Merleau-Ponty - Eye and Mind (1961)
Merleau-Ponty - Eye and Mind (1961)
Merleau-Ponty - Eye and Mind (1961)
17
351
352
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
This question, however, is not and must not be asked. The gradient is a net
we throw out to sea, without knowing what it will haul in. Or yet, it is the
slender branch upon which unforeseeable crystallizations will form. No
doubt this freedom of operation will serve well to overcome many a point-
less dilemma—provided only that from time to time we bring it into fo-
cus, and we ask ourselves why the apparatus works in one place and fails
in others. In short, this flowing science must understand itself. It must see
itself as a construction based on a brute or existent world and not claim
for its blind operations the constitutive value that the “concepts of nature”
were able to have in an idealist philosophy. To say that the world is, by
nominal definition, the object x of our operations is to adjust the scien-
tist’s epistemic situation to the absolute, as if everything that was and is has
never existed save in order to enter the laboratory. Thinking “operation-
ally” becomes a sort of absolute artificialism, such as we see in the ideol-
ogy of cybernetics, where human creations are derived from a natural in-
formation process, but which is itself conceived on the model of human
machines. If this kind of thinking takes over humanity and history, and if,
pretending to be ignorant of what we know about humanity and history
through contact and through location, it sets out to construct them on the
basis of a few abstract indices as a decadent psychoanalysis and cultural-
ism have done in the United States, since man truly becomes the manipu-
landum he thinks he is, then we enter into a cultural regimen in which
there is neither truth nor falsehood concerning humanity and history,
then we enter into a sleep or nightmare from which nothing would be able
to awaken us.
It is necessary that the thought of science—surveying thought,
thought of the object in general, be placed back in the “there is” which
precedes it, back in the site, back upon the soil of the sensible world and
the soil of the worked-upon world such as they are in our lives and for our
bodies, not that possible body which we may legitimately think of as an in-
formation machine, but this actual body I call mine, this sentinel standing
silently under my words and my acts. It is necessary that associated bodies be
awakened along with my body, “others,” who are not my congeners, as the
zoologist says, but others who haunt me and whom I haunt; “others” along
with whom I haunt a single, present, and actual Being as no animal has
ever haunted the others of his own species, territor y, or habitat. In this pri-
mordial historicity, the agile and improvisatory thought of science will
learn to ground itself upon the things themselves and upon itself, and will
once more become philosophy. . . .
Now art and especially painting draw from this pool of brute sense,
about which activism wants to know nothing. Art and painting alone do
this in full innocence. From the writer and the philosopher, we want opin-
353
E Y E A N D M I N D
ions and advice. We will not allow them to hold the world suspended. We
want them to take a stand; they cannot waive the responsibilities of man
who speaks. Music, at the other extreme, is too far on the hither side of the
world and of the designatable to depict anything but certain sketches of
Being—its ebb and flow, its growth, its upheavals, its turbulence. Only the
painter is entitled to gaze upon everything without being obliged to ap-
praise what he sees. For the painter, we might say, the watchwords of
knowledge and action lose their meaning and force. Political regimes
which denounce “degenerate” painting rarely destroy the pictures. They
hide them, and one senses here an element of “one never knows” amount-
ing almost to an acknowledgment. The reproach of escapism is seldom
aimed at the painter; we do not hold it against Cézanne that he lived hid-
den away at L’Estaque during the Franco-Prussian War. Everyone recalls
with respect his “Life is frightening,” although the most insignificant
student, after Nietzsche, would flatly reject philosophy if it was said that
philosophy does not teach us how to live life to the fullest. It is as if in the
painter’s calling there were an urgency that passed beyond every other
urgency. The painter is there, strong or frail in life, but sovereign incon-
testably in his rumination on the world, sovereign without any other
“technique” than the one that his eyes and hands are given by means of
seeing, by means of painting; he is there relentless to pull from this world,
in which the scandals and achievements of history resound, canvases
which will hardly add to the angers or the hopes of humanity; and no one
mutters. What, then, is the secret science which he has or which he seeks?
That dimension by means of which Van Gogh wants to go “further”? What
is this fundamental of painting, perhaps of all culture?
II
The painter “takes his body with him,” says Valéry. And indeed, we cannot
see how a Mind could paint. It is by lending his body to the world that the
artist changes the world into paintings. To understand these transubstan-
tiations we must go back to the working, actual body—not the body as a
chunk of space or a bundle of functions but that body which is an inter-
twining of vision and movement.
