Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Notes On A Visual Philosophy by Agnes Denes: Hyperion, Volume I, Issue 3, October 2006

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 26

Notes on a Visual Philosophy

by Agnes Denes

Hyperion, Volume I, issue 3, October 2006


Notes

on a Visual

Philosophy

by Agnes Denes

1 H y p e r i o n— N o t e s o n a Vi s u a l Philosophy
INTRODUCTION

T here is little doubt that most of the readers of Hyperion will need no
introduction to Agnes Denes or her art. There is no doubt whatever that
those familiar with contemporary art are thoroughly acquainted with Denes
and with her inestimable accomplishments. One cannot be intimate with the
art of the second half of the twentieth century and not know, and not frequently
over the years have stood in awe of, the range, innovation, and intellectual
breadth of Denes’s work.

Yet, there is no reason to be remiss in observing here the achievements of


one of the leading artists of the present moment. Agnes Denes has been one
of the noted innovators in contemporary art over the past several decades,
and she has been and is one of the most prominent philosophical forces in the
field. Her work assembles a stunning array of intellectual disciplines and puts
them in service of an aesthetic ambition that challenges the viewer’s ability
to comprehend the depth of her learning and the power of her imaginative
transformation of her materials.

Throughout her career, Denes has reset the boundaries of artistic practice.
Consistently, she has been ahead of her time, and, in many areas, remains
to this day unrivalled among contemporary artists in her use of sophisticated
materials of imaginative thought. She is one of the earliest of the Conceptual
Artists, initiating many of the strategies that have become standard artistic
practice, and a pioneer of ecological art. She has been an innovator in the
use in art of serial imagery, linguistic analysis, and Deconstructive tactics,
and, perhaps above all, in the artistic approach to philosophical issues,
mathematics, and advanced theories of physical science.

Underlying this extraordinary range of intellectual endeavor is not only an


extraordinary mind but a coherent and unified intellectual objective. Denes’s
aim is to employ her art as an integrative methodology, to draw together,
or rather to demonstrate the inherent relationships among, the variety of
areas of advanced inquiry that she investigates and that otherwise remain
isolated in their self-defined fields of specialization. She takes art to be a
language of visual perception, a form of lingua franca capable of opening a
flow of information among what she terms “alien systems and disciplines.”
What makes such integration possible, and what innately subtends these
self-distinguishing areas of investigation, is a system of universal forms and
concepts. It is, for Denes, the business of art per se, and in particular of the
art she has striven throughout her career to create, to visualize such forms,
to dramatize them, and thereby to render a language for seeing the universal
concepts—a language of “pure form,” and thus a language of “pure meaning.”

Hyperion —Volume I, issue 3, October 200 6 2


Art is capable of creating a new philosophy and a “new type of logic,” a logic
of hidden patterns. It is a logic that makes art the central repository and
integration platform for science, philosophy, and mathematics, as well as
instinct, intellect, and the intuition—it is a logic that makes art the essential
form of inquiry into the nature of the world. Her work can be seen as a project
of aesthetic theorization, for as she has written, “Art is a reflection on life and
an analysis of its structure.”

Agnes Denes is as capable and compelling a writer as she is an artist, and


these propositions can be read in their full intricacy in the essay immediately
below. “Notes on a Visual Philosophy” serves as something of a statement
of purpose for Denes. It has long been out of print, and it serves here as the
first in a series of writings by Denes, either out of print or never previously
published, that Hyperion has the privilege of placing where they belong: into
the ongoing public discourse. We humbly thank Agnes Denes for permitting us
the distinction of publishing these materials.

—Mark Daniel Cohen

NOTES ON A VISUAL PHILOSOPHY

T he symmetries operating in my work are subtle and complex. Some


are more easily discernible than other, some operate on the surface
of perceptions on the visual level, others are deeply hidden in the ideas
and philosophies underlying my work. Whether obvious or subtle, visible or
elusive, these symmetries are inherent and real. The fact that they were never
consciously sought, since the work was not created with this goal in mind,
makes their presence even more exciting.

In mathematics symmetries are precise, well-defined operations such as


rotation, translation and inversion. In the sciences these operations are
applied to an idealized physical world where they abound, ranging from
bilateralism in people to celestial motion to time-reversible laws. Even broken
symmetry, so popular among physicists today, has precise meaning. Logic,
which manipulates concepts mathematically, has exact symmetries. In art and
music they appear on many levels serving esthetic functions.

In my work everything, including symmetry, is created through a conscious use


of instinct, intellect and intuitions. When I visualize (give form to) processes
such as math and logic, or when I apply X-ray technology and electron
microscopy to organic and crystal structures, one might say I reveal well-
defined symmetries and antisymmetries. When I deal with abstract concepts
definitions blur and the symmetries go beyond ordinary mathematical confines.
Some examples follow:

3 H y p e r i o n— N o t e s o n a Vi s u a l Philosophy
—Mapping the loss that occurs in communication, i.e. between
viewer and artist, between giver and receiver, between specific
meaning and symbol, between nations, epochs, systems and
universes.

—Mapping human parameters within the changing aspects


of reality, within the transformations and interactions of
phenomena.

—Working with the paradox, the contradictions of human


existence such as our illusions of freedom and the
inescapability of the system; our alienation in togetherness; the
individual human dilemma, struggle and pride versus the whole
human predicament; our importance or insignificance in the
universe.

—Trying to give form to invisible processes such as evolution,


changing human values, thought processes and time
aspects (pinpointing the moment growth becomes decay
in an organism: penetrating the “folds of time” to record its
“instants”).

—Finding contradictions and balances, pitting art against


existence, illusions versus reality, imagination versus fact,
chaos versus order, the moment versus eternity, universals
versus the self.

These symmetries are less available and definable but they are there
nevertheless, working on mysterious levels in the interactions of phenomena
and ideas. I may even venture to say that these unnamed, unmeasured
symmetries operating in the network of concepts are the anatomy or
substructure of invisible underlying patterns of existence that make new
association and analogies possible.

