Causation and Emptiness in Early Madhyamika
Causation and Emptiness in Early Madhyamika
Causation and Emptiness in Early Madhyamika
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of
Indian Philosophy
ii
The lesson to be learned from the case of the chariot may be put as
follows: anything whose nature can be accounted for wholly in terms
of the properties of the parts of which it is composed is not ultimately
in
Does Nàgàrjuna have an argument for the claim that causal depen
dence in general entails lack of intrinsic nature? I think he does. But
to find it we need to first go back to the discussion of causation in
MMK 1, and then think through the consequences of its conclu
sion.18 This chapter begins with the famous claim that an existent
cannot be said to originate from itself, from what is other, from what
is both itself and other, and from no cause at all. It is generally agreed
that the first and second lemmas represent the alternatives of
satkñryavñda and asatkaryavâda respectively that were widely de
bated among Indian philosophers concerned with the nature of the
causal relation. According to the former view, the effect pre-exists in
unmanifest form in its (material) cause. According to the latter, cause
and effect are distinct entities with distinct natures. Now Hayes (1994:
313) concedes that the prospects of the first alternative are dim. It is
hard to make out what it would mean to say that the effect already
exists prior to its production; to be told that it only exists as a
potentiality is not really to be told any more than just that the cause
will bring it into existence, something we presumably already know.
What Hayes cannot see is why Nàgàrjuna thinks the second alter
native must be rejected. He takes the argument that is supplied in
MMK 1.3cd, 'The intrinsic nature not occurring, neither is the
extrinsic nature (parabhâva) found', to be little more than a play on
words that exploits the ambiguity of the Sanskrit bhâva: 'Something
whose being (bhava) is dependent on another cannot have a nature
(bhâvà) that is its own'. This leads him to see the argument of the
three times (MMK 1.5-7) as a distinct argument against the causal
relation. But this misses the thread of the argument against
asatkaryavâda.
Let us look more closely at how Nàgàrjuna actually argues. The
relevant verses are these:
1. Not from itself, not from another, nor from both, nor with
out cause, Never in any way do there obtain any existing
things that have arisen.
absence of the effect at that time shows that the conditions have not
yet produced any result. (5cd: 'When something has not originated,
why then are they not non-conditions?' 6c: 'If non-existent, what is it
the condition of?') And there is no third time between the time when
the effect does not yet exist and the time when the effect does exist
(7ab: 'a dharma does not operate when [the effect] is ... both existent
and non-existent'). One can supply a third time, the time when the
effect is undergoing production, only by supposing that the effect is
partite and hence not ultimately real. Here it is crucial to recall that
what we are seeking is the ultimate truth concerning the causal
relation; and this must obtain among things that are themselves
ultimately real. Since ultimately real things are impartite, they cannot
be said to undergo a temporally thick process of production; at any
moment, either such an entity exists or it does not. A chariot may
undergo such a process: first there are just the scattered parts, then
some are put together with others to form significant sub-assemblies,
and when enough of these are put together the chariot comes to be.30
But something simple, a dharma, cannot emerge into existence a bit at
a time; either it's there or it is not.
Some care is called for if one is to appreciate the force of this
argument. It is particularly important to bear in mind that the
satkâryavâdin's challenge to asatkâryavâda is still in force. Given that
cause and effect are distinct entities, what is the necessary connection
between them such that the one results in the other? The causal realist
will want to reply that the cause simply produces the effect, as a
potter produces a pot. The effect has the nature it has because it was
produced by a cause with a certain nature of its own, just as this sort
of pot came into existence because the potter had these desires and
performed these actions. But this model of the production relation
requires that the effect gradually emerge through a production pro
cess that occurs over an extended period of time. We see how the
potter could control the nature of the pot because we picture the
potter shaping the clay on the wheel, applying glaze, and then firing it
overnight. And this model is unavailable to the causal realist in the
case of ultimately real entities. If the production relation is to supply
the missing explanatory link, it must relate cause and effect at some
time other than when the effect is undergoing production. This leaves
the time when the effect exists, and the time before the effect has come
into existence. The first alternative is clearly a non-starter. And the
trouble with the second is that it requires that a relation connect an
existing thing with a non-existent. An existing cause can no more
conditions exists, the effect does not yet exist, and when
does exist the set of conditions no longer exists. But why s
this rule out our saying that the conditions produce the effec
is the error in seeing the causal relation as something joi
distinct things at distinct (though contiguous) times? In fa
no error in this-provided we are willing to concede that
relation is conceptually constructed. This was Hume's c
and Bhâvaviveka concurs: 'However, parabhava of the con
found due to intentness of the mind on the desire for w
ductive of the arising of bhava - i.e., just by virtue of ex
(Prajnàpradïpa on MMK 1.3, Pandeya 26). That is, our exp
the past association of a set of conditions and an effect l
expect something with the nature of the effect to arise ou
(distinct) conditions, and the causal relation is just our pro
that expectation. Only the intervention of the mind can ex
two things occurring at distinct times can come into so
relation. The only alternative is to embrace a block un
ception of time, according to which all three times exist t
some timeless sense of 'exists'. And as the Sarvàstivàdins d
this renders impossible a coherent account of change, and t
end leads to eternalism.
