This Content Downloaded From 111.93.136.226 On Fri, 05 Aug 2022 03:54:52 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 111.93.136.226 On Fri, 05 Aug 2022 03:54:52 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 111.93.136.226 On Fri, 05 Aug 2022 03:54:52 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/23069892?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Feminist Studies, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Feminist Studies
Snmati Basu
Did we triumph as feminists when rape (on the street, in the dorm, at
war) was recognized as violence (and not just a property violation), and
states enacted sanctions and protections against rape? For many of us who
petitioned and marched to demand remedies against sexual violence, it
was a feminist axiom to understand rape as an archetyped mark of patriar
chal dominance deeply resistant to legal accountability. Despite problems
such as botched prosecutions or shamed silences or the intransigence of
law, bringing recognition to sexual violence was indeed a symbolic success.
However, the satisfaction of legal remedies is also eclipsed by the problems
of their very institution: the decoding and use of these laws in a variety of
settings raises questions about meanings of violence and sex, agency, and
consent. Although it may be disconcerting to interrogate the terms of the
185
been the unit to which Ghosh was brought and hence was abuzz with
excitement. It appeared that the police felt some sympathy for Ghosh's
fugitive status, yet by virtue of being the very unit designed to pay atten
tion to violence against women, did not want to be seen as minimizing a
high-profile rape case. Their statements thus evoked and yet sought to
mediate the allegations. The parties' actor and journalist friends dropped
in periodically over a couple of days to make inquiries; Ghosh called on a
friend's cell phone. In one of these telephone conversations, I heard a
police officer advise him that "once the case has became so public there is
not much we can do. Try to talk to your common friends and get her to
withdraw the case or else make arrangements for bail. It's a hot time for
376 [rape] cases these days; there's nothing the police can do" (Ajkal 376
case-er gorom abhaoa cholchchey). A journalist friend of Ghosh's came in to
check with the officer shortly thereafter, saying they were trying to get
friends together to convince the couple to settle, or else "the lawyers
would get bloated over it for ten or twelve years" (naholey dosh-baro bochchor
dhorey ukiler pet phanpabey). Chakraborty's one condition was marriage, so
friends were trying to see if they could arrange anything. Remarkably, in
the space of the Women's Grievance Cell, the marital resolution of this
putative rape case echoed the more quotidian work of the cell, where alle
gations of domestic violence were evaluated and more often than not
resolved through family mediation.2
The case galvanized public discussion about "appropriate" modes of
arrest: actors and artists wrote about destroying the "sanctity" of the
theater, and the chief minister spoke out against the "unbecoming con
duct" of the police in "storm[ing] the auditorium in order to arrest an
actor [which] cannot be a policy of the government." While the police put
the arrest on hold, Ghosh applied for anticipatory bail to avoid arrest, and
the High Court judge declared in the subsequent plea hearing that Ghosh
and Chakraborty "should be able to settle their dispute through peaceful
discussion" in five days: "Both of you are in the same profession and know
each other. You should be able to sort out your differences through
discussions. The court should not interfere in the matter."3 Following
this, the couple met in the prosecutor's office to work out an agreement;
the case dropped out of media at this point and was presumably settled.
It was difficult not to feel irritated at the ways in which this apparently
feeble case was used in popular discussion to dismiss rape claims generally
or with the seeming prudishness of the plaintiff whose occupation, educa
tion, and progressive social milieu appeared at odds with her horrified in
vocation of cohabitation as a form of rape, as well as at Chakraborty's
erasure of her own sexual agency. But this hypervisible case also provided a
glimpse into the links between rape, marriage, resource acquisition, shame,
consent, and, ultimately, feminist organizing. This article examines these
linkages in recent rape cases in India to examine feminist theories of rape. I
argue for greater attention to the relationship between sexual violence and
the social contract of compulsory heterosexual marriage and examine the
circuits of property exchange within which rape is often encoded.
