Feminist Legal Theory 1
Feminist Legal Theory 1
Feminist Legal Theory 1
Rothenberg
F
EMINISM SEEKS TO UNDERSTAN"TI AND TO VAL"C.t. the expe-
riences, insights, and logic of women's lives. Feminisr legal theory
provides a healthy skepticism toward traditional legal doctrine and
insists that we reexamine even formally gender-neutral rules to uncover
the problematic assumptions behind them. It also challenges the traGi-
tiona! split between private and public spheres, as well as rile way in
which traditional conceptions of justice translate into public policy.
Finally, feminist perspectives tend to value the importance of narrative,
thereby challengmg the traditionally "objective" approach ro case law
reporting. Stories put issues in context, just as case studies do for eiliicists
and health care providers, and hence help us to challenge the assumptions
we make about individuals and the role of the law in their li•.!es.
These important themes are reflected in a diversity of feminist legal
theories. 1 In this article, I outline the major feminist theories in order to
Liberal Feminism
Liberal feminism is based on a belief in formal gender equality, par-
ticularly in the economic and political arenas (see, e.g., Ginsburg 1971,
1975; Williams 1982). Since women possess the same capabilities as
men, liberal feminists claim that women should be entitled to equal
rights, equal employment opportunities, and equal pay.· Under this
equality model, gender classifications are ro be challenged because they
reflect and reinforce stereotypes that fail ro treat men and women as
individuals. Liberal feminism draws heavily on the notions of rationali-
ty, individual autonomy, and choice that are central to liberal political
theory. Thus, liberal feminists have focused primarily on the goals of
eliminating state-imposed gender distinctions and of preventing the state
from limiting individual choice.
One significant source of law for liberal feminist theory ~ the Equal
Protection Clause of the 14th Amendment to the U.S. Constitution,
which provides that no state shall deny to any. person, equal protection
of the law. Simply put, similarly situated persons, namely men. and
women, should be treated equally. Advocates for women's equality first
tried, unsuccessfully, to utilize the Equal Protection Clause almost 125
years ago w6en a woman was refused the right to practice law (Bradwell
v. Illinois, 83 U.S. (16 Wall.) 130, 21 L.Ed. 442 (1872); In re Goodell,
39 Wis. 232 (1875)), and then again at the rum of the century to chal-
lenge "protective" labor laws that limited the number ol hours women
could work (Muller v. Oregon, 208 U.S. 412 (1908)). In both types of
cases, the court justified treating women differently from men based on
women's physical and mental attributes, their "nature," and their sup-
posed need to be protected.
[ 70 ]
ROTHENBERG • FEMINISM. LAW, A..""'D BIOETHICS
It was not until the early 1970s that tenets of liberal feminism began
to take hold in the courts. The first case defending women's rights on lib-
eral feminist grounds invalidated a statutory preference for men over
women in the appointment of estate administrators (Reed v. Reed, 404
U.S. 71 (1971)). Many cases soon followed that challenged the constitu-
tionality of laws that treated men and women differenrly and that advo-
cated applying a higher standard of scrutiny to such cases. Ironically,
many of the successful test cases were brought by men who claimed that
various laws were unfair and unconsrirurional-for instance, laws
requiring men to meet more stringent tests of spousal dependency in
order to claim government benefits (Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S.
677 (1973)), laws establishing a higher legal drinking age for men (Craig
v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976)), and laws rendering men ineligible for
alimony (Orr v. Orr, 440 U.S. 268 (1979)).
Concurrently, activists and the courts began ro ciiscover additional
protections in the Equal Pay Act of 1963 129 U.S.C.-~. §§206{d), 216-
217), which mandated that employers pay women the same wages as
men holding the same jobs, and in Title VII of the Civil Rights Ac: of
1964 (42 U.S.C.A. §2000e et seq.), which bannec sex discrimination in
employment and labor organizations. By 1971, the Supreme Court
upheld a finding of sex discrimination under Title Vll when an employ-
er refused to hire mothers but not fathers with preschool children
(Phillips v. Martin Marietta Corp., 400 U.S. 542 1971)).
