Environmental Ethics and Sustainable Development Hand Out Edited 2012
Environmental Ethics and Sustainable Development Hand Out Edited 2012
Environmental Ethics and Sustainable Development Hand Out Edited 2012
tells us how the world should be. Normative Ethics is also called as
prescriptive ethics. It is the study of ethical theories that prescribe
how people ought to act. It examines standards for the rightness
and wrongness of actions. Normative Ethics offer the moral
principles to use to resolve difficult moral decisions.
Environmental ethics is a branch of environmental philosophy
concerning non human nature. Environmental Philosophy is the
study of the concepts and principles relating to human interactions
with nature and the natural environment. Moral philosophy from
Socrates to Sartre has always been anthropocentric. Environmental
ethics is revolutionary in departing from a bi-millennial tradition in
moral philosophy that has identified humans exclusively as the
subject matter of ethics.
Environmental ethics is concerned with the issue of responsible personal
conduct with respect to natural landscapes, resources, species and non-
human organisms. Conduct by persons is the direct concern of moral
philosophy. This analysis of moral responsibility explains why
environmental ethics has only recently attracted the attention and
concern of environmentalists and the general public. Until quite recently,
human effects on the environment were regarded as neutral since we
assumed nature was both impersonal and too vast to be injured by our
interventions. At the very least, we were quite unable to foresee the
harm resulting from our dealings with nature. Now of course we know
3
Criticism of ModernizationTheory
According to Scott (1996), modernization theory was ethnocentric,
euro-centric, and deterministic, which failed to make a distinction
between countries, regions & structural conditions. Modernization
theory was unable to predict effects and outcomes, and simplification of
the social and political change that accompanies the development
process. It entirely ignores the socio-cultural variables & the major
targets (poor).It ignored external (exogenous) causes of poverty and
under development and it blames the victim themselves for their
poverty. Modernization theory puts industrial revolution as
preconditions for development.Industrial revolutions and economic
growth in turn can cause environmental degradation. It denigrates
traditional societies as ‘non-modern’ because of their misinterpretation
of ‘lower’ or ‘other’ form of development. It does not consider
exogenous factors of underdevelopment.
2.1.2.Structuralism
Structuralism is a development theory which focuses on structural
aspects which impede the economic growth of developing countries.
The unit of analysis is the transformation of a country’s economy
from, mainly, subsistence to a modern, urbanized manufacturing and
service economy. Policy prescriptions resulting from structuralism
thinking include major government intervention in the economy to fuel
the industrial sector, known as import substitution industrialization
17
It also defined as "Improving the quality of life while living within the
earth's carrying capacities” (WWF, 1991). The report also claimed that
"sustainable development can only be pursued if population size and
growth are in harmony with the changing productive potential of the
ecosystem."
More recently the interpretations of the term sustainable development
have been broadened to include issues such as poverty, health care, and
education.
The Johannesburg Declaration on Sustainable Development (2002,)
stated that: “poverty eradication, changing consumption and production
patterns, and protecting and managing the natural resource base for
economic and social development are overarching objectives of, and
essential requirements for sustainable development."
Why We need Sustainable Development?
There is a growing consensus that current forms of development are not
sustainable (World Resources Institute). Sustainable development looks
at issues of equality - 80% of the world's resources are used by 20% of
the world's population. Sustainable development is important as it takes
into account equity (social justice) and environment, as well as
economic factors, in order to ensure a more balanced form of
development.
Specific features of Sustainable Development
27
As what works in one community may not work in another or may work
for different reasons, SD includes flexibility, diversity & stability
(ecologic, economic, socio- cultural), consideration of unintended
consequences (change is the norm, not the exception); and notions of
enoughness and reversibility.
Core Issues of Sustainable Development are the following:
• Environment-natural resources, thier threats driving forces /hot
spots/ & challenges
• Sustainable Livelihood Security& its factors
• Energy, sources and associated consequences
• Industry and its impact on economic, social development and the
environment
mainly focuses on the element of poverty and the division between rich
and poor countries- North and South- under moral issues. Gasper states
as an “interdisciplinary” meeting place.”Goulet describes it as a kind of
‘disciplined eclecticism’, as he argues “eclectic in its choice of subject
matter but disciplined in its study of it”.
Regarding its origins, development ethics can be characterized as a
relatively new field of study. Even though the ethical question of
whatisgoodlife and the term ‘eudemonia’- a synonymous of happiness-
trace back to ancient Greek philosophers and particularly to Aristotle’s
‘Nicomachean Ethics, the cultivation of moralandethical issues
regarding development studies and the formulation of development
ethics such as came to the front with the rise of an economic and
humanistic movement in 1950s. This humanistic approach of the
economy and society is theoretically represented by the French
economist Louis Joseph Lebret and his student American Denis Goulet
and defines development as the basic question of values and the creation
of a new civilization.