Rethinking Resistance:
Discourse, Materiality, and Culture in Rape
In her landmark article on the cultural construction of sexuality and rape,
Christine Helliwell reports a respondent as saying, "It's only a penis. . . .
How can a penis hurt anyone?"4 Provoking us to think beyond overdeter
mined patriarchal violence, Helliwell argues that the terms of rape are not
Nivedita Menon also contends that both feminist and sexist analyses
"mystifjy] 'sexuality' as the truest, deepest expression of selfhood" or as a
"natural" entity existing outside discursive categories.12 To take the argu
ment out of the realm of "the West," one may therefore look to rape sce
narios as scripts that inscribe gender-power dimorphism and meanings of
sexuality and that serve to inscribe the body in a given culture. The Indian
examples in the previous paragraph, while also pertaining to realms such
as urban public space, caste relations, religious interpretation, and crimi
nal justice systems, also enforce gendered power. They are self-conscious
and self-perpetuating instantiations of using the penis to mark terror and
subjugation.
Because the early strategies of feminist mobilization aimed at estab
lishing the significance of sexual violence, the conundrum for later gener
ations of feminist theorists has been to imagine solutions beyond legal
deterrence and to address such discursive constitutions of sexual violence
a category beyond reparation and that forms of resistance and social trans
formation may be embedded in rape survivor narratives and subsequent
organizing. She propounds a "new theory of rape" that would "supple
ment feminist accounts of women's experience with a contextual analysis
of the ways in which experience is given meaning at a particular time and
place"; that is, it would attend both to cultural inscriptions of violence as
well as to voices of resistance.14
perpetrators; the police were unable to arrest any specific women for the
crime (and even alleged that some men did it and women were protecting
them).15 Although embedded in a horrific narrative of community terror,
the Kasturba Nagar women's actions indicate the retaliatory use of bodily
violence not just to harm or kill but to transform the signifiers of victim
hood, class, and legal protection as well. They challenged the power of
rape through a collective, coordinated, visceral response that elides legal
punishment, in blatant mockery and rebuke of the law. Similarly, the rape
of activist Bhanwari Devi described above became a site where ideologies of
rape were consciously challenged by protest campaigns, such as in slogans
that mocked the loss of honor of the rapists.16
In contrast, Chakraborty's claim of harm and violence sits more un
comfortably askew feminist analyses of rape: it does not evoke pain, coer
cion, or humiliation; indeed, it implicates feminists by questioning
women's sexual agency and affirmative consent. But it does push us to
look beyond the body, to consider rape in terms beyond corporeal vio
lence. Her actions and the following cases gain meaning, I argue, when we
consider the social structures of marriage and the legalities through
which marriage is instituted. Feminist struggles to theorize sexual agency
and sexual victimization, equality and difference, are embedded in these
contradictory legalities.
Similarly, criminal law provisions for return of dowry are used as a proxy
for recovering matrimonial property, however little. In these cases, in the
Chakraborty rape case, and in the rape cases that follow, criminal law
provisions that rely on essentialized notions of female victimization and
female sexual passivity offer women protection, in the form of criminal
sanctions by the state, while civil remedies offer few punitive solutions
against failures to provide maintenance or housing.
Women's chances of deploying the criminal-sanctioning power of the
state vary depending on their class, caste, and religion. Judges and law en
forcement officials do not necessarily follow the feminist spirit of these
laws. Still, these criminal provisions potentially confer gender-based enti
tlements. To use an almost dusty formulation from 1980s feminist jurispru
dence, these laws highlight gendered difference (and violence against
women as a fundamental expression of differences in power) and offer
protection. In contrast, civil marriage law is more gender neutral on its
face, although it ultimately reinforces male economic and social power.
Scholars of gender and law in India have demonstrated the inequities of
marriage law in a variety of settings, echoing classic formulations such as
Martha Fineman's analysis of economic vulnerabilities generated through
the social categories defined in marriage. Similarly, Susan Moller Okin
argues that divorce law both reflects and creates economic disparities: "By
attempting to treat men and women as equals at the end of marriage,
current divorce law neglects not only the obvious fact that women are not
the socioeconomic equals of men in our society, but also the highly rele
vant fact that the experience of gendered marriage and primary parenting
greatly exacerbates the inequality that women already bring with them
into marriage."17 Given the limited "civility" of equal marriage, criminal
law can be used as a form of leverage.
