Feminist Jurisprudence - Grounding The Theories, Cain
Feminist Jurisprudence - Grounding The Theories, Cain
Feminist Jurisprudence - Grounding The Theories, Cain
Citations:
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
Feminist Jurisprudence:
Grounding The Theories
Patricia A. Caint
INTRODUCTION
This essay originates from my participation in a workshop of the
same title at the 20th National Conference on Women and the Law, held
in Oakland, California in the Spring of 1989. The workshop focused on
the following two questions: (1) to what extent is feminist theoretical
scholarship in the field of law actually grounded in the experience of
women (i.e., based on feminist method); and (2) to the extent that the
theory is grounded in women's experience, does it reflect the diversity of
women's experience?
Because I had recently been struggling with both of these issues, I
readily accepted the invitation to participate. At the time, I hoped that
my preparation for the workshop would help clarify my own thinking
about the connections between feminist method and theory. My particu-
lar concern was that feminist legal theorists often ignore, or at best
marginalize, lesbian experience. I call this the problem of the invisible
lesbian. It is a problem that has serious consequences for the building of
feminist legal theory.
What makes any theory particularly feminist is that it is derived
from female experience, from a point of view contrary to the dominant
male perception of reality. If feminist legal theory is derived from a femi-
nist method uninformed by critical lesbian experience, the theory will be
incomplete. Lesbian experience is essential to the formation of feminist
t Professor of Law, University of Texas. This essay began as a conversation with Jean Love and
Leigh Leonard. Some of the resulting thoughts were tested at the Women and the Law Con-
ference. Once the thoughts were reduced to writing, the essay and I spent a wonderful after-
noon in an expanded conversation with the West Coast Fem-Crits. I am thankful to Christine
Littleton and Deborah Rhode for setting up the conversation and to the following women for
participating: Alison Anderson, Barbara Babcock, Martha Chamallas, Kimberle Crenshaw,
Barbara Fried, Trina Grillo, Angela Harris, Jean Love, Margaret Jane Radin, Carol Sanger,
Elizabeth Schneider, Reva Siegel, Nomi Stolzenberg, Nadine Taub, Stephanie Wildman, Viv-
ian Wilson, and Zipporah Wiseman. I am also grateful for additional comments from Mary
Dunlap, Anne Goldstein, Sylvia Law, Frances Olsen, and Marjorie Shultz. I have not
answered fully everyone's concerns in this final draft, but I have listened and I hope the con-
versation will continue.
A. Feminist Jurisprudence
The first recorded use of the phrase "feminist jurisprudence"
occurred in 1978 at a conference celebrating the twenty-fifth anniversary
of women graduates of the Harvard Law School. Professor Ann Scales,
then a Harvard student, moderated a panel of feminist lawyers, legal edu-
cators, and judges. The question for debate was whether there was in
fact, or should be, such a thing as a feminist jurisprudence. As I under-
stand it from Professor Scales, the consensus was that there should not
be.
Professor Scales, unwilling to abide by the consensus, entitled her
first scholarly article Towards a Feminist Jurisprudence.3 She admitted
that the risk of calling her project "feminist jurisprudence" was that the
work might be misunderstood as a politically-motivated argument for
special laws favoring women. Actually, she intended to question, from a
feminist perspective, the completeness of a jurisprudence that is not
responsive to specifically female concerns (e.g., pregnancy).'
More recently, Professor Robin West has claimed that "feminist
jurisprudence is a conceptual anomaly." 5 Existing jurisprudence is mas-
culine, according to West, because it is about the connection between
patriarchal laws and human beings, who are presumed by those laws to
be male. Feminist jurisprudence cannot exist until patriarchy is
abolished.6
I understand Professor West to be saying that we cannot create a
complete theory of law (a jurisprudence) that is truly feminist until condi-
tions are such that we can build the theory authentically. So long as
patriarchal dominance continues, female authenticity is presumably
impossible.7 As Catharine MacKinnon keeps reminding us, she (the
"female") cannot articulate her own definitions now "because his foot is
on her throat." 8
Without fully accepting the West/MacKinnon thesis (I believe we9
10 1 suspect that both Professors West and MacKinnon would agree that we have such glimpses.
Otherwise their own feminist projects would be subject to charges of inauthenticity or false
consciousness. Indeed, West asserts that we do have glimpses of freedom from patriarchy.
West, supra note 5, at 48. It has been reported, however, that feminists generally are not
agreed on the meaning of the concept "authenticity" and further, that MacKinnon's view of
the concept is that it is "unhelpful." Colker, Feminism, Sexuality, and Self: A Preliminary
Inquiry into the Politics of Authenticity (Book Review), 68 B.U.L. REV. 217, 218-19 n.3, 220
n.8 (1988).
