Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Structural Flaws of Income As A Base For Taxation: John - Prebble@vuw - Ac.nz

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

STRUCTURAL FLAWS OF INCOME AS A BASE FOR

TAXATION

WORKING PAPER SERIES


Working Paper No.6

John Prebble
Faculty of Law
Victoria University of Wellington
New Zealand
John.Prebble@vuw.ac.nz
http;//www.vuw.ac.nz/~prebble

This paper is work in progress. Please do not quote


without the permission of the author.

Centre for Accounting, Governance and Taxation


Research
School of Accounting and Commercial Law
Victoria University of Wellington
PO Box 600
Wellington
New Zealand

Phone 64 4 4636957 Fax 64 4 4636955


http;//www.accounting-research.org.nz
Working Paper: Do not Cite

1
Structural Flaws of Income as a Base for Taxation

2
John Prebble

Contents

An institution in decay..................................................................... 2
History................................................................................................. 3
The foundations of income tax ...................................................... 7
Ectopia ................................................................................................ 8
Criticisms of the ectopia thesis .................................................... 10
Fictions.............................................................................................. 11
Explanatory utility of the ectopia concept ................................. 15
The tax value method..................................................................... 17
Why does income tax survive? .................................................... 19
Conclusion........................................................................................ 23

An institution in decay
Fifteen years ago Ross Parsons published his Wilfred Fullagar
Lecture in the Australian Tax Forum. His subject was
3
“Income Taxation–an Institution in Decay”. His lecture was
influential. Scholars cite it regularly. This evening I shall
consider Parsons’s thesis and evaluate it from several points
of view: factually, historically, philosophically, and as a
prophecy that society would abandon income taxation.
Parsons’s fundamental position was that, “The analytical
fabric of the income tax … had congenital and … incurable
defects, born as it was of a union of institutions which had no
common policies”. The institutions to which he referred were
first the income tax itself, and secondly the concept of
income. In Parsons’s opinion, income tax adopted the concept
of income from the law of trusts, which, he explained, is
based on principles that are different from and irrelevant to
4
the policies and imperatives of income tax law.

1
This paper is a revised version of the author’s inaugural Ross Parsons
Memorial Lecture, delivered in Sydney on 14 June 2001. It is due to be
published in due course as an article in the Sydney University Law
Review. Comments, please, to John.Prebble@vuw.ac.nz.
2
BA, LLB (hons) (Auckland); BCL (Oxon); JSD (Cornell); Inner Temple.
Professor and former Dean of Law at Victoria University, Wellington,
New Zealand. www.vuw.ac.nz/~prebble.
3
(1986) 3 Australian Tax Forum 233.
4
Id 238 – 240.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


2
Working Paper: Do not Cite

5
Parsons chose the Simons definition as the appropriate
benchmark against which to test the judicial concept of
income that has developed in Australian and United Kingdom
law. Essentially, Simons said that the tax base should embrace
all economic gains, but that it should embrace only economic
6
gains. Parsons explained that the Australian tax base fails on
both counts.
There are several fundamental problems with the judicial
concept of income, that is, the concept of income that the
courts employ for tax purposes. First, the judicial concept sees
income as a flow, rather than as a gain. Secondly, as a
consequence, it taxes some apparent flows that do not entail
gains. Thirdly, it omits gains that we call capital gains.
Australia attempted to remedy that shortcoming by bolting a
7
capital gains tax onto the income tax in 1986. Fourthly, it
relies on legal transactions rather than on underlying
economic movements. I shall return several times to this
fourth point during this lecture.
Ross Parsons would agree with me that the shortcomings
that I have just listed are not stand-alone defects of income
taxation but symptoms of the analytical shortcomings of the
concept of income. I shall continue from here in a moment,
after considering some history.

History
One way in which Parsons has been influential is in respect of
his opinion that tax law adopted its concept of income from
trust law. Nowadays a number of other people hold this belief
and have written about it. When I find these people I ask them
8
for their source. The source is invariably Parsons. On the
other hand, Parsons himself cites as his only authority Inland
9
Revenue Commissioners v Blott . Parsons argued that the

5
Simons, H, Personal Income Taxation. The Definition of Income as a
Problem of Fiscal Policy (1938) Chicago, University of Chicago Press,
50-51.
6
Idem. Simons’s full definition was: “Personal income may be defined as
the algebraic sum of (1) the market value of rights exercised in
consumption and (2) the change in the value of the store of property rights
between the beginning and end of the period in question. In other words, it
is merely the result obtained by adding consumption during the period to
‘wealth’ at the end of the period and then subtracting ‘wealth’ at the
beginning. The sine qua non of income is gain as our courts have
recognised in their more lucid moments–and gain to someone during a
specified time interval.”
7
Income Tax Assessment (Capital Gains) Act 1986.
8
The present author is among these people. Prebble, J, “Why is tax law
incomprehensible?” [1994] British Tax Review, 380, 388.
9
[1921] AC 171.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


3
Working Paper: Do not Cite

House of Lords in the Blott case used the trust case of Bouche
10
v Sproule to conclude that a bonus issue of shares was not
income for purposes of the United Kingdom income tax. Even
if Parsons had been correct in his analysis of Blott’s case, it
would not necessarily follow that trust law was the source of
the concept of income for tax law. In fact, if anything, Inland
Revenue Commissioners v Blott taken together with Bouche v
11
Sproule establishes the opposite. The majority in Blott first,
and independently, establishes the parameters of the concept
12
of income. They then turn to Bouche v Sproule merely as
13
confirmation of their conclusion, not as the source of it. The
two branches of the law draw separately on the same concept
of income, a concept of income that exists independently from
14
either of those two branches. As Viscount Finlay put it,
The question whether it was income or capital could not be
affected by the purpose which led to the institution of the inquiry.
The fundamentals of the legal concept of income that the
House of Lords deployed in Inland Revenue Commissioners v
Blott remain with us today, but they have a history that goes
back at least to the poll taxes of the seventeenth century. As
their name implies, poll taxes were capitation taxes, but
Parliament levied them on a progressive scale. Discovering
people’s income was either impractical or intrusive. Instead,
the graduation used ranks and occupations as a surrogate, to
tax income indirectly, on the assumption that people’s income
corresponded with their position in life. For instance, the poll
tax of 1641 levied £100 on dukes, with rates falling through to
15
ranks of nobility to £10 on esquires.
The assessed taxes of the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries also approached income asymptotically, though they
chose expenditure, not rank, as an appropriate surrogate for
16
income. The hearth tax of 1662 was an early example,
imposing tax on the basis of the numbers of fireplaces in
17
people’s houses. The window tax of 1695, charged two
shillings a year to the occupant of each dwellinghouse, with
higher rates for larger houses. The tax estimated size by
counting windows, assessing an additional four shillings if

10
(1887) 12 App Cas 385.
11
Viscounts Haldane, Finlay, and Cave. Lords Dunedin and Sumner
dissented.
12
[1921] AC 171, 184 (Viscount Haldane), 196 (Viscount Finlay), 200
(Viscount Cave).
13
[1921] AC 171, 185 ff (Viscount Haldane), 197 ff (Viscount Finlay),
201 ff (Viscount Cave).
14
[1921] AC 171, 197.
15
16 Chas I c 9.
16
14 Car II, c 10.
17
7 & 8 Will III c 18 (1695-96).