A few recent cases illustrate the interaction of the laws governing rape
and marriage, particularly the ways in which one entity works in the
shadow of the other. The first example is drawn from my fieldwork at the
Women's Grievance Cell. A large man wearing a fancy suit and gold
jewelry came in with a huge file of legal papers, discussing "Suparna's"
attempts to set up a meeting and have him bring her money. The story, as
narrated by some officers after his departure, was that he claimed to be in
media/film and to have been set up by a gangster group that drugged him
and then entrapped him with a woman who was, presumably, a profes
sional extortionist. Unaccountably, he continued to be involved with the
group, as well as the woman. He had set the woman up in a flat, had a
child with her, and lived there quite a lot of the time, all the while claim
ing that he had been coerced into a registered marriage.18 His fifty-four
year-old wife had threatened divorce on grounds of adultery if he did not
quit this relationship. Suparna had threatened to file a §376 (rape) case on
the grounds that he went through a formal bigamous marriage with the
full knowledge that it was invalid and hence fraudulent, thereby continu
ing a sexual relationship with her under circumstances she would not
have knowingly consented to. The police officer told me that in her meet
ings she had stressed that she needed to be fair to both women's claims.
And in fact, these women who bitterly opposed each other had each
framed their claims with a tidy strategy: his best recourse was to use
persuasion and/or his ample financial resources to extricate himself. As
with Chakraborty's case, here rape is evoked in the context of a long-term
cohabitation by a woman who is not claiming a violation of chastity nor is
solely dependent on marriage for economic sustenance. Regarding a simi
lar case, Menon opines that a woman may be "cheated and exploited" in
such situations, but "if as feminists we were to see it as rape, we would be
participating in a discourse that sets up sex as legitimate only within the
framework of marriage."19 Yet although this case evokes uneasiness about
recognizing female sexual agency and measuring respectability through
social status conferred by marriage, it also illustrates that criminal com
plaints are used to contest "civil" issues of marriage entitlements.
Moreover, these two cases are part of well-worn legal trajectories in
which rape prosecutions invoke marriage as putative solutions. They un
derline the stature of rape as sex rather than violence. But they also depict
rape as a violation of property, to be made whole by restoring the woman
to the marital state to which she was entitled when exposed to sex. As the
following cases show, marriage is the form of property synechdocally at
stake in rape. In these cases, a marriage proposal or relationship serves as
the alibi that erases notions of violence. In 2002, Rafik Taksir's imprison
ment for rape and kidnapping was set aside by the Goa High Court when
he pointed out that he had married the rape survivor after his conviction:
the judgment said "it is true that the scars of trauma suffered by the
victim cannot be erased from her memory but the evidence on record
does indicate to a certain extent that the appellant and the victim were in
love."20 Similarly, in 2005, a Delhi court acquitted Kanhu Panda of rape
and kidnapping (originally charges were filed against him and three of his
friends for gang rape) when letters from the woman and pictures of their
wedding ceremony were presented: the judge commented that "if one
goes through these letters, there remains no doubt that the prosecutrix
was deeply involved with the accused"; her pictures in wedding attire
served as evidence to prove that she did not marry under coercion. Panda
"expressed his desire to marry the victim despite belonging to a different
caste" and was granted bail in order to marry at the Bhadrak temple
where "their well-wishers had also hosted a grand feast to mark the occa
sion," then went back to jail as a prisoner under trial "hop[ing] his wife
will withdraw the case against him and look[ing] forward to a married life
outside jail."21 Remarkably, evidence of consent often appears visually
rather than orally in these appellate judgments (old love notes, wedding
pictures), validating past or future relationships rather than the time and
context of the sexual act at issue. This has the effect of erasing violence
from rape, grounding agency in marriage rather than sex, and disman
tling the very notion of consent.
Notions of consent were also transformed when the High Court
reduced rape charges on a variety of exculpatory grounds that invoked
the motivation of defendants (mens red). This inverts the common criminal
trial procedure wherein the raped woman's state of mind is at the core of
the argument, as Susan Estrich argues for U.S. law.22 In these cases, the
question of women's motivation becomes almost invisible, except by
proxy in filing the charges. These exculpations included several examples
of the accused being "an illiterate laborer from a rural area," connoting
rape as an urban phenomenon related to confusion of values over sexual
ity and public space, and signaling feminist insistence on legal sanctions
against rape as an urban value incomprehensible to those ensconced in
local understandings of male sexual privilege.
This "prosecutrix" may receive the benefit of the doubt because she was
seen as innocent and virginal; however, women not perceived to embody
perfect chastity or class privilege would not, by implication, warrant the
same protection. In contrast, a more complex notion of women's sexual
agency was deployed in the order of the 2003 case, Uday v. State of Karnataka,
to dismiss the notion of a naive belief in "promises of marriage." The court
determined that the question of marriage was not a false promise because
the woman had been "overcome with emotions and passion" and
"succumbed to the temptation," that she had willingly consented to sex
"not because he promised to marry her but because she also desired it."2"1
The ascription of sexual agency to the woman was, not surprisingly, to
her legal disadvantage. This raises the question of whether this case should
be commended for its equitable recognition of women's sexual passion or
condemned as a slippery new pathway for dismissing rape charges by
putting the motivation of the raped subject at the center of the claim.
The most transparent example of the equivalence in currency be
tween marriage and rape is provided by a 2005 case, in which Bhura, who
worked as a ward boy at a hospital, raped a nurse, gouged out her right
eye and severely injured the left, locked her up and left her for dead. But
in a postconviction application submitted prior to sentencing, he asserted:
"To save the life of the victim as well as the lives of both of the families, the
convict, from the core of his heart, without prejudice to the merits of the
case, is ready to perform marriage with the victim." The nurse vocifer
ously responded that her assailant should be accorded the maximum
punishment instead or even hanged; feminist organizations berated the
judge for even admitting this application, noting that "the court should
not be a marriage bureau for criminals."25 However, the application repre
sents not just a desperate and pathetic bid for clemency but also an offer of
reward that a man with the worst of prospects has the power to grant.
How could we not believe in genuine repentance and integrity if marriage
was on offer?
the case, prosecuting rape using standards of fraud rather than invoking
legal definitions of sexual violence.
Tsun-Yin Luo's study of suggestions to marry rapists in contemporary
Taiwan maps ideological similarities in gender formations in a very differ
ent socioeconomic milieu than India's. Luo contends that the "cultural
not have sex-specific requirements for the duties of 'husband' and 'wife'. . .
. The state actively participates in establishing the distinction between what
is profane (instrumental, everyday life) and what is sacred (ritualistic expres
sions of group particularity)." Stevens contends that kinship is a funda
mental sacred axis around which the state functions, echoing Nancy
Cott's assertion that "the institution of marriage and the modern state
have been mutually constitutive" by demonstrating the ways in which the
state sanctions "terms of legitimacy," "form|sj of kinship relations," and
hence the premises of full citizenship.36 Wendy Brown characterizes the
state somewhat differently as acting to inscribe the family as a prepolitical
domain beyond direct intervention but starkly shaping sociopolitical rela
tions as a result, thereby "operat[ing] as an insignia of the extent to which
politics between men are always already also the politics of exchanging,
violating, protecting and dominating women; the one constitutes the
imperatives of the other."37 Rape, in this formulation, interrupts the
patterns through which circuits of kinship are to be rendered sacred and
thereby evokes the wrath of the state by striking at its foundational value;
norms of kinship are restored through state-sanctioned legal categories for
which marriage is the conduit. However, because, as Stevens notes, "the
apparent equality of the political statuses 'husband' and 'wife' actually
obscures an underlying dynamic that continues to render marriage a site
of gendered political inequality,"38 marriage per se is scant compensation
even though it is the optimal identity before the state.
Stevens's and Brown's conceptions of marriage collapse the space be
tween conjugality and kinship, between the couple and broader impera
tives of family, depicting them as co-constructed and mutually
beneficial. It bears noting that the separation between these two terms,
however, has been deemed by historians of South Asia to be a critical axis
of the emergence of modernities: notions such as the rise of the individ
ual legal subject interpellated by market forces and conjugal intimacy
within the safe haven of the nuclear family emerged in nationalist
discourse, pushing against the dominant needs of the extended familty
and affecting the milieu within which postcolonial marriage law (center
ing on the couple) was constructed.39 Still, these historians assert, these
new subjectivities existed alongside conservative patriarchal formulations
of kinship. In any case, "modern" ideas of conjugal equality did not alter
the status of marriage as the path to women's property.
Seeing marriage as an axis for instituting and sheltering gendered
subordination, even while granting legal privileges, is critical to under
standing the rape cases analyzed here. In the state sanctions of marriage to
rapists and the use of rape law as a tool to punish defaulters to marriage, as
well as in the attempts of Oindrila Chakraborty and Suparna to make sex
criminal unless it was converted to marriage, we see both the privileged
status conferred by marriage, as well as the irony of a legal strategy that
seeks out a category of subordination (which is also "protection"). To
return to Helliwell and Marcus's suggestions that we challenge discursive
constructions of rape and their embeddedness in gender norms by altering
the power of signifiers, invocations of marriage in the shadow of rape are
singularly ineffective in transforming valences of sexual passivity or socioe
conomic dependence; they reinscribe victimhood even as marriage offers
forms of redress.
"Do we want equality of the sexes—or do we want justice for two kinds of
human beings who are fundamentally different?""10 Williams asks, echoing
Helliwell's contention that law itself makes sexual difference salient.
While Williams leans to the "equality" side of the question, arguing that
that is ultimately more beneficent for the symbolic inscription of gender
within law, the way in which she poses the argument drives home the
potential incompatibility between these two views. Carol Smart, tracing a
similar dichotomy in feminist discourses on rape law between liberal,
gender-blind, rights-based approaches and that of moral outrage and
protection, emphasizes the irony that both positions can be successfully
argued but that they "shared with legal discourse the construction of
woman as her sex, and in turn a sexed body open to/vulnerable to the
'desires' and designs of men. In the former the body becomes the eternal
victim, in the latter the deserving victim. Neither discourse empowers."
Thus, Smart notes, the problem is that
Can we afford to critique the essentialist bases of rape legislation and their
construction of the gendered body, when feminist movements have
worked so hard to seek legal recognition of rape as an act of violence
working through social categories of sex? Can protection ever alter the
terms of power? Yet the related question is, can we live with marriage as a
form of compensation for rape claims or indeed with marriage as any kind
of compensation at all?
Oindrila Chakraborty's case provides a reminder of this uneven ter
rain of rape legislation in India. She utilized a solid legal strategy (that
marriage, and by laying open their alliances, signal the ways in which
feminist theories can trouble law and their own place within it.
Notes
2. See Srimati Basu, "Playing Off Courts: The Negotiation of Divorce and Violence in
Plural Legal Settings in Kolkata, India," Journal of Legal Pluralism 52 (2006): 41-75.
3. Legal Reporter, "Court Directs Actors to Patch Up: 'Rape' Case Adjourned till Feb.
7," Telegraph (Kolkata), 3 Feb. 2005. The circumstances of the rape charge were often
elided in newspaper accounts that relied on evoking a stereotypical rape rampage,
such as this sarcastic condemnation of police behavior of charging into the women's
changing rooms ("greenrooms"): "They may have thought that an actor charged
with rape rushes to the women's greenroom at every free moment to continue his
favorite activity, or, in all the excitement they had forgotten the gender of the
alleged rapist, or, they thought that he had hidden in the women's rooms. That is
what they would have done under similar circumstances, probably." See "Opinion
Life Chasing Art," Telegraph (Kolkata), City Page, 3 Feb. 2005.
4. Christine Helliwell, '"It's Only a Penis': Rape, Feminism, and Difference," Signs 25, no.
3(2000): 789-816.
5. Maria Barbara Watson-Franke, "A World in Which Women Move Freely without Fear
of Men: An Anthropological Perspective on Rape," Women's Studies International Forum 25,
no. 6 (2002): 599-606. The classic proponent of this argument is Peggy Sanday, in texts
such as her "Rape-Free versus Rape-Prone: How Culture Makes a Difference," in
Evolution, Gender, and Rape, ed. C.B. Travis (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2003), 337-62.
6. Section 375 of the Indian Penal Code defines rape, while 376 defines punishment for
rape. Nivedita Menon describes ongoing attempts at reform of sexual assault law in
"Sexual Violence: Escaping the Body," in Recovering Subversion: Feminist Politics beyond the
Law (New Delhi: Permanent Black, 2004), 106-65, 111-12. According to Menon (138),
draft proposals for reform in 1993 and 2000 have moved toward increasingly gender
inclusive language.
7. Vibhuti Patel, "Women's Liberation in India," New Left Review, no. 153 (September
October 1985): 75-86.
8. See "Report Confirms Marine Drive Rape," Times of India, 17 June 2005; Shefalee
Vasudev and Methil Renuka, "Sexual Crimes: Rape!" India Today, 9 Sept. 2002, 48; and
Raji Rajagopalan, "Sexual Abuse Reported in India," Herizons 18, no. 2 (2004): 13.
9. Vasudev and Renuka, "Sexual Crimes," 48. Although the judge ultimately dismissed
the case of the social worker citing improbability, the event became a prominent
platform for organizing against rape in the women's movement in India. "Stigma:
Rape Case Shocks Women in India," New Internationalist, no. 277 (1996): 5, provides one
of numerous accounts of the case. See "Islamic Village Council Orders Woman to
Marry Father-in-Law Who Raped Her," Off Our Backs 35, nos. 7-8 (2005): 5-6; "Probe
into Bihar Dalit Women's Rape," India-Asian News Service, 3 Sept. 2006, available online
at www.india-forums.com/news/national/1005-probe-into-bihar-dalit-women-rape.
htm; and Tanika Sarkar, "Semiotics of Terror: Muslim Children and Women in
Hindu Rashtra," Economic and Political Weekly 37, no. 28 (2002): 2872-76. R.S. Gupta is
quoted in Vasudev and Renuka, "Sexual Crimes," 48.
10. Catharine MacKinnon, Toward a Feminist Theory of the State (Cambridge: Harvard Uni
versity Press, 1989), 172.
11. Helliwell, "It's Only a Penis," 812, 796-98.
12. Menon, "Sexual Violence," 141, 107.
13. Sharon Marcus, "Fighting Bodies, Fighting Words: A Theory and Politics of Rape
Prevention," in Feminists Theorize the Political, ed. Judith Butler and Joan W. Scott (New
York: Routledge, 1992), 387, 391.
14. Carine Mardorossian, "Toward a New Feminist Theory of Rape," Signs 27, no. 3 (2002):
748.
15. Vivek Deshpande, "'This is Justice,' Say His Victims," Indian Express, 16 Aug. 2004; Satish
Nandgaonkar, "The Day of the Furies," Telegraph (Kolkata), 22 Aug. 2004.