By "authenticity" I mean individual authenticity, i.e., that which makes me uniquely me.
MacKinnon's pronouncement that "authenticity" is not helpful probably reflects the fact that
her critique focuses on the category "woman" and not on individual women. Indeed, the
strength of her critique lies in its "group" viewpoint.
Also, I am using the term "authenticity" in a moral sense, whereas MacKinnon's critique
is a political one. Her critique is one that could lead to changes in material conditions for
individual women, and thereby to their attainment of individual "authenticity" in the sense of
the term that I intend. The relevant question to put to MacKinnon would be: Do you think
the search for the authentic self is a worthwhile goal?
Although it is not my intent to develop the concept of authenticity fully in this article,
some elaboration is called for. First of all, I believe that we each have an authentic self that is
unique and that it is a moral goal to act in accord with that authentic self. Cf W. SHAKE-
SPEARE, HAMLET PRINCE OF DENMARK, I.iii.78 (W. Farnham rev. ed. 1970) (quarto 1604-
05) ("(T]o thine own self be true .... ").
Furthermore, I believe the patriarchal structure of society prevents women from attaining
a sufficient concept of their individual authentic selves. In accord with this, I find it unsurpris-
ing that Kierkegaard's two categories of despair "which is conscious of being despair, as also it
is conscious of being a self" are defined as (1) the despair of womanliness (despair of not
willing to be oneself) and (2) the despair of manliness (despair of willing despairingly to be
oneself). See S. KIERKEGAARD, THE SICKNESS UNTo DEATH 180-207 (1954).
I associate the concept of "authenticity" with other existentialists, such as Martin
Heidegger and Jean Paul Sartre. Sartre, although he never developed an existentialist ethics,
connected the concept of freedom with moral (authentic) choice. We are morally responsible
when we choose freely and self-consciously. We act in "bad faith" when we attempt to avoid
the responsibility of freedom, when we deny the existence of self as subject and instead act
according to an objective role created for us--or, indeed, whenever we choose on the basis of
something outside "self," including on the basis of an abstract moral principle. See T.
LAVINE, FROM SOCRATES TO SARTRE: THE PHILOSOPHIC QUEST 365-75 (1984).
"Authenticity," in the sense that I use it, is necessarily connected with freedom. I, as an
individual woman, will have glimpses of my authenticity whenever I am freed from the cate-
gory woman; that is, whenever I am able to transcend my socially constructed (and unauthen-
tic) self.
II West, supra note 5, at 60.
12 Some years ago, when I first ventured to teach a feminist seminar in law, I opted to call the
class "feminist legal theory" rather than "feminist jurisprudence," because the latter implied
the existence of a full-fledged feminist theory of law, which I knew I did not have. I viewed
the concrete creation of feminist legal theories as a move "towards a feminist jurisprudence."
See Scales, supra note 3.
13 See, e.g., Minow, Foreword: Justice Engendered, 101 HARV. L. REV. 10 (1987); Resnik, On
the Bias: FeministReconsiderationsof the Aspirationsfor Our Judges, 61 S. CAL. L. REV. 1877
(1988); Scales, The Emergence of Feminist Jurisprudence, 95 YALE L.J. 1373 (1986); West,
supra note 5; F. Olsen, The Sex of Law (n.d.) (unpublished manuscript available from the
Berkeley Women's Law Journal).
14 See, e.g., S. ESTRICH, REAL RAPE (1987); C. MACKINNON, SEXUAL HARASSMENT OF
WORKING WOMEN (1979) [hereinafter C. MACKINNON, SEXUAL HARASSMENT]; Bender, A
Lawyer's Primer on Feminist Theory and Tort, 38 J. LEGAL EDUC. 3 (1988); Fineman, Domi-
GROUNDING THE THEORIES
B. Feminist Method
Recent feminist legal scholarship emphasizes the importance of fem-
inist method.1 7 While it is not clear whether feminist method is, in fact,
limited to consciousness-raising," nor whether it should be, 19 there does
appear to be general agreement that feminist method begins with the pri-
macy of women's experience. Listening to women and believing their
stories is central to feminist method.2" If we are careful to listen to
women when they describe the harms they experience as women, we are
likely to get the legal theory right (i.e., perceive the problem correctly
and propose the right solutions).
Consider Carol Gilligan's pathbreaking work in psychology.21 Fem-
inist method led Gilligan to suggest new theories regarding women's
22 Gilligan's main thesis is that women's moral development is distinct from that of men.
Women develop a morality based on an ethic of care, whereas men develop a morality based
on justice, defined as an ability to rank abstract rights against each other in a hierarchical
system of values. Id. at 64-105.