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


4
Working Paper: Do not Cite

one’s house had ten windows, and eight shillings for houses
with twenty or more windows. In effect, the hearth and
window taxes achieved a form of taxation that was doubly
indirect. They used one surrogate (numbers of hearths and
windows) to estimate another (size of house) which itself was
a surrogate for people’s income. New assessed taxes in the
eighteenth century cut out one step of indirectness and
imposed duties on items that were considered to be luxurious,
18 19
such as horses, carriages, clocks and watches, dogs, and
20
male servants.
The assessed taxes proved inadequate to fund the
Napoleonic Wars at the end of the eighteenth century.
Parliament’s initial response was to increase the rates, which
21
resulted in the Triple Assessment of 1798, promoted by Pitt
as an emergency war tax. Like the assessed taxes that
preceded it, the Triple Assessment used expenditure in an
effort to assess income. The Triple Assessment required
people to pay the same amount that they paid in 1797 again,
and in addition an extra assessment of the 1797 amount,
multiplied by factors that increased in proportion to the totals
of the 1797 payments.
Originally, Pitt intended to triple the amounts paid on
22
items of special luxury. This intention appears to be the
23
origin of the name, “Triple Assessment”. In the event the
24
multipliers chosen varied from one tenth to five. It is evident
from Pitt’s comments that he regarded the true tax base as
income, with luxury expenditure being merely an indication
of the size of one’s income. In the debate on the Bill, Pitt
explained that “the fairest criterion for judging of the
proportions which ought to be paid by the various classes of
society according to their income, was the return of the
25
assessed taxes.” The multipliers employed in the Triple

18
20 Geo II, c 10 (1747).
19
37 Geo III, c 108 (1797).
20
17 Geo III, c 39 (1777).
21
(1798) 38 Geo III, c 16.
22
Debate on Mr. Pitt’s Proposition for Trebling the Assessed Taxes,
December 4, 1797, Para. 1066 - 1089. At para. 1068 the clerk wrote: “It
was his [Pitt’s] intention, therefore, as these [taxes on servants, horses,
carriages, dogs and watches] were chiefly articles of luxury, to triple the
duties upon the latter.”
23
For slightly different explanations see P.E. Soos, The Origins of
Taxation as Source in England (1997) Amsterdam, IBFD Publications
145; and B.E.V. Sabine A Short History of Taxation London, Butterworths
(1980), 113.
24
38 Geo III, c 16, §1.
25
Debate on Mr. Pitt’s Proposition for Trebling the Assessed Taxes,
December 4, 1797, Paras 1066 – 1089, para. 1067.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


5
Working Paper: Do not Cite

Assessment operated to create a crude progressive scale for


taxing the surrogate of income that was its target. For
instance, if an individual’s 1797 taxes assessed on male
servants, carriages, and saddle and carriage horses came to
less than £25 the sum was multiplied by three, but if it was
26
£50 or more the sum was multiplied by five.
One problem with the Triple Assessment was that people
who had a good portion of their wealth tied up in assets that
the tax caught, but who were not hugely wealthy, risked
paying a significant fraction of their income in tax: at least, a
fraction that at the time people thought to be too high. This
potentially inequitable result had always been a flaw in the
assessed taxes’ strategy of using expenditure as a surrogate
for income. The greatly increased rates of the Triple
Assessment, together with the steep scale created by the
progressive increase in the factors used to multiply the 1797
rates, risked bringing the consequences of this flaw home to
taxpayers’ pockets with a vengeance.
Pitt’s remedy was to add a rider to abate the tax in
proportion to people’s income. There was another progressive
scale for this purpose. People with annual incomes under £60
had to pay a maximum of one one hundred and twentieth of
their annual income. The scale rose by twenty-nine
27
increments to ten per cent for incomes over £200 a year. The
schedule to the Triple Assessment set out rules for estimating
income, rather than calculating it. The schedule contained
nine “cases” of income, such as income from lands derived by
owners and tenants, as well as income from professions,
28
trades, vocations, annuities, interest, rent charges, and so on.
That is, not only did the concept of income precede the
enactment of the United Kingdom’s first income tax, but the
schedular and case system that remains a salient feature of
29
that tax to this day has deeper historical origins.
The Triple Assessment was widely evaded and did not last
long. Parliament replaced it in 1799 with the income tax
30
proper, which taxed income directly rather than via a
surrogate. There was a progressive rate, which peaked at ten
per cent for incomes of £200 or more. “Income” was defined
as income from land, trade, annuities and professions. The

26
38 Geo III, c 16, §1.
27
Cobbett, W, 33 Parliamentary History, (1797-1798, 38 Geo III) 1076
(Pitt).
28
(1798) 38 Geo III, c 16, Schedule I.
29
Income and Corporation Taxes Act 1988 (UK).
30
39 Geo III, c 13.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


6
Working Paper: Do not Cite

idea of schedules, carried forward from the Triple


31
Assessment, was not used initially, but was added in 1803.
The income tax of 1799 inherited the very concept of
income that Parliament had used the year before to abate the
Triple Assessment: a regular flow that is measured annually.
This is the concept that has descended to us today. It is the
same concept that has worked its way through the law of
trusts. Simply, the judicial concept of income adopts the
ordinary meaning of the word, little informed by the views of
economists.

