Utz 2016 Music - Analysis PDF
Utz 2016 Music - Analysis PDF
Utz 2016 Music - Analysis PDF
12076
CHRISTIAN UTZ
[The copyright line for this article was changed on 12th October 2016 after original online
publication.]
Ex. 1 Lachenmann, Pression, first two systems in 1972 and 2012 versions. © 1972
by Musikverlage Hans Gerig, Köln, copyright assigned 1980 to Breitkopf & Härtel,
Wiesbaden.
studies (Utz 2013a and 2013b), which have already referenced recordings and
reconsidered earlier analyses of the piece.4 With regard to temporality or the
experience of time, this earlier analysis suggested the interaction of three different
sound-time archetypes, which shall be re-examined here for their impact on
performance practice.
59 60 180 181
saltando
116 117 118
13 14 15 343 346
[pppp]
Transformative/Processual Time
A model orientated towards real-time listening rather than towards the activation
of long-term memory might focus on what has been described as ‘categorical
transformation’ within and between ‘sound families’ in Lachenmann’s music
(Neuwirth 2008). The composer was clearly conscious of this idea when
composing Pression and the conceptually related string quartet Gran Torso
(1970–1, revised 1976 and 1988): he stated that in the quartet ‘pitch and noise
were not opposites, but constantly emerging from one another in different ways
as variants of superordinate sound categories’ (Lachenmann 1996d, p. 227).5
In almost all recordings the pressed-bow sound, which is supposed to suppress
any manifestation of pitch,6 actually retains elements of clearly decodable pitch
areas; conversely, the ‘distinct pitch section’ contains noise components, as the
D!3 here is actually split into two adjacent pitches, producing interfering beats
and thus noise components. The most relevant sound document in this respect is
Michael Bach’s 1991 studio recording, in which the pressed-bow section renders
a clearly audible D!2 which is further linked to other prominent occurrences of
D! in the piece (Fig. 2). Thus, the pressed-bow and distinct-pitch sections here
correspond closely, even though this might be the result more of coincidence
than of conscious planning; that ‘noise’ and ‘pitch’ do not function as opposites,
pressed bow (1–98) saltando (99–164) discrete pitch (165–280) coda (281–349)
86 87 116 117 118 180 181
13 14 15 59 60 261 262 343 346
D2 D3 D3 D3
however, also becomes obvious in other areas of Bach’s recording where the pitch
class of D! surfaces. This would suggest a perceptual approach that comprehends
Pression as a constant and audacious variation on D!, which is repeatedly distorted
and blurred but always resurfaces. This model can also be applied beyond the
domain of pitch: in fact, the entire piece might be perceived as a continuous
transformation within and between four large-scale areas (see again Fig. 2), each
dominated by a particular sound quality emerging from an amorphous ground:
pressed bow (crotchets 1–98), saltando (crotchets 99–164) and discrete pitch
(crotchets 165–280), with the fourth area (crotchets 281–349) leading the sound
back to a very remote and soft plane, recapitulating, echo-like, all three salient
sound qualities heard earlier, in the manner of a coda (Jahn 1988, pp. 44 and 51).
Processual time could probably best be communicated in performance by
presenting each sound event as part of a large transformative chain over
the duration of the entire work. One image that comes to mind is the
outworn metaphor of organic growth, which, though commonly rejected in
key areas of new-music discourse, still figures prominently in many performers’
conceptualization of time formation and rhetorical expressive gestures, although
it might be termed differently, for example as ‘synthesis’ (Rink 2002, p. 56).7 It
appears that a slow tempo and a minimisation of contrasts would be adequate to
enhance the often meticulously formed transitions between the different sound
fields of Pression.
Music Analysis published by Society for Music Analysis and John Wiley & Sons Ltd
5/1/1–5/3/9 body with the palm
Music Analysis,
[combined with] bowing on
tailpiece
3 8 165–179 15.3333 13.94 0.04 55–59 15.3333 13.94 0.03 – bowing behind/near the wood of
5/3/10–5/4/9 the bridge → bright noise
(Continued)
00/00 (2016)
Table 1 Continued
9 180–252 72.3333 65.76 0.18 60–83 71.3333 65.35 0.16 – bowing at ponticello; pressing the
6/1/1–6/4/19 thumb of the left hand against the
string; lifting thumb to create
pitched sound of open string →
flautando/pinching the string
between thumb and index finger
glissando al pont
variants of D!3 → unison;
11 269–281 12.8750 11.70 0.03 89–91 12.8750 11.70 0.03 – echo-like recapitulation of sec. 9
7/2/1–7/3/1 (string II, F3)
4 12 282–325 44.1250 42.11 0.10 92–106 44.1250 40.11 0.10 – sharp jerk (quasi whistle)/saltando;
7/3/2–8/2/6 fingertips along the strings (left
hand without bow)/legno
saltando/legno battuto [combined]
13 326–349 24.0000 22.82 0.06 107–116 30.0000 30.27 0.07 – fingertips along the strings;
8/2/7–8/3/15 plucking strings/buzzing
resonance by stopping strings with
wood of the bow; wiping with
wood of the bow; Bartók pizzicato
+ saltando
Total 349 390.95 1.00 363 407.18 1.00
*The sections in the 1972 version (published by Breitkopf & Härtel in 1980, HG 865) are indicated by page number/staff system/crotchet and by
consequentially numbered crotchets. The counting of crotchets follows the analysis in Jahn (1988, pp. 44–6), where the events 3/3/4 and 7/1/10 are counted
as only one crotchet each (in the second instance, Lachenmann actually notates a semibreve with fermata in the staff system but three crotchets in the
A PERFORMANCE-SENSITIVE APPROACH TO MORPHOSYNTACTIC ANALYSIS
‘timeline’). In one instance Jahn’s indications were corrected (the ‘bar’ 6/4/7–6/4/10 features four crotchets, but Jahn only counts three [crotchets 240–242];
possibly this is due to a printing error, because in the 2012 edition the analogous passage, bar 80, indeed features only three crotchets). The sections in the
2012 version (Edition Breitkopf 9221) have been indicated by bar numbers and beats. The durations in both versions have been calculated assuming an exact
13
minutes longer than the durations specified in the score versions. Although
statistically the deviations are fairly constant over the four main sections or fields
of the piece (both when compared to the score and among the performers),
a more detailed comparison of the durations of all thirteen subsections
(Fig. 4b) shows how strong the organisation of time differs among performers.