Perhaps the biggest challenge for liberal feminists has involved issues
that relate to pregnancy and childbearing. In 19-4, the Supreme Court
upheld the constitutionality of a comprehensive stare disability insurance
plan that excluded benefits for pregnancy ( Geduldig t-·. Aiello, 417 U.S.
484 (1974)) and, in 1976, held that an employer ·was not in violation of
Title VII when medical benefits did not include COStS associated ·with
pregnancy (General Electric Co. v. Gilbert, 429 U.S. 125 (19-6)).
Following these two rulings, feminists lobbied Congress to pass the
PregnanH Discrimination Act of 1978 (42 U.S.C.A. 52000e(k)), which
specifically states that sex discrimination under Title vn includes dis-
tinctions based on pregnancy, childbirth, or related medical conditions.
The Supreme Court has since held that an emplo::er's feral-protection
policy that excluded fertile women from cerrain jobs constituted sex dis-
crimination under Title VII (International Union, UAW v. johnson
Controls, Inc., 499 U.S. 187 (1991)), bur it has nor issued any similar
rulings based on a constitutional analysis.
( 7I )
KENNEDY INS1111ITE OF ETHICS JOURNAL • MARCH I996
Cultural Feminism
[ 72 ]
ROTHENBERG • FEMINISM, LAW, AND BIOETIIICS
equipped than the adversarial court system to foster and maintain fami-
ly and physician-patient relationships. Similarly, cultural feminists have
suggested that courts apply a feminist ethic of care when determining
standards of negligence in order to recognize a duty to rescue strangers
where none currently exists {Bender 1988}. In order to promote and sup-
port a caring society, they argue, why should health care professionals
not have a legal duty to have to srop by the side of the road and provide
medical assistance to a person injured in an automobile accident?
Cultural feminists also have challenged the categorization of physician-
assisted suicide as "a criminal act of murder," rather than as "an act of
caring" that would alleviate pain and suffering {Bender 1992).
Cultural feminism may also question current standards of proper
informed consent. Currently, standards of informed consem: require the
disclosure of information that a "reasonable person"" would want to
know in order to make an informed decision. However; if men and
women think and speak in "different voices," there may be no one com-
mon conception of a reasonable person. Indeed, current conceptions of
such a person tend to reflect a masculine notion oi reasonability, and
cultural feminists urge that we expand this notion to indude women's
values.
Radical Feminism
[ 73 ]
KENNEDY INS1TI1i'TE OF ETHICS JOURNAL • MARCH I996
Postmodern Feminism
Postmodern feminism is a more recent addition to feminist discourse.
This perspective rejects the assumptions and generalizations at the core
of the preceding feminist theories. According to postmodern feminists,
no objective reality can describe the "essential" woman; consequently,
such feminists embrace the particular "situated" realities of all individ-
ual women. Postmodernists encourage feminists to consider real life
experiences influenced by each woman's race, class, age, and sexual ori-
entation (see Frug 1992; Bartlett 1994, pp. 13-18; Cain 199<):; pp. 838-
41 ). Critical legal feminist scholars have incorporated themes of post-
modernism by rejecting abstract universal theory and embracing the
need f~r a social policy that provides practical and just solutions to real
life problems (see, e.g., Rhode 1990; Radin 1990).
How might the three major feminist theories enrich the debate over
contemporary issues in bioethics and public policy? Here I shall consid-
er the issue of egg "donation," a process more accurately described as
the harvesting of eggs from one woman, usually with compensation, by
[ 74 ]
ROTHENBERG • FEMINISM. LAW, AND BIOETHICS
an IVF clinic for use by a contracting woman and/or couple who desires
the birth of a baby. How might each feminist theory help us to frame and
answer the questions raised by the process?
