Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

20718997

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 11

Utopia and Reality in the Philosophy of Ernst Bloch

Author(s): ZE'EV LEVY


Source: Utopian Studies, Vol. 1, No. 2 (1990), pp. 3-12
Published by: Penn State University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20718997 .
Accessed: 23/12/2010 12:28

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=psup. .

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Utopian
Studies.

http://www.jstor.org
Utopia and Reality in thePhilosophy of Ernst Bloch
ze'ev levy

1. "Urgrund" m? "Endziel."

Ernst Bloch was one of the most original and least dogmatic Marxist
thinkers of our time.1 In addition to the impact ofMarx, especially the early
writings, one can discern in his oeuvre salient influences of classical philos
ophy?Kant, Hegel, Schelling?as well as of Neo-platonism. In the latter
one also encounters many traces of Christian and Jewishmysticism. Bloch
met Jewishmystical trends in theZohar, themagnum opus of theKabbalah,
with which he became acquainted through the writings of Gershom
Scholem. All these different components gave birth to a world-view which
conceived of the Utopian endeavour as an elementary activity of the human
mind: yearning, anticipation and fantasy. In this sense he frequently spoke
about "dreams as wish-fulfillment" and "anticipatory consciousness"
(Prinzip II chs. 14, 21, 22), and viewed the world as a "laboratory of
possible good" ("laborat?rium possibilis salutis"), i.e. something that has
not yet been completely realized (T?binger 212-242). He thus strove to lay
"
down the "blueprints" ("Grundrisse alluding to Marx's famous first
draft of Capital) of a better world (Prinzip title of part IV). The world
comprises unlimited possibilities which have not yet been actualized. In this
consists the significance of utopia.
Bloch deduces his notion of utopia from his all-encompassing philo
sophical conception. Following Hegel, he conceives of reality as a
"mediation" between subject and object. The whole of being takes place
between two poles. One precedes the process of mediation; it is its
"primordial cause" ("Urgrund") which existed before the dichotomy of
subject and object, ofmatter and spirit (mind). The second pole is the "final
goal" ("Endziel"), the ultimate merger of subject and object. However,
what distinguishes Bloch as a philosopher is his almost prophetic vision
which is perpetually turned toward the future: the veritable act of creation
was not in the beginning but will occur at the end. This is the genuine mean
ing of "utopia" inBloch's thought, namely a typically religious experience,
although without God. This end he often designated as "Ultimum" i.e. the
embodiment of ultimate reality and ultimate meaning. Unlike the traditional
trend of philosophy, inaugurated by the Presocratics, and recently taken up
again by some thinkers in the aftermath of French structuralism (e.g. Michel
4 UTOPIAN STUDIES

Foucault), Bloch asserts that lifeand existence cannot be understood by the


question "where from?"; it is incumbent upon us to understand them by
asking "where to?" and "what for?" Leaning on the erstwhile Christian
theologian Marcion and his modern counterpart Adolf von Harnack, he
reaffirms their conclusion that, despite God's alleged intention ("And God
saw everything that He had made, and, behold, it was very good."
[Gen. 1:31]), the present world is nevertheless not yet the best and most
perfect world. It stillwaits for its forthcoming full redemption (Atheismus
236-242). (Bloch, of course, does not accept Marcion's and von Harnack's
apologetic principal thesis, that the New Testament is completely
independent of theOld Testament, and thatChristianity did not absorb any
influences from the ancient Jewish sources.)
Although Bloch's thought focuses on the "final goal," he does not
neglect the role of the "primordial cause." It also has itsproper place in his
concept of utopia. It ismotivated by a more or less hidden cosmic drive
which Bloch designates as "hunger," and counterposes to Freud's concept
of libido (Prinzip 71). There exists an essential difference between the two
concepts. Without gratification of the sexual drive, an individual will still
stay alive, whilst non-gratification of hunger leads to death. This "hunger,"
in thewide and metaphorical sense of Bloch, is a flagrant manifestation of
reality; it concerns the innermost essence of the subject as well as of the
object. Its full and adequate satisfaction remains, however, for the time
being stilla matter of the future. But what isof the essence, forBloch, is that
there is already, at least inpotentia, the "possibility" (on this category see
below) to overcome this hunger.
This was undoubtedly one of themost startling conceptual intuitions of
the young Bloch: to describe the history of the world, or more exactly,
human history, as a totality that ought to be conceived and explicated by its
end (in the twofold sense of this word). What I mean here by "end" is,
obviously, not the "end" of all movement and development, but "end" as a
futurewhich opens up "endless" new possibilities. This ismore or less the
core of Bloch's all-embracing philosophical system as he developed it
throughout the years, a historical-philosophical conception of the utopia as
a potential realization of the possible. This theme represents the nub of all
his inquiries, and attains itsgrandiose and most systematic crystallization in
his magnum opus, Das Prinzip Hoffnung.

