use images to convey detailing, tactility, and material-
ity, which remain key term in his later work that often posi-
tions itself in opposition not only to the conventions of archi-
tecture photography as such, but also and more generally to the
consumption of works through images and “information” that
in turn feeds a particular kind of photogenic architecture. But
rather than a general rejection of the image, Frampton’s propos-
al was that these graphic techniques could themselves become a
way to achieve a surplus experience, which is what transforms
mere building into architecture, i.e., takes us out of the sphere
of pure necessity into the space of freedom and reflection, and
Otero-Pailos shows how this theme emerges in Frampton’s ear-
ly encounter with the works of Hannah Arendt, as well as his
50. Roger’s own writings, which Frampton did not notice at the time, were
in fact steeped in phenomenology, even though not in any technical
sense of the term. See for instance Rogers, “The Phenomenology of Eu-
ropean Architecture”, Daedalus Vol. 93, No. 1 (Winter, 1964): 358-372.
218
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
51. The Essex circle notably comprised Joseph Rykwert, Dalibor Vesely, and
Alberto Péréz-Gomez, all of which have produced eminently erudite
historical work. In this context the latter’s Architecture and the Crisis of
Modern Science (1983) must be mentioned, not least because it shows
that a phenomenological analysis of conceptual history in no way im-
plies an impressionistic treatment of historical documents and sources.
219
architecture, critique, ideology
220
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
221
architecture, critique, ideology
222
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
223
architecture, critique, ideology
224
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
225
architecture, critique, ideology
60. For a reading not unsympathetic to such claims, but that nevertheless
fundamentally problematizes the claim to truth, see Fritz Neumeyer,
“Tektonik: Das Schauspiel der Objektivität und die Wahrheit des
Architekturschauspiels,” in Kollhoff, Über Tektonik in der Baukunst.
Neumeyer shows that it is indeed the case that this truth is often an
“image” of truth, a rhetorical display of structural honesty, more than
organic relation between the demands of engineering and architectural
expressivity. Even more emphatically than Frampton he also notes the
extent to which the value of the tectonic, particularly in its constant
referencing of the phenomenological body as a source of meaning, can
only be defensive: its task is “not to once more make the disappearing
body appear, but to prevent it from completely disappearing” (59).
226
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
61. At the same time as these new means were tested in architecture, they
were being mischievously dismantled in the visual arts. Dan Graham’s
Homes for America (1966) is an obvious example, and even more so Rob-
ert Smithson’s early photo-text-essays; on Smithson, see chap 6, below.
227
architecture, critique, ideology
228
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
229
architecture, critique, ideology
230
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
231
architecture, critique, ideology
232
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
233
architecture, critique, ideology
234
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
235
architecture, critique, ideology
image of the loop, one must also bear in mind its acoustic result:
it eventually renders the elements that initially enter into it in-
discernible. In this sense, feedback and all of its kindred terms
(control, self-regulation)—and in this they belong to same or-
der as those features singled out by Jameson (collapse of depth
models, the waning of affect, history returning as pastiche)—are
phenomenal characteristics of the cultural logic of late capital-
ism, and they belong to its own self-image, to its appearance
(Schein in Hegel’s sense, which must not be conflated with mere
illusion; appearance is perfectly real, although not the all of the
real), but are equivocal and slippery when understood as ana-
lytic or epistemological tools.
Or, to put it as simply as possible, there is an imminent risk
that the analysis of the postmodern absorbs the features of its
objects so as to eventually merge with it, that it itself becomes
postmodern, which is no doubt a problem that any analysis that
wants to remain in the Marxist tradition (which surely applies to
Jameson) must face—it is a risk that one cannot avoid running,
if the analysis is to reach the same level of sophistication and
self-reflexivity, the same level of Hegel’s “cunning of reason,” as
its object, which is needed if there is to be a possibility of going
beyond or break away from it. Martin’s vocabulary retreats from
the affirmative Beyond, instead his attention to the recurrence
and return of ghosts of utopia, to the way in which all carefully
sealed and safeguarded disciplinary insides just as insistently as
unconsciously produce their own outsides, testifies to the need
to find a different exit, one that remains faithful to a kind of im-
manence, both practically and theoretically. That network are
never closed, but always contain moments of reversal, and that
the topology of globalization is never a simple extension out-
wards, from center to periphery, but that every inclusion also
excludes, is both a threatening No way out and a promise of a
return that would not simply present us with ghosts.
236
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
64. For the emergence of the category “space,” see chap. 3, above.
237
architecture, critique, ideology
238
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
66. Martin here draws on Louis Marin, Utopiques: Jeux d’espaces (1973) and
Fredric Jameson, Archaeologies of the Future: The Desire Called Utopia and
Other Science Fictions (2005). Curiously enough he here (as well as in the
reference to literature on utopia, UF 208 note) omits Françoise Choay’s
La règle et le modèle, which derives a systematic and specifically architec-
tural theory of utopia as a “model” on the basis of More, and follows its
ramifications up to early modernism. See also chap. 6, below
239
architecture, critique, ideology
some fifteen years later, Martin refuses to see these figures in terms
of an end, neither as the tragic endpoint of the avant-garde as in
Tafuri and Dal Co’s reading of Mies’s Seagram building,67 nor as
the triumphant fulfillment of liberalism, but as a mutation on
a different level, unwittingly captured by Fukuyama’s image of
the end of history as the “victory of the VCR.” What this im-
age signals, is rather a sense of history as reruns and bootleg cop-
ies, rewind and fast forward, which for architecture implies that
it is no longer faced with media from the outside, but has itself
become one of them and forms part of a continual modulation.
Tafuri’s assessment, “the war is over,”68 i.e., that the battles of
the avant-gardes no longer make any sense given their exhaustion
as possibilities for a radical change, is for Martin premature; in
fact it marks a moment of transition to a situation where Tafuri’s
“plan”—the project aiming to plan and control the future that af-
ter the 1929 crash was absorbed into the State-Capital complex,
depriving modernism of its founding illusion—gives way to a dif-
ferent kind of game, the two sides of which are the simulations of
nuclear war and risk, and Buckminster Fuller’s more benevolent
version in the World Game whose stake is the fate of “Spaceship
Earth.” Both of them play with “the very idea of the graspable”
(UG 34), and indicate the extent to which history is remodeled
as a permanent instability that calls for preemptive risk manage-
ment strategies and displaces the modernist utopias of form as a
blueprint for the future.
The famous reading of John Portman’s Westin Bonaventure
Hotel in downtown Los Angeles proposed by Jameson is thus
67. This interpretation, which suggests that Mies’s late work should be
understood in terms of silence and a withdrawal of language, has gener-
ated a long series of responses. For a discussion of the idea of silence as
negation, see chap. 1 above, and in more detail, my The Silences of Mies
(Stockholm: Axl Books, 2008).
68. See Tafuri, “The Ashes of Jefferson,” in The Sphere and the Labyrinth The
Sphere and the Labyrinth, trans. Pellegrino d’Acierno and Robert Con-
nolly (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990), 301.
240
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
only half of the story, and Martin proposes that the spatial
dislocation characteristic of late capitalism’s cultural logic on
another level gives way to integration in a flexible system of
pattern-based networks. As it is made visible in gridded surface
of the curtain wall, which can be taken as an epitome of post-
war corporate architecture’s remodeling (rather than betrayal)
of prewar modernism, the organizational complex, of which the
later postmodernism is a continuation and intensification, con-
stitutes an organicism, rather than a denaturalization and a dis-
enchantment of an earlier auratic experience; the aura that once
signaled the autonomy of art is neither falsely perpetuated nor
destroyed, as was once Benjamin’s alternative in the face of me-
chanical reproducibility, but dispersed and spread out on a sys-
temic level that operates by way of integration through images,
patterns, and a technique for handling stimuli and affects. As
such, this complex is equally a biopolitical machine, and it does
not work by substituting ornament for structure or image for
substance, as was initially argued in Venturi and Scott Brown’s
opposition between the duck and the shed, and then repeated
in countless analyses, but through a technology of organization
that makes all such oppositional terms ceaselessly trade places
in a “total flow” (Jameson) of modulation, which in turn is inte-
grated in a network of networks.