It is enough to see something in order to know how to reach it and
deal with it, even if I do not know how that is done in the machine made
of nerves. My moving body counts in the visible world, participates in it;
that is why I can direct my body in the visible. Moreover, it is also true that
vision depends on movement. We see only what we gaze upon. What would
354
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
vision be without any eye movement, and how would the movement of the
eyes not blur things if movement were itself a reflex or blind, if it did not
have its antennae, its clairvoyance, if vision were not prefigured in it? All
my changes of place figure in principle in an area of my landscape; they
are carried over onto the map of the visible. Everything I see is in prin-
ciple within my reach, at least within the reach of my sight, and is marked
upon the map of the “I can.” Each of the two maps is complete. The vis-
ible world and the world of my motor projects are both total parts of the
same Being.
This extraordinary overlapping, which we never give enough thought
to, forbids us to conceive of vision as an operation of thought that would
set up before the mind a picture or a representation of the world, a world
of immanence and of ideality. Immersed in the visible by his body, itself
visible, the seer does not appropriate what he sees; he merely approaches
it by means of the gaze, he opens onto the world. And for its part, that
world in which he participates is not in-itself or matter. My movement is
not a decision made by the mind, an absolute doing which would decree,
from the depths of a subjective retreat, some change of place miraculously
executed in extended space. It is the natural sequel to and the maturation
of vision. I say of a thing that it is moved, but my body moves itself; my
movement unfolds itself. It is not in ignorance of itself, blind to itself; it
radiates from a self. . . .
The enigma derives from the fact that my body is simultaneously see-
ing and visible. The one who gazes upon all things can also be gazed upon
and can recognize, in what he sees then, the “other side” of his seeing
power. He sees himself seeing; he touches himself touching; he is visible
and sensitive for himself. He is a self, not by transparency, like thought,
which never thinks anything except by assimilating it, constituting it,
transforming it into thought—but a self by confusion, narcissism, inher-
ence of the one who sees in what he sees, of the one who touches in what
he touches, of the sensing in the sensed—a self, therefore, that is caught
up in things, having a front and a back, a past and a future. . . .
This initial paradox cannot but produce others. Visible and mobile,
my body is a thing among things; it is one of them. It is caught in the fab-
ric of the world, and its cohesion is that of a thing. But because it sees and
moves itself, it holds things in a circle around itself. Things are an annex
or prolongation of my body; they are incrusted in its flesh, they are part of
its full definition; the world is made of the very stuff of the body. These re-
versals, these antinomies, are different ways of saying that vision is caught
or is made in the middle of things, where something visible undertakes to
see, becomes visible for itself and through the vision of all things, where
the indivision of the sensing and the sensed persists, like the original fluid
within the crystal.
355
E Y E A N D M I N D
356
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
357
E Y E A N D M I N D
stores to the visible through the traces of a hand. In whatever civilization it
is born, from whatever beliefs, motives, or thoughts, no matter what cere-
monies surround it—and even when it appears devoted to something
else—from Lascaux to our time, pure or impure, figurative or not, paint-
ing celebrates no other enigma but that of visibility.
What we have just said amounts to a truism. The painter’s world is a
visible world, nothing but visible: a world almost mad, because it is com-
plete though only partial. Painting awakens and carries to its highest
power a delirium which is vision itself, since to see is to have at a distance;
painting extends this strange possession to all aspects of Being, aspects
which must somehow be made visible in order to enter into painting.
When, apropos of Italian painting, the young Berenson spoke of an evo-
cation of tactile values, he could hardly have been more mistaken; paint-
ing evokes nothing, least of all the tactile. What it does is entirely differ-
ent, almost the inverse. Painting gives visible existence to what profane
vision believes to be invisible; thanks to painting we do not need a “mus-
cular sense” in order to possess the voluminosity of the world. This vora-
cious vision, reaching beyond the “visual givens,” opens upon a texture of
Being of which the discrete sensorial messages are only the punctuations
or the caesurae. The eye dwells in this texture as man dwells in his house.
Let us remain within the visible in the narrow and prosaic sense.
The painter, any painter, while he is painting, practices a magical theory of
vision. He has to admit really that the things pass into him or that, accord-
ing to Malebranche’s sarcastic dilemma, the mind goes out through the
eyes to wander among the things, since he never stops adjusting his see-
ing upon their basis. (It makes no difference if he does not paint from “na-
ture”; he paints, in any case, because he has seen, because the world has
at least once engraved in him the ciphers of the visible.) He must affirm,
as one philosopher has said, that vision is a mirror or concentration of the
universe or that, in another’s words, the idios kosmos opens by virtue of vi-
sion upon a koinos kosmos, finally that the same thing is both out there in
the heart of the world and here in the heart of vision—the same or, if you
will, a similar thing, but according to an efficacious similarity which is the
parent, the genesis, the metamorphosis of being into his vision. It is the
mountain itself which from over there makes itself seen by the painter; it
is the mountain that he interrogates with his gaze.