The world is becoming more complex. Information and ideas are coming in
faster than they can be assimilated, while disciplines become progressively
alienated from each other through specialization. Even words lose their
precision as they take on multi-meanings, while communication, based on
superficial understanding of things, eventually breaks down. A new type
of analytical attitude is called for, a clear overview or a summing up. Not
losing sight of abstract reasoning, but using induction and deduction in the
discovery of the real and concrete structures, the substances of things and
ideas emerge. In this sense they represent the primary being of things to act
as universal forms or ideas when brought to the surface to interact with each
other. When “things” are pared down to their core or essence, superfluous
data fall away and new associations and insights become possible.

Hyperion —Volume I, issue 3, October 200 6 4


My concern is with the creation
of a language of perceptions that
allows the flow of information
among alien systems and
disciplines in which essences
carry pure meaning into pure form
and all things can be considered
once more simultaneously. From
specializations to essences, from
patterns to symmetries, to form,
seeking ultimates in the elemental
nature of things and vice versa.
Thus analytical propositions are
presented in visual form where
both the proposition and its
deductive reasoning achieve their
own essence and communicate
visually. The resulting art is a
dramatization or “visualization”
of these forms, entities or
summations. They are words,
sentences or paragraphs in a
language of seeing. They are the
universal concepts or substances
I often refer to in my writings.

To clarify this further, I consider


a universal concept one that
possesses universal validity and is
structure, free but determined by the form they make. They are a
tem of mathematical precision, inevitable and inescapable, and

the perfect representative of a system or function. It can be a well-conceived,


to them, invisible—they are each alone but fused into a single
A society of isolated individuals who are imprisoned in a sys-

well-balanced idea with immediate universal connotations, that communicates


directly and will yield further inquiries while it can withstand the stress of
& The People Paradox—The Predicament, 1980 (detail)

experimentation.
Agnes Denes, Pascal’s Perfect Probability Pyramid

Universal concepts seeking analogies and new associations are not easily
subjected to the analysis of symbolic logic. It takes a new type of logic and
Lithograph on paper, © 1980 Agnes Denes

perhaps a new philosophy to categorize their symmetries and consequences.

When these hidden patterns and processes are realized in visual form
ambiguities can be clarified, misconceptions reexamined and the subjective
self-state of a system can be studied to seek the imperfection or restate
the perfection in its design. Processes can be held still for analysis, their
intricacies brought into perspective and all that is unseen, undiscovered or
guessed at but feasible can gain recognition until it can establish its own
living paradox.

validity.

Pattern finding is a symmetry operation. It is the purpose of the mind and the
construct of the universe. There are an infinite number of patterns and only

5 H y p e r i o n— N o t e s o n a Vi s u a l Philosophy
some are known. Those that are still unknown hold the key to unresolved

a spiraling number system.


probability of intrinsic repetition in chance events, resulting in
A pyramid of binomial coefficients that represents the relative

India ink on orange graph paper, © 1973 Agnes Denes


Agnes Denes, Pascal’s Triangle II, 1973
enigmas and paradoxes. Thus formal and exclusively visual information can
be refined to such an extent as to impart the most precise and significant
information in addition to visual gratification.

These thoughts are further clarified by quoting from my lecture entitled


“Evolution and the Creative Mind”. This lecture was first delivered at the
Smithsonian Institution, Washington, D.C., 1976.

My art exists in a dynamic, evolutionary world of rapidly


changing concepts and measures, where the appearances of
things, facts and events are assumed manifestations of reality
and distortions are the norm....

Although I deal with difficult concepts, my work remains visual.


The process of “visualization” is doubly important since aspects
of the work explore invisible systems, underlying structures and
patterns inherent in our existence....

I incorporate science,
philosophy and many other
disciplines that enrich my
work and are so necessary
to any worthwhile human
activity in the world today.

I communicate my ideas
in whatever form is most
true to the concept. It is
the concept that dictates
the mode of presentation.
My projects take several
years to complete and they
are in a constant state
of flux. The work follows
an evolutionary attitude
and process. It questions,
dissect, reevaluates and
reconstructs through the
conscious use of instinct,
intellect and intuition.

...By questioning our


existence as well as
existence itself, we
create an art universal
in terms of all humanity.

Hyperion —Volume I, issue 3, October 200 6 6


Personally, I am fascinated by
our human position of being
somewhere in the middle of
this “existence.” We live on an
average galaxy; we don’t live
too long, and yet, we can look
out to the edge of the universe
into light years and penetrate
the atom chasing quarks and
another world within. The
world seems to begin at the
surface of our skin; there is a
world beyond it and a world
within, and the distance is
about the same. I like that.

Once we abandon Newtonian


static physics and accept
Einstein’s four-dimensional
principles of relativity, we
question reality and know that
even the laws of nature may
undergo evolutionary changes.
We even invented the
uncertainty principle, although
we use it for other reasons.

We haven’t begun to
understand the implications of
eses, the profundity of human thought reduced to its mathemati-
triangular table lists logical implications, functions, and hypoth-
A satire on human self-importance—based on the modal system
S8 and the propositional calculus of Russell and Whitehead, the

this new, relativistic existence, where everything we had known


and had believed now seems to be wrong. In this new dynamic
world, objects become processes and forms are patterns
cal simplicity, procedural repetition, and ineluctability.
India ink on orange graph paper, © 1970 Agnes Denes

in motion. Matter is a form of energy and our own human


substance is but spinning velocity. There is no solid matter
and no empty space: time becomes an earthbound reality but
Agnes Denes, The Human Argument, 1969-70

remains an enigma in the fourth dimension. We must create a


new language, consider a transitory state of new illusion and
layers of validity and accept the possibility that there may be no
language to describe ultimate reality, beyond the language of
visions.

In our limited existence, evolution provides answers as to


where we’ve been and where we are going: a future prediction
based on previous phenomena. The universe contains
systems, systems contain patterns. The purpose of the mind is
to locate these patterns and to seek the inherent potential for
new systems of thought and behavior.

7 H y p e r i o n— N o t e s o n a Vi s u a l Philosophy
My work touches on the various stages of the development of
my species, reevaluates and makes new comparisons in order
to enhance perception and awareness, to form new insights
and new methods of reasoning....

This analytical attitude probes the structural and philosophical


significance of an invisible world where elusive processes,
transformations and interactions of phenomena go unseen,
buried in the substance of time and space. I am referring to
known or unknown events hidden from recognition either
by their nature of spatio-temporal limitations or by our being
unaware of their existence and functions.

