Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Complex Calculators in The Classroom Theoretical and Practical Teaching in Pre-Calculus

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 25

Complex calculators in the classroom: theoretical and

practical reflections on teaching pre-calculus


Jean-Baptiste Lagrange

To cite this version:


Jean-Baptiste Lagrange. Complex calculators in the classroom: theoretical and practical reflections
on teaching pre-calculus. International Journal of Computers for Mathematical Learning, Springer
Verlag, 1999, 4 (1), pp.51-81. �10.1023/A:1009858714113�. �hal-02379794�

HAL Id: hal-02379794


https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02379794
Submitted on 25 Nov 2019

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est


archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents
entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non,
lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de
teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires
abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés.
Complex calculators in the classroom: theoretical and practical
reflections on teaching pre-calculus
Jean-baptiste LAGRANGE
Institut universitaire de formation des maîtres
153, rue de St Malo 35043 Rennes Cedex FRANCE
Email: lagrange@univ-rennes1.fr

Abstract
University and older school students following scientific courses now use complex calculators
with graphical, numerical and symbolic capabilities. In this context, the design of lessons for
11th grade pre-calculus students was a stimulating challenge.
In the design of lessons, emphasising the role of mediation of calculators and the development
of schemes of use in an ‘instrumental genesis’ was productive. Techniques, often discarded in
teaching with technology, were viewed as a means to connect task to theories. Teaching
techniques of use of a complex calculator in relation with ‘traditional’ techniques was
considered to help students to develop instrumental and paper/pencil schemes, rich in
mathematical meanings and to give sense to symbolic calculations as well as graphical and
numerical approaches.
The paper looks at tasks and techniques to help students to develop an appropriate
instrumental genesis for algebra and functions, and to prepare for calculus. It then focuses on
the potential of the calculator for connecting enactive representations and theoretical calculus.
Finally, it looks at strategies to help students to experiment with symbolic concepts in
calculus.

Introduction
Traditionally, computers and calculators are distinct technological tools in the teaching and
learning of mathematics. Early computer use in mathematics teaching was through
programming, but more recent use tends to favour use of generic packages including software
dedicated to algebra or geometry. In the teaching and learning of algebra and calculus in the
last 10 years there have been many experiments using Computer algebra systems, like
MAPLE and DERIVE, see (Mayes, 1997). Over these years, the use of increasingly
sophisticated hand held calculators has impinged on everyday life as well as on classroom
activities. When sophisticated numerical and graphical capabilities were added, it became
clear to students and sometime to teachers that calculators could play a role in solving
problems involving functions (see Tall, 1996, Trouche, Guin, 1996).
New hand held calculators offer, to some extent, a synthesis of computer software and
calculators1. Like computers they have powerful applications: computer algebra systems,
geometric software and spreadsheet. From calculators they inherit ergonomic characteristics
(small, disposable) and numerical and graphical utilities important to the study of functions.

1
This paper is based on a project where every student had a relatively expensive Texas Instrument TI–92.
Manufacturers now offer complex calculators pricing like ordinary graphing calculators. For instance, the new
TI-89 has the capabilities of the TI-92, except geometry, that we did not use in the project. Looking at the
interface, the TI-92 is like a small computer (high resolution screen, alphabetical keyboard) and the TI-89 is like
a graphing calculator. This difference is not very consequential for the discussion in this paper. Casio offers also
a graphing calculator with symbolic capabilities (the GRAPH 80).
This paper presents an analysis of an attempt to integrate these powerful calculators in the
teaching of pre-calculus in France. This integration has been carried out in four classes of the
ordinary French scientific upper secondary level (11th grade)2. In this paper, I do not seek to
prove that teaching and learning with calculators is definitively better than with traditional
paper and pencil. I merely assume that these calculators are legitimate means of doing
mathematics3. From this assumption, this paper provides reflection, based on theory and
practice, on the changes that these calculators may bring to the teaching and learning of
mathematics, and a search for efficient means to use them in order that students learn
meaningful mathematics.
This TI-92 experiment is a continuation of an earlier French experience looking at the
integration of DERIVE into the study of algebra and calculus. Working in close co-operation
with a group of teachers supported by the National Ministry of Education (DISTEN group,
see Hirliman, 1996) to study the effects of this integration, we carried out a number of
classroom observations from grade 9 to grade 12 (Artigue, 1995, 1997). We also questioned
twenty five teachers and nearly five hundred of their pupils.
From this research we compiled a number of interesting insights on how technology may
support the learning of mathematics, which will be referred to later in this paper. However, an
important limitation of the DERIVE study was that students generally lacked the familiarity
with this technology necessary to really use it to support their mathematical activities and
learning. On many occasions, we saw students using their own numerical calculator to try to
solve a problem numerically, when we expected them to solve it symbolically with the help of
the computer algebra system.
So, when ‘computer-like’ calculators became available we saw the potential for easier student
access to computer algebra technology which might affect their everyday mathematical
practices, and that we would be able to observe more substantial changes. Therefore an offer
by the National Ministry of Education to support a teaching experiment for pre-calculus 11th
grade classes where every student had a TI-92, was stimulating and welcome. However, from
the DERIVE experiment, we knew that the integration of symbolic facilities into the work of
the student was not an easy project. For that reason we had to develop a theoretical approach
to this integration and design lessons/activities which could be applied in a wide range of
settings: to students at various levels of attainment, with varied attitudes to calculators and
mathematics; to teachers with distinctive epistemological views, teaching strategies and
attitudes to calculator use.
It appeared that we had to reflect on two linked set of issues.
• First, how can we conceptualise changes in the mathematical activity in a classroom when
every student has a powerful ‘computer-like’ calculator? To what extent can computer
approaches in the teaching of mathematics be used? How does our experience of using
computer algebra help us? What aspects of the work will be affected by the personal
character of the calculator?

2
Michele Artigue was the leader of the team. Badre Defouad and the author participated with the teachers,
Michele Duperrier and Guy Juge, to the definition of the sessions and did classroom observations and interviews.
A report on the project can be obtained from DIDIREM Université Paris VII 75251 Paris Cedex 05, France. The
project was founded by the French ministry of Education (DISTEN B 2). In the paper, ‘we’ and ‘our’ will refer
to the team. ‘I’ and ‘me’ will be used to express my own ideas and work.
3
Legitimacy of a technological tool is a complex question, which do not limit to improved efficiency. Use by
professional mathematicians, acceptance by parents, allowance at exams are other important factors of
legitimacy.
• Second, what conceptualisation of calculator use, with its many multilevel capabilities,
arises in the teaching of a specific subject? What help do the numerical and graphical
utilities bring? Regarding support for algebraic calculations, do the calculators help to
build symbolic definitions of concepts? How can we think the introduction of the symbolic
capability related with a concept (the key pressed to get a derivative or a limit...)? Does it
help to students to conceptualise, if so in what way? Are these capabilities a danger ? Do
students need to be at a certain skill or conceptual level before using tools like this?
These issues, concerning both technology and mathematics, are of general interest to those
involved in mathematical education. The goal of this paper is to reflect on these issues and
explore outcomes from real teaching situations.

