National Law University Odisha, Cuttack: Book Review
National Law University Odisha, Cuttack: Book Review
BOOK REVIEW
On
SUBMITTED TO
1
CONTENTS
1 INTRODUCTION 3
2 5
BRIEF SUMMARY
3 CRITICAL EVALUATION 37
INTRODUCTION
The new collection of essays by Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle, expands and
delves into the arguments of his earlier collection, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard
University Press, 1977). In this new book, Dworkin responds to the critiques that have
been addressed to the thoughts expressed in his earlier volume. At the same time, he
develops his thinking and makes his philosophy clear.
The book is divided into six parts; further sub-divided into 19 Chapters.
Part One and Two "The Political Basis of Law" and "Law as Interpretation", directly
support the foundation of Taking Rights Seriously. In addition, Dworkin discusses the
distinction between decision-making principles, decisions based on the interests of
defendants and litigants, judicial conceptions of the law and fundamental political
principles of the regime, and decisions based on policy or utility. He also elaborates in
more detail on his particularly provocative and controversial argument that judges should,
and most often decide "hard cases" through principled decisions.
Dworkin's next series of essays discusses the proper judicial approach in deciding cases.
Dworkin agrees with positivists that, when the rules are clear, they control and, in such
cases, litigants are entitled to a decision consistent with these rules. In cases where no rule
clearly controls, Dworkin breaks away from positivism and insists that there is a unique
and correct response. The answer lies in the examination of the principle or principles that
apply to the case.
Part Three is entitled as "Liberalism and Justice," in which Dworkin discusses the
political right to equal concern and respect that, in his view, is our central individual right
and the foundation of the Anglo-American tradition of rights. In "Liberalism", Dworkin
contends that the right to equal concern and respect is the heart of liberalism as a political
philosophy.
Dworkin therefore rejects utilitarianism, wealth maximization, the intention of the
drafters of the Constitution and the commitment to treat as central foundations in the
pursuit of principles. Instead, he turns to what he sees as the core principle from which
everything else seems to flow. In Dworkin's opinion, this is the principle of equality. In
particular, he believes that all citizens have the right to government treatment that gives
them equality of dignity and respect.
Part Four titled as "The Economic View of Law". Dworkin takes on Posner, Calibresi,
and their fellow countrymen, who argue that the law in general, and judges in particular,
should aim to increase the total richness of the community. In two technical essays,
Dworkin defends his view that rights are to be assigned on the basis of justice or equal
concern and respect, not communal wealth maximization, and argues that the whole
economic approach to law "lacks any defensible philosophical base.
In the end, Dworkin's commitment to neutrality and equality should allow for one
fundamental exception. There is no neutrality when it comes to the principle of neutrality,
and there is no equality when it comes to the principle of inequality.
Fortunately, they are followed by Parts Five and Six, where Dworkin joins
contemporary political discussions on reverse discrimination and press freedom. The
three essays on reverse discrimination strongly and subtly call for affirmative action
programs, including those using racial quotas.
BRIEF SUMMARY
The author then come finally to policy-based civil disobedience. When the actors seek to
reverse a policy because they believe the policy, they oppose is a bad policy for everyone,
not just for some minority; they think they know what is in the majority’s own interest, as
well as their own, better than the majority knows. He then distinguishes persuasive from
non-persuasive strategies in this new context. Persuasive strategies aim to convince the
majority that its decision, about its own best interests, is wrong, and so to disfavour the
program it formerly favoured. Non-persuasive strategies aim rather to increase the price
the majority must pay for a program it continues to favour. The distinction between
persuasive and no persuasive strategies is even more important in the case of policy-based
than justice-based disobedience, because it seems problematic that non-persuasive
strategies could ever be justified in a working theory of the former.
He then analysed Would the fact that we believed this justify illegal acts whose point was
to impose so high a price, in inconvenience and insecurity, that the majority would
abandon its economic policy, though it remained convinced that it was the best policy?
Author said no. But of course, the risks of bad nuclear strategy are vastly greater than
the risks of mistaken economic policy.
Should people who act out of civil disobedience court punishment or even demand to be
punished? Author then stated that Socrates was wrong in thinking that civil disobedience
is incomplete without punishment, without the actor presenting himself and it cannot be
sound when we are considering integrity-based disobedience. Punishment may of course
be part of the strategy when disobedience is justice- or policy-based.
So, author finally concluded that the law properly understood might support what we call
civil disobedience, can be an effective argument only when we reject this aspect of
positivism and insist that, though the courts may have the last word in any particular case
about what the law is, the last word is not for that reason alone the right word.
CHAPTER V: IS THERE REALLY NO RIGHT ANSWER IN HARD
CASES?