The liberal feminist would frame the issue in terms of the similarities
and differences in the roles men and women face in such situations. For
instance, although men do not donate or sell eggs, they do donate and
sell sperm; since men can sell sperm and liberal feminists want to pro-
mote choice, perhaps women should be able to sell their reproductive
material as well. If we allow a marker for sperm, why not allow a mar-
ket for eggs? On the other hand, liberal feminists will call our attention
to the extent to which egg and sperm donation are not truly analogous.
For example, egg retrieval is much more complex, risky, and time-con-
suming than is sperm donation. Thus, proper compensation would be
greater for the sale of eggs, but not so great as to preclude economic
arrangements between the infertile and those who want to sell their eggs.
As part of promoting "procreative liberty," however, the liberal feminist
will argue that it is important to have an informed consent process in
place that clearly spells out the benefits and risks of the procedure both
to the woman supplying the eggs and to the woman receiving them, as
well as the intent of all parries. For example, the woman who agrees to
have her eggs extracted should have no expectation of maternal rights.
and, absent a prior rdationship, no involvement with the intended moth-
er or any future child. Such policies would closely parallel those cur-
rently in place for sperm donation. Given full disclosure and a fair and
reasonable compensation scheme, liberal feminists would support a pub-
lic policy that recognizes egg donation as a choice for women.
In contrast, cultural" feminists might frame the issue by asking what
impact egg donation would have on family relationships, furu.~;._e connec-
tions, and the role of motherhood. If egg donation is viewed as a para-
digm in which altruistic women help infertile women to become moth-
ers, the cultural feminist might support it in the context of a noncom-
mercial 5.rrangement. Egg donation would be characterized as a caring
gesture, involving an open arrangement in which the relationship among
both women and any offspring could continue to grow. On the other
hand, cultural feminists are not likely ro support a market for women's
eggs by IVF clinics. Such a scheme might be viewed as commodifying
motherhood and undermining caring relationships.
Radical feminists, finally, would be very suspicious of egg donation.
Whereas artificial insemination can be done with a turkey baster, egg
[ 75 ]
KENNEDY INSTITIITE OF ETHICS JOUIU../AL • MARCH I996
[ 76 ]
ROTHENBERG • FEMINISM, LAW, ANTI BIOETI-nCS
[ 77 ]
KENNEDY INSTIThTI OF ETHICS JOURNAL • MARCH !996
each of the feminist theories. Liberal feminisrs would argue that such a
pregnancy clause would violate the constitutional rights of pregnant
women and would make bad public policy. Cultural feminists might
argue that the state should not impose irs judgment on that of the preg-
nant woman who is the one best equipped to evaluate her needs in the
context of her relationships. Radical feminists would object to a law that
subordinates pregnant women to the state in the determination of what
is best for her and her fetus. In spire of such concerns, members of the
drafting committee believed that maintaining the pregnancy clause
might prove to be a nonnegotiable issue with the Catholic Conference
and ultimately with the Maryland Legislature.
A second problem with the proposal was its inclusion of provisions
that appeared gender neutral on their face but proved nor to be on clos-
er inspection. The proposal declared that the state has an interest in
ensuring that the welfare of minor children not be impaired as a result
of a competent individual's decision to withhold or withdraw life-sus-
taining procedures (Hoffmann 1994, pp. 1074-75). Thus, although the
proposal declared that a competent individual has a right to refuse life-
sustaining medical treatment, it stated that if the individual was the sole
provider of a minor child and life-sustaining treatment would allow the
individual to continue to care for the child, that individual would have
to seek court approval before being permitted to refuse life support. The
provision considered neither the nature of the proposed treatment nor
the religious conviction of the individual (Hoffmann 1994, pp. 1070-71,
n. 19). Although the term "individual" includes both men and W<>f?en,
in fact the large majority of sole providers of minor children are
women--often women who are suffering from HIV/AIDS . ..Thus, this
provision had an unfair and disparate impact on women. This reality
was broughtrto the attention of the committee by a number of public
interest lawyers, almost aU of whom were women.
