The Meaning of Monuments and Their Historical Development
The Meaning of Monuments and Their Historical Development
The Meaning of Monuments and Their Historical Development
Source: Aloïs Riegl, Moderne Denkmalkultus : sein Wesen und seine Entstehung, (Wien: K. K.
Zentral-Kommission für Kunst- und Historische Denkmale : Braumüller, 1903). Translation first
published as Aloïs Riegl, ''The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Character and Its Origin,'' trans.
Kurt W. Forster and Diane Ghirardo, in Oppositions, n. 25 (Fall 1982), 21-51.
Monument is some form of a human creation, erected for a specific purpose. A work of art can possess an artistic value if it is palpable,
visual or audible
creation of man; and a historical monument with such physical characteristics has historical value. HISTORICAL
1
VALUE- in a very broad sense, every historical event, activity, monument that we have knowledge constitutes a small link in the chain
of development. Every work of art is a historical monument
represents a specific stage in the development of the visual arts. In the strictest sense, no real
equivalent can ever be substituted for it. Conversely, every historical monument is also an art
monument, because even a secondary literary monument like a scrap of paper with a brief and
insignificant note contains a whole series of artistic elements-the form of the piece of paper, the
letters, and their composition-which apart from their historical value are relevant to the
development of paper, writing, writing instruments, etc. To be sure, these are such insignificant
elements that for the most part we neglect them in many cases because we have enough other
monuments which convey much the same thing in a richer and more detailed manner. But were
this scrap of paper the only surviving testimony to the art of its time, we would consider it,
though trivial in itself, an utterly indispensable artifact. To the extent that it is present, the artistic
element of such a document interests us only from a historical point of view: such monuments
are indispensable links in the development of art history. The "art monument" in this sense is
really an "art-historical monument"; its value from this point of view is not so much artistic as
historical. It follows that the differentiation of "artistic" and "historical" monuments is
inappropriate because the latter at once contains and suspends the former.
But do we really appreciate only the historical value of a work of art? If this were so, then
all the art from all epochs would have the same value in our view and would only increase in
value by virtue of rarity or age. In reality, we admire some recent works more than earlier ones,
e.g., a Tiepolo of the eighteenth century more than a Mannerist work of the sixteenth century. In
addition to historical interest, there is, then, something else which resides in a work's specifically
artistic properties, namely conceptual, formal, and coloristic qualities. Apart from the art-
historical value, there is also in all earlier art a purely artistic value independent of the particular
place a work of art occupies in the chain of historical development. Is this "art-value" equally as
present as the historical value in the past, so that it may claim to be an essential and historically
independent part of our notion of monument? Or is this “art-value” merely a subjective one
invented by and entirely dependent on the changing preferences of the modern viewer? Were this
the case, would such art-value have no place in the definition of the monument as a
commemorative work?
There are two fundamentally different responses to this question today: an older one
which has not entirely disappeared, and a newer one. From the Renaissance—when, as we shall
argue later, historical value was first recognized –until the nineteenth century, an inviolable
artistic canon prevailed which claimed an absolute and objective validity to which all artists
aspired but they never achieved with complete success. Initially, ancient art seemed to conform
to this canon most closely, even to the point of representing its very ideal. The nineteenth century
definitively abolished this exclusive claim, allowing virtually all other periods of art to assume
their own independent significance, but without entirely abandoning the belief in an objective
artistic ideal. Only around the beginning of the twentieth century have we come to recognize the
necessary consequences of the theory of historical evolution, which declares that all artifacts of
the past are irrecoverable and therefore in no way canonically binding. Even if we do not limit
ourselves to appreciating modern works of art but also admire the concept, form, and color of
older works, and even if we prefer the latter, we must "realize that certain historic works of art
correspond, if only in part, to the modern Kunstwollen. It is precisely this apparent
correspondence of the modern Kunstwollen and certain aspects of historical art which, in its
conflicting nature, exerts such power over the modern viewer. An entirely modern work,
necessarily lacking this background, will never wield comparable power. According to current
notions, there can be no absolute but only a relative, modern art-value.
When an art monument is appreciated only because of the time it was made
in, then it becomes a historical monument. But art is appreciated for much
more than just the era it was made in, it is appreciated for artistic properties
2
like conceptual, formal and colouring qualities. Kunstwollen- artistic
expression of some fundamental spirit of age
Value of an art monument cannot be only a
relative, modern one because this will make the
art-value of a monument temporary and subjective.
With this in mind, one must define the term art-value in different ways, depending on
whether one adopts the earlier or the modern point of view. According to the former, a work of
art possesses art-value insofar as it corresponds to a supposedly objective but never satisfactorily
defined aesthetic. In the modern view, the art-value of a monument is established by the
requirements of the modern Kunstwollen but these requirements are even less well defined and in
the strictest sense can never be defined because they vary from subject to subject and moment to
moment.