The evolution of approaches to the use of computer technology in the learning


of mathematics

Constructivist approaches
When computers became available, many hopes were placed on the autonomous cognitive
activity that a learner could develop when faced with specific tasks (Artigue, 1996). The
general frame was a Piagetian approach: acting in adequately problematic settings, the learner
meets insufficiency or inconsistency of his/her knowledge. Introducing computer environment
could help to create settings of this kind. The emphasis was put on the role of purposeful
action in the conceptualisation of knowledge in opposition with the passive reception of
meaningless mathematical contents. Computer tasks appeared well suited to these
conceptions4.
Another conception of the construction of mathematical concepts was easily adapted to
computers: many concepts, especially in algebra and calculus, appear with two linked aspects,
as a procedure and as an object. Gray and Tall (1993) introduced the name ‘procept’ to
describe this duality in many areas of mathematics including calculus concepts. Computer
activity, especially programming, can give a sense of this duality. A function, for instance,
can be defined by means of a programmed procedure, then it will be considered and
manipulated through the name of the procedure.
Repo (1994) reports on an example of this approach in the learning of calculus with the use of
DERIVE. She blames the “quite algorithm oriented” learning of mathematics prevalent in
Finnish schools, and offers six “critical activities” to activate prior knowledge of students,
to internalise the concept of derivative, co-ordinate the representations of this concept,
generalise it and understand its reversibility. I will briefly study Repo’s research because it
had a significant influence on the view of Computer Algebra Systems as “cognitive and
didactic tool to engage in reflective abstraction” (Mayes, 1997, p. 185). As for me, I see limits
in this approach and considering these will help to adjust my reflections.
Repo’s research design is that of a comparative study: a control group received “standard
mathematics teaching”, and the experimental group 50 lessons in computer room based on the
above critical activities. In an immediate post-test, the experimental group performed
significantly better on conceptual items, and in a delayed post-test it showed better retention
of algorithmic skills.
My first criticism is that no evidence is given of the influence of the computer on these
improved performances. The control group had a mainly algorithmic introduction to calculus,

4
Papert (1980) is an influential example of a Piagetian approach in a computer environment.
and a common consequence is that they had a low understanding of calculus and a poor long-
term retention of algorithms, so the better achievement in the experimental group may refer to
the poor performances of the control group, rather than to the computer activities. Repo’s
approach stresses an opposition between conceptual understanding and algorithmic skills, and
the activities focus on understanding. Therefore the way students acquired these long-lasting
skills is unclear. In France, approaches based on this opposition and on strong assumptions on
the role of DERIVE to enhance the conceptual learning have been tried. I argue (Lagrange,
1996) that there is a gap between these assumptions and what actually happens in the
classroom. Using symbolic computation in the teaching of mathematics requires teachers and
researchers to think in depth about the relationship between the conceptual and the technical
part of the mathematical activity rather than opposing them.
On a wider reflection Noss and Hoyles (1996, p. 21) stress the potential productivity of the
constructivist approaches, but also their limits. First, when knowledge is built trough actions
in a given computer context, pupils are able to produce powerful reflections on objects in this
context to solve difficult problems, but it is not clear that this knowledge helps with tasks
outside the computer context. It appears, therefore, very contextualised, and the
decontextualisation is a problem. Second, the ‘procedure-object’ approach is sometimes a too
rigid way for building concepts. There is no permanent necessity to consider first an
‘operative’ (Sfard, 1991) approach of concepts. In contrast, computers now offer a range of
views (or windows) on a concept wider than just the procedure-object duality. For instance,
the graphical utility is one between many views of the concept of function in a computer
environment, and the resulting plot can be considered as a procedure (tracing the plot) and as
an object (the global properties of the plot).

The computer’s role in the mediation of students’ activity


Noss and Hoyles (ibid., p. 54) point out the dialectic between human culture and technology.
A ‘cognitive’ tool is made from human cognition and it has an effect on the cognitive
functioning of a person who uses it. In this way, Noss and Hoyles stress, a computer
application may operate as a linguistic tool, and they emphasise programming as a tool for
expressing and articulating ideas. In their approach to the teaching of a topic like
proportionality (p. 75), they combine paper and pencil problem solving, a computerised
‘target game’ and work on Logo procedures for drawing objects in proportion. The power of
expression of the computer helps to broaden students' conceptions of multiplication and,
working on Logo procedures, students act on the relation of proportionality and on a
formalisation of this relation. In off-computer activity students are able to refer to the Logo
formalism for explanation and evaluation.
So, in Noss and Hoyles‘ view, the computer environment is not only a field for students’
purposeful actions. The computer offers special means for interacting with objects. Using the
means, students enlarge their conceptions of the objects, especially towards generalisation and
formalisation. Therefore, Noss and Hoyles introduce this mediation as a major role for the
computer in the student’s process of abstraction. This idea of mediation of instruments in the
mental sphere of human activity was initiated by Vygotskii. Primarily, the mediation is the
use of properties of a given object to act on another for a given task5. The point is that
mediation changes the nature of the action of human over objects. In the psychological

5
« Mediation is a trick of the mind » Hegel quoted by Moro, Scheuwly (1997, p.2).
sphere, Vygotskii’s assumption is that “language, (..) algebraic symbols, (..) and all possible
signs and symbols” are instruments which change the mental activity6.
This idea of mediation is useful in our project because a purely constructivist view of the use
of computers is insufficient to analyse the interaction between the user, his/her instrument and
the objects in the settings. A constructivist view assumes that the computer settings will
provide the means for a predictable and meaningful interaction. What actually happened when
we observed the use of DERIVE was different: interaction situations of the students and
DERIVE were often less productive than teachers’ expectation. Teachers generally expected
that students would build mathematical meaning from DERIVE’s feed-back. Students’
reactions and reflections did not have this meaning because their perception of the feedback
was influenced by the operation of the software (Lagrange, 1996). For instance 9th grade
students with little familiarity with DERIVE, were asked to observe the result of the Expand
command on the square of algebraic sums. The teacher expected that the students would
concentrate on regularities in this expansion like, for instance, the relation of the number of
terms in the sum and in the expansion. In contrast students reflected deeply on the order of the
terms in the expansion, which is a regularity only linked to the software. Mediation accounts
for this phenomenon because students perceived the mathematical settings through DERIVE,
and being unaware of the properties of this instrument, they could not understand that the
regularities that they found had no mathematical significance. In contrast, the teacher was an
expert both in mathematics and in DERIVE, and did not mind this regularity7.
How do contemporary instruments like computers and calculators fit with a theory of
mediation? A computer, as considered by Noss and Hoyles, is an instrument in two
dimensions: a physical object with a keyboard, a screen and so on, and an abstract operative
language. Noss and Hoyles focus on the abstract dimension of the Logo language, and
therefore meet Vygotskii’s view of mental instruments. In the use of complex calculators that
I intend to analyse, this view seems less effective, particularly in the phase where the user is
learning new capabilities. In this phase, a user sees the internal capabilities through the
features of the interface (for instance, with a TI-928, the different capabilities for solving are
seen through various entries of the algebra menus). This perception of the calculator does not
distinguish between the interface and the internal logic. This phase of learning is what I want
to analyse because, in this phase, cognitive processes are likely to appear, involving both the
calculator and mathematics.
For this reason, I prefer to consider a calculator as a complex instrument like those existing in
the area of professional working (for instance a computerised system to pilot a process) rather
than to reduce it to an addition of a neutral interface and an internal algebraic language. An
advantage of this approach is that it is easier to think about the changing relation of the user
and his/her calculator: in this relation, the user discovers together the characteristics of his/her
calculator together with the mathematical underlying features.

The role of the instrumental schemes


The process of development of new uses of an instrument, and the associated cognitive
changes, have been analysed by psychologists in terms of conceptualisation. In a ‘study of

6
Quoted by Moro, Scheuwly (ibid, p. 3).
7
Artigue (1995) named « pseudo-transparency » this phenomenon: in the mediation, the instrument is
transparent for the teacher, but not for students.
8
In the paper, TI-92 may be replaced by TI-89 or other complex calculator with the same symbolic, graphic and
numeric capabilitites. See note 1.
thought in relation to instrumented activity’, Verillon and Rabardel (1995)9 stress that a
human creation, an ‘artefact’, is not immediately an instrument. A human being who wants to
use an artefact builds up his/her relation with the artefact in two directions: externally s/he
develops uses of the artefact and internally, s/he builds cognitive structures to control these
uses. After Piaget, Verillon and Rabardel describe these structures in terms of schemes, which
are mental means that a person creates to assimilate a situation. When a person acts on
settings trough an instrument his/her behaviour has a specific organisation. For that reason,
the authors10 introduces the notion of ‘instrument utilisation schemes’. These utilisation
schemes have the properties of adaptation and assimilation of the schemes and direct the uses
of the instrument by the person. Being mental structures of a person, utilisation schemes are
not given with the artefact. They are built in an ‘instrumental genesis’ which combines the
development of uses and the adaptation of schemes: when developing the first uses, a person
pilots the artefact through existing schemes, then this primitive experience is the occasion of
an adaptation of the schemes, and the better adapted schemes are a basis for developing new
uses, and so on. This genesis is both individual and social: a person builds his/her own mental
structures, but, generally, an instrument is not used by only one person and therefore the
process of adaptation takes place in a social context.