I believe that art is the essence of life, as much as anything can


be a true essence. It is extracted from existence by a process.
Art is a reflection on life and an analysis of its structure. As
such, art should be a great moving force shaping the future.

From the anthology SYMMETRY-Unifying Human Understanding

Publ. Pergamon Press. 1986

© 1986 Agnes Denes

published in Hyperion: On the Future of Aesthetics, a web publication of


The Nietzsche Circle: www.nietzschecircle.com, Volume I, issue 3, October 2006

Hyperion —Volume I, issue 3, October 200 6 8


The Mood of the Matter:

The Aesthetic Emotion at the Heart of Modernism

by Mark Daniel Cohen

No Limits, Just Edges: Jackson Pollock Paintings on Paper

Hyperion, Volume I, issue 3, October 2006


The

ood
of the Matter
The Aesthetic Emotion at the He
eart of Modernism

No Limits, Just Edges: Jackson Pollock Paintings on Paper


Solomon R. Guggenheim Museum, New York, NY
May 26 – Sep 29, 2006

by Mark Daniel Cohen

1 Hyp e r i o n — T h e M o o d o f th e M atter

Parler aujourd’hui de poésie philosophique . . . N’est-ce pas
oublier que le but de celui qui spécule est de fixer ou de créer
une notion-c’est-à-dire un pouvoir et un instrument de pouvoir,
cependent que le poète moderne essaie de produire en
nous un état et de porter cet état exceptionnel au point d’une
jouissance parfaite . . .
—Paul Valéry


A state, in itself, is nothing whatever.
—T. S. Eliot

f there is such a thing as the aesthetic emotion, what of it? If there is a


I distinctive state of mind, a décor of awareness, an atmosphere of thought,
that works of art instigate in the receptive intelligence and in which they are
received, through which they are viewed, what difference does it make? If they
cast a hue upon the glass in the window of perception, set a suffusing tint in
the mental lens that drenches our vision of them, a haze of vibrant tonality
comparable to the invisible color of a room that we but momentarily notice as
we enter—if they determine us such that they determine how we see them—
what is the worth and the function of it? What does that capability convey,
and what about art does it reveal to us? If art has, as one of its defining
characteristics, as one of the qualities by which we recognize it, by which we
know it for what it is, an attribute comparable to that of a mood-altering drug,
what is the self-identifying mood that it induces and what is the significance?

For if so, there must be a commonality to all the moods induced by works of
art. Otherwise, we would not call them all by a single name, we would not
know them all to be of a relation—as there must be a family of such moods,
or else all works of art would seem to be by a single artist, so there must be a
family resemblance. But if so, this contentless quality, this vehicle of meaning,
must itself have a meaning, or we are stymied at the start—this very possibility
of meaning would itself be without meaning, would be mere soft-tissue
machinery without import. And it must have import, it must carry significance
in the sense of meaning as implication, or nothing could follow. It must lead
somewhere. Otherwise, it would be inert, and if art is anything, it is dynamic.
It is an application of consciousness that has been energized, that drives
forward in some fashion, that results in some manner, in some matter—in
something of urgency. Art is imperative. It is dire. Else, it would not be art.

The question of the induction of mood is itself an imperative, for there is a

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 200 6 2


heritage of art that has been defined by and valued for its elegance of mood,
for the tonality of its impression, for its ceremonious incursion upon the portals
of awareness. There is a long-standing sense of art as a retinue of knowing,
as a procession of comprehension marked by its formality rather than by any
particular and distinctive content of its insight. Art has long been known more
as a way of knowing than by anything in particular known, known more as a
ceremony of awareness, as a pomp and circumstance of impression provided
for the monarch of the mind. And as such, art amounts to a set of protocols for
intellectual obeisance—for a bow granted, and a criticality foresworn, for the
sake of the austerity of the cortege before the aristocracy of intellectuality—for
the highest dignity of knowing’s sake.

Which is to say that the artistic presentation of its subject matter possesses
an intrinsic gravity, has a quality of impeccability, that potentially is a way of
granting an air, or of taking on airs. It is a question of style, of style installing
an attitude and a principle of reception—of the artistic emotion as an open
acceptance rooted in the sheer dignity of the report. This is the aspect of
art that certifies Susan Sontag’s sense of it as an “autonomous model of
consciousness,” as a form of knowing more than a resume of things known,
or things presented as discovery. In the increments of its inflections, in the
discretionary variations of the forms, there is an extraordinary capability, for
Sontag’s argument is incisive—the disposition of the will, of the posture of
approach to the world, determines to a significant degree what becomes
known of it. But in the commonality, in the family resemblance that makes
all things artistic art, there is an element of risk: there is an intrinsic
haughtiness, a lofty prepossession, that wraps anything which receives an
artistic presentation. Art by its nature crosses the bridge between creating
an impression and making things impressive; inherently what it portrays it
approves, even if that approval stands behind a surface irony. Works of art
bear a stamp of conviction. And as art sweeps into the awareness, accepted
for its being art, so too is swept in whatever it signifies.

This is the matter of beauty—the compelling vision, the admirable aspect—


and what is at issue is beauty’s ability to beguile. It sets us at the precipice,
for, as in all things, in art we must choose between prostration and power.
Either we permit ourselves the mesmerization of the prepossessing image,
the dazzling of the bedeviling display, the mindlessness of succumbing to the
varnish of the shimmering veneer, or we select to think our own thoughts, to
adopt our own values, and, thereby, set our own course. The gilt crust of the
Byzantine icon dissuades the lancet of the analytical thrust, and this inherency
of the peril aligns itself with Dave Hickey’s sense of beauty as a Trojan horse,
as a conveyer of the ideological faiths of its moment in history—as a visual
credibility lathed in shimmering hypnotic ostentation onto anything of power’s
requisite, indiscriminately applicable.

However, the risk is run and Hickey’s characterizing holds only on the
foundation of beauty’s meaning. If beauty has an import of its own, if it leads to
something on the basis of its intrinsic implications—if it is itself a configuration

3 Hyp e r i o n — T h e M o o d o f th e M atter
of thought and not simply an inflecting conveyance of cargoed thinking—then
it deposes the ideological infiltrator. But if it is the vapidity of mere gloss
reflected in the fixed eye of the deer in the headlights, then it is nothing but an
entrainment of the volition and it makes an obedience of us. It can be vision,
or it can be occlusion; it can be insight or insignificance. And so, either beauty
has a meaning of its own, or it is intellectual betrayal, a mesmerizing sell of the
prevailing system of value, a quisling of the will.