Generally, ethical judgments regarding the good life, the good society,
and the quality of relations among people always serve, directly or
indirectly, as operational criteria for development planners and as
guidelines for researchers. Development ethics borrows freely from the
work of economists, political scientists, agronomists, and specialists of
other disciplines. Ethics places each discipline’s concept of development
38
value system wherein any society has adopted. Goulet stresses the
importance of the dynamic of value change in determining what is to be
defined as the ‘good life’ and the ‘good society’. In his words,
“development is above all a question of values”. Despite the fact that
development is a relative good in terms of value issues, Goulet argues
that there are three common acceptable universal values, namely 1) life-
sustenance 2) esteem 3) freedom that societies and individuals ought to
investigate within a value based context of the “the good life”. These
universal accepted values compose the ethical goals of development.
1. Life-sustenance refers to the nature of. Goulet points out that one
of development’s most important goals is to prolong men’s lives
and render those men less stunted by disease, extreme exposure to
nature’s elements, and defenselessness against enemies. The
importance of life sustaining goods (e.g. food, shelter, healing or
medicine) is generally acknowledged by all societies. Because of
life sustenance as a value of universal significance, life-sustaining
indices are also used as a measurement of development.
2. Esteem: all human beings in all societies feel the necessity for
respect, dignity, honor, and recognition. The discussion involves
esteem values and material propensity, and, particularly, how
esteem contends with development (in a sense of high rate of
welling- being, economical and technological advance).
44
goals are usually interactive and no range exists among life protection,
esteem and freedom. The essential point is that authentic development
should not judge the aforementioned goals (as is conventionally the
case) but these goals must become the criteria which authentic
development itself must be judged. In this mode, grading a nation high
economic growth does not mean that it has followed an authentic
development pattern. No authentic development can be achieved if
massive consumption leads societies to an entirely material way of
living emphasizing the notion of ‘have’ instead of ‘be’; if structural
relations between nations and within them (among classes and
individuals) are competitive and there is not equal distribution of
development proceeds; if the exploitation of material resources leads to
the destruction of ecological balance, if technological advantages are
used to abolish freedom.
Authentic development, namely sustainability and human development
is at the center of discussion for the last decades. In an effort to define it,
during the progress of a seminar entitled “Ethical issues in development”
that took place at the city of Colombo in Sri Lanka in 1986 it is agreed
that any definition of development should take into account at least the
following six conceptual propositions:
1. Economic component, related with wealth, material life conditions
(amenities), and their equal distribution of them.
49
to the non-human natural world. Some have claimed that this extension
should run to sentient animals, others to individual living organisms, and
still others to holistic entities such as rivers, species and ecosystems.
Under these ethics, we have obligations in respect of the environment
because we actually owe things to the creatures or entities within the
environment themselves. Determining whether our environmental
obligations are founded on anthropocentric or non-anthropocentric
reasoning will lead to different accounts of what those obligations are.
The critique of anthropocentric assumptions and moral judgments and
their supplementation with non anthropocentric (i.e., biocentric or
ecocentric) commitments have driven much environmental ethical
theorizing since the academic founding of the field in the 1970s. The
critique of anthropocentrism, however, is not seen as a purely
intellectual task by environmental philosophers. Most theorists identify
the militantly and exclusively anthropocentric world view as the root
cause of environmental problems such as species extinction, the loss of
natural areas and wilderness, and the general decline of environmental
quality. As a consequence, the rejection of anthropocentrism has become
the hallmark of environmental ethics since the 1980s, although not all
environmental philosophers believe that an exclusively anthropocentric
orientation necessarily leads to the destruction of wild species and
ecosystems. For these dissenting voices in the field, a sufficiently
reformed and enlightened anthropocentrism not only is capable of
53
So, one set of policies will lead to one group of future people, while
another set will lead to a different group. Our actions impact who will
exist in the future, making our knowledge of who they will be
incomprehensible. Since there is no definitive set of future people to
receive the benefits or costs of our actions, to whom do we grant moral
standing? Secondly, and of particular importance for environmental
ethics, how could any future people legitimately complain that they have
been wronged by our environmentally destructive policies? For if we
had not conducted such policies, they would not even exist.
In response to the non-identity problem, it has been argued that while we
do not know exactly who will exist in the future, we do know that some
group of people will exist and that they will have interests. In light of
this, perhaps our obligations lie with these interests, rather than the
future individuals themselves. As for the second aspect of the problem,
we might claim that although future generations will benefit from our
environmentally destructive policies by their very existence, they will
nevertheless have been harmed. After all, cannot one be harmed by a
particular action even if one benefits overall? To illustrate this point,
James Woodward gives the example of a racist airline refusing to allow
a black man on a flight that subsequently crashes. Isn’t this man harmed
by the airline, even though he benefits overall?
Even if we do decide to grant moral standing to future human beings,
however, that still leaves the problem of deciding just what obligations
64
against the needs and interests of those human beings in the future? Can
we justifiably let present people go without for the sake of future
humans?
Clearly then, the problems posed by just a minimal extension of moral
standing are real and difficult. Despite this, however, most
environmental philosophers feel that such anthropocentric ethics do not
go far enough, and want to extend moral standing beyond humanity.