Schemes in calculus using a complex calculator


Verillon and Rabardel 's cognitive approach to instruments shares many aspects of Hoyles and
Noss' view of the computer in mathematical activity: the instrument is not something neutral,
it has an effect on the cognitive functioning of a person who uses it. The cognitive approach
describes this effect as the development of specific schemes, and organises this development
in a genesis. This approach was stimulating for our project of integrating ‘computer-like’
calculators because they are complex devices with a lot of capabilities, each of them implying
many specific schemes that the user has to co-ordinate to achieve a given task. The idea of
genesis is useful because our project took place over a year and we had to think through the
development of the uses and the schemes, together with the progression of the mathematical
topics.
As an example, Figure 1 displays various schemes, calculator oriented or not, algebraic,
graphic or symbolic that a user of a TI-92 can use to search for the variations of a function
x 2 + x + 0.01
like . The schemes have several dimension of functionality: decisional, they
x
organise and control the action ; pragmatic, they act on the settings ; interpretative, they help
to understand the settings.

9
See also, in French, Rabardel (1995, p. 37).
10
See also Rabardel (ibid, p. 93).
Nature of TI-92 output Decisional Pragmatic Interpretative
scheme dimension dimension dimension
Graphic, Graphing in the Consider the Function is
TI-92 standard window graph of the increasing.
is a good function in the Graph is a straight
approach for the standard window line
variations of a
function
Algebraic, none Graphical Consider the f(x) is not a linear
criticism evidence must be algebraic function
compared to definition of the
algebraic aspects function
Analytic, Expanding an Consider another There is
TI-92 expression will algebraic something special
give a linear and a expression of the near x=0
fractional part, function
helping the
interpretation of
the graph
Graphic, Graphic display Zoom in around There are two
TI-92 will confirm x=0 and y=0 until turning points near
analytic ideas something appears zero and there is a
discontinuity

Calculus, Use the derivative Find the zeros of Position of the


TI-92 to search for the the derivative turning points is
turning points algebraically
confirmed
Calculus, When the result of Adjust the limit Nature of the
TI-92 limit is undef, command to discontinuity is
then there are left obtain left and found
and right hand right hand limits
limits
Figure 1: Schemes in a search for the variations of a function
Being adaptive mental constructs, schemes cannot be entirely described in a rational form. In
Figure 1, some of them are approached by their nature and by features of the above three
dimensions. Many other schemes exist and are more difficult to describe. For instance, in the
Graph window, a student often develop exploratory zooming based on his (her) private
knowledge and previous experience. Moreover, schemes in Figure 1 are made of a number
of ’sub-schemes’ more difficult to explicit11. Nevertheless, the brief description of schemes in
Figure 1 accounts for the complexity of an action with this complex instrument, and from this
description, I will show what relation students may have with these schemes.
The first scheme (graphing in the standard window) is prevalent among most students. In the
initial stages of learning calculus very few students are able to produce critical interpretations
such as those in the second scheme, even when they have the algebraic knowledge to do so.
The more able students develop schemes where graphical action is linked with algebraic and
analytic interpretation: they see, in the graph, properties that they anticipate from an algebraic

11
Trouche (1996, p. 303) produces a comprehensive analysis and classification of schemes in a search for a limit
of a function.
analysis of the function. This co-operation of schemes of different nature gives them a new
efficiency.
Transforming the expression of the function like in the third scheme is not a spontaneous
action. Most students initially choose the transformation randomly among the TI-92
capabilities rather than from rational reflection. Teaching can help to develop this reflection.
Switching back to the graph window, as in the fourth scheme, is quite natural. Some students
anticipate immediately the required zooming, while others take considerable time over this
decision. The latter may use trial and error processes, productive for some but unproductive
for others.
The calculus approach in the fifth scheme may derive from a teaching method. I observed,
however, that this scheme is activated only when the function is similar to standard functions
considered in the teaching. When a student is perplexed, because of an unusual function, this
scheme is not likely to appear. It may not appear with the example of Figure 1, because
variations are not perceptible in a standard window. It certainly does not appear when a
student meets a new type of function, for instance a trigonometric function when the student
is used to rational functions.
The sixth scheme is about limits. It illustrates how specific an instrumental scheme may be. In
ordinary paper and pencil practice, the notion of left and right hand limit is difficult because
their computation implies a reflection on the sign of sub-expression which is not familiar to
students. With the TI-92, the scheme described in Figure 1 works well on most functions and
contributes to give sense to this notion. However, this sense is often partial, because most
students have difficulties in interpreting the values of the limits in term of asymptotical
behaviour of the graph.
In this brief description of features of schemes appearing in a calculus task, and their
apprehension by students, the question of genesis appears with some complexity. The
development of utilisation schemes by students appears to be linked to the development of
their mathematical knowledge. But what is the nature of this link? Schemes appear to be more
or less influenced by teaching. But what is this influence, and how is teaching to be oriented
to help the development of suitable schemes, their generalisation and their co-ordination ?
These questions call for theoretical and practical reflection that I will undertake in the
following section.

An approach of teaching with instruments

Schemes for building knowledge


Rabardel and Vérillon's approach is an ergonomic one: finding a better way of
conceptualising human-instrument relations. Hoyles and Noss' concern, as well as ours, is
slightly different: to try to conceptualise how the use of instruments intervenes in the learning
of mathematical topics. With respect to this aim we can go back to Vergnaud’s (1990) work
on the role of schemes in conceptualisation: schemes organise the behaviour of a person in a
class of problems and situations representative of a field of concepts and are a basis for
knowledge in this field. A given concept, from this viewpoint, can be seen in relation to the
set of problems to which it provides a means of solution, and knowledge of this concept
derives from the schemes that a person builds to solve these problems.
When a person learns mathematics with an instrument, his (her) schemes organise behaviours
related to the use of the instrument as well as more general conducts. Interpreting Noss and
Hoyles' study of a teaching of proportionality, I can see that Logo programming is an
instrumental practice for manipulating a formalisation of proportionality in a problem of
expanding given patterns. Acting with this instrument, students develop utilisation schemes,
for instance rules of transformation of Logo expressions to maintain the shape of a pattern.
These schemes are specific and not directly transferred in a non-Logo context. But, together
with other schemes, they are a frame for students’ conceptual reflection, and they make
specific contributions to that reflection.
At this point, comparing earlier approaches where mathematical knowledge is thought to be
built from situations involving personal interaction with the computer, the potential
contributions of computers and of calculators appears different: technology acts as a mediator
for the action of students. In this mediation technology is by no means neutral: students have
to elaborate utilisation schemes, a non-trivial task.
This approach is consistent with Hoyles and Noss' view of the role of technology in building
mathematical meanings. In addition, I focus on the development of uses and utilisation
schemes because in our project the students use a complex calculator over the course of a year
as a everyday support to their mathematical practices. Given this, adequate utilisation
schemes of ‘hand held’ technology are a condition for this support. In turn, the development
of schemes (the instrumental genesis) is dependent on students’ progressive understanding of
the calculus. For this reason I emphasise this genesis and its role in students' learning.
The genesis is, however, problematic. Mathematical meaning and knowledge grow with the
multiple schemes that students develop when doing tasks in a domain, but not all schemes are
productive of adequate knowledge in all situations. Consider, for instance, the limit of a
rational expression at a finite or infinite point. In an ordinary ‘non computer’ context, students
1
may apply the following reasoning to, say, lim : ‘one over a large number will be small...,
x→∞ x
therefore, the limit is 0’. When the expression is more complex they may transform it, e.g.
( )
change lim x − x 2 into lim ( x(1 − x )) . Numerical and graphical approaches may contribute
x →∞ x →∞
to students’ progressive understanding of this task.
In contrast, with a calculator like the TI-92 or algebraic software like DERIVE, students are
able to associate the idea of limit with a single scheme: pressing the ‘limit’ key of the
calculator and reading the output on the screen. This scheme is effective for the task but, as
Monaghan et al. (1994) observed, it may result in giving students a narrow understanding of
the notion of limit. Comparing students who made extensive use of DERIVE with other
students, they found that the latter had more varied representations of limits including
infinitesimal approaches, whereas the DERIVE students focused solely on limits as objects.
Viewing their report from the perspective of my theoretical framework, I say that the scheme
associates too closely the idea of limit with the limit capabilities of DERIVE and this scheme
generates a restricted mathematical meaning.
On the other hand, the scheme for right and left hand limits in the example of figure 1 is very
close to the above ‘key-stroke limit scheme’. I said above that it is productive when giving
students a sense of the existence of the limits, otherwise hard to grasp, because of the
difficulty of calculation.
So, depending on their co-operation with other schemes or meanings, schemes of use of the
TI-92 or DERIVE are productive or not. Therefore, for the support of the technology to be
effective teachers must control students’ development of utilisation schemes and their co-
ordination with the advancement of mathematical knowledge. However, there might be a
contradiction here, because schemes are mental structures built by the student, rather than
objects for the process of communication, like teaching. I thus examine the role of teaching in
the context of the use of technology by students.