The foundations of income tax


Parsons may have been wrong about the origin of the judicial
concept of income as a tax base, but he was correct that
income taxation has congenital and incurable defects. He was
also correct that these defects lie in the fact that income tax
law needs a concept of income at its core. Let me first
examine the defects, and then try to explain why they are
incurable.
The defects are a function of the fact that income tax law is
separated from its subject matter. Looked at another way, tax
law’s concept of income is not income itself but a simulacrum
of income. The separation of income tax law from its subject
matter can be seen best in the law’s efforts to tax business
profits. Business profits arise independently of the law, and
sometimes even in spite of the law. They are not a result even
of contract law, let alone of tax law. They are the result of
people’s economic transactions with one another. The
fundamental problem of any income tax law is that it cannot
tax economic transactions directly. Rather, it taxes the legal
32
forms that we use to represent economic transactions.
Let me illustrate with a comparison from criminal law. Ms
Turpin and Ms Good look very much alike, but Ms Turpin is
a robber and Ms Good a teacher. One of Ms Turpin’s victims
gets a good look at her and manages to compose an identikit

31
43 Geo III, c 22.
32
Exceptionally among common law jurisdictions, the United States of
America tries to circumvent this problem by employing a substance-over-
form approach in tax cases. Gregory v Helvering 293 US 465 (1935). The
United States has not always managed to maintain this approach. See, eg,
the cases known as the “Mexican railcar cases”, such as Chicago,
Burlington, & Quincy R Co v United States, 455 F. 2d 993 (Ct Cl 1972)
and Missouri Pacific Railroad Co v United States, 497 F. 2d 1386 (Ct Cl
1974). For a recent discussion and references, see P.A. Glicklich and M.J.
Miller “Appeals Court adheres to precedent, tells IRS that it’s too late to
issue regulations” in Glicklich & SH Goldberg, Selected US Tax
Developments, newsletter of Roberts & Holland LLP, New York, (2001).

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


7
Working Paper: Do not Cite

portrait. The portrait is a good likeness of Ms Turpin, but it


looks even more like Ms Good. On these facts, nobody would
suggest that Ms Good, the teacher, committed the crime. In
tax law, however, a taxpayer crafts a series of legal
transactions to represent an underlying economic substance.
Either calculatedly or not, the legal transactions sometimes
look more like some other economic substance. Perhaps what
is economically a partnership looks more like a mortgage.
Absent an avoidance rule, tax law will ordinarily tax the
transaction as a mortgage, and not as a partnership. We can
compare that characterisation to criminal law finding Ms
Good guilty of robbery because the victim’s simulacrum of
the robber looks more like Ms Good than Ms Turpin.
Criminal law does not work like that, but income tax does.

Ectopia
As I have said, tax law generally taxes the results of legal
transactions rather than their underlying economic effect. The
courts are always telling us that tax law does not tax on the
33
basis of economic equivalence. But the problem is deeper.
In order to make income tax work at all, the law must make a
number of assumptions that are not in fact correct,
assumptions as to both the factual and the legal nature of the
taxpayer’s income. The effect of these assumptions is that the
base that the law taxes is removed even further from the facts
of the case.
34
I have written several articles on this phenomenon, which
I call “ectopia”. “Ectopia” means “displacement” or
“dislocation”. We see it in “ectopic pregnancy”, meaning a
pregnancy that develops in the wrong place. Like the ectopia
of a pregnancy in the fallopian tube, the ectopia of the concept
of income is pathological and incurable.

33
Eg Commissioner of Inland Revenue v Europa Oil (NZ) Ltd [1971]
NZLR 641, 648 PC.
34
“Ectopia, formalism, and anti-avoidance rules in income tax law”
(1994) in W. Krawietz N. MacCormick & G.H. von Wright (eds)
Prescriptive Formality and Normative Rationality in Modern Legal
Systems, Festschrift for Robert S. Summers, Duncker and Humblot, Berlin,
367-383; “Philosophical and design problems that arise from the ectopic
nature of income tax law and their impact on the taxation of international
trade and investment”, (1995) 13 Chinese Yearbook of International Law
and Affairs, 111-139, reprinted as “Ectopia, tax law, and international
taxation” [1997] British Tax Review 383; “Can income tax law be
simplified?” (1996) 2 NZ Journal of Taxation Law and Policy 187;
“Should tax legislation be written from a principles and purpose point of
view of a precise and detailed point of view?” [1998] British Tax Review
112; see also “Why is tax law incomprehensible?” (1994) British Tax
Review 380-393.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


8
Working Paper: Do not Cite

By an apt coincidence, the secondary meaning of


“income”, which has nothing to do with tax, involves a
problem that is literally pathological. An “income” as a
35
tumour or “a morbid affection of any part of the body”. My
thesis is that the metaphorical pathology of income tax law is
so extreme that it makes tax law a different species from other
kinds of law. As physiological incomes are different from
healthy flesh, so income tax law is different from other law.
Some people in the audience have been kind enough to read
my articles. In deference to those charitable people I shall not
deal with ectopia at length, but I summarise my major themes.
The fundamental difficulty is that we cannot have an
income tax without a concept of income. For a number of
reasons, our concept of income must be artificial. I have
mentioned one, the fact that we tax a legalistic simulacrum of
transactions rather than the transactions themselves. Other
reasons include the problems of place and of time.
The problem of place arises in connection with
international transactions. Income tax law assumes that all
income can be located in one jurisdiction or another as a
matter of physical fact, or, as Isaacs J put it, as “a hard,
36
practical matter of fact”. Almost any example of an
international transaction will dispel this assumption. Where is
the source of the profit that a multi-national company makes
on selling a computer to a retail buyer in Sydney? In one
sense the question makes no sense. Profit is a net concept, the
difference between receipts and expenditure. A difference
cannot exist physically in space.
From another point of view the question makes a little
more sense, in that a fraction of the multi-national company’s
profit comes, no doubt, from activity at each of its
manufacturing plants, its head office, its despatch department,
its marketing department and its treasury administration, to
name only some of the more obvious profit centres. However,
anyone with the barest acquaintance with transfer pricing
rules and practices will appreciate that dividing profit among
these centres is an inexact process that uses surrogates for
truth rather than the underlying truth itself.
The problem of time is worse. Ideally, we would wait for a
business to go through its whole life, from foundation to
liquidation, before determining whether there had been profits
and, if so, how much they were. Of course, tax systems, like
shareholders, cannot wait so long; so, like accountants, tax

35
Dialect, Northern or Scottish, Oxford English Dictionary, 2nd ed 1989.
36
Nathan v Federal Commissioner of Taxation (1918) 25 CLR 183, 189–
190.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


9
Working Paper: Do not Cite

authorities require businesses to divide their lives into periods


delimited by dates. Both accountants and tax law always use
twelve months, but there is no special reason for this
convention apart from convenience.
One result is that Parliament must legislate so that receipts
and expenses are treated not as the taxpayer actually meets
them, but as they might have occurred had they been spread
evenly over time. Income smoothing for farmers is a good
37
example.
I have discussed some problems of timing to show how tax
law must distort facts and law in order to operate. But the
major problem that relates to time is the distinction between
capital and revenue. An annual taxing system must have this
distinction, but the distinction causes capital and revenue to
be treated differently, even though they are essentially
fungible, with all the consequences that we know.
None of this is to criticise Parliament’s response.
Parliament cannot allow clever people to defer receipts or to
create contrived interest deductions. If Parliament must create
and tax a simulacrum of interest payments rather than actual
interest payments that is understandable. It is probably even a
38
good thing. My point is more fundamental. It is that an
income tax system cannot work without such pretences.

