A Sociology of Crime
A Sociology of Crime
A Sociology of Crime
Typeset in Bembo
by Keystroke, Neville Lodge, Tettenhall, Wolverhampton
For Sociology
Contents
1 Sociology 1
PART I
Positively undertaken 39
Introduction 41
2 State 46
3 Society 84
PART II
Interpretatively turned 113
Introduction 115
4 Claims-making 124
vii
CONTENTS
PART III
Politically challenged 239
Introduction 241
7 Class 247
8 Gender 316
9 Race 353
PART IV
Epistemically undermined 389
Introduction 391
10 Power 397
11 People? 433
12 Conclusion 473
References 480
Index 554
viii
Figures and
boxes
Figures
1.1 Members of the public admitting to lawbreaking 5
1.2 Creating crime and criminals 34
5.1 Four types of deviant behaviour 190
8.1 Data appendix 342–3
Boxes
1 Philosophical tributaries of the interpretative turn 120
2 One criminologist’s theoretical journey 155
3 Two-set classes or two-class sets 245
4 Marx and Engels on “globalization” 248
5 Reiman on Marx’s analysis of criminalization in capitalist society 249
6 Capitalism as a totalizing process 256
7 A note on structural Marxism 259
8 Matoesian on “detailing-to-death” in a rape trial 346
9 Chambliss on race and the War on Drugs 365
10 “The accumulated evil of the whole”: Afghanistan 2001–2016 436
11 Politics or crime? 445
12 When Canada used hunger to clear the West 456
13 Canadian government withheld food from hungry aboriginal
kids in 1940s nutritional experiments, researcher finds 458
ix
Preface
xi
PREFACE
xii
PREFACE
xiii
PREFACE
xiv
PREFACE
xv
1 Sociology
MEAT IS MURDER
Introduction
It doesn’t matter where we start, so let’s jump right in. Crime is
readily at hand. Check the news feed on your cell phone. What
crime stories are being reported there? On New Year’s Eve 2015, the
Flipboard daily edition had the following headlines, among others:
“Security Raised at New Year Celebrations Amid World Terror
Fears”;“Ramadi residents fleeing ISIS:‘They want to use us as human
shields’”;“TCU QB Boykin charged with felony assault, suspended”;
“Bill Cosby Accuser Beth Ferrier on His Arrest for Decade-Old
Alleged [Sexual Assault].” In August 2016, Canadian supermarket
checkout stands announced “Canada’s New Crime Wave” on the
front page of Maclean’s (“Canada’s National Magazine”). In the last
days of the 2015 Canadian federal election campaign, as this writ-
ing was under way, the national news spoke of radio and print ads
put out by Prime Minister Stephen Harper’s Conservatives targeting
Justin Trudeau’s Liberals, saying that the latter would, if successful in
winning the election, make marijuana available for sale to children
and would bring prostitution in the form of brothels to residential
neighbourhoods.1 The ads were being released in areas of the country
with large South Asian populations.
The early part of the election campaign was dominated by the trial
of Mike Duffy, a Harper-appointed senator, former journalist and
Canadian national media celebrity who, in July 2014, was charged
with 31 offences including bribery, and fraud and breach of trust in
1
1: SOCIOLOGY
2
1: SOCIOLOGY
face to the last African American shot dead by a white police officer
in the land of the free; US police killed 1,126 people in 2015, killing
blacks at twice the rate as whites.7 You know how to call the police,
and may well have seen the inside of your local courthouse.You are
familiar with the uniformed security officers you see everywhere,
who look like police and have quasi-police powers, not to mention
the security cameras at every turn. Where you live may be a “neigh-
bourhood watch” community, and you may have received a recorded
phone message informing you of some local crime concern.You lock
your doors at night.You will recognize police cars and police officers
(on foot, on bikes, on horses, on motorcycles) when you see them
on the streets and highways you frequent, or at televised funerals for
“fallen officers,” at memorial parades and ceremonial events or dur-
ing seasonal roadside “blitzes” for drinking and driving.You may have
been kettled (contained) by them at a protest or demonstration.You
may recall the visit of a police officer to your school or your child’s
school. You will probably have an opinion about the desirability of
capital punishment, the criminalization of abortion, the legalization
of marijuana (see also Potter and Kappeler 1998: vi). You may have
strong feelings about terrorism, violent crime, “pedophiles,” gangs,
the War on Drugs, cyberstalking, solitary confinement, drinking
and driving, sexual assault, criminals who “get off easy,” mandatory
minimum sentences, whether “Black Lives Matter,” home invasions,
Oscar Pistorius.8 These feelings may have been stoked by the election
platform of one or other of the political parties vying for your vote
recently. The notice board in the shop where you bought coffee this
morning may have sported a poster like this one advertising a play:
“Hard Boiled: A Sal Dali Crime Tale.” Or, on the surface of the paved
trail where you run each day, there may look back at you in stark,
hard-to-remove capital letters the slogan, “MEAT IS MURDER.”
Moreover, you yourself may have been the victim of crime. Your
house or car may have been broken into, your purse snatched, your
corner store held up, your local bank robbed, your credit card or other
form of identity stolen, your property vandalized, your person assaulted,
your village or town destroyed. If it hasn’t happened to you, you will
probably know of a relative, friend, neighbour or local resident who has
been victimized by such an act, or you will have seen it on the news.
Such an experience may, in fact, have prompted you to be inter-
ested in crime, interested enough to have picked up or uploaded
3
1: SOCIOLOGY
4
1: SOCIOLOGY
5
1: SOCIOLOGY
(although more than a few of you certainly have), let alone been
charged, tried, convicted or sentenced for such an offence, so that
it may be said of you that you got away with it. The label was never
applied. “Getting away with” crime is very much part of the crime
landscape. Indeed, the fact that crime may be got away with means
that it is not a naturally self-revealing thing. It must be shown to be
such.While we are inclined to think that an action in itself is or is not
criminal, we are prepared to allow that it must be identified, observed,
apprehended or detected as such; such that if that labelling does not
occur in any particular instance, we do not become “criminal” in
any socially meaningful sense. So, although we may retain the sense
that our action was, indeed, a criminal one, and that we did indeed
get away with it, it does not follow that we think of ourselves as
criminals. So there are crimes and there are criminals. The two do
not necessarily equate.
We know, too, that for an action to be found to be a crime, in the
end it must be shown to have been committed with criminal intent
(although there are exceptions like drinking and driving). The gun
could have gone off accidentally, the child could have been too young
to appreciate the gravity of the act, the adult may not have been
criminally responsible by virtue of mental illness, mental handicap
or having been forced. The act could have been in self-defence. The
homicide may have been justifiable if carried out by, say, a uniformed
soldier in combat. Accusations can be false, identities mistaken, evi-
dence tainted, witnesses hostile, charges withdrawn, sentences can be
inadequate or excessive, convictions wrongful. Crime, in short, is a
contested category, and we know it.
Whether you are interested in crime or not, you know that many
people in society cannot help but be “interested” in it as it is their job
to engage with it on a daily basis. A considerable range of occupa-
tions deals with crime, from police to Supreme Court Justices, from
legal secretaries to crime scene investigators, from narcotics divi-
sions to war crimes units, from crime beat reporters to prison guards,
from academic criminologists to Ministry of the Attorney-General
researchers and so on. Some types of crime are engaged in by some
people on a more or less occupational basis like drug trafficking and
drug dealing, armed robbery, safe cracking, shoplifting, contract kill-
ing, burglary, living off the avails of prostitution, human trafficking,
assassination of official enemies, state terrorism, accounting fraud,
6
1: SOCIOLOGY
bribery of officials and so on. See, for example, The New Confessions
of an Economic Hit Man by John Perkins (2016) or “The bribe
factory” (2016).9
Crimes, then, have perpetrators or offenders, the ones who com-
mit the offence, and victims, the ones who suffer the loss attending
the offence. We allow, though, that some crimes may be thought of
as “victimless,” as the only one harmed, if anyone, appears to be the
offender him- or herself. And some may acquire the status of what
Joseph Gusfield, referring to drinking and driving, calls “moral fault
without censure”: “at the level of public attention there is the persis-
tent and shrill cry for more punishment; at the level of daily events
there is the negotiation between lawbreakers and law enforcers and
the continued existence of prohibited acts” (Gusfield 1981: 132).
Taking this a step further, Eglin will never forget regularly witness-
ing a posse of Mexican police standing waiting to go on (or come
off) shift, quite oblivious to cars driving past them using the off ramp
to drive on to the periferico (a major highway) at the Plateros exit
in Mexico City; or another group of such police quite openly and
nonchalantly guarding an illegal casino set up in the middle of the
Cuernavaca Fair in 2004 (Cuevas Villalobos 2004).
Nevertheless, crimes, we say, are wrongs. They are not morally
neutral. When such acts occur, they are not mere matters of interest
but, depending on their nature and gravity, they elicit moral condem-
nation, not only from their victims but from society generally. They
demand redress, we say, in the form of punishment of the offender or
restoration of the victim’s loss or both. And we have institutions spe-
cifically designed to provide those remedies.That “loss” can be in the
form of terrible physical or emotional damage suffered by the victim,
which may last for years in the form of post-traumatic stress disorder
(PTSD). The offence caused by the crime to the integrity of the
victim’s person can be extended to their home or other possessions,
to their family and friends. A “wave” of offences in a particular area
may occasion a crime scare in the form of fear among local residents
and demands for greater enforcement of the law in order to restore
(a sense of) public safety (Fishman 1978: 531). Criminal offences have
the capacity to stir moral outrage throughout a community, whether
locally, regionally, nationally or, indeed, internationally.We know this
to be true of the 2011 “Norway attacks” by Anders Breivik in which
he shot dead 69 participants of a Workers’ Youth League summer camp
7
1: SOCIOLOGY
8
1: SOCIOLOGY
9
1: SOCIOLOGY
10
1: SOCIOLOGY
crime is, what it can mean for us, how we should act towards it, is
given for us in the language and mores of everyday life. Though the
course for which you are (most probably) reading this book may not
be the first course in sociology that you have taken, the ready recog-
nizability of what you have read so far has in no way depended on
such formal studies. That crime involves offenders and victims, types
of offence and offender, the criminal law, police, courts and correc-
tions is something so obviously the case as possibly to raise in your
mind the question as to why the authors are bothering. What is the
point of telling us what we already know? When are we going to get
to the meat(!), you may well be asking.
In fact, it is wholly typical of standard works in sociology, includ-
ing innumerable introductory textbooks, to use at the beginning of
them a variant version of the way this book’s subject is being intro-
duced. The opening strategy is to present such members’ knowledge
in the form of factual propositions about the subject in question
(knowledge that), to characterize this knowledge as “commonsense
knowledge,” what everyone thinks they know about crime, and then
to contrast it with the “scientific” knowledge of the subject that the
writer, the professional sociologist, is about to impart – what is really
going on (see contributions by Sacks, and Garfinkel, in Hill and
Crittenden 1968: 12–17; Lynch and Bogen 1994: 70; Hutchinson
et al. 2008: 19). “Virtually canonical in these preliminary discussions
is a list of statements describing how sociological knowledge dif-
fers from commonsense belief ” (Lynch and Bogen 1997: 486). For
example, it may be asserted that whereas people commonly think that
assaults are typically carried out in public, at night, by strangers, the
truth is that they mostly occur in private, during the day, by a person
the victim knows. Walter DeKeseredy begins his book on Women,
Crime and the Canadian Criminal Justice System like this:
One does not have to read this book or others like it to discover
that many Canadians see their country as being riddled with preda-
tory violent women and girls. This is largely because on any given
day, newspapers and television stations typically present at least one
sensational story about a terrifying, albeit statistically insignificant,
crime committed by a female, such as Karla Homolka.You will also
often hear some journalists, conservative politicians, and many male
members of the general public contend,“But women do it too!” . . .
11
1: SOCIOLOGY
12
1: SOCIOLOGY
research – of the professional social scientist that can reveal the order
in the mess of observable particulars. Again, referring to introductory
textbooks, Lynch and Bogen (1997) write:
13
1: SOCIOLOGY
reality” (Schutz 1962b [1953]: 21, quoted in Kim and Berard 2009:
271). Or, in its classical formulation:
14
1: SOCIOLOGY
15
1: SOCIOLOGY
16
1: SOCIOLOGY
the witnessed scene is just what it appears to be (and not the set of a
film or play) and so on. Notice, too, that the phrase “waiting for the
bus” is both a description and explanation of the action in question;
the people involved are seen to be waiting, and why they are wait-
ing is because they want to get on the bus (which will take them
to where they are going; in other words, we take it that they have a
destination). To attribute such social identities to people and to see
them as engaged in actions for a reason or purpose is to “socialize”
the scene, to make it social, to do a sociology on it. For a clear and
cogent analysis of “aspects of members’ ethnographic work in making
[their] setting observable and reportable” (Sharrock and Turner 1980:
29) see the analysis by these authors of the way a caller to the police
describes the parked automobile that is the object and subject of her
concern.
And, notice also, we see such things at a glance, without the need
for an interview. That is to say, in the world of everyday life, one, as
it were, takes up the work of being a member of society and sees,
and acts towards, the world accordingly. Others are seen, according
to such things as the (social) time and place of their being encoun-
tered, as workers, shoppers, students, beggars, business people, tourists,
etc. That is, allowing for a “restricted class” of categories that are
“routinely ‘emblematically assignable,’ or ‘perceptually recordable’
at a glance” such as police officers, “nuns, hospital physicians,” etc.
(Coulter 2001: 37; see also Jayyusi 1984: 68–73), people don’t just
appear before us bearing a label with their category identity stamped
upon it in large lettering.We see who they are by such things as when
and where we encounter them and what activities they are engaged
in (Eglin 1980).Thus, persons observable as “taking in the sights” can
be seen as “tourists.” By virtue of the time of day, persons observable
as “finishing up the job” or “driving home from work” may be seen as
“workers.” Because of their institutional location, persons observable
as “on their way to or from class” may be seen as “students.”
And if you are inclined to say, “Well, what’s the big deal, that’s
just who they are, and that’s just what they are doing,” then it needs
to be said that while the people and actions concerned may very
well be describable in terms of those categories – that is, while such
descriptions may be perfectly correct – it is also the case that they
can be described as children (all of them), as males, females and oth-
ers, as persons of tall, medium and short height, and, mutatis mutandis,
17
1: SOCIOLOGY
18
1: SOCIOLOGY
terms (offender and victims), gendered terms (man and women) and
political terms (anti-feminist terrorist and feminists).These categori-
zations provided the resources out of which disputes were constructed
about what the “Montreal Massacre” amounted to as social action,
for participants, for news reporters, for media commentators and for
subsequent academic, professional sociological analysis. That is, the
language of description – in this case, the categories and descriptors
used to refer to the people and actions concerned – provided for
what could be intelligibly said about them. This included that what
he had done could be seen as a terrible crime.
19
1: SOCIOLOGY
Together these ideas entail the view, as stated above, that the ordinary,
everyday life we live with and among others is not just “social” in
character, but fundamentally sociological.That is, sociology is not simply
the name of the specialized conceptual and methodological apparatus
brought to the analysis of social life by professional practitioners of
an academic discipline called sociology, but is a collection of such
practices that all members of society engage in as a condition of living
everyday life. “The study of common sense knowledge and common
sense activities consists of treating as problematic phenomena the
actual methods whereby members of society, doing sociology, lay or
professional, make the social structures of everyday activities observ-
able” (Garfinkel 1967: 75). By “everyday life” or “everyday activities”
20
1: SOCIOLOGY
is meant all of social life lived under the auspices of what phenom-
enologists call the “natural attitude” or the “attitude of everyday life,”
whether in everyday or specialized settings. Moreover, professional
sociology is underpinned by this lay sociology.
This approach entails the view that, far from being deficient in
terms of professional sociology’s formal theoretical schemes for
explaining social action, persons’ actions can routinely be seen to be
intelligible in terms of the practical circumstances with which they
engage. Furthermore, insofar as “language is understood as practical
action” (Lynch 2014: 112, note 19) then, “following Wittgenstein,
persons’ actual usages are rational usages in some ‘language game.’
What is their game?” (Garfinkel 1967: 70, emphasis in original).
Garfinkel might have better said, “What is that game?” Because “a
language-game is any array of human activities within which the
use of language is embedded,” then no language game is “anyone’s
singular ‘possession’” (Coulter 2016: 2).
21
1: SOCIOLOGY
22
1: SOCIOLOGY
them as such reports rests upon our unnoticed use of certain sense-
making methods or interpretative procedures. Such methods are
the focus of ethnomethodology. Since most of us encounter crime
most commonly in the form of media depictions of it, and since
much is made in professional sociology about the news media’s “con-
struction” of crime through their reporting and commentary on it,
it is fitting perhaps to begin the book by showing how our pre-
ferred approach treats the subject in its “media-ted” manifestation.
We shall use the following case of a newspaper headline to bring
out how its reading depends on some general methods of sense-
making available to any competent members of society picking up a
newspaper.
Our original analysis of this headline in the first edition of this book
(Hester and Eglin 1992: 119–128) was revised and expanded by
Francis and Hester in An Invitation to Ethnomethodology (2004: 37–44)
as an example of that mode of ethnomethodological analysis they call
self-reflection. The analysis presented here is a summary version of
their revision of our original. Such an analysis requires taking three
methodological steps (Francis and Hester 2004: 25–26):
1. Notice something that is observably-the-case about some talk,
activity or setting.
2. Pose the question: “How is it that this observable feature has been
produced, such that it is recognizable for what it is?”
3. Consider, analyze and describe the methods used in the produc-
tion and recognition of the observable feature.
Step 1: imagine you see this headline on the front page of the news-
paper. What do you take it to be saying in the quite ordinary way
that you read a newspaper? We take it, and we take it that you take
it, to mean that a mother killed her child (most probably a baby or
young infant) and as a result, was arrested and charged by the police.
Notice that the headline doesn’t say this in so many words and, if you
stretch your imagination, you can think up other possible meanings.