The role of tasks and techniques


I look at the teaching of techniques and at the relationship of this with the instrumental
genesis, as this is a key point in the use of technology to teach and learn calculus. In Repo’s
(1994) research we saw above that approaches of this use may pretend to favour students’
higher conceptual thinking, in opposition with the usual training to algorithms in the
paper/pencil context. More precisely, authors and teachers assume that the symbolic
capabilities in this technology are means to lessen the stress on techniques which, they
consider, restrain students’ reflection on concepts. This view was clearly present in teachers’
expectations in the French DERIVE experiment, and reflecting on this was useful in
establishing the limits of this excessively conceptual approach (Lagrange, 1996).
First, the technical work did not vanish when doing mathematics using Computer Algebra.
Not all students welcomed the relief from the usual pen and paper skills: some of them
considered these skills as important for success in Mathematics. It also appeared that using
Computer Algebra itself required specific techniques. For instance, when a student obtains an
output using the system, this output is not always the usual expression generally accepted in
the pen and paper context. In this situation few students could transform the system's output to
obtain the usual expression. A consequence is that although most students thought of
Computer Algebra as a helpful tool for ‘double checking’, they generally lacked the
techniques to perform effectively this double check.
Understanding mathematics with the help of Computer Algebra was not a view that students
generally considered. Even when they enjoyed the new classroom situations they experienced
using Computer Algebra, they generally did not recognise that these situations could bring a
better comprehension of mathematical content because the situations focused on conceptual
aspects of a subject, and not on the usual techniques associated with this content.
This observation was a starting point for a reflection on the relationship between the technical
and conceptual part of mathematical activities. Chevallard (1992, 1996) stresses the links
between techniques and theory. Every topic, mathematical or not, has a set of tasks and
methods to perform these tasks. Newcomers in the topic see the tasks as problems.
Progressively they acquire the means to achieve them and they become skilled. That is how
they acquire techniques in a topic. Furthermore, in teaching and learning situations, the
students and the teachers are not interested in simply acquiring and applying a set of
techniques. They want to talk about them, and therefore they develop a specific language.
Then, they can use this language to question the consistency and the limits of the techniques.
In this way they reach a theoretical understanding of a topic.
A break from teaching based exclusively on training in algorithmic skills is certainly
interesting. However, teachers' and researchers' views of the support of symbolic computation
tends to hide the need for a set of techniques.
So, I emphasised above the role of schemes in the process of conceptualisation, and now I
stress the need for techniques in the teaching of concepts. But what is the relationship
between schemes and techniques? I said above that schemes, being internal adaptive
constructions of a person, cannot be taught directly. In contrast, techniques are rational
elaborations used in teaching. Techniques are official means of achieving a task but, in facing
the task, a person doesn’t ‘follow’ a technique, especially when the task is new or more
complex or more problematic than usual. When knowledge is requested a person acts through
schemes.
So, in an educational context, techniques can be seen as official, rational objects for
communicating whereas schemes are structures actually produced in students’ mind12.
Drilling on a single technique for a given task without reflection is only able to produce
manipulative schemes and poor knowledge. Many innovators, particularly in the field of the
use of computer, argue this to diminish the role of techniques and try to promote ‘conceptual
mathematics’. I observed in the DERIVE experiment that diminishing the role of techniques
encouraged teachers to avoid devoting time for discussion on these. In contrast, talking of
techniques in the classroom might help students to develop suitable schemes. Furthermore, in
this communication a specific language and theoretical reflection is able to appear and
students can enhance the reflective part of their schemes.

Techniques in the use of a complex calculator


Returning the use of symbolic computation, graphical, numerical and symbolic facilities make
traditional techniques less relevant. In addition, the role of those techniques is often
undervalued because teachers see them as the routine part of their activity. New techniques
should be taught to help the development of utilisation schemes but teachers often believe that
these techniques are obvious or linked too closely to the calculator to be relevant. The
necessity and relevance of new techniques may be made clear by considering the task in
Figure 2. It was given in a French experimental exam designed to test the adequacy of a set of
questions when students are allowed to use calculators. The text is written to avoid giving
advantage to students with a symbolic calculator: a factorised expression of the derivative is
given, so students without symbolic facilities are able to do the subsequent question
(variations of f) in a similar manner to students who obtain this expression from their
symbolic calculator. But, when I consider the TI-92 answer for the derivative, I see that the
task of the user with a symbolic calculator is not straightforward. The TI-92 answer is neither
the expression of the text nor the raw form obtained when applying the rules of
differentiation. Recognising the expression of the text as a factorised form the user may apply
the factor command. Again, the expression is not the same as in the text. Therefore the user
has first to show how the TI-92 answer can be obtained from the raw differentiation and then
reflect on the two TI-92 expressions to show their equivalence with the expression of the text.
Techniques exist to do that (for instance, differentiating sub expressions helps to obtain the
raw form, reflecting on the desired form helps to choose the right application), and, although
linked to the calculator, these techniques might be a topic for teaching. For instance, reflecting
on the desired expression on theTI-92 may help students to focus on the forms of the
expressions.

12
In this paragraph, I look briefly at the relationship between schemes and techniques, to emphasise their
respective functions. Schemes and techniques may be viewed in a more dialectical relation. There is a wide
range, from personal hidden elementary schemes to social global schemes. The latter are more easily
rationalised. Teaching can act more directly on these schemes, very similar to techniques. See again Trouche
(ibid.)
The text of the question
Consider the function f define for strictly positive real numbers by
f ( x ) = x ln( x ) − 2 ln( x ) − (ln( x ) ) .
2

⎛ 2⎞
Demonstrate that the derivative of f is given by f ' ( x ) = ⎜ 1 − ⎟ (1 + ln( x ) )
⎝ x⎠
Using the TI-92 to answer

Figure 2: a task in an experimental exam


TI-92 techniques are specific because they rationalise schemes of use of an instrument, and,
according to Rabardel and Vérillon, these schemes develop in an instrumental genesis. A
consequence is that the organisation of the tasks and associated techniques must comply with
the constraints of that genesis and direct it in a productive way: schemes cannot develop
arbitrary and not all combinations of schemes are productive for mathematical meaning.
Below I look more closely at these constraints and their implications in terms of tasks and
techniques, from the experience of the TI-92 project.