What exactly does he ask of it? To unveil the means, which are noth-
ing but visible, by which the mountain makes itself into a mountain before
our eyes. Light, lighting, shadows, reflections, color, all these objects of
his investigation are not altogether real beings; like ghosts, they have only
visual existence. In fact they exist only at the threshold of profane vision;
they are not commonly seen. The painter’s gaze asks them how they make
358
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
359
E Y E A N D M I N D
360
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
III
361
E Y E A N D M I N D
which, he has every reason to believe, other people see in the very same
way, but which is no more for himself than for others a flesh. His “image”
in the mirror is an effect of the mechanics of things. If he recognizes him-
self in it, if he thinks it “looks like him,” it is his thought that weaves this
connection. The specular image is in no sense a part of him.
There is no longer any power of icons. However vividly an etching
may “represent to us” forests, towns, men, battles, storms, it does not re-
semble them. It is only a bit of ink put down here and there on paper. A
figure flattened down onto a plane surface scarcely retains the forms of
things; it is a deformed figure that must be deformed—the square be-
comes a lozenge, the circle an oval—in order to represent the object. It is
an image of the object only on the condition of “not resembling it.”10 If not
through resemblance, how, then, does it work? It “excites our thought” to
“conceive,” as do signs and words “which in no way resemble the things
they signify.”11 The etching gives us sufficient indices, unequivocal “means”
for forming an idea of the thing that does not come from the icon itself;
rather, it arises in us, as “occasioned” by the icon. The magic of intentional
species—the old idea of efficacious resemblance so strongly suggested to
us by mirrors and paintings—loses its final argument if the entire power
of the picture is that of a text to be read, a text totally free of promiscuity
between the seeing and the visible. We need no longer try to understand
how a painting of things in the body could make them felt in the soul—
an impossible task, since the resemblance between this painting and those
things would have to be seen in turn, since we would “have to have other
eyes in our brain with which to apperceive it,”12 and since the problem of
vision remains intact even after we have introduced these simulacra, wan-
dering between things and us. What the light casts upon our eyes, and
thence upon our brain, does not resemble the visible world any more than
etchings do. Nothing goes from things to the eyes, and from the eyes to vi-
sion, no more than from things to a blind man’s hands, and from his
hands to his thoughts. Vision is not the metamorphosis of the things them-
selves into the vision of them; it is not the double belonging of the things
to the big world and to a little private world. It is a thinking that strictly de-
ciphers the signs given within the body. Resemblance is the result of per-
ception, not its basis. Thus, the mental image, the visualization [la voy-
ance ] which renders present to us what is absent, is a fortiori nothing like
a breakthrough to the heart of Being. It is still a thought relying upon bod-
ily indices—this time insufficient ones—which are made to say more than
they mean. Nothing is left of the oneiric world of analogy. . . .
What interests us in these famous analyses is that they make us aware
of the fact that every theory of painting is a metaphysics. Descartes does
not say much about painting, and one might think it unfair on our part
362
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
to make so much of a few pages on engravings. Yet the very fact that he
speaks of painting only in passing is itself significant. Painting for him is
not a central operation contributing to the definition of our access to
being; it is a mode or a variant of thinking, where thinking is canonically
defined as intellectual possession and self-evidence. His very brevity is the
indication of a choice; a closer study of painting would draw a different
philosophy. It is significant, too, that when he speaks of “pictures”
[tableaux ] he takes the drawing as typical. We shall see that the whole of
painting is present in each of its modes of expression; there is a drawing,
a line that embraces all of painting’s boldness. But what Descartes likes
about engravings is that they preserve the form of objects, or at least they
give us sufficient signs of their forms. They present the object by its out-
side, or its envelope. If he had examined that other, deeper opening upon
things given us by the secondary qualities, especially color, then—since
there is no rule-governed or projective relationship between them and
the true properties of things, and we understand their message all the
same—he would have found himself faced with the problem of a con-
ceptless universality and opening upon things. He would have been
obliged to find out how the uncertain murmur of colors can present us
with things, forests, storms—in short the world. He would have been
obliged, perhaps, to integrate perspective, as a particular case, into a
broader ontological power. But for him it goes without saying that color is
an ornament, mere coloring, and that the entire power of painting lies in
that of drawing, and the power of drawing rests upon the ordered rela-
tionship between it and objective space established by perspectival pro-
jection. Pascal’s famous saying that painting is frivolous because it at-
taches us to images whose originals would not move us is a Cartesian
saying. For Descartes it is self-evident that one can paint only existing
things, that their existence consists in being extended, and line drawing
makes painting possible by making possible the representation of exten-
sion. Thus painting is only an artifice that puts before our eyes a projec-
tion similar to the one things themselves would (and do, according to the
commonsense view) inscribe in them. Painting causes us to see, in ab-
sence of the true object, just as we see the true object in life; and in par-
ticular it makes us see space where there is none.13 The picture is a flat
thing that gives to us artificially what we would see in the presence of “di-
versely positioned” things, by offering sufficient diacritical signs, through
height and width, of the dimension that it lacks. Depth is a third dimension
derived from the other two.