23 See generally Chused, The Hiring and Retention of Minorities and Women on American Law
School Faculties, 137 U. PA. L. REV. 537 (1988) (despite an increase in female full-time faculty
from 13.7% in 1980 to 20% in 1986, there are a number of disturbing trends that evidence a
continuing exclusion of women from full-fledged membership in the profession).
24 See C. HEILBRUN, REINVENTING WOMANHOOD (1979). In this elegant and provocative
book, Carolyn Heilbrun gives us many examples of women academics who have judged other
women from a male-centered perspective.
25 There is another risk for those of us cloistered away amongst the rational and the male. The
risk is that, even when we do listen to women's voices, they will be the voices of women who
are most like us. Thus, we must consciously seek out the stories of those who differ from us.
There are many good anthologies of women's real stories that can broaden our views of life.
For stories of lesbian experience, see COMING OUT STORIES (S. Wolf & J. Stanley eds. 1980);
LESBIAN NUNS: BREAKING SILENCE (R. Curb & N. Manahan eds. 1985). For stories of
women of color, see THIS BRIDGE CALLED MY BACK (C. Moraga & G. Anzaldua 2d ed.
1983). For stories that are woven together around the concept of consciousness-raising, see A.
SHREVE, WOMEN TOGETHER, WOMEN ALONE (1989).
26 See Littleton, supra note 17 (reviewing MacKinnon's book, Feminism Unmodified, and credit-
ing MacKinnon primarily for her methodological contributions to feminist jurisprudence).
27 For a full discussion of consciousness-raising as method and the relationship between method
and politics, see chapters five and six of MacKinnon's most recent book. C. MACKINNON,
FEMINIST THEORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 83-125.
28 Betty Friedan, for example, chronicles the responses she received from women all over the
country after the publication of her book, The Feminine Mystique, in 1963. B. FRIEDAN, IT
CHANGED MY LIFE: WRITINGS ON THE WOMEN'S MOVEMENT 20-27 (1976). Anais Nin
speaks of having received a similar response from women after the publication of her Diary:
"When I published [the Diary] I thought it was the story of one woman.... But I suddenly
found that my diary didn't belong to me, that it was other women's diaries too." A. NIN, A
WOMAN SPEAKS 148 (E. Hinz ed. 1975).
GROUNDING THE THEORIES
36 The first wave of feminism occurred at the end of the 19th century and marks the beginning of
the women's movement. Some writers speak of the women's movement as though it began in
the 1960s, thereby distorting history and ignoring a much longer feminist tradition. The goals
accomplished in the first wave included the passage of married women's property acts and the
enactment of the 19th amendment granting women suffrage. For a good, yet brief, discussion
of feminist history (herstory), see Bender, supra note 14, at 12-15.
37 Although the modern women's movement owes much to the first wave of feminism, it also
owes much to the civil rights and the peace movements of the late 1950s and the 1960s. See
generally S. EVANS, BORN FOR LIBERTY 263-85 (1989).
38 Equal Pay Act of 1963, 29 U.S.C. § 206 (1982).
39 Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 1981 (1982).
40 "EEOC commissioners and staff ... expressed a general belief that the addition of sex to the
law had been illegitimate--merely a ploy to kill the bill-and that it did not therefore consti-
tute a mandate to equalize women's employment opportunities." C. HARRISON, ON
ACCOUNT OF SEX: THE POLITICS OF WOMEN'S ISSUES 1945-1968, at 187 (1988).
41 Id. at 188.
42 Id. at 192-93. See also S. EVANS, supra note 37, at 277.
43 "The purpose of NOW is to take action to bring women into full participation in the main-
stream of American society now, exercising all the privileges and responsibilities thereof in
truly equal partnership with men." Nat'l Organization for Women, Statement of Purpose,
reprinted in B. FRIEDAN, supra note 28, at 87.
44 C. HARRISON, supra note 40, at 198-99.
45 S. EVANS, supra note 37, at 278.
46 B. FRIEDAN, supra note 28, at 120-22.
47 See id. at 159. (At a 1970 national feminist demonstration at which participants were asked to
wear lavender lesbian armbands as a symbol of solidarity, Friedan refused. "For me ... the
women's movement . . . had nothing whatsoever to do with lesbianism.")
GROUNDING THE THEORIES
48 S. EVANS, supra note 37, at 294. See generally LESBIANISM AND THE WOMEN'S MOVEMENT
(N. Myron & C. Bunch eds. 1975).
