Chapter One: 1.1 What Is Logic? 1.1.1 A Branch of Philosophy What Is Philosophy?
Chapter One: 1.1 What Is Logic? 1.1.1 A Branch of Philosophy What Is Philosophy?
Chapter One
Introduction
1.1 What is Logic?
1.1.1 A Branch of Philosophy
What is Philosophy?
The word "philosophy" is derived from the Greek words and word-fragments:
Philia/ phile /philo—love of, affinity for, liking of
How do ideas exist if they have no size, shape, or color? (My idea of the
Empire State Building is quite as "small" or as "large" as my idea of a book.
I.e., an idea is not extended in space.) What is space? What is time?
1
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
What is spirit? or soul? or matter? space? Are they made up of the same sort
of "stuff"?
When, if ever, are events necessary? Under what conditions are they
possible?
3. Axiology: the study of value; the investigation of its nature, criteria, and
metaphysical status. More often than not, the term "value theory" is used
instead of "axiology" in contemporary discussions even though the term
“theory of value” is used with respect to the value or price of goods and
services in economics.
2
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
Status of value: how are values related to (scientific) facts? What ultimate
worth, if any, do human values have?
5. Æsthetics: the study of value in the arts or the inquiry into feelings,
judgments, or standards of beauty and related concepts. Philosophy of art is
concerned with judgments of sense, taste, and emotion.
Aristotle (384-322 B.C) is the father of logic. His logic is called syllogistic logic.
The major logician of the middle age was Peter Abelard (1079-1142). He was
a French philosopher and he refined Aristotle’s logic and originated a theory
of universals
3
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
4
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
5
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
6
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
classes and tests, and will the job produce an excessive drain on your
energies?
As with warnings, if there is no evidence that is intended to prove anything,
then there is no argument.
C. Conditional statements the reason is the antecedent and the consequent
show a causal connection; not inferential relationship.
Example:
If Alemu studies hard, (antecedent) he will pass the exam. (consequence)
Note that:
A single conditional statement is not an argument.
A conditional statement may serve as either the premise or the conclusion
(or both) of an argument.
Example:
If Alemu studies hard, he will pass the exam.
Alemu really studies hard.
Therefore, Alemu will pass the exam.
The inferential content of a conditional statement may be re-expressed to
form an argument.
D. Explanations
The reason is statements in explanations intend to shed light on some
accepted facts; but not they use accepted facts as a claim to prove a
conclusion.
Just as arguments have premises and conclusions, so do explanations
have explanans and explanandum.
Explanandum: is the statement that is to be explained.
Explanans: is the statement or group of statements that purports to do
the explaining. As both express the outcome of a reasoning process,
explanations and arguments have certain similarities, however,
explanations do not claim to prove anything.
Many [particularly, scientific] explanations can be re-expressed to form
arguments.
7
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
8
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
9
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
10
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
the premise or conclusion. For example, someone might argue that because
Claudia is mendacious, it follows that she tells lies, or that because a certain
paragraph is prolix, it follows that it is excessively wordy. These arguments
are deductive because their conclusions follow with necessity from the
definitions of “mendacious” and “prolix.”
A syllogism, in general, is an argument consisting of exactly two premises
and one conclusion. Categorical syllogisms will be treated in greater depth in
Chapter 5, but for now we will say that a categorical syllogism is a syllogism
in which each statement begins with one of the words “all,” “no,” or “some.”
Example:
All ancient forests are sources of wonder.
Some ancient forests are targets of the timber industry.
Therefore, some sources of wonder are targets of the timber industry.
Arguments such as these are nearly always best treated as deductive.
A hypothetical syllogism is a syllogism having a conditional (“if . . . then”)
statement for one or both of its premises. Examples:
If estate taxes are abolished, then wealth will accumulate disproportionately.
If wealth accumulates disproportionately, then democracy will be threatened.
Therefore, if estate taxes are abolished, then democracy will be threatened.
If Fox News is a propaganda machine, then it misleads its viewers.
Fox News is a propaganda machine.
Therefore, Fox News misleads its viewers.
Later in this book, the first of these arguments will be given the more specific
name of pure hypothetical syllogism because it is composed exclusively of
conditional (hypothetical) statements. The second argument is called a mixed
hypothetical syllogism because only one of its component statements is a
conditional. Later in this book, the second argument will be given the more
specific Latin name modus ponens.
A disjunctive syllogism is a syllogism having a disjunctive (“either . . .
or . . .”) statement.
Example:
11
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
In general, inductive arguments are such that the content of the conclusion
is in some way intended to “go beyond” the content of the premises. The
premises of such an argument typically deal with some subject that is
relatively familiar, and the conclusion then moves beyond this to a subject
that is less familiar or that little is known about. Such an argument may
take any of several forms: predictions about the future, arguments from
analogy, inductive generalizations, arguments from authority, arguments
based on signs, and causal inferences, to name just a few.
12
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
13
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
14
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
15
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
16
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
(But it is Valid)
Similarly, an argument with true premise and true conclusion could be
invalid.
Example:
All Soft drinks are non-alcoholics. T
Coca-Cola is non-alcoholic. T
Therefore, Coca-Cola is soft drink. T
But it is invalid
3. Sound and Unsound Arguments
Truth and Falsity is relevant to evaluate arguments as Sound and Unsound.
Sound Deductive Arguments
A sound deductive argument is an argument that is valid and has all true
premises. The only case of a Sound Deductive argument is true premises and
true conclusions.
Unsound Deductive Arguments
Regardless of their truth or falsity all invalid deductive arguments are
Unsound.
Summary
The relationship among Truthfulness, validity and soundness is summarized
as follows.
Pre. Con. Validity Soundness
T T ? ?
T F Invalid Unsound
F T ? Unsound
F F ? Unsound
N.B The question mark (?) in the table indicates that based on the factual
and/or the inferential claim the argument could be valid, invalid, sound or
unsound.
N.B The case: True Premise & False Conclusion is impossible; if it happened,
the argument is necessarily invalid.
17
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
18
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
19
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
A cogent argument is an inductive argument that is strong and has all true
premises. Also, the premises must be true in the sense of meeting the total
evidence requirement. If any one of these conditions is missing, the argument
is uncogent. Thus, an uncogent argument is an inductive argument that is
weak, has one or more false premises, fails to meet the total evidence
requirement, or any combination of these. A cogent argument is the inductive
analogue of a sound deductive argument and is what is meant by a good, or
successful, inductive argument without qualification. Because the conclusion
of a cogent argument is genuinely supported by true premises, it follows that
the conclusion of every cogent argument is probably true in the actual world
in light of all the known evidence.
A cogent argument is an inductive argument that is strong and has all true
premises. Argument is cogent if and only if it is inductively strong and all the
premises are true. Uncogent argument is an inductive argument that is weak,
and has one or more false premise, or both.
A few U.S. presidents were unmarried.
Therefore, probably the next U.S. president will be unmarried.
Every previous U.S. president died in office.
20
_________________________________________________________________________________________________________________
Therefore, probably the next U.S. president will die in office.The above two
mentioned examples are uncogent inductive argument.
21