2. The logical category of "possibility."


From all this, it follows that the logical category of "possibility" fulfils
a central role in Bloch's thought. The primordial hunger that activates the
(human) subject, puts before humanity two possibilities: desire or hope.
This is where the concept of utopia makes its entrance, because hope
appears in the beginning as something Utopian. Hope, indeed, expresses the
vision, or the foresight, of the possibility to realize something which is not
yet anywhere. This is the literalmeaning of theword "u-topia"?a nowhere
which can be reached inpotentia. What is ruled out a priori is impossible; it
Utopia and Reality 5

cannot even become an object of hope, and will never become a utopia. It
would be no more than an illusion or, to use a Freudian term, a delusion.
Hope, Bloch's principal notion, embodies "
the tendency and the tension
toward the future, toward the "Novum. In this sense he characterizes the
Utopian future as "dawn forwards" ("D?mmerung nach Vorw?rts")
(Prinzip 129). The singular characteristics are not yet bright because the sun
which radiates its lighton everything has not yet risen; it is stilldawn, but no
longer dark. The direction which one ought to follow is already visible. All
thismetaphorical rhetoric is intended to show that hope isnot merely a pro
jection of reason, a "mental creation" of human thought, but an expression
of what is reallypossible. This future possibility, which looks to us today as
a distant dream, is not simply a dream, but a "day-dream"; it results from
conscious thought. Bloch insists on the essential distinction between day
dreams and night-dreams. In line with Freud's interpretation, he charac
terizes night-dreams as the effects of unconscious and repressed desires and
drives, usually relating to one's own personal problems. Day-dreams, on the
other hand, represent a free "expedition" forwards, rich in fantasy, but this
' '
time the 'dreamer' is conscious. These dreams manifest the inclination4 'to
mend theworld" (Weltverbesserung"). (Perhaps Bloch borrowed this term
from theKabbalistic termTikkun Olam Dili) jlpift ? ) It isone of themany
metaphorical speculations which abound inBloch's philosophy. The result
is a very complicated system of relationships between subject, object, reality
and possibility.
Reality holds within itself the anticipation of a possible future. Bloch
was perhaps influenced on this issue by the Jewish philosopher Franz
Rosenzweig; in the twenties he belonged, with Erich Fromm amongst
others, to Rosenzweig's circle. Rosenzweig emphasized, in his Star of
Redemption, the idea (which he formulated in religious terms) that the
individual's task consists in transmittingGod's love of humanity to others.
But themain point to be underscored in this context is the following: accord
ing to Rosenzweig's argument, the redemption of theworld consists of the
transformation of the good, looming in the future, into a reality of the
present. Both philosophers conceive of true reality as the reality of some
thing imminent which, for the time being, is still absent but can come into
being. Only Bloch elaborated this idea explicitly. Rosenzweig" expressed itby
the Schellingian formula of (<Nicht-seiendes Sein, whilst Bloch preferred
the ontological category of "Noch-nicht-Sein" (T?binger 210 ff.). As an
objective possibility the future a
represents reality today. This is, according
to Bloch, the essence of utopia. But now he introduces another important
distinction: theoretical versus real possibility.
Theoretical possibility means that the object concerned is not yet
realizable. It is a possibility, but a theoretical one only, a sort of fantasy, of
longed-for dreams. It lacks a real relationship with existence or history. As
against this, real possibilities?without going here into the inherent logical
difficulty of this notion?exhibit a practical relation to the future. They are
concretely linked to the hoped-for utopia. In this case utopia is no empty,
merely theoretical, possibility, but a very real one. As such it is not only
6 UTOPIAN STUDIES