And an art of meaningless beauty falters regardless of the judged worth of


the ideology it ships, for its own value must be intrinsic—a value that cannot
be acquired by proximity. Despite its august aspect, despite the nobility of its
receipt, a beauty devoid of internal implication can of necessity be judged of
worth only by measuring along its outward vector—only according to the effect
it has on us. Art’s accomplishment is then within the viewership; art’s labor
is in the restorative potential. Vapid beauty makes art into a sub-species of
therapy, and art becomes valuable solely for its capability to retread. Its claim
is to its subject rather than its subject matter, and the hazard of installing a
conventionalized thinking follows naturally, for the purpose of therapy always
has been the adjustment of the patient and not the critique of the prevailing
norms to which the patient adjusts, norms that go unquestioned. Therapy is
inherently a conservative endeavor.

And so the circle closes, for if beauty is without an inherent meaning, if the
tenor of aesthetic disclosure reveals nothing but what it has been loaded to
carry, it makes for a meaningless art. The art of therapy is opposite the art
of meaning, the art truly of revealing, for all that is unclosed is the art itself,
and us. It is we in our new dress of appropriate and appropriated attitude,
and the capability of the art to grant us our renewed dispensation, that is the
substance of the work—and there is nothing more. There is no third party,
no conclusion to the syllogism written in the flesh, in the tissues of the mind,
in the districts of our inner life that we comprehend as the heart. There is no
output of the process, no result, nothing added to what it was we had when
we began—there is a Phenomenological short circuit, a failure to break the
circle of perception, and only the initiating components have been re-colored,
the inner décor has been redone. What is at issue is solely what we are to
become, and what we are to become is inured to what there is, without a
revelation of what that is, without an understanding that exists for its own sake
and not for the sake of making us sedate and apt for the larger dispensation,
as we find it—as it finds us.

The tenor of the aesthetic is art’s defining characteristic, the quality by which
we know to recognize it, and with fully nonrepresentational abstraction,
the tenor is the single remaining active element. The question of its
meaningfulness—of its capability of output, of its leading somewhere—
becomes imperative. Jackson Pollock may be the paradigmatic instance of the
question at this time. Pollock’s work is the heart, and surely the best known
and most easily recognized example, of the arm of Abstract Expressionism
devoted to the rendering on the canvas (or paper) of the emotional state of

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 200 6 4


the artist through
the recording of
the spontaneous
gesture—or so
the story has
come to be told.
It is the branch
of the movement
navigated by those
whom the critic
Harold Rosenberg
marked with the
phrase “Action
Painters,” and
as the point of
the exercise
presumably is to
put it in the most
generous fashion,
the establishing of
an atlas of capable
inner states, a
cartography of human
mental tonalities, what is at issue is the tenor, the very vibrancy and tonality, of
Photo: Hester + Hardaway, © 2006 Pollock-Krasner Foundation/Artists Rights

the aesthetic inner condition, drawn like blood from the artist himself, sampled
from the artist employed as something of a lab rat, or an experimenter
experimenting on himself.

The question is imperative, and Pollock must be considered the most recent
first-rank demand for an answer. As the last, to date, painter of historic
Colored pencils and pencil on blue paper, 6 x 7 5/8 inches

significance, the last who can even be considered a candidate to enter the
pantheon on the same terms as Picasso, Vermeer, Velasquez, Rembrandt, he
forces a question that is as easy to phrase as it is inescapable: with a mature
Pollock drip painting, what is the point? Or, beyond the evidence of Pollock
having been Pollock, is there one?

Although oriented on only Pollock’s paintings on paper, and thus absent any
Jackson Pollock, Untitled, ca. 1939-40

of the major works, the exhibition at the Guggenheim Museum in New York
provided an adequate and ample overview of Pollock’s manner and its genesis
The Menil Collection, Houston.

through the development of his art. More than 60 paintings were included
that ranged over the entirety of his painting career, from his earliest period
Society (ARS), New York.

beginning in 1935 to the year of his last works on paper, 1952. (Pollock died
in an automobile crash on August 11, 1956. The exhibition was organized to
commemorate the fiftieth anniversary of his death. The last four years of his
life saw an arguable falling off of power in the paintings, and, as the material
from the museum makes clear, they were “almost devoid of drawings.”)

The word “drawings” is not quite right, for, as acknowledged in the exhibition,

5 Hyp er i o n — T h e Mo o d o f th e M atter
Pollock did not make preparatory sketches for
his paintings, and these works on paper are
not recordings of intentions for other, more fully
developed achievements. They are finished works
in themselves, and all are in the mode of the period
in Pollock’s career in which they occur, as calibrated
by his major paintings. They are a parallel track, if
they should be distinguished at all from the main line
of his art. They are the entire career in miniature,
and we see all of Pollock’s manner on display,
from the early figurative period, flush with personal
symbology and the evident influences of Cubism,
Surrealism, and Jungian psychology, represented by
such works as Untitled, ca. 1939-40, and The Mask,
ca. 1943, to the mature, explosive abstraction of
the poured works, such as Untitled (Green Silver),
ca. 1949, and [Silver over Black, White, Yellow, and
Red], 1948.

And so we see what we know so well from the major


works, and the culmination is in the period of the
“drip paintings” (a phrase deserving of the scare
quotes for there was far more involved technically
than the mere spilling of pigment, there was far more
of deliberateness than Pollock is often credited with practicing, and not mere

Gouache, oil, pen and ink, and fabric on paper, 29 7/8 x 21 7/8 inches (75.9 x
spontaneity). There, apparently, the artist’s inner condition is laid upon the
paper like a jazz improvisation laid upon the air—in the most emotionally
intricate instances, a complex state of inner life fixed in a work of art, knowable
and capable of being revisited—a sophistication of the inner world revealed
and accomplished, an enrichment of the possibility of sheer living, an
amplification of ourselves.