49 NOW was the organization at the center of the women's movement and although its member-
ship included many active lesbians, the organization itself consciously avoided lesbian issues in
the early days. Such homophobic attitudes appear to have been worse on the East Coast than
on the West Coast. See D. MARTIN & P. LYON, LESBIAN WOMAN 256-76 (1972).
50 Fossum, Women Law Professors, 1980 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 903, 906.
51 In checking the Index to Legal Periodicals for 1967-70, I found only 36 entries under the
heading "Women." INDEX TO LEGAL PERIODICALS SEPTEMBER 1967 - AUGUST 1970, at
849 (M. Russell & G. Meyer eds. 1971). In the 1970-73 volume, there were over 100 entries
under "Women." INDEX TO LEGAL PERIODICALS SEPTEMBER 1970 - AUGUST 1973, at 953-
55 (G. Meyer ed. 1974).
52 See, e.g., Epstein, The Docile Majority: Bridging the Gap, 25 RUTGERS L. REV. 12 (1970);
Sassower, The Legal Profession and Women's Rights, 25 RUTGERS L. REV. 54 (1970). Some
of the significant early work regarding women was done by male academics. See L.
KANOWITZ, WOMEN AND THE LAW-THE UNFINISHED REVOLUTION (1969); White,
Women in the Law, 65 MICH. L. REV. 1051 (1967).
53 For a critique of equality theory on the grounds that it accepts the male norm, see Finley,
supra note 14.
54 Lesbians differed from heterosexual women in one very noticeable respect, however. Lesbians
were denied custody of their children because they were deemed unfit mothers. Thus, there is
some early separate lesbian-feminist scholarship on custody. See, e.g., Hunter & Polikoff, Cus-
tody Rights of Lesbians, 25 BUFFALO L. REV. 691 (1976); Hitchens & Price, Trial Strategy in
Lesbian Mother Custody Cases: The Use of Expert Testimony, 9 GOLDEN GATE U.L. REV.
451 (1978-79).
BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
55 See generally Kay, Equality and Difference: The Case of Pregnancy, I BERKELEY WOMEN'S
L.J. 1 (1985); Law, Rethinking Sex and the Constitution, 132 U. PA. L. REV. 955 (1984);
Wildman, The Legitimation of Sex Discrimination: A Critical Response to Supreme Court
Jurisprudence,63 OR. L. REV. 265 (1984); Williams, The Equality Crisis: Some Reflections on
Culture, Courts, and Feminism, 8 WOMEN'S RTS. L. REP. 175 (1982).
56 This was the thesis of Ann Scales' first article. Scales, supra note 3.
57 The risk of pregnancy is lower for lesbians, of course. And, statistically, fewer lesbians get
pregnant (while they are lesbians) than heterosexual women. Thus, accommodation for preg-
nancy, although relevant for some lesbians, has never been at the top of the lesbian agenda.
58 By "cultural feminist," I mean (loosely) those feminists who recognize the existence of a sepa-
rate women's culture, which has values that ought to be reclaimed from the patriarchy. See
generally Alison Jaggar's discussion of the politics of radical feminism, which focuses on the
reinterpretations and re-conceptions of value by feminists who recognize how women's culture
has been devalued by the patriarchy. A. JAGGAR, FEMINIST POLITICS AND HUMAN NATURE
249-55 (1983).
Robin West uses the term "cultural feminist" to include those feminists who believe that
"the important difference between men and women is that women raise children and men
don't." West, supra note 5, at 13. Thus, her use of the term is narrower than my understand-
ing of the term. See infra notes 69-74 and accompanying text.
59 See, e.g., Kuykendall, Toward an Ethic of Nurturance: Luce Irigarayon Mothering andPower,
in MOTHERING: ESSAYS IN FEMINIST THEORY 263 (J. Trebilcot ed. 1984); Ruddick, Mater-
nal Thinking, in MOTHERING: ESSAYS IN FEMINIST THEORY 213 (J. Trebilcot ed. 1984).
60 See West, supra note 5, at 1. West's claim that the law does not recognize harms that stem
from the connected experiences of women is not totally true. Tort claims for loss of consor-
tium are discussed by modern day courts in terms of injury to the relationship. See, e.g.,
Rodriguez v. Bethlehem Steel Corp., 12 Cal. 3d 382, 525 P.2d 669, 115 Cal. Rptr. 765 (1974).
Of course, early recognition of such claims occurred in the days when wives were viewed as
the property of their husbands. Thus, the theoretical basis for early claims was property dam-
age rather than relational harm. See M. CHAMALLAS & L. KERBER, WOMEN, MOTHERS AND
THE LAW OF FRIGHT: A HISTORY 5-6 (Legal History Program Working Papers Series 3,
March 1989).