Only by doing this, such thinkers argue, can we get the beyond narrow
and selfish interests of humans, and treat the environment and its
inhabitants with the respect they deserve.
3.5 Anthropocentrism and Animal rights
3.5.1 Extending Moral Standing
An anthropocentric ethic claims that only human beings are morally
considerable in their own right, meaning that all the direct moral
obligations we possess, including those we have with regard to the
environment, are owed to our fellow human beings. While the history of
western philosophy is dominated by this kind anthropocentrism, it has
come under considerable attack from many environmental ethicists.
Such thinkers have claimed that ethics must be extended beyond
humanity, and that moral standing should be accorded to the non-human
natural world. Some have claimed that this extension should run to
sentient animals, others to individual living organisms, and still others to
holistic entities such as rivers, species and ecosystems. This section
66
superior to animals because human beings have the capacity for using
reason to guide their conduct, while animals lack this ability and must
instead rely on instinct. It follows, therefore, that the function of animals
is to serve the needs of human beings.
Following Aristotle, the Christian philosopher St. Thomas Aquinas
(1225-1274) argues that since only beings that are rational are capable of
determining their actions, they are the only beings towards which we
should extend concern "for their own sakes" (Regan and Singer, 1989: 6-
12). Aquinas believes that if a being cannot direct its own actions then
others must do so; these sorts of beings are merely instruments.
Instruments exist for the sake of people that use them, not for their own
sake. Since animals cannot direct their own actions, they are merely
instruments and exist for the sake of the human beings that direct their
actions. Aquinas believes that his view follows from the fact that God is
the last end of the universe, and that it is only by using the human
intellect that one can gain knowledge and understanding of God. Since
only human beings are capable of achieving this final end, all other
beings exist for the sake of human beings and their achievement of this
final end of the universe.
Remnants of these sorts of views remain in justifications for discounting
the interests of animals on the basis of the food chain. On this line of
thought, if one kind of being regularly eats another kind of being, then
the first is said to be higher on the food chain. If one being is higher than
68
another on the food chain, then it is natural for that being to use the other
in the furtherance of its interests. Since this sort of behavior is natural, it
does not require any further moral justification.
b. Kantian Theories
Closely related to Worldview/Religious theories are theories such as
Immanuel Kant's (1724-1804). Kant developed a highly influential
moral theory according to which autonomy is a necessary property to be
the kind of being whose interests are to count directly in the moral
assessment of actions (Kant, 1983, 1956). According to Kant, morally
permissible actions are those actions that could be willed by all rational
individuals in the circumstances. The important part of his conception
for the moral status of animals is his reliance on the notion of willing.
While both animals and human beings have desires that can compel
them to action, only human beings are capable of standing back from
their desires and choosing which course of action to take. This ability is
manifested by our wills. Since animals lack this ability, they lack a will,
and therefore are not autonomous. According to Kant, the only thing
with any intrinsic value is a good will. Since animals have no wills at all,
they cannot have good wills; they therefore do not have any intrinsic
value.
Kant's theory goes beyond the Worldview/Religious theories by relying
on more general philosophical arguments about the nature of morality.
Rather than simply relying on the fact that it is "natural" for rational and
69
confronted with "pain stimuli"; both animals and human beings have
brains, nerves, neurons, endorphins, and other structures; and both
human beings and animals are relatively close to each other on the
evolutionary scale. Since they are similar to each other in these ways, we
have good reason to believe that animals are conscious, just as are
human beings.
Harrison attacks these points one by one. He points out that so-called
pain-behavior is neither necessary nor sufficient for the experience of
pain. It is not necessary because the best policy in some instances might
be to not show that you are in pain. It is not sufficient since amoebas
engage in pain behavior, but we do not believe that they can feel pain.
Likewise, we could easily program robots to engage in pain-behavior,
but we would not conclude that they feel pain. The similarity of animal
and human physical structures is inconclusive because we have no idea
how, or even if, the physical structure of human beings gives rise to
experiences in the first place. Evolutionary considerations are not
conclusive either, because it is only pain behavior, and not the
experience of pain itself, that would be advantageous in the struggle for
survival. Harrison concludes that since the strongest argument for the
claim that animals are conscious fails, we should not believe that they
are conscious.
Problems with Indirect Duties to Animals
73
Another argument against indirect theories begins with the intuition that
there are some things that simply cannot be done to animals. For
example, I am not permitted to torture my own cat for fun, even if no
one else finds out about it. This intuition is one that any acceptable
moral theory must be able to accommodate. The argument against
indirect theories is that they cannot accommodate this intuition in a
satisfying way. Both Kant and Carruthers agree that my torturing my
own cat for fun would be wrong. However, they believe it is wrong not
because of the harm to the cat, but rather because of the effect this act
will have on me. Many people have found this to be a very unsatisfying
account of the duty. In other words, unless it is wrong in itself to harm
the animal, it is hard to see why such an act would lead people to do
other acts that are likewise wrong. If the indirect theorist does not have a
better explanation for why it is wrong to torture a cat for fun, and as long
as we firmly believe such actions are wrong, then we will be forced to
admit that indirect theories are not acceptable.