Criticisms of the ectopia thesis


I have tried to explain the thesis that income tax law is
different in kind from most other law because of the
dislocation between income tax law and the facts to which it
relates. People have responded with various criticisms or
questions, which are directed to suggesting that income tax
law is not so very unusual. This evening, I shall address just
one of those criticisms, that the law is well used to fictions.
Are not the assumptions that give us our concept of income
just examples of legal fictions? I shall attempt to answer that
question first generally and then particularly.
Regarding the matter in general, it is a characteristic of law
as an institution to enjoy an almost symbiotic relationship
with its subject matter. When sovereigns legislate, they make
sure that their laws relate as closely as possible to the subject
matter of those laws, if only for efficiency. A sovereign who
wants to forbid assault does not create an offence of
consensual hugging, at least not intentionally. But a sovereign
who wants to tax the profits of hire purchase transactions
efficiently may pass a law that pretends that hire purchase

37
Eg Income Tax Assessment Act 1997 (Cth) Division 392.
38
Eg Income Tax Act 1996 (NZ) subpart EH.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


10
Working Paper: Do not Cite

transactions are credit sales. Section FC 10 of the New


Zealand Income Tax Act 1994 is such a provision. Australia
introduced Division 240, a provision that contains rules that
have a similar effect, in the Tax Law Amendment Bill (No 3)
of 1999. The new rules remain in Bill form at the time of
writing, but they are expected to be enacted during 2001.
Economically hire purchase transactions are credit sales, but
that is neither their legal form nor their legal substance. To be
effective, tax law must pretend that they are something else.
Credit is as different from hire purchase as a hug is from an
assault, but such recharacterisations are commonplace in tax
law. The general point is that, unlike the position in respect of
other forms of law, the separation between tax law and its
subject matter is real, inherent, and unavoidable. I shall try to
demonstrate that tax law uses fictions to bridge this
separation, whereas the role of fictions in other areas of law is
less fundamental.

Fictions
I pass now to legal fictions more specifically. My thesis is that
the fictions of income tax law are of a different character from
other legal fictions. I shall illustrate by considering several
fictions from history. Roman law had many fictions. For
instance the fictio Legis Corneliae addressed the problem of
Romans dying in captivity. If a Roman was captured he lost
his citizenship, and with it his capacity to make a valid
testament. The Romans glossed the Lex Cornelia with a
fiction that for succession purposes Roman citizens should be
deemed to have died at the instant of capture, while still free
39
men and citizens.
That is a fiction from Roman law. Two fictions from the
common law are the doctrine of trover and the concept of
attractive nuisance. When you sued people for the return of
your goods you pleaded that they had found them, even if the
defendant had taken the goods by force. This pleading was to
bring your claim within the form of action of trover and
40
detinue, which did not allow for theft. The courts well knew

39
Justinian The Institutes, translated and annotated and with commentary
th
by T.C. Sandars, 7 ed (new impression) London 1962, 180. The Lex
Cornelia de falsis (BC 81) provided the same penalty for forging the
testament of a person dying in captivity as for forging the testament of
someone dying in his own country. The law could not have intended to
attach a penalty to forging a testament that was invalid. Accordingly, it
must be assumed that the deceased had the power of making a testament
both when he in fact made it and when he died.
40 rd
Blackstone III Private Wrongs 153, 3 ed London 1862, 160 – 161.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


11
Working Paper: Do not Cite

what was going on and assumed the fictional fact that the
defendant had indeed found the goods.
My second common law example is the attractive
nuisance. An attractive nuisance is something on your land
that is dangerous but that attracts children to play on it. The
common law said that you did not have to worry as the
children were crushed under tons of falling scrap metal or had
their limbs torn off by locomotive turntables that were out of
control. You did not invite the children; they were trespassers
and they got what was coming to them. Occasionally the
courts found all this too robust and held that people leaving
attractive but dangerous articles on their land must be taken to
have issued an invitation to come in and play on those
articles; so the maimed children were not trespassers, and the
41
occupiers were liable.
The three fictions that I have mentioned share a common
characteristic: by implication, they created rules that someone
could have drafted expressly. Rome could have ruled that the
wills of former citizens dying in captivity were valid. England
could have created a form of action for suing a thief for one’s
goods or could have passed a statute providing for a greater
degree of liability on the part of occupiers, as in fact England
42
did many years later.
The fictions of income tax law are very different. The
classic legal fiction entails pretence, but taxation fictions
entail duplicity. The pretence of the classic legal fiction is a
roundabout route to a just result that courts employ when a
direct route is not available. In contrast, the duplicity of a
taxation fiction is a necessary part of the route of one’s legal
argument and even part of the result of the argument. Let me
illustrate.
Rules that spread interest that is paid on day one over the
life of a loan assume expressly or impliedly that the interest is
43
paid at regular rests. Rules that attribute the income of
44 45
foreign trustees or of foreign companies to Australian
residents assume impliedly that the Australian residents in
question indeed derive the income.

41
Sioux City & Pacific Rly Co v Stout (1873) 17 Wall. 657 (US SC), City
of Pekin v McMahon 154 Ill 141 (1895), and United Zinc v Bruitt 258 US
268, 275 (1921) per Holmes J. But see Addie v Dumbreck [1929] AC 358
HL.
42
Occupiers’ Liability Act 1957.
43
Eg, New Zealand Income Tax Act 1994, subpart EH (the qualified
accrual rules).
44
Eg Income Tax Assessment Act 1936 s 97(1)(a).
45
Eg Income Tax Assessment Act 1936 Part X, Division 2, Subdivision B.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