Teaching pre-calculus with computer-like calculators


Our team choose a level where the legitimacy of an unusual and relatively expensive
calculator might be accepted13. In the French general upper secondary level, students are in
three main branches: literature, economy and science. In this latter branch students' use of
calculators with sophisticated numerical and graphical capabilities is now well established.
Thus, we expected that students accept the TI-92 in spite of its unusual aspect, as an
'enhanced' substitute for their familiar calculator. We chose the first year (eleventh grade),
because the 'baccalaureat', at the end of the second and last year of this course brings students
much anxiety, with possible negative effects on the experiment. The curriculum of this first
year is an introduction to calculus concepts (functions, limits and derivatives) and to their
application, based on problem solving and on experimenting. This curriculum suited our
approach well, because it focuses on the development of abilities in algebra and calculus and
on the understanding of functional concepts, an interesting frame for an instrumental genesis.
We worked with two teachers in two distinct regions of France. Thus, although the teachers
collaborated, we might observe two distinct experiences of the integration of the TI-92. In the
first year, our work was mainly observing classroom sessions and students. The teachers had
been working with us in the DERIVE experiment, and we asked them to adapt the many
sessions that teachers built in this experiment, in order to use the calculator in every suitable
classroom situation.
The observation of the students was done by way of three attitudinal questionnaires and three
individual interviews of a sample of students. From the observation in the first year and from

13
See footnote 3.
the analysis of classroom sessions in the same year, we built our project, a series of lessons
and classroom activities that the French Ministry of Education will publish as a guideline for
teachers. We experimented this project in the second year: the teachers taught the lessons and
we did an observation like in the first year.
The aim of this paper is not to report this whole experimentation, but to emphasise the role of
teaching. Lagrange (to appear) will focus on the observation of students. It will show how, in
the first year, the acquisition of utilisation schemes was a long and complex process, effective
for some students and more problematic for others, with significant differences between
individual students and between the two classes. It will also discuss the improvement that the
project that we experimented the second year brought in students' attitudes and abilities. Here,
in this paper, from the lessons that we experimented in the second year, I offer a view on how
teaching might help the development of schemes productive to mathematical meaning. The
observation of students' genesis in the first year will be used to show the necessity of this
view14, and classroom observations in the second year will help to discuss its effectiveness.

Tasks and techniques to develop an appropriate instrumental genesis for algebra


and functions
Obviously, at the beginning of an instrumental genesis, a user exercises the schemes s/he built
for other familiar instruments. For instance, when a beginner uses his/her new TI-92 to do a
division, like 34 divided into 14, s/he keys in 3 4 / 1 4 = like on an ordinary numerical
calculator and s/he is very surprised when the TI-92 answers 17/7. Tasks and techniques are
to be organised to help him/her learn that, in the default mode, the TI-92 simplifies radicals
and rational numbers symbolically and that decimal approximations must be specifically
requested. Moreover, the user has to consider that the graph window handles functions in an
approximate mode. Meanwhile, s/he has to consider, more acutely than usual, the difference
between the mathematical treatment of numbers and the approximations of everyday practice.
Then schemes of use of the algebraic capabilities are essential. Symbolic applications like
DERIVE or the main module of the TI-92 are basically algebraic, even when they include
facilities in calculus: their core is the treatment of expressions that a student has to understand
before s/he is able to use them for problems on functions. A key point is the notion of
equivalence of expressions and the need for awareness of the different equivalent forms of an
expression. A TI-92 user meets automatic simplification as soon as an expression is entered.
The following screen displays an example of a puzzling phenomenon occurring with an
automatic simplification. Two obviously equivalent expressions are ‘simplified’ in two
radically different forms.

So a student cannot rely on automatic simplification to obtain the form s/he needs for an
expression. S/he must consciously learn to use the items of the algebra menu (Factor,

14
Defouad (to appear) analyses more comprehensively the varied individual genesis of students.
Expand, ComDenom), to decide whether expressions are equivalent as well as anticipate the
output of a given transformation on a given expression.
The following screens (Figure 3) give a hint of the tasks involved in our scheme, to develop
students’ algebraic instrumental schemes.

Screen A Screen B
Figure 3: algebraic tasks
In a first task students had to enter the expressions on the left of the screen A and then observe
the TI-92 simplification on the right of the screen A. They then identified the mathematical
treatment: expanding, factoring, ordering, partial fractional expanding. In another task, an
expression G was given, with three other apparently similar expressions H, I, J. The student
had to find a TI-92 command to decide what expression H, I, J is equivalent to G. In this task,
x 2 − 6x + 2 −11x + 4 x 3 x 11
G was , H was + , I was − + and J was
2x − 1 2x − 1 2 4(2 x − 1) 2 4
(x + )(
7 −3 x− 7 −3 ) . By expanding G, students had no difficulty seeing that I was the
2x − 1
opposite of G (screen B). In contrast, showing that G and H are equivalent, is not
straightforward: in the screen B, the function for the reduction of a sum of rational
expressions has been used to reduce a sub-expression. Factor was the appropriate function to
obtain J from G.
Work on the equivalence of expressions proved necessary not only at the beginning of the
TI-92 use. For example, towards the end of the academic year of student TI-92 use the teacher
⎛ π⎞
asked them to differentiate the trigonometric function x → cos⎜ 3x − ⎟ by hand and with the
⎝ 6⎠
TI-92, and to explain why resulting expressions are equivalent. The application of rules of
⎛ π⎞ ⎛ π⎞
differentiation gives −3 sin⎜ 3x − ⎟ when the TI-92 gives 3 cos⎜ 3x + ⎟ . We expected that
⎝ 6⎠ ⎝ 3⎠
⎛ π⎞ ⎛ π⎞
students could give a reason like cos⎜ a + ⎟ = − sin⎜ a − ⎟ , because they knew the property
⎝ 3⎠ ⎝ 6⎠
⎛ π⎞
cos⎜ a + ⎟ = − sin(a ) but only 8 in a class of 26 were able to do that. Others expressed
⎝ 2⎠
general reasons like “the calculator doesn’t work like we do”. So the work on the equivalence
of expressions had to be continued when new expressions were introduced to help students to
build suitable utilisation schemes.
As stated before, conscious use of the algebraic capabilities of the TI-92 may help students to
focus on the most suitable form for a given task, whereas paper and pencil schemes focus on
the rules of transformation. One may reasonably think that the joint development of the TI-92
and paper/pencil schemes is able to give an understanding of the equivalence of expression.
This is an example of how paper and pencil and TI-92 practices are to be thought
complementary in teaching, rather than opposed.
Like many calculators, the TI-92 offers a graphical window and a numerical table with a wide
range of capabilities. Therefore, it may enhance early functional thinking because graphical
and numerical schemes are essential for the growth of the function concept. As seen above, in
Figure 1, notions like the variations of a function implies the co-ordination of algebraic and
graphico-numerical utilisation schemes. Able users adjust settings of the graph window to
make visible properties that they see algebraically, and use algebraic transformations to prove
properties that they read from a graph.
A relevant task for developing these schemes is the study of functions whose properties are
not obvious in a standard graph (see Figure 1 for an example, and Guin, Trouche, 1998 for
others). From a task like this, teaching may focus on techniques for useful zooming
(identifying values of interest, specifying the graph window to show those values...) and for
relevant algebraic transformation (Expand for finding the asymptotic behaviour, Solve for the
intersection with axis...). From this, students can get a better view of the treatment of
functions in the graph window.