Indirect theorists can, and have, responded to this line of argument in
three ways. First, they could reject the claim that the indirect theorist's
explanation of the duty is unsatisfactory. Second, they could offer an
alternative explanation for why such actions as torturing a cat are wrong.
Third, they could reject the claim that those sorts of acts are necessarily
wrong.
3.5.3. Direct but Unequal Theories
74
is made available; the thought here is that dogs deserve much more
consideration than the operators of such places give them. However,
when it is pointed out that the conditions in a factory farm are as bad as,
if not much worse than, the conditions in a puppy mill, the usual
response is that those affected are “just animals” after all, and do not
merit our concern. Philosophical thinking on the moral standing of
animals is diverse and can be generally grouped into three general
categories: Indirect theories, direct but unequal theories, and moral
equality theories. Indirect theories deny animals’ moral status or equal
consideration with humans due to a lack of consciousness, reason, or
autonomy. Ultimately denying moral status to animals, these theories
may still require not harming animals, but only because doing so causes
harm to a human being's morality. Arguments in this category have
been formulated by philosophers such as Immanuel Kant, René
Descartes, Thomas Aquinas, Peter Carruthers, and various religious
theories. Direct but unequal theories accord some moral consideration to
animals, but deny them a fuller moral status due to their inability to
respect another agent's rights or display moral reciprocity within a
community of equal agents. Arguments in this category consider the
sentience of the animal as sufficient reason not to cause direct harm to
animals. However, where the interests of animals and humans conflict,
the special properties of being human such as rationality, autonomy, and
self-consciousness accord higher consideration to the interests of human
83
we cannot use it merely as a means to our ends. Instead, each such being
must be treated as an end in itself. In other words, a being with inherent
value has rights, and these rights act as trumps against the promotion of
the overall good. Regan relies on a version of the Argument from
Marginal Cases in arguing for this conclusion. He begins by asking what
grounds human rights. He rejects robust views that claim that a being
must be capable of representing itself as legitimately pursuing the
furtherance of its interests on the grounds that this conception of rights
implies that the marginal cases of humanity do not have rights.
However, since we think that these beings do have moral rights there
must be some other property that grounds these rights. According to
Regan, the only property that is common to both normal adult human
beings and the marginal cases is the property of being a subject-of-a-life.
A being that is a subject-of-a-life will: have beliefs and desires;
perception, memory, and a sense of the future, including their own
future; an emotional life together with feelings of pleasure and pain;
preference- and welfare-interests; the ability to initiate action in pursuit
of their desires and goals; a psychological identity over time; and an
individual welfare in the sense that their experiential life fares well or ill
for them, logically independently of their utility for others, and logically
independently of their being the object of anyone else's interests. This
property is one that all of the human beings that we think deserve rights
have; however, it is a property that many animals (especially mammals)
85
treated and how they are killed, we are using them as a means to our
ends and not treating them as ends in themselves. Thus, we may not
raise animals for food. Likewise, when we experiment on animals in
order to advance human science, we are using animals merely as a
means to our ends. Similar thoughts apply to the use of animals in
rodeos and the hunting of animals.
a. Singer and the Principle of Equal Consideration of Interests
Peter Singer has been very influential in the debate concerning animals
and ethics. The publication of his Animal Liberation marked the
beginning of a growing and increasingly powerful movement in both the
United States and Europe.
Singer attacks the views of those who wish to give the interests of
animals less weight than the interests of human beings. He argues that if
we attempt to extend such unequal consideration to the interests of
animals, we will be forced to give unequal consideration to the interests
of different human beings. However, doing this goes against the
intuitively plausible and commonly accepted claim that all human beings
are equal. Singer concludes that we must instead extend a principle of
equal consideration of interests to animals as well.
However, there are some properties which only human beings have
which have seemed to many to be able to ground a full and equal moral
status; for example, being rational, autonomous, or able to act morally
have all been used to justify giving a stronger status to human beings
87
than we do to animals. The problem with such a suggestion is that not all
human beings have these properties. So if this is what grounds a full and
equal moral status, it follows that not all human beings are equal after
all.
If we try to ensure that we choose a property that all human beings do
have that will be sufficient to ground a full and equal moral status, we
seemed to be pushed towards choosing something such as being sentient,
or being capable of experiencing pleasure and pain. Since the marginal
cases have this property, they would be granted a full and equal moral
status on this suggestion. However, if we choose a property of this kind,
animals will likewise have a full and equal moral status since they too
are sentient.
The attempt to grant all and only human beings a full and equal moral
status does not work according to Singer. We must either conclude that
not all human beings are equal, or we must conclude that not only
human beings are equal. Singer suggests that the first option is too
counter-intuitive to be acceptable; so we are forced to conclude that all
animals are equal, human or otherwise.