12
Working Paper: Do not Cite

Take a more complex example: the basic assumption of


income tax law that there is a logical real-world distinction
between capital and revenue is a fiction. There are
innumerable pairs of cases that illustrate the flaws in that
assumption, but I’ll use the classic teacher’s comparison
between Californian Oil Products Ltd v Federal
46
Commissioner of Taxation on one hand and Heavy Minerals
47
Pty Ltd v Federal Commissioner of Taxation on the other. In
both cases, the business of the taxpayer was destroyed. Both
taxpayers received compensation for the loss; but Californian
Oil Products’s compensation was capital and Heavy
Minerals’s compensation was revenue. Heavy Minerals was
the later case; so the court had to distinguish Californian Oil
Products. Windeyer J distinguished the earlier case by
explaining that Californian’s business was destroyed as a
matter of law, whereas Heavy Minerals’s business was
destroyed only as a matter of fact. That analysis is correct
from the point of view of a tax lawyer, but a tax payer could
be forgiven for finding it unpersuasive.
Californian’s problem was that its American principal, the
Union Oil Company, decided not to sell it any more oil,
terminated Californian’s purchasing contract, and paid
compensation. Heavy Minerals’s business was mining and
selling the product, rutile. The company’s difficulty was that
the world price of rutile fell below Heavy Minerals’s cost of
production. The company had protected itself against this
eventuality by forward sales contracts, but its customers
preferred to cancel the contracts and compensate Heavy
Minerals for its loss of profits rather than to buy rutile from
Heavy Minerals and sell it at a loss.
In effect, Sir Victor Windeyer told Heavy Minerals to
brace up and not be so feeble. It was in this case that he
coined his famous apophthegm, “He ain’t heavy, he’s my
mineral”. That’s thought to be a reference to Sir Peter Abeles,
who was one of the principals of Heavy Minerals. His Honour
told Sir Peter that unlike the poor fellows in Californian Oil
Products, who had been eviscerated by the perfidious
Americans, Heavy Minerals still had a good business. No one
was telling Sir Peter not to mine rutile. He should just roll up
his sleeves and get on with it.
As I have explained, Windeyer J’s distinguishing of
Californian Oil Products and his reasoning in Heavy Minerals
were unexceptionable in law. The reason is that the High
Court was not purporting to calculate Heavy Minerals’s tax

46
(1934) 52 CLR 28.
47
(1966) 115 CLR 512.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


13
Working Paper: Do not Cite

liability on the basis of the profit from its actual economic


business, but on the basis of the contracts that were used as
the legal vehicle for that business and on the basis of the
rights and duties that formed the legal context of the business.
Sir Victor was correct that from a legal point of view Heavy
Minerals’s business remained intact, even though nobody
wanted rutile at the price that they had to charge. On the other
hand, Californian Oil Products’s business had depended on a
contractual right to buy products from the Union Oil
Company. Once that right was gone there was no legal basis
for their business.
All that sounds fine when you say it quickly, but it makes a
nonsense of any policy of income tax law. In its most general
sense, the policy of income tax law in respect of businesses
must be to tax real business profits. Profits from economic
activity exist in the natural world, but profits defined by law
are a construction of human thought. Economic profits
constitute the only reality that a government can tax. Using
profits defined by law as the vehicle to do the taxing does not
change the underlying reality, though the result will be to
over-tax or to under-tax in individual cases.
Income tax law achieves its policy of taxing business
profits as best it can by defining a surrogate of business
profits in legal terms. In this respect, income tax law is an
imperfect means to an end, because the definition of business
profits can never be perfectly accurate. In fact, as I have tried
to point out, the definition is often very inaccurate. The true,
economic, business profit, which would be the proper subject
of the tax base if we could ever get at it, is removed from its
legal simulacrum by an ectopia.
Other law is different. For instance, if it chooses, tort law
can redraft itself so as to operate without the fiction of
inviting children to enter premises to play on dangerous
turntables. Indeed, it did so in several Occupiers’ Liability
48
Acts in the 1950s and 1960s. But income tax law cannot
abandon the fiction of a logical and factual boundary between
capital and revenue.
Lon Fuller, the great American jurist of the mid-twentieth
49
century, identified several characteristics of legal fictions.
He said that fictions are like scaffolding. As the law develops
we can abandon them without injuring the policy or vested

48
Eg Occupiers’ Liability Act 1957 (England), Occupiers’ Liability
(Scotland) Act 1960, Occupiers’ Liability Act 1962 (New Zealand).
49
Legal Fictions (Stanford, 1967). I thank Dr Alex Frame of Wellington,
who introduced me to this monograph.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


14
Working Paper: Do not Cite

50
interests that they are designed to sustain. In contrast, it is
my thesis that the fictions of income tax law are an integral
part of the law’s modus operandi. We need fictions because
income tax law is separated from its factual subject matter. It
works only by using fictions that pretend that it is not
separated. Tax law works imperfectly, but it does work. This
is a curious example of two wrongs making a right, or, at
least, of a wrong that hides the true answer being partially
corrected by a second wrong.

Explanatory utility of the ectopia concept


I hope that I have persuaded at least some people here this
evening that I am correct in my conclusion that income tax
law may be law as tax specialists know law, but it is not law
as other people know it. Other people reasonably expect law
to have a close and almost symbiotic relationship with its
subject matter. Tax specialists know that income tax law’s
relationship with its subject matter can be so haphazard that at
times it appears to be almost a matter of random serendipity
when fact, law, and tax consequence coincide.
Ross Parsons identified this phenomenon. He took the
view that it would lead to the demise of income taxation. I am
not sure that he was correct, for reasons that I shall explore in
a minute. But first, let me explain that studying the ectopia of
tax law is not merely an intellectual conceit. The exercise tells
us a good deal about the nature of income tax law, its inherent
limitations, and the limitations on what can be done to reform
it.
I have discussed these matters in a number of articles.
Tonight I shall list their conclusions. First, the ectopia of
income tax law explains why that law is unduly complex.
People think that with good will and conscientious effort
drafters should be able to compose income tax legislation that
is as comprehensible as other legislation. It is true that one
can make improvements, but income tax law will never be as
51
clear as, for example, a criminal code.
Secondly, people think that tax statutes could be simplified
if only they were drafted in broad, principled codes, rather
52
than in numerous, detailed, sub-codes. That thought is

50
Id 70.
51
“Why is tax law incomprehensible?” (1994) British Tax Review 380-
393; “Can income tax law be simplified?” (1996) 2 NZ Journal of
Taxation Law and Policy 187.
52
See, eg, J Avery Jones, “Tax law, rules or principles?” (1996) 17 Fiscal
Studies 63, 75–76.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