Third, and more generally, many of the proposal's provisions
appeared to excessively burden the family in the decision-making
process by requiring a legalistic rather than a supportive approach to
family relationships. The approach taken reflected a presumption that
the state needs to protect the individual from harm in every possible sit-
uation: for example, family members would have to go to court under
delineated conditions to prove that their ill relative would have wanted
to discontinue life support or that doing so would be in the relative's best
ROTHENBERG • FEMINISM, LAW, AND BIOETHICS
[ 79 ]
KENNEDY INSTITIJfE OF ETHICS JOUR."iAL • MARCH I 996
ical decision making should establish the presumption that family and
friends with close relationships to the patient are best able to give voice
to a family member or friend with limited decision-making capacity. As
we all agreed, most individuals do nor sign advanced directives or write
their wishes down, but that does not mean that only a court can protect
their interests. Not having filled out a form should not mean that your
family has no voice to act on your behalf. Rather, when a health care
provider, institution, or the state wants w challenge the decision of a sur-
rogate, they should have the burden to petition the court, not the other
way around. Obviously, there may be times when an individual needs
the court's protection, but these circumstances should be regarded as the
exception rather than the rule. In addition, I urged that the patient care
advisory committee may serve as an alternative to the judicial process to
mediate such matters. Clearly, the perspectives of cultural feminism
helped to frame the deference to family decision making and the shift
from a presumption of distrust and protectionism to one of trust and
support of caring relationships.
Following this analysis, I focused i:nore specifically on the gender
implications of the proposal and its distrust of women. Not only were
families not to be trusted, but pregnant women would not be able to
exercise their right tO have a living will respected and sole care givers of
minor children, the majority of whom are women, would not be able to
terminate life-sustaining treatment without the court's approval. As a
result, the proposal created these women differently from all other com-
petent individuals.
Many other participants at the conference expressed significant prob-
lems with the content and approach of the committee proposal. As a
result, a coalition was formed to draft an alternative. The coalition
included representatives of the elderly, women's groups, an Alzheimer's
association, and a number of medical, hospital, and legal organizations.
As I would later testify at a hearing on the issue, the original proposal
had ignored reality because it failed to recognize that not all feelings and
.I
contingencies can be codified (Hoffmann 1994, p. 1104); the alternative
proposal was much shorter, simpler, and less legalistic. Further, the coali-
tion's alternative shifted the presumption to trusting the family, not the
state, to make decisions. To the extent that safeguards were included, it
was felt that they should not overly burden care givers making decisions
for incapacitated patients. Even though some recent empirical data sug-
gest that surrogates may not make the same decisions that patients
[ 8o ]
ROTHENBERG • FEMINISM. LAW, AND BIOETHICS
would make for themselves, many individuals still prefer that their fam-
ily members, rather than physicians and judges, make these decisions
(Hoffmann 1994, p. 1102, n. 151, 152).
This shift in presumption to one of trust in caring relationships per-
meated the coalition proposal. The coalition proposal extended the con-
ditions under which a surrogate could make decisions to withhold or
withdraw life support and gave a clear decision-making priority to those
most likely to be closest to the patient (Hoffmann 1994, p. 1093). It rec-
ognized that a close friend, and not just family members, might have the
authority to make decisions for an incompetent patient. It expanded the
use of an oral advanced directive to include appointment of a health care
proxy. The coalition proposal also prohibited a health care provider
from overriding the instructions of a surrogate without first going to
court and proving that the surrogate was not following statutory guide-
lines for decision making (Hoffmann 1994). The proposal modified the
guardianship law to allow a guardian to authorize the withholding or
withdrawal of life support without court approval if the patient had exe-
cuted an advanced directive, and it treated artificial feeding and hydra-
tion like other forms of life-sustaining treatment. Further, both the coali-
tion proposal and the committee's final proposal eliminated the provi-
sion that required competent individuals who were the sole care givers
of minor children to seek court approval for termination of life-support
decisions. Finally, and significantly, the coalition proposal did not
include a clause restricting the right of pregnant women to have their
advance directives followed.