Another argument Singer employs to refute the claim that all and only
human beings deserve a full and equal moral status focuses on the
supposed moral relevance of such properties as rationality, autonomy,
the ability to act morally, etc. Singer argues that if we were to rely on
these sorts of properties as the basis of determining moral status, then we
88
eating meat, Singer argues that the interests the animals have in avoiding
this unimaginable pain and suffering is greater than the interests we have
in eating food that tastes good.
Singer does not unequivocally claim that we must not eat animals if we
are to correctly apply the Principle of Equal Consideration of Interests.
Whether we are required to refrain from painlessly killing animals will
depend on whether animals have an interest in continuing to exist in the
future. In order to have this interest, Singer believes that a being must be
able to conceive of itself as existing into the future, and this requires a
being to be self-conscious. Non-self-conscious beings are not harmed by
their deaths, according to Singer, for they do not have an interest in
continuing to exist into the future.
Singer argues that we might be able to justify killing these sorts of
beings with The Replaceability Argument. On this line of thought, if we
kill a non-self-conscious being that was living a good life, then we have
lessened the overall amount of good in the world. This can be made up,
however, by bringing another being into existence that can experience
similar goods. In other words, non-self-conscious beings are replaceable:
killing one can be justified if doing so is necessary to bring about the
existence of another. Since the animals we rear for food would not exist
if we did not eat them, it follows that killing these animals can be
justified if the animals we rear for food live good lives. However, in
order for this line of argumentation to justify killing animals, the animals
91
must not only be non-self-conscious, but they must also live lives that
are worth living, and their deaths must be painless. Singer expresses
doubts that all of these conditions could be met, and unequivocally
claims that they are not met by such places as factory farms.
Singer also condemns most experimentation in which animals are used.
He first points out that many of the experiments performed using animal
subjects do not have benefits for human beings that would outweigh the
pain caused to the animals. For example, experiments used to test
cosmetics or other non-necessary products for human beings cannot be
justified if we use the Principle of Equal Consideration of Interests.
Singer also condemns experiments that are aimed at preventing or curing
human diseases. If we are prepared to use animal subjects for such
experiments, then it would actually be better from a scientific point of
view to use human subjects instead, for there would be no question of
cross-species comparisons when interpreting the data. If we believe the
benefits outweigh the harms, then instead of using animals we should
instead use orphaned infants that are severely cognitively disabled. If we
believe that such a suggestion is morally repugnant when human beings
are to be used, but morally innocuous when animals are to be used, then
we are guilty of speciesism. Likewise, hunting for sport, using animals
in rodeos, keeping animals confined in zoos wherein they are not able to
engage in their natural activities are all condemned by the use of the
Principle of the Equal Consideration of Interests.
92
4.2.2 Animals
If only human beings have moral standing, then it follows that if I come
across a bear while out camping and shoot it dead on a whim, I do no
wrong to that bear. Of course, an anthropocentric ethic might claim that
I do somewrong by shooting the bear dead – perhaps, for example,
shooting bears is not the action of a virtuous individual, or perhaps I am
depleting a source of beauty for most other humans – but because
anthropocentrism states that only humans have moral standing, then I
can do no wrong tothe bear itself. However, many of us have the
intuition that this claim is wrong. Many of us feel that it is possible to do
wrong to animals, whether that be by shooting innocent bears or by
torturing cats. Of course, a feeling or intuition does not get us very far in
proving that animals have moral standing. For one thing, some people
(hunters and cat-torturers, for example!) no doubt have quite different
intuitions, leading to quite different conclusions. However, several
philosophers have offered sophisticated arguments to support the view
that moral standing should be extended to include animals.
Peter Singer and Tom Regan are the most famous proponents of the
view that we should extend moral standing to other species of animal.
While both develop quite different animal ethics, their reasons for
according moral status to animals are fairly similar. According to Singer,
the criterion for moral standing is sentience: the capacity to feel pleasure
and pain. For Regan, on the other hand, moral standing should be
93
These moral limits are ‘rights’, and are possessed by all creatures who
are subjects-of-a-life.
But what does all this have to do with environmental ethics? Well, in
one obvious sense animal welfare is relevant to environmental ethics
because animals exist within the natural environment and thus form part
of environmentalists’ concerns. However, extending moral standing to
animals also leads to the formulation of particular types of
environmental obligations. Essentially, these ethics claim that when we
consider how our actions impact on the environment, we should not just
evaluate how these affect humans (present and/or future), but also how
they affect the interests and rights of animals. For example, even if
clearing an area of forest were proven to be of benefit to humans both in
the short and long-term that would not be the end of the matter as far as
animal ethics are concerned; the welfare of the animals residing within
and around the forest must also be considered.