Taber would no doubt disagree. He agrees that the satkârya /
asatkaryvada problematic constitutes the framework for Nâgàrjuna's
arguments. But he complains that Nàgàrjuna simply uses the objec
tions of adherents of one theory to attack the other, without con
sidering the 'most reasonable' position that certain cases of causation
might be amenable to treatment under one model, while others are
better accounted for in terms of the other, or exploring the possibility
that there might be refinements of either theory that would enable it
to circumvent the objections raised against it (1998: 221). But while
open-mindedness and flexibility are no doubt intellectual virtues, it is
not clear that they will help us evade Nâgàrjuna's conclusion. For
once we accept the claim that partite entities are conceptually con
structed, then satkaryavada is ruled out as an account of causal
relations among ultimately real things. Yet the satkaryavadin has a
legitimate complaint against asatkñryavñda: if cause and effect are
truly distinct ultimate reals, we need some account of the necessary
connection between them.
That this demand is not easily fulfilled may be seen by looking at
current attempts to respond to it. The most popular approach seeks
to use model-theoretic semantics to explain what sort of necessity is
IV
NOTES
That which is called by you an action pertaining to existents with the four conditions
is considered either to have conditions itself or not to have them. Whether it is
This argument, CandrakTrti makes clear, follows the same reasoning pattern as does
the argument of MMK 2 concerning where motion takes place. And that argument
can be understood as employing the logic of the three times (see de la Vallée Poussin
21 If, Pandeya 199)) Thus the example of the burnt and unburnt employed in
Akutobhayâ could be taken as showing that the argument of MMK 1.4 is actually a
version of the same 'three times' argument deployed in MMK 1.5-7.
26 See MMK 4.6cd: na kâranasyâsadrsam karyam ity upapadyate, on which Cand
rakTrti comments laconically: bhinnalaksanatvàn nirvanavad evety abhiprayah (de la
Vallée Poussin 126, Pandeya 83). I take the point here to be just a refinement of a
Samkhyan argument against asatkàryavâda to the effect that if causation is dia
chronic, as with the lump of clay and the pot, then if the effect does not pre-exist in
its cause, why does an effect of just this sort (a pot) arise, and not any other (curds,
say, or a golden ring)? It is up to the asatkâryavâdin to provide some account of the
necessary connection we take there to be between what we consider cause and effect
such that upon the occurrence of sense-object contact, a sensory cognition will occur
and not nirvana. Perhaps resemblance between cause and effect might go some way
toward allaying this suspicion that on their account anything might follow anything
else. But where cause and effect are both distinct and do not resemble one another,
this suspicion remains in full force.
27 This is in effect how Naiyâyikas responds to the Advaitan infinite regress argu
ment against their formulation of asatkâryavâda. See Prasastapâda's discussion of
inherence in Padârthadharmasamgraha IX. 161.
28 If we follow Buddhapálita and CandrakTrti in their interpretations of verse 4,
there is no infinite regress argument in this verse. Instead, MMK 1.4—7 all present
variations on a single argument, that of the three times.
29 Strictly speaking it is MMK 1.7 that deals with the notion that the hetu is pro
ductive or originative in nature. Verses 5 and 6 simply assert that the alleged con
ditions cannot be designated as such either before or after the effect has arisen. But
CandrakTrti takes the argument of these verses to rely on the idea that in order for
some set of entities and events to count as hetu, they must collectively serve to bring
about or produce the effect. He comments on 6c: 'How would it be a condition of a
non-existent object, of something not found? If it were suggested that the designation
will come from the future existence [of the object], this is not so:
And the difficulty with the notion of power (sakti) is precisely that it is no more than
a sort of black box that is posited in order to close the explanatory gap between cause
and effect. To attribute a power to the conditions is to say no more than that they are
REFERENCES
ABBREVIATIONS
Department of Philosophy
University of Liverpool
Liverpool L69 7WY
UK
E-mail: msideri@ilstu.edu