16. Menon, "Sexual Violence," 133.
17. Patricia Uberoi, "Hindu Marriage Law and the Judicial Construction of Sexuality," in
Feminist Terrains in Legal Domains: Interdisciplinary Essays on Women and Law in India, ed. Ratna
Kapur (New Delhi: Kali for Women, 1996), 184-209, provides vivid examples of
"ethnosexology" in judicial pronouncements. Also see Agnes Flavia, Law and Gender
Inequality: The Politics of Women's Rights in India (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2000);
Maitrayee Mukhopadhyay, Legally Dispossessed: Gender, Identity, and the Process of Law
(Calcutta: Stree, 1998); Srimati Basu, She Comes to Take Her Rights: Indian Women, Property,
and Propriety (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999); Martha Fineman,
introduction to At the Boundaries of Law: Feminism and Legal Theory, ed. Martha Albertson
Fineman and Nancy Sweet Thomadsen (New York: Routledge, 1991); and Susan
Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Basic Books, 1989), 166.
18. A registered marriage typically requires a month's advance notice. Bigamy is illegal
under the Hindu Marriage Act, and only the legal wife has any property/mainte
nance claims (although all children do).
19. Menon, "Sexual Violence," 124.
34. Johanna Niemi-Kiesilainen, "The Reform of Sex Crime Law and the Gender-Neutral
Subject," in Nordic Equality at a Crossroads: Feminist Legal Studies Coping with Difference, ed.
Eva-Maria Svensson, Anu Pylkkanen, and Johanna Niemi-Kiesilainen (Burlington,
VT: Ashgate, 2004), 170.
35. Christine Keating, "Framing the Postcolonial Sexual Contract: Democracy, Frater
nalism, and State Authority in India," Hypatia 22, no. 4 (2007): 137. "Personal" law
codes pertain to family law, that is, marriage, adoption, custody, and guardianship
and inheritance. They vary for each religious community, and there is also a secular
option available for marriage law.
36. Jacqueline Stevens, "On the Marriage Question," in Women Transforming Politics: An
Alternative Reader, ed. Cathy J. Cohen, Kathleen B. Jones, and Joan C. Tronto (New
York: New York University Press, 1997), 62-63, 66.
37. Wendy Brown, "Finding the Man in the State," Feminist Studies 18 (Spring 1992): 25.
38. Stevens, "Marriage Question," 69.
39. Rochona Majumdar, "Looking for Brides and Grooms: Ghataks, Matrimonials, and the
Marriage Market in Colonial Calcutta, circa 1875-1940," Journal of Asian Studies 63, no. 4
(2004): 911-35; Rachel Sturman, "Property and Attachments: Defining Autonomy
and the Claims of Family in Nineteenth-Century Western India," Comparative Studies in
Society and History 47, no. 3 (2005): 611-37; Mytheli Sreenivas, Wives, Widows, Concubines:
The Conjugal Family Ideal in Colonial India (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2008).
40. Wendy W. Williams, "The Equality Crisis: Some Reflections on Culture, Courts, and
Feminism," in The Second Wave: A Reader in Feminist Theory, ed. Linda Nicholson (New
York: Routledge, 1997), 77,84.
41. Carol Smart, Law, Crime, and Sexuality: Essays in Feminism (London: Sage, 1995), 86, 87.
42. Echoing activist Flavia Agnes, Menon argues that many progressive judgments have
in fact defined the terrain of rape law at least as much as legislation; see "Sexual
Violence," 123.
43. "Fast Track Justice," Times of India, 6 May 2005, 18; "Bihar Court Hands Out Rape
Verdict in Five Hours," Times of India, 20 Oct. 2006, 12; Monobina Gupta, "Rape Relief
within Weeks," Telegraph (Kolkata), 24 Oct. 2005: 1.
44. "Sex with Minor on Promise of Marriage Is Rape," Times of India, 3 Oct. 2006.
45. Dhananjay Mahapatra, "Rape Victim's Words Gospel Truth: SC," Times of India, 17
May 2006, 11. Menon, "Sexual Violence," 130, lays out some problematic ways in
which lack of corroboration is validated only in certain performances of femininity
allied with chastity. See "SC Tells Courts Not to Take Rape Cases Lightly," Hindustan
Times, 4 Oct. 2006, 6.
46. Stevens, "Marriage Question," 63.