But is that all? Is it just us? Is there nothing more to all this? Certainly, © 2006 Pollock-Krasner Foundation/Artists Rights

Clement Greenberg—who, if he is now to be called upon for anything, is to be


called upon for the artist he championed most strenuously, whose reputation
ultimately will determine Greenberg’s own—leaves us precisely there, perhaps
against his own attempted judgment. Greenberg, evidently, had little use
Jackson Pollock, The Mask, ca. 1943

for Rosenberg’s idea of action painting or for spontaneity of expression as


the purpose of the art. He argued Pollock more as a technical innovator, as
a practitioner of inventive compositional strategies, employing a network
of painted lines and “interstitial spots and areas” in a manner similar to the
Society (ARS), New York.

earlier Analytic Cubism’s “facet-planes” to achieve a “minimal illusion of depth”


and a “dramatic and pictorial unity” resulting from subtly executed but rigidly
Private collection

controlled principles of variation in the network. In short, a Pollock painting is


designed, not just splashed on.
55.6 cm)

However, Greenberg knew better than to leave things at that, and he


addresses the pay-off: “When I first began to admire Pollock’s painting it

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 200 6 6


was for its intensity and force; later on, it was for its clarified splendor and
eloquence; right now I would praise it most for its range of mood.” And so,
the inner state is the matter, even if not spontaneous and uncontrolled in
its application—what is revealed is the shifting temper of internal life, the
aesthetic emotion fanned into a spectrum of variations. What is revealed is us.

The mood is the matter—a state of mind, an atmosphere of the awareness,


an inner environment in which thinking occurs rather than the occurrence of
a thought, rather than a concrete meaning. And the distinction between the
amorphous vapors of an intellectual flavor and the specifiable implication of an
assertive expression fixes the soul of a significant dispute, one that stands at
the core of the art of the modern era.

The French poet and—to use a word that is less than adequate to characterize
the range and texture of his accomplishment—intellectual Paul Valéry hailed
the purpose and achievement of modern poetry along the lines of a quality
akin to an aura, a potency like a charged mist of altered mental life:


Parler aujourd’hui de poésie philosophique . . . N’est-ce pas
oublier que le but de celui qui spécule est de fixer ou de créer
une notion-c’est-à-dire un pouvoir et un instrument de pouvoir,
cependent que le poète moderne essaie de produire en
nous un état et de porter cet état exceptionnel au point d’une
jouissance parfaite . . .

(To speak today of philosophical poetry . . . Is it not to forget


that the goal of he who speculates is to fix or to create an
idea—that is to say a power and an instrument of power,
whereas the modern poet tries to produce in us a state and to
carry that exceptional state to the point of perfect pleasure . . .)

For Valéry, there is a clear discrepancy between philosophy and poetry, for
there is an evident and palpable distinction between the philosophical idea
and the poetic “state” of mind, the aesthetic emotion, which, for Valéry, is
brought in modern poetry to the intensity of a perfection and is the goal of the
enterprise, the final acquisition of the reader, and, whatever it may produce, if
it results in anything, self-evidently does not lead to and has no dealings with
the idea.

In his essay “Dante,” collected The Sacred Wood, T. S. Eliot, no minor figure
in the arena of modern poetry, cited this assertion by Valéry in order to dismiss
the point in its entirety. “A state, in itself, is nothing whatever.” For Eliot, the
achievement for poetry is to arrive at a concrete vision, to convey a thought
that is precisely communicated. “The poet does not aim to excite—that is not
even a test of his success—but to set something down; the state of the reader
is merely that reader’s particular mode of perceiving what the poet has caught

7 Hyp e r i o n — T h e M o o d o f th e M atter
in words.” There is, in essence, a meaning to the successful poetic work, a
conception that is to be conveyed, and not the vagueness of a condition to be
instigated. However, Eliot’s approbation is not for the idea specifically, not for
Valéry’s alternative to the “state.” The poetic vision is precise, and it is also
something emotionally drenched—a conception of what is lived, of “something
perceived”—of the reality of the world as it is experienced. Even thought, when
encountered poetically, must be the idea realized, “when it has become almost
a physical modification,” and not pure theory. It is meaning that Eliot values,
not a general condition of awareness, but it is meaning of another kind, not
meaning as, specifically, idea, a designation that spans a particular octave and
compass of thought.

It is not quite an irony that, despite their opposition, Valéry and Eliot both
assert a primacy of something other than and, even in Eliot’s case, vaguer
than reason and ideational thought. Although Eliot comes far closer, it is the
case that neither looks to a meaning in the work of art in the normal sense of
the word. And although Eliot wants something definite and, on its own terms,
knowable, it is he who refers to the “artistic emotion,” which is a characterizing
element of his artistic “vision.” What Eliot is after is a precisely related chorus
of emotional tones, and it must be observed that Valéry no more refers to
emotions than he does to the idea. His “state” is something else—a mood that
is something other than Eliot’s artistic emotion. Nevertheless, both thinkers
see art as oriented on us—for Eliot, it asserts something about us; for Valéry,
it alters us. Between them, something has been omitted; something in the way
of exact meaning regarding an external issue has been overlooked.

With Valéry, the mood is the matter, and it is no small matter, for mood is at the
very heart of Modernism. If one reckons Modernism in the arts as beginning
with Mallarmé and his revised aesthetic—the aesthetic of Symbolism,
which influenced so many of those we take to be the foundational artists of
Modernism—then the essence of the new mode at the end of the nineteenth
century was an orientation on the mood rather than on the specifiable idea.
Indefiniteness was the open door to the new vision. As described by Arthur
Symons, art for Mallarmé had to shift its focus from the tangible reality of the
clearly observable world to something evident but far more fleeting, something
evanescent, something like water flashing on a stone, something more of an
impression than an observation: “Note, further, that [Mallarmé] condemns the
inclusion in verse of anything but, ‘for example, the horror of the forest, or the
silent thunder afloat in the leaves; not the intrinsic, dense wood of the trees’.”

What is at issue, what is artistic here, is not the fact of the wood that
constitutes the trees but the “fact” of the silent thunder skirting the leaves and
the shudder that braces them like a cold, serrated chill slicing down the spine.
From this comes Impressionism in painting, for Monet attended the evening
talks that Mallarmé held at his home, and Impressionism in music, if that term
so applies, for Debussy came as well, and the most advanced developments
in subsequent French poetry, and much more—perhaps all that we now
call Modernism. From this may well come the very idea of abstraction—the

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 200 6 8


dissolution of the observable world, of the wood of the trees.