These shifts, Martin suggests, fundamentally depend on
the translation of all variables to an ecology or environment
of (proto)-linguistic unities, a concept that extends from the
natural to the political and the aesthetic, which is also how he
proposes to understand the third parameter of the postmodern,
Language. Once more referencing the Gray-White debate, which
opposed the proponents of autonomous form, purified of its
social mission, to those opting for a content derived from his-
tory or mass culture, Martin proposes that it “made no differ-
ence that one side spoke of semantics while the other spoke of
241
architecture, critique, ideology
69. Martin here draws on the polemic against Chomsky’s linguistic tree-
structure in Deleuze and Guattari’s Thousand Plateaus, which asserts that
language is fundamentally as transmission of slogans, but also orders or
“order-words” (mots d’ordre).
242
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
70. And in fact, already the shed-duck opposition is unstable on its own
terms. Martin here draws on the analyses of Aron Vinegar; see Vinegar
I Am A Monument: On Learning from Las Vegas (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT,
2008), 49–92, and chap. 2, above.
243
architecture, critique, ideology
244
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
245
architecture, critique, ideology
246
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
75. On Whyte and the Organ, see Martin, The Organizational Complex:
Architecture, Media, and Corporate Space (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 2003),
121.
247
architecture, critique, ideology
248
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
249
architecture, critique, ideology
77. The terms progetto and progettazione are highly polysemic in Tafuri, as
Martin notes, especially if one also looks at the earlier book Teorie e
storia, and it is doubtful that it can be reduced to something that would
be a mere “ideological phantasm” (UG 149). See also chap. 1, above,
note 16.
78. Martin here comes close to what Deleuze has called the virtual, which
cuts through the divide between possible and real, and introduces
another sense of temporality. The absence of a reference to Deleuze
here is probably due to Martin’s implicit polemic against how he has
been appropriated in certain strands in contemporary architectural
theory, notably as a precursor of the digital. There is however no need
to restrict the relevance of Deleuze’s thought to this particular reading;
for more on this, see chap. 6 and 7, below.
250
4. The Recent Past of Postmodern Architecture
251
architecture, critique, ideology
79. Derrida develops this on the basis of a reading of Hamlet, of how the
ghost always requires a technical supplement, a material device in order
to appear at the very limit of appearing; see Derrida, Spectres de Marx
(Paris: Galilée, 1993), chap. 1.
252
the other while ascertaining an overarching order). Its utopian
gesture is not divisive but conciliatory, in attempting to provide
for as variegated architectural spectrum as possible—a multitude
of small utopias, which, as Martin note, however runs the risk of
wholly fragmenting all collective identities into so many private
spheres, neighborhoods, and gated communities.
The promise of a rethought postmodernism, thought
through to its innermost contradictions and beyond them, the
task of “learning to think the thought called Utopia once again”
(UG 179), is poised at the precise point of this reversal, where
the retreat into the interiority of Architecture would not take
us back to an illusory autonomy of forms, but perhaps to a differ-
ent form of autonomy that would restore architecture’s emancipa-
tory agency; a way of bringing together inside and outside that
would render them legible precisely in their contradiction, a cri-
tique of ideology that provides an agency to forms by allowing
them to signal their own incompletion, rather than presenting
them as a compensatory fantasy. The recent past, read in such
a way, would be not be consigned to a past offered up for an
analysis that scans its shortcomings in order to know better, but
rather constitute a recentness that impacts just as much on the
present by splitting it, estranging us from its simple thereness
and solidity.
5. Looping Ideology
255
architecture, critique, ideology
256
5. Looping Ideology
257
architecture, critique, ideology
258
5. Looping Ideology
and the OMA has gained such immense visibility also outside
the architecture world. The projects, writings, and books of
Koolhaas and OMA have succeeded in straddling the divide be-
tween theory and practice, sophisticated thinking and popular
culture, presumably because the sense of urgency they radiate,
and because of their refusal to take commonplaces for granted.
From the seventies onwards, he has ceaselessly asked the ques-
tion—which to many might seem to border on the senseless,
since it appears to defy the codes of intellectual responsibility as
such—why we perceive our present, our cities and architectures,
as lacking something, as imperfect, and why we expect architec-
ture to provide us with this missing thing that would once more
make the socius whole. In this there is an unmistakable affin-
ity to the reversal of inherited judgments undertaken by Robert
Venturi and Denise Scott Brown in the sixties and early seven-
ties, closely linked to the emergence of pop art, which was one
of the defining earlier moments when the culture of media and
electronic images came to disrupt the order and hierarchy of the
fine arts, including architecture.6 The idea of a transformed per-
ception of the architectural lowlands however no longer relates
to Las Vegas and the disdained commercial landscape around
Route 66, but to urban forms outside the Europe-America axis,
and it no longer defines itself in relation to the divide between
the modern and the postmodern, even though traces of this can
be mobilized for ironic purposes.7 The shift in perception pro-
posed here however only marginally thrives on formal ambigui-
ties of architectural language, and instead engages the multiva-
6. For the relation to Venturi, see Rem Koolhaas and OMA, Harvard
Design School Guide to Shopping (Cologne: Taschen, 2001), 590–617.
7. See, for instance the “Generic City,” in Koolhaas and OMA, S, M, L, XL
(New York: Monacelli Press, 1995): “The style of choice is postmodern,
and will always remain so. […] Instead of consciousness, as its original
inventors may have hoped, it creates a new unconscious. It is modern-
ization’s little helper.” (1262)
259
architecture, critique, ideology
260
5. Looping Ideology
261
architecture, critique, ideology
262
5. Looping Ideology
of People and Money (New York: New Press, 1998), and Territory, Author-
ity, Rights: From Medieval to Global Assemblages (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2006).
263
architecture, critique, ideology
reflect and express these processes, prying them apart and mak-
ing them into objects as well as moments of critical thought.
Inserting the building into a network structure, where it is no
longer solely a form that can be characterized by morphologically
based concepts drawn from the history of art or architecture (is it
still modernist, or postmodernist, or something else?), or simply
a reflection of external functions, but a conduit for information,
behavior, actions, and perceptions that works equally by way of
its material structure, the image quality that it projects, and the
abstract machine or diagram of power relations that it actualizes,
thus requires a different kind of theoretical approach. The ma-
teriality of architecture is in this sense only to a limited extent
equivalent to the matter that it contains, and if the technological
framing that enables matter to hold together in a particular con-
figuration pervades matter itself into its innermost fibers, the idea
of architecture as an art that in essence deals with gravity, with
matter as opacity, weight, and resistance, must be rethought.12 On
the other hand, this does not simply eradicate form, but pushes it
in a different direction, so that it comes be generated from a much
wider set of parameters, of which Koolhaas’s “informal” may one
important indication, as long as we don’t take it as simply a nega-
tion, but rather a way of taking form to the limit.
The founding work for any such analysis remains Beatriz
Colomina’s analysis of architecture as a mass medium, which
was instrumental in taking architectural history beyond its nor-
12. Hegel seems to have been the first to develop a systematic analysis of
gravity and opacity as the foundation of architecture, which is why it for
him is the first, but also lowest art form, destined to be superseded by
other forms that gradually detach themselves from matter and weight.
For a discussion of this, and of Hegelian motifs inform the nineteenth-
century discourse of tectonics, see my “Hegel and the Grounding of
Architecture,” in Michael Asgaard och Henrik Oxvig (eds.), The Para-
doxes of Appearing: Essays on Art, Architecture, and Philosophy (Baden: Lars
Müller Publishers, 2009).
264
5. Looping Ideology
265
architecture, critique, ideology
266
5. Looping Ideology
267
architecture, critique, ideology
268
5. Looping Ideology
20. See for instance the retrospective comments on Delirious New York,
where Koolhaas speaks of Manhattanism as a “divorce between appear-
ance and performance: it keeps the illusion of architecture intact, while
surrendering wholeheartedly to the needs of the metropolis. This archi-
tecture relates to the forces of the Grossstadt like a surfer to the waves.”
“Elegy for the Vacant Lot,” in S, M, L, XL, 937; see also “New York/
La Villette,” in OMA-Rem Koolhaas: Architecture 1970–1990, ed. Jacques
Lucan (New York: Princeton Architectural Press, 1991), 160. For the
non-cynical reading of “surfing” adopted here, see Jacques Lucan, “The
Architect of Modern Life,” in ibid, 37.