The centre of the pressed-bow section (subsection 4, crotchet 86), at least 60
seconds according to both versions of the score, ranges between 27 and 81
seconds (average: 58 seconds);12 the saltando section (subsection 6, crotchets
99–133), which requires particular care in performance (34 or 38 seconds,
according to the scores) and for which Mosch’s reflection about the additional
time required to produce the sounds may be most convincing, ranges between 37
and 59 seconds and on the majority of recordings is considerably greater than the
prescribed duration (average: 51 seconds); in the longest subsection of the piece,
the ‘morsing’ area (subsection 9, crotchets 180–255),13 which stages the slow
emancipation of pitch from noise, performers’ time also differs strongly (63–102
seconds; average: 81 seconds), although a third of the performances (five out
of fifteen) are faster than or almost equal (63–67 seconds) to the prescribed
duration (66/65 seconds), owing probably to the clearer rhythmic profile of this
subsection and the ternary metre alluded to in the 1972 version by dotted bar
lines.
A more qualified comparison is gained when the ratios of performers’
deviations from notated time are compared (Fig. 5). The deviation of the total
durations ranges between 6% (Stromberg’s 2013 recording) and 45% (Lessing’s
of 2005).14 What is more important, however, is the standard deviation among
the deviation ratios of the thirteen subsections for each performer (ranging
between 17% and 49%), which tells us how constant the overall tempo is kept
and to which degree the proportions between the sections of the score were
preserved in performance even where the chosen tempo is considerably slower
than that indicated. Considering both values, the recordings of Kasper in 2009,
Kooistra in 1992, Bach in 1989 and 1991, Grimmer in 1991 and Fels in 1995
emerge as the most consistent, though both Fels and Bach, in his 1989 recording,
deviate from the score considerably in terms of total duration.
Returning to the three domains of time experience derived from our
morphosyntactic analysis, we now may look at the degree of contrast between
the events and at the vividness with which the sounds’ individuality is rendered.
In a session of close listening I chose three recordings in which one of the time-
experience domains appears to predominate.
Spatialised Time
Michael Kasper’s 2009 recording definitely follows the score most literally in
terms both of duration and of performing ‘the right sound at the right time’.
The contrasts between the different sound qualities are clear-cut. This also
means that the sectional form is rendered quite transparent, for example by
Processual Time
In several instances Kasper’s performance seems a little too straightforward:
for example, in the long ‘morsing’ subsection (subsection 9), which slowly
introduces pitched sounds, he articulates distinct pitches without making audible
the laborious manner in which they are produced (the left thumb, muting the
bowed string from below, is temporarily removed, while the bow excites the
string very close to or on the bridge); this is consistent with the architectonic
model, which emphasises the boundary between noise and pitch. Michael Bach’s
1991 recording, by contrast, makes the technical difficulty of this passage clearly
audible: each ‘pitched’ tone sounds different, and each occupies a different
position on the gradual scale between noise and pitch. In many other respects,
as outlined earlier, Bach’s recording approaches the transformative time model:
it keeps the purely amorphous passages such as the first subsection rather short,
while prolonging the areas of transition (subsections 5, 7 and 11, as well as
subsection 13, the final one; see again Figs 4b and 5). His pressed sound is
exciting, always at the edge of rupture, but held together by the basic sonority
of D!.
Not unlike Kasper, Bach felt the need to issue a witty statement about his
performance of Pression in the CD booklet suggesting a desire to overcome the
composer’s somewhat conventional reference to a ‘traditional sequence of tension
and development’ (Bach 1992).15 This is clearly audible in the risk Bach takes
in producing each sound. However, the impression of a transformative thread
running through the entire performance prevails, not least owing to sensitive,
though not totally coherent, timing decisions.
Presentist Time
To my ear, two recordings best represent the idea of discontinuous presence:
Walter Grimmer’s of 1991 and Taco Kooistra’s from the following year.