It will be worth our while to dwell for a moment upon this third di-
mension. There is, at first glance, something paradoxical about it. I see ob-
jects that hide each other and that consequently I do not see since they are
363
E Y E A N D M I N D
one behind the other. I see depth and yet it is not visible, since it is reck-
oned from our bodies to things, and since we are glued to our bodies.
This mystery is a false mystery. I do not truly see depth or, if I do, it
is only another width. On the line from my eyes to the horizon, the fore-
ground forever hides all the other planes, and if on either side I think I see
things staggered at intervals, it is because they do not completely hide
each other. Thus I see each thing outside the others, according to a width
measured differently.14 We are always on the hither side of depth, or
beyond it. Never are the things one behind the other. The encroachment
and latency of the things do not enter into their definition. They express
only my incomprehensible solidarity with one of them—my body; and by
their positivity they are thoughts that I form and not attributes of things.
I know that at this very moment another man, situated elsewhere—or
better, God, who is everywhere—could penetrate their hiding place and
see them openly deployed. What I call depth is either nothing, or else it is
my participation in a Being without restriction, first and foremost a par-
ticipation in the being of space beyond every particular point of view.
Things encroach upon one another because they are outside one another. The
proof of this is that I can see depth by looking at a picture which everyone
agrees has none and which organizes for me an illusion of an illusion. . . .
This two-dimensional being, which makes me see a third, is a being that
is pierced [troué ]—as people said during the Renaissance, a window. . . .
But in the final analysis the window opens only upon partes extra partes,
upon height and width merely seen from another angle—upon the ab-
solute positivity of Being.
It is this space without hiding places which in each of its points is
only what it is, neither more nor less, this identity of Being that underlies
the analysis of engravings. Space is in itself; or rather, it is the in-itself par
excellence. Its definition is to be in itself. Every point of space is, and is
thought as being, right where it is—one here, another there; space is the
self-evidence of the “where.” Orientation, polarity, envelopment are, in
space, derived phenomena connected to my presence. Space remains ab-
solutely in itself, everywhere equal to itself, homogeneous; its dimensions,
for example, are by definition interchangeable.
Like all classical ontologies, this one elevates certain properties of
beings into a structure of Being, and in so doing it is both true and false.
Reversing Leibniz’s remark, we might say that it is true in what it denies
and false in what it affirms. Descartes’ space is true, when contrasted with
a thought too empirically dominated, which dares not construct. It was
necessary first to idealize space, to conceive of that being—perfect of its
kind, clear, manageable, and homogeneous—which thought surveys [la
pensée survole ] without a viewpoint: a being which thought transcribes in
364
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
its entirety onto three right-angled axes. This had to be done so that we
could one day experience the limitations of that construction and under-
stand that space does not have three, neither more nor less, dimensions,
as an animal has either four or two legs, that dimensions are taken by dif-
ferent systems of measurement from a single dimensionality, a polymor-
phous Being, which justifies all of them without being fully expressed by
any. Descartes was right in liberating space. His mistake was to erect it into
a positive being, beyond all points of view, all latency and depth, devoid of
any real thickness.