269
architecture, critique, ideology
21. “We are engaged,” Koolhaas says, “with an effort to support within
[China’s] current situation the forces that we think are progressive and
well-intentioned |…] We’ve given them a building that will allow them
to mutate.” Time Asia, May 2, 2004. To some extent the split between
these two agendas is due to the context of presentation, as we will see,
but it also corresponds to a deeper problem lodged within architectural
practice and theory as such. This problem is obviously not particular
to Koolhaas, although his projects tend to make it acutely visible in a
reflexive form, which is why he becomes an easy target for criticism, but
also the reason why, as the present essay argues, his work indeed consti-
tutes works in a qualified sense, and call upon, even demand, a response
not just from within the architectural profession.
22. These and the following quotes relating to the CCTV project are all
taken from one of OMA’s official websites, as accessed January 22,
2009. The same text, with small variations, can be found in Koolhaas,
Content (Cologne: Taschen, 2004).
270
5. Looping Ideology
271
architecture, critique, ideology
272
5. Looping Ideology
rial power, where we find the Forbidden City and Tien’an Men
Square, the building symbolically redraws the map of Chinese
power, by opposing itself to the old television center located
close to the centers of political administration. Built a Soviet
style in the early 1980s, the old building is a fairly anonymous
high-rise, heavily guarded and allowing for no public access, and
it can be taken as an epitome of all the qualities from which that
new leadership in China is attempting to move away.
On the level of imagery, the new CCTV building has a clear-
ly iconic status (the idea of an icon is also embraced by OMA,
who regularly use the term in their publicity). The iconic func-
tion also comes across in the way in which the building has
already long since been used in advertising, as a symbol for a
new Chinese modernity that is opening up towards a global
mediascape. On the local level, its impact can be measured by
its frequent present in cartoons, and it has come to form part
of common jokes, where it is compared to a pair of trousers.
But as a political brand, it must also unite several contradictory
features: the emphasis on openness and communication flows
must co-exist with an image of centrality and authority, above
all because of the role played by CCTV as a unifying mechanism
in Chinese media culture, This iconic quality can thus obviously
also meet with negative reactions, even a sense of fear, since the
building is sometimes understood as an image and embodiment
of governmental power and repression.
The role of the CCTV headquarters as a window to the
world is however just as insecure as its status in the quickly
changing domestic Chinese mediascape.25 There is at present
only one English-language channel being broadcast by CCTV,
25. For an analysis of the Chinese media system as it appeared in the initial
stages of the CCTV project, see Zhengrong Hu, “Towards the Public?
The Dilemma in Chinese Media Policy Change and Its Influential
Factors.” Research Paper, John F. Kennedy School of Government,
Harvard University, 2005.
273
architecture, critique, ideology
Inside/outside
The CCTV project picks up many formal characteristics from
Koolhaas’s previous works, some of which can be traced back
to his earliest works, the projects at the AA, The Berlin Wall as
Architecture (1972), and Exodus, or the Voluntary Prisoners of Ar-
chitecture (1972, together with Elia Zenghelis, Madelon Vries-
endorp, and Zoe Zenghelis), above all the idea of split between
274
5. Looping Ideology
26. Koolhaas, “Field Trip: A (A) Memoir (First and Last…),” in Koolhaas
and OMA, S, M, L, XL (New York: Monacelli Press, 1995), 22. The fol-
lowing quotes with page number are all drawn from the same text.
275
architecture, critique, ideology
276
5. Looping Ideology
277
architecture, critique, ideology
278
5. Looping Ideology
279
architecture, critique, ideology
280
5. Looping Ideology
281
architecture, critique, ideology
282
5. Looping Ideology
283
architecture, critique, ideology
284
5. Looping Ideology
285
architecture, critique, ideology
286
5. Looping Ideology
287
architecture, critique, ideology
43. Already in 1989, Koolhaas writes: “At the moment when the electronics
revolution seems about to melt all that is solid—to eliminate all neces-
sity for concentration and physical embodiment—it seems absurd to
imagine the ultimate library” (S, M, L XL, 606). For a discussion of the
other entries in the competition (which was won by Dominique Per-
rault), see Anthony Vidler, “Books in Space: Tradition and Transpar-
ency in the Bibliothèque de France,” Representations 42 (1993). Vidler
suggests that “Koolhaas’ mistake was to configure information under
the sign of translucency and shadowy obscurity; the politics of the mo-
ment insisted, and still insist, on the illusion that light and enlighten-
ment, transparency and openness, permeability and social democracy
are not only symbolized but also effected by glass” (131f). As we will
see, the play with transparency in the CCTV center takes this idea one
step further, and shows how transparency as such can be a means of
hiding, and how visibility can become a means of obscuring.
44. S, M, L XL, 616
288
5. Looping Ideology
289
architecture, critique, ideology
290
5. Looping Ideology
291
architecture, critique, ideology
292
5. Looping Ideology
293
architecture, critique, ideology
in its very structure, and perhaps it can even be said to enjoy its
symptom, in the sense that the particular joy that it produces is
always and necessarily entwined with fear, violence, and repres-
sion, also in a political sense, so that “beauty” becomes “directly
proportional to horror,” as in the case of the Berlin wall project.
The alternative between a reading that ultimately finds
compliance and submission, and one that sees a subversive and
emancipatory potential, is also reflected on a more straightfor-
ward level in a difference in the communicative strategies em-
ployed by OMA. In their various public appearances, they tend
to emphasize different things in the Western and the Chinese
context, so that the idea of openness seems be aimed at Western
intellectuals, whereas in China the technical complexity and the
sophisticated engineering solutions are highlighted. While un-
doubtedly an effect of the different intellectual and ideological
contexts of Chinese politics and a Western audience of archi-
tecture critics and intellectuals, this can also be taken as symp-
tomatic of a split in the role of the architect, of which Koolhaas
would be a paradigmatic case at the present moment: is he a
provider of high tech solutions and a seductive imagery that in
the end must accommodate themselves to the political order,50
or a producer of political or social visions that may have the
capacity to challenge this very order? On the one hand, the com-
plex publicity maneuvers of the OMA testify to the delicacy of
these issues, and to the limitations of architectural work. But
50. A significant amount of criticism has been leveled against the build-
ing from the point of view of engineering, most vocally in a speech at
Harvard University in March 2008 by Alfred Peng, who can be seen as
representative a more traditionally “official” view of architecture. This
stress on technological efficiency also comes across in Peng’s state-
ment that the architect has no responsibility for the organization of the
building in terms of social structures (interview conducted by Helena
Mattsson and the author in Beijing in November, 2008). The source
of this conflict is obviously two wholly different ideals of the architect,
where Peng and OMA can be located at the extremes of the spectrum.
294
on the other hand, the materialization of ideology is also the
becoming-physical of its contradictions, which allows us to read
the work precisely as a work in the emphatic sense, in the same
way that we read other works of art not just as passive reflec-
tions of an existing order, but as interventions, as resistance and
transformation.
The work of Koolhaas has been labeled as “postcontempo-
rary,”51 and maybe this term (which in Jameson’s case seems to
displace the idea of the “postmodern” in a somewhat obscure
manner) can provide us with a clue to the reading of this strange
work that is the CCTV headquarters. On the one hand it re-
mains sealed in the contradictions of the present moment, on
the other hand it points to a future that it projects, but also em-
balms already in advance, and in this sense it constitutes a point
of intersection between different times and histories, between
ideological masking and unmasking, which is what I have here
attempted to grasp in the term “allegory.” It makes our present
readable precisely by staging the conflicts inherent in any at-
tempt to grasp it.
297
architecture, critique, ideology
298
6. Imagining otherwise
299
architecture, critique, ideology
300
6. Imagining otherwise
301
architecture, critique, ideology
302
6. Imagining otherwise
303
architecture, critique, ideology
304
6. Imagining otherwise
Impasses
The concept of heterotopia plays a complex and even contradic-
tory role in Foucault’s early work, and some interpreters have
seen it as their task to restore order, either by constructing a sys-
tematic theory, or by criticizing what they perceive as Foucault’s
confusions.12 But perhaps what is needed is neither to dispel
the confusion by showing it to be a surface illusion that can
be corrected at a deeper level, nor to understand it as merely a
case of inconsistency, but rather to enter into the contradiction
as such, i.e., to see it as that which demands and even “gives”
something to think. As Deleuze suggests in his interpretation,
that Foucault’s trajectory leads him into a series of impasses is
not a sign of inconsistency, since these impasses are more like
Badiou, whose conception however is that of major and unprecedented
shifts in thought, and the event is for him unique and wholly extraordi-
nary, whereas Deleuze’s idea, which I think applies to Foucault as well,
is oriented towards taking hold of a different dimension of the ordinary.
I discuss these differences in more detail in my “Framing the Event,” in
Ingrid Gareis, Georg Schöllhammer, and Peter Weibel (eds.), Moments:
A History of Performance in 10 Acts (Karlsruhe: ZKM, 2013).
11. Molly Nesbit, “Light in Buffalo,” in Joseph Backstein, Daniel Birn-
baum, and Sven-Olov Wallenstein (eds.), Thinking Worlds: The Moscow
Conference on Philosophy, Politics, and Art (New York and Berlin: Stern-
berg Press, 2007), 108.
12. The systematizing tendency prevails in Edward Soja’s influential Third-
space: Journeys to Los Angeles and other Real-and-Imagined Places (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1996). For Soja, Foucault is part of a general “spatial turn” in
the humanities and social sciences, which for him also includes thinkers
as different and Benjamin and Heidegger, as well as many others, which
in the end renders the concept too fluid and imprecise.
305
architecture, critique, ideology
306
6. Imagining otherwise
see it as resulting from the matter of thought itself, from the dense
interplay of language and space that ties together the fabric of
the early works.
It is equally true that both versions of heterotopia, whose
relation Foucault curiously enough never discusses, as if they
would simply be a case of mere homonymy, are presented in
opposition to utopia, and can be understood as yet another case
of a critique of utopian thinking. Such an opposition would be
in line with Foucault’s later genealogy of knowledge and power,
which often implied a resistance toward what he felt to be the
all too facile themes of utopia and transcendence as they had
been bequeathed to us by a long tradition. But this resistance
is obviously a complex and delicate task; a counter-history, if
it is to generate possibilities for acting differently, and operate
as a strategic history of the present or an ontology of actual-
ity, also requires that we are able to free a virtual becoming, or
a becoming-virtual, inside the present in its relation to a past
that is no longer simply past, in relation to a future that is not
just an extension of the present. It calls upon us to release a
swarm of other pasts and futures that constitute a proliferation
of doubles, so as twist free from the historicist version of history
as a burden that enforces an already formed, and thus in a sense
past future upon us. In this sense we may take heterotopia as a
reformulation of utopia, or as attempt to excavate an untimely
moment inside utopia, for which the other, the heteron, at a cer-
his comments on Kant. The most systematic explication can be found in
Le gouvernement de soi et des autres: Cours au collège de France (1982–1983),
ed. Michel Senellart (Paris: Seuil, 2008). For a discussion of Foucault’s
shifting attitudes towards Kant, which extend from his translation of
and long preface to the Anthropology, to the last texts that in a certain
way takes him back to the initial problem, although now seen in much
more positive fashion, see my “Governance and Rebellion: Foucault as
a Reader of Kant and the Greeks”, Site 22–23 (2008). For investigations
of the temporal structure of Banham’s history, see Anthony Vidler,
Histories of the Immediate Present: Inventing Architectural Modernism (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: MIT, 2008).
307
architecture, critique, ideology
tain point appeared like a more apt term than the negative ou,
the negative “non-” of place in u-topia.
Such a counter-memory, in its attention to what has been
effectively said, to the specific dimension that Foucault tried to
circumscribe in the concept of “statement,”15 must thus not shut
us off from the space and time of actions—a foreclosure of prac-
tice that for many readers, if not for Foucault himself, seemed
like an unavoidable effect of the dispassionate and distanced
gaze of the archeologist. The work on the “order of discourse”
must also make it possible to interrupt a discourse that issues
orders that we are assumed to obey and accept. In Foucault’s lat-
er work, the many analyses of power and resistance, of processes
of subjectivation and the complex of governing that came to
the fore from the mid seventies onwards, obviously take on this
task. This also means that the earlier work in some sense may
be retroactively understood as an impasse that would trap us in
discourse as opposed to things, which would amount to a highly
sophisticated form of modern idealism, from which Foucault in
fact always sought to break away.
Tracing the concept of heterotopia in its relation to utopia
would be one way to see how these problems were already ger-
minating in the early texts, but also, in a certain sense, to un-
derstand the extent to which this impasse (if it is one) remains
valid even for us, today. To some extent this means that it would
be misleading to ask whether Foucault succeeded in undoing,
15. The statement (énoncé) which forms the proper object of archeology,
must be distinguished from the phrase, which relates to the depth of
the subject and is an object of interpretation, and the proposition, which
can be formalized and inserted into an axiomatic system. Whereas the
phrase is dialectical (one phrase represses another), and the proposi-
tion generates a typology (they form hierarchies and may include each
other), the statement belongs to a topology. The statement is essen-
tially “rare,” Foucault says, and should be related neither to the subject
nor the object, and the uncovering of such an autonomous dimension
is decisive for the archeological method. For an analysis of these three
levels, see Deleuze, Foucault, chap. 1.
308
6. Imagining otherwise
The quadrant
The idea of a systematic analysis of “other places,” what Fou-
cault not without a certain irony calls a “heterotopology”—for a
science, a logos of the topos of the other as a disruptive force, seems
paradoxical through and through—initially appeared in the first
of two radio talks broadcast in December 1966, “Les Héteroto-
pies” and “Le Corps utopique.” The two talks were part of a
series of radio shows entitled “Utopia and Literature,” and in
the first of these two brief excursions Foucault presents the basic
outlines of heterotopia as a spatial otherness. This would be fur-
ther developed in the public lecture from 1967 known under the
name “Des espaces autres,”16 which has become the principal
16. This text, which forms the basis for most discussions of heterotopia in
Foucault, for a long time remained unpublished. There was a partial trans-
lation into Italian as early as 1968, but the integral text was published
only in 1984, the year of Foucault’s death, when it translated into German
in the catalog to the Internationale Bauausstellung in Berlin, where it
could pick up obvious resonances from the particular status of the city as a
no-place between East and West. Since then is has been republished many
times. The French text can be found in Dits et écrits (Paris: Gallimard,
1994), vol. IV, 754f; trans. by Robin Hurley as “Different Spaces,” in Es-
sential Works, ed. Paul Rabinow and James D. Faubion (London: Penguin,
2001), vol. 2, 177ff. Henceforth cited as EW, with pagination.
309
architecture, critique, ideology
310
6. Imagining otherwise
17. In the first Critique Kant explicitly places the question of how the
faculty of thought itself is possible outside of the scope of transcenden-
tal philosophy (A xvi), since this would be either an empirical question,
or overstep the boundaries of what can be known and take us into the
sphere of the noumenal. Foucault’s project to uncover a dimension of
the a priori that at the same time would be historical in this sense con-
stitutes a kind of anti-Kantian (in appealing to empirical and historical
changes) Kantianism (in claiming to locate conditions of possibility for
empirical experience).
311
architecture, critique, ideology
radio talk and the public lecture), both of which seem to reject
utopia, although the meaning of the latter concept seems far
from unequivocal. We seem to be have entered into something
like a conceptual quadrant: in the first pair, heterotopia is op-
posed to utopia as real social space is opposed to the phenome-
nological dialectic of the lived body; in the second, it is opposed
to utopia as a radical experience of ungrounding is opposed to
the false security provided by myth and fabulation. What are we
to make of this constellation, this rapid succession of seemingly
incompatible statements presented in the space of less than a
year? In what sense, if at all, could they be taken as different as-
pects of the same investigation into the multidimensionality of
the topos? In order to grasp the dynamic of this enigmatic quad-
rant, we must look at the successive versions in more detail.
312
6. Imagining otherwise
18. Les mots et les choses, (Paris: Gallimard, 1966) 7; The Order of Things, trans.
Alan Sheridan (London: Routledge, 1989), xvi, Henceforth cited in the
text as MC with pagination (French/English).
313
architecture, critique, ideology
the other to irrupt inside the same, but in this it also renders
these otherwise fixed oppositions fluid and mobile, and makes
them available for archeological analysis.19
This experience of otherness is where Foucault finds the
point of entry to his own archeological project, i.e., the possibil-
ity to uncover a interstitial dimension that he would lie between
the basic codes of a culture that determine what can be under-
stood as “empirical,” and those scientific or philosophical theo-
ries that account for the existence of order in general. The idea
of a between introduces a certain ambiguity into the argument,
as if this dimension would both underlie and be juxtaposed to
the others. This is not incidental, and it already points ahead
to a crucial question that will at least be hinted at in the spatial
concept of heterotopia, i.e., if the epistemic rules do not them-
selves already presuppose some other form of ordering that can-
not be discursive, and if so, how these two moments are to be
articulated in relation to each other. The heterotopia created
in Borges, Foucault says, opens onto an archeological space, an
19. It is indeed true that this heterotopic non-place in Borges’s text still
bears a concrete geographical name: China, the mythical other, which
functions as “a precise region whose name alone constitutes for the
West a vast reservoir of utopias,” as Foucault remarks, whose “culture
is the most meticulous, the most rigidly ordered, the one most deaf to
temporal events,” and whose writing “does not reproduce the fugitive
flight of the voice in horizontal lines,” but rather “erects the motion-
less and still recognizable images of things themselves in vertical
columns”—all of which, in our “dreamworld,” makes China into the
“privileged site of space” (MC 10/xix). While undoubtedly part of an
Orientalist projection that designates the East as the other of the West,
and whose philosophical roots lead back to Leibniz and his fascination
for the kinship between non-phonetic writing and the idea of an uni-
versal characteristic, this also indicates the unavoidable link that binds
alls “others” to a “place,” indeed to an imaginary and ideological place:
see Leibniz, Discours sur la théologie naturelle des chinois, ed. Christian
Frémont (Paris: L’Herne, 1987). But it also points to an unavoidable
embodiment of the heterotopic, although it would be reductive to claim
that this makes heterotopia something purely imaginary. Accounting for
the necessary co-implication of these moves is one of Foucault’s major
problems, also beyond these particular texts from the 1960s.
314
6. Imagining otherwise
315
architecture, critique, ideology
20. For a brief and concise discussion of Bachelard’s theory of science, see
Domique Lecourt, L’épistémologie historique de Gaston Bachelard (Paris:
Vrin, 2002 [1967]). The essential difference is that the epistemological
break for Bachelard constitutes an object of science by severing it from
its “prehistory” in sensuous experience, whereas the break for Foucault
simply takes us from one discursive object to another, all located on
the same level. His constant resistance to the term “ideology” is rooted
in this, and the concept of savoir is intended to suspend the opposition
between science and ideology, a distinction that at the time was crucial
for Althusser’s use of Bachelard to establish an epistemological break in
Marx. These two readings of Bachelard developed in parallel, although
with diametrically opposed results.
316
6. Imagining otherwise
but on the other hand, when seen as a limit, it displays the cracks
and fissures that provide mobility to the historical conditions.
At this point, Foucault however seems more bent on rejecting
traditional solutions to the problem of change, and his propos-
als remain largely negative, in that they leave open a space for
transformation without determining it more precisely.
In this sense, the heterotopia that we encounter in the en-
cyclopedia of Borges would be the provisional name for this
site, the Outside, that from out of which thought emerges and
which opens the possibility of thinking the Other as the void
that always inhabits the Same. This heteros topos is neither dia-
lectically nor logically opposed to the topology of everyday lan-
guage, to its orders, categories, and linkages, but situated below
or in between them—to once more repeat the symptomatically
ambiguous formula that Foucault provides— so as to form the
condition of possibility of any stable signifying order, while si-
multaneously showing all such stability to be situated and local,
and thus, at the limit, always struck by a certain impossibility. It
is only on the basis of this non-ground, or of a ground that im-
mediately breaks open, that archeology can begin to articulate
itself as an experience in search of a subject and an object, and of
the tenuous and instable link that for a certain period will bind
them together.
Utopia as transcendence
As we have noted, the two versions of heterotopia given by
Foucault—the first pointing towards the abyssal condition of
language and classification, the second, to which I will return
in the next section, toward the spatial ordering of society—are
however as it were syncopated by the reappearance of utopia.
To be sure, the second radio talk from 1966 may be taken as a
reminiscence of older themes, or as a hesitation with respect to
the rejection of phenomenology and humanism in The Order of
317
architecture, critique, ideology
318
6. Imagining otherwise
319
architecture, critique, ideology
320
6. Imagining otherwise
321
architecture, critique, ideology
322
6. Imagining otherwise
Other spaces
If we now pass on to the second instance of heterotopia, pre-
sented in the public lecture from 1967, “Of Other Spaces,” we
immediately notice that it opens up a rather different perspec-
tive than the linguistic version offered in The Order of Things, but
also takes a route that at first seems opposed to the meditation
on the utopian body. Heterotopia now appears as connected to
323
architecture, critique, ideology
324
6. Imagining otherwise
from 1967, this theme is still only implicit, and while the analy-
sis of the way in which a given society orders its categories and
its social relations remains at a tentative and largely descriptive
level, it nevertheless engages a whole set of material and spatial
issues that would not reenter his work until much later.
The 1967 lecture begins by noting that if the nineteenth cen-
tury was obsessed with history and chronology, with the problem
of the originary and the derivative, today we imagine ourselves in
a space of simultaneity, of networks and interlinking. And when
structuralism acknowledges this, Foucault notes, this is not sim-
ply in terms of a negation of temporality and a predilection for
some frozen eternal order—which at the time were commonplace
accusations in the wake of the debate between Sartre and Lévi-
Strauss—but a way to rethink the interlacing of time, space, and
event, which is also how we might understand Foucault’s own
positive connection to structuralism, rather than in terms of the
strange idea that historical change would somehow be impossible
to understand, which was often ascribed to him.32
Space indeed has an entangled history of its own, and
Foucault parenthetically gives us a few hints of what such a his-
tory might look like, from the ancient and medieval hierarchy of
325
architecture, critique, ideology
33. Maybe such an intuition also lies behind Heidegger’s remark in one of
his last texts, when he, in the context of a discussion of how modern
technology transforms space, notes that the latter must be under-
stood on a pair with Goethe’s Urphänomen: it cannot be derived from
anything else, it is neither subjective nor objective, but precede this
alternative—and, he adds, this impossibility of reducing or turning away
from the phenomenon toward something else is what produces anxiety.
See Heidegger, “Die Kunst und der Raum” (1969), in Aus der Erfahrung
des Denkens, Gesamtausgabe vol. 13 (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann,
1983), 206. This brief essay was originally conceived in dialog with the
work of the Basque sculptor Eduardo Chilida; for discussions of this
encounter and Chilida’s work, see Otto Pöggeler, Bild und Technik (Mu-
nich: Fink, 2002), 225–31, and Andrew J. Mitchell, Heidegger Among the
Sculptors: Body, Space, and the Art of Dwelling (Stanford: Stanford Univer-
sity Press, 2010), 66–94, none of which however address the question of
anxiety.
326
6. Imagining otherwise
327
architecture, critique, ideology
328
6. Imagining otherwise
329
architecture, critique, ideology
Limits of heterotopia
The idea of heterotopia was early on picked up in a critique of
Foucault, proposed from a Marxist perspective by some of the
key figures in Venice School in the late 1970s. These polemics
tend to assume that Foucault not only wanted to reassess Marx-
ism, but in fact to simply discard its lessons in favor of an ideal-
ism that dissolves all material specificity of the social order. In
the collective volume Il dispositivo Foucault (1977, with contri-
butions from Franco Rella, Manfredo Tafuri, Georges Teyssot,
and Massimo Cacciari), Foucault’s conception of power was
scrutinized in a highly critical but ultimately misleading fash-
ion.35 But while it was misguided, the polemic can still be seen
as instructive, since it provides a negative relief against which
Foucault’s conception becomes clearer, and also because it ar-
ticulates parts of its polemic in terms of architectural issues.
In the introduction Franco Rella proposes an interpreta-
tion that sets the tone for the following discussions, in which
Foucault’s rejection of the juridical (prohibitive, negative) and
unitary concept of power leads to the idea that power would be
nothing but a plurality of dispositifs that attempt to “suture an
empty center,” something wholly “other,” a blank or a void in
being (DF 10 note).36 For Rella, Foucault’s understanding of
35. Il dispositivo Foucault (Venice: Cluva, 1977)). Henceforth cited as DF
with pagination.
36. In the following I will focus on the texts by Rella and Teyssot, which
are the most rewarding. Cacciari aligns himself with Rella’s claims, and
suggests that “The anarchical dispersal of power, understood simply as
disciplinary techniques, coexist with a fetishistic conception of power”
(DF 61), to the effect that Foucault’s analysis is claimed to ultimately
rest on “mystical-ideal” (62) dialectic between Unity and Multiplicity.
Tafuri’s contribution is strangely enough the most disappointing, since
one would have expected more: after a few interesting although tan-
gential remarks on the relation between word and image in The Order
of Things, he too succumbs to idea that power in Foucault would wholly
dispersed, ungraspable, even mystical. He ends up equating it with an
equally misguided interpretation of Derrida’s idea of dissemination: “a
kind of private game without rules whose social effects can be verified”
330
6. Imagining otherwise
331
architecture, critique, ideology
37. “It may be that Foucault only speaks so eloquently of power (and, let
us not forget this, in real and objective terms, as dispersed multiplici-
ties, but in terms that do not question the objective perspective he
assumes on them—an infinitesimal and pulverized power, but whose
reality principle is not put into question) because power is dead, and
not just irreparably dead through dispersal, but quite simply dissolved
in a way that still escapes us, dissolved through reversibility, by having
been annulled and hyperrealized in simulation.” Baudrillard, Oublier
Foucault (Paris: Galilée, 1977), 13. Immediately before this Baudrillard
also states, similarly to Rella, that “Foucault’s presentation is mirror of
those powers that de describes” (11). Rella inversely connects Foucault
to Baudrillard and the “nouveaux philosophes” (DF, 17, note 16).
332
6. Imagining otherwise
38. For a discussion that attempts to combine Foucault with Marx, see
Richard Marsden, The Nature of Capital: Marx after Foucault (London:
Routledge, 1999). In this reading, Marx explains the “why,” the struc-
tures that limit social action, but not the “how,” the mechanisms that
make these structures operative, whereas Foucault explains the “how”
of power mechanisms, but not the ultimate goals of disciplinary power.
While to some extent attractive, this solution however introduces pre-
cisely the crucial moment of teleology that Foucault rejects, and for him
the “why” will always be a shifting and unstable effect of the “how.”
333
architecture, critique, ideology
334
6. Imagining otherwise
335
architecture, critique, ideology
336
6. Imagining otherwise
337
architecture, critique, ideology
scribed in terms of the new experience they give rise to. And
furthermore, intentional re-creations of places may seem like a
resistance to the emptiness of universal placelessness, but are in
fact and integral part of global spatial system that works pre-
cisely by diversification, localization, and regionalization. The
various claims for the place made in art and architecture, frag-
mentary and contradictory as they are, cast a particular light on
this process.
In many respects, contemporary artistic practices, especially
in claiming to intervene into the fabric of everyday life and to
detach our perceptual and mental habits from an unquestioned
anchoring, aspire to release a heterotopic energy belonging both
to language and space, and particularly to the interstitial ele-
ment that articulates them upon each other. Foucault’s inclu-
sion of the museum as a heterochrony that accumulates past
time points to one aspect of this process, in which the horizon-
tal flow of events is folded back upon itself, twisted out of joint,
and laid out before us in order to be evaluated anew. The es-
tranged gaze on the contemporary moment made possible by
the museum and similar institutions of accumulation shows our
current practices in a different light, reveals the contingencies
and necessities that permeate them, and in this it also asks to
what extent we could do things otherwise.
The crucial issue seems to be to retrieve a sense of mobility,
of inventing a capacity for displacement that would not simply
congeal into objects of appreciation, but release a similar energy
in whoever encounters such events. And perhaps it is not coin-
cidental that the last example Foucault provides us with at the
end of the 1967 lecture on other spaces is the boat. It is presented
as the heterotopia par excellence that condenses all the ambiva-
lences of the preceding examples, and it is difficult not to recall
the glorious description of the Ship of Fools, at the outset of The
History of Madness, located at the moving frontier between inner
338
6. Imagining otherwise
339
architecture, critique, ideology
the world of real objects.47 From our vantage point, the produc-
tive link is however not to the status of late modernist paint-
ing, but to the emerging artistic practices in which the ideas of
site and space were radically transformed, precisely in terms
of a heterochrony and a heterotopy that overlays time, space,
and language in a new way. Locating them within Foucault’s
heterotopia-utopia quadrant will to be sure not provide them
with a general grid of intelligibility, but rather give rise to a set
or resonances, sometimes collapsing concepts into each other,
sometimes breaking them apart. In this, it remains faithful to
the idea of impasses that are not there to be surmounted, but
explored as that which gives thought mobility, pushes it ahead,
from one place to another.
47. For a discussion of these different readings of Manet, see Carole Talon-
Hugon, “Manet ou le désarroi du spectateur,” in Maryvonne Saison
(ed.). Michel Foucault, La peinture de Manet (Paris: Seuil, 2004).
340
6. Imagining otherwise
341
architecture, critique, ideology
51. The same things could undoubtedly be said about Smithson’s most fa-
mous work, The Spiral Jetty. Here too the work can be accessed through
photographs, films, and texts, as well as through its physical manifesta-
tion. The latter has however come to overshadow the other dimensions
of the work, transforming the “elsewhere” into a physical difficulty of
actually getting to the site, or into a kind of ironic Fort-Da game because
of the sinking and rising of Great Salt Lake, which in certain periods
have made the work invisible.
52. Smithson, “Incidents of Mirror-Travel in the Yucatan,” The Collected
Writings, 132f.
342
6. Imagining otherwise
53. Cited from the reprint in Robert Smithson: Sculpture, ed. Robert Hobbs
(Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1981), 110.
54. For Smithson, the monuments of modernity are monuments of entropy
and decay, and upon closer inspection they prove be “ruins in reverse.”
See for instance the reading of minimalist sculpture in “Entropy and
the new Monuments” (1966) and “A Tour of the Monuments of Pas-
saic, New Jersey” (1967).
343
architecture, critique, ideology
344
6. Imagining otherwise
345
architecture, critique, ideology
346
6. Imagining otherwise
347
architecture, critique, ideology
348
6. Imagining otherwise
349
architecture, critique, ideology
350
6. Imagining otherwise
351
architecture, critique, ideology
352
6. Imagining otherwise
353
architecture, critique, ideology
74. Ibid.
354
6. Imagining otherwise
extend over more than a decade. If the Houses start off from the
isolation of syntactic features in order to attain a state of self-
reference that also lets the formal other, form’s otherness, irrupt
inside autonomy, the excavations take the opposite route and
present us with a formidable semantic profusion that overlays
systems of representation and draws on a vast array of literary,
scientific, and historical references, in order to attain a maxi-
mum density; the “palimpsest” is not by chance one of the re-
current concepts. Here, three of these works will be in focus: the
project for Cannaregio (1978), for Parc de la Villette (1985–86),
and for an art museum in Long Beach (1986).
In the Cannaregio project, three different forms of memory
traces are superimposed: the plan for hospital that Le Corbusier
had projected for the area; the writings and speculations of
Giordano Bruno, who resided in Venice in the 1590s, and was
burnt at the stakes in 1600; and finally a general reflection on
memory as such, which each in their respective ways produce a
temporal loop that Eisenman contrasts to the nostalgia for the
future in modernism, for the past in postmodernism, and for
the present in contextualism.75. Eisenman’s proposal consists of
three brief textual statements (“Three texts for Venice”), and
an overarching plan in which echoes of Le Corbusier’s hospital
and forms drawn from House 11 a are overlaid on the topogra-
phy of Cannaregio. The encounter between the first text, “The
Emptiness of the Future,” and the site generates a series of voids,
zones of absence that indicate the ghostly presence of Corbusier
and early modernism. The second text, “The Emptiness of
the Present,” produces a diagonal line across the plan, like a
cut that partly uncovers a deeper layer, partly activates the se-
ries of L-shapes drawn from House 11 a, all of which operate as
75. Eisenman, “Three texts for Venice”, in Jean-Louis Bédard (ed.), Cities of
Artificial Excavations: The Work of Peter Eisenman, 1978–1988 (Montreal:
Centre Canadien d’Architecture & Rizzoli, 1994), 47.
355
architecture, critique, ideology
356
6. Imagining otherwise
357
architecture, critique, ideology
358
6. Imagining otherwise
fied sense that would merit our interest. And when Bois takes
the opposite direction and reduces the narrative poetic that
gives these works their specific fragmentation to techniques for
achieving a “moiré effect”82 this transforms them into a version
of late modernist painting, which evacuates their claim to still
be works precisely at the limit of architecture, located in a par-
ticular tradition that they both question and affirm (and, one
might add, reduces them to a painting that at the time would
hardly have merited such extended exegetical efforts).
Beyond this alternative, and perhaps also as synthesis of
their respective claims, the reading of Michael Hays proposes
that these works are emblematic of the predicament of the late
avant-garde, precisely in amalgamating the acknowledgment of
the impact of history (or History, in an emphatic sense) and the
flattening of historical depth brought about by the universal rei-
fication brought about by late capitalism. What Eisenman does,
so Hays, is to inscribe these effects of loss, render them readable
and palpable, and so allow us to reflect on them in a critical way.