However, many environmental philosophers have been dissatisfied with
these kinds of animal-centered environmental ethics. Indeed, some have
claimed that animal liberation cannot even be considered a legitimate
environmental ethic. For these thinkers, all animal-centered ethics suffer
from two fundamental and devastating problems: first of all, they are too
narrowly individualistic; and secondly, the logic of animal ethics implies
unjustifiable interference with natural processes. As for the first point, it
is pointed out that our concerns for the environment extend beyond
95
Such conclusions not only seem absurd, but also inimical to the
environmentalist goal of preserving natural habitats and processes.
Having said all of this, I should not over-emphasize the opposition
between animal ethics and environmental ethics. Just because animal
ethicists grant moral standing only to conscious individuals that does not
mean that they hold everything else in contempt (Jamieson, 1998).
Holistic entities may not have independent moral standing, according to
these thinkers, but that does not equate to ignoring them; after all, the
welfare and interests of individual entities are often bound up with the
healthy functioning of the ‘wholes’ that they make up. Moreover, the
idea that animal ethics imply large-scale interferences in the
environment can be questioned when one considers how much harm this
would inflict upon predator and scavenger animals. Nevertheless,
clashes of interest between individual animals and other natural entities
are inevitable, and when push comes to shove animal ethicists will
invariably grant priority to individual conscious animals. Many
environmental ethicists disagree, and are convinced that the boundaries
of our ethical concern need to be pushed back further.
1.2.3 Individual Living Organisms
As noted above, numerous philosophers have questioned the notion that
only conscious beings have moral standing. Some have done this by
proposing a thought experiment based on a ‘last-human scenario. The
thought experiment asks us to consider a situation, say after a nuclear
97
which many living things lack. However, perhaps what Schweitzer was
getting at was something like Paul W. Taylor’s more recent claim that
all living things are ‘teleological centers of life’. For Taylor, this means
that living things have a good of their own that they strive towards, even
if they lack awareness of this fact. This good, according to Taylor, is the
full development of an organism’s biological powers. In similar
arguments to Regan’s, Taylor claims that because living organisms have
a good of their own, they have inherent value; that is, value for their own
sake, irrespective of their value to other beings. It is this value that
grants individual living organisms moral status, and means that we must
take the interests and needs of such entities into account when
formulating our moral obligations.
But if we recognize moral standing in every living thing, how are we
then to formulate any meaningful moral obligations? After all, don’t we
as humans require the destruction of many living organisms simply in
order to live? For example we need to walk, eat, shelter and clothe
ourselves, all of which will usually involve harming living things.
Schweitzer’s answer is that we can only harm or end the life of a living
entity when absolutely necessary. Of course, this simply begs the
question: when is absolutely necessary? Taylor attempts to answer this
question by advocating a position of general equality between the
interests of living things, together with a series of principles in the event
of clashes of interest. First off, the principles state that humans are
99
of plants? If it is low enough so that I can eat them, weed them and walk
on them, what is the point of granting them any moral standing at all?
There remain two crucial challenges facing philosophers who attribute
moral standing to individual living organisms that I have not yet
addressed. One challenge comes from the anthropocentric thinkers and
animal liberationists. They deny that ‘being alive’ is a sufficient
condition for the possession of moral standing. For example, while
plants may have a biological good, is it really good of their own? Indeed,
there seems to be no sense in which something can be said to be good or
bad from the point of view of the plant itself. And if the plant doesn’t
care about its fate, why should we? In response to this challenge,
environmental ethicists have pointed out that conscious volition of an
object or state is not necessary for that object or state to be a good. For
example, consider a cat that needs worming. It is very unlikely that the
cat has any understanding of what worming is, or that he needs worming
in order to remain healthy and fit. However, it makes perfect sense to
say that worming is good for the cat, because it contributes to the cat’s
functioning and flourishing. Similarly, plants and trees may not
consciously desire sunlight, water or nutrition, but each, according to
some ethicists, can be said to be good for them in that they contribute to
their biological flourishing.
The second challenge comes from philosophers who question the
individualistic nature of these particular ethics. As mentioned above,
101
these critics do not believe that an environmental ethic should place such
a high premium on individuals. Indeed, for many, this individualistic
stance negates important ecological commitments to the interdependence
of living things, and the harmony to be found in natural processes.
Moreover, it is alleged that these individualistic ethics suffer from the
same faults as anthropocentric and animal-centered ethics: they simply
cannot account for our real and demanding obligations to holistic entities
such as species and ecosystems. Once again, however, a word of caution
is warranted here. It is not the case that philosophers who ascribe moral
standing to individual living things simply ignore the importance of such
‘wholes’. Often the equilibrium of these entities is taken extremely
seriously. However, it must be remembered that such concern is
extended only insofar as such equilibrium is necessary in order for
individual living organisms to flourish; the wholes themselves have no
independent moral standing.
4.2.4 Holistic Entities
Although the centrality of holism in both ecology and environmental
ethics is indisputable, the meaning of the concept within each field is
difficult to define with precision.
Holism might be understood best in contrast to reductionism.