So, let us spell out what our “obvious” reading consists of (and what
it doesn’t) (Francis and Hester 2004: 38):
1. that the mother is the mother of the dead child (and is not
someone else’s mother);
23
1: SOCIOLOGY
2. that the mother was charged by the police (and not [by] someone
or something else);
3. that the child was killed by its mother (and not by someone else).
Step 2: how do we come up with this reading? What methods of
practical reasoning, involving what commonsense knowledge of the
social structures, have gone into both the production and recognition
of this story in this headline? How do we see that this, after all, is a
crime story, that it’s about a crime?
Step 3: the general answer that professional MCA gives is that to
do so, we, as ordinary members of society reading the newspaper,
engage in membership categorization analysis ourselves. In other
words, MCA has two senses. It refers both to lay “members’ methods
of sociological inquiry” and to the form of analysis that professional
ethnomethodologists carry out on the MCA carried out by lay mem-
bers of society. Of what does members’ MCA consist in the case of
this headline? To answer this question, we shall employ the concep-
tual framework of professional MCA bequeathed to us by Harvey
Sacks (1967, 1972a, 1972b, 1992a, 1992b), and practitioners influ-
enced by his work, chiefly Watson (1976, 1978, 1983), Payne (1976),
Jayyusi (1984) and others (Eglin and Hester 1992, 2003; Hester and
Eglin 1997).
“Membership categories” are classifications or social types used to
describe persons. Examples include “mother,”“father,”“son,”“daugh-
ter,” “hockey player,” “hell’s angel,” “musician,” “scholar,” “lunatic,”
“bore,” etc. Our knowledge of the world is informed by such cat-
egories: “they provide a means for us to make sense of the social
world” (Francis and Hester 2004: 39). We will introduce the other
terms as we work through an abbreviated account of the analysis of
our reading of the headline. For a full analysis, readers should turn to
Francis and Hester’s account.
24
1: SOCIOLOGY
To say that such pairs are standardized means that it is known what
the typical rights, obligation, activities, attributes and so forth are of
the one part with respect to the other . . . Furthermore, mention
of one part of such a pair is to imply the other – to have the other
programmatically present.
(Francis and Hester 2004: 40)
25
1: SOCIOLOGY
that we take it that the mother and child in the headline are mother
and child to each other.
A second observation is that the headline does not say that the
mother was charged by the “police,” but we read it that way. This
is because of our “orientation to category predicates.” Sacks speaks,
in particular, about “category-bound activities.” These are activities
(or, perhaps better, actions) that are expectably and properly done by
persons who are the incumbents of particular categories, when those
categories are drawn from certain collections or MCDs. Subsequent
researchers have extended Sacks’s work in this area. Sharrock (1974),
Payne (1976),Watson (1978, 1983), Jayyusi (1984) and Hester (1992),
for example, have all observed that category-bound activities are
just one class of predicates which “can conventionally be imputed
on the basis of a given membership category” (Watson 1978: 106).
Other predicates include rights, expectations, obligations, knowledge,
attributes and competences. Thus, “charging” is an activity bound
to or predicated of such a membership category. When we read of
“charging,” there are, hypothetically at least, several possibilities.
26
1: SOCIOLOGY
If we have taken it that the mother is the mother of the dead child, and
that the mother has been charged by the police, then “it seems reason-
able that it is she who has killed her child, rather than some unnamed
category of person. This is so because the police . . . charge people
because they have committed offences” (Francis and Hester 2004:
42). Sacks provides a formal way of linking police and offender, and
charging and offending.Thus, in the making sense of any description,
we make use of the principle of “co-selection”:
Speakers and hearers, then, assume that words are consistently co-
selected (something postmodernists do not appear to have grasped;
see Part IV of this book). This means that it is taken for granted
that words are not chosen randomly or incoherently, but instead are
selected because they cohere and are consistent with each other.They
are designed to “go together” as selections which inform or mutu-
ally elaborate the meaning of each other. In terms of the consistency
27
1: SOCIOLOGY
28
1: SOCIOLOGY
[A] car pulls up and stops. It doesn’t seem to stop anywhere spe-
cial, just pulls up and stops on a street. The door opens and a girl
of about 18 charges out, runs across a lawn and stops, and starts
shrieking. In the front seat are an older man and woman. The guy
jumps out of the car, charges across the lawn, comes up to the girl
and gives her a smack right in the face. At which point some of
the passing cars slam on their brakes, and some people start getting
out of their cars.
The man and the girl stand there, face to face, screaming at each
other, and then he just grabs her and drags her back to the car. And
people look at each other, shrug, and say, “Oh well,” get back in
their cars and go on their way.
(Sacks 1989: 344)
29
1: SOCIOLOGY
Synopsis
Each successive chapter of the book after this one presents a particular
sociological perspective’s theoretical take on crime. The selection of
chapters is informed by, without precisely following, that to be found
in the outstanding introduction to sociology; namely, Perspectives in
Sociology (sixth edition, 2016) by Cuff et al.The sequence of chapters
attempts to reflect both the rough chronological order in which the
perspectives appeared on the sociological scene, the epistemological
and methodological eruptions along the way, and the way in which
30
1: SOCIOLOGY
31
1: SOCIOLOGY
32
1: SOCIOLOGY
33
1: SOCIOLOGY
34
1: SOCIOLOGY
Conclusion
It is important, finally, to appreciate what may and may not be
expected from a textbook such as this. Crime can certainly be
regarded as a voluminous subject.The library shelves, whether actual
or virtual, are filled with works about it. According to the biblical
story at least – “And hasn’t the Tree of Sin been at the same time
the Tree of Knowledge ever since the time of Adam?” (Marx 1861–
1863: n. p.) – crime appeared at the dawn of humanity’s creation, and
we have every reason to suppose that it will play a part in its end.
From Fyodor Dostoyevsky to The Godfather, from Elmore Leonard to
the latest caper movie, it is a source of the profoundest reflection, the
most grievous suffering and the lightest entertainment. What this
book offers is what professional sociology has to say about it, seen in
the light of members’ methods of sociological inquiry. In short, this
amounts to far less than everything that could be said about crime,
but it is grounded in what can be said about crime. For crime is a
word, in a language, expressing a concept that has its home in social
action and interaction. Before anything else, then, it is a sociological
thing.
35
1: SOCIOLOGY
Exercises
1. Start a fieldwork notebook in either paper or digital form that you
will keep throughout your course of study with this book. Call it
something like “My Encounters with Crime.”To begin with, pick
a day and very deliberately record every instance in which crime
comes up over its course. Re-read the introduction to this chapter
to remind yourself of what to be on the lookout for – from deci-
sions you make about preferred routes to take wherever you are
going, to other matters of personal security, to conversations about
crime, to seeing police cars, warning signs and the like, to news
items you view, etc., etc. Pay attention to detail. Keep the notebook
going with such observations throughout your course of studies.
2. Devote a special section of the notebook to making a list of all the
crimes you have committed. Make a note about how you think of
yourself in relation to them.
3. Using the chapter’s analysis of “Mother charged in death of child,”
collect a news headline about crime and attempt to analyze the
methods of membership categorization involved in your reading
of it. You will find it more fruitful to deal with a mundane case
from the inside pages of your local newspaper rather than a more
sensational case from the front page.
Review questions
1. What do you understand by the idea of the “conceptual landscape”
of crime? Can you add additional landmarks to the map sketched
in the chapter?
2. What is meant by “members’ methods of sociological inquiry”?
3. What are the differences between “lay” and “professional”
sociology?
4. Who’s a sociologist?
Further reading
Francis, David and Stephen Hester. 2004. An Invitation to
Ethnomethodology: Language, Society and Social Interaction. London:
Sage. Chapters 1–3 set out the ethnomethodological position
adopted herein, in accessible terms, and with many helpful exam-
ples such as the full analysis of “Mother charged in death of child.”
36
1: SOCIOLOGY
Notes
1 CBC News, “Conservative ads aimed at Chinese, Punjabi voters claim
Trudeau backs brothels, pot sales to kids,” 14 October 2015: www.cbc.
ca/news/canada/british-columbia/conservative-advertising-chinese-
punjabi-1.3268011 (Accessed 14 October 2015).
2 Duffy was acquitted of all charges on 21 April 2016.
3 The inquiry was officially launched on 3 August 2016 by the Liberal
government, with work beginning on 1 September 2016.
4 Ford died from cancer on 22 March 2016 at the age of 46.
5 CBC News, “Dennis Oland murder trial hears officer urged to lie
about crime scene,” 14 October 2015: www.cbc.ca/news/canada/new-
brunswick/oland-murder-trial-saint-john-1.3268364 (Accessed 14
October 2015). On 24 October 2016, Oland’s conviction was over-
turned on appeal and a new trial ordered.
6 Marisa Taylor and Jonathan S. Landay,“Psychologists accused of ‘criminal
enterprise’ with CIA over torture,” truthout.org, 14 October 2015: www.
truth-out.org/news/item/33227-psychologists-accused-of-criminal-
enterprise-with-cia-over-torture (Accessed 14 October 2015).
7 “The counted,” The Guardian: www.theguardian.com/us-news/series/
counted-us-police-killings (Accessed 20 August 2016); Mark Berman and
Mark Guarino, “Chicago releases ‘unprecedented’ evidence from nearly
100 investigations into police shootings, uses of force,” The Washington
Post, 3 June 2016: www.washingtonpost.com/news/post-nation/
wp/2016/06/03/chicago-set-to-release-massive-trove-of-evidence-
from-100-investigations-into-police-shootings-alleged-misconduct/
(Accessed 4 June 2016).
8 GeoffreyYork,“Oscar Pistorius found guilty of murdering girlfriend,” The
Globe and Mail, 3 December 2015: www.theglobeandmail.com/news/
world/south-africas-supreme-court-convicts-pistorius-of-murder/
article27576426/?utm_medium=Newsletter&utm_source=Morning+
News+Update&utm_type=text&utm_content=MorningNewsUpdate
&utm_campaign=131730108 (Accessed 4 December 2015).
37
1: SOCIOLOGY
9 “The bribe factory,” The Melbourne Age and The Huffington Post, 30
March 2016: www.theage.com.au/interactive/2016/the-bribe-factory/
(Accessed 31 March 2016).
10 Thanks are due to Dr Jeffrey Aguinaldo for this reminder.
38
PART I
Positively
undertaken
Introduction
Positivistic sociology
The desire to “help people,” to “make the world a better place” or
to “change the world” expressed by many undergraduate students
of sociology (Berger 1963: 1–3) would have been understood by
the founders and followers of the European Enlightenment from
the seventeenth century onwards. They sought to remake the world
they had inherited by breaking the fetters of superstition, religion
and rule by monarchs and aristocrats, in the name of liberty, equality
and fraternity (the slogan of the French Revolution of 1789), and
democracy and human rights (as in the US Bill of Rights of 1789).
If social improvement was their goal, reason and scientific method
were their means.“Enlightenment’s program was the disenchantment
of the world” (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002: 1, channelling Max
Weber).When applied to social thought and analysis, this coupling of
scientific reason and social improvement gave rise to the “positivistic
41
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
42
INTRODUCTION
Crime
An overriding concern to “do something about crime” shaped the
social sciences’ attitude towards it from the outset and throughout
their inquiries.This concern was founded in an anxiety about the state
of civil society that arose in the wake of the Industrial Revolution
and “the dissolution of the traditional social order” (Giddens 1971:
37). “Positivistic” social science in general and criminology in par-
ticular were conceived against the background of this anxiety about
the perceived “evil consequences” of industrialization. For example,
what came to be known as “juvenile delinquency” was problematic
because it was taken as portending the greater evil of adult crime,
and that, in turn, was seen to threaten the very fabric of civil society
with the prospect of anarchy (Houston 1972). The development of
scientific inquiry into these phenomena was explicitly conceived as
directed towards their amelioration or correction (and thus to the
relief of this anxiety). In alternative words also attributed to Comte,
“savoir pour prévoir, prévoir pour prévenir.” Lukes has this to say
about Comte’s most famous follower:
43
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
Conclusion
As in the case of the other “social sciences,” professional sociology’s
emergence as a university-based discipline in the 1890s in Europe
and the United States depended in large part on its early practitioners
being able to demonstrate that they had a distinct subject matter that
could be addressed scientifically. Durkheim subtitled his 1897 book
on suicide “a study in sociology,” thereby marking the distinctiveness of
this scientific approach to the subject he had set out two years before
in his Rules of Sociological Method. Thus grew up an approach to the
44
INTRODUCTION
45
2 State
46
2: STATE
47
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
48
2: STATE
49
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
“crimes known to the police” with figures derived from the public
itself, through what are known as “self-report” and/or “victimiza-
tion” surveys. That is, a sample of the population is asked to report
what, if any, offences they have committed; or of what, if any, crimes
they have been victim. Eglin’s informal surveys of his students’ crimi-
nality, noted in Chapter 1, are examples of such self-report studies.
The results of such surveys are seen to provide useful correctives
for the perceived deficiencies of official statistics that are based on
“crimes known to the police.” For many years, it has been standard
practice for state agencies dedicated to the collection, production
and dissemination of official crime statistics, such as the Canadian
Centre for Justice Statistics (CCJS) of Statistics Canada, to accompany
their detailed statistical reports (consisting mainly of pages of tables)
with an elaborate foreword or appendix discussing the reliability and
validity of the data reported in the tables.2
The annual issuing of the crime figures becomes the occasion
for widespread reporting in the news media. Attempts are routinely
made to read social significance into (that is, to do a sociology of)
the rise and fall of the figures, whether as a whole or in terms of
such categories as youth crime, violent crime, hate crime, cyber-
crime, drug offences or family violence, among others. Commentary
is sought from, or questions put to, local, regional and national politi-
cians, academic social scientists, spokespersons for the police, groups
advocating for the rights of women, racial or ethnic minorities, gun
control advocates, victims of crime generally and so on. Word may
spread on social media. Longer articles will appear on blogs and in
national news magazines. Academics will incorporate the latest data
into ongoing research projects and the papers that flow from them
that will, in turn, be presented at conferences which may themselves
make the news in a subsequent cycle. Such work will be taken up for
inclusion in the latest edition of some textbook or handbook in the
relevant discipline (Smith 1975). Student readers of this book may
wish to consult the websites of their state’s statistical agency to gain
an appreciation of what may be called, facetiously, modern society’s
crime production industry.3 In such ways do the administrative activi-
ties of the state bleed into the capillaries of the society that it seeks
to govern.
The point here, however, is simply to notice that for modern
societies, crime is an “official” matter. To say this is to repeat what
50
2: STATE
has been the ongoing theme of this discussion; namely, that crime
is a concept defined, administered and enforced by the state and its
agencies. Crime as the official, state-sanctified thing that it is in state
societies is produced out of the activities of government and public
administration. If the modern state is thought of as consisting of three
branches – legislative (through a parliament or congress), executive (a
prime minister, cabinet and civil service) and judicial (the legal system
including a supreme court) – then crime is defined by the legisla-
tive branch and administered and enforced by both the executive
and judicial branches. To say as much may be to simplify somewhat
varying arrangements across different societies, but it is not to adopt
any theory of state or society. It is enough to say that the state’s inter-
est is in administering its population. In the grammar section of this
chapter, we shall argue that this fact is too little taken account of in
the debate over the meaning and use of official crime statistics.
Correctional criminology
The greater part of the scientific study of crime is taken up by cor-
rectionally motivated, positivistically researched theories of so-called
criminal behaviour.We say “so-called” for reasons explained below. In
fact, for most, if not all, correctional criminologists, such work is what
defines criminology (see, for example, Wilson and Herrnstein 1986).
Following Matza (2010 [1969]), we identify the central components
of correctional criminology as follows:
1. the equivalence of social and sociological problems;
2. the derivation of sociological questions from social concerns;
3. the objective of sociological inquiry as the amelioration or
“correction” of social problems;
4. an “overwhelming” preoccupation with questions of aetiology or
causation in relation to criminal behaviour;
5. a commitment to the methodological principles of positivistic
social science.
Thus the standard steps in an investigation of some crime topic are
modelled on those to be found in a thousand sociological research
methods textbooks: define it, classify it, count it, correlate it, explain
it and prevent/cure/treat it. Bottomley notes the paradoxical com-
bination of the desire to be “scientific” and adhere to the ideals of
“scientific objectivity” while providing “theories which would at
51
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
Then there is Young (1986: 28, quoted in Sim et al. 1987: 42; and
Smart 1990: 72): “Let us state quite categorically that the major task
of radical criminology is to seek a solution to the problem of crime
and that of a socialist policy is to substantially reduce the crime rate.”
One could multiply such programmatic statements with count-
less more drawn from texts in the field, but to bring the story closer
to the present, here’s one from a review of a representative work
(Braga and Weisbrud 2010) that we consider below, as published in
Contemporary Sociology, the book review journal of the American
Sociological Association: “The book also represents an excellent case
study in applied social science, where strong theory and rigorous
52
2: STATE
53
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
54
2: STATE
55
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
56
2: STATE
57
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
In the epigraph that heads this chapter, the economist Josiah Stamp
captures in a particularly colourful way a point that no serious
58
2: STATE
59
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
If the family were white, the police would take the offense more
seriously. A stabbing by a white woman of her husband suggests a
potential homicide to police, while a similar Black cutting can be
written off as a “North Westville battery.”
(Skolnick 1975 [1966]: 172)
60
2: STATE
61
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
62
2: STATE
are made. Where do they go? Who gets to see them? To what uses
are they actually put? How do they figure (!) in the enterprises into
which they are inserted?
Now, it is true that, as stated above, thanks to Foucault and to sci-
ence and technology studies more generally, the production of official
data, including official crime statistics, has come to be the subject of
criminological inquiry into what is called the “co-construction”
of state, statistics and society:
63
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
Data from the UCR Survey provide key information for crime
analysis, resource planning and program development for the
policing community. Municipal and provincial governments use
the data to aid decisions about the distribution of police resources,
definitions of provincial standards and for comparisons with other
departments and provinces.