edifying and convincing, but?this is the crux of thematter?it also displays


theways and means for its realization. Utopia is a striving toward the "real
possible,'' since present reality already contains the elements for itspossible
future changes (i.e. possibilities that do not exist in actu but are at hand in
potentia). Humanity's creative capacities which are still dormant can be
aroused and realized?this is implied by the idea of utopia. Utopias embody
these possibilities; therefore they play such an essential and decisive role in
human consciousness.
But now, suddenly, Bloch introduces one more surprising, unexpected
idea. The utopia is a real possibility, but itsessence consists in that, notwith
standing being anchored in the present as a "real possibility," it is at the
same time unconditioned. By this idea Bloch's outlook differs from that of
vulgar Marxism, though perhaps not so much fromMarx's thought. The
laws of social development, contrary to the simplistic and dogmatic versions
of Marxism, are not necessary in the same sense as natural laws. Let me
illustrate thispoint by an example which has been popular with dialecticians
sinceHegel. The seed already contains, as a real possibility, theplant, treeor
animal which will grow out of it or be born from it (it is irrelevant to our
problem that not every seed will bring forth fruit).What ought to be under
scored here is that nobody would define the tree which grows here as a
utopia. The very term is out of place here. In other words, what is condi
tioned (i.e. stems from predetermined conditions) cannot be included in
what Bloch calls utopia. It certainlywas not incidental that vulgar Marxism
denied the significance of utopia. According to its pseudo-"scientific"
conceptions, socialism would grow out of capitalism by necessity (although
revolutions are likely to accelerate the process), due to the "inevitable con
tradictions" between the forces and relations of production. This will
happen in the same way that capitalism evolved from feudalism. Such a
mechanistic view left no place for the concept of utopia. The proclaimed
ideal was, according to Engels' famous slogan, to transform socialism from
a "utopia into a science." Bloch, who repudiates this simplistic view, reha
bilitates at the same time the "lost face" of utopia. This implies a dialectical
process too: neither to conceive of utopia as a "theoretical possibility" (see
above), as preached by the pre-Marxist Utopian socialists; nor to adopt the
allegedly "scientific" antithesis, preached by traditional Marxism; but to
conceive of utopia as a synthesis that overcomes the regrettable onesided
ness of the two former versions. Utopia can become an objective and real
possibility only when it is not bound by predetermined conditions. Only an
unconditioned utopia can become a realizable utopia.
Bloch did not recant hisMarxist outlook; he intertwined into his world
view the two chief philosophical components of Marxism: dialectical and
historical materialism. He added, however, an original layer to each one of
them. In order to overcome theplatitudes of the vulgar versions of dialectical
materialism, he introduced the notion of "primordial hunger"
("Urhunger") which serves as a more or less natural motive ("agens"). It
remains questionable, however, whether this can be considered as an
ordinary materialist conception, as Bloch wishes to affirm. The notion of
Utopia and Reality 7