Reductionism is arguably the central approach to Western science,
traceable back to the ancient Greek Milesian school of thought (c. sixth
century B.C.E.), which attempted to discern the fundamental stuff out of
102
food chains conduct the energy upwards from the soil, death and decay
returns the energy back to the soil. Thus, the flow of energy relies on a
complex structure of relations between living things. While evolution
gradually changes these relations, Leopold argues that man’s
interventions have been much more violent and destructive. In order to
preserve the relations within the land, Leopold claims that we must
move towards a ‘land ethic’, thereby granting moral standing to the land
community itself, not just its individual members. This culminates in
Leopold’s famous ethical injunction: “A thing is right when it tends to
preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community. It is
wrong when it tends otherwise.”
Several philosophers, however, have questioned Leopold’s justification
of the land ethic. For one thing, it seems that Leopold jumps too quickly
from a descriptive account of how the land is, to a prescriptive account
of what we ought to do. In other words, even if Leopold’s accounts of
the land and its energy flows are correct, why should we preserve it?
What precisely is it about the biotic community that makes it deserving
of moral standing? Unfortunately, Leopold seems to offer no answers to
these important questions, and thus no reason to build our environmental
obligations around his land ethic. However, J. Baird Callicott has argued
that such criticisms of Leopold are unfair and misplaced. According to
Callicott, Leopold lies outside of mainstream moral theory. Rather than
assign moral standing on the identification of some particular
105
leaves the question of what to do when the interests of wholes clash with
the interests of individuals. If humans cannot be sacrificed for the good
of the whole, why can rabbits?
The answer that has been put forward by Callicott claims that while the
biotic community matters morally, it is not the only community that
matters. Rather, we are part of various ‘nested’ communities all of which
have claims upon us. Thus, our obligations to the biotic community may
require the culling of rabbits, but may not require the culling of humans.
This is because we are part of a tight-knit human community, but only a
very loose human-rabbit community. In this way, we can adjudicate
clashes of interest, based on our community commitments. This
communitarian proposal certainly seems a way out of the dilemma.
Unfortunately, it faces two key problems: first, just who decides the
content and strength of our various community commitments; and
second, if human relationships are the closest, does all this lead back to
anthropocentrism? As for the first point, if deciding on our community
attachments is left up to individuals themselves, this will lead to quite
diverse and even repugnant moral obligations. For example, if an
individual believes that he has a much stronger attachment to white
males than to black women, does this mean that he can legitimately
favor the interests of the former over the latter? If not, and an objective
standard is to be imposed, we are left with the enormous problem of
discovering this standard and reaching consensus on it. Secondly, if our
108
term metaphysic of subject and object is also fatal because it denies man
the meaning that he needs to live.
4.5 Radical Ecology
Not all philosophers writing on our obligations concerning the
environment see the problem simply in terms of extending moral
standing. Instead, many thinkers regard environmental concerns to have
warranted an entirely new ideological perspective that has been termed,
after its biological counterpart, ‘ecology’. While the ideas and beliefs
within this ‘radical ecology’ movement are diverse, they possess two
common elements that separate them from the ethical extensionism
outlined above. First of all, none see extending moral standing as
sufficient to resolve the environmental crisis. They argue that a broader
philosophical perspective is needed, requiring fundamental changes in
both our attitude to and understanding of reality. This involves
reexamining who we are as human beings and our place within the
natural world. For radical ecologists, ethical extensionism is inadequate
because it is stuck in the traditional ways of thinking that led to these
environmental problems in the first place. In short, it is argued that
ethical extensionism remains too human-centered, because it takes
human beings as the paradigm examples of entities with moral standing
and then extends outwards to those things considered sufficiently
similar. Secondly, none of these radical ecologies confine themselves
solely to the arena of ethics. Instead, radical ecologies also demand
119
calling for nothing less than the redirection of human history. Naess, like
Socrates, makes no claims to certainty. In word and deed, Naess instead
has inspired others to engage in deep philosophical questioning through
example.
Adherents of the deep ecology movement share a dislike of the human-
centered value system at the core of European and North American
industrial culture. Deep ecologists argue that environmental philosophy
must recognize the values that inhere objectively in nature independently
of human wants, needs or desires. The popularity of deep ecology spans
from headline grabbing environmental activists dressed in coyote
costumes to scholars of an astonishing assortment of backgrounds and
interests. Authors have made connections between deep ecology and
ecological science (Golley 1987), religions from around the world New
Age spirituality direct action/ecological sabotage (Foreman 1991), the
poetry of Robinson Jeffers (Sessions 1977), the land ethic of Aldo
Leopold (Devall and Sessions 1985), the monism of Baruch Spinoza
(Sessions 1977, 1979, 1985; Naess 2005), and the phenomenology of
Martin Heidegger (Zimmerman 1986). Such variety is invigorating, but
it makes it difficult to find the common thread in all these diverse
manifestations of deep ecology. As one commentator has observed,
anyone who attempts to reconcile Heidegger’s with Leopold’s
contributions to deep ecology finds the going rugged. (To differentiate
between the broad popular and narrow academic usages of deep ecology,
121
the term Deep Ecology will be used to denote the latter.) Much more
narrowly, deep ecology represents the psychologization of
environmental philosophy. Deep ecology in this sense refers to an
egalitarian and holistic environmental philosophy founded on
phenomenological methodology. By way of direct experience of
nonhuman nature, one recognizes the equal intrinsic worth of all biota as
well as one’s own ecological interconnectedness with the life world in
all its plenitude.