For our task, it is indispensable to clarify this difference in the perception of art-value
because it influences fundamentally all aspects of the preservation of monuments. If there is no
such thing as an eternal art-value but only a relative, modern one, then the art-value of a
monument ceases to be commemorative and becomes a contemporary value instead. The
preservation of monuments has to take this into account, if only because it may have a practical
and topical significance quite apart from the historical and commemorative value of a
monument. Strictly speaking, contemporary appreciation will have to be excluded from the
notion of the monument itself. If one agrees with the understanding of art-value as it has
emerged from the entire complex of nineteenth-century art-historical research, then one may no
longer speak of "artistic historical monuments," but only of "historical monuments." This is the
meaning given to the term in the text.
In contrast to intentional monuments, historical monuments are unintentional, but it is
equally clear that all deliberate monuments may also be unintentional ones. Since those who
fashioned the works which we have sub-sequently termed "historical monuments" wanted
primarily to satisfy their own practical and ideal needs—those of their contemporaries and, at
most, those of their immediate progeny—without as a rule intending to leave testimony of their
artistic and cultural life to later centuries, when we call such works of art "monuments," it is a
subjective rather than an objective designation. It is not their original purpose and significance
that turn these works into monuments, but rather our modern perception of them. Both
intentional and unintentional monuments are characterized by commemorative value, and in both
instances we are interested in their original, uncorrupted appearance as they emerged from the
hands of their maker and to which we seek by whatever means to restore them. In the case of the
intentional monument, its commemorative value has been determined by the makers, while we
have defined the value of the unintentional ones.
Historical value does not exhaust the interest and influence that artworks from the past
arouse in us. Take, for instance, the ruins of a castle, which betray little of the original form,
structure, internal disposition of rooms, and so forth, and with which the visitor has no
sentimental association. The castle's historical value alone fails to account for the obvious
interest which it excites in the modern observer. When we look at an old belfry we must make a
similar distinction between our perception of the localized historical memories it contains and
our more general awareness of the passage of time, the belfry's survival over time, and the
visible traces of its age. The same distinction may be observed in a written testimony. A piece of
parchment from the fifteenth century recording no more than the purchase of a horse evokes in
us not only a dual commemorative value, but also, because of its written contents, a historical
one established by the nature of the transaction (economic and legal history), by the names
mentioned (political history, genealogy, land use) and so forth, and by the unfamiliar language,
the uncommon expressions, concepts, and decisions which even someone unschooled in
history would immediately recognize as old-fashioned and belonging to the past. Modern
interest in such an instance is undoubtedly rooted purely in its value as memory, that is, we
Historical monuments are unintentional. Most People usually tend to have a lot of value to
monuments were made to satisfy the needs of the memory. Even though they have no connection
user and not as some kind of a testimony to the to a monument sentimentally, or know it’s
future generations. It is out perception of them that historical value, because of when it was 3
makes them monuments and gives value to them. constructed or when an old piece was written it
ignites an interest in the modern observer.
consider the document an involuntary monument; however, its value as memory does not
interfere with the work as such, but springs from our appreciation of the time which has elapsed
since it was made and which has burdened it with traces of age. We have distinguished historical
monuments from intentional ones as a more subjective category which remains nonetheless
firmly bound up with objects, and now we recognize a third category of monuments in which the
object has shrunk to a necessary evil. These monuments are nothing more than indispensable
catalysts which trigger in the beholder a sense of the life cycle, of the emergence of the particular
from the general and its gradual but inevitable dissolution back into the general. This immediate
emotional effect depends on neither scholarly knowledge nor historical education for its
satisfaction, since it is evoked by mere sensory perception. Hence it is not restricted to the
educated (to whom the task of caring for monuments necessarily has to be limited) but also
touches the masses independent of their education. The general validity, which it shares with
religious feelings, gives this new commemorative (monument) value a significance whose
ultimate consequences cannot yet be assessed. We will henceforth call this the age-value.
From these reflections it is clear that the modern cult of monuments is not restricted to
caring for historical monuments; it also requires consideration for monuments of mere age-value.
Just as intentional monuments are part and parcel of historical monuments, so all historical ones
can be categorized as monuments having an age-value. Outwardly these three classes of
monuments can be thought of as contained within one another, while the scope of their memory-
value widens. To the class of intentional monuments belong only those works which recall a
specific moment or complex of moments from the past. The class of historical monuments is
enlarged to include those which still refer to a particular moment, but the choice of that moment
is left to our subjective preference. Finally, the category of monuments of age-value embraces
every artifact without regard to its original significance and purpose, as long as it reveals the
passage of a considerable period of time. These classes form three consecutive phases of the
generalization of what a monument means. A cursory glance at the history of preservation up to
this time reveals how these three classes have arisen in identical sequence over historical time.
4