61 Leslie Bender asks, for example, "Why ... do tort damages recognize financial loss and yet
remain reluctant to recognize relational loss ... ?" Bender, supra note 14, at 37.
62 I include in "Stage Two" all theorists who reject the liberal feminist approach of "Stage One,"
but do not (yet) embrace postmodernism. (See discussion of Stage Three infra pp. 204-05.)
Because I do embrace postmodernism to the extent it eschews essentialism, universality, and
the limits of categorization, I am wary of the categorization I create by placing theorists into
GROUNDING THE THEORIES
argued that men and women are different, but the difference is that men
dominate and women are subordinate.6 3 Which came first, dominance or
difference, is an unimportant question, in her view. The important thing
is to end the dominance. 64 Legal arguments that pose the issue as one of
difference between the sexes are not likely to end the dominance. Mac-
Kinnon calls for a paradigm shift, away from differences in biology, dif-
ferences in experience, differences in essence, to the only difference that
really matters: the difference in power. Her "inequality" approach to
sex discrimination recognizes the imbalance in power between men and
women. "Practices which express and reinforce the social inequality of
women to men are clear cases of sex-based discrimination .... "65 Sexual
harassment is one such practice.66
One might expect cultural feminists and dominance theorists who
engage in legal scholarship (such as Gilligan and MacKinnon, respec-
tively) to acknowledge the relevance of lesbian experience in their writ-
ings. It is particularly surprising to discover the invisible lesbian
problem in the work of cultural feminists. In disciplines other than law,
feminist theorists working to reclaim women's culture and its values have
often focused on lesbian community.6 7 But in legal 6scholarship,
8
discus-
sions of female value focus on "woman as mother.
Robin West's article, Jurisprudenceand Gender,69 is a prime exam-
ple of the problem. West posits that current (masculine) jurisprudence is
based on the concept of human beings as separate from each other and
that this "separation thesis" forms the core of both liberal and critical
male legal theories. Feminist theory, in contrast, views human beings as
primarily connected to one another. Both cultural and radical feminists
use this "connection thesis." West begins her article with four examples
of women's primary and material experience with connection: (1) preg-
nancy; (2) heterosexual penetration; (3) menstruation; and (4) breast-
feeding.7 ° Despite West's awareness of the pressure on all women to be
heterosexual, 7 ' her list of "connection" experiences ignores specifically
lesbian experiences of "connection."
what appear to be separate stages of feminist scholarship. I ask the reader to imagine the
boundaries as more fluid than my brief identification of the categories/stages suggests.
63 C. MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, 32-45 (1987).
64 "[O]n the first day that matters, dominance was achieved .... Id. at 40.
65 C. MACKINNON, SEXUAL HARASSMENT, supra note 14, at 174.
66 Id.
67 See generally A. JAGGAR, supra note 58, at 249-302 and sources cited therein. In the field of
philosophy, there are works that build ethical theory on women's bonding to other women.
See, e.g., J. RAYMOND, A PASSION FOR FRIENDS: TOWARD A PHILOSOPHY OF FEMALE
AFFECTION (1986); S. HOAGLAND, LESBIAN ETHICS: TOWARD NEW VALUE (1988).
68 Here, I mean mother in the broad social sense as a person who is nurturing and self-
sacrificing.
69 West, supra note 5.
70 Id. at 3.
71 "Most women are indeed forced into motherhood and heterosexuality." Id. at 71.
BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
To the claim that lesbian experience is different, that lesbians are not
subordinate to men, that their care is not male-directed, MacKinnon
appears to have two different responses. Her first response is that excep-
tions do not matter. MacKinnon's intent is to offer a critique of the
structural condition of women as sexual subordinates and not to make
existential claims about all women.7 8 It does not affect her theory that
all women are not always subordinated to men. 79 Thus, for MacKinnon,
lesbian experience of non-subordination is simply irrelevant.
Her second response is more troubling. It goes beyond the assertion
that lesbian experience is irrelevant; it denies the claim that lesbian expe-
rience is free from male domination.
Some have argued that lesbian sexuality-meaning here simply women
having sex with women, not with men-solves the problem of gender by
72 Although she does not include herself in the list of legal scholars who have engaged in "cul-
tural feminist" projects, she explains her "connection thesis," as applied to women, in terms of
women's biological connection to pregnancy. Thus, West has been described by Joan Wil-
liams as a "biological determinist." Williams, DeconstructingGender, 87 MICH. L. REV. 797,
800 n.ll (1989).
73 See, e.g., M. DALY, PURE LUST (1984); M. DALY, GYN/ECOLOGY (1978).
74 See, e.g., S. HOAGLAND, supra note 67.
75 "[l]f you look at... whether women have ever not been subordinate to men,... as I see it, if
bottom is bottom then look on the bottom, and there is where women will be." Feminist
Discourse, supro note 8, at 71.
76 C. MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note 63, at 39; Feminist Discourse, supra
note 8, at 74.
77 C. MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note 63, at 39.
78 See, e.g., C. MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note 63 at 55-56, 305-06 n.6.
79 "Structural truths about the meaning of gender may or may not produce big numbers....
[T]o say 'not all woman [sic] experience that,' as if that contraindicates sex specificity ... is to
suggest that to be sex-specific, something must be true of 100 percent of the sex affected." C.
MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note 63, at 55.
GROUNDING THE THEORIES
80 C. MACKINNON, FEMINIST THEORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 141-42 (footnote omitted).
81 For example, the image of the lesbian in the dominant culture is that of a masculine, often
predatory, character, the "butch" of the butch-femme lesbian couple. MacKiuuon's refer-
ences to lesbians often reinforce this stereotype. See, e.g., C. MACKINNON, FEMINIST THE-
ORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 119 (lesbian sex does not necessarily transcend the
"erotization of dominance and submission"); C. MACKINNON, SEXUAL HARASSMENT, supra
note 14, at 206 (positing a lesbian harasser). I believe MacKinnon does herself (as well as
lesbians) a disservice by not acknowledging the reality of co-equal relationships that many
lesbians experience. Indeed, the extreme dissonance between traditional male-created con-
cepts of lesbian existence and the reality of much lesbian existence tells us that the patriarchy
has constructed lesbianism in a way that supports its norm of enforced heterosexuality.
Although MacKinnon recognizes this patriarchal response to lesbianism ("l]esbians can so
violate the sexuality implicit in female gender stereotypes as not to be considered women at
all," id. at 110), she never reveals an understanding of lesbian existence different from the
patriarchal image of the "butch."
82 I mean this statement literally. Mary Dunlap, a lesbian lawyer, was on a panel at the Buffalo
Law School with MacKinnon (and others), entitled "Feminist Discourse, Moral Values and
the Law." Responding to MacKinnon's view of "woman," silenced by "man's" foot on her
throat, Dunlap rose and said: "I am a woman standing... [and] I am not subordinate to any
man." MacKinnon failed to acknowledge the potential relevance of Dunlap's life experience
as a lesbian to her claim of non-subordination. See infra pp. 211-12; see also C. MACKINNON,
FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note 63, at 221, 305-06 n.6.
83 Dalton, supra note 35.
84 These two camps parallel Robin West's prior categorization of feminists as either cultural or
radical. West, supra note 5.
BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
as the core experience for building a legal theory premised on caring and
86
connection. 85 And although "woman as sexual subordinate" theorists
are more likely to acknowledge the fact of lesbian existence,87 they foeus
on a critique of male dominance rather than on lesbian bonding as a
possible alternative to male dominance."
85 But see Reese, The Forgotten Sex: Lesbians, Liberation, and the Law, 11 WILLAMETTE L.J.
354 (1975) (lesbian-centered critique of areas of the law that ignore the existence of lesbians).
86 E.g., Catharine MacKinnon. See, e.g., C. MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note
63.
87 See C. MACKINNON, FEMINIST THEORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 119; C. MACKINNON,
SEXUAL HARASSMENT, supra note 14, at 206. MacKinnon claims that a feminist jurispru-
dence would recognize that the question of gay and lesbian rights is a question of sex equality
rights. C. MACKINNON, FEMINIST THEORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 248. Unfortunately,
she does not elaborate on this point other than to articulate the connection between discrimi-
nation based on sexuality and discrimination based on gender, a connection that is at the core
of her theory.
88 See, e.g., C. MACKINNON, SEXUAL HARASSMENT, supra note 14, at 203-06 (discussing sexual
harassment of gay and lesbian employees).
89 Dalton, supra note 35.
90 For an excellent overview of postmodern feminism, and of these three French theorists in
particular, see R. TONG, FEMINIST THOUGHT: A COMPREHENSIVE INTRODUCTION 217-33
(1989).
91 S. DE BEAUVOIR, THE SECOND SEX (1952).
92 They have also been influenced by Jacques Derrida and Jacques Lacan. R. TONG, supra note
90, at 219-23.
93 Id. at 219.
94 See Dalton, supra note 35, at 7-8.
GROUNDING THE THEORIES
95
realities, in our lived experiences. These include differences of race,
class, age, physical ability, and sexual preference.
Postmodern legal theorists will want to reject the limitations caused
by any categorization. Although they will want to listen to the reality of
lesbian experience, these theorists will not be inclined to build a grand
theory based on the concept of "woman" as "lesbian." In the final part
of this essay, I offer some thoughts about the potential relevance of les-
bian experience to the postmodern development of feminist legal theory.
95 For an especially good critique of the failure of feminist legal theorists to acknowledge and
understand the difference that race makes, see Harris, Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal
Theory, 42 STANFORD L. REV. 581 (1990).
96 I borrow the phrase "dominant discourse" from Martha Fineman, who argues that current
theories of child custody are shaped by the "dominant discourse," a discourse which excludes
the mother's experience. Fineman, supra note 14, at 730. Ironically, I am rebelling against a
"dominant discourse" that privileges the experience of motherhood over other experiences of
female connections. See also West, supra note 5, at 28, claiming that cultural feminism, which
focuses on the mother-child connection, is "our dominant feminist dogma."
97 Cain, Teaching FeministLegal Theory at Texas: Listening to Difference and Exploring Con-
nections, 38 J. OF LEGAL EDUC. 165 (1988). See id. at 171, explaining that if students will
listen to each other in a way that encourages identification rather than contrast, then they will
"connect" in ways that lead to deeper understanding.
98 Spelman recognizes the limitations of this solution, concluding, "But it doesn't bury them very
BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
100 Bulkin, 'Kissing/Againstthe Light': A Look at Lesbian Poetry, in LESBIAN STUDIES 40-41 (M.
Cruikshank ed. 1982).
101 Id.(quoting Adrienne Rich).
102 An Interview with Adrienne Rich, quoted in Bulkin, supra note 100, at 44-45.
BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
103 I do this in my feminist legal theory class. Most of the students are women.
104 Rich, Compulsory Heterosexuality and Lesbian Existence, 5 SIGNs 631 (1980).
105 Id. at 632, 647-48 (footnote omitted).
GROUNDING THE THEORIES
106 Rich asks why, "Jilf women are the earliest sources of emotional caring and physical nurture
for both female and male children ....the search for love and tenderness in both sexes does
not originally lead toward women .... Id. at 637.
107 Frye, A Lesbian Perspective on Women's Studies, in LESBIAN STUDIES 194, 196 (M. Cruik-
shank ed. 1982).
108 Id.
109 Id.
BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
1II. SILENCE
Engage in self-reflection.
[Did she really mean that? Am I supposed to sit here and consider
lesbianism as a possibility? ... Why not? . .. And if I do consider it,
but choose men anyway, is my choice more authentic? What about
tomorrow? Do I choose again?]
[She doesn't understand. I did choose. Twenty years ago I chose
for the children. Does that make my choice inauthentic? What does my
choice mean for me today?]
[What about those of us who choose to live alone, who reject inti-
macy altogether? Am I choosing to be lesbian if I reject men or only if I
choose women? As a woman alone, how am I perceived?]
[To take lesbianism seriously, do I have to reject men? Can I choose
both women and men?]
[What is all this about choice? I've been a lesbian all my life. I
never chose it. I've just lived my life as it was.]
IV. CONNECTIONS
The fact that so many women can identify common life experiences
that are ignored by the male version of reality makes any critique based
on such common experiences compelling and powerful. But theorists
ought to resist transforming a critical standpoint into a new all-encom-
passing version of reality. Indeed, my fear is that what started as a useful
critique of one privileged (male) view of reality may become a substitute
claim for a different privileged (female) view of reality.
Catharine MacKinnon, for example, critiques the patriarchy from a
"woman as sexual subordinate" standpoint. As compelling as her cri-
tique is, it should not be viewed as the one and only existential reality for
women. And yet MacKinnon herself is so committed to this standpoint
that she sometimes seems to claim it as the only reality for women. 112
MacKinnon's theory is that woman's subordination is universal and
constant, but not necessarily inevitable.' 13 She cautions against building
theory on the basis of Carol Gilligan's discovery of woman's "different
voice" because the women Gilligan listened to were all victims of the
patriarchy. Thus, MacKinnon is wary of assigning value to their moral
voice. As she explains,
[bly establishing that women reason differently from men on moral ques-
tions, [Gilligan] revalues that which has accurately distinguished women
from men by making it seem as though women's moral reasoning is some-
how women's, rather than what male supremacy has attributed to women
for its own use. When difference means dominance as it does with gender,
for women to affirm differences is to affirm the qualities and characteristics
of powerlessness .... To the extent materialism means anything at all, it
means that what women have been and thought is what they have been
permitted to be and think. Whatever this is, it is not women's,
possessive. 114
When MacKinnon espoused these beliefs regarding women's subor-
dination and inauthenticity in a dialogue with Gilligan at the now some-
what infamous "Mitchell Lecture" at Buffalo, Mary Dunlap (a lesbian),
who was also a speaker at the event, interrupted. Dunlap said:
I am speaking out of turn. I am also standing, which I am told by
some is a male thing to do. But I am still a woman-standing.