To the federal government, the UCR survey provides infor-
mation for policy and legislative development, evaluation of new
legislative initiatives, and international comparisons.
To the public, the UCR survey offers information on the nature
and extent of police-reported crime and crime trends in Canada.
As well, media, academics and researchers use these data to exam-
ine specific issues about crime.
(Statistics Canada 2016b: “Description” paras 3–5)
The data are collected, then, for practical purposes: providing data
for crime analysis by police, allocating resources across multiple
jurisdictions, providing information to governments and informing
the public. The distribution of the money that the Department of
Justice (DoJ) will spend on legal aid, for example, will be informed
by regional variations in criminal charges laid, as well as by factors
affecting service delivery, such as the rural/urban population break-
down. The DoJ is, then, one market for the crime statistics. Other
64
2: STATE
65
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
66
2: STATE
67
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
In this way, the contents of the case folder differ from the entries in
an “actuarial record” like a bank account statement.
68
2: STATE
For the police, real crime exists independently of the CJS. But the
criminologist assuming this runs into intractable methodological dif-
ficulties: how could one ever find out? The problem, however, with
this question is that it is not ultimately an issue of the methodology
of empirical inquiry, but one of conceptual grammar. That crime
is a matter of definition, perception, reporting, recording and legal
determination by the CJS means that it is not available to empirical
inquiry (like counting) except through the operations of the CJS itself, to
the extent that such “socially organized measures for [its] detection and
control . . . can be enforced” (Garfinkel 1967: 215). Moreover,
police and clinic personnel both claim, both are given, and both,
in the particular ways of their respective professions, enforce a
monopoly on the rights to define the real occurrence of these
events and to advocate legitimate controls for them.
(Garfinkel 1967: 216)
69
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
all available records and recordings for one evening’s work in the
gang car . . . [including] the transcripts of citizens’ calls, dispatch-
ers’ assignments of the calls, transcripts of the police response
(tape-recorded), the author’s field notes from the car, and the cor-
responding records (e.g., patrol logs) of the police response for
that evening.
(Meehan 2000: 341)
70
2: STATE
The gang cars had been introduced into Bigcity by the mayor during
an election year to deal with the perceived gang problem. Through
his analysis, Meehan is able to show, in interactional detail, “how
groups of ordinary young people were constituted as gangs at vari-
ous points in the course of citizen complaints and police responses to
incidents during a time when gangs [had] been publicly designated
as a problem” (2000: 340). Moreover, his analysis demonstrates “that
police recordkeeping is geared toward external accountability and
is only a gloss for ‘what happened’” (2000: 342). That is, entirely in
keeping with Stamp’s epigraph,
71
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
feel to the reader like a critique of the whole enterprise, but critique,
at least in the conventional sense of showing the mistakes, failures and
successes of the enterprise in question, is not its principal purpose.
This is so for at least the following two reasons. The first fact of the
matter is that correctional criminology and the administrative crimi-
nology from which it derived and departed are institutional facts of
life of long standing in modern public administration and professional
sociology.They are, in a perfectly Durkheimian way, undeniable social
facts in themselves. In some incontrovertible way, they “work” for the
enterprises of which they are part.They produce results and the results
are used for the purposes trafficked in by their respective institutional
settings. To say as much is not to take some uncritical, milquetoast
attitude to the bureaucratic or research practices of modern (or post-
modern) societies, their states and their professions. It is not being said
here that such administrative and professional academic endeavours
are impervious to critique or should be left alone to go about their
respective businesses in peace. Not at all. Rather, the attitude adopted
here is one of awe at the fact that such socially organized life exists at
all. “Not how the world is, is the mystical, but that it is” (Wittgenstein
2007 [1922]: 6.44, p. 107). That correctional criminology and adminis-
trative criminology manage to do what they do, that they can be what
they are, this is the question being addressed here. Moreover, to the
extent that a politics may be attributed to the ethnomethodological
position being adopted here, that politics is indeed
And second, part and parcel of the way such institutional facts of life
are sustained as such is that critique is built into their practices.To put
it another way, program evaluation is done by the program itself as
part of the program (Rawlings 1981). Consider the extent to which
this is true of the whole criminal justice system. Thus, even before a
criminal law is passed defining some action as crime, it is presented
as a bill to parliament or congress; is given, say, three readings; is
72
2: STATE
And it’s not just the sociology of science. Labelling theory (symbolic
interactionism) may have something to learn, perhaps, from Justice
Morris Fish of the Supreme Court of Canada in a 2010 case in which
the court narrowly overturned a 2005 child pornography conviction
on the basis of a botched search warrant:
73
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
74
2: STATE
75
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
These are the opening three sentences of the abstract of the published
version of the 2015 Presidential Address given before the American
Sociological Association. We mention this to indicate their status as
representative of the discipline’s self-understanding, at least according
to what is arguably its foremost professional organization. Specifying
the full model for crime, we have the following:
The first two terms are then placeholders for any number of slot-
fillers. Popular candidates have been name-your-drug (see Chapter 4),
comic books,TV, video games, pornography, Dungeons and Dragons,
the media and jazz:
76
2: STATE
with respect to the “this’s”: they have to start with this much; this
sight; this note; this collection of whatever is at hand. And whatever
is there is good enough in the sense that whatever is there not only
will do, but does . . . What the inquiry can come to is what the
death came to.
(Garfinkel 1967: 18, emphasis in original)
77
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
may explain the criminal act (murder). But three things must be
noted about this account. The first is that explanation here is not
causal in the natural scientific sense, but rests on reasons for action.
We may say in ordinary language that the bad marriage “caused” the
spouse to hate their spouse and that such hatred “caused” the murder,
but we are not supposing that these relations are causal in the way that
the application of heat causes water to boil (though we may use such
a metaphor for effect). No, we are engaged in the analysis of reasons
for action in a moral context, an altogether different framework for
understanding, and one that is ultimately social in character, resting
on our members’ knowledge of how such things as marriages can “go
wrong,” and how spouses can come to hate each other sufficiently to
want to kill each other.The links among the social state, the individual
condition and the action are “socially-conceptual.” That is, they rest
on the inter-linked meanings of “bad marriage,” “hatred of spouse”
and murder-in-this-case. Indeed – and this is the second thing to
note – determining what took place – namely, that this homicide is
a murder – depends on explaining why it took place; namely, that this
was an act of hatred arising from a bad marriage. That is, coming up
with the explanation is part of the way the fact of the matter is itself
established.This crucial feature of the way that facts and explanations
are related in practical reasoning has been classically demonstrated
in connection with suicide, contra Durkheim, by Garfinkel (1967),
Sacks (1963; 1972a: 57), Blum and McHugh (1971: 100–101), who
also discuss murder, and Atkinson (1978: 171–172). It is captured in
these words of Garfinkel (1967: 106): “If the interpretation makes
good sense, then that’s what happened.” He is here referring to jurors’
decision-making in a study that we review in Chapter 6.
The third thing is that that moral context of understanding is one
in which the typical goal of the inquiry is to assess responsibility for
the action, not scientifically to explain its causes. The practical actor
is concerned to distribute guilt and innocence, blame and blameless-
ness, fault and its absence, inadvertence and its opposite and so on (see
Hart 1965 [1948–1949]: 170). Wresting the accountability of action
from its moral and legal context in order to treat its factual elements
as a set of independent empirical data linked in a nexus of causal
relations is to miss the phenomenon entirely (Stetson 1999: 87–88).
We take up the further sociological analysis of members’ explanatory
accounts – in the form of justifications and excuses – in Chapter 5.
78
2: STATE
79
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
service of the “best” people who have received the “best” education.
In the immortal words of Robert McNamara:
Management is in the end the most creative of all the arts for
its medium is human talent itself. The real threat to democracy
comes . . . from undermanagement . . . To undermanage reality is
not to keep it free. It is simply to let some force other than reason
shape reality.
(from The Essence of Security [1968],
quoted in Chomsky [2005 (1970)]: 51)
80
2: STATE
(see Rock [1986] for one notable example). For us, the presumed
equivalence of sociological and social problems belied by this practice
indicates an endorsement by the sociologist of the norms, values and
beliefs the perceived violation of which gives rise to the “problems”
in the first place.We question this endorsement! For us, such grounds
are to be treated as topics of inquiry rather than as resources for
generating “sociological problems.” We are interested in the use of
values, norms and beliefs by members of society as means for produc-
ing social order, and so we see no justification for subscribing to that
which we want to treat as problematic. Both in their applied work,
and more fundamentally in their theoretical formulations, adminis-
trative and correctional criminology have contributed to the process
through which crime is constructed as a problem in society. But this
is the subject matter of Chapter 4.
Exercises
1. Using endnote 3 of this chapter as a guide, find and browse the
website of your country’s crime statistics agency. Become familiar
with the types of tabular data collected and presented, the variables
in the tables and the sources of data, whether offences known to
the police, self-report studies or victimization data. Notice any
special reports on particular topics. Read the appendices accompa-
nying the tables concerning the reliability and validity of the data.
In your fieldwork notebook, note whatever strikes you in relation
to the themes of this chapter.
2. Having discovered when your country’s annual statistics are
released, check the websites of your local or national news organi-
zations to see how they are reported, what issues are made of them
and who gets to comment on them in the news media. Use your
notebook to record observations of interest.
3. Locate the website of your local, regional or national crime pre-
vention council or equivalent. Browse and note its contents.
Review questions
1. Why do states collect crime statistics? What are they for?
2. What did Garfinkel (and Bittner) mean by “good organizational
reasons for bad clinic records”? What are “good organizational
81
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
reasons” for “bad crime statistics”? From what point of view are
such statistics “bad”?
3. What are our arguments for referring to criminal behaviour as
“so-called”? What are the consequences of these arguments for
correctional theories of crime?
4. Compare and contrast the moral assessment of responsibility for
an action and the scientific explanation of its causes.
Further reading
Seidman, David and Michael Couzens. 1974. “Getting the crime
rate down: Political pressure and crime reporting.” Law and Society
Review 8 (3): 457–494. A classic uncovering of the political manip-
ulation of crime rates during the administration of US President
Richard Nixon.
Rock, Paul. 2012.“Sociological theories of crime.” In M. Maguire, R.
Morgan and R. Reiner (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Criminology.
Fifth edition. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 39–80.
A well-informed and clear review of the major schools of socio-
logical theory of crime.
Winch, Peter. 2008 [1958]. The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation
to Philosophy. Third edition. London: Routledge. See chapter 3 for
lucid and devastating criticism of the idea that sociology can be
a science, with particular reference to the differences among the
concepts of motive, reason and cause.
Notes
1 Vold’s (1958) use of the term to refer to the eighteenth-century “classi-
cal” school of criminology (Bottomley 1979: 2) is different from what is
meant here.
2 See Statistics Canada, Uniform Crime Reporting Survey: www23.statcan.
gc.ca/imdb/p2SV.pl?Function=getSurvey&SDDS=3302 (Accessed 1
April 2016). The UCR survey is discussed in more detail later in the
chapter.
3 In Canada, consult the Canadian Centre for Justice Statistics; in the
United States, it is the Federal Bureau of Investigation; and in the United
Kingdom, it is the Office for National Statistics (before 2013, the Home
Office).
4 Sarah Leavitt, “More aboriginal women allege abuse at hands of Quebec
provincial police,” CBC News, 31 March 2016: www.cbc.ca/news/canada/
82
2: STATE
montreal/quebec-police-aboriginal-indigenous-sex-abuse-allegations-
1.3512459 (Accessed 1 April 2016).
5 Thanks go to David Francis for this particular formulation.
6 Geoffrey York,“Oscar Pistorius found guilty of murdering girlfriend,” The
Globe and Mail, 3 December 2015: www.theglobeandmail.com/news/
world/south-africas-supreme-court-convicts-pistorius-of-murder/
article27576426/?utm_medium=Newsletter&utm_source=Morning+
News+Update&utm_type=text&utm_content=MorningNewsUpdate
&utm_campaign=131730108 (Accessed 4 December 2015).
7 Thanks go to Herbert Pimlott (Communication Studies,Wilfrid Laurier
University) for this phrase describing social workers.
83
3 Society
84
3: SOCIETY
Society is now clear in two main senses: as our most general term
for the body of institutions and relationships within which a rela-
tively large group of people live; and as our most abstract term
for the condition in which such institutions and relationships are
formed.
(Williams 1985: 291)
85
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
Functionalism
In Chapter 2 we said that an abiding methodological characteristic
of mainstream studies in correctional criminology is their “abstracted
empiricism.” This expression coined by Mills (1959) is one part of a
pair, the other being “grand theory.” By “grand theory,” Mills means
to refer to the elaborate “armchair” theorizing of the US sociolo-
gist Talcott Parsons who employs the “functionalist” perspective
for thinking about society. Functionalism is ancient in origin, but
it was formulated again for the social sciences in the nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries by, especially, the anthropologists Bronislaw
Malinowski and Alfred Radcliffe-Brown, and the sociologist Émile
Durkheim. The basis of functionalism is the “organic analogy,” the
idea that society is like an organism, particularly the human organism.
In bio-medical terms, an organism like the human body may then be
thought of as being a system, comprising various sub-systems, each
part specialized in some way but contributing to the functioning
of the whole. This analogy is then adopted for thinking about the
internal structure of society.The whole society is likened to a system
that has various needs or functions (“functional imperatives”) that
must be met in order for it to survive; that is, to adapt to its external
environment, and to regulate and integrate itself internally. The parts
of society – namely the institutions that make up the economy, the
polity, kinship relations and cultural and community organizations
86
3: SOCIETY
87
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
88
3: SOCIETY
89
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
Tonry: why crime rates are falling throughout the Western world
90
3: SOCIETY
91
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
92
3: SOCIETY
In view of this, then, it is relatively easy to see that public trials and
punishments can serve as not only reminders but also celebrations
of the morality. In this sense, the “criminal” serves not only a useful
purpose, but also a necessary one.
93
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
94
3: SOCIETY
more than indicate the range of analytic possibilities that the func-
tionalist perspective opens up in this regard, for the fact is, “there
have been very few dedicated functionalist criminologists” (Rock
2012: 63). In the matter of the administration of justice through the
courts, we can point to Gusfield’s (1981) argument about the purpose
of the rhetoric associated with the notion of the “killer-drunk” as
found in appeal court judgments. Quite apart from whatever util-
ity such language has in expediting the operation of the courts or
the apprehension of criminals, such declamations serve the societal
symbolic function of marking moral boundaries by constructing and
dramatizing the image of the “evil one” in whatever is the incarna-
tion of the day (Pearson 1983). What is worth noting here is that
the public, ritual exiting from society of the embodied version of the
hated image – namely, the now convicted person – is not matched
by an equivalent public ritual of re-entry into society when his or
her time is served (Erikson 1962: 311). In terms of this approach,
the person is a prop of the ritual, and not the other way round. It
is the occasion of public vilification that the society needs, not the
reformation of the criminal.
A particularly poignant case of this ritual scapegoating is recounted
in Janet Maybee’s (2015) book about the persecution of harbour pilot
Francis Mackey following the Halifax Explosion of 6 December 1917
during World War I that killed at least 2,000 people and caused mas-
sive damage to the city of Halifax, Nova Scotia. Mackey had been
assigned to pilot one of the two ships – namely the munitions ship,
Mont Blanc – that collided on that terrible day.
Despite a promise to the contrary, his pilot’s licence was not returned,
preventing him from working. Local and provincial officials made
strenuous efforts to prosecute him. “The cost of legal counsel while
supporting his large and growing family was a huge burden for an
95
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
96
3: SOCIETY
97
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
who better to prepare His chosen few than the clergy themselves?”
(Box 1981 [1971]: 34, original emphasis). However, Mrs Hutchinson
declared that obedience to the clergy was irrelevant as far as God’s
grace was concerned, and many agreed with her. Soon, a majority
of the local congregation preferred meeting at her house to meet-
ing at the church. She not only instructed them in correct religious
thinking, she also called into question the state of grace of the church
leaders themselves. Faced with this challenge, the clergy impeached
her and subsequently declared her guilty of “casting doubt upon the
authority of the church.” As Box puts it:
98
3: SOCIETY
99
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
a way for a new morality and a new faith, which the Athenians then
needed because the traditions by which they had hitherto lived no
longer corresponded to the conditions of their existence . . . From
this viewpoint the fundamental facts of criminology appear to us
in an entirely new light. Contrary to current ideas, the criminal no
longer appears as an utterly unsociable creature, a sort of parasitic
element, a foreign, unassimilable body introduced into the bosom
of society. He plays a normal role in social life.
(Durkheim 1982 [1895]: 101–102, emphasis added)
100
3: SOCIETY
101
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
102
3: SOCIETY
gloves moves the dispute arising from a cheap shot from private
to public.
Third, Colburn concludes by emphasizing the functional character of
fistfights. By symbolically and publicly affirming the unwritten norm
of respect between competitors, fistfights restore trust among players
that they all, on both sides, respect the rules of the game. Moreover,
the fights may be said to have also a partially instrumental function
as “an informal mode of social control enacted by players” (Colburn
1986 [1985]: 69). Because of the speed, continuous play and hard
hitting that characterizes ice hockey, referees do not see all the viola-
tions. Their formal control of the game is then supplemented by the
informal control exercised by the players themselves.
But what, you say, does this have to do with crime? There is no
crime on the hockey rink. Fistfights in ice hockey are not crimes. But
that’s just the point. Here is an arena (literally) of social life where the
police almost never enter, except for the purpose of crowd control.
And on those rare occasions when they do intervene (but after the
game, not on the ice), it’s just because some illegitimate assault has been
perpetrated that has escaped or exceeded the bounds of the formal
and informal control mechanisms of the game itself. Even though the
very same physical behaviour engaged in by the same persons, but
going down in or outside the bar where they are drinking afterwards,
may well occasion police apprehension, arrest and being charged
with assault, on the ice in the course of a game it counts as part of the
game. Just as the gruesome homicide that comprises the public state
execution may be seen in a Durkheimian way as ritually affirming the
moral values that bind the society together (Box 1981 [1971]: 36–40),
so the fistfight in ice hockey binds the players to the values of honour
and respect for the game without which it would not be possible to
play at all. Sanctioned violence serves to denounce the unsanctioned
kind, thereby integrating the participants into the peaceful pursuit of
a fiercely competitive sport.