He was also right in taking his inspiration from the perspectival tech-
niques of the Renaissance; they encouraged painting to produce freely ex-
periences of depth and in general presentations of Being. These tech-
niques were false only in that they claimed to close the investigation and
history of painting, in that they claimed to found once and for all an ex-
act and infallible art of painting. As Panofsky has shown concerning the
Renaissance, this enthusiasm was not without bad faith.15 The theoreti-
cians tried to forget the spherical visual field of the ancients, their angu-
lar perspective which connects the apparent size not to distance but to the
angle from which we see the object. They wanted to forget what they dis-
dainfully called perspectiva naturalis, or communis, in favor of a perspectiva
artificialis capable in principle of founding an exact construction. To ac-
credit this myth, they went so far as to expurgate Euclid, omitting from
their translations the eighth theorem, which bothered them. But the
painters knew from experience that no technique of perspective is an ex-
act solution and that there is no projection of the existing world which re-
spects it in all aspects and which deserves to become the fundamental law
of painting. They knew that linear perspective was far from being an ulti-
mate breakthrough; on the contrary, it opened several pathways for paint-
ing. For example, the Italians took the way of representing the object, but
the Northern painters discovered and worked out the formal technique
of Hochraum, Nahraum, and Schrägraum. Thus plane projection does not
always stimulate our thought to rediscover the true form of things, as
Descartes believed. Beyond a certain degree of deformation, it refers us
back, on the contrary, to our own vantage point; as for the things, they flee
into a remoteness that no thought traverses. Something about space
evades our attempts to survey it from above. The truth is that no acquired
means of expression resolves the problems of painting or transforms it
into a technique. For no symbolic form ever functions as a stimulus. Sym-
bolic form works and acts only in conjunction with the entire context of
the work, and not at all by means of trompe l’oeil. The Stilmoment never
dispenses with the Wermoment.16 The language of painting is never “insti-
365
E Y E A N D M I N D
366
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
tween space and thought, the autonomous order of the composite of soul
and body. The enigma of vision is not eliminated; it is shifted from the
“thought of seeing” to vision in act.
Still, this de facto vision and the “there is” which it contains do not
upset Descartes’ philosophy. Since it is thought united with a body, it can-
not, by definition, truly be conceived. One can practice it, exercise it, and,
so to speak, exist it; yet one can draw nothing from it which deserves to be
called true. If, like Queen Elizabeth,19 we want at all costs to think some-
thing about it, all we can do is go back to Aristotle and scholasticism, and
conceive thought as corporeal, which does not conceive itself, but which is
the only way to formulate, for the understanding, the union of soul and
body. The truth is that it is absurd to submit to pure understanding the
mixture of understanding and body. These would-be thoughts are the em-
blems of “the practice of everyday life,” the verbal blazons of the union, le-
gitimate on the condition that we do not take them to be thoughts. They
are indices of an order of existence—of humanity and world as existing—
that we are not burdened to think. This order marks out no terra incognita
on our map of Being. It does not confine the scope of our thoughts, be-
cause the order as well as the scope of our thoughts is sustained by a Truth
which grounds its obscurity as well as our own lights. We have to go to these
lengths to find in Descartes something like a metaphysics of depth. For we
are not present at the birth of this Truth; God’s being is for us an abyss. An
anxious trembling quickly mastered; for Descartes it is just as futile to
plumb that abyss as it is to think the space of the soul and the depth of the
visible. Our position disqualifies us from looking into such things. That is
the secret of Cartesian equilibrium: a metaphysics which gives us definitive
reasons to do metaphysics no longer, which validates our self-evidence
while limiting it, which opens up our thinking without rending it.
The secret has been lost, and lost for good, it seems. If we are ever
again to find an equilibrium between science and philosophy, between
our models and the obscurity of the “there is,” it must be a new equilib-
rium. Our science has rejected the justifications as well as the restrictions
which Descartes assigned to its domain. It no longer claims to deduce its
invented models from the attributes of God. The depth of the existing
world and that of an unfathomable God no longer double the flatness of
“technicized” thought. Science manages without the detour into meta-
physics that Descartes had to make at least once in his life; it begins from
the point he ultimately reached. Operational thought claims for itself, in
the name of psychology, that domain of contact with oneself and with the
world which Descartes reserved for a blind but irreducible experience.
Operational thought is fundamentally hostile to philosophy as thought in
contact, and if it rediscovers the sense of that philosophy, it will be
367
E Y E A N D M I N D
through the very excess of its daring; it will rediscover this sense when,
having introduced all sorts of notions that Descartes would have held to
arise from confused thought—quality, scalar structures, solidarity of ob-
server and observed—it suddenly realizes that one cannot summarily
speak of all these beings as constructa. Meanwhile, philosophy maintains
itself against such operationalist thinking, plunging itself into that di-
mension of the composite of soul and body, of the existent world, of the
abyssal Being that Descartes opened up and so quickly closed again. Our
science and our philosophy are two faithful and unfaithful offshoots of
Cartesianism, two monsters born of its dismemberment.