primordial hunger as a natural motive has sense only when it is directed


toward some end. But then it is no more a matter of nature but a human
affair. Vico (whom Marx held in high esteem) asserted that history differs
from nature because the first is performed by humans whilst the second is
not. Similarly, in order to overcome the platitudes of the vulgar versions of
historical materialism, Bloch added the central concept of his whole
philosophy, the concept of hope. Here again one encounters the religious
dimension of Bloch's Marxism, although it is an atheistic religiosity.
In this context it is also important to stress the following point. Bloch
conceives of utopia as some kind of merger between subject and object,
which impromptu reduces the problems of nature to human history: firstly,
to the yearning of romanticism for a better world; secondly, to themessianic
expectations which draw their inspiration from Jewish and Christian mysti
cism. Although he declares himself to be aMarxist, he presents his thoughts
in an entirely different garb to that of common Marxist reasoning. The
unusual force of his argumentation is also verymuch reinforced by his im
pressionistic and idiosyncratic manner of writing, which is quite unique in
contemporary philosophical and scientific literature. This evidently
engenders many difficulties for readers who wish to come to grips with his
philosophy, which often looks almost esoteric. He describes, for example,
utopia in a quasi-religious style as "the Kingdom of the children of God,"
borrowing the expression from Thomas M?nzer, the revolutionary
theologian of the Reformation (M?nzer). But he conceives of this
"Kingdom of the children of God" at the same time as the "realm of
freedom" ("Reich der Freiheit"), employing the renowned expression of
Marx. Then all exploitation of people by one another will disappear. He
therefore acclaims the Bible (including the New Testament), and in
particular the books of prophecy, as the first announcement of this great
futurewithout exploitation and oppression. This endows the Bible with its
unique significance amongst all the religious scriptures of humankind. (This
view perhaps expresses some kind of inadvertent ethnocentrism, but this is
irrelevant in the present context). When he draws inspiration from theBible,
Bloch is evidently less concerned with theGod of Job, who answers Job's
questions as a God of nature, than with Isaiah's God of justice. Only the
latter is a worthy source of authentic religiosity. The Bible is, therefore, not
to be considered as the particular property of the Jewish people, for its
humanist and universal message belongs to thewhole of humanity. In line
with his own philosophy, Bloch interprets the Bible, perhaps a little bit
arbitrarily, as the proclamation of a Utopian better world for all. The Bible
on the one hand, and the humanist principles ofMarx's theory on the other,
thus form together the two fundamental cornerstones of Bloch's Utopian
vision.
Freedom?the ultimate end of hope?is not an abstract, empty freedom
but a concrete, real freedom. This means that there is the possibility to reach
and realize it. Itwill be freedom from hunger and distress, from fear and
anxiety; at the same time itwill be the freedom to develop, without restraints,
the manifold inclinations, capabilities and potentialities concealed in
8 UTOPIAN STUDIES