15
Working Paper: Do not Cite

53
wrong, too, though again it is true that there can be some
improvements. Nevertheless, because of the problem of
latifundian legislation by principle I suspect Mr Ralph’s
recommendations for a consistent entity regime were doomed
54
from conception; (and I wrote this sentence before I heard
that the consistent entity proposal had died).
Thirdly, although ectopia is present throughout the income
tax system, and is seen everywhere in the distinction between
capital and revenue, there are some areas of law where
ectopia is particularly marked. In these areas, modern tax
systems typically respond with increasingly complex remedial
fictions that are calculated to bring tax law and its subject
matter closer together. The many regimes of international tax
law are the foremost example: increasingly complex rules
about source and residence; transfer pricing; controlled
foreign companies; foreign tax credits; and conduit taxation
55
demonstrate my point.
Fourthly, the ectopia of tax law leads to and, I submit,
justifies, the enactment of open-ended general anti-avoidance

53
“Should tax legislation be written from a principles and purpose point of
view of a precise and detailed point of view?” [1998] British Tax Review
112.
54
Review of Business Taxation, last date viewed 9 July 2001.
www.rbt.treasury.gov.au/publications/paper4/part5/section13.htm.
The Australian Review of Business Taxation under the chairmanship of
Mr John Ralph published several reports in 1999, from J. Ralph
(Chairman of Comm) Review of Business Taxation, First Report, A Strong
Foundation AGPS (1999) to J. Ralph (Chairman of Comm) Review of
Business Taxation, Final Report, A Tax System Redesigned AGPS (1999).
The “consistent entity regime” was a version of that hoary perennial, the
idea that a uniform system of taxation for all business entities, including
companies, trusts, unit trusts, and so on can only be a good thing. A
corollary is that a uniform system does not exist now only because tax
policy has been left to people who cannot see the wood for the trees.
It seems that the Australian government had become exasperated with
the increasing complexity of tax laws that appeared to have resulted from
leaving tax design to tax experts. In a new approach, it intended that the
Ralph review should take a practical, businesslike stance, not unduly
hampered by advice from tax lawyers. As a result, the consistent entity
regime built up a more formidable head of steam than such proposals
usually achieve. Its demise came when eventually it was exposed to expert
scrutiny. What had been reasonably clear to experts from the beginning
became clear also to higher-level policy makers: that notwithstanding its
common-sense, intuitive attractions, the consistent entity regime suffered
from the defects that are endemic to proposals to draft income tax laws on
the basis of broad, logical, principles of wide application.
55
“Philosophical and design problems that arise from the ectopic nature of
income tax law and their impact on the taxation of international trade and
investment”, (1995) 13 Chinese Yearbook of International Law and
Affairs, 111-139, reprinted as “Ectopia, tax law, and international
taxation” [1997] British Tax Review 383.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


16
Working Paper: Do not Cite

rules like Part IVA of the Australian Income Tax Assessment


Act 1936 and section BG 1 of the New Zealand Income Tax
56
Act 1994. The gap between tax law and fact that is the
subject of this lecture means that there are perforce gaps in
the formal coverage of an income tax statute. The statute
needs a general, substance-over-form rule to protect the tax
base.
People often criticise general anti-avoidance rules for their
lack of specificity. They say that the imprecision of anti-
avoidance rules erodes the rule of law. I am not sure that I
agree with that criticism. After all, in the end it is the court,
not the commissioner, that decides whether a general anti-
avoidance rule applies. But even if the criticism is justified,
this characteristic of general anti-avoidance rules is part of the
price we pay for having a tax on income. Income is imprecise;
so the rules that buttress income taxation must share that
imprecision.
This consideration should lead us to reflect on the history
of general anti-avoidance rules. Often, critics demand
specificity. Tax commissioners and occasionally Parliaments
may be sympathetic. They sometimes promulgate guidelines
57
or even enact rules to refine the scope of a general rule. In
principle, that approach is bad practice. The point of a general
anti-avoidance rule is that it should be general. Specificity,
however well intentioned, risks eroding the effectiveness of
the rule.

The tax value method


A fifth consequence of ectopia is that people are forever
trying to reform and improve income tax. That is not
surprising. Ectopia is always with us, it is always causing
problems, and people are always responding.
During 2000 and 2001 Australia has examined proposals
for a major change in the way that it defines income. The new
58
idea has been called the “tax value method”. The conceptual

56
Ectopia, formalism, and anti-avoidance rules in income tax law” (1994)
in W. Krawietz N. MacCormick & G.H. von Wright (eds) Prescriptive
Formality and Normative Rationality in Modern Legal Systems,
Festschrift for Robert S. Summers, Duncker and Humblot, Berlin, 367-
383.
57
See, eg, McBarnett, Doreen and Christopher Wheelan, “The Elusive
Spirit of the Law: Formalism and the Struggle for Legal Control” (1991)
54 Modern Law Review 848, 860 ff; Lehmann, G, “Judicial and Statutory
Restrictions on Tax Avoidance”, in Richard E Krever, (ed) Australian
Taxation, Principles and Practice (Melbourne 1987) 295-313.
58
Review of Business Taxation, last date viewed 9 July 2001.
www.rbt.treasury.gov.au/publications/paper4/part2/section4.htm#heading
1. See also footnote 54, above.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


17
Working Paper: Do not Cite

base is superficially similar to Henry Simons’s definition of


59
income, that is, the increase in the taxpayer’s net assets over
time. A short description of the tax value method is “net cash
flows plus the change in value of assets”.
The tax value method is a compromise between competing
policies. On one hand, there appears to be an endeavour to
bring the concept of income under income tax legislation
closer to true economic measurement. On the other hand,
compliance considerations mandate that calculations are
according to the criteria of accounting rather than of
economics. In particular, the tax value method does not take
account of unrealised gains nor of assets that are very hard to
identify or to value, such as additional market penetration
60
achieved by advertising expenditure. Discussion papers
appear to be careful to eliminate references to law as much as
possible, but no doubt legal concepts will continue to play an
important part. For example, there will be the question of
determining whether there has been a realisation.
I hesitate to make detailed comments about the tax value
method in front of an Australian audience. I would expose my
ignorance very quickly, if I have not already done so. But I
hope by generalisation to put the tax value method into the
analytical framework of this evening’s lecture. First, as Ross
Parsons explained, the fundamental difficulty with income tax
law is to define the concept of income. The tax value method
is an effort to cope with that task. In principle, it should
approach closer to the economic concept of income than the
current judicial concept does, because, in principle,
accounting is more concerned with economic substance than
is law. In practice, concern about compliance costs and
practicalities in general may mean that the tax value concept
of income will not approach much closer to Henry Simons’s
61
economic benchmark than does the existing judicial
concept. Secondly, it seems unlikely to be possible to
eliminate legal concepts entirely. That is, Australian law will
still have to tax a legal simulacrum, not actual economic
activity. Nevertheless, the objective is clearly to minimise the
ectopia between the two. Let us hope that this occurs. Thirdly,
although the tax value method addresses problems of capital
and revenue and of timing in general, it faces the same
problems of source and residence as does the current system,
but it does not claim to mitigate those problems. They will

59
See footnote 6, above.
60
Eg. Commonwealth Treasury and the Australian Taxation Office, The
Tax Value Method Canberra 7 February 2000.
61
See footnote 6, above.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


18
Working Paper: Do not Cite

remain with us. If Australia adopts it, the tax value method
may prove to be an amelioration, but it will not be the last
62
word. I would keep Australia’s general anti-avoidance rule
in the statute in the meantime.