What evidently substitutes for the material fact of the world is us—the human
perspective, for the horror of the forest and the thunder afloat in the leaves
are our impressions, our intrusions on the observation. They are subjective
components of experience and not native facts, whatever those facts might
ultimately be, if even there are any. It is we who invade the trees with horror
and thunder, when we see them—when we feel them. Here is, it appears
at first blush, the human naivety arising: the reflex action by which and
the intellectual posture with which we measure the truth of things against
ourselves, our interests, our values, our needs. The inclusion of the subjective
component, of the personal reaction, reveals nothing to us other than
ourselves. If we deduct ourselves and our self-fascination from the equation,
there is no reason to believe in our emotional impressions, for with regard to
the world beyond our minds, we have no reason to think our emotions any
more reliable, and many reasons to think them a great deal less dependable,
than our sensory perceptions. The thunder is us, our own demands and
reactions, and nothing else.

And so, Eliot is right. The mood itself and in itself is nothing whatever. It is
Phenomenology in the most demoted sense—not an investigation that retires
to the search for first principles, that returns to zero and initiates an attempt
to determine what we know and what the prerequisites of knowing are, but a
blind, uncritical faith in mere impression, in perception as foundational truth, or
the nearest thing we can hope to obtain. And the thunder is nothing more than
us yelling back at ourselves.

But that was not the idea of Modernism, not the idea of Mallarmé, for in
Mallarmé, there was the idea. The poet who stands as the fount of Modern Art
had a philosophy, or pursued one. There was something he was attempting
to set down, although clearly he felt the need to alter radically the means by
which what he saw could be set down. Mallarmé had a vision and a body of
ideas concerning the world—a new vision of the world—a philosophy to which
he devoted an enormous amount of time in his attempt to write it out, and
the poetry was intended, by all indications, to evoke portions of that vision.
The poetic technique was a means to an end, and the end was a meaning,
not merely a mood, a state of mind, triggered for the sake of its pleasure.
Mallarmé referred to this work presumably of direct exposition as l’oeuvre, and
it was not completed. All we have are the notebooks he left behind.

And so, in the end, Eliot is wrong because he is right—the state in itself is
nothing whatever, but the state is not the point, and Eliot’s assault of Valéry
is misjudged. The state of mind, the quality of imagination, to be induced by
artistic means is itself a portion of the artist’s methodology. Its purpose is
to calibrate the reader, to gauge the reader, to make the reader capable of
coming upon realizations that then follow naturally. Like the casting of a spell
that conjures insights, like a wiping of the glass on perception’s window to
sponge away the deluding mists through which we attempt to view the world in

9 Hyp e r i o n — T h e M o o d o f th e M atter
which we live, the artist’s effect for Mallarmé, the result of the newly computed
aesthetic emotion, is to render us able of clear vision, and what is then to
come is an ontological insight, a vision of the truth, not encapsulated in artistic
statement but made available by artistic influence, by instilling the poet’s mind
into the mind of the reader. Like any poet worthy of the title, Mallarmé is not
attempting to say what he means. He is trying to show us what he means, or,
rather, he is trying to make us adept of seeing for ourselves what it is he sees.

Thus, the induction of the exceptional state of mind is for the sake of altering
us to a purpose, of changing our perceptual capacity such that we can “see”
beyond the range and specifications of normative perception, such that we
can “see” beyond the veil of appearances—such that we can see the truth,
spontaneously realized. It is evident at this point that a distinction is best
made between emotion and mood, for we must consider that two different
capabilities are under consideration here. What Mallarmé sought to raise
through the influence of his notoriously obscure poetic technique is something
other than a component of ordinary emotional experience—it is something
other than ordinary in any possible sense. He looked to a revelatory state
of mind, and we may reserve the word “mood” for that—the term surely was
employed by Yeats for similar purpose. It then becomes clear that what Eliot
valued was emotions, artistically encapsulated—in a sense, he saw the
poet as the documentarian of human emotive existence. The “state” of mind
for Valéry, who was something of a devotee of Mallarmé and Mallarmé’s
Symbolist aesthetic, is more akin to the art of the sorcerer. What he is after is
a different quality of “vision.” And it is best to assign the “aesthetic emotion,”
despite Eliot’s use for his purposes of the similar phrase, to the designation of
mood, to the overarching aura of the artistic frame of dreaming.

This is the essence of Modernism, this search for an insight into a truth that
evades the ordinary mind, this hunt for the quarry of truth that eludes the
hounds of rational pursuit. The game is a species of the sublime, and it is the
soul of the endeavor of every major abstract visual artist from Kandinsky to
Pollock and beyond. The purpose of the project of abstraction—or Modernist
abstract art, or abstract painting that had not demoted itself to the stable of
formalism—is to create an artistic mood, to purify and induce the aesthetic
feeling, so as to trigger the spontaneous realization of the truth of things,
so as to alter the mind’s eye, so as to see as we are otherwise incapable of
seeing—so as to unchain the potencies of the mind that have been shackled
to the normative vision of the real.

Sontag once characterized the modern artist as a broker in madness, and the
attribution holds if we view such artistic madness as the poise it appears to
possess from the point of view of ordinary thought, if we take the departure
from the normal and move doggedly into the truth as if “mad.”

In short, this is Kant—the aesthetic mind as capable of conceiving what breaks


the norms of the rational, as penetrating more deeply than the limits of reason
permit, as able to know comparatives that result of no standard computational

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 2006 10


comparisons,
as powered to
recognize the
absolutely great.
As sublime; as
unchained. And it
is not very different
from Nietzsche,
if we take the
Dionysian, in
its version as a
state of mind,
as possessing
a special status,
as in some
sense more
exalted than the
Apollinian state—
as revealing
something of truth.
The distinctions
between the aesthetics of Kant and of Nietzsche, the differences between
them regarding the value and the function of art, are finally in the details. The
details are imperative, they speak of conceptions of art and of reality that differ
profoundly, but there is a family resemblance in these aesthetic philosophies
that must not be ignored. In broad terms, the essential point is the same,
and the manner in which philosophical positions arrange themselves when
seen in a distant overview is as important as the intricate examinations of
the differences of detail, even if academic careers generally are not made
Photo: David Heald, © 2006 Pollock-Krasner Foundation/Artists

by observing broad alignments and discrepancies, for they tell us the large
Enamel and aluminum paint on paper mounted on canvas

questions we are entertaining, and what, in the gravest sense, is at stake. It


is imperative that we know how our positions line up. In Kant and Nietzsche,
and in Schopenhauer and many others, there is announced the death of the
Jackson Pollock, Untitled (Green Silver), ca. 1949

credibility of the quotidian, of the plainly self-presented, and there is claimed