This chapter starts with the question i.e., Is there no right answer to a question of law?
Suppose Tom and Tim have signed a contract on Sunday, and Tom now sues Tim to
enforce the terms of the contract, whose validity Tom contests. Does it is necessary for
the judges to look for the right answer to the question of whether Tom’s contract is valid,
even though the community is deeply divided about what the right answer is? Or is it
more realistic to say that there simply is no right answer to the question? This is a
significant topic in various disagreements over what the law is. Many titles discussed,
including the issue of whether in hard cases judges always have discretion and whether
what some legal philosophers call "lapses" in the law are present. According to author,
the following characteristic are found in legal terms, such as the definition of a binding
contract, civil liability and crime: if the concept is in any given case, judge have at least a
prima facie requirement to rule on a legal claim; but if the concept does not exist, then
judges must decide on an individual basis. Those are called "dispositive" concepts.
For example, lawyers tend to be assuming that an agreement of promises is a legitimate
contract, or is not. If it does, judges would at least have a prima facie obligation, if
demanded under its jurisdiction, to uphold those promises; but if does not, they at least
have a prima facie duty not to do so for contractual purposes. But is it true that an
exchange of promises always either does or does not constitute a valid contract, or that
someone always is either liable or not liable in tort, or guilty or not guilty of a crime?
Author then distinguished two versions of no-right-answer thesis. According to the first
version, the third alternative in the legal issue also ignores that an exchange of
promises may not be a valid contract, such that judges have a duty to enforce the
exchange, nor a contract that is not valid, with the consequence that judges have a duty
not to enforce it, that may be considered an "inchoate" contract. In the other hand, the
second version of the thesis of no-response implies that, in that context, no logical
space occurs between proposals that a contract is valid and not valid or that a person is
responsible or that a crime is or isn't. It believes there's no third way, but refuses that
one of the two alternatives is always available so one of them can't be valid.
If one of the thesis versions is correct, it may be wrong to say that either party has the
right to decide and the right to accept that there is the judge's discretion in either way.
There are also numerous lawsuits. Yet this major disparity remains. In the case of the first
version, the law affirms this discretion, since the law distinguishes circumstances under
which the exchange of promises, for example, falls into a separate, consequent category
of discretion. On the other hand, when the second version is discreet, the judge must do
what is required, not in affirmative but by default: because the law does not stipulate
anything, even discretion.
Author said that wealth maximization will encourage respect for individual rights. A
society that sets out to maximize social wealth will require some assignment of rights to
property, labour because wealth is measured by what people are willing to pay, in money
or its equivalent, but no one can pay what he does not own, or borrow if he has nothing
to pledge or if others have nothing to lend. According to the economic analysis of law,
rights should be assigned instrumentally, in such a way that the assignment of rights will
advance wealth maximization. Economic analysis does not suppose that there is some
independent moral argument in favour of giving or withholding that right. So, it cannot be
claimed, in favour of economic analysis, that it points to what is independently, on moral
grounds, the right answer. On the contrary, it claims that the right answer is right only
because the answer increases social wealth.
The theory selected must be a patterned rather than a historical theory, to use Robert
Nozick’s useful distinction. Historical theories argue that a distribution is just, whatever
inequalities or other features it displays, if it is reached in accordance with correct
principles of justice in acquisition and transfer. Patterned theories argue that a distribution
is just only if it conforms to some pattern that can be specified apart from the history of
how that distribution occurred. Wealth maximization specifies a patterned rather than a
historical test for the assignment of rights. It is almost incoherent to propose that a
patterned distribution might be instrumental in achieving a historically contingent
distribution. The defender of wealth must choose some patterned conception of justice,
like highest utility, equality, maximin, meritocracy, or desert.
Finally, the author stated that the instrumental claims for wealth maximization are
more plausible if they are harnessed to one of the nonmeritocratic-patterned theories of
justice, such as utility or maximin, than to anything else. They cannot then be ruled
out conceptually as Posner’s instrumental claims can be.
Therefore, the argument of economic analysis, that judges decide hard cases so as to
maximize social wealth, is not a genetic, chemical, neurological explanation. It is true
that something like an invisible hand explanation of why common law decisions promote
social wealth has been offered but this is not part of the claims of Posner, Calabresi, or
other proponents of economic analysis. Economic analysis has never been presented as a
Freudian analysis. But even if it had, that analysis would presuppose the sense of a
straightforward claim. So economic analysis, seems to rest on the sense and the truth of a
straightforward motivational claim, which is that judges decide cases with the intention
of maximizing social wealth. It follows that the descriptive claims of economic analysis
are radically incomplete. If they are to have descriptive power, they must be recast in
some way appropriate to a weak instrumental claim. They must pick out particular
classes of judicial decisions and explain why it was plausible for judges to suppose that a
rule improving social wealth was likely to advance some independent social goal these
judges valued— utility, maximin, the relief of poverty, the economic power of the
country in foreign affairs, or some other goal.