Why does income tax survive?


In his lecture, Parsons predicted the demise of income tax.
Wisely, he did not put a date on his prophecy. He was well
aware that there are a number of factors independent of
income tax itself that make it very difficult for governments to
move to different forms of taxation. He mentioned political
63
difficulties in changing to indirect taxes, though since
Parsons’s time Australia has worked through at least some of
those. More importantly, he pointed out that Australia “cannot
64
go it alone in abolishing [the] income tax”. The reason is
that international fiscal relationships, for the most part
crystallised in double tax treaties, are based on the assumption
that all jurisdictions use income as their primary tax base. It is
not practical for a single country to change to a tax that is
fundamentally different. At least, that is what everyone
assumes. Whether true or not, that widely held assumption
might as well be true.
Parsons was certainly correct about the political and
international problems of switching from income taxation.
Nevertheless, his work conveys the impression that he was
reasonably confident that the demise of income tax was a
medium-term prospect, essentially requiring not a great deal
more than international good will. Was he right?
My estimate is that Parsons was wrong on this point.
Contrary to Professor Parsons, I believe that income tax is
with us indefinitely. Internally, and as an institution, income
tax is terribly flawed. But there are many exogenous factors
that give it indirect support. I’ll try to list them.
First, although the last fifteen years or so have seen modest
reversals of the inexorable growth of the state, it is hard to see
fiscal retrenchment going much further. Certainly, I cannot
foresee any modern state reducing its revenue needs enough
to be able to abandon income tax without replacing it with a
tax of comparable power. If this conclusion is correct, it
would seem that the only real alternative to an income tax is a
65
direct expenditure tax such as that proposed by Kaldor and

62
Income Tax Assessment Act 1936, Cth, subpart IVA.
63
R. Parsons, “Income taxation, an institution in decay”, (1986) 3
Australian Tax Forum 233, 265.
64
Id 266.
65
N. Kaldor, An Expenditure Tax (1955) London, Allen & Unwin.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


19
Working Paper: Do not Cite

66
taken up by the Meade Committee, or some variant of an
expenditure tax. Is the income tax so flawed that governments
will collaborate in the immense international undertaking that
would be necessary to move everyone at once to an
expenditure tax?
People occasionally suggest that an indirect value added
tax is a possible substitute for income taxation, but prospects
are not promising. An inherent problem is that value added
taxes are regressive and require compensating payments to the
low-paid and to beneficiaries. A value added tax that collected
anything like an income tax would require compensating
payments that would reach to middle income levels. Most
modern states regard the fraction of their citizens who are in
receipt of benefits as already too high. People would not
welcome an increase.
A practical problem with value added taxes is that, apart
from New Zealand, no country has managed to enact a value
added tax that is even close to comprehensive. Special interest
groups and people concerned about regressivity typically
combine to force Parliaments to insert all sorts of exemptions.
So long as value added tax rates remain reasonably low an
economy can perhaps tolerate a non-comprehensive value
added tax. But a value added tax that is set at a rate high
enough to replace the typical modern income tax would be
67
very distorting. The conditions that allowed New Zealand to
introduce a comprehensive value added tax in 1985 are not
likely to be duplicated elsewhere. As a result, states are likely
to continue to settle for value added taxes at sub-optimal rates
that operate in partnership with income taxes and not as
replacements for income taxes.
Another problem is the special position of the United
States of America. When we speak of major international tax
reform that most countries will follow we are in effect
speaking of a movement that America would have to lead, or
at least join, but for a number of reasons America may be less
inclined or able to engage in fundamental reform than may
other countries. Tax is a problem for everyone, but because
America has managed to keep its taxes to a lower fraction of
gross domestic product than have other countries tax is not
quite as serious a problem to America as it is to the rest of us.

66
The Structure and Reform of Direct Taxation, (1978) the Report of a
Committee under the Chairmanship of James Meade, Institute for Fiscal
Studies/George Allen & Unwin.
67
Coincidence of: response to a fiscal crisis; steep reduction in income tax
rates; numerous other regulatory reforms; unicameral legislature; single
state; relatively homogeneous population.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


20
Working Paper: Do not Cite

A further factor is that America is a federal country, which


makes tax reform more difficult than for some of us.
Moreover, there is §9(4) of the United States Constitution. It
reads:
No Capitation, or other direct, Tax shall be laid, unless in
Proportion to the Census or Enumeration herein before directed to
be taken.
In 1895, the Supreme Court held in Pollock v Farmers’
68
Loan and Trust Co that §9(4) prohibited Congress from
enacting an income tax. The reasons were that an income tax
is a direct tax and it is not a tax that one can apportion over
the states on a population basis. In 1913, the Sixteenth
Amendment reversed the Farmers’ Loan case with these
words:
The Congress shall have power to lay and collect taxes on
incomes, from whatever source derived, without apportionment
among the several States, and without regard to any census or
enumeration.
On the face of it, §9(4) still prohibits a direct tax on
expenditure as opposed to income, though this prohibition has
not inhibited tax reformers from proposing to replace
conventional income tax with something along the lines of
Kaldor’s suggestions. For instance, in 1995 Senators Nunn,
Kerrey and Domenici sponsored a bill for the “USA” or
69
“unlimited savings allowance”, essentially a Kaldor measure
that would have taxed expenditure only, using a graduated
70
scale. There is also Hall and Rabushka’s “flat tax” proposal,
for a cleverly-modified value added tax that, despite its name,
achieves rate progression at low incomes. The flat tax has
found supporters in the former presidential candidate Steve
71 72
Forbes and Congressman Dick Armey.
American scholars debate whether the Sixteenth
Amendment would authorise these or similar taxes. In a
73
lengthy and thoughtful article, Jensen argues that it would
not, because such taxes are both direct and unapportioned, but
they are not taxes on income. Others reply that they are taxes