I am not subordinate to any man! I find myself very often contesting
112 "Although feminism emerges from women's particular experience, it is not subjective or par-
tial, for no interior ground and few if any aspects of life are free of male power." C. MACKIN-
NON, FEMINIST THEORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 116.
113 Indeed, her theory of oppression is so complete that it has been described as "metaphysically
perfect." FeministDiscourse, supra note 8, at 70 (comment of Ellen DuBois); see also Bartlett,
MacKinnon's Feminism: Power on Whose Terms? (Book Review), 75 CALIF. L. REV. 1559,
1562-63 (1987). MacKinnon herself describes the system of male dominance as "metaphysi-
cally nearly perfect." C. MACKINNON, FEMINIST THEORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 116
(emphasis added). For a refutation of the inevitability of women's subordination, see C.
MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note 63, at 305-06 n.6 ("If subordination had
to be, it would surely be a waste of time to fight for women's rights.").
114 C. MACKINNON, FEMINIST THEORY OF STATE, supra note 16, at 51.
BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
believe Robin West's claim that all women are "connected" to life is a
fair claim upon which to critique the male version of the "separation
thesis." But I do not believe that the "connection thesis" is true of all
women.1 2 ° Feminist legal theorists must be careful not to confuse
"standpoint critiques" with existential reality. And the theorist who has
not confused the two must also be careful to prevent her readers from
making the confusion.
The problem with current feminist theory is that the more abstract
and universal it is, the more it fails to relate to the lived reality of many
women.121 One problem with much feminist legal theory is that it has
abstracted and universalized from the experience of heterosexual women.
Consider again Marilyn Frye's challenge to heterosexual academic femi-
nists: "I wish you would notice that you are heterosexual. I wish you
would grow to the understanding that you choose heterosexuality ...
that you are and choose to be a member of a privileged and dominant
' 122
class, one of your privileges being not to notice."
Marilyn Frye's challenge was specifically addressed to heterosexual
women. When I elected to adopt her challenge at the Women and the
Law Conference (and in this essay), I was choosing a "'lesbian stand-
point" to critique the dominant reality in the same way that some cul-
tural feminists have chosen a "mother standpoint" to critique patriarchy.
My intent was not to convert a roomful of women to lesbianism. It was
to raise everyone's self-consciousness about our different "standpoints."
Feminist legal theory must recognize differences in order to avoid rein-
forcing lesbian invisibility or marginality, i.e., impeding "the liberation
and empowerment of woman as a group. "123
My "lesbian standpoint" enables me to see two versions of reality.1 24
The dominant reality, which I experience as "theirs," includes the fol-
lowing: lesbians are not mothers, all women are dominated by men, male
relationships are valuable and female relationships are not, lesbian is a
dirty word, lesbians are sick, women who live alone desire men, women
who live together desire men, no one knows a lesbian, lesbians don't have
families, all feminist legal theorists are heterosexual, all women in this
room are heterosexual, lesbians are sex, most women are heterosexual
and not lesbian.
120 Nor does West believe it is true of all women; she specifically disclaims such a position. West,
supra note 5, at 71.
121 See generally E. SPELMAN, supra note 98.
122 Frye, supra note 107.
123 Rich, supra note 104, at 648.
124 And both versions of reality inform my knowledge of the world. As Nancy Hartsock explains:
The concept of a standpoint structures epistemology in a particular way. Rather than
a simple dualism, it posits a duality of levels of reality, of which the deeper level or
essence both includes and explains the "surface" or appearance, and indicates the logic
by means of which the appearance inverts and distorts the deeper reality.
Hartsock, supra note 11, at 285.
214 BERKELEY WOMEN'S LAW JOURNAL
By contrast, the reality that I live, the reality I call "mine," includes
the following: some mothers are lesbian, many women are lesbian, many
lesbian women are not dominated by men, many women do not desire
men, lesbian is a beautiful word, lesbians are love, love is intimacy, the
heterosexual/lesbian dichotomy is false, all lesbians are born into fami-
lies, lesbians are family, some feminist legal theorists are lesbian, lesbians
are brave.
Why is the lesbian so invisible in feminist legal theory? Why is "my
reality" so different from "their reality?" And which reality is true? For
the postmodernist, the last question is meaningless. But the first two are
not.