Helping students to develop flexible links between calculus concept representations


Work and schemes in algebra and functions is not itself calculus, but it is the first part of a
genesis in which limits and differentiation can develop. The use of the TI-92 in pre-calculus is
quite simple: a menu entry for the symbolic calculation of limits and a key for the calculation
of derivatives. So, as a difference with algebra and functions, no specific instrumental
learning will be necessary. However, we saw above, with limits, that this use tends to produce
symbolic manipulative schemes, likely to generate a narrow understanding of these concepts
if they are alone. This implies a deep reflection on how teaching can help the development of
other schemes, instrumental or not, that students could associate to the idea of limit and
derivative.
Tall (1996) stresses that there is not a single way, but ‘a spectrum of possible approaches ...
from real-word calculus ... through the numeric, symbolic and graphic representations in
elementary calculus, and on the to the formal ... approach of analysis’. He emphasises the
need for helping students to move flexibly from one representation to another. He notes,
moreover, that in teaching the balance between various approaches is difficult to establish
because an approach well suited for one student will not necessary suit another, due to
differing cognitive profiles. Traditional balances exist but technology tends to toss them
about.
For instance, in France, every student in the secondary level now has a graphico-numerical
calculator. This situation clearly changes the balance of numeric and graphical representations
and of the symbolic view of the concepts of calculus. For instance, in a traditional approach,
searching for the variations of a function began with symbolic study. The result of this study
was a set of particular values of the variable (turning points, asymptotic branches...). Values
of the function were calculated for those particular values: they were few because of the
lengthy calculations by hand. These values helped to scale, then plot the graph of the function,
which, in turn, helped to check the consistency of the symbolic study. So, in this traditional
approach, the symbolic study commanded the study of variations. In contrast, with numerico-
graphical calculators, graphing, zooming, calculating tables of values is very easy and a
student will use these facilities extensively to get graphical or numerical evidence of limits or
variations. Symbolic calculations are relatively difficult, as they necessitate paper and pencil
work, and a different reflection. Many authors emphasise the potential of graphic calculators
for developing new understandings and skills (see for instance Shoaf-Grubbs, 1995). It is,
nevertheless, true that these calculators make the traditional balance of symbolic and
graphico-numerical representations redundant, but a new balance is not yet clearly
established. A cautious approach would be to encourage students to use a symbolic approach
to control their calculator work, but students often prefer experimenting rather than analysing.
Trouche (1996) noticed this behaviour and emphasises the schemes that students should
develop to control the graphs and numbers they obtain on their calculators: these schemes are
theoretical (through algebraic or analytic considerations), enactive (the student acts on the
picture, for instance s/he traces a graph) or reflective (producing other graphs/pictures). He
suggests specific teaching strategies to help students to get these schemes.
Now, with the TI-9215, calculators are graphico-numeric and symbolic. Little is known of
how this new feature will affect the balance between representations. In most studies, students
do not have enough practice of computer algebra to effect a change in the links between
representations, or authors do not consider this question16.
A first difficulty is the higher complexity of this instrument. With common graphing
calculators, graphical and numerical schemes are instrumental when analytic schemes are
associated with pencil and paper practices. In contrast, with the TI-92, co-ordinating analytic
and graphico-numerical schemes implies controlled switches between windows. In those
switches, a flexible view of the organisation of functions in the calculator is essential. An
example of the difficulties occurring because of a limited view was observed with one
student. She had limited knowledge of the capabilities of her TI-92 and one of her peers
entered the following into her calculator:

So, the second function, y2, was systematically defined as the derivative of the first function
y1. When she had to study a function, she introduced this function as y1, and then, without
doing anything, y2 was its derivative. She did know that, but not the way it worked. So in
ordinary tasks with her calculator she was comfortable. But when she had to use another
calculator, or in a task involving two functions, she was totally confused.
Whatever the difficulties, the design of teaching modules for pre-calculus courses forced our
team to make assumptions on how, with easier symbolic calculation, teaching may obtain an
adequate balance between representations. We assumed first that easier symbolic calculation
enlarges the possibility of linking enactive representations and theoretical calculus, and also
that teaching must avoid the danger of too close an association between concepts and
symbolic manipulative schemes, wiping out other representations.

15
and other calculators: see note 1.
16
Ruthven (1997) reviewed a number of researches into CAS in mathematics education. The prevalent topic
appearing in this review was the comparison of student performances between CAS and non CAS students.
Research reports on the impact of CAS in the everyday teaching are very recently available. One of them is
Guin, Trouche (1998)’s study.
Linking enactive representations and theoretical calculus
Enactive representations (Tall, 1996) exist in the prior differential knowledge of students. For
instance, most students have a sense of the tangential behaviour of curves from their
geometrical experience. It seems important to use this knowledge as a basis for the theoretical
concept of derivative, because differentiation is an analytic answer to the question of the
tangent line for a curve defined by a function. However, in the ordinary context of paper and
pencil calculations, students cannot really question their enactive differential notions because
they would have to consider, and give sense to, expressions which are beyond their
experience17. Using symbolic computation potentially helps students to work with these
expressions and to understand their meaning.
As an example, let us consider the introduction of the concept of derivative we experimented.
It starts from the following problem: Let (G) be the graph of the function f defined by
f ( x ) = x 2 − 1 and A be the point (1 , 0). For every straight line passing through A, a number
m exists such that an equation is y = m( x − 1) . What straight line gives the best fit of the
graph (G)? Through geometrical experience students were able to guess that the line of best fit
is when m=2. But the teacher stressed that, for m=1.9 and m=2.1, the lines also fit well, and
students recognised that zooming doesn’t help to distinguish the ‘fitness’ of the three lines.

From this reflection it appeared necessary to consider the distances between an arbitrary point
on the curve, near A, and the points of same abscissa (1+h) on the lines. The first three lines
of the TI-92 main screen below display the expressions of this distance for the three lines.

The simplified forms (on the right of the screen) gave a hint of why the line fits better for
m=2. In ordinary paper and pencil practice, the expressions and simplification would have
been complex for students and would have hidden the sense of the expressions. A feature of
symbolic computation is that students were able to focus on the symbolic forms without being

17
Motion and velocity are other enactive differential notions that could be considered. Questioning this notion
seemed even more difficult for students. So we did not consider this notion in the introduction of the concept of
derivative. It seemed however interesting that students establish the link between this notion and the
differentiation when the concept of derivative and associated schemes were steady enough.
For a very stimulating picture of problems arising when students have to build mathematical representations of
motion, see Boyd and Rubin (1996). Interestingly, they study the effect of mediation by a non-computer
technology: the interactive video.
disturbed by the complexity of hand calculations18. Students were, moreover, able to address
the more general question of what line fits the best among all lines passing through A.
Calculating with a parameter is never easy for students at this level, but the symbolic
computation (last line of the screen) made it similar to the preceding calculations.
Furthermore, given the aim to develop students’ links between their enactive conceptions of
tangent lines and the theoretical notion of derivative, one example is clearly not enough.
Symbolic computation again may make a contribution because students were able to address
the same question, first for other points of the same graph (G), then for other functions. The
example below shows a screen for the same function defined by f ( x ) = x 2 − 1 at the point
x=2, then for a cubic function at the point x=1.

In this process, students operated by themselves progressive modifications of the above


expression, and in doing so, concentrated on the expression and grasped its sense19. The
symbolic capabilities of the TI-92 were essential in helping students to focus on the algebraic
forms. However, they needed good algebraic schemes of use of the TI-92 to give sense to the
transformations.