Ultimately, the Maryland Legislature considered modifications of
both proposals. Political compromise resulted in the passage of the
Maryland Health Care Decisions Act on May 12, 1993. The statute
incorporated advanced directive forms that do include a section allow-
ing women to write additional instructions concerning pregnancy. -If the
section is left blank, it is presumed that her choice of treatment will be
the same independent of whether she is pregnant. More generally, the
legislation ldopted the approach of the coalition proposal to presume
trust of care givers rather than courts with a few additional safeguards
(Hoffmann 1994, pp. 1108-30).
This legislative approach, which shifts reliance from rbe court to the
family, may have significant gender implications. An analysis of "right-
to-die" cases by Miles and August (1990) found asymmetric gender pat-
terned reasoning in which judges were less likely to consider evidence of
[ 8I )
KENNEDY INSTITUTE OF ETHICS JOURNAL • MARCH I996
I wish to thank my colleagues ]ana Singer and Diane Hoffmann for theiN_nsighrs and
expertise, Maggie Little for her thoughtful comments and suggestions, and the other fac-
ulty and participants at the Kennedy Institute's Feminist Perspectives on Bioerhics course
for their collaborative spirit.
,
NOTES
1. See Rothenberg (1995). The analytical framework for describing the major
feminist theories was crafted in part from the following outstanding works:
Feminist Legal Theory: Foundations (Weisberg 1993); Feminist Legal
Theory: Readings in Law and Gender (Bartlett and Kennedy 1991); "Gender
Law" (Bartlett 1994), "Feminist Jurisprudence: Grounding the Theories"
(Cain 1989); and "Feminism and the Limits of Equality" (Cain 1990).
[ 82 ]
ROTHENBERG • FEMINISM, LAW, AND BIOETHICS
REFERENCES
Bartlett, Katharine T. 1994. Gender Law. Duke journal of Gender Law &
Policy 1: 1-18.
- - - , and Kennedy, Roseanne, eds. 1991. Feminist Legal Theory: Readings
in Law and Gender. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Bender, Leslie. 1988. A Lawyer's Primer on Feminist Theory and Tort. journal
of Legal Education 38: 3-37.
- - - . _1990. From Gender Difference to Feminist Solidarity: Using Carol
Gilligan and an Ethic of Care in the Law. Vermont Law Review 15: 1-48.
- - - . 1992. A Feminist Analysis of Physician-Assisted Dying and Voluntary
Active Euthanasia. Tennessee Law Review 59: 519-46.
Cain, Patricia. 1989. Feminist Jurisprudence: Grounding the Theories. Berkeley
Women's Law journa/4: 191-214.
- - - . 1990. Feminism and the Limits of Equality. Georgia Law Review 24:
803-47.
Carbone, June R. 1994. Feminist Perspective on Divorce. The Future of
Children 4: 183-209.
Frug, Mary Joe. 1992. Postmodern Legal Feminism. New York: Routledge.
Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's
Development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Ginsburg, Ruth Bader. 1971. Sex and Unequal Protection: Men & WoiTJ:<:n as
Victims. journal of Family Law 11: 347-62.
- - - . 1975. Gender & the Constitution. University of Cincinnati Law
Review 44: 1-44.
Hoffmann, Di'}Ile. 1994. The Maryland Health Care Decisions Act: Achieving
the Right Balance. Maryland Law Review 53: 1065-1130.
Law, Sylvia A. 1984. Rethinking Sex and the Constitution. University of
Pennsylvania Law Review 132: 955-1040. ,
Littleton, Christine A. 1987. Reconstructing Sexual Equality. California Law
Review 75: 1279-1337.
- - - . 1989. Feminist Jurisprudence: The Difference Method Makes. Stanford
Law Review 41: 751-84.
KENNEDY INSTmiTE OF ETHICS JOURNAL • MARCH I996