Nothing is left for our philosophy but to set out to prospect the ac-
tual world. We are the compound of soul and body, and so there must be
a thought of it. It is to this knowledge by position or situation that
Descartes owes what he himself says of it, or what he sometimes says of the
presence of the body “against the soul,” or of the exterior world “at the tip”
of our hands. Here the body is no longer the means of vision and touch,
but their depository. Our organs are not instruments; on the contrary, our
instruments are added-on organs. Space is not what it was in the Optics, a
network of relations between objects such as would be seen by a third
party witnessing my vision, or by a geometer who reconstructs my vision
and surveys it. It is, rather, a space to be reckoned starting from me as the
null point or degree zero of spatiality. I do not see it according to its exte-
rior envelope; I live it from the inside; I am immersed in it. After all, the
world is around me, not in front of me. Light is found once more to be ac-
tion at a distance. It is no longer reduced to the action of contact or, in
other words, conceived as it might be by those who cannot see. Vision re-
assumes its fundamental power of manifestation, of showing more than it-
self. And since we are told that a bit of ink suffices to make us see forests
and storms, light must have its own power to generate its imaginary. Its
transcendence is not delegated to a reading mind which deciphers the im-
pacts of the light qua thing upon the brain and which could do this quite
as well if it had never inhabited a body. No longer is it a matter of speak-
ing about space and light, but of making the space and the light that are
there speak. There is no end to this questioning, since the vision to which
it is addressed is itself a question. All the investigations we believed closed
have been reopened. What is depth, what is light, tiv to o[n? What are they—
not for the mind that cuts itself off from the body but for the mind
Descartes says is suffused throughout the body? And what are they, finally,
not only for the mind but for themselves, since they pass through us and
around us?
This philosophy, which is still to be made, is what animates the
painter—not when he expresses opinions about the world but in that in-
368
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
IV
The entire history of painting in the modern period, with its efforts to de-
tach itself from illusionism and acquire its own dimensions, has a meta-
physical significance. There can be no question of demonstrating this
claim. Not because of the limits of objectivity in history and the inevitable
plurality of interpretations, which would forbid linking a philosophy and
an event, for the metaphysics we have in mind is not a separate body of
ideas for which inductive justifications could then be sought in the expe-
riential realm—and there are, in the flesh of contingency, a structure of
the event and a virtue peculiar to the scenario that do not prevent the plu-
rality of interpretations but in fact are the deepest reason for it. They
make the event a durable theme of historical life, and have a right to
philosophical status. In a sense everything that may have been said and
will be said about the French Revolution has always been and will hence-
forth be within it, in that wave arising from a roil of discrete facts, with its
froth of the past and its crest of the future. And it is always by looking
better at how it was made that we provide and will go on providing new rep-
resentations of it. As for the history of works of art, in any case, if they are
great, the sense we give to them after the fact has issued from them. It is
the work itself that has opened the field from which it appears in another
light. It metamorphoses itself and becomes what follows; the interminable
reinterpretations to which it is legitimately susceptible change it only into
itself. And if the historian unearths beneath its manifest content a surplus
and thickness of sense, the texture which was preparing a long future,
then this active manner of being, this possibility he unveils in the work,
this monograph he finds there—all are grounds for a philosophical medi-
tation. But such a labor demands a long familiarity with history. We lack
everything for its execution, both the competence and the location. But
since the power or the generativity of works of art exceeds every positive
causal or filial relation, it is not illegitimate for a layman, speaking from
his memory of a few pictures and books, to say how painting enters into
his reflections, and to register the feeling of a profound discordance, a
mutation in the relationship between man and Being, when he brings a
universe of classical thought into confrontation with the investigations of
modern painting. A sort of history by contact that perhaps does not go
369
E Y E A N D M I N D
beyond the limits of one person, though it owes everything to the fre-
quentation of others. . . .