Symbolic aspects of calculus concepts


I expressed my concerns above that students may use the symbolic capabilities for very
simple limits or derivatives and see nothing more in those concepts than the manipulative
aspects. In the paper and pencil context the tendency for students to consider mathematics as
meaningless symbolic manipulation exists, but these manipulations are often tedious and
better replaced by a reflection which involves other representations of the concepts. As
Monaghan et al. (1994) argue, symbolic computation may make manipulations effortless but
tends to obscure other representations linked with infinitesimal approaches. For that reason,
we preferred to introduce the TI-92 capabilities for limits and derivative only after students
did considerable work on the concepts, linking enactive views with graphico-numerical
approaches and symbolic forms. This is clearly distinct from approaches like Watkins (1992)
which introduce calculus concepts as outputs of symbolic computations. Watkins’ concern,
however, is with vocational courses where little time is devoted to conceptual developments.
At the secondary general level the balance of representations should be a major goal.
So, in our proposition, the limit concept was introduced from an intuitive view that a function
‘tends toward zero as x tends toward zero’. Students did a lot of graphic and numeric work,
passing from ‘ f(x) is small when x is small’ to ‘f(x) can be arbitrarily small provided that x is

18
Students were however interested for knowing the reason why the expressions simplified in that form. That is
why the teacher asked them to develop and simplify with paper and pencil one of the expressions. Done
separately of the main process of solving, and for only one expression, this hand calculation gave this process a
complementary meaning without obscuring it.
19
This process has clear links with the formalisation of proportionality in expanding patterns of Noss and
Hoyles: pupils have a perceptive (enactive) idea of patterns in proportion, and the computer helps them to
consider a formalised relation between those patterns.
small enough’. Then students had to study by the same means standard, as well as non
regular, limits before the limit function of the TI-92 was introduced.
The concept of derivative was introduced from a geometrical representation, as outlined
above, and another two sessions focused on activities where students had first to build a
formal definition of the derivative and then as for the limits, search for derivatives of standard
as well as non regular functions. In this work, students used the symbolic and graphic
facilities of the TI-92, but not the key for the symbolic differentiation (see screens).

After this it was time to consider the symbolic aspects of the concepts, namely the algebraic
rules by which a person or a machine is able to obtain derivatives or limits of expressions.
The question was how to use the TI-92 to teach students algebraic rules that their calculator
uses, and to give those rules a meaning.
Authors introduced the “black-box-white-box process” which could be an answer to the above
question.
Using the CAS20 as a black box enables students to discover mathematical theories,
concepts or algorithms (...) to the point where the students say ‘we are able to do what
the CAS can do’ (Heugl, 1997, p. 34).
This is, in my opinion, too simplistic a view of the support computer algebra can give: using a
CAS as a black box, students will only discover symbolic entities. Learning theories and
concepts implies wider strategies, as we have seen above. However, as the black-box-white-
box process focuses on symbolic aspects of concepts, it could be useful for teaching symbolic
rules.
For instance, students could consider several examples of how the TI-92 computes limits and
derivatives and then learn to do those calculations by themselves. In this process the student is
likely to have more self-reflection than in a formal approach where the teacher demonstrates
the rules. However, from experience, we consider that implementing such processes is not so
simple. The first problem is that in this process students are prone to see only the
manipulative aspect of the rules, even when previous teaching focused on other
representations of the concepts.
Another difficulty occurs when students have insufficient algebraic maturity to give a suitable
meaning to the feedback from the computer. Pozzi (1994) gives an example where students
had to understand the rule for the differentiation of a product of functions. They considered
( )
the differentiation of x → cos( x ) 7 x 3 + 2 x , and, using DERIVE, they obtained
( )
( 21x + 2) cos( x ) − x 7 x + 2 sin x . Then, they deeply reflected on the central part of the
2 2

expression cos( x ) − x(7 x 2


+ 2) and found it to be very similar to the original function. They
tried unsuccessfully to derive a general rule from this example. Clearly, their reflection was

20
Computer Algebra System
misplaced because they did not see that the central part is not a sub-expression of the
derivative. Once more, we see how good algebraic schemes are essential to be able to make
sense of computer algebra output.
Pozzi further stresses that ‘computer algebra systems can support students to make sense of
their algebraic generalisation’ but he maintains that ‘this is only likely to be achieved if
(students) use the computer to explore and verify their conclusions and not simply as a
symbolic calculator’. So students should be encouraged to make conjectures about general
properties and produce examples to test these conjectures.
As an example of this we designed a session to enable students to discover the algebraic
properties of limits and to learn how to use them.
This algebra of limits is summarised in the following TI-92 table.

In this table, the four indefinite limits appear ‘undef’. The actual aim of the lesson was that the
students bear in mind these four cases as well discovering the means to solve these limits. For
⎛ 1 1⎞
instance, they should be able to recognise that lim⎜ 4 − 2 ⎟ is indefinite and to find that this
x→0 ⎝ x x ⎠
expression has actually a value (+∞).
We asked students to experiment on an example of explicit functions and not on symbolic
notations like in the above table. The data-matrix editor21 of the TI-92 was used to support
this investigation. The teacher introduced the first examples of limits of sums to give students
a method, and to introduce the problem of indefinite cases. Students were then requested to
produce others examples of possible values for lim ( f ( x ) + g ( x )) , when lim f ( x ) = +∞ and
x →0 x →0
lim g ( x ) = −∞ . Then they had to make conjectures for products and quotients and produce
x →0
examples to illustrate these. The TI-92 gave the values of the limits but the teacher asked the
students to explain the values by qualitative reasons or by calculation.
At this time students’ knowledge about limits was new and they encountered many
difficulties recalling even simple limits. We were aware that this lack of mathematical
maturity might cause them too much to rely on the TI-92 for the calculation of limits and thus
to use try and error strategies rather than anticipating. After a first experimentation of the
lesson we decided to make the limit point zero for all the limits.
With these settings students produced a lot of examples and convinced themselves that if
lim f ( x ) = +∞ and lim g ( x ) = −∞ , lim ( f ( x ) + g ( x )) may ‘give everything’. The other
x →0 x →0 x →0
indefinite cases did not appear immediately. For example, lim ( f ( x ) × g ( x )) presented
x →0
difficulties when lim f ( x ) = +∞ and lim g ( x ) = 0 , because many students produced
x →0 x →0
examples where this limit was zero, and thought it was a general rule. But other students

21
This module is like a symbolic simplified spread-sheet software.
produced examples where this limit was different, and convinced the class that it is again an
indefinite case.
The need for controlled anticipation induced students to think of limits on the basis of their
prior infinitesimal knowledge and the emphasis of the teacher that their reasoning corroborate
values obtained of the TI-92 helped here. The problem of indefinite cases clearly appeared to
students, and they could easily recall them from the examples that they produced. This is an
example on how the symbolic calculator might help the students to conduct a mathematical
activity in symbolic aspects of a concept in calculus without forgetting previously constructed
representations.
A number of sessions of more open research followed these introductory lessons. This paper
is a first look into how a teaching of pre-calculus might help the development of productive
calculator use schemes. Thus, it leaves the students at a first stage of their genesis. Analysis of
the sessions would help to see how in these sessions students put their schemes at work,
questioned and enhanced them.

Conclusion
To conclude, I will outline the issues discussed in this paper, and point out questions for
further analysis.
The table in Figure 4 summarises the key points which arise when I tried to conceptualise
changes in the mathematical activity in a classroom when every student uses a ‘computer-
like’ calculator and to see how teaching can take this use into account in a subject like pre-
calculus. I saw the role of mediation of these calculators from the many new potentialities and
constraints that they bring : when a student has one of these for everyday work in
mathematics, his/her action depends strongly on these. Using it along a year s/he develops
schemes specific to the calculator, together with other schemes. This instrumental genesis has
its own constraints deriving from the specificity of the calculator as well as of the
mathematical topic. As a student understands a mathematical topic from the schemes s/he
builds to do tasks in this topic, teaching has to be attentive to this genesis. The teaching
experiment I did with the DIDIREM team is a practical example of how a reflection on the
instrumental genesis helps to design lessons, developing students’ suitable schemes and
connecting various representations of concepts.
The role of schemes in the understanding of mathematics is not a new idea. In contrast, the
need for conceptualising the development of specific schemes of use recently appeared in the
research studies when students uses of technology moved from occasional to regular. The
context of long term everyday use of technology forced researchers to look at this
instrumental genesis. Techniques are now seen by mathematics educators as an important
level between the tasks and the theoretical reflection. However, this role has rarely been
considered in the use of computerised tools. This paper offers to look at the techniques as
official, rational objects in the classroom and to schemes as more 'private' entities making up a
frame for the learners’ knowledge. Highlighting various techniques and encouraging
discussion on them, teaching influences students’ development of utilisation schemes and is
thus able to direct it in a mathematically productive way.
In this paper, my approach of the changes induced by a complex calculator in the learner’s
action was a broad one and issues would deserve further analysis. Particularly, I had just a
short look at the effect of calculator language use on the students’ work. A reasonable
assumption would be that this language gives students an ‘expressing power’ that they could
use when working with the calculator, and also in classroom interactions as observed by
Hoyles and Noss (ibid. p. 153). These authors however demonstrated that this potential is not
a general property of the use of technology, but a consequence of particularities of the
microworlds that they analysed. Thus a more precise analysis of students’ uses of calculator
expressions to handle objects is to be done. This analyse should search for the possible
schemes and technologies which would give sense to these uses. More generally, with or
without calculator, we have to consider the instrumental dimension in students’ work. A
deeper look into this dimension would help to appreciate the respective contributions of the
paper/pencil work and of calculator use.