humanity's inner being, which embody truly human nature. (Well-known


ideas fromMarx's work, including the early writings and theCritique of the
Gotha Programme, reverberate here.) The realisation of the true identityof
subject and object which Bloch tries to elaborate in his book on Hegel
(Subjekt), relies, therefore, on Marx's idea of humanisation of nature and
naturalisation of humanity. Naturalisation implies that people are capable
of achieving optimal fulfillment of their inherent human nature.
Unfortunately this still remains a utopia because until now such a reality has
nowhere come into existence. But it is a real possibility; it is unconditioned
and depends ultimately on free human activity.
Bloch inverts the traditional Marxist theory of knowledge. It is not
enough to reject the vulgar 'mirror' theory (which predominated inMarxist
thought for so long, triggered off mainly by Lenin's Materialism and
Empiriocriticism). Many Marxist thinkers had already done this before
Bloch. He, however, changed the very assignment of epistemology; no
'
longer dealing with cognition of the' 'become' ("Gewordenen "), but of the
"becoming" ("Werdenden"), focussing attention once more on the "not
yet." This opens up far-reaching opportunities for both epistemology and
ontology: the firstmanifests "anticipatory consciousness" (the titleof the
second part ofDas Prinzip Hoffnung) whilst the second is concerned with
"Noch-nicht-Sein" (T?binger 210). Bloch pursues the same idea, which
appeared for the first time in Schelling's later philosophy and which was
later taken up by Rosenzweig. Notwithstanding these striking influences,
one ought not, however, to overlook one decisive difference. Rosenzweig
distinguished, inhis Star of Redemption, between "nicht Sein"and "nicht
seiend Sein "(it is impossible to render this distinction intoEnglish), inorder
to accommodate the biblical conception of creation with his own
philosophy (whose three fundamental elements?God, world, humanity?
he apprehended as being completely distinct and independent from each
other). He was concerned with a theological problem, namely to explicate a
cosmic event of the past in linewith his own religious belief. Bloch, on the
other hand, although he was also fascinated by certain mystical and
messianic ideas, dealt with a philosophical problem, inorder to explicate a
foreseeable event of the future. But this too does not yet exhaust thewhole
difference. According to Rosenzweig "nicht seiend Sein" is a "Sein"
("being") which has not yet become "seiend" ("extant"). According to
Bloch "Noch-nicht-Sein" is a possible being; although not yet extant, its
possibility imposes on humanity, not on God, the urgent task to do every
thing to bring it into existence. Utopia thus embodies the good and the
commendable, which for the time being is stillwanting. It does not only
express the longed-for positive being which has not yet come into being, but
reflects and entails the negation of the negative being that prevails at
present. The famous dialectical concept of "negation of negation" which
has been so strongly jeopardized by dogmatic abuses and misinterpretations
sinceMarx and Hegel, thus recovers some of its erstwhile dignity. It helps
Bloch to give an adequate expression of the relationship between the idea of
utopia and true reality.
Utopia and Reality 9

What fascinates Bloch more than anything else is, perhaps, the follow
ing.He attempts to elucidate why people are attracted to something which is
not yet there.How can this strange phenomenon be accounted for?Why do
people engage in fantasies and day-dreams of this sort?What is the peculiar
drive that generates hope? Since thinking the possible has no limits, one can
always suppose and postulate new possibilities. There will always be
utopias. People will never cease to ponder over possibilities that are not yet
realities. Utopian yearning is an inseparable part of human consciousness.
This leads Bloch to the surprising conclusion that, in contradistinction to
customary belief, the true roots of utopia have to be looked for not in the
social tier but in the anthropological. It is the will?a will, based on
humanity's latent creative capabilities?to liberate oneself from one's
immediate factual surroundings, in order to create new "possibilities" such
as have not even been "dreamed" of. It belongs to the very concept of
utopia, not merely to predict new possibilities, but to discover those possi
bilities with which the present reality is pregnant (i.e. already comprehends
inpotentiel). By nursing them, people change the reality inwhich they live.
This is the "principle of hope" ("Das Prinzip Hoffnung"). Hope must
derive from something given, and at the same time imply an active attitude
to it. There ought to be a clear linkage between exposition of possibilities
and scientific investigation of such possibilities; thismust include ex tempore
ways for their realization.
This entails an interestingmutual relationship of the kind explored by
modal logic. Since the relevant possibilities for the improvement of the
human condition are necessary, they are indeed possible. In this connection
Bloch enlarges his earlier dichotomous distinction between "theoretically
possible" and "really possible," and speaks about four "layers of the
category possibility" (Prinzip 258-288):
1. The "formally possible": This is the naive optimistic position which
disregards the given reality; itbrings forth an abstract and irresponsible
idea of utopia. Moreover such a Utopian idea isno more than the thought
of one singular person. Such persons formulate the content and goals of
the Utopian idea as a corollary to theirnegation of the existing reality,but
do not take into consideration how to bring the new reality into being,
and by what means. They are also unaware of those possibilities of
change which, as we have seen, are already concealed in the existing
reality. For this reason all the famous classical utopias were doomed to
failure. Bloch devotes much space and attention to their analysis. They
came too early, and were therefore severed from the real possibilities of
the social reality of their time. Such was the predicament of Owen, Saint
Simon and Fourier, and before them, Thomas More, Bacon, Campanella
and the like.
2. The "cognitively possible" (259 ff.): This means reflecting on new prob
lems, as well as proposing new solutions. It leans on reason, but, like the
former position, remains stuck in the limited frame of subjectivity. It is
also still incapable of becoming a social programme.
10 UTOPIAN STUDIES

3. The "objectively possible" (264 ff.): This ismore or less the same as the
"theoretically possible" whose shortcomings Bloch had criticized.
Although it springs out of the social reality itself, it nevertheless lacks
practical usefulness because it restricts itself to theoretical aspects only.
4. The "dialectically possible" (271 ff.): As one would expect, this kind of
possible iswhat Bloch most cherishes inhis concept of utopia. It expresses
most strikingly the dialectical bond between the utopia which possesses a
firm relationship with reality and reflects its progress, and the utopia
which embodies human freedom. This means that it is unconditioned
(see above) and not subjected passively to objective reality.A propos,
this conception of the "dialectically possible" has been further
developed by the sociologist Zygmunt Baumann, who characterized
utopia as a group of "ideal possibilities"; its opposition to the existing
social reality exposes those possibilities which can be found there in
potentia. This sounds perhaps a little bit strange, but it engenders the
vision?Bloch would probably say "the hope"?of novel formations of
human reality.
The Utopian vision grows out of the present reality. It is not something
hovering over it. Itmanifests ideas which (can) function in the present, and
belongs therefore to the reality which it endeavours to transform. Bloch
infers from all this that no profound social changes can occur without
taking into account the significant role that the utopia fulfils as a guiding
visionary principle.

3. Utopia and Ideology.

There looms, however, another danger, namely that all the multiple
meanings bestowed upon the concept of utopia will leave it ultimately
without any fixed and definite meaning. If Imay use a current termof post
structuralist literarycriticism, the concept of utopia runs the risk of "decon
struction." Bloch tries to evade this danger by his "principle of hope."
Hope forms the link between theory and praxis. The fact that it judges the
existing reality critically demonstrates that hope always transcends the
existent. Otherwise itwould be useless as well as meaningless to hope for
anything. Everything would become hopeless. Exdefinitio, hope relates to
something which is still absent. So, by explicating utopia through the
concept of the possible, by establishing iton the principle of hope, and by
linking it to the future, Bloch distinguishes it from the concept of ideology.
This ought to prevent its devaluation. It seems, however, questionable
whether this intention, to remove the concept of utopia from the realm of
ideology, does not impair after all the proper understanding of ideology.
Bloch defines ideology, quite caustically, as themaid-servant of the ruling
class. He conserves Marx's idea of "ideological superstructure" but does so
in a much more simplistic form. According to his argument, utopias, unlike
ideologies, can never represent or serve a ruling class. Is this really the case?
Moreover, what happens on the other hand to a concept such as "socialist
ideology"? Would itbe no more than a meaningless contradict io inadjecto?
Utopia and Reality 11

Bloch is certainly right in saying that every ideology comprises certain forms
of deceit and falsity. It ismost often meant to conceal the true intentions of
its spokespersons. Ideology indeed turns, as shown very convincingly by
Roland Barthes, into a "myth." Itmight, nevertheless, stillmake some
sense to speak of a Utopian ideology. Bloch indeed does so. It should focus
on the humanly "possible"; it should also include the "principle of hope."
But such an ideology is, by Bloch's own criteria and definitions, not an
ideology but a utopia.
Perhaps this issue can be resolved in the following manner. Every single
Utopian category ought to be judged by the yardstick of criticism of ideology.
If after such a critical scrutinyof the utopia there remain substantial Utopian
components, it gains more value qua utopia. This would be no mere
"wishful thinking" or abstract expectation; itwould truly establish the
foundation of a concrete utopia ("Herausbringen" 186-191). Bloch did not
restricthimself to an analysis of Marxism as a critique of prevailing social
conditions and ideologies, supplementing it, as itwere, by some Utopian
surplus-value; he conceived of it as a realistic scrutiny of the future, based
on firm relations between theory and praxis (see above). This iswhat Bloch
calls "future-latency in the present" ("Zukunfts-Latenz inder Gegenwart")
which ipsofacto indicates a "future-tendency" ("Zukunfts-Tendenz"), i.e. a
real possibility (188). Instead of dealing with ideologies by categories, one
ought to treat categories without ideology (he had, of course, inmind the cate
gory of possibility). Then the utopia will represent a "pure Utopian surplus
without ideology" ("lauter utopischer ?berschuss ohne Ideologie") (189).
With regard to this last point, I should like, at the end of this article, to
venture another definition of the concept of ideology; this is to overcome its
simplistic identification with the interests of the ruling class, which regret
tably remains part of Bloch's analysis. It seems tome that the following
distinction between ideology and utopia is preferable. Utopia manifests the
programme of an ideal and perfect social order which does not yet exist any
where. This order differs substantially from the present existing reality.
Ideology, on the other hand, is a thought-system which does not necessarily
manifest or proffer a perfect social order. Therefore it can also serve the
existing social order. This does not contradict, however, the assumption that
there are ideologies which express the striving for a better world-order. After
all, as we have seen above, Bloch himself had no qualms about employing
the term "utopian ideology." Ideology as such is not to be condemned, for
itdepends on what it stands for.One could therefore recapitulate: utopia is
always struggling for the realization of the possible best; it ismotivated by
hope for the "optimum. "Ideology is something different; itcan fulfil three
different roles which must not all be disparaged:

1. A covert defense of the existing order and its ruling class. This isBloch's
conception of ideology.
2. A call for changes in the present order. This does not mean support of the
"ruling class" (I do not deal here with the question of towhat extent the
notion of a "ruling class" is still applicable).
12 UTOPIAN STUDIES

3. To strive for a better social order in the future, guaranteeing a dignified


life for all human beings.
This third role of ideology shares much with the concept of utopia. It
alone can be designated as44Utopian ideology." According to these criteria,
Plato's Republic could be apprehended as a utopia par excellence (it is again
of no concern in this context whether Plato's state ought to be also judged
critically for displaying totalitarian features, etc.). On the other hand,
Plato's last book, theLaws, which he wrote after his failure to realize his
blueprint in Sicily, could then be apprehended as some kind of ideological
platform. The simple identification of ideology with the defense of the
interests of the ruling class certainly cannot be upheld any more.

NOTES
1. A similar, though not identical, version of this article has appeared, inGerman, inBloch
Almanach 7. Ludwigshafen: Folge, 1987: 25-51, and, inHebrew, in the "Introduction" to
Ernst Bloch: Selected Writings. Tel-Aviv: Sifriat-Poalim, 1987: 5-29.

REFERENCES
Baumann, Zygmunt. Socialism, theActive Utopia. London: Allen and Un win, 1976.
Barthes, Roland. Mythologies. Paris: Seuil, 1957.
Bloch, Ernst. Atheismus im Christentum. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1968.
_Das Prinzip Hoffnung. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1959.
_"Herausbringen, unverf?lschtes Ordnen?Uber die M?glichkeit eines Systems,
aber eines Offenen." Der Mensch als geschichtliches Wesen?Festschrift f?r M. Land
mann. Ed. Klaus-J?rgen Grundner. Stuttgart: Klett, 1974.
_Subjekt-Objekt?Erl?uterungen zu Hegel. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1962.
_Thomas M?nzer als Theologe der Revolution. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1969.
_"Zur Ontologie des Noch-nicht-Seins." T?binger Einleitung in die Philosophie.
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970.

You might also like