Solomon R. Guggenheim Museum, New York.

special powers of accuracy for aesthetic perception. Much of the modern


world essays from this position. The differences regarding what is to be found
Gift, Sylvia and Joseph Slifka. 2004.63.

in the artistic vision is in the end of small importance because there is no


saying it, no recounting it, no bringing it back for those who have not made the
Rights Society (ARS), New York.

aesthetic excursion. It is available only through the actual artistic product, and
thus what we really have is a wall Kant builds against himself; Also Sprach
Zarathustra, the philosophical work of literary art; and the body of Modernist
22 3/4 x 30 3/4 inches

art that has sprung from this soil, or from thoughts similar that were nourished
by underground tributaries of purely artistic origin.

Of course, something must be said—in relation to Kant, who is being offered


as providing the foundation of Modernism generally and of abstraction
specifically—regarding the shift in this argument from the beautiful to the

11 Hyp e r i o n — T h e M o o d o f th e M atter
sublime. It can be claimed that abstraction in art bypasses the beautiful,
in Kant’s sense of it, and directs the aesthetic interest immediately to the
sublime. The prepossessing quality of the image—the hypnotic aspect,
the impeccability of its presentation—is not in its pleasure, universal to the
judgment or otherwise, but in its provocation of the sense of sublimity, become
possible precisely because nature is not represented.


. . . whereas natural beauty (such as is self-subsisting) conveys
a finality in its form making the object appear, as it were,
preadapted to our power of judgement, so that it thus forms of
itself an object of our delight, that which, without our indulging
in any refinements of thought, but, simply in our apprehension
of it, excites the feeling of the sublime, may appear, indeed,
in point of form to contravene the ends of our power of
judgement, to be ill-adapted to our faculty of presentation, and
to be, as it were, an outrage on the imagination, and yet it is
judged all the more sublime on that account.
(The Critique of Judgement, trans. Meredith, § 23)

Not capable of an envisioning in nature, in the given availabilities of form,


the sublime is a function—like the abstract composition whose principles of
departure from nature is necessarily not derivable from nature—of purely
mental formulations, of powers capable only to thought.


For the sublime, in the strict sense of the word, cannot be
contained in any sensuous form, but rather concerns ideas of
reason, which, although no adequate presentation of them is
possible, may be excited and called into the mind by that very
inadequacy itself which does admit of sensuous presentation.
Thus the broad ocean agitated by storms cannot be called
sublime. Its aspect is horrible, and one must have stored one’s
mind in advance with a rich stock of ideas, if such an intuition
is to raise it to the pitch of a feeling which is itself sublime—
sublime because the mind has been incited to abandon
sensibility and employ itself upon ideas involving higher finality.

That quality of finality available only to the mind threatens not only to defy
observation in nature but to elude visual organization in the work of art,
corresponding potentially and in aesthetic ambition to the difficulty of founding
or finding comprehensive laws for abstract composition. The correspondence
to the sublime may evade all visual encapsulation, whether natural or
devised—it may be essentially non-visual.

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 2006 12



But in what we are wont to call sublime in nature there is such
an absence of anything leading to particular objective principles
and corresponding forms of nature that it is rather in its chaos,
or in its wildest and most irregular disorder and desolation,
provided it gives signs of magnitude and power, that nature
chiefly excites the ideas of the sublime.

The suggestion of Pollock here is self-evident and inescapable, as well as


the necessity of resorting not to the visual encapsulation but to the evocative
mood.

(Kant’s specification of a “finality,” of a completeness of form, of a self-


contained and self-accomplished quality, that is to be discovered in the
mind but not in nature, if extended to the possibility of a finality not to be
visualizable in any manner, implies a correspondence to higher geometry, in
which structures that can be described with precision trigonometrically cannot
be visualized, even to the mind’s eye, i.e., multi-dimensional forms, such as
a Hypertorus or Hypersphere: “Hence it gives a veritable extension, not, of
course, to our knowledge of objects of nature, but to our conception of nature
itself—nature as mere mechanism being enlarged to the conception of nature
as art—an extension inviting profound inquiries as to the possibility of such
a form.” Nature defined as the mechanism of form itself, as the possibility of
form, extended—structural coherence beyond the capability of the senses
seen as the substance of the sublime. However, this line of thought is
necessarily the subject for another and more extensive inquiry.)

And so, the stream of Abstract Expressionism reputedly dedicated to the


spontaneous emotional expression of the artist, the current of the “Action
Painters,” may be about something more than mere sincerity of inner reaction
and personal attitude. It may be comparable to the other branch of the mode
in its intrinsic ambition, to the more geometric manner of such as Rothko
and Newman that pursues the insight of the sublime through mathematical
regularities, that pursues an honesty and not a sincerity, that chases after a
truth-telling. It may be so, but the determination is difficult if not impossible, for
as the realization sought is inherently unspeakable, it is unspeakable even to
ourselves. With regard to the sublime, we cannot be certain of what we are
looking to see or if we are seeing what qualifies as the accomplishment. What
we typically have done is attempt to recognize the sublime by feel, to attribute
an insight upon feeling awestruck by the work of art, and there remains
perpetually the risk of “reading into” the work, of convincing ourselves we
feel the presence of the awesome revelation and then attaching that feeling
to the work, claiming the feeling an objective attribute of the art, of intruding
ourselves into the art rather than observing with full critical-mindedness what
is before us—of talking ourselves into it. As viewers of abstract visual art, we
are doomed to working blind.