68
157 US 429 (1895), 158 US 601 (1895).
69 th
USA Tax Act of 1995, S. 722, 104 Congress.
70
R.E. Hall and A. Rabushka, The Flat Tax (2nd ed 1995) Hoover
Institution Press, Stanford.
71
E. Tollerson, “Bowing Out: Forbes Quits and Offers his Support to
Dole”, New York Times, 15 March 1996, at A26.
72
Freedom and Fairness Restoration Act of 1995, HR 2060 and S. 1050,
104th Congress (sponsored by Representative Armey and Senators Shelby,
Craig, and Helms.
73
E.M. Jensen, “The Apportionment of ‘Direct Taxes’: Are Consumption
Taxes Constitutional?”(1997) 97 Columbia Law Review 2334. The author
is indebted to Jensen’s article for the references in these paragraphs to
discussion on Article 9(4) and the Sixteenth Amendment.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


21
Working Paper: Do not Cite

on income, for such reasons as that people would use their


74
income to pay the taxes. Another argument is that the taxes
may not be taxes on all income, but they are taxes some of it,
75
that is, on the portion of taxpayers’ income that they spend.
One scholar goes so far as to say that the Constitution more or
less leaves it up to the Congress to define what it means by
76
“income”. Even Jensen agrees that it is most unlikely that a
court would strike down a Federal tax on the basis of
77
unconstitutionality. Instead, he implies that conscientious
78
legislators should not enact such taxes.
79
This summary of current American opinion as to the
taxing power of the Congress suggests that constitutional
factors would be likely to constitute no more than a mildly
inhibiting element if it were a matter of enacting an
expenditure tax. Practically speaking, what is more serious is
that proposals for major tax reform seem to make little
progress in the United States. It is hard to think that a
jurisdiction that still hews to the classical system of company
taxation is ready for radical reforms.
A third reason to think that Parsons’s prediction of the
near-imminent demise of income tax will not come to pass is
a question of point of view. Most of us who study income tax
from a legal perspective tend to focus on the taxation of
businesses, because that is the most interesting part of income
tax and that is where most of the problems lie. But we must
not forget that most income tax is paid on wages and salaries
and on passive income, with very little practical difficulty.
Ectopia chiefly affects business income, which produces a
significant but not overwhelming fraction of tax receipts. Are
the problems of taxing business income enough to persuade
the modern state to undertake the upheaval of changing its tax
system?
Fourthly, tax departments have a bad press, so that we tend
to underestimate the very significant advances that they have
made in the last twenty years or so. Increasing use of self-
assessment and increasing computerisation together mean that

74
L. Zelenak, “Radical Tax Reform, the Constitution, and the
Conscientious Legislator”, (1999) Columbia Law Review 833, 851.
75
Id, 847 ff. The text is a perhaps over-simplified paraphrase of Professor
Zelenak’s closely constructed arguments.
76
M.E. Kornhauser, “The Constitutional Meaning of Income and the
Income Taxation of Gifts (1992) 25 Connecticut Law Review 1, 24.
77
Jensen, supra n 59, 2414.
78
Id, 2419.
79
The author thanks Hugh Ault, Professor of Law, Boston College,
Massachusetts, currently of the OECD, Paris, for help with materials on
matters relevant to the United States constitution.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


22
Working Paper: Do not Cite

tax commissioners can undertake more auditing with fewer


resources, thus counteracting some of the shortcomings of the
tax base, at least from the point of view of the state, if not of
the business taxpayer.
Fifthly, the very availability of computers enables tax law
to take measures to minimise at least some of the effects of
ectopia. For instance, the New Zealand financial transactions
rules require taxpayers to calculate income according to yield
80
to maturity formulas. This regime thus brings the relevant
tax law much closer to the economic facts to which it relates.
Practically speaking, that development could not have
occurred without people having computers for the
calculations, or at least programmable calculators.
Finally, may I advance a hypothesis. This hypothesis is
that transitional and political difficulties may mean that it is in
practice impossible to change one major tax for another. At
any rate, no one has done it yet. For this purpose, I am not
sure how I should define a “major tax”: perhaps a tax that
collects more than twenty per cent of gross domestic product.
It is true that countries have managed to change from one
minor tax to another. In 1799 England changed from the
Triple Assessment to the income tax. Australia has just
81
changed from wholesale sales taxes to a value added tax.
But in 1799 neither the Triple Assessment nor the income tax
had anything like the importance that income tax has today;
and by the criterion that I have suggested neither the
Australian wholesale sales taxes nor the new goods and
services tax can be classed as a major tax in the sense in
which I am using the term. In Australia, income tax, the real
workhorse, has kept going in the background.
It may be possible that two potentially major taxes can co-
exist and that Parliament can steadily increase the rate of the
new tax and reduce the rate of the old tax until the old tax is
gone. That might be a theoretical strategy for moving from an
income tax, if there were a suitable candidate to be the new
tax. But a switch from income tax to expenditure tax cannot
be achieved gradually. The two taxes could not apply at the
same time to the same taxpayer. It’s all or nothing. Practically
speaking, “all” may not be a possibility.

Conclusion
The conclusion may be shortly stated. First, Professor Ross
Parsons was correct that income tax law suffers from

80
Income Tax Act 1994, subpart EH.
81
A New Tax System (Goods and Services Tax Imposition – General) Act
1999 (Cth).

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


23
Working Paper: Do not Cite

congenital defects. On the other hand, he was wrong in his


opinion that these defects came from adopting as its core
element the concept of income of trust law. True, the idea of
income is the same in both branches of the law, but that is
because the Australian/United Kingdom common law has but
a single concept of income.
Thirdly, the source of the concept of income is in a sense
not relevant, in that inherent in any income tax is a concept of
income that cannot avoid being flawed. The reason is that,
unlike most law, tax law cannot avoid being separated from
its factual subject.
Fourthly, the separation, or ectopia, from which income tax
law suffers has as one of its symptoms a number of concepts
that are similar to legal fictions, but that are more
fundamental to the law than are legal fictions as ordinarily
understood.
Fifthly, the ectopia of income tax law offers an explanation
for a number of the more puzzling aspects of this branch of
the law, including its complexity and its incoherence. These
same factors may justify states in adopting general, open-
ended anti-avoidance rules, despite the erosion of the rule of
law that seems characteristic of such rules.
Bearing these factors in mind, it is unsurprising that
Professor Parsons was pessimistic about the future of income
tax law and foresaw its demise. Nevertheless, Parsons may
have given insufficient weight to exogenous factors. Even
more pessimistically, we may predict that these factors will
preserve income tax and that it will continue. Our pessimism
may be tempered by the thought that however imperfect
income tax is as a measure to gather revenue, as a subject of
study it has never ending fascination.

Parsons Lect Working Paper 2


24

You might also like