Giacometti says, “I believe Cézanne was seeking depth all his life.”21
Robert Delaunay says, “Depth is the new inspiration.”22 Four centuries
after the “solutions” of the Renaissance and three centuries after
Descartes, depth is still new, and it insists on being sought, not “once in his
life” but all throughout a life. It is not possible that what is at issue is an in-
terval without any mystery, an interval as seen from an airplane, between
these trees nearby and those farther away. Nor is it a matter of the sleight
of hand by means of which one thing is replaced by another, as a per-
spective drawing represents to me so vividly. These two views are very ex-
plicit and raise no question. What brings about the enigma is their con-
nection; the enigma is what is between them. I see things, each one in its
place, precisely because they eclipse one another; they are rivals before
my gaze precisely because each one is in its own place. The enigma is their
known exteriority in their envelopment and their mutual dependence in
their autonomy. Once depth is understood in this way, we can no longer
call it a third dimension. In the first place, if it were a dimension, it would
be the first one; there are forms and definite planes only if it is stipulated
how far from me their different parts are. But a first dimension and one
that contains all the others is no longer a dimension, at least in the ordi-
nary sense of a certain relationship according to which we make measure-
ments. Depth thus understood is, rather, the experience of the reversibil-
ity of dimensions, of a global “locality” in which everything is at the same
time, a locality from which height, width, and distance are abstracted, the
experience of a voluminosity we express in a word when we say that a thing
is there. In pursuing depth, what Cézanne is seeking is this deflagration of
Being, and it is all in the modes of space, and in the form as well. Cézanne
already knew what cubism would restate: that the external form, the en-
velope, is secondary and derived, that it is not what makes a thing take
form, that that shell of space must be shattered—the fruit bowl must be
broken. But then what should be painted instead? Cubes, spheres, and
cones—as he said once? Pure forms having the solidity of what could be
defined by an internal law of construction, forms which taken together, as
traces or cross-sections of the thing, let it appear between them like a face
in the reeds? This would be to put Being’s solidity on one side and its va-
riety on the other. Cézanne had already made an experiment of this kind
in his middle period. He went directly to the solid, to space—and came to
find that inside this space—this box or container too large for them—the
things begin to move, color against color, they begin to modulate in the
instability.23 Thus we must seek space and its content together. The prob-
370
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
371
E Y E A N D M I N D
372
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
already familiar to the painters, that there are no lines visible in them-
selves, that neither the contour of the apple nor the border between field
and meadow is in this place or that, that they are always on the near or the
far side of the point we look at. They are always between or behind what-
ever we fix our eyes upon; they are indicated, implicated, and even very
imperiously demanded by the things, but they themselves are not things.
They were supposed to circumscribe the apple or the meadow, but the
apple and the meadow “form themselves” from themselves, and come into
the visible as if they had come from a pre-spatial world behind the scenes.
Now the contestation of the prosaic line does not rule out all lines in
painting, as perhaps the impressionists have believed. It is simply a matter
of freeing the line, of revivifying its constituting power; and we are not
faced with a contradiction when we see it reappear and triumph in painters
like Klee or Matisse, who more than anyone believed in color. For hence-
forth, as Klee said, the line no longer imitates the visible, it “renders vis-
ible,” it is the sketch of a genesis of things. Perhaps no one before Klee had
“let a line dream.”34 The beginning of the line’s path establishes or installs
a certain level or mode of the linear, a certain manner for the line to be
and to make itself a line, “d’aller ligne.”35 Relative to it, every subsequent
inflection will have a diacritical value, will be another aspect of the line’s
relationship to itself, will form an adventure, a history, a sense of the line,
insofar as the line slants more or less, more or less rapidly, more or less
subtly.
Making its way in space, it nevertheless eats away at prosaic space and
its partes extra partes; it develops a way of extending itself actively into that
space which subtends the spatiality of a thing quite as well as that of an
apple tree or a man. It is just that, as Klee said, in order to give the gener-
ating axis of a man, the painter “would have to have a network of lines so
entangled that it could no longer be a question of a truly elementary rep-
resentation.”36 It makes little difference whether the painter decides, like
Klee, to hold rigorously to the principle of the genesis of the visible, the
principle of fundamental, indirect, or—as Klee used to say—absolute
painting, and then leave it up to the title to designate by its prosaic name
the being thus constituted, in order to leave the painting free to function
more purely as a painting; or alternatively, like Matisse in his drawings, the
painter decides to put into a single line both the prosaic, identifying char-
acteristics of the being and the hidden operation that composes in the
being the indolence or inertia and the force in order to constitute it as
nude, as face, or as flower. There are the two holly leaves that Klee has
painted in the most figurative way. These two holly leaves are rigorously in-
decipherable at first, and they remain to the end monstrous, unbelievable,
phantasmic, because of exactness. And Matisse’s women (let us keep in mind
373
E Y E A N D M I N D
374
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
is taken at the moment when both feet are touching the ground; for then
we almost have the temporal ubiquity of the body which brings it about
that the person bestrides [enjambe ] space. The picture makes movement vis-
ible by its internal discordance. Each member’s position, precisely by vir-
tue of its incompatibility with that of the others (according to the body’s
logic), is dated differently, and since all of them remain visibly within the
unity of one body, it is the body which comes to bestride duration. Its
movement is something conspired between legs, trunk, arms, and head in
some virtual focal point, and it breaks forth only subsequently by change
of place. When a horse is photographed at that instant when he is com-
pletely off the ground, with his legs almost folded under him—an instant,
therefore, when he must be moving —why does he look as if he were leap-
ing in place? And why, by contrast, do Géricault’s horses run on canvas,
in a posture impossible for a real horse at a gallop? It is because the horses
in Epsom Derby bring me to see the body’s grip upon the ground and, ac-
cording to a logic of body and of the world that I know well, these grips
upon space are also grips upon duration. Rodin said profoundly, “It is the
artist who is truthful, while the photograph lies; for, in reality, time never
stops.”38 The photograph keeps open the instant which the onrush of time
closes up forthwith; it destroys the overtaking, the overlapping, the “meta-
morphosis” of time. This is what painting, in contrast, makes visible, be-
cause the horses have in them that “leaving here, going there,”39 because
they have a foot in each instant. Painting searches not for the outside of
the movement but for its secret ciphers. There are some still more subtle
than those of which Rodin spoke: all flesh, and even that of the world, ra-
diates beyond itself. But whether, depending on the epochs and the
“schools,” one is attached more to manifest movement or to the monu-
mental, painting is never altogether outside time, because it is always
within the carnal.
Now perhaps we have a better sense of how much is contained in
that little word “see.” Vision is not a certain mode of thought or presence
to self; it is the means given me for being absent from myself, for being
present from the inside at the fission of Being only at the end of which do
I close up into myself.
Painters have always known this. Da Vinci invoked a “pictorial
science” which does not speak in words (and still less in numbers) but in
works that exist in the visible just as natural things do—and which yet
communicates itself through them “to all the generations of the uni-
verse.”40 It is this silent science, says Rilke (apropos of Rodin), that brings
into the work the forms of things “whose seal has not yet been broken”; it
comes from the eye and addresses itself to the eye.41 We must understand
the eye as the “window of the soul.” “The eye . . . through which the beauty
375
E Y E A N D M I N D
376
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R
restoration of the visible, they also annex the occultly perceived portion
of the invisible.”45 There is that which reaches the eye head on, the frontal
properties of the visible; but there is also that which reaches it from be-
low—the deep postural latency whereby the body raises itself to see—and
that which reaches vision from above like the phenomena of flight, of
swimming, of movement, where it participates no longer in the heaviness
of origins but in free accomplishments.46 Through vision, then, the
painter touches both extremities. In the immemorial depth of the visible,
something has moved, caught fire, which engulfs his body; everything he
paints is in answer to this incitement, and his hand is “nothing but the in-
strument of a distant will.” Vision is the encounter, as at a crossroads, of all
the aspects of Being. “A certain fire wills to live; it wakes. Working its way
along the hand’s conductor, it reaches the canvas and invades it; then, a
leaping spark, it arcs the gap in the circle it was to trace: the return to the
eye, and beyond.”47 There is no break at all in this circuit; it is impossible
to say that here nature ends and the human being or expression begins.
It is, then, silent Being that itself comes to show forth its own sense.
Herein lies the reason why the dilemma between figurative and nonfigu-
rative art is badly posed; it is at once true and uncontradictory that no
grape was ever what it is in the most figurative painting and that no paint-
ing, no matter how abstract, can get away from Being, that even Caravag-
gio’s grape is the grape itself.48 This precession of what is upon what one
sees and makes seen, of what one sees and makes seen upon what is—this
is vision itself. And to give the ontological formula of painting we hardly
need to force the painter’s own words, Klee’s words written at the age of
thirty-seven and ultimately inscribed on his tomb: “I cannot be grasped in
immanence.”49
Because depth, color, form, line, movement, contour, physiognomy are all
branches of Being and because each entwines the tufts of all the rest, there
are no separated, distinct “problems” in painting, no really opposed
paths, no partial “solutions,” no cumulative progress, no options that can-
not return. There is nothing to prevent the painter from going back to
one of the emblems he has shied away from—making it, of course, speak
differently. Rouault’s contours are not those of Ingres. Light is the “old
sultana,” says Georges Limbour, “whose charms withered away at the be-
ginning of this century.”50 Expelled at first by the painters of matter, it
reappears finally in Dubuffet as a certain texture of matter. One is never
377
E Y E A N D M I N D
378
T H E M E R L E A U - P O N T Y R E A D E R