13 Hyp e ri o n — T h e M o o d o f th e M atter
The question,
in short and in
each case of
abstraction, is—
does the artist get
there? In Pollock’s
case, with the
mature works, with
the drip paintings,
it is Greenberg’s
notifications that
give us the option.
The netting of
line work that
establishes the
beginnings of
the perception of
depth, the faceting
of the surface that
arranges repetition
tactics to organize
the visual presentation, the carefully accomplished compositional strategies,
demonstrate the presence of a methodology for achieving an orchestrated
effect, a means for reaching past the limits of an unthinking commission
of reactive gesturing—for getting somewhere, somewhere of aesthetic

© 2006 Pollock-Krasner Foundation/Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York.


deliberateness. As compositional structures, they are, and they are of course,
geometric, and they relate Pollock’s apparently spontaneous paintings

Enamel on paper mounted on canvas, 21 x 31 1/2 inches (61 x 80 cm)


to the clearly more cautious works of geometric Abstract Expressionism,

Jackson Pollock, [Silver over Black, White, Yellow, and Red], 1948
Musée national d’art moderne, Centre Georges Pompidou, Paris
demonstrating Pollock’s works to be variations of the same mode. But these
technical factors indicate mere possibilities of achievement, means that, as
Greenberg once observed, do not guarantee an end, and we remain with the
question: what precisely are we seeing?

And there is no settling the question, for we would have to know the sublime
to know if we are seeing the sublime in Pollock’s paintings, and the unsettling
result is that abstract art remains a matter of faith—and faith is not an
intellectual stance. But there are determinations, modest ones, we can make.
With Pollock, we know there are claims by mathematicians that fractal patterns
have been located in his paintings. Richard P. Taylor, Adam P. Micolich, and
David Jonas presented their findings in Nature (see Nature, vol. 399, 3 June
1999), and they observed that the fractal dimensions increased over time
as Pollock refined his drip technique, demonstrating a deliberateness to the
application of the technique and showing, in their words, “the fingerprint of
nature.” The aesthetic question then becomes whether we are seeing the
“fingerprint” of something more than nature observed, whether we are seeing
the fingerprint of the truth of nature—of nature in itself, beyond normative
perception.

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 2006 14


The findings support and cement Greenberg’s claims about the care and
intricacy of the compositional strategies, as well as the alignment with the
more easily recognized geometric manners of other Abstract Expressionists.
In short, the apparent difference in manner between Pollock and Rothko, say,
may be a matter of nothing more than sophistication of geometric technique,
as if that were nearly nothing. But the question of ultimate significances is not
answered in this—the fractal patterns still are only aspects of the works, facial
features of the paintings. Nevertheless, we can now begin to infer on the basis
of the hypothetical, for cogent thought is always promising.

If it were to be the case that Pollock’s works induce the mood of spontaneous
realization—that they are not spontaneous renderings but carefully wrought
works for triggering spontaneous insight—if Pollock does raise the intuitive
grasp into consciousness, does his mathematics participate in the process?
Even assuming the efficacy, we cannot be sure the math would be the active
agent, but inferences can be drawn from the further assumption, from the
“what if,” from the construction done from the other end. If the math were to
be proved participative in the insight, if the intuition were demonstrated to be
triggered by a confrontation with geometric structure, made conscious by a
conscious engagement with geometric formulation, then it would follow that
the intuition is itself geometrically structured—that geometry is intuitive. For a
system to be relatable to another system, the systems must be systematically
similar, they must be of a piece structurally, the principles of organization must
bear a resemblance—the systems must be capable of integration. Further, art
is the providing of the vicarious experience—it is the sensory presentation of
the “what if”—and thus Pollock’s fractal patterns must be “digestible” by the
imagination and, if capable of intrusion into and invocation of the intuition, they
must be “digestible” there, as well.

Although art can be made with fractal patterns, fractals, as well as geometric
figures of any disposition, do not in themselves make a work of art. The
unadorned Golden Ratio is merely the Golden Ratio. If it were the case that
Pollock takes us “there” and does so by means of his complex geometries,
he could do so only by envisioning fractal structures within an artistic
imaginative expanse, only by combining awareness of geometry with the
artistic emotion, with and within the aesthetic mood. That mood is dependent
upon artistic means, it would be rendered artistic by being rendered artistically,
and the capability factor here would be the handmade quality, the “painting”
quality—the quality of the atelier, the haptic component, in which the aspect
of the hand, heightened through the honing and control of craft, would ramp
up the density of the encoded data, would enrich the work, and transform
the compositional elements into experiential qualities, as if environmental for
the imagination. The hand, through its inescapable tracking of unconscious
impulse—through its orchestration of its intricately committed gestures,
through its recording and coordinating of its variations of movement—intrudes
more information into the work than ever could be installed deliberately,
infuses the work with the tempo as well as the temper of the unconscious,
whence most of those commitments arise, and the geometrical, compositional

15 Hyp e ri o n — T h e M o o d o f th e M atter
elements of the work become instilled with the directions and the deliberations
of the intuition, and are capable of serving as the trigger for the realization of
the intuitional content—potentially.

At this juncture, a potentiality is what it all must remain, for dealing with the
sublime has this difficulty intrinsically. The sublime stands at the frontier
of consciousness, charting the territory between the conscious and the
unconscious minds, and resides entirely upon the possibility that we know
something more in our unconscious “state” than we do in full consciousness.
And therein is the problem. If we were to dredge the depths of what we
know without knowing it, we might well by the transposition distort beyond
authenticity the very knowledge we are attempting, and if the truth of things
has no relation to our unconscious awareness, if the unconscious mind is
the habitat of pure fantasy, then the entire enterprise is hopeless, and we
might have no capability for recognizing that fact. Worse still, the very phrase
“unconscious awareness” might be of necessity a contradiction in terms, in
which case we are chasing a chimera, and art is merely a pleasurable state of
mind, and a self-hypnosis.

But it is all a matter of faith, and to take the faith as lightly as we can, to take
it as promising only the credible and coherent possibility that art may open
our better mind, the mental realm in which we realize more than we typically
know, we must acknowledge the fact that Modernism generally, and Pollock
as one of its most salient examples, presents nearly insuperable challenges
to confirmation. But in that we ought to recognize that Modernism, the
great artistic innovation of the last century, has left us with one of the great
challenges to aesthetic thought, and it is ours to take up the challenge, one
that will be faced only when we find a method to discover to ourselves what, if
anything, Modernist Art has discovered.

published in Hyperion: On the Future of Aesthetics, a web publication of


The Nietzsche Circle: www.nietzschecircle.com, Volume I, issue 3, October 2006

Hyp er i on —Vol u m e I, i ssu e 3, O ctob er 2006 16

You might also like