Neither a mere surrender to the collapse of objective spirit (the
Symbolic, in Hays’s Lacanian vocabulary), nor a flight into the
aesthetic pleasures of abstract forms, his work forms a last line
of resistance that upholds Architecture in the face of its immi-
nent impossibility, as it were oscillating between a negativity
that is still a determined negation of this world, this phase in
history, and an infinite negativity for which there is no more
determined content to be grasped.
The question might be put in slightly simpler terms, which
however soon enter into a vertiginous self-reflection: in what
sense can these artificial excavations lay claim to uncover some-
thing repressed, if this still excludes any access to a real that
would precede it? In an essay on the status of the rhetorical fig-
359
architecture, critique, ideology
ure, written one year after the Long Beach project, Eisenman,
with reference to the techniques of scalar displacement and su-
perposition, writes: “Because elements along each of these axes
are relocated, they began to also superpose on other elements
to reveal unexpected correspondences which in their former
reality would have remained unintelligible. What is revealed
from the initial superpositions cannot be predicted. These are
the so-called “repressed texts” that are found by reading these
new rhetorical figures [---] This repressed text is a fiction which
recognizes its own fictive condition. In its way, it begins to ac-
knowledge the fictional quality of reality and the real quality of
fiction.”83
Eisenman would sometimes speak of this fictive reality and/or
real fiction in terms borrowed from Derrida, as a “logic of
grafting,”84 where the grafted elements produce new and incal-
culable rhetorical effects that cannot be calculated in advance.
Time, narrative, and the history to be recreated are all results of
operations without any proper ground, and architecture’s mem-
ory is fabricated in the present so that whatever is preserved and
recollected is nothing but the result of a stratigraphic overlay
that modifies what is visible underneath as the sheets on top are
moved around—all of which would once more locate Eisenman’s
work at the third level of Miwon Kwon’s typology of sites, i.e.,
the discursive site that emerges from a superimposition of times
and spaces: a fiction in the sense of being made and produced,
rather than discovered.
And yet, as Kwon notes, there would still remain a question
to be asked: “What would it mean now to sustain the cultural
and historical specificity of a place (and self) that is neither a
83. Eisenman “Architecture and the Problem of the Rhetorical Figure,”
reprinted in Nesbitt, Theorizing a New Agenda, 180–81, my italics.
84. For Eisenman’s use of grafting, see Eisenman, “The End of the Classi-
cal: The End of the Beginning, the End of the End” (1984), reprinted in
Nesbitt, Theorizing a New Agenda.
360
simulacral pacifier nor a willful invention?” The answer she
gives draws on Kenneth Frampton’s idea of a necessary media-
tion between the local and the universal, and the necessity of
“a terrain between mobilization and specificity,” the “relational
specificity” that addresses “the differences of adjacencies and
distances between one thing, one person, one place, one thought,
one fragment next to another, rather than invoking equivalen-
cies via one thing after another.”85 To this Eisenman’s answer,
at it emerges from his artificial excavations, would probably be
that any such finding must be an invention, and to this extent
yet another fiction of a ground, no matter how shifting and un-
stable, to which we could return. To this one must however add
that fiction is not just simply what is imaginary in the sense
of unreal or contained in the space of mental interiority, but is
something made, and in this it draws along with it a whole com-
plex of spaces and times; it folds the heterotopias of language
and space together, and in tearing apart those inherited forms
in which “since the beginning of time, language has intersected
space,” it also renders possible a thinking otherwise, so that the
site as fiction is not just, and to the extent that we remain open
to its virtuality, not even primarily, a story of the depletion and
loss of forms, but of that which calls upon creation to be expe-
rienced.
1. For a collection of texts addressing this topic, and where the present
text was published in a first version, see Deborah Hauptmann and
Warren Neidich (eds.), Cognitive Architecture: From Bio-politics to Noo-
politics: Architecture & Mind in the Age of Communication & Information
(Rotterdam: 010, 2010). In media theory, the idea of vitalism has been
put forth most eloquently in the writings of Scott Lash, who extends
its genealogy back to Tarde, Bergson, and Simmel, and inscribes it in a
general movement towards a new philosophy of life; see Lash and Celia
Lury, Global Culture Industry (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007).
363
architecture, critique, ideology
364
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
365
architecture, critique, ideology
366
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
367
architecture, critique, ideology
From the vantage point of the present, we might say that the
problem of life was always there, and without attempting here to
undertake the massive task of tracing an encompassing genealogy
of Lebensphilosophie in the twentieth century,8 it can still be safely
conjectured that the relations to be traced between its past and
its current return would not obey the simple schema of repres-
sion and return, rejection and reappraisal, but would rather con-
stitute a set of complex retrievals and repetitions, bringing other
constellations of the past to bear on the present, and discovering
subterranean links between past moments where a congealed po-
lemic only perceived massive oppositions. Furthermore, the way
in which the concept of life re-enters the scene today, through
the works of Foucault, Deleuze, Agamben, and many others, is in
crucial respects conditioned by recent transformations in the life
sciences that have opened a set of new issues in ontology, politics,
ethics, and aesthetics, which in turn may incite us to re-read earli-
er positions as already engaging such questions as they appeared,
consciously or not, to the thinkers of the early twentieth century.
In relation to architecture and visual culture, the re-emer-
gence of themes from vitalist philosophy sometime seems to
be conditioned by a transformed understanding of the image.
Today, visual objects are increasingly understood as having an
agency of their own, a capacity to act on us in unforeseen ways.
This is undoubtedly on a more straightforward level due to their
sheer ubiquity. At what we can take as the historical limit of
classical critical theory, they were theorized under the rubric of
“simulacra,” a concept that still betrayed an unmistakable yet
368
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
369
architecture, critique, ideology
370
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
(and in fact, Lash and Lury place their investigations into the contem-
porary culture industry under the rubric “libidinal economy”). For
Lyotard, the idea of intensity was opposed to Hegelian dialectics and
its modern avatar in the critical theory of Adorno, and then to theory
in general, in what seems like a consciously self-defeating move, or
perhaps as in instance of a death drive inherent in theory as such, which
seems to be implied in some of his statements. For Lyotard’s initial
responses to Adorno, see my The Silences of Mies (Stockholm: Axl Books,
2008), 68–80. After these first and dismissive remarks, Adorno in fact
became an insistent if not always acknowledged presence in Lyotard’s
attempt to formulate a systematic aesthetic theory, and the renewed
attention to affectivity and “passibility” in his writings from the mid
eighties onward in many ways crosses my final proposal here. For a
discussion of Lyotard’s work in this respect, see Daniel Birnbaum and
Sven-Olov Wallenstein, Spacing Philosophy: Jean-François Lyotard and the
Philosophy of the Exhibition (forthcoming).
371
architecture, critique, ideology
372
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
373
architecture, critique, ideology
374
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
375
architecture, critique, ideology
there is large gap between 1976, the year of the first volume of
The History of Sexuality, and the subsequent two volumes on sex-
uality published shortly before his death in 1984—a long caesura
which was a time of reflection but probably also of crisis (the
“inability to cross the line,” of which Foucault speaks in the im-
portant preface to the second volume), that seemed to have end-
ed with the return to a modified reflection on subjectivity, eth-
ics, and freedom. Today however, this eight-year gap has been
filled with the published courses from the Collège de France,
and reading these texts we can see how Foucault already around
the time of the 1976 lectures series “Society Must Be Defended” in
fact began to re-orient himself in multiple and not necessarily
coherent ways. From this point onward he develops the idea of
a history of forms of governmentality, he works on the idea of
the technologies of the self and on the idea of candor and truth-
telling (parrhesia) in Greek and Roman texts, he returns to Kant
and the enlightenment, and claims to pursue the question of
modernity as a question of the “ontology of actuality,” in the
wake of Weber and the Frankfurt School—all of which can only
with great difficulty be brought together into a unified set of
problems that would amount to a distinct third phase. And it
is in this context that the idea of biopolitics emerges, sometime
between 1976 and 1977, and in Foucault’s own development it
in fact appears more like a transitional idea than a sustained
theme.
When the idea emerges in the first volume of The History of
Sexuality, it first seems like an extension of the analysis of dis-
cipline. Discipline and Punish had already pursued this in terms
of the inscription of the body into an institutional field: the
army, school, hospital, prison, etc., and this is where Foucault
could be said to undertake a kind of proto-architectural analy-
sis, most famously in the case of Jeremy Bentham’s Panopticon.
The investigation of disciplinary power had traced a transfor-
376
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
377
architecture, critique, ideology
378
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
develop the idea that the soul, or more precisely a certain in-
terpretation of the soul, constitutes the prison of the body, and
that we are not aware of what a liberated body might be capable
of outside of its relation to the soul understood in terms of its
Aristotelian form. As Spinoza famously writes in the Ethics: “in
fact, no one has been able determine what a body is capable of
(quid corpus possit), that is, experience has not yet enlightened us
as to what the body—to the extent that is not determined by the
soul—can or cannot do according to the laws of nature, if the lat-
ter is considered solely as corporeal.”19 But, Deleuze cautions us,
we should not understand this as a simple reversal that subjects
the soul to the body. Spinoza’s famous parallelism does not set-
tle for a mere inversion of the hierarchical schema, but instead
configures its parts into a new dynamic interrelation: “the body
surpasses the knowledge we have of it, just as thought surpasses the
consciousness we have of it,” and if the “model of the body, accord-
ing to Spinoza, does not imply any devaluing of thought in rela-
tion to extension,” it is because it, more importantly, “implies
a devaluation of consciousness in relation to thought: a discov-
ery of the unconscious, which is an unconscious of thought no less
profound than the unknown of the body.”20 This unconscious of
19. Spinoza, Ethics, Book III, Theorem 2, Remark. This capacity is crucially
linked to the idea of affects, which must be distinguished from psy-
chological states such as emotions. Affects are both confused ideas in
the mind and a corresponding increase or decrease in the body’s vital
force or power to act, its potentia agendi. As potentia, affect is both the
capacity to affect and to be affected; it is an openness to the world that
cannot be reduced to mere modifications of consciousness, instead our
conscious relation springs from a deeper affective level.
20. Deleuze, Spinoza: Philosophie pratique (Paris: Minuit, 1981), 29. The
theme of a “mere reversal” is a well-known leitmotif in Heidegger’s
reading of Nietzsche, and one of the main reasons why Nietzsche would
have been unable to escape Platonism, and Deleuze may be taken to
respond here to an objection of the Heideggerian kind. However, for
Deleuze, neither Spinoza nor Nietzsche can be understood as failed at-
tempts to step out of an epochal structure called “metaphysics”; they do
not announce, however imperfectly, its end or overcoming, but rather
perform transformations that can be picked up by us and developed in
379
architecture, critique, ideology
380
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
381
architecture, critique, ideology
382
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
383
architecture, critique, ideology
384
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
385
architecture, critique, ideology
25. This division between the bios and the mathema is emphasized by Alain
Badiou in his review of Deleuze’s Le Pli, in L’annuaire philosophique
(1988–1989), which is a much more nuanced confrontation that the
more known, although rather one-sided reading proposed in his De-
leuze: “La clameur de l’Être” (Paris: Hachette, 1997).
26. This is one of the basis claims in the first volume of Giorgio Agamben’s
Homo Sacer series. For a critical discussion of Agamben’s proposals, es-
pecially the sharp distinction between zoe (qualified life) and bios (mere
life in general), see Jacques Derrida, Séminaire: Le bête et le souverain, vol.
1 (2001–2002) (Paris: Galilée, 2008), 419ff.
386
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
387
architecture, critique, ideology
Vitalism, noopower,
and the philosophy of life
But while it is true that the ubiquitous references to Foucault
in most contemporary discussions of biopower and biopolitics
necessarily involve a highly selective reading, the relevance of a
philosophy of life, or more generally, of theoretical work that
takes the contested nature of the living being as its problem, can
not be settled simply by discussing the merits of various exegeti-
cal investigations of Foucault’s work, especially so given the in-
conclusive and tentative character of his last researches. Many
avenues of thought were left undeveloped as Foucault progress-
es, and some of them have been pursed by others, regardless of
whether this contradicts Foucault’s own trajectory or not.
As we have noted, in the first take on biopower, Foucault
suggested that in modernity life not only becomes the object of
a science that discovers that it has a history and a depth (evo-
lution), it also appears as a multiplicity that must be surveyed
and channeled, both on the level of the individual (sex) and the
collective (population). And as the other side of this new mode
of knowledge and power, there also emerges a life that resists, a
series of counter-definitions that extend at least from Nietzsche,
through pragmatism (James, Dewey), the ontologies of Bergson
and the sociology of Tarde, but also important strands of phe-
nomenology from Husserl through the early Heidegger and
Merleau-Ponty, and up to Deleuze. And indeed, many others
have, in parallel to Foucault or as an explicit transformation of
his work, understood this type of vitalism as his essential legacy.
388
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
389
architecture, critique, ideology
390
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
391
architecture, critique, ideology
392
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
certain way, this remains close to what Foucault said about early
liberalism: it is first and foremost not an ideology in the sense
of a false, distorted, or imaginary representation of reality, but
a new form of governing by affecting and channeling conducts,
i.e., a way to work with reality; liberalism does not simply pro-
vide us with an theoretical and/or ideological smoke-screen be-
hind which other and more real things (actions, practices, mate-
rial events) are taking place; instead, itself a practice, it is a way
to make certain things real by working with and intensifying,
tempering, or redirecting processes already underway in reality
itself. And furthermore, it even more acutely poses the problem
of resistance: where would we locate an outside that could be a
resource for experiencing, thinking, and acting in some other
way than those that are not even imposed on us, but emerge as
if out of our own most spontaneous preferences?
In a wider context, visual arts, architecture, advertising, and
media in general can be seen as part of the same process, whereby
our minds are governed (in the Foucauldian sense of “conduct of
conduct,” and not as repression or coercion) in order attain new
levels of action and reaction, and the noetic has in a sense that
by far transcends the traditional analysis of ideology become a
site of conflict, even of political struggle, at a level which extends
below that of human subjectivity and integrates consciousness in
a process of transformation which is neither nature nor culture.
This power and this politics would inscribe themselves on the
most fundamental level of mental life, at which our most basic
affects and ideas are organized, where memory, fantasy, and in-
telligence emerge, and which recently has come to be described
in terms of a certain “plasticity.”35 The connection to visual arts
the singular and yet forms a community), and, finally, aesthetics (to what
extent can this being-together be prefigured in works of art, without
becoming an already defined content that is enforced upon them).
35. For the philosophical idea of plasticity, which on the one hand has its
roots in Hegel, on the other hand in neuroscience, see the extended
393
architecture, critique, ideology
394
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
tions not just of skill and dexterity, but also of the Machiavellian
virtù, which in his time was largely (though no exclusively) the
prerogative of the prince, but today can be made into something
common: it is the capacity to seize the moment, to adjust to sit-
uations and shifts in the balance of power, in order to extract a
new force, even and perhaps even primarily, by extracting some-
thing from the opposing forces and turning them against them-
selves. Such a mutation should be understood as transcending
the sphere of art as well as politics on the inherited sense, and it
affects the very fabric of life, the underlying substructures of the
mind. The political challenges of such a shift are of course for-
midable: how should we conceive of an ethics or a politics, how
should we account for a possible formation of a possible ethi-
cal or political agency, when the “multitude” that it must orga-
nize and integrate—without reducing it into the all-too classical
form of a subject, individual or collective—extends beyond what
we normally circumscribe by the use of our inherited political
categories? Whether such a turning around, or stepping out—
“Exodus,” as Virno calls it—is the kind of radical shift that it
claims, or a mirage produced by the powerful logic of Capital
itself, as many of those who uphold the ethos of the traditional
Left have argued, remains to be seen.
395
architecture, critique, ideology
396
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
397
architecture, critique, ideology
398
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
399
architecture, critique, ideology
400
7. Noopolitics, Life, Architecture
401
architecture, critique, ideology
402
Tor Lindstrand, Proposal for Perth To what extent can the relation be-
(Entertainment Centre), (2012). tween the theory and practice of ar-
chitecture be understood as critical?
Instead of setting one against the
other, should we not instead linger
on the “and” that links them here,
which not only allows us to under-
stand their conjunction as a histori-
cally variable intersection, but also
highlights the idea of critique as an
activity that points towards a split-
ting and a division that shatters the
present, and renders not just the
future but even the past open? And
might not such a dissolution of a
conventional temporal axis provide
us access to a history that is, precise-
ly like the future, a space of possibil-
ities, in which critique and creation
continually call upon each other?