Frameworks and Principles Behind Our Moral Dispositions Lesson 2 Virtue Ethics
Frameworks and Principles Behind Our Moral Dispositions Lesson 2 Virtue Ethics
Frameworks and Principles Behind Our Moral Dispositions Lesson 2 Virtue Ethics
Part III
FRAMEWORKS AND PRINCIPLES
BEHIND OUR MORAL DISPOSITIONS
Lesson 2
VIRTUE ETHICS
Virtue Ethics is said to have started with the great philosophers Socrates, Plato
and Aristotle. In the medieval era, the Italian philosopher and theologian Thomas
Aquinas revived, enhanced and “Christianized” Greek Virtue Ethics.
VIRTUE ETHICS
Virtue Ethics is a moral philosophy that teaches that an action is right if it is an
action that a virtuous person would person in the same situation. A virtuous person is
someone who acts virtuously and people act virtuously of they possess and live the
virtues. A virtue is a moral character that an individual needs to live well.
Virtue Ethics emphasizes on developing good habits of character and avoiding
bad character traits or vices.
Virtue ethicists, such as Aristotle, hold that people live their lives trying to
develop their faculties to the fullest extent. Developing one’s moral capacity to the
fullest is pursuing ethical excellence, which is displayed by the virtues.
Basically, the virtues are the freely chosen character traits that people praise in
others. People praise them because:
- They are difficult to develop;
- They are corrective of natural deficiencies; and
- They are beneficial both to self and society.
A moral person is someone who develops the virtues and unfailingly displays
them over time. The ancient Greeks list four cardinal virtues: wisdom, courage,
moderation and justice. The Christian teaching, on the other hand, recommends faith,
hope and love.
Page 1 of 6
Notes in GE 5 – Ethics
ARISTOTLE’S ETHICS
At least two of Aristotle’s works specifically concern morality: the Eudemian
Ethics and the Nicomachean Ethics. The Nicomachean Ethics has been regarded as the
Ethics of Aristotle since the beginning of the Christian era.
Three general descriptions, which are interrelated, can be used to depict
Aristotle’s ethics.
Aristotle’s ethical system may be termed as “self-realizationism”. When
someone acts in line with his nature or end (“telos”) and thus realizes his full potential,
he does moral and will be happy.
Aristotle’s view is eudaimonistic. It focuses on happiness (eudaimonia), or the
good for man, and how to obtain it.
Aristotle’s moral philosophy is aretaic or virtue-based. Virtue ethics is interested
basically in what we should be – the character or the sort of person we should struggle
to become.
Aristotle’s “Telos”
‘Telos’ is an end or purpose. Aristotle believes that the essence or essential nature
of beings, including humans, lay not at their cause (or beginning) but at their end
(‘telos’).
Aristotle argues that rational beings can discover the ‘essences’ of things and that
a being’s essence is its potential fulfillment or ‘telos’. The essence or ‘telos’ of ‘human
being’ is rationality and, thus, a life of contemplation (Philosophy) is the best kind of life
for true human flourishing.
Aristotle believes in the excellence of philosophical contemplation and virtuous
actions stemming from virtuous persons.
Virtue as Habit
Aristotle’s idea of happiness should also be understood in the sense of human
flourishing. This flourishing is attained by the habitual practice of moral and
intellectual excellences, or virtues.
The function of human being consists in activities which manifest the best states
of his rational aspect, the virtues.
An action counts as virtuous, according to Aristotle, when a person holds oneself
in a stable equilibrium of the soul, in order to select the action knowingly and for its
own sake.
Page 2 of 6
Notes in GE 5 – Ethics
Moral virtue, for Aristotle, is the only practical road to effective action. The
virtuous person, who has good character, sees truly, judges rightly, and acts morally.
Page 5 of 6
Notes in GE 5 – Ethics
Being relatively complex but generally sensible, Thomistic ethics does not fall
into just one near contemporary category of moral theory. By not giving emphasis on
the result of actions in his so-called features of actions, we can say that he is more of a
deontologist. His basic tenet that actions must be directed to what is good somehow
relates his theory to utilitarianism and consequentialism in general. By advocating the
roles played by virtues in morality, Aquinas is a virtue ethicist. Aquinas’ doctrine of
natural law categorically discards wholesale particularism.
Because of his notion of the natural law, we can say that Aquinas is definitely
against some contemporary moral philosophies.
Thomistic ethics is comparatively applicable.
Unsurprisingly, we can find many similarities between Aquinas’ moral
philosophy and that of Augustine. Aquinas is more inclined to view earthly happiness
as also desirable, but insofar as those present goods are directed toward and
subordinated to the realization of everlasting ones in heaven.
Main Reference:
ETHICS: Principles of Ethical Behavior in Modern Society
by Jens Micah De Guzman et al.
Virtue Ethics, pages 93 – 111
Prepared by:
MICHAEL ANGELO F. EMPIZO
Saint Louis College, City of San Fernando, La Union
Solemnity of the Lord’s Ascension
May 24, 2020
Page 6 of 6