Understanding Deep Ecology in its academic sense demands reading the
work of four environmental philosophers: philosophers: the Norwegian
Arne Naess, the Americans George Sessions and David Rothenberg, and
the Australian Warwick Fox. Deep Ecology is inextricably associated
with Naess and owes its prominence to him. Naess’s many strengths—
strong will, humble demeanor, playful personality, estimable academic
reputation, aversion to judgment, predilection for inclusivity, and an odd
mix of interests—have stimulated many others to spend considerable
amounts of time, talent, and energy teasing out the nuances of his
creative insights.
Deep ecology is perhaps most easily understood when considered in
opposition to its ‘shallow’ counterpart. According to deep ecologists,
shallow ecology is anthropocentric and concerned with pollution and
resource depletion. Shallow ecology might thus be regarded as very
much the mainstream wing of environmentalism. Deep ecology, in
122
involves identifying ourselves with all other life forms on the planet.
The Australian philosopher Warwick Fox has taken up this theme of
self-realization in his own eco-philosophy, ‘transpersonal ecology’. Fox
does not regard environmental ethics to be predominantly about
formulating our moral obligations usual ethical concern of formulating
principles and obligations thus becomes unnecessary, according to Fox,
for once the appropriate consciousness is established, one will naturally
protect the environment and allow it to flourish, for that will be part and
parcel of the protection and flourishing of oneself.
Critics of deep ecology argue that it is just too vague to address real
environmental concerns. For one thing, in its refusal to reject so many
worldviews and philosophical perspectives, many have claimed that it is
difficult to uncover just what deep ecology advocates. For example, on
the one hand, Naess offers us eight principles that deep ecologists should
accept, and on the other he claims that deep ecology is not about
drawing up codes of conduct, but adopting a global comprehensive
attitude. Now, if establishing principles is important, as so many
ethicists believe, perhaps deep ecology requires more precision than can
be found in Naess and Sessions’s platform. In particular, just how are we
to deal with clashes of interests? According to the third principle, for
example, humans have no right to reduce the richness and diversity of
the natural world unless to meet vital needs. But does that mean we are
under an obligation to protect the richness and diversity of the natural
125
is, but quite another to say how society ought to be. Even if we accept
that there are no natural hierarchies within nature (which for many is
dubious), there are plenty of other aspects of it that most of us would not
want to foster in our human society. For example, weak individuals and
weak species are often killed, eaten and out-competed in an ecosystem.
This, of course, is perfectly natural and even fits in with ecology’s
characterization of nature as interconnected. However, should this
ground human societies in which the weak are killed, eaten and out-
competed? Most of us find such a suggestion repugnant. Following this
type of reasoning, many thinkers have warned of the dangers of drawing
inferences about how society should be organized from certain facts
about how nature is.
Some environmental philosophers have also pointed to a second problem
with Bookchin’s theory. For many, his social ecology is anthropocentric,
thus failing to grant the environment the standing it deserves. Critics cite
evidence of anthropocentrism in the way Bookchin accounts for the
liberation of both humans and nature. This unfolding process will not
just occur of its own accord, according to Bookchin; rather, human
beings must facilitate it. Of course, many philosophers are extremely
skeptical of the very idea that history is inevitably ‘unfolding’ towards
some particular direction. However, some environmental philosophers
are more wary of the prominent place that Bookchin gives to human
beings in facilitating this unfolding. Of course, to what extent this is a
137
thinkers would argue that rationalist thought is not the enemy, but
instead the best hope for securing proper concern for the environment
and for women. For as we have seen above, such thinkers believe that
relying on the sentiments and feelings of individuals is too unstable a
foundation upon which to ground a meaningful ethical framework.
Karen J. Warren has argued that the dualisms of rationalist thought, as
outlined by Plumwood, are not in themselves problematic. Rather,
Warren claims that they become problematic when they are used in
conjunction with an ‘oppressive conceptual framework’ to justify
subordination. Warren argues that one feature inherent within an
oppressive conceptual framework is the ‘logic of domination’. Thus, a
list of the differences between humans and nature, and between men and
women is not in itself harmful. But once assumptions are added, such as
these differences leading to the moral superiority of humans and of men,
then we move closer to the claim that we are justified in subordinating
women and nature on the basis of their inferiority. According to Warren,
just such logic of domination has been prevalent within western society.
Men have been identified with the realm of the ‘mental’ and ‘human’,
while women have been identified with the‘physical’ and the ‘natural’.
Once it is claimed that the ‘natural’ and the ‘physical’ are morally
inferior to the ‘human’ and ‘mental’, men become justified in
subordinating women and nature. For Warren then, feminists and
142