Allan Bakke was himself refused admission to two other medical schools, not because of
his race but because of his age: these schools thought that a student entering medical
school at the age of thirty-three was likely to make less of a contribution to medical care
over his career than someone entering at the standard age of twenty-one. The Davis
medical school permitted whites to apply for the sixteen places reserved for members of
“educationally or economically disadvantaged minorities,”. In fact, several whites have
applied, though none has been accepted, and the California Court found that the special
committee charged with administering the program had decided, in advance, against
admitting any.
Every citizen has a constitutional right that he not suffers disadvantage, at least in the
competition for any public benefit, because the race or religion or sect or region or other
natural or artificial group to which he belongs is the object of prejudice or contempt.
That is a fundamentally important constitutional right, and it is that right that was
systematically violated for many years by racist exclusions and anti-Semitic quotas.
There is no suggestion in that program that Bakke shares in any collective or individual
guilt for racial injustice in the United States; or that he is any less entitled to concern or
respect than any black student accepted in the program. He has been disappointed, and
he must have the sympathy due that disappointment, just as any other disappointed
applicant. Each is disappointed because places in medical schools are scarce resources
and must be used to provide what the more general society most needs. It is not Bakke’s
fault that racial justice is now a special need but he has no right to prevent the most
effective measures of securing that justice from being used.
After reading this book, I came across with few criticisms. Some of them are: -
Dworkin argued principle are based on rights; he claims that “particular programs
must be carried out or abandoned because of their impact on particular
people, even if the community as a whole is somehow worse off as a result.”
On the other hand, policy is based on goals; he “try to show that the
community as a whole would be better off if a particular program were
pursued.” He says when there will be conflict between goals and rights, then
“policy must yield to principle.” But then, he didn’t refine this distinction
properly and illustrate its use everywhere in the book.
Similarly, in the essays on positive and reverse discrimination, Dworkin
argues that no principle based on individual rights can be found to conflict
with the goal of affirmative action. Thus, rather than deciding wholesale for or
against discriminatory measures, we must judge various programs of
affirmative action one by one, by weighing practical costs and benefits. The
distinction is used to similar effect in the essay on nuclear protest, where
Dworkin separates civil disobedience based on policy disagreements from
disobedience based on principle, and suggests that the law should be enforced
leniently against protesters who stand on principle. After all, he doesn’t define
what is mean by “principle”?
Dworkin first emerged as a critic of two fundamental claims of Hart's: that law in
a country can be identified according to an ultimate rule of recognition implicitly
accepted and applied by officials; and that, in situations in which existing legal
criteria do not resolve a case, judges have a legislative-like discretion to make new
law. Dworkin's response was that judges are always trying to discover the law, not
make it, and that what is law must be understood in terms of the set of principles
that would best justify existing legal materials. Here Dworkin totally disregard the
judge made laws.
Dworkin's basic account of interpretation as integrity was also criticised heavily.
He rejects the alternative of pragmatism and proposes that it can never be legally
correct for a judge to promote desirable future consequences at the expense of the
decision indicated by integrity. There are two serious weaknesses in Dworkin's
defence of this position. The first being for example, many people assume that the
best possible personal morality includes deontological and consequentialist
elements which interrelate in ways not precisely definable; Dworkin really does
not come to terms with the possibility of a similarly pluralist account of legal
interpretation. The second weakness is the failure to integrate what is said with an
important component of an appellate judge's role in the United States, the search
for majority opinions. Dworkin's general position about conscious deviations from
the result required by law as integrity is that such deviations are unambiguously
contrary to law.
In one of his essays, he says that there is always a right answer in hard cases even
though the correctness of the right answer cannot always be made absolutely clear.
In attempting to answer this question, Dworkin points to the fact that attorneys
invariably frame their arguments as assertions that their clients have the right to a
favourable decision, rather than arguing that the judge should merely exercise his
or her discretion in favour of their clients. So, it was criticised on the ground that it
places a stronger duty on judges to decide cases and explain their decisions in light
of an intellectually honest and rigorous analysis. It does not allow judges to
assume that their own preferences may properly come into play. Moreover,
Dworkin's position allows us to criticize judicial decisions in hard cases not
merely upon the grounds that they are unwise as a matter of policy, but also upon
the grounds that they are wrong. So, under Dworkin's philosophy, hard cases have
right answers and those answers are to be found in principles, not policies.