Mediation Learning pre-calculus


Situations of use of a • new potentialities • specific utilisation schemes (analytic,
complex calculator graphical, symbolic)
• new constraints
• productivity of • tasks to develop algebraic and functional
Instrumental genesis schemes schemes
• role of techniques • situations to link representations in
calculus (enactive-theoretic-symbolic)

Figure 4
Key points in teaching pre-calculus with complex calculators

Acknowledgement
Special thanks are extended to John Monaghan. He made many helpful suggestions on the
content as well as helping to overcome language difficulties.
References
Artigue, M.: 1995, ‘Une approche didactique de l’intégration des EIAO à l’enseignement’, in
D.Guin, J.F.Nicaud, D.Py (eds), Environnements Interactifs d’Apprentissage avec
Ordinateur, Eyrolles, Paris, 17-28.
Artigue, M. : 1996, ‘Computer environments and learning theories in mathematics education’.
In B.Barzel (ed.), Teaching Mathematics with Derive and the TI-92, 1-17. Münster : Zentrale
Koordination Lehrerausbildung.
Artigue, M.: 1997, ‘Le logiciel DERIVE comme révélateur de phénomènes didactiques lies a
l’utilisation d’environnements informatiques pour l’apprentissage.’ Educational Studies in
Mathematics, 33(2),133-169.
Boyd, A. and Rubin, A.: 1996, ‘Interactive video: a bridge between motion and math.’
International Journal of Computers for Mathematical Learning 1.1, 57-93.
Chevallard, Y.: 1992, ‘Concepts fondamentaux de la didactique: perspectives apportées par
une approche anthropologique.’ Recherches en Didactique des Mathématiques, vol. 12.1., 73-
112.
Chevallard, Y.: 1996, ‘La fonction professorale: esquisse d'un modele didactique’, in R.
Noirfalise, M.J. Perrin-Glorian (eds.) Proceedings of the 8th summer school of ‘didactique des
mathématiques’. IREM Clermont Ferrand, 83-122.
Defouad B.: (to appear), ‘Processus d’instrumentation de la TI-92 en classe de première S’ in
Proceedings of the congress ‘ Calculatrices symboliques et géométriques dans l’enseignement
des mathématiques ’, May 1998 Montpellier France.
Guin, D. et Trouche, L.: 1999, ‘The complex process of converting tools into mathematical
instruments: the case of calculators.’ The International Journal of Computers in Mathematics
Education. 3.3
Grey, E. and Tall, D.: 1993, ‘Success and failure in mathematics: the flexible meeaning of
symbols as process and concept.’ Mathematics Teaching, 142, 6-10
Heugl, H.: 1997, ‘The influence of Computer Algebra in the Teaching and Learning of
mathematics’ in Berry, Monaghan (eds.) The state of computer algebra in mathematics
education. Chartwell-Bratt, Bromley, 32-38.
Hirlimann, A.: 1996, ‘Computer Algebra Systems in French Secondary Schools.’, The
International DERIVE Journal, vol.3. 3, 1-4.
Lagrange , J.B.: (to appear) ‘Techniques and concepts in pre-calculus using CAS:
a two year classroom experiment with the TI-92’. To appear in The International Journal of
Computer Algebra in Mathematics Education.
Lagrange, J.B.: 1998, ‘Students using a TI-92: technical work and understanding in the
beginning of calculus’ in proceedings of the ICTCM 1997 Chicago (USA).
Lagrange, J.B.,:1997, ’Using a Computer Algebra System in the Mathematics Classroom’ in
M. Borba and alt. (eds.), Proceedings of the WG16, ICME 8. UNESP- State University of Sao
Paulo at Rio Claro, Brazil, 113-118.
Lagrange, J.B.: 1996, ‘Analysing actual use of a computer algebra system in the teaching and
learning of mathematics.’ International DERIVE Journal, vol.3. 3, 91-108.
Mayes R.: 1997, ‘Current state of research into CAS in mathematics education’ in J. Berry, J.
Monaghan (eds.) The state of computer algebra in mathematics education. Chartwell-Bratt,
Bromley, 171-189.
Monaghan, J., Sun, S. and Tall, D.: 1994, ‘Construction of the Limit Concept with a
Computer Algebra System.’ In Proceedings of PME 8 University of Lisbon, Portugal, III,
279-286.
Moro, C. and Scheuwly, B.: 1997, ‘L’outil et le signe dans l’approche du fonctionnement
psychologique’ in C. Moro and alt. (eds.) Outils et signes Peter Lang.
Noss, R.and Hoyles, C.: 1996, Windows on Mathematical Meanings, Kluwer.
Papert, S.: 1980, Mindstorms, Children, Computers, and Powerful Ideas. Basic Books, New
York.
Pozzi, S: 1994, ‘ Algebraic Reasoning and CAS: Freeing Students from Syntax ?’ in H.
Heugl, B. Kutzler (eds.) DERIVE in Education, Chartwell-Bratt, Bromley.
Rabardel, P.: 1995, Les hommes et les technologies - Approche cognitive des instruments
contemporains, Armand Colin, Paris.
Repo, S.: 1994, ‘Understanding and Reflexive Abstraction: Learning the concept of derivative
in the computer environment.’ International DERIVE Journal, vol.1. 1.97-113.
Ruthven, K.: 1997, Computer algebra systems in advanced-level mathematics. Report to
School Curriculum and Assesment Authority. University of Cambridge. UK.
Sfard, A.: 1991, ‘On the dual nature of mathematical conceptions: reflections on processes
and objects as different sides of the same coin.’ Educational Studies in Mathematics, vol. 22
1-36.
Shoaf-Grubbs, M.M.: 1995, ’Research Results on the effect of the graphic calculator on
female students’ cognitive levels and visual thinking’ in L. Burton and B.Jaworski (ed.)
Technology in Mathematics Teaching, Chartwell-Bratt, 213-227.
Tall, D.: 1996, ‘Functions and calculus’ in Bishop A.J. et al. (eds.) International Handbook of
Mathematics Education, Kluwer Academic, 289-325.
Trouche L., Guin D., 1996, "Seeing is reality : how graphic calculators may influence the
conceptualisation of limits", Proceedings, 20th Conference of the International Group for the
Psychology of Mathematics Education, vol 4, 323-333, Valencia.
Trouche, L.: 1996, Etude des rapports entre processus de conceptualisation et processus
d’instrumentation Philosophical Dissertation., University of Montpellier 2, France.
Vergnaud, G.: 1990, ‘La théorie des champs conceptuels.’ Recherches en Didactique des
Mathématiques, vol. 10.2-3., 133-170.
Verillon,P. and Rabardel, P.: 1995, ‘Cognition and Artifacts: a contribution to the study of
thought in relation to instrumented activity’ European Journal of Psychology of Education,
vol. X, n°1, 77-101.
Watkins, A.: 1992, ‘Introducing Calculus with DERIVE’ in J. Böhm (ed.) Teaching
Mathematics with DERIVE. Chartwell Bratt, 1-20.

You might also like