Grimmer’s use of gut strings lends his performance the utmost intensity but
somehow greys out the overall timbre. Kooistra develops a similar intensity, and
his interpretation of the pressed-bow section is probably the most adventurous
and least ‘classicist’ of all the recordings. Strong contrasts and an irregular though
not exceptionally deviant timing may further contribute to the impression of
exclusive ‘moments’. This, however, is clearly incompatible with Kooistra’s own
comments about the work, which – like the composer’s – emphasise its classical
dimensions:
Of course, the listener has many additional options. She might choose to
focus on a single sound in the Kasper recording, losing herself in the individual
sound’s topology without following the piece’s architecture. Or she might listen
to Kooistra’s recording – probably in tune with the performer’s intention – as
a linear narrative. However, the substantial, even amazing differences between
the recordings should not be underestimated. What we hear in the recordings
of Pression is not one piece of music but fifteen different pieces.16 Arguably, this
is not due to the tabulature-like notation, since the individual sounds are, as
already observed by Mosch, rendered with a high degree of consistency in most
recordings. In fact, it seems that most performance effects contributing to the
different kinds of performed and experienced temporality discussed above are the
results of conscious decisions by the performers to communicate an inherent time
quality of the music, clearly aiming beyond a mere execution or reproduction of
the notation.
In any case, the composer might not be too happy with this discussion
of implicit temporal dimensions in his music. Although he has declared the
experience of presence as a ‘key utopia’ of his composing (Lachenmann 2003;
see Utz 2015), which led, among other things, to the composition of his late
orchestral piece NUN (‘Now’, 1999–2002), he is outspoken in his criticism of
attributed temporality in music:
Ex. 2 Xenakis, Nomos Alpha: score, bars 1–30, with sonic complexes marked and numbered events (after DeLio 1980, p. 79).
1 2 3 4
S2 S3 S1 S4
1
S6 S7 S5 8 S8
8 5 6 7
9 S5 S6 S8 S7
10 11 12
15
CHRISTIAN UTZ
S1
14 S2 15 S4
13
23
29 S3 16
Music Analysis published by Society for Music Analysis and John Wiley & Sons Ltd
00/00 (2016) Music Analysis,
A PERFORMANCE-SENSITIVE APPROACH TO MORPHOSYNTACTIC ANALYSIS 21
[T]hat which can be notated, demarcates the playable and thereby the unplayable.
The notation in the score renders legible that which is not audible and the
performance renders audible that which is not playable in the score. [ . . . ] Reading
and performance of the music is the art of tracing lines, punctuating, crossing and
Fig. 6a Xenakis, Nomos Alpha: comparison of six recordings (duration of events 1–16
= sections 1–2 / bars 1–30)
going beyond. [ . . . ] The bringing to life of sound. That is what matters. Its energy
and infinite difference. Between the strings and the bow, not unity but multiplicity.
Between body and sound, not the performance but a plurality of performances!
(Deforce 2011, pp. 6–7)
notation while also acknowledging ‘utopian’ elements in his scores that cannot
be rendered literally in performance:
‘My works are to be performed according to the score, in the required tempo, in
an accurate manner. [ . . . ] It is very difficult, but sometimes they succeed. I do
take into account the physical limitations of performers [ . . . ] but I also take into
account the fact that what is limitation today may not be so tomorrow. [ . . . ] In
order for the artist to master the technical requirements he has to master himself.
Technique is not only a question of muscles, but also of nerves. In music the
human body and the human brain can unite in a fantastic, immense harmony.
No other art demands or makes possible that totality. The artist can live during
a performance in an absolute way. He can be forceful and subtle, very complex
or very simple, he can use his brain to translate an instant into sound but he
can encompass the whole thing with it also. Why shouldn’t I give him the joy of
triumph – triumph that he can surpass his own capabilities?’ (Varga 1996, pp.
65–6)
1 2 3 4 5 6
7 8 9
10
12
A PERFORMANCE-SENSITIVE APPROACH TO MORPHOSYNTACTIC ANALYSIS
14 15
13
16 17 18
25
Fig. 8 Ferneyhough, Time and Motion Study II: beginning; events 1–18 (bars 1–9),
comparison of 3 recordings (durations)
obscure the performed actions to a considerable extent, leaving only very few
caesuras or regions of low density as large-scale ‘spatial’ markers. Thus neither
a large-scale architecture nor an isolation of ‘moments’ (despite the composer’s
insistence on discontinuity) seems to render an adequate analytical approach
here. The processual model, in contrast, seems in tune with the fact that the
electronics replay events that have already been performed, which contributes to
an impression of permanent transition.
Although it is extremely hard to isolate single events in this ‘stream of
consciousness’, the beginning and ending of the piece conform to their
conventional framing function by reducing complexity and putting the focus
on the cellist. Not unlike the beginning of Xenakis’s piece, the first nine bars
(according to my analysis) establish a series of eighteen contrasting events,
cued by salient attacks and impulses (Ex. 3). All three professional recordings
of the piece render the temporal and proportional order of these events with
remarkable consistency, considering the notational challenges involved (Fig.
8). The ‘extremely nervous’ character indicated in the beginning and obviously
anticipating the piece’s narrative of the ‘oppressed individual’ is arguably best
rendered in the most recent recording by Neil Heyde (2007) which keeps the
timing most consistent while (similarly to Strauch’s Xenakis recording) some
events are rendered rather hastily (event 18, for example, is virtually non-existent
in his performance, while both Taube’s 1977 recording and Gauwerky’s from
1988 focus on this event as a ‘cadential’ marker concluding the first section of
the work).
In a video documentary, Neil Heyde defends the composer’s notation, saying
that alternative solutions to score the sound events, such as semi-improvisational
indications on a time scale, would not ‘necessarily keep challenging’ him to work
harder; and he particularly highlights the ‘helpfulness’ of poetic instructions in
the score such as ‘sudden extremes of stillness and mobility, like certain reptiles
and insects (i.e., praying mantis)’. The composer supplements this by saying that
today’s ‘highly intelligent performers’ are no longer content to play ‘what is in
front of them or what someone else thinks is in front of them [ . . . ], entering into
this much more organic confrontation between [ . . . ] poetic imaginaries and the
practice of the music’ (Archbold, Heyde and Still 2007, 9:10–13:00).
Performing Time
The integration of quantitative and qualitative performance studies into
morphosyntactic analysis might be considered a promising field in current music
research so long as it avoids the one-sidedness potentially inherent in all the
subdisciplines involved: structural analysis, music psychology, historical and
empirical research, performance practice. A highly complex phenomenon such
as the performance and experience of musical temporality cannot be adequately
grasped by either of these subdisciplines alone but requires forms of mutual
1. On a basic level, the performer must decide whether to render the ‘time
of music’ as represented by the rhythmical-metrical structure of the piece
literally or whether elements of a rhetorical performance style should be
(consciously or spontaneously) incorporated even when this is not indicated
by tempo changes in the score: a general rubato, particular tempo decreases
to mark the beginning and/or end of phrases or sections, perhaps the
deliberate expansion or shortening of rests, and so on. It is evident that
these decisions are particularly dependent on larger and often historically
‘loaded’ performance traditions.
2. In cases where a performer decides not to observe a prescribed tempo,
should the ratios between events and sections be preserved and thus the
alternative tempo be kept more or less strictly throughout, or should tempo
changes that are not indicated be allowed or perhaps even emphasised in
order to render the impression of discontinuity?
3. Should the individuality of musical events in general be stressed by
attributing particular timing, timbre, dynamics or performance movements
to each event group or ‘sound family’, or should the performer aim to
minimise contrasts by understanding all individual events as parts of a
large transformation process?
4. What degree of precision should be devoted to the performance of events or
sections that are obviously (partly) ‘conceptual’ or (consciously) ‘utopian’?
Should precision of pitch/rhythm be superior or subordinate to the overall
temporal order?
that is still poorly documented and presents an obvious desideratum for future
research.
Seen from this angle, it is clear that all three discussed scores represent
the musical avant-garde’s criticism of unreflective performance practices very
decidedly, since they provoke the cellist to reconsider or even reinvent every single
movement and sound as well as the way they are communicated to an audience.
However, the case studies have also made it apparent that a prominent type of
convention in performance, which is aptly summarised if perhaps overgeneralised
in Cook’s term ‘rhetorical performance’, nevertheless remains vital to both
composers’ and performers’ imagination of sound time from the 1960s until
the present day. This is true not only for the widespread remnants of rhetorical
performance surviving in the narrower field of new-music performance practice,
but also for the idea, indebted to nineteenth-century aesthetics, that virtuosity
‘transcends’ musical experience beyond established perceptual constraints.
Working out performance-sensitive analyses thus should not lead to
misconceptions about a performance-related or perceptual methodological
positivism. To reduce musical experience to fragmentary real-time listening,
to the bodily experience of performed sound or to the energy produced during
performances would turn the necessary amendments which the performative
turn has made to established musicological practices into an impoverishment.
More than a decade ago Nicholas Cook postulated that musical works should
be regarded as both ‘frameworks for a performance culture’ and as ‘objects
of contemplation or critical reflection’ (2005, [para. 24]). The implications
of compositional structure on performance and perception cannot be limited
to what is performable or perceivable, since this would imply a normative
understanding of what can be performed or perceived (a criticism of the musical
avant-garde based on alleged ‘cognitive constraints’, as formulated in Lerdahl
1988, has been refuted so often and so convincingly that it seems unnecessary to
return to it here at length; see especially Cook 1999, pp. 241–5). It is the marked
impetus of liberation from established modes of perception and performance,
a trope deeply embedded in musical modernity, which the three works by
Lachenmann, Xenakis and Ferneyhough discussed above share. Their act- and
perception-oriented composing might be seen not so much as a naive adherence
to a modernist concept of technical progress, but as an insistent reminder that
our senses are acting and evolving within an unlimited universe of musical sound
time that composers, performers and listeners are constantly reconfiguring.
Name of performer, year recorded, publisher and year of release (where applicable),
total duration and URL of performance (where available)
a. Lachenmann, Pression
1. Werner Taube, 1971 (Edition RZ, 1990), 8′ 20′′
NOTES
This essay is an expanded version of a paper presented at the Eighth
European Conference on Music Analysis held in Leuven, Belgium, in
September 2014. I am grateful for advice received from Oscar Bandtlow,
Nicholas Cook, Ellen Fallowfield and Lukas Haselböck, and for financial
support for my research from the Austrian Science Fund (FWF): P 24069-
G21.
1. The method has been elaborated in a series of publications, including Utz
(2013a), (2013b), (2013c), (2014), (2015) and (forthcoming).
2. The first edition, originally published in 1972 by the editor Hans Gerig
(Cologne), was reissued by Breitkopf & Härtel in 1980 (HG 865); the
revised edition was published by Breitkopf & Härtel first as a handwritten
autograph dated ‘6. März 2010’ at the end of the score and ‘Juli 2010’
in the performance instructions (here marked as ‘preliminary version’),
then, in 2012, in a computer-engraved version (Edition Breitkopf 9221).
In terms of note values, the 2012 edition adds fourteen crotchets, resulting
in a total of 363 crotchets (see Table 1); in general, the musical structure is
preserved in the 2012 edition, including most fermatas and the few isolated
remarks referring to the temporal organisation. Detailed comparisons of
the different versions are provided in Orning (2012), Lessing (2013)
and particularly Orning (2013). My analysis will refer to the 1972
edition; events in the score are localised by crotchets, counted from
the beginning, following and slightly correcting the procedure in Jahn’s
analysis (1988, pp. 44–6 and Utz 2013b, p. 12 n. 4; see also Table 1).
References to the 2012 version are given in bar numbers (see also Orning
2013).
3. To date no detailed study introduces the compositional process which
resulted in Pression. Though Mosch has remarked on the systematic
treatment of performance techniques in this piece (2006, p. 28), all that
can been said so far is that Pression is not, like most other works from
this period, based on the complex post-serial systematic of Lachenmann’s
‘structural net’ (Strukturnetz) (see Cavallotti 2006, p. 79), a system first
developed during the early 1960s that the composer has since employed
continually.
4. Earlier analyses were published in Jahn (1988); Mosch (2006); Lessing
(2006), (2010) and (2013) and Neuwirth (2008). Performance is discussed
in detail in Mosch (2006), Lessing (2006 and 2010) and Orning (2012)
and (2013); Orning is a Norwegian scholar and cellist.
5. ‘Ton und Geräusch waren keine Gegensätze, sondern gingen als
Varianten übergeordneter Klangkategorien immer wieder auf andere Weise
auseinander hervor’ (Lachenmann 1996d, p. 227).
6. This intention cannot be directly inferred either from the score or from
Lachenmann’s comments on Pression, but it can be tentatively transferred
from remarks in the cello part of his string quartet Gran Torso (see Hilberg
1995).
of the score, as can be seen from, among other things, the technique of
damping the strings with the chin.
12. It has to be emphasised here that the three recordings in which this section
is surprisingly short (27, 36 and 37 seconds) are the three YouTube videos
included, two of which are semi-professional in nature (concert recordings
by advanced cello students). All other performances stay above 52 seconds
here.
13. Metaphorical descriptions of some sections in this piece are provided
in the performance instructions to the 2010/2012 version, including the
‘“Morse”-Section’, a term which probably originated in Jahn’s analysis,
where it is rendered for this section without comment (Jahn 1988, p. 43).
14. Stromberg cuts down the 60 seconds of the pressed-bow section to 37,
while Kasper expands it to 67; thus Kasper’s comes closest to the prescribed
duration of the score.
15. ‘It is not what is written down, marked out exactly in terms of its
sound realisation, and considered as sealed once and for all but those
natural, rather subcutaneous penetrations into the sound dimension which,
proceeding from the written aspect, are first realised in the process of
origination that may be understood [ . . . ] as an unexpected enrichment or
as a disturbing “contamination” and a misleading accessory feature. Viewed
in this way, no open contradiction to the score should be in evidence even if
Pression sounds differently each time it is performed, this in keeping with the
varying outer and inner conditions of reception or [ . . . ] the [ . . . ] intentions
[ . . . ] of an interpreter who aimed at the appearances necessarily resulting
from his activity and removed from his intentional sphere of influence.
[ . . . ] In fact, a clearly delineated Lachenmannian style has already
established itself and been documented today. We know how the composer
preheard his music and how it is to be performed. However, does not this
aspect of Lachenmannian performance convention, presenting itself here
in Pression [ . . . ] in a traditional sequence of tension and development,
express the cheerfully classicistic, the self-balancing, ironically historicizing
withdrawal of an originally more “expressionistic” mentality?’ (Bach
1992).
16. This observation takes up the conclusion of Lukas Haselböck’s paper
‘Troping Processes and Irony in Schubert’s Schöne Müllerin’, presented
at the 2014 EuroMAC Conference in Leuven in the same session at which
the author presented the paper on which this essay is based.
17. See the expansive analyses in DeLio (1980) and Peck (2003). The latter is
particularly relevant for our context because it considers the piece primarily
from the perspective of performance and perception. See also Harley
(2004), pp. 42–4.
18. The eight sound complexes are defined by Xenakis and also rendered in
graphic form (Xenakis 1992, pp. 222 and 232–3; see also DeLio 1980,
pp. 76–81 and Peck 2003, p. 88): (1) ataxic cloud of sound points; (2)
relatively ordered ascending or descending cloud of sound points; (3)
relatively ordered cloud of sound points, neither ascending nor descending;
(4) ionised atom represented on a cello by interferences, accompanied by
pizzicati; (5) ataxic field of sliding sounds; (6) relatively ordered ascending
or descending field of sliding sounds; (7) relatively ordered cloud of sliding
sounds, neither ascending nor descending and (8) atom represented on a
cello by interferences of a quasi unison.
19. See Peck (2003) and Berry (1989). The tautological character of Peck’s
suggestions is obvious; ‘introductory material should have a quality of
leading somewhere [ . . . ]; expository material should be deliberate and
obvious, and possess a certain stability. [ . . . O]ne should present closing
material with a sense of finality’ (Peck 2003, pp. 109–10).
20. Hughes reviews Xenakis’s Nomos Alpha attending to Emmanuel Levinas’s
discussion of this work in Otherwise than Being, arguing that Palm’s
recording successfully communicates ‘the particular sound of the moment,
rather than [ . . . ] the larger architecture of the composition’, owing to
the ‘energy of his performance’ and ‘his labored breathing’: ‘Palm gives
the listener an image of the cellist as absolutely committed, body and
soul, to this difficult and very physical piece; not passively absorbed but
rather utterly focused on the production of sound demanded by the score.
The sounds are so precise, so carefully played, and yet so surprising,
that Palm himself gives the impression of dwelling, like the listener,
fully in the particular sound of the moment, rather than in the larger
architecture of the composition’ (Hughes 2010, p. 204). Palm’s recording
is definitely very energetic but surely not ‘precise’, for it renders most
sounds in a rather chaotic and opaque way. (The first event, bars 1–
3, is omitted entirely from Palm’s recording.) Levinas exemplified the
Heidegger-indebted trope of a ‘vibration’ or ‘resonance’ of being/essence
by referencing Xenakis’s Nomos Alpha: ‘the strings and wood turn into
sonority. What is taking place? [ . . . ] The cello is a cello in the sonority that
vibrates in its strings and its wood [ . . . ] . The essence of the cello, a modality
of essence, is thus temporalized in the work’(quoted in Hughes 2010,
p. 116).
21. ‘Nomos Alpha is klankarchitectuur in beweging. Een muzikale ruimte waarin
structuren uitdijen tot indrukwekkende klankcomplexen en weer inkrimpen
tot de gebalde kracht van één toon’ (Deforce 2012, p. 82).
22. ‘[I]n measure 1–3 in Nomos Alpha, the metronome marking is for a half-
note = 75 MM. It is possible to play the sixteenth note pizzicati using
either a quasi-tremolo (as if for a mandolin) using one or two fingers of
the right hand, or by combining a pizzicato in the left and right hands. But
Xenakis stated he wanted the pizzicati in this section played in the normal
manner, with one finger, which makes these first three bars extremely
difficult, if not impossible to play at that speed’ (Saram 2010, p. 298).
Arne Deforce uses a ‘mandolin’ pizzicato in his 2010 recording of the
work.
23. ‘[A]t measure 4 and seq., the “fcl” (struck collegno) is at double the speed of
the articulations of the first three bars, as Xenakis asks for two articulations
to each sixteenth-note! This is clearly impossible with a normal legno battuto.
In order to realize such a passage, the cellist would need a bow notched with
closely ground “teeth” that would be drawn across the string for measures 4,
5, and 6. This could then possibly reach the speed of articulation required’
(Saram 2010, pp. 298–9).
24. See Iddon (2006), p. 96: ‘[T]he score for Time and Motion Study II expresses
more closely the gestures that a performer is expected to make to allow the
sounding result of the piece to come into being. This is foregrounded
most strongly in the performance directions for various sections, including
such instructions as “sudden extremes of stillness and mobility, like certain
reptiles and insects (i.e., praying mantis)”, “sharp and dry (the feel of
powdered glass between the fingers)” or “analytic but flexible: like a
sleepwalker’s dance . . . ”. Even without this, however, the absence of a
notation for the sounding result of the piece (with the exception of the final
page’s scordatura), or any indication of the sounds that should be heard
from the tape loops, suggests strongly that this is a score for performance,
rather than for listening. Moreover, the level of notational detail—up to
five separate staves of densely written material—plays a further part in
questioning notions of what constitutes an efficient performance.’
25. On the dissemination of this topos in the history of twentieth-century music,
see Utz (2014) and (2015).
REFERENCES
Alperson, Philip, 1980: ‘“Musical Time” and Music as an “Art of Time”’, Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 38/iv (1980), pp. 407–17.
Archbold, Paul; Heyde, Neil and Still, Colin, 2007: Brian Ferneyhough: Time and
Motion Study II: Electric Chair Music: a Documentary and Performance [DVD]
(London: Optic Nerve), https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=sykB4znEk2Q.
Bach, Michael, 1992: ‘Impression’, in Helmut Lachenmann: Chamber Music, CD
booklet, CPO 999 102-2.
Barry, Barbara R., 1990: Musical Time: the Sense of Order (Stuyvesant, NY:
Pendragon Press).
Berger, Karol, 2007: Bach’s Cycle, Mozart’s Arrow: an Essay on the Origins
of Musical Modernity (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California
Press).
Berry, Wallace, 1989: Musical Structure and Performance (New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press).
Bregman, Albert S., 1990: Auditory Scene Analysis: the Perceptual Organization of
Sound (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Cavallotti, Pietro, 2006: Differenzen: Poststrukturalistische Aspekte in der Musik
der 1980er Jahre am Beispiel von Helmut Lachenmann, Brian Ferneyhough und
Gérard Grisey (Schliengen: Argus).
Cook, Nicholas, 1999: ‘Analyzing Performance and Performing Analysis’, in
Nicholas Cook and Mark Everist (eds), Rethinking Music (Oxford: Oxford
University Press), pp. 239–61.
———, 2005: ‘Prompting Performance: Text, Script, and Analysis in
Bryn Harrison’s être-temps’, Music Theory Online, 11/i, http://www.
mtosmt.org/issues/mto.05.11.1/mto.05.11.1.cook.html.
———, 2011: ‘Off the Record: Performance, History, and Musical Logic’, in
Irène Deliège and Jane Davidson (eds), Music and the Mind: Essays in Honour
of John Sloboda (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 291–310.
———, 2013: Beyond the Score: Music as Performance (Oxford and New York:
Oxford University Press).
———, forthcoming: ‘Inventing Tradition: Webern’s Piano Variations in Early
Recordings’, Music Analysis, 36.
Crispin, Darla and Snyers, Kathleen (eds), 2009: Unfolding Time: Studies
in Temporality in Twentieth-Century Music (Leuven: Leuven University
Press).
Deforce, Arne, 2011: ‘The Art of Practicing’, in Iannis Xenakis: Nomos Alpha &
Omega: the Complete Works for Solo Cello ‘+1’, CD booklet, pp. 6–7, Aeon
AECD 1109.
———, 2012: Laborinth II: Denken als experiment: 472 ‘meditaties’ over de noodzaak
van het creatief denken en experimenteren in het uitvoeren van complexe muziek
van 1962 tot heden [Labyrinth II: Thinking as Experiment: 472 ‘Meditations’
on the Necessity of Creative Thinking in the Performance of Complex Music
from 1962 to Today], PhD diss., University of Leiden.
Deliège, Irène and Mélen, Marc, 1997: ‘Cue Abstraction in the Representation
of Musical Form’, in Irène Deliège and John Sloboda (eds), Perception
and Cognition of Music (Hove, East Sussex: Psychology Press), pp. 387–
412.
DeLio, Thomas, 1980: ‘Iannis Xenakis’ “Nomos Alpha”: the Dialectics of
Structure and Materials’, Journal of Music Theory, 24/i, pp. 63–95.
Feller, Ross, 1992: ‘Resistant Strains of Postmodernism: the Music of Helmut
Lachenmann and Brian Ferneyhough’, in Judy Lochhead and Joseph
Auner (eds), Postmodern Music/Postmodern Thought (New York: Routledge),
pp. 249–62.
Ferneyhough, Brian, 1998a: ‘Time and Motion Study II’ [1977], in James Boros
and Richart Toop (eds), Collected Writings, 2nd edn (Amsterdam: Harwood),
pp. 107–11.
———, 1998b: ‘Aspects of Notational and Compositional Practice’ [1978],
in James Boros and Richard Toop (eds), Collected Writings, 2nd edn
(Amsterdam: Harwood), pp. 2–13.
———, 1998c: ‘Unity Capsule: an Instant Diary’ [1980], in James Boros and
Richard Toop (eds), Collected Writings, 2nd edn (Amsterdam: Harwood), pp.
98–106.
———, 1998d: ‘Responses to a Questionnaire on “Complexity”’ [1990], in James
Boros and Richard Toop (eds), Collected Writings, 2nd edn (Amsterdam:
Harwood), pp. 66–71.
———, 1998e: ‘Shattering the Vessels of Received Wisdom: In Conversation
with James Boros’ [1990], in James Boros and Richard Toop (eds), Collected
Writings, 2nd edn (Amsterdam: Harwood), pp. 369–405.
Ferneyhough, Brian and Archbold, Paul, 2011: ‘Brian Ferneyhough in
Conversation with Paul Archbold’, in Paul Archbold, Performing Complexity:
a Pedagogical Resource Tracing the Arditti Quartet’s Preparations for the Première
of Brian Ferneyhoughʼs Sixth String Quartet (London: Kingston University
Press), http://itunes.apple.com/gb/itunes-u/arditti-quartet/id441504831.
Fitch, Lois, 2013: Brian Ferneyhough (Bristol: Intellect).
Furtwängler, Wilhelm, 1954: ‘Heinrich Schenker: Ein zeitgemäßes Problem’, in
Ton und Wort: Aufsätze und Vorträge 1918 bis 1954 (Wiesbaden: Brockhaus),
pp. 198–204.
Harley, James, 2004: Xenakis: His Life in Music (New York: Routledge).
Hilberg, Frank, 1995: ‘Probleme eines Komponierens mit Geräuschen: Aspekte
der Materialbehandlung bei Helmut Lachenmann’, Mitteilungen der Paul-
Sacher-Stiftung 8, pp. 25–30.
Hinrichsen, Hans-Joachim, 2011: ‘Kann Interpretation eine Geschichte
haben? Überlegungen zu einer Historik der Interpretationsforschung‘, in
Heinz von Loesch and Stefan Weinzierl (eds), Gemessene Interpretation:
Computergestützte Aufführungsanalyse im Kreuzverhör der Disziplinen (Schott:
Mainz), pp. 27–37.
Houben, Eva-Maria, 1992: Die Aufhebung der Zeit: zur Utopie unbegrenzter
Gegenwart in der Musik des 20. Jahrhunderts (Stuttgart: Steiner).
Hughes, Robert, 2010: Ethics, Aesthetics, and the Beyond of Language (Albany:
State University of New York Press).
Iddon, Martin, 2006: ‘On the Entropy Circuit: Brian Ferneyhough’s Time
and Motion Study II’, Contemporary Music Review, 25/i–ii (2006), pp. 93–
105.
Imberty, Michel, 1993: ‘How Do We Perceive Atonal Music? Suggestions for a
Theoretical Approach’, Contemporary Music Review, 9/i, pp. 325–37.
Jahn, Hans-Peter, 1988: ‘Pression: Einige Bemerkungen zur Komposition Helmut
Lachenmanns und zu den interpretationstechnischen Bedingungen’, in
Snyder, Bob, 2000: Music and Memory: an Introduction (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press).
Spitzer, Michael, 2004: Metaphor and Musical Thought (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press).
———, 2010: ‘Mapping the Human Heart: a Holistic Analysis of Fear in
Schubert’, Music Analysis, 29/i–iii, pp. 149–213.
Stockhausen, Karlheinz, 1960: ‘Momentform: Neue Beziehungen zwischen
Aufführungsdauer, Werkdauer und Moment’, in Texte zur Musik, Bd. 1,
Aufsätze 1952–1962 zur Theorie des Komponierens, ed. Dieter Schnebel
(Cologne: Du Mont, 1963), pp. 189–210.
Stravinsky, Igor, 1947: Poetics of Music in the Form of Six Lessons [1942]
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Utz, Christian, 2013a: ‘Erinnerte Gestalt und gebannter Augenblick: Zur
Analyse und Interpretation post-tonaler Musik als Wahrnehmungspraxis:
Klangorganisation und Zeiterfahrung bei Morton Feldman, Helmut
Lachenmann und Brian Ferneyhough’, in Jörn Peter Hiekel (ed.), Ans
Licht gebracht: Zur Interpretation neuer Musik heute (Mainz: Schott), pp. 40–
67.
———, 2013b: ‘“Liberating” Sound and Perception for the Interpretation
of Contemporary Music: Historical and Methodological Preconditions’,
in Christian Utz (ed.), Organized Sound: Sound and Perception in
Twentieth- and Twenty-First-Century Music (Saarbrücken: Pfau), pp. 11–
46.
———, 2013c: ‘Das zweifelnde Gehör: Erwartungssituationen als Module
im Rahmen einer performativen Analyse tonaler und post-tonaler
Musik’, Zeitschrift der Gesellschaft für Musiktheorie, 10/ii, pp. 225–57,
http://www.gmth.de/zeitschrift/artikel/720.aspx.
———, 2014: ‘Vom adäquaten zum performativen Hören: Diskurse zur
musikalischen Wahrnehmung als Präsenzerfahrung im 19. und 20.
Jahrhundert und Konsequenzen für die musikalische Analyse’, Acta
musicologica, 86/i, pp. 101–23.
———, 2015: ‘Paradoxien musikalischer Temporalität in der neueren
Musikgeschichte: Die Konstruktion von Klanggegenwart im Spätwerk
Bernd Alois Zimmermanns im Kontext der Präsenzästhetik bei Giacinto
Scelsi, György Ligeti, Morton Feldman und Helmut Lachenmann’, Die
Musikforschung, 68/i, 22–52.
———, forthcoming: Bewegungen im Klang-Zeit-Raum: Theorien und Geschichte
der Musikwahrnehmung im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert als Grundlagen einer
Analyse posttonaler Musik (Hildesheim: Olms).
Varga, Bálint András, 1996: Conversations with Iannis Xenakis (London: Faber
Music).
Xenakis, Iannis, 1992 [1955–65/1971]: Formalized Music: Thought and
Mathematics in Composition, rev. edn (Stuyvesant, NY: Pendragon).
ABSTRACT
The present article aims to develop an approach to musical meaning that
integrates performative dimensions systematically into a broadened concept of
analysis, connecting particularly to recent research into the temporal qualities
of musical perception. Taking three key works from the solo cello repertoire of
the 1960s and ’70s – Helmut Lachenmann’s Pression, Iannis Xenakis’s Nomos
Alpha and Brian Ferneyhough’s Time and Motion Study II – as a basic corpus of
study, this ‘morphosyntactic’ view of sound structure is complemented with a
comparison of different recordings of these three works by interpreting software-
based collections of data of timing and tempo as well as close listening, in
addition to documentation of the composers’ and performers’ conceptions
of time and tempo. The analyses propose an interaction of three different
categories of form-building time-space concepts that are deeply embedded in
the history of music theory and aesthetics: ‘spatial time’, ‘processual time’ and
‘presentist time’. Performers may shift between or merge these three archetypes
by varying temporal and dynamic consistency or contrast, among other means.
The performance-related data are compared with the perspectives of performers
and composers, corroborating the space of ‘informed intuition’ even in the
performance of these very prescriptively notated scores and demonstrating on
multiple levels the continuous impact of ‘rhetorical’ performance traditions
(despite or within their compositional deconstruction) in the music of the postwar
and contemporary avant-garde.