103
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
104
3: SOCIETY
105
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
The question then posed itself: just which categories of persons were
selected to speak on this issue by reporters and editors, and under
106
3: SOCIETY
Such events allow not only that one may talk to strangers, say in the
street, but that one may express emotions publicly to the point of
being intimate with others – holding them and crying with them
– and be seen to be doing so for recognizable reasons; that is,“observ-
ably-reportably.” When the President has been shot, one may be
recognizably seen as crying in the street because the President has been shot.
The killing of the women engineering students, once it is dubbed
the “Montreal Massacre,” is made a public disaster, and broadcast and
responded to as such. It thereby establishes a “we-relation” among
strangers whereby “we” become “parties to the disaster,” and may
behave in terms of the category-bound predicates of the categories of
that MCD; for example, crying, being horrified, expressing outrage,
etc. Permission to speak is a category predicate. In a remarkable ana-
lytic step accompanying the passage just quoted, Sacks proposes that
it is in just such ways that “a small part of the sense of what is called
the ‘integrative function of crime’ [may be achieved], i.e., in such a
situation you know what’s on all these people’s minds” (1992b: 194).
But it is not just anybody who is a party to the crime/disaster
who is selected to be interviewed, quoted and given opinion slots
in the news media to formulate the significance, that is, the functions
of the massacre. Knowledge is socially distributed, which is something
107
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
Conclusion
Functional analysis is “that kind of analysis which sees things as parts
of systems and examines them to see how they interlock with other
parts of the system and what effect they have on the state of the system
overall” (Sharrock 1980: 124). At face value, this view entails taking
a step that is essential to any form of sociological analysis; namely,
putting things in context. You might even say that sociology equals
contextualizing. This fundamental move in sociological inquiry pro-
vides for the possibility of devastating criticism of those who examine
things without reference to their context. In the functionalist case, it
affords the argument that appearances can be misleading and avail-
able theories misguided. Thus, for example, we can say that the view
that rules secure social order is incomplete, insofar as in the game of ice
hockey, fistfights break a rule in order to secure compliance with “the
rules.”What appears as mere disruptive violence is, in fact, normative
behaviour oriented to the maintenance of the “system” (which is the
108
3: SOCIETY
game).That is, the manifest appearance of disorder may have the latent
function of bringing about order.
The problem with the functionalist appeal to context, however, is
that the context used in the analysis is supplied by the analyst on the
basis of his or her theory, and not by the parties to the interaction
being analyzed in the terms that are relevant to them. As the case
of the Montreal Massacre shows, members of society are more than
ready to posit the consequences, to formulate the functions, positive
and negative, of the massacre and to do so in terms that are relevant
to the categories of persons doing the formulating and about whom
they are being formulated.They hardly need professional sociologists
to do it for them.
Professional sociological functionalism seeks (sought?) to explain
social order as the integration of society’s members around funda-
mental values, achieved in part through the institutionalized public
rituals of criminalizing those who offend against those values. But
listen to A. R. Louch: “Social institutions are frequently explained
as socially integrative. In a sense, of course, institutions are socially
integrative, for that is what we mean by a society” (1966: 108–109).
In other words, insofar as society exists, it is already integrated,
for that’s part of the meaning of the concept “society.” This suggests
further that in order to know what we mean by the functions of an
institution – to be able to conceive of what needs the criminal justice
system, for example, satisfies – the CJS itself must already be in exist-
ence. For another example, “The need for family life is inconceivable
outside the institution of the family. Consequently, it would be cir-
cular to speak of the institution as answering to that need” (Louch
1966: 108). Similarly, to bring the matter back to “deviant” if not
“criminal” “behaviour”:
109
PART I: POSITIVELY UNDERTAKEN
Exercises
1. Make a point of reading, listening to or watching news stories
reporting the conviction and sentencing of offenders. Take note
particularly of any commentary – by, say, the judge, the lawyers
concerned, the police or “experts” – that formulates the function
of the punishment handed down by the court. Have an ear, espe-
cially, for the use of the phrase “sending a message.” Note who says
it, about whom it is said, and to whom it is directed, who it is that
needs to “hear” the message. Do this in light of Sacks’s remarks
about “something for us” and “something for them.”
2. Record any instance you come across of members’ formulating of
functions in relation to crime.
Review questions
1. How does Durkheim come to argue that crime is necessary for
a healthy society? But is it crime or criminalization that is func-
tional? What does it mean to say that the relationship between
society and crime in Durkheim’s view is conceptual rather than
empirical?
2. In light of Colburn’s analysis of the functional value of the fistfight
in ice hockey, can you think of other examples of “rule-following
110
3: SOCIETY
Further reading
Gusfield, Joseph R. 1981. The Culture of Public Problems: Drinking
Driving and the Symbolic Order. Chicago, IL: Chicago University
Press. See particularly “Part Two: The Ritual of Law: Creating
a Moral Order,” especially chapters 5 and 7, for Gusfield’s deft
functionalist analysis of the “myth of the killer-drunk.”
Pearson, Geoffrey. 1983. Hooligan: A History of Respectable Fears.
London, UK: Macmillan. This is an illuminating account of the
generational succession of demonized images of young people
from the moral panic about mods and rockers in the UK and back
into history.
Maybee, Janet. 2015. Aftershock: The Halifax Explosion and the
Persecution of Pilot Francis Mackey. Halifax, NS: Nimbus Publishing.
A poignant, dramatic and compelling account of the production
of a scapegoat for one of the worst maritime disasters of all time.
111
PART II
Interpretatively
turned
Introduction
Interpretative sociology
The 1960s were a major watershed in the development of profes-
sional sociology. Two signal challenges emerged to the prevailing
models of inquiry, one epistemological or methodological, the other
political. The assumption of Parsonsian grand theory – that a social
structure of institutionalized normative expectations, underpinned
by consensus on underlying fundamental values and internalized in
the personalities of well-socialized members of society, was the cru-
cial ingredient, and therefore explanation, of social order in stable
societies – was challenged theoretically and empirically by a range
of studies that came to be known as conflict theory. We take up the
political challenge with its focus on class, gender and race in Part III, in
order to trace out its consequences for the sociology of crime.
115
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
116
INTRODUCTION
117
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
From what has been said above, it is clear that Weber, wanting it both
ways, fails to see the logical incompatibility of meaningful action and
causal explanation, and fails to see what Schutz subsequently points
out (see Lynch 1998: 25), that “interpretative understanding” is,
in the first place, what distinguishes the social actor, what we are
calling the lay sociologist, rather than the professional sociological
observer. Moreover, Weber’s distinction between action and social
action cannot be maintained since “all meaningful behaviour [i.e.
action] must be social, since it can be meaningful only if governed
by rules, and rules presuppose a social setting” (Winch 2008 [1958]:
108–109). But he did put interpretative sociology with its focus on
action and social action on the map, only to have the latter concept
taken up by Parsons in The Structure of Social Action (1968 [1937]) but
there stripped of its necessary dependence on the actor’s point of
view and lost to view in mainstream sociology. Lynch (1998: 24–26)
gives a good account of these developments that is relevant to this
and the following paragraph.
Fortunately, it was recovered and reconstructed in the 1950s in
the works of two philosophers that helped subsequent sociologists
to make the interpretative turn – important essays by Alfred Schutz
developed from his book The Phenomenology of the Social World (Schutz
1967 [1932]) and subsequently made available in volume 1 of his
Collected Papers (Schutz 1962a [1954], 1962b [1953]); and The Idea
of a Social Science by Peter Winch (2008 [1958]), reflecting the views
of Wittgenstein. Both philosophers explicitly address Weber’s views
on action and social action and critically revise them in much the
same way, despite differences in philosophical language. The essen-
tial point is perhaps best expressed in the following passage from
Schutz:
118
INTRODUCTION
119
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
While Schutz’s work was a significant resource for Garfinkel’s development of ethnometh-
odology (Lynch 1998: 25), Winch’s book, which brought Wittgenstein’s philosophy into
sociology, was particularly influential for British ethnomethodologists of the Manchester
school (Hutchinson et al. 2008: 34; Psathas 2008), notably W. W. Sharrock who has written
extensively in this vein. The natural-language philosophy of Gilbert Ryle and J. L. Austin was
also drawn on by the Manchester school. Its kinship with phenomenology may be gauged by
the fact that Austin describes his own work as a sort of “linguistic phenomenology” (Austin
1961: 130; Pitkin 1972: 120). Blumer’s account of symbolic interactionism is indebted to
the philosophical social psychology of George Herbert Mead, one of the founders, with
C. S. Peirce and John Dewey, of the US philosophical school known as pragmatism. Suffice
it to say that all three schools of philosophy may be said to be neo-Kantian: “Wittgenstein
teaches what might be considered a sort of linguistic Kantianism” (Pitkin 1972: 120; see also
Janik and Toulmin 1973, especially chapter 7); phenomenology (Edmund Husserl, Schutz)
is a direct descendant of Kant; the road from Kant to Mead to symbolic interactionism is
sketched by Deutscher (1973: 326); “Kant was the great pioneer of construction” (Hacking
1999: 41). Schutz (1962a [1954]: 54) cites Mead; Garfinkel (1967: 70) cites Wittgenstein
(see also Dingwall 2000: 891). In contrast to the standard “externalist” view of the relation-
ship of mind and reality, which posits that the two are independent of each other, all three
philosophical schools mentioned take an “internalist” view of the relationship. This is to say
that reality is taken to be “mind-dependent” or “theory-dependent” (Anderson et al. 1985:
31–39) or, indeed, “language-dependent” (Winch 2008 [1958]). The interpretative turn is
thus related to the “linguistic turn” in analytic philosophy (Rorty 1967; Hacker 2013) and
to the “practice turn” (Lynch 1993; Schatzki et al. 2001) in science and technology studies
(Lynch 2014: 112, note 19).
120
INTRODUCTION
121
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
122
INTRODUCTION
123
4 Claims-making
124
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
125
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
126
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
127
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
128
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
Small (1978 [Cook 1969]) poses the question: what led to the crimi-
nalization of narcotics use in the period 1908–1923? Beginning with
the Opium Act of 1908, a series of Acts were passed culminating in
the Opium and Narcotic Drug Act of 1929 which together criminal-
ized the import, manufacture, sale, possession and use for other than
medical purposes of opium and its derivatives, and of cocaine and
marijuana.This legislation is the foundation of the current Controlled
Drugs and Substances Act (1996). Small accounts for this by appealing
to the claims-making and other activities of various moral crusad-
ers and to the favourable social context that shaped and was in turn
shaped by them. The three important features of this context are:
1. the racial conflict between “whites” and “orientals”;
2. the status conflict between the high-status medical profession and
its clients, using narcotics for therapeutic purposes, and the low-
status users, particularly Chinese, using opium for pleasure and
leisure;
3. the prevailing cultural beliefs and values about drugs and their link
with sexual promiscuity and “race mixing.”
The racism of the time was expressed in such claims as “they [Asiatics]
make the country of no value for the surplus population of Great
Britain,” uttered by Duncan Ross of Vancouver (House of Commons
Debates 1907–1908) and “whatever their motive, the traffic [in drugs]
always comes with the Oriental, and . . . one would, therefore be jus-
tified in assuming that it was their desire to injure the bright-browed
129
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
races of the world” (Murphy 1922: 184, cited by Small 1978 [Cook
1969]: 37). We may add now that
This was a practice that didn’t end until after World War II.The deci-
sion not to let 354 of the 376 passengers, predominantly Sikh men,
on the ship Komagata Maru land at Vancouver on 23 May 1914, and
then to deport them, was a particularly blatant case of the application
of this racist policy.3
The criminalization was shaped by the differential power arising
from status differences of different groups of users and producers
of opium. “It made little difference in Canada or the United States
that the ‘evidence clearly indicates that the upper and middle classes
predominated among narcotic addicts in the period up to 1914’”
(Hagan 1980: 614, quoting Duster 1970: 9). Thus, while physicians
created addicts among their often middle-class and maternal cli-
entele by prescribing medicines containing opiates for a variety of
complaints, neither they nor their practice were considered criminal.
The 1908 Proprietary or Patent Medicine Act prohibited only indis-
criminate use of medical opiates, backed up by only minor penalties.
In contrast, there was virtually no opposition to the criminalization
of “non-therapeutic” opiate use associated in the public mind with
the low-status immigrant Chinese population. Similarly, producers of
other drugs – alcohol and tobacco – were often British, of high sta-
tus and contributed useful taxes; their activities were not proscribed.
The same was not true of the low-status (often Chinese) producers
of smoking opium. Together with den proprietors and storekeepers
who sold opium, they could expect the exercise of the “drastic right
of search” without warrant of their “non-dwelling houses” by police,
no appeals for those with no fixed residence, seven-year maximum
sentences and possible deportation for conviction for trafficking, and
whipping for giving drugs to minors.
130
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
“Persons using this narcotic, smoke the dried leaves of the plant,
which has the effect of driving them completely insane.The addict
loses all sense of moral responsibility. Addicts to this drug, while
under its influence, are immune to pain, and could be severely
injured without having any realization of their condition. While
in this condition, they become raving maniacs and are liable to
kill or indulge in any form of violence to other persons, using the
most savage methods of cruelty without, as said before, any sense
of moral responsibility.”
(Murphy 1922: 336, cited in Small 1978 [Cook 1969]: 33)
131
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
132
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
This demand was satisfied in the 1911 Act and “the offence of pos-
session remained a highly valued enforcement resource” (Small 1978
[Cook 1969]: 40). Following the establishment of a national enforce-
ment network in 1919, addicts were differentiated by the second
Chief of the Division of Narcotic Control, Colonel Sharman, into
three categories: medical addicts, professional addicts and criminal
addicts. It was the last of these three categories that would, of course,
receive criminal sanctions. Finally, the RCMP, which replaced the
Royal North-West Mounted Police in 1920, saw in narcotics work
a means of survival. Because of their role in strike-breaking, as in
the Winnipeg General Strike of 1919, they were in danger of being
disbanded.
133
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
134
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
135
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
There is perhaps no stronger case for the position taken in this work
– that to understand crime, it is necessary first to understand the
criminal law – than that of the extent of the crime made possible
by the laws criminalizing drugs. We conclude this section with the
following reflection by Sharrock on the possible consequences of
de-criminalizing drugs:
136
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
137
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
were active in getting rape (Rose 1977; Snider 1985), what was then
called “wife battering” (see below), sexual harassment (Grahame
1985; MacKinnon 1987: chapter 9; Wise and Stanley 1987) and por-
nography (Mahoney 1988; Cole 1989) defined as problems; they
contributed significantly to the process by which child abuse (Lenton
1989) came to be perceived as a problem, especially its offshoot, the
problem of child sexual abuse (for example, Mitchell 1985). In all
these cases, some degree of criminalization of the offending activities
resulted. Other sub-movements fought for de-criminalizing vari-
ous practices; for example, abortion and prostitution (for example,
Shaver 1985; Bell 1987; Jenness 1990 ) while others elevated women’s
inequality in employment (for example, pay inequity) and in fam-
ily, matrimonial and welfare law to the status of major public issues
(Brophy and Smart 1985).
New crimes were created, notably the extension of sexual assault
to cover the case of a husband raping his wife. After 1990, the cir-
cumstance of a wife killing her abusive husband became in a sense
de-criminalized in Canada, the United States and elsewhere where
the “battered wife syndrome” was present.That is, there became avail-
able to a woman charged with killing her husband the “battered wife
defence.” The preceding period of claims-making activities focusing
on the “battered wife problem” has been the subject of considerable
inquiry (see Walker 1990; Loseke 1991).
138
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
139
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
140
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
of Ferraro (1989; see also her 2003 article). Although not about the
creation of a new criminal law, Loseke and Cahill’s (1984) study
of the role of “experts” in constructing a new type of “deviant,”
namely the battered woman who stays with her partner, is a classic
work in the field.The construction in this case is analyzed as the out-
come of the work of “professional entrepreneurs” in the social work
and allied helping professions. It has been reprinted in each edition
of Rubington and Weinberg’s equally classic collection, Deviance:The
Interactionist Perspective (tenth edition, 2008).
141
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
142
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
143
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
In each case, the key assertion is that the actual character of a sub-
stance [such as a drug], condition, or behaviour remained constant.
144
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
But in each case the authors fail to acknowledge that their iden-
tification of “the nature of [the drug],” or their assertion of the
constancy of a condition or behaviour, can itself be construed as a
definitional claim. In naming, identifying or describing conditions,
these authors inevitably give definition to the putative behaviours
and conditions they discuss. While the claims of the claims mak-
ers are depicted as socio-historical constructions (definitions) that
require explanation, the claims and the constructive work of the
authors remain hidden and are to be taken as given.
(Woolgar and Pawluch 1985: 217)
145
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
are. Without concepts and the practices of which they form part,
there would be no facts to state in the first place. How can there
be a fact of a daffodil’s colour or the moon’s shape without our
practices of distinguishing colours and shapes? As Wittgenstein has
taught us so effectively, concepts are human institutions.
(Francis 2005: 282–283)
Francis continues:
Notice Francis’s conclusion. It’s not that the facts are either institu-
tional or brute or some combination of the two. It’s that the distinction
itself makes no sense. In parallel terms, it’s not that reality is objective
or subjective or both, it’s that the distinction itself makes no sense. It’s
not that crime and crime problems are constructed or objectively real
or both, it’s that the distinction itself makes no sense (see Sharrock and
Watson [1988] for a pointed discussion of professional sociology’s mis-
begotten fixation on these and like dualisms). Rather than rendering
claims-makers’ activities, including their coining of labels for the issues
that concern them, in this professional sociology’s theoretical language
of “constructing reality,” we should return them to the institutional
contexts in which they arise, live and have their being, so that it can
be seen what they are doing just there. Abstracting them from their
homes, for the purposes of a misbegotten sociological metaphysics or
epistemology, is really a very strange thing to be doing; it “is to demand
something extraordinary” (Bogen and Lynch 1993: 220).
146
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
Conclusion
Stripped of their philosophical trappings and the rhetorical struc-
ture of their explanatory form (Woolgar and Pawluch 1985), the
descriptive content of constructionist accounts can be illuminating
and instructive (Bogen and Lynch 1993: 225). Whereas we may be
inclined to think that social problems, deviance and crime are bad
because they are bad, the constructionist perspective reminds us that
somebody has to define the actions in question as bad, and then work
to get that definition accepted in society more generally.Their “bad”
status, that is, is the product of enterprise, involving claims-making.
That wife battering was, by and large, not recognized as a social prob-
lem before 1970, but was considered a major problem in 1980 only
points to the importance of the claims-making activities of those that
effected this change in its status. That opium and cocaine and mari-
juana use were, before 1908 in Canada, not regarded as social problems
and not against the law, only raises the sociological question of how
they became crimes (and subsequently regarded as social problems)
in and after 1908, 1911 and 1923 respectively. What is critical about
such a question and the descriptive analysis that flows from it is the
challenge it poses to those who would have it (claim?) that the devi-
ant status of such activities is simply natural. On the contrary, says the
constructionist, it is the product of social groups working to make
them so. Furthermore:
147
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
148
4: CLAIMS-MAKING
Exercises
1. Collect and record in your notebook all instances of claims-mak-
ing about crime (as one or other type of social problem) that come
your way in the course of a week – from friends, relatives, class-
mates, teachers, work-mates, associates at meetings, store-keepers,
religious officials, coaches, politicians, etc.; in advertising; in the
mail; in the news; in your reading, etc. Note the claims themselves,
who is making them, by what means, directed at whom, to what
end. Note particularly the categories of persons or groups being
referred to, the use of “atrocity tales” or “horror stories,” the appeal
to statistical facts, other rhetorical features of the language being
used and so on.
Review questions
1. What is the constructionist sociologist getting at in saying that
the problem of drinking and driving, or “drugs” or child abuse is
socially constructed?
2. What does it mean to say that some prominent constructionists
want to “have their constructionist cake and to eat it too”?
3. Try and state how it makes sense to say that an object, including
a crime problem, can be both socially constructed and real at the
same time.
Further reading
Pfohl, Stephen J. 1977.“The ‘discovery’ of child abuse.” Social Problems
24 (3): 310–323. The classic study.
Woolgar, Steve and Dorothy Pawluch. 1985. “Ontological gerry-
mandering: The anatomy of social problems explanations.” Social
Problems 32 (3): 214–227. The classic critique.
149
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
Notes
1 For example: www.toxel.com/inspiration/2010/08/07/human-meat-
packages-from-peta/ (Accessed 25 May 2016).
2 Matthew Behrens, “Saying no to Canada’s death game,” rabble.ca, 22 June
2016: http://rabble.ca/columnists/2016/06/saying-no-to-canadas-
death-game (Accessed 25 June 2016).
3 Renisa Mawani, “The legacy of the Komagata Maru,” The Globe and
Mail, 18 May 2016: www.theglobeandmail.com/opinion/the-legacy-of-
the-komagata-maru/article30066572/ (Accessed 30 June 2016). See also
Johnston (2014).
4 “Sweeney wants to stop social problems before they start,” Kitchener-
Waterloo Record, 7 May 1987, B4, “Local.”
150
5 Defining the
situation
The first premise is that human beings act toward things on the
basis of the meanings that the things have for them . . .
151
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
Chapter synopsis
In accordance with these premises, and allowing for the social
constructionist focus on how certain forms of behaviour become
prohibited by criminal law (see Chapter 4), symbolic interaction-
ist studies of crime focus on the examination of the processes and
contexts of social interaction whereby and in which:
152
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
153
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
154
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
From being among the first (in the UK) to join, in the late 1960s, the interactionist critique
of the structural consensus orthodoxy of the 1950s, Jock Young became a leader in the
1970s of the left idealism of the “new” (that is, Marxist) critical criminology, only to take up
left realism in the 1980s. In so doing, he completed a cycle which returns to the essentially
cause-and-cure correctionalism from which this sequence of changes initially departed,
a correctionalism with its attendant positivistic features of a reliance on official statistics,
155
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
the large-scale social survey and variable analysis, and a corresponding return to reformist
politics. As Smart (1990: 72) says, “The problem of positivism is, therefore, not redeemed by
the espousal of left politics. Positivism poses an epistemological problem; it is not a simple
problem of party membership.” It is altogether a remarkable journey (see Young 1999).
For some, this shift crystallized half way in the form of a “radical
interactionism” (for example, Carlen 1976); McBarnet’s (1981) study of
conviction occupies similar transitional ground. Indeed, Hagan (1991),
among others, treats labelling theory as a species of conflict theory.We
noted the same about Shirley Small in Chapter 4. However, both the
interactionist perspective and labelling theory, and what Spector and
Kitsuse (1987 [1977]: chapter 3) call “value-conflict theory,” depart
from the structural conflict or Marxist perspective insofar as they do
not standardly have recourse to the wider structural context of society,
and they do not privilege class among the various dimensions of con-
flict. As for an overt political stance, where this is not altogether absent
in published accounts, it amounts usually to the advocacy of pluralism
and a concern for liberalizing the criminal law, its administration and
enforcement by recommending, for example, “radical non-interven-
tion” in the primary deviance of the young (Schur 1973). We restrict
our treatment of the whole perspective to its “pure” interpretative form.
156
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
157
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
158
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
159
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
“real crime” that is independent of the work of the police and courts.
It is for this reason that both are realist models of crime. In contrast,
the symbolic interactionist approach prefers to take an interpretative
or constructionist view: there is no crime apart from that which is
actually identified as such.
We shall return to this distinction between the realist and inter-
pretative models below (see grammar section) in relation to Becker’s
diagram of four types of deviant behaviour which, according to
Pollner, confuses the realist and interpretative models of crime. For
the present, we wish to emphasize that the symbolic interactionist
view of crime provides for the examination of policing as involving
the interpretation of acts and persons as criminal. It is through these
interpretations that some acts and some persons are selected to be our
crimes and criminals.This view provides then for the examination of
how crime is identified and who is selected for the role of criminal.
These tasks fall to the police as one “crime-defining agency.”
Symbolic interactionist interest in the process of selecting crime
follows from its view of the police as actors just like any other social
beings.That is, they are viewed as possessing selves with which they act
in, and interact with, their environment.The self is conceived as a pro-
cess through which humans point things out to themselves, thereby
constituting the “outer world” as a meaningful one at the same time
as appropriating that world as their own. The resources used in this
process of making meaning include “concepts,” “frames of reference”
and “definitions of the situation.” In short, what a person “sees” in
the world depends on their “point of view.” Thus, what counts as an
act(ion) is behaviour under some meaning conferred on or attributed
to it by the actor.To understand the actions of the police, the sociologist
must “take the role of the other” in order to see how police perceive
their circumstances and accordingly construct their actions. Similarly,
the police engage in a similar process of role-taking in attributing
meaning to the behaviour of those they define as criminal.
Symbolic interactionist studies of policing have therefore paid
particular attention to the processes of social interaction and interpre-
tative schemata through which certain acts and persons are selected
or identified as criminal, including what kind of criminality they
are seen as exhibiting and what type and degree of law enforcement
they correspondingly warrant. Studies of police decision-making are
heavily weighted in favour of the uniformed branch.They standardly
160
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
161
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
Some officers also substitute a large heavy duty flashlight for the
nightstick . . . [since] . . . if used correctly, the flashlight can inflict
more damage than the baton and is less likely to break when
applied to the head or other parts of the body.
(Hunt 1985: 339, note 2)
162
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
163
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
the police vehicle, but then had the audacity to run away with the
police officer’s property; that is, the cuffs. The response is described
as follows:
[A]ll of a sudden Susan [the police officer] looks up and sees her
cuffs running away. She (Jane [the other police officer]) said Susan
turned into an animal. Susan runs up the steps [and] grabs the girl
by the legs. Drags her down the five steps. Puts her in the car. Kicks
her in the car. Jane goes in the car and calls her every name she
can think of and waves her stick in her face.
(Hunt 1985: 328)
164
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
not responsible for their acts, are less likely to experience “abstract,
punitive force” (1985: 332).
These justifications in terms of abstract categorizations of persons
invoke, from the police point of view, “a higher moral purpose that
legitimates the violation of commonly recognized standards” (Hunt
1985: 332). It is an example of what Emerson (1969: 149; see below)
calls a “principled justification” where “one depicts the act as an
attempt to realize some absolute moral or social value that has prec-
edence over the value violated by the act” (as quoted by Hunt 1985:
340, note 15). Hunt offers as an example of this the following case:
165
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
166
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
167
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
168
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
169
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
170
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
171
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
172
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
173
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
the offence may assist in typifying the trouble, but it will not be the
only criterion. Serious offences create a “presumption of trouble,”
but trouble is also predicted on the basis of the presence of adverse
patterns of behaviour and social circumstances that typically precede
delinquency.
The court’s focus on the offender rather than the offence flows
from its commitment to treatment rather than simple sanctioning
of the juveniles who come before it. As Emerson puts it, the court’s
concern is not so much “what happened,” but “what is the problem
here.” Once it has decided that it has trouble on its hands, it looks
in greater depth at the juvenile’s overall behaviour, personality and
family and social circumstances (part of what Foucault means by
“discipline” – see Chapter 10). There then occurs what Emerson
calls a “second sorting” which involves establishing or typifying the
juvenile’s “moral character” (see Sacks 1972c on the assessment of
moral character).
Assessments of moral character provide for the kind of special
handling that cases require. That is, assessments of moral character
differentiate kinds of trouble and provide accounts for the delinquent
behaviour. Three general types of moral character are distinguished
by the court: the “normal,” the “hard-core” and the “disturbed.” The
juvenile with a “normal” moral character is seen as being like most
kids, acting for basically normal and conventional reasons, despite
some delinquent behaviour. Those seen as “hard-core” are typi-
fied as criminal-like delinquents, motivated by malice and hostility,
consciously pursuing illegal ends. The “disturbed” moral character
belongs to those who are driven to acting in senseless and irrational
ways by obscure motives and inner compulsions. These distinctions
echo those described in Cicourel’s earlier (1995 [1968]) study of
juvenile justice.
The significance of the categories of juvenile moral character is
that they provide institutionally relevant means for explaining the
juvenile behaviour and they provide justifications for the court’s
actions. Thus, to decide that a youth is “disturbed” is to account for
his or her behaviour and to provide the relevance of psychiatric care;
while to typify the youth as “hard-core” explains the behaviour as a
product of that kind of criminally motivated actor who needs punish-
ment and restraint.The decision that the juvenile is “normal” explains
the behaviour as the result of conventional motives and provides
174
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
175
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
176
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
177
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
178
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
179
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
There are structural limits to the scope of “bargaining” set by, for
example, mandatory minimum penalties for certain repeated convic-
tions and, conversely, by the considerable sentencing discretion in the
hands of the judge in Canada: a reduced charge may not mean much
if the judge can give the same sentence for it as for the original charge.
180
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
181
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
For the team of the public defender and the district attorney, the
question here is not one of guilt or innocence, but of “reasonable-
ness”; they take the guilt of the defendant not to be in question.
Consequently, when the case of such a defendant, who will not play
the game, gets to court, the defence provided by the public defender
amounts to what Sudnow calls “adequate legal representation.” That
is, the lawyer will respectfully observe proper legal procedure and will
not interfere with the court’s routine progress towards a conviction.
In return, the DA (the prosecutor) will not go out of his or her way
to make out the defendant to be a monster. Instead he or she
Because such trials result from defendants not accepting a plea deal,
then it is their “fault”:
What the hell are we supposed to do with them? If they can’t lis-
ten to good reason and take a bargain, then it’s their tough luck. If
they go to prison, well, they’re the ones who are losing the trials,
not us.
(Sudnow 1965: 272)
182
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
183
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
In The Society of Captives, Sykes (1958) presents the theory that the
inmate social system is developed to cope with the “pains of impris-
onment.” These pains consist of a collection of “deprivations”:
1. the deprivation of liberty, particularly the freedom to see one’s
family and friends;
2. the deprivation of goods and services, particularly those necessary
to maintain a cherished self-identity;
3. the deprivation of heterosexual relationships;
4. the deprivation of autonomy, particularly not being allowed to
make decisions about how daily activities will be allocated;
5. the deprivation of security, particularly the close physical proxim-
ity of persons with records of violent aggression.
(Box 1981 [1971]: 216)
184
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
who exemplifies compliance with the code. “He is able to ‘take it.’
He has strength . . . and ‘confronts his captors with neither subservi-
ence nor aggression’ ([Sykes 1958:] p. 102)” (Wieder 1974: 123–124).
Sykes suggests that by evaluating each other in terms of the social
type “real man” (that is, in terms of exemplary commitment to the
code), the inmates are able to “reduce the pains of imprisonment and
can achieve a sense of self-respect” (Wieder 1974: 124).
Similar findings have been made by Garabedian (1963, 1964). His
account (1964) reflects that of Sykes by addressing the social types
provided by the code. He thus identifies “square johns,” “politicians,”
“right guys” and “outlaws” and describes the types of behaviours
which are associated with each of them. “Commitment” to the con-
vict code is exemplified by such behaviours as breaking the prison
rules, avoiding contact with the officials and refusing to participate
in staff-sponsored programs. Because they are more likely to engage
in such behaviours, the “outlaw” and “right guy” are viewed as more
committed and hence are held in greater esteem within the prisoner
community than those typified as “politicians” and “square johns”
(Wieder 1974: 124).
Several studies in this genre have indicated that there tends to
be more than one type of subculture within prisons. Thus Irwin
and Cressey (1962) and Irwin (1970) point to the existence of the
“thief subculture” and the “convict subculture.” The former consists
of the norms and values that are said to be characteristic of profes-
sional thieves and other career criminals. It is also seen as a subculture
that is imported into the prison from outside. The latter, the con-
vict subculture, on the other hand, is viewed as arising in response
to the conditions found within the prison. This is the subculture of
the hard-core, long-term and institutionalized inmates. According
to Box (1981 [1971]: 217), this subculture pertains to that company
of “men who have spent most of their lives, including their youth,
in state institutions”; these are inmates who have been, for the most
part, “ineffectual criminals, but who, because of their experience in
prisons and similar institutions, know exactly how to work the sys-
tem.” From this group of inmates, a neophyte prisoner might learn
how to manipulate other prisoners and how to hustle, but he or she is
not likely to learn how to be a more effective criminal. On the other
hand, the thief subculture referred to by Irwin and Cressey (1962) is
carried by those “who are essentially criminals and only incidentally
185
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
186
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
187
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
188
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
189
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
190
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
191
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
theorists do. But outside such language games, people don’t generally
use the expression “deviant behaviour” that much. Jayyusi, pointing
to the domain of the sociology of deviance as comprising “the mor-
ally displayed and premised descriptions of persons by other persons
(either ‘lay’ persons or ‘officials’),” makes the point:
192
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
193
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
with the way “reality” is being used here in the writer’s text and, we
venture, in ordinary language generally: “the function of ‘real’ is not
to contribute positively to the characterization of anything, but to
exclude possible ways of being not real” (Austin 1962: 70, emphasis
in original).
194
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
police, courts and prisons. Moreover, that relevance has been rec-
ognized by the re-publication of many of the studies reviewed here,
studies that have now acquired the status of “classics.”
Our grammatical respecification of labelling theory’s recourse
to the distinction between, in Pollner’s (1987) terms, mundane and
constitutive models of deviance showed the theoretical use of the dis-
tinction to be confusing and unnecessary. Persons are regularly found
to be obedient and law-abiding, wrongfully accused, secretly “devi-
ant” and plainly guilty.The innocent can be “fixed-up,” be wrongfully
accused, be wrongfully convicted and can serve long prison sentences
for offences they are subsequently found not to have committed. Of
them, the Thomases’ “theorem” at the head of this chapter rings true:
“if men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences”
(Thomas, W. I. and Thomas, D. S. 1928: 572). Having invoked the
“definition of the situation” on the same page, the Thomases used
this quasi-proverbial dictum (see Sacks 1973) to draw a lesson from
the story of a paranoid man who
had killed several persons who had the unfortunate habit of talking
to themselves on the street. From the movement of their lips he
imagined that they were calling him vile names, and he behaved
as if this were true. If men define situations as real, they are real in
their consequences.
(Thomas, W. I. and Thomas, D. S. 1928: 572,
cited in Merton 1995: 384)
Exercises
1. Using your notebook, do some fieldwork in your local court-
house.While open to the public, security checks notwithstanding,
notice that it is a workplace for a variety of occupations. How
is this visible? Familiarize yourself with the building’s layout, its
195
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
entrances and exits, front, side and back. Who uses which ones?
Observe the signs and notices. Who are they for? What business
do people, other than courthouse staff, have there? How can you
tell? What are people actually doing there? Waiting? Talking? If so,
with whom? If there is more than one courtroom, note if they are
used for different things. Are there other rooms ancillary to any
courtroom? What goes on there?
2. If you can spare the time, spend a couple of hours observing pro-
ceedings in court itself. Be alert, and be detailed. Note the comings
and goings, the actual activities of the different parties, the way
events are ordered, who speaks, when, to whom, about what. See
– you are an apprentice sociologist, an ethnographer-in-training.
Of course, you were that already, when you found the courthouse
and started to find your way around in it.
Review questions
1. According to Hunt (1985), what are the demand conditions of
police work on the street for which the police concept of “normal
force” is designed?
2. What is the process by which labelling contributes to the forma-
tion of criminal identity?
3. What are the consequences of viewing motives not as mental
states, but as linguistic objects with their own “vocabularies”?
What are “techniques of neutralization”?
4. What is the problem with Becker’s (1963) diagram of four types of
deviant behaviour? How can the problem be dissolved?
Further reading
Hunt, Jennifer. 1984.“The development of rapport through the nego-
tiation of gender in field work among police.” Human Organization
43 (4): 283–296. Hunt’s account of the vicissitudes of her fieldwork
as a woman in the masculinist world of policing is as illuminating
in its way as her study of police concepts of force is itself.
Bauer, Shane. 2016.“My four months as a private prison guard.” Mother
Jones, July/August: www.motherjones.com/politics/2016/06/cca-
private-prisons-corrections-corporation-inmates-investigation-
bauer. Contemporary grit.
196
5: DEFINING THE SITUATION
197
6 Practical
reasoning
198
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
199
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
200
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
201
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
202
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
203
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
arising from those calls, are those by Zimmerman and colleagues (e.g.
Zimmerman 1984, 1992a, 1992b; M. R. Whalen and Zimmerman
1987, 1990; J.Whalen and Zimmerman 2005; J.Whalen, Zimmerman
and M. R.Whalen 1988; Mellinger 1992), Sharrock and Turner (1978,
1980), Meehan (1988, 1989, 2000, 2006; see Chapter 2 in this book)
and Eglin and Wideman (1986).
How police go about seeing what constitutes an actionable mat-
ter for them, what sort of actionable matter that is, and the practices
they adopt for dealing with such matters are analyzed in, for exam-
ple, Bittner (1967a, 1967b; see chapter section below), Sacks (1972c)
and Hayduk (1976). The practical decision-making of probation and
juvenile officers is documented in Cicourel (1995 [1976, 1968]) and
Bittner (1976). Let us insert here a quotation from the 1976 edition
of Cicourel’s classic ethnography The Social Organization of Juvenile
Justice, originally published in 1968, to give a flavour of his remarkable
work emphasizing the dual cognitive and organizational components
of police reasoning:
204
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
Chapter synopsis
Let us emphasize that the above listing is a sampling only of the many
studies in ethnomethodology and conversation analysis (EMCA) bear-
ing on the contingencies of criminalization. This is obviously even
more true of the works selected below to represent the field. While
we have identified three relevant forms of analysis (the “strands”)
and four topical themes characterizing EMCA inquiries into crime,
law and criminalization, studies themselves tend not to fall neatly
into these categories. Our selection covers most of the ground, but
remains somewhat arbitrary. Except for the first two cases, we follow
the sequence of moments of criminalization identified in Chapter 1.
Because EMCA informs the grammatical perspective we are adopt-
ing throughout the text, we also draw on relevant studies in EMCA
in the grammar section of each chapter.
We begin with what is chronologically the first study in the field, that
by Garfinkel (1967) on jury deliberations from the 1950s, and follow
it with the 2014 study of the same topic by Pomerantz and Sanders
employing CA, specifically MCA. We hope thereby to show both
the continuity of focus on practical reasoning with contrasting styles
205
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
206
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
207
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
208
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
209
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
210
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
211
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
212
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
Since, “if he does not know a man personally there is very little
that he can assume about him” (1967a: 707), then a first practice of
peace keeping is for an officer to acquire a rich body of particular-
ized knowledge about the persons and places on his beat, knowledge
which provides the basis for an aggressively personal approach to
residents. In exchange for interrogation rights and obedience – refus-
ing to play by insisting on rights is one way to get arrested – residents
enjoy expressive freedom and a variety of services that officers render
to them. This is not done, Bittner says, out of a spirit of altruism, but
because “the hungry, the sick and the troubled are a potential source
of problems” (1967a: 708). Such services range from providing help to
get lodgings and welfare to keeping an eye out for missing dentures.
Second, police adopt the practice of proceeding against persons on
the basis of perceived risk rather than culpability. For officers:
For the minor matters that comprise the bulk of their work, the
overriding police preference is for not arresting where control can be
effected in other ways.This does not hold for serious offences such as
213
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
Whether the “slow burn” can be explained by the fact that Bittner,
according to his own account (Brodeur 2007: 110), was never
214
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
215
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
getting the suspect not only to talk, but to continue to talk until a
confession is obtained. By drawing on the modes of ethnomethodo-
logical inquiry mentioned above,Watson is able to show in detail that
“getting the suspect to talk” and “persuading” the suspect to confess
are methodical and socially organized.
216
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
217
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
218
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
219
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
what the suspect talks about. The police officer, within the limits of
topical coherence imposed by the unfolding story, can introduce new
materials for incorporation into the developing “confession.”
220
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
221
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
become a truth machine, and on what does its probative value actu-
ally rest? Is it simply a matter of the claimed hardness of science’s
data and methods, or does the science rest on an unacknowledged
assemblage of “soft” social considerations that make its “hardness”
possible?
In Truth Machine, Lynch and his colleagues (2008) address both
the historical and sociological questions. Their 400-page book is the
result of a series of historical and ethnographic investigations over a
15-year period between the late 1980s and the early 2000s, primarily
in the United States and the United Kingdom. The methods used
include interviews, observations, participation at laboratories and
courtrooms, conversation analysis and documentary reconstruction.
222
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
For this summary, we shall consider just one of the cases treated in
the book, that of Smith.
The Smith case involved a rape and murder. Much of the prosecution’s
case turned on using DNA fingerprinting to match the accused’s
blood and semen with those in stains found at the crime scene. The
defence held that evidence up to scrutiny, thereby making evident
the complex journey travelled by the evidence from crime scene to
courtroom in the course of which it was constituted as evidence.
“Much in the way a suspect passes through a series of stages before
becoming a criminal, crime scene and suspect samples pass through
a series of stages on the way to becoming criminal evidence” (Lynch
et al. 2008: 121). What the study brings out is how the credibility of
the scientific evidence rests upon a whole series of administrative
tasks that have nothing to do with the science itself, but with what
the authors call “the administration of objectivity.”This series of tasks
is known to the personnel involved as the chain of custody.
223
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
224
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
225
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
226
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
227
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
with these descriptions the witness makes Meese and his actions
seeable as non-official.The witness thereby also proposes a descrip-
tion for his own actions. While he might be seeable as destroying
documents that were being sought by the “Attorney General,” he
refers to Meese as a “friend of the President.” Depending on which
description of Meese and his action prevails, the witness either
impeded an internal “fact finding excursion” or was involved
in the “obstruction of justice” and the destruction of evidence
needed by an official inquiry.
( Halkowski 1990: 569)
228
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
229
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
use of mundane reason with respect to, first, the resolution of what
Pollner calls “reality disjunctures” in court; and, second, judges’ use
of the mundane model of crime.
230
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
231
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
232
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
233
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
234
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
235
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
Exercises
1. Without making it a “big” project, voice-record a snatch of con-
versation among friends or roommates or with family members
over a meal or during a car ride, about some crime-related topic.
Do it unobtrusively, or openly; it doesn’t really matter which.
Transcribe, say, a minute or so of the talk according to the models
shown in the chapter. See, in further reading, chapters 2 and 4 of
An Invitation to Ethnomethodology by Francis and Hester (2004).
Identify the actions each speaker is doing and what they are mean-
ing to say, in each turn of talk, as they are taken and understood by
236
6: PRACTICAL REASONING
Review questions
1. What do you understand by “the rule of practical circumstances,”
and how is it related to the “etcetera clause”?
2. What do Lynch et al. (2008) mean by “the administration of
objectivity”?
3. How, according to Halkowski’s (1990) study, is role an interactional
device?
4. With reference to Wieder’s study (1974) of the convict code, how
do you understand the difference between the idea of the social
actor as a rule-governed creature and the idea of the actor as a
rule-using creature?
Further reading
Francis, David and Stephen Hester. 2004. An Invitation to
Ethnomethodology: Language, Society and Social Interaction. London,
UK: Sage. Look again at Chapter 2 for the three-step methodology
for EM/CA inquiry, then see how it is applied to conversation in
Chapter 4.
Eglin, Peter and Stephen Hester. 2003. The Montreal Massacre:
A Story of Membership Categorization Analysis.Waterloo, ON:Wilfrid
Laurier University Press. The book analyzes how the stories of
crime, horror, tragedy, gun control, the killer, violence against
women and the killer’s story, together with the event’s functional
237
PART II: INTERPRETATIVELY TURNED
238
PART III
Politically
challenged
Introduction
241
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Emancipatory sociology
If, roughly speaking, before the 1960s, professional sociologists had
approached class, gender and race as forms of social stratification
that worked to bind a society together by integrating its members
around a concept of their place in society, from the 1960s, that view
was overturned as practitioners put their theorizing at the service of
emancipating the social category in question. Quite explicitly, theory
and praxis were seen and advocated as going hand in hand.The sepa-
ration of science from politics that Weber (and Durkheim) famously
advocated, and which, in any case, was the accepted view of the
matter in the natural and social sciences, was criticized and rejected.
Those who defended it were seen as ideological supporters of the
status quo. That would include us, the authors of this book.
In the history of social thought, it was, of course, Marx and the
Marxists who had always insisted on the unity of theory and praxis,
242
INTRODUCTION
243
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Crime
Theorizing aside, it may be said that the empirical motivation for
the critical revisionism entailed by the political challenge posed by
self-styled “radical sociology,” when addressed to the subject of crime,
came from observations such as these:
According to the official statistics for England and Wales and stud-
ies of officially convicted offenders, the official picture of crime
is one of a criminal population compris[ing] mainly . . . young
working-class males whose criminal activity is concerned chiefly
with property, violence, and a wide range of offences associated
with the automobile.
(Phillipson 1974: 100)
This is the picture for the United Kingdom in the early 1970s. From
the United States, we have the following popular/official picture of
the typical criminal in 2010:
244
INTRODUCTION
Grammar
At the end of a lecture titled “The MIR Membership Categorization
Device” that Sacks gave in 1964 and 1965, he speculates about what
he calls “two-set classes” or, in the last paragraph, “two-class sets.”
We opt for the latter expression. He’s referring to the class, gender,
race (and age) binaries. Although he wraps this line of thought about
“membership categorization devices” in demurrals, he also allows
that these classes of categories do seem to have descriptive validity
and, in particular, that the MIR device they instantiate does provide
a “basic mechanism of social control” that could be “something that’s
of theoretical importance in sociology” (Sacks 1992a: 48). Given their
obvious relevance to the subject matter of Chapters 7, 8 and 9, we
quote the passage in full in Box 3.To explain the acronym MIR:“‘M’
stands for membership, ‘I’ stands for inference-rich, and ‘R’ stands for
representative” (Sacks 1992a: 41; Schegloff 1992a: xli). See Box 3.
Finally, let me offer something to consider. I have no idea whether it’s so. It sounds altogether
too smooth to me, and nonetheless it also looks, on the face of it, to be very descriptive.
Many of these classes are, or can be built as, two-set classes. Sex is a two-set class. Race
can be formulated as a two-set class; for example, non-whites and whites. And there’s rich
and poor, old and young, etc. The question I’m asking is, does it matter, for the kinds of
things that can be done with these classes, how many sets they contain? Two-set classes
would seem to have certain kinds of attractions. For example, they’re tremendously easy
to compare. With a two-set class you can apparently make an observation of comparative
lack much more easily than otherwise. And I wonder, for example, whether many kinds of
conflict and perhaps most sorts of revolutions occur by virtue of these two-set classes; as
we say, the haves and the don’t haves. Under such a view, you can see all sorts of different
things being fitted to the notion of the haves and don’t haves. Marx can be seen to have
245
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
this two-set class. The movement for equality of women can be seen to be using it. And
the Negro revolution as well.
To establish a two-set class you might start with one group who you locate as the group
in power, or the haves. Give them a name: Whites, men, the old. And then assimilate all
the others to some predominant feature of those others; for example, a lot of them are
Negro so you call it “the black revolution.” But if you go through the ways revolutions tend
to organize themselves, or the ways movements tend to organize themselves, or notice
that games – which are indeed model conflict situations – are so often either two-party
systems or variants of two-party systems, it begins to look as though formulating in terms
of two-class sets is a method of doing things. Whether this is so or not, I haven’t the vagu-
est idea and it needn’t be taken with any seriousness. But what I said earlier, about this
device as a basic mechanism of social control is, I think, important. If we can come to see
what’s involved in it, I think we can see something useful, and something that’s of theoretical
importance in sociology.
Source: Harvey Sacks (1992a: 47–48), “Lecture 6: The MIR Membership Categorization Device.”
246
7 Class
Introduction
There is a good reason why meat is not murder in capitalist society,
and that is because the institutionalized and industrialized killing of
animals for food for the market does not interfere with the orderly
exchange of labour for wages, nor violate the property rights of either
party – capitalist or worker – in the exchange. On the contrary, the
institutionalized and industrialized killing of animals for food for
the market is organized in and as the orderly exchange of labour
for wages. Notice that the language of analysis has changed from the
previous chapters: “capitalist society,” “market,” “exchange,” “labour,”
“wages,” “property rights,” “capitalist” and “worker” are concepts of
political economy, the home of Marxist sociological analysis. There
is, we think, no better way to introduce Marxist analysis than via an
iconic case of it, namely a passage from the Communist Manifesto. Not
only is the Manifesto perhaps the primordial Marxist document, the
selected passage is quite remarkable for its prescience. It’s as though
Marx and Engels were referring to the neoliberal, corporate-capitalist
“globalization” of our times, and not that of the early industrial capi-
talism of theirs (pre-1848). Accordingly, we invite you to read Box
4 (see also Panitch 2001, especially p. 121). Then consider what was
247
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Modern industry has established the world market, for which the discovery of America paved
the way . . .
. . . the bourgeoisie has at last, since the establishment of modern industry and of the
world market, conquered for itself, in a modern representative state, exclusive political sway.
The executive of the modern state is but a committee for managing the common affairs
of the whole bourgeoisie.
The bourgeoisie, historically, has played a most revolutionary part.
The bourgeoisie . . . has resolved personal worth into exchange value, and in place
of the numberless indefeasible chartered freedoms, has set up that single, unconscionable
freedom — free trade. In one word, for exploitation veiled by religious and political illusions
it has substituted naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation . . .
The need for a constantly expanding market for its products chases the bourgeoisie over the
whole surface of the globe. It must nestle everywhere, settle everywhere, establish connections
everywhere.
The bourgeoisie has through its exploitation of the world-market given a cosmopolitan
character to production and consumption in every country.To the great chagrin of reaction-
ists, it has drawn from under the feet of industry the national ground on which it stood. All
old-established national industries have been destroyed or are daily being destroyed . . . In place
of the old local and national seclusion and self-sufficiency, we have intercourse in every
direction, universal interdependence of nations. . . .
The bourgeoisie, by the rapid improvement of all instruments of production, by the
immensely facilitated means of communication, draws all, even the most barbarian, nations
into civilisation. The cheap prices of commodities are the heavy artillery with which it bat-
ters down all Chinese walls, with which it forces the barbarians’ intensely obstinate hatred of
foreigners to capitulate. It compels all nations, on pain of extinction, to adopt the bourgeois
mode of production; it compels them to introduce what it calls civilisation into their midst,
i.e., to become bourgeois themselves. In one word, it creates a world after its own image.
Source: Marx and Engels (1987 [1848]: 23–25, emphasis added): The Communist Manifesto.
driving the support for Bernie Sanders and Donald Trump in their
2016 US presidential campaigns, not to mention the “success” of
Brexit in the 2016 UK referendum about whether to leave or remain
in the European Union.
But then where and how does crime enter into Marxist analysis?
We invite you now to read a sample of contemporary erudition in
the form of a much-condensed version of Jeffrey Reiman’s (2013)
248
7: CLASS
Marx [1967 (1887)] says that capitalism is a system of “forced labour – no matter how
much it may seem to result from free contractual agreement” [Marx, Capital, vol. 3,
p. 819] . . . [A]s long as it occurs in a context in which a few own all the means of production,
those who do not own the means of production will be compelled to give up some of their
labour without compensation to those who do. Thus, Marx [1967 (1887)] describes the
wage-worker as a “man who is compelled to sell himself of his own free will” (Capital, vol.
1, p. 766) . . . [I]n capitalism, the state uses overt force to protect private property . . . Thus
the state can treat capitalists and workers as having the same or “equal” property rights
over what they own. It just turns out that what capitalists own is means of production, and
what workers happen to own is the muscles in their arms . . .
1. Crime, then, is any violation by one individual of the property rights of another in what-
ever he owns, including his body [because bodily actions are what workers trade with
capitalists for their wages].This explains why the criminal law is primarily directed against
acts of violence, theft and fraud . . .
2. This account also tells us what we are not likely to see as crime in capitalist society,
mainly, exercises of the power inherent in the ownership of property itself. Thus, we
will not generally find that death due to preventable dangers in the workplace will be
taken as murder because that would assume that the worker was somehow forced into
the workplace by the power inherent in his boss’s private ownership of the means of
production. Because that is just the power that is invisible in capitalism, the worker is
taken as freely consenting to his job and thus freely accepting its risks.
Source: Jeffrey Reiman (2013: 227–229, 235–236): “Appendix 1:The Marxian critique of criminal justice.”
249
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
being displayed in the support for Trump and Sanders and Brexit, and
was being explained as the result of
After shifts in the global economy in the 1970s, the economic and
geographic inequality endemic to capitalism deepened and sharp-
ened. In the aftermath of the 2007–2008 crash, when Capitalism Hit
the Fan (Wolff 2013), inequality dramatically increased even further,
to the point that “in [2016] just [8] individuals had the same wealth
as 3.6 billion people – the bottom half of humanity,” while “a global
network of tax havens further enables the richest individuals to hide
$7.6 trillion” (Oxfam 2016: n. p., updated by Oxfam 2017). If capi-
talism was already global long before Marx, the current version that
we know as “globalization” is markedly more so. It has led some to
speak of a “transnational” class of economic actors; namely, the huge
corporations that effectively own the world and run it through both
national governments and international institutions (George 2015;
Harris 2016). We should not be surprised, then, to find equivalent
“globalization” in all aspects of criminalization, and consequently
in criminology. In recent years, Routledge, for example, has pub-
lished handbooks in International Criminology (Smith et al. 2011) and
International Crime and Justice Studies (Arrigo and Bersot 2014), as
well as the International Handbook of Green Criminology (South and
Brisman 2013) that positions the environment in a global context.
These are matters we take up in Chapters 11 and 12. The questions
remain as always, however: what are regarded as the crimes, and who
are regarded as the criminals?
Marxism has its own very particular way of framing, studying and
answering these two fundamental questions. Given the inevitable limi-
tations of a textbook treatment in the face of a formidable amount of
scholarly research in Marxist studies generally, including Marxist sociol-
ogy and Marxist criminology, we will try to stick to essentials in what
follows. Our aim is to bring out what is distinctive about the Marxist
250
7: CLASS
The general result at which I arrived and which, once won, served
as a guiding thread for my studies, can be briefly formulated as
follows: In the social production of their life, men enter into defi-
nite relations that are indispensable and independent of their will,
relations of production which correspond to a definite stage of
development of their material productive forces. The sum total of
these relations of production constitutes the economic structure
of society, the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political
super-structure and to which correspond definite forms of social
consciousness.The mode of production of material life conditions
the social, political, and intellectual life process in general. It is not
the consciousness of men that determines their being, but, on the
contrary, their social being that determines their consciousness.
(Marx 1970 [1859]: 3)
251
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Thus, for example, these groupings may be related in the sense that
one may own the bulk of land and especially capital while the other
may possess only their labour power. Insofar as the means owned or
possessed by each grouping are jointly required for production, then
the two classes may be said to be interdependent. But insofar as the
political domination of the one is built on the economic exploitation
of the other through the extraction of surplus value (i.e. robbing the
252
7: CLASS
The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas,
i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society, is at the
same time its ruling intellectual force.The class which has the means
of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time
over the means of mental production, so that thereby, gener-
ally speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental
production are subject to it.
(Marx and Engels 1970 [1845/1846]: 64, emphasis in original)
253
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
The revolutions that did take place occurred not in capitalist socie-
ties, but in peasant ones. Since early in the twentieth century, then,
Marxist thought has been preoccupied with revising Marxian theory
to account for this failure.
In very general terms, the solution has been sought in an enhanced
role being given to culture (ideas, ideology) in the theory to explain
why people in general and workers in particular fail to see where their
254
7: CLASS
real interests lie, and thus why they fail to take the action required for
their own emancipation. Emancipation from what? From the shackles
of what the first industrialized workers, with deliberate reference to
slavery itself, then being abolished (in the 1820s), called “wage slav-
ery”; that is, taking orders in exchange for a pittance. The argument
is that they are victims of “false consciousness” propagated through
the ideas (culture) disseminated in capitalist society by the “owners
of the means of mental production” (the media) who just happen to
be “the owners of the means of material production” (capital) (Marx
and Engels 1970 [1845/1846]: 64). For example, at the time of writ-
ing, General Electric owned 49 per cent of NBCUniversal, which
includes the NBC television network in the United States.This prob-
lem was the preoccupation of Western Marxism through the first half
of the twentieth century, culminating in the “critical theory” of the
Frankfurt School; some of its members, forced to flee Germany under
Nazism, brought it to the United States shortly before and after World
War II (1939–1945). This train of thought in Marxism later gave rise
to the field known as “Cultural Studies,” which was much taken up
with “communication” and “media” as vehicles of ideology.
If “Western Marxism” was almost entirely a European affair, it
was because a left-inspired organized labour movement had been
crushed in the United States in the first three decades of the twen-
tieth century by state force. No labour party survived in the United
States. Instead, there is effectively a single party in the United States,
what Noam Chomsky calls the “business party,” with two factions,
the Democrats and the Republicans.1 It was not till the 1960s, then,
as part and parcel of the intellectual ferment that was an intrinsic
part of this revolutionary moment, that Marxist sociology, drawing
also on the Frankfurt School’s transplanted critical theory, took off
there. If it is true that large-scale class struggles bent on overturning
capitalism have largely, but not entirely, disappeared from the social
arena, this has not prevented class analysis from continuing to have a
presence in sociological theorizing (see Atkinson 2015). It has also
not meant that widespread social protest has disappeared from the
scene (see the end of this section). Even so, it has been increasingly
the case that practitioners of class analysis have come to supplement
the consideration of class with an appreciation of the importance
of other dimensions of conflict, notably race and gender, but also
religion, ethnicity and nationalism, and then sexual orientation and
255
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
256
7: CLASS
257
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
the state in Marxist theory didn’t fully match the facts. Not all actions
of government and the judiciary were seen to favour directly the
immediate interests of capital.The social legislation which began in the
mid-nineteenth century that shortened the working day and in other
ways regulated the health and safety conditions of work in the factories
of manufacturing industry, and that came to encompass state pensions,
unemployment insurance and welfare provision, public education and
health care, culminated in the post-World War II “welfare state” when,
in the words of then British Prime Minister Harold Macmillan, workers
“never had it so good.” How was Marxist theory to account for this?
The answer was the “structuralist” view of the role of the state.
Structuralist accounts reveal the extent to which the state develops
interests of its own, acts relatively independently of the capitalist class
and, indeed, becomes a site on which the contradictions of capital-
ism – for example, the built-in conflict between capital and labour
– are themselves played out. It is said to enjoy “relative autonomy.”
This kind of emphasis is captured through the frequent use of the
expression, “reproducing capitalist social relations,” to describe the role
of the state in managing class conflict. It also recognizes the extent
to which apparent consensus and working-class consent prevail in
what Marxist analysts would still want to call “class-divided societies”
(Standing 2014). Studies of this type are indebted to the structural
Marxism of Antonio Gramsci, Louis Althusser and Nicos Poulantzas
and the poststructuralism of Foucault (Scraton 1985): for example,
Gramsci’s “concept of hegemony . . . demonstrates how dominance
can be achieved and maintained without the use of direct coer-
cion” (Scraton 1990: 15; see Beckett and Sasson 2000 in section on
“Policing the dangerous classes”). See Box 7.
The conceptual innovation in the structuralist conception consists
of increasing the number of “functions” the state performs for capital
from one to three.These functions are accumulation, legitimation and
coercion. Accumulation retains the original idea of Marx and Engels
that the state, as the instrument of capital, passes laws and otherwise
administers the public purse in ways that favour business.This is done
through the tax system, through grants and loans to corporations and
in a myriad other ways.The new element (even though it was clearly
foreshadowed in Marx’s work) is the emphasis on the role of legitima-
tion, of “selling” to the public in general, and workers in particular,
the idea that they live in the best of all possible worlds. Part of the
258
7: CLASS
The meaning of the term “structural” in “structural Marxism” derives from structural lin-
guistics (Ferdinand de Saussure) where it refers to the system of contrasts (of sounds
and sense) from which any sign gets its meaning, and which then comprise “an underlying
framework of language and meanings whose symbolic systems shape up or ‘structure’ what
individuals can do, albeit unconsciously and unbeknownst to them” (Cuff et al. 1990: xv). We
may say that it structures people’s consciousness or thought processes, or at least the con-
tents of our thought, and thus explains the emphasis given to ideology in structural Marxist
theory. In partial contrast, “structural” in “structural conflict perspective” refers to “how the
organization of the whole society shapes or structures individual behaviour” (Cuff et al.
1990: 128–129, xv; see Williams 1985: 301). The two uses are not unrelated as the ideas
of de Saussure in linguistics were influenced by those of Durkheim in sociology (Cuff et al.
2016: 191–192). Poststructuralism is the movement in philosophy and the human sciences
that takes its point of departure from the notion of structure to be found in structural lin-
guistics and, subsequently, the structural anthropology associated with Claude Lévi-Strauss.
We take it up in Part IV along with Beata Stawarska’s (2015) dramatic revisionist account
of de Saussure’s structuralism as linguistic phenomenology.
259
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
260
7: CLASS
Marxist sociology
Although the term “structural conflict theory” is applied to a vari-
ety of approaches in sociology, it may nevertheless be said that these
positions share in common at least the following two features:
1. any social fact (institution, practice, law . . .) is to be understood by
seeing it in relation to the structure of society as a whole;
2. the structure of society is best described, ultimately, in terms of a
conflict of interests rather than a consensus of values; thus power
is the fundamental societal ingredient; Marxist conflict theory, in
addition, holds that:
3. of the various dimensions (class, status, party, gender, race . . .)
of conflict over power, that between classes (in Marx’s sense) is
fundamental;
4. sociological analysis is intendedly critical of social arrangements,
and directed towards social and political change, usually of a social-
ist nature. Thus we get Marxist or “critical” criminology (Scraton
2007). For example: “It should be clear that a criminology which
is not normatively committed to the abolition of inequalities of
wealth and power, and in particular of inequalities in property
261
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Marxist criminology
Not surprisingly, Marxist or critical or, indeed, “post-critical”
(O’Reilly-Fleming 1996) criminology reflects the theoretical dis-
tinctions to be found in Marxist sociology generally.The former also
has at least one distinction of its own. As Hinch (1987) contends:
262
7: CLASS
263
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
264
7: CLASS
The distinction between “left realism” and “left idealism” has been
used, chiefly by Young, as a way to distinguish earlier, idealist work in
“radical” (Platt and Cooper 1974) or “new” (Taylor et al. 1973) crim-
inology from later, realist studies (Young 1979, 1986; Lea and Young
1984; Matthews and Young 1986; Kinsey et al. 1986). By left idealism,
its critics mean to refer to a combination of (1) an instrumentalist
conception of the state’s use of the legal system as a coercive tool for
criminalizing and putting down working-class opposition (as above);
and (2) what they consider a romanticized image of the criminal and
the deviant in which working-class street crime is seen as overt or
incipient political rebellion. Against this view, exponents of left realism
point out that members of the working class – notably women (see
Fairweather, quoted in Edwards [1990: 148]) – are themselves the
chief victims of working-class crime, and that their voices are among
the loudest of those calling on the state to impose law and order via
the standard means of the law, the courts and the police.
Thus, the current state of affairs in Marxist criminology (see
Matthews 2012), without regard for the impact of poststructuralism
(which we take up in Chapter 10), is one in which the earlier instru-
mentalist emphasis has given ground to two contrasting developments.
The one, left realism, returns to cause-and-cure correctionalism, if
not outright administrative criminology; while the other, embodying
a more structuralist emphasis, continues to provide analyses of the
relations among changes in crime control, the state and the politi-
cal economy of capitalism (Scraton 1985); furthermore, it finds itself
expanding to take in the types of domination based on gender and
race in addition to that founded in class (see Scraton 1987, 1990:
22; Fleming 1985; O’Reilly-Fleming 1996). In summary, Marxist
criminology asks the following questions:
1. What social relations and whose interests are served by the crimi-
nalization of certain forms of behaviour?
2. How are those relations and interests served through the organiza-
tion and operation of police work?
3. How are those relations and interests reproduced in the adminis-
tration of justice through the courts?
4. How are those interests reflected in the organization and operation
of the correctional system?
5. How do the news media and the communications industry
as a whole, acting in the interests of capital, shape the public’s
265
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Criminalization to divide-and-rule:
Comack on the origins of Canada’s drug laws
Empirical observation must in each separate instance bring out
empirically, and without any mystification and speculation, the
connection of the social and political structure with production.
(Marx and Engels 1970 [1845/1846]: 46)
266
7: CLASS
267
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
268
7: CLASS
Conflict between these two principal classes – the capitalists and the
workers – thus describes at its simplest the social relations of that
mode of production known as industrial capitalism.
To elaborate, for British Columbia in the 1880s, increased ration-
alization of the means of production was in part a device used by
the capitalists to de-skill workers and thus reduce whatever control
the latter could exert over the production process. By developing
a “split labour market” – pitting skilled workers against a growing
army of unskilled workers – important divisions are created within
the working class; “divide-and-conquer” is a well-tried method of
class control. Immigration supplied a ready source of cheap, unskilled
labour. For various historical and geographical reasons, it was the
Chinese (but also the Japanese and East Indians) who filled that bill
in late nineteenth-century British Columbia. They were widely
employed in the canneries, mines and, of course, in the construction
of the Canadian Pacific Railway. One partial explanation, then, for
the racial hostility that the Chinese were subjected to throughout
this period is to be found in the resentment of skilled white work-
ers at a group that employers encouraged them to see as the cause
of “wage differentials and conflicts within the workplace” (Comack
1985: 75). The “Chinese question,” as one prominent theme of the
prevailing ideology of the times, is to be understood, then, as “an ideal
expression of the dominant material relationships.”
That the “Chinese question” came to be dealt with through the
criminalization of opium only in 1908 depended on the role the state
played, as the chief actor in the legal and political super-structure,
during this stage in the rise of industrial capitalism. Within Marxist
theory, the state’s function in capitalist society, under the structural-
ist interpretation, is seen to be the reproduction of capitalist social
relations. This involves the three tasks of accumulation, coercion
and legitimation introduced above. Comack confines herself to a
consideration of accumulation and legitimation.
As we have said, “accumulation” refers to the work of creating
the conditions that foster profitable capital growth. This is stand-
ardly achieved through providing grants, loans, tax breaks and the like
to the capitalist class. “Legitimation” refers to the work of securing
the consent of the working class to this (unequal and exploitative?)
social arrangement. It standardly occurs within the context of a liberal
democratic or social democratic framework. This is because such a
269
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
270
7: CLASS
the sea. The state’s problem was now one of legitimation. As Comack
puts it,
271
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
272
7: CLASS
273
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
The principal agents of the state charged with enforcing public order
are, of course, the police. For the Marxist criminologist, the police
are thus not simply neutral keepers of the peace in the general inter-
est, but political agents of state and corporate power whose job it is
to manage, if not suppress, opposition and dissent in the interests of
the ruling class of the day. Using the criminal law where necessary,
their job is to control the “dangerous classes.” It’s no accident, as
Marxist analysis likes to say, that the first modern police organization
was established by the Metropolitan Police Act in 1829 in London,
followed shortly thereafter by similar organizations in the United
States and in Canada. For this period corresponded with the coming
274
7: CLASS
In the United States and Canada, the period between 1880 and 1920
known as the “Progressive Era” “was a critical period in that most
of what we think of as the modern criminal justice system was cre-
ated during this time” (Krisberg 1975: 15). It was a period of mass
immigration, labour strife and urban disorder, giving rise to fears
among the white ruling class that they were being swamped by an
“alien invasion” of inferior and unfit races of people (Europeans).
“The perceived atmosphere of impending doom for the white race
brought forth proposals to sterilize the mentally defective, the insane
and the criminal classes” (1975: 164). It was also the period in which
“much of the modern core of criminology was generated” (1975: 15).
Thus, the “dangerous classes” are the population that the criminal
code and criminal justice system were and are principally designed to
control, and the population whose “criminal behaviour” the standard
causal theories in correctional criminology have been designed to
explain.
The new scientists of crime and crime control were called upon
to construct theories and programs that would enable the domi-
nant elite to cope with real and imagined threats to its hegemony.
Perhaps the most important contribution of the new criminolo-
gists was to justify the ruling class’s overlooking of the relationship
between social injustice and the apparent threat to the social order.
(Krisberg 1975: 165)
That is, theoretical criminology itself has been, and largely continues
to be, a practical enterprise (conducted in the natural attitude with
275
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
In the first half of the twentieth century, Hagan (1980: 617) notes
how, in contrast to alcohol prohibition, “narcotics legislation focused
more narrowly, and more successfully, on minorities of the poor who
could be defined as disreputable.”
276
7: CLASS
my view that the white people, tacitly, have agreed that we’ll let
the police take care of that and that we don’t have to see them, or
we don’t have to hear them.”
(McMartin 1995: A1, quoting Robert A. Jones,
columnist for the Los Angeles Times in the wake of the
verdict in the O. J. Simpson trial; Jones is white.)
The civil and human rights of the people have been at odds with
the property rights of the “landed gentry” for over two centuries.
And in this defining struggle, the FBI, police, et al. are merely the
enforcers for those who write the laws to make their activities
legal and hire the guns to keep the dangerous classes [the poor,
immigrants, ethnic minorities, youth, and dissidents] at bay.
(Editorial, Covert Action Quarterly 1995: 2)
277
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
2014]). The social dynamite are workers, strikers, union activists and
their political representatives, “organized working-class terrorists, or
unemployed youth, especially black youth” (Brake and Hale 1992:
30, referring to the UK), aboriginal groups, visible minority groups,
women’s groups, gays (Kinsman 2010), animal rights militants, uni-
versity students and activists of all sorts. Such groups require special
handling, not just by the regular police, but by the “political police”;
for example, the Canadian Security Intelligence Service (CSIS), the
former RCMP Security Service in Canada, created “as a paramilitary
force often used to control workers and native peoples” (Caputo et al.
1989: 9; Brown, L. and Brown, C. 1978), the FBI in the United States
(Chomsky 1988a: 69–70, 1988b [1975], 1989: 189; Churchill 1991:
103; Churchill and Vander Wall 1988) and the former Special Branch
in the United Kingdom (Bunyan 1977). But it has also come to mean
the “surplus population”:
278
7: CLASS
The Nixon campaign in 1968, and the Nixon White House after
that, had two enemies: the antiwar left and black people. You
understand what I’m saying? We knew we couldn’t make it illegal
to be either against the war or blacks, but by getting the public to
associate the hippies with marijuana and blacks with heroin, and
then criminalizing both heavily, we could disrupt those communi-
ties. We could arrest their leaders, raid their homes, break up their
meetings, and vilify them night after night on the evening news.
Did we know we were lying about the drugs? Of course we did.
(John Ehrlichman, quoted in Baum 2016: para. 2)
279
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Their study seeks to explain the shift from the welfare state to the
“security state.”
Renewed in the 1980s, the War on Drugs caused “an enormous
increase in drug-related (often victimless) crimes and an explosion in
the prison population, reaching levels far beyond that in any industrial
country and possibly a world record, with no detectable effect on
availability or price of drugs” (Chomsky 2000: 81).
“While the War on Drugs only occasionally serves and more often
degrades public health and safety,” a well-informed and insightful
review concludes,“it regularly serves the interests of private wealth:
interests revealed by the pattern of winners and losers, targets and
non-targets, well-funded and underfunded,” in accord with “the
main interests of U.S. foreign and domestic policy generally” and
the private sector that “has overriding influence on policy.”
(Chomsky 2000: 81)
280
7: CLASS
281
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
282
7: CLASS
283
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Class
284
7: CLASS
Box and Hale (1982) show that in England and Wales from 1949 to
1979,“for every 1,000 increase in youth unemployment 23 additional
young males get sent to prison after the effect of crime rates and court
workload have been controlled” (Box 1983: 216, emphasis in original).
The condition is exacerbated for black and other ethnic minority
young men. And what is the purpose of this preference for imprison-
ing the “problem population” of young, working-class, urban (black)
males (and increasingly females)? Given, as we shall see, the extent
to which “crimes of the powerful,” as Marxist criminologists would
call them, go more or less unprosecuted and unpunished, then the
purpose cannot be to control serious crime.
285
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Readers may rightly feel that these data are “old.”We encourage you
to consult more recent or current sources such as the latest edition
of The Rich Get Richer and the Poor Get Prison (Reiman and Leighton
2016), Laureen Snider’s (2015) brief but hard-hitting book on cor-
porate crime in Canada, and Harry Glasbeek’s (2002) thoroughly
illuminating and closely analyzed Wealth by Stealth: Corporate Crime,
Corporate Law, and the Perversion of Democracy. We are confident that
you will find no appreciable differences in disparities, except insofar
as they have become worse. It is also instructive simply to google “top
corporate criminals” or “Corporate Crime Reporter” and bask in the
criminality of the richest and most powerful non-state institutions in
the world, many of which are household names: see especially “Top
100 Corporate Criminals of the 1990s.” At the time of writing, for
example, the Canadian press was reporting both theft of wages and
theft of taxes by employers and the rich.
What Snider and West were saying in 1980 (above) about wage
theft is exactly the case in 2016. According to the interim report
of an Ontario Ministry of Labour research study obtained by The
Toronto Star, not only has no employer in the province been imprisoned
for stealing wages, “less than 0.2 per cent of bosses guilty of mon-
etary violations are ever prosecuted” (Mojtehedzadeh 2016, emphasis
added).
Victims of wage theft across Ontario have lost out on $28 million
over the past six years because the Ministry of Labour failed to
collect the pay owed to them by law-breaking bosses, new statistics
show.
286
7: CLASS
As for theft of taxes, in what was just the latest in a series of “rev-
elations” about “legal” tax avoidance by Canadian corporations, the
Canadian government, in 1980 and again since 2009, was reported as
having established tax treaties with a range of other countries, most
notably Barbados, to act as tax havens for corporations. As of 2015,
C$108.3 billion was parked in these tax havens (Dubinsky 2016).
Notice: this is the state facilitating the profitability of capital.
287
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
288
7: CLASS
289
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
290
7: CLASS
the story in the United States, see Shelden 2008.) The classic trilogy
of class struggle, unemployment and “crime” was thus formed. The
poor turned to “crime” as a means of survival. The authorities then
responded by enacting harsh criminal law to deal with this perceived
threat to social stability and to protect the interests of the new com-
mercial class emerging at this time.Thus the methods of punishment
that became routine at this time were execution, mutilation and
flogging.
The sixteenth century witnessed further changes in the politi-
cal economy that in turn led to new forms of punishment. These
changes included the growth of towns, increased demand for con-
sumer goods, growth of the financial system, expansion of trade and
markets and the conquest of foreign territories. All these added up to
the Age of Mercantilism. However, at the same time, the population
began to decline which meant a decline in the labour pool. This in
turn led to a rise in wages and a consequent decline of manufactur-
ers’ and merchants’ profits. The commercial class therefore appealed
to the state for help. Attempts were made to increase the labour
pool by increasing the birth rate through tax breaks for early mar-
riages and large families, laws prohibiting the clergy from sanctioning
unwed mothers, condemnation of the customary one-year period
of mourning and attempts to stop infanticide. When these were less
than successful, laws were passed forbidding the migration of labour,
fixing maximum wage levels, establishing working hours of between
12 and 16 hours a day, prohibiting worker associations and work stop-
pages and encouraging child labour. Most important, however, was
the introduction of state-sponsored systems of forced labour. Thus,
law violators and others under state supervision were drafted into the
“Houses of Correction.” The acute labour shortage became linked
to the perceived “plague of the beggars” and laws were broadened to
define vagrants to include all who refused to work at prevailing rates.
By the end of the seventeenth century, the “Houses of Correction”
became, in response to economic conditions, a significant part of
penal policy. In them prisoners were forced to work and thus develop
the habits of industry. The Houses were run either by state adminis-
trators or by private contractors. Either way, the inmates were used
to aid private enterprise at a time of labour shortage. This is a prac-
tice that has survived into the twenty-first century, regardless of the
available supply of “free” labour.
291
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
292
7: CLASS
293
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
294
7: CLASS
The “crisis” was manifested in three main ways. First, there was
a breakdown in social relations because of the casualization of the
agricultural proletariat in, speaking of England, the southeastern agri-
cultural counties.This led to rising rates of vagrancy, pauperism, petty
“crime” (our quotes) and riots. Second, there were riots and rising
rates of juvenile “crime” (our quotes) in London, a state of affairs with
which the existing constabulary could not cope.Third, in the north-
ern industrial regions, labour markets tied to single industries like
cotton were vulnerable to the cycles of demand in international trade.
In “bad years,” this led to a breakdown in labour market discipline. In
these circumstances, the new policy of mass imprisonment was seen
as a potentially effective response to the breakdown in public order.
Even though there may have been a coincidence of interest among
the reformers and the bourgeoisie, it is important to remember, as
Ignatieff reminds us, that the reformers did not justify their program
as a response to the problems of labour discipline during this time
of crisis. The reformers’ ideas antedate these discipline problems by
a substantial period of time. Consequently, it would be incorrect to
reduce the emergence of the penitentiary to the economic interests
and problems of the bourgeoisie at this time of crisis. On the other
hand, of course, it is difficult to imagine that the reformers would
have succeeded in implementing their program “if the authorities had
not believed they were faced with the breakdown of a society of sta-
ble ranks and the emergence of a society of hostile classes” (Ignatieff
1983 [1981]: 90).
In sum, then, in Ignatieff ’s account, we find that the rise of the
penitentiary is explained not solely in instrumental terms. Ignatieff
does not, as do Rusche and Kirchheimer, account for the emergence
of the prison solely in terms of its instrumental “functions” for the
industrial capitalists. Rather, it is a more structuralist account and
seeks to incorporate an independent domain of ideas into its explana-
tory approach. To be sure, the emergence of the prison is not then
explicable in a simplistic idealist fashion. Ideas are important, it seems,
when viewed in conjunction with the forces of economic interests
and problems of class relations. As Ignatieff puts it,
the new carceral system was not the work of an overarching stra-
tegic consensus by a ruling class, but instead fell into place as a
result of a conjuncture between transformation in the phenomena
295
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
The work of Marxist theorists and their thesis that the function of the
prison is one of discipline and mystification has also been applied to
the contemporary prison. Thus, Fitzgerald (1977) compares what he
calls the “official functions” of the prison with those that are visible
from a Marxist point of view. From the official point of view, the
functions are reformation and rehabilitation, protection of society,
deterrence and punishment. Of course, of these the only one that is
successfully achieved is the last. Thus, prisons do not rehabilitate or
reform, they do not protect society because prisoners typically learn
from each other how to be “better” criminals, and they do not seem
to be very effective deterrents, reflected in the extremely high rates of
recidivism. However, from a Marxist point of view, prisons do appear
to be quite successful in some respects. Thus, Fitzgerald points out
that they serve a “sanitation function” insofar as they remove from
view those unproductive and recalcitrant elements created by the
social structural arrangements of capitalist society. Indeed, in some
Latin American cities, police forces have taken upon themselves the
task of “social cleansing” more directly by murdering, for example,
indigent youth trying to eke out an existence on the streets (see,
for example, Graham 2016). Furthermore, by sentencing individ-
ual offenders, the prison permits the “individualization” of crime
and therefore strengthens the individualistic ideology so central to
capitalism. Criminals are thus defined as “failures” in the “normal”
competition characteristic of capitalist society. This serves to mys-
tify the political character of eliminating such persons. The prison
may also be said to serve a “distraction” function insofar as the mas-
sive incarceration of largely petty offenders from underprivileged
and minority groups diverts attention away from the “criminality”
of the rule-makers and the “crimes” of the powerful. Punishment
of lower-class offenders also serves to distract attention from acts
which are much more harmful to the population at large, but which
are not criminalized. Finally, prison can be seen to serve a “symbolic
function” in that it represents what is currently conceived as “good”
296
7: CLASS
297
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
298
7: CLASS
299
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
In other words, then, the state can be seen to have its own “authori-
tarian agenda” and “vision of order” (Ignatieff 1978), which cannot
be simplistically tied to the immediate interests of the economically
powerful.
In addition, far from being “economically rational,” in structuralist
terms, the expansion of the prison system and the containment of
increasing numbers of “offenders” within it can be seen to contrib-
ute to the contradictions of capitalism. We note briefly three ways in
which the growth of punishment described above embodies “struc-
tural” contradictions. First, by expanding the prison system and by
incarcerating ever-increasing numbers of prisoners within it, the state
contributes to the very problem of overcrowding in prisons that the
expansion was designed (in part) to alleviate. Second, at a time of
fiscal crisis, and with cuts in public expenditure high on the political
agenda, it is contradictory to spend more and more money punishing
people. Such a policy serves to deepen the fiscal crisis. Third, given
the crime-producing tendencies of incarceration, the expansion of
the prison system serves to create more and more criminals, a process
which, incidentally, costs more and more to control.
300
7: CLASS
301
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
302
7: CLASS
rank, top and bottom classes, people of low, medium and high station,
plural versions of many of the foregoing, and more you can probably
think of and think up. For we language users don’t stop. To repeat
a fundamental point from Chapter 1: “Language is an instrument.
Its concepts are instruments” (Wittgenstein 1972 [1953]: 569). We
use them for doing things, for performing actions. As instruments
or tools, concepts or words can be modified, extended, re-tooled.
And in any use, their meaning will be informed by the context of
their use. Thus have people from the dawn of time used language to
mobilize one another in support of political goals defined in such
terms as fairness (say, in the price of bread), justice, liberty, equality
or solidarity, independently of whether or not they had a theory on
which to hang their claims.
303
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
social position is made rather than merely inherited” (1985: 61). And
it made and makes a difference whether a particular item in this
vocabulary of terms is avowed by, or ascribed to, a person or group
(see Jayyusi 1984; Eglin and Hester 1992). In the one use, a person
may invoke the concept of class to make a proud declaration of self-
identity. In the other use, an insult or putdown may be intended:
“Around 1830, class became an essentially relational concept, a social
epithet aimed at establishing distance in interactions, at including
or excluding people as belonging or not belonging to the speaker’s
world” (Gobo 1993: 473). Sacks points out, for example, that for the
MCD “class,” as for age,
Except ironically, one does not hear “lower class” applied by a person
to him- or herself; it is more readily used in sneering contempt for
others to whom the speaker fancies him- or herself superior. It’s not
so much a description as an evaluation of the other.
To get greater purchase on the grammar of the concept of class,
we turn to a study in ethnomethodological conversation analysis of
the interactional use of language. Why? Because in EM/CA,
To be sure, in the case that follows, the words “social class” do not
appear, but the concept that they name may readily be inferred from
the use of other terms in the family of concepts of which “social
class” is a member. In the case at hand, it is clear enough that class or
class-related matters are the basis of the public defender’s pitch for a
reduced sentence for the defendant.
304
7: CLASS
PD2: See, here’s his problem. The guy lives and works in South
Beach, he’s got a good job, well, least he’s working, he supports
his family, wife and kids, and it’s his third drunk driving offense.
And, uh, if he does 75 days straight time, he’s going to lose his job,
his wife’s going to be on – kids, you know – family’s going to be
on welfare.
(Maynard 1984: 157)
305
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
306
7: CLASS
About “half of all family law litigants have no lawyer” (2014: A8).
As cases become longer and more expensive, only those earning less
than half the minimum wage are eligible for legal aid in Ontario. One
307
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
superior court judge said “that the country’s courts were becoming
‘only open to the rich’” (2014: A8).
308
7: CLASS
309
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
way his daughter did. It was Eleanor who really carried on the fam-
ily business” (Rachel Holmes [2014], quoted in Hunter 2015: IN2).
It is true that those who own the least may suffer more when
what they have is stolen, because they are losing a much greater
percentage of their worldly goods in this one transaction than a
middle- or upper-class person, who has property in many differ-
ent forms and locations, would be. The real basis for comparison
310
7: CLASS
here is not how much is lost per theft, but which class has more
to lose? Which would be the most threatened if 50-80 percent of
their wealth were to be confiscated, by land redistribution or by
revolution? Only then is it obvious how much our present sys-
tem of laws safeguards the institutions of private property, which
allows the most privileged to preserve, protect, and pass on their
vast enclaves of wealth.
(Snider 1988: 312)
311
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
312
7: CLASS
313
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Exercises
Review questions
314
7: CLASS
Further reading
Glasbeek, Harry. 2002. Wealth by Stealth: Corporate Crime, Corporate
Law, and the Perversion of Democacy. Toronto, ON: Between the
Lines. Crystal-clear, undogmatic, Marxist analysis of the “corporate
advantage” and its deleterious political consequences.
Reiman, Jeffrey and Paul Leighton. 2016. The Rich Get Richer and
the Poor Get Prison: Ideology, Class, and Criminal Justice. Eleventh
edition. London UK: Routledge. Elegant, precisely documented
and damning Marxist-informed analysis of the US criminal justice
system.
Snider, D. Laureen. 2015. About Canada: Corporate Crime. Black Point,
NS and Winnipeg, MB: Fernwood. Brief, hard-hitting account.
Notes
1 See www.brainyquote.com/quotes/quotes/n/noamchomsk447305.html
(Accessed 10 July 2016).
2 Thanks go to Tim Bousquet, editor of the Halifax Examiner, for the refer-
ence to Walker’s piece. See “In the Harbour” in the issue for 15 July 2016:
www.halifaxexaminer.ca/featured/nova-scotia-wants-to-spend-several-
billion-dollars-on-new-highways-morning-file-friday-july-15-2016/
(Accessed 15 July 2016).
315
8 Gender
316
8: GENDER
from the internal chains which suppressed them and with which they
suppressed themselves. “The personal is the political” was its slogan,
“consciousness-raising” its particular method. The target was “patri-
archy” (rule of the fathers), the source of those external and internal
bonds. Feminists’ goal was and is not simply to name and understand
this institution, but to destroy it. (In this endeavour they are joined
by many pro-feminist men who seek to throw off their own shack-
les.) Their efforts have had the profound effects already mentioned.
Nevertheless, given at least the continuing global wage gap between
men and women, the recurrent reports across the Western world of
sexism in countries’ military, police and fire services, of sexual assault
and misogyny on university campuses and of sexual harassment every
where, the project remains incomplete and continues to be pressed
forward. The third wave has sought to assert claims for recognition
by and for diverse groups within and without the women’s move-
ment based on racial and sexual identity.The charge contained in the
following headline is representative of the third wave: “Today’s femi-
nist problem? Black women are still invisible” (Anderson 2016). The
so-called fourth wave appears devoted to “calling-out” misogyny and
sexism in social media. There can be no doubt that it is second-wave
feminism from the 1960s onwards that has had the profoundest effect
on the academy in general and professional sociology in particular,
and this includes the sociology of crime.
317
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
318
8: GENDER
319
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
then we have the kind of Marxist feminism exhibited in this classic work
of Dorothy Smith. Her thesis is that women’s situation is related to the
family’s place in corporate capitalist society. The thesis is developed
in a sequence of arguments.
1. Capitalist society differentiates the institutional orders that both ordi-
nary members of society and professional functionalist sociologists
take for granted and think of as universal; namely, the economy, the
government, the family, and cultural and community organizations
(the AGIL). In so doing, it externalizes them; that is, makes them
appear as if their existence is independent of the people (individu-
als) who make them up and whose activities make them happen. It
is tempting then to see them as separate spheres of social action and
ask how they are related: for example, was the nuclear family a cause
of industrialization, or was it the other way round? This misses,
Smith argues, how their “separation” is a product of the capitalist
mode of production itself; this origin in fact unites them.
2. The differentiation and externalization of the economy and the
family have different consequences for men and women. Drawing
on Marx’s concept of alienation, she writes, “The same moment
which alienates the worker alienates also the women, although
in a different way” (Smith 1977 [1973]: 18). That is, the historical
emergence of the capitalist enterprise separates workplace from
home. The workplace is in the realm of the public; the home is the
realm of the private. Women are assigned to the private sphere of
domestic activity. Women’s work becomes a “private service” to
their husbands.
3. Functionalist sociology has failed to make these connections. It
assumes as necessary and universal what is in fact contingent and
particular. This is particularly true of Smelser’s (1959) analysis
of the relationship of the family to industrialization in terms of
Parsons’s AGIL: “What is made possible by [functionalist] proce-
dure is the treatment of a version of the family which is special to
our historical time and to our relations of production as if it were
a universal form of the family” (1977 [1973]: 21). That is, Smelser
treats the relation between the bourgeois family and the capitalist
enterprise as if it were a universal relationship between family
and economy. “It is clear he is describing a form of the family as a
service organization to the occupational performance” (1977 [1973]: 22,
emphasis added):
320
8: GENDER
321
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
322
8: GENDER
323
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
324
8: GENDER
Feminist criminology
“There never has been nor is there one feminist movement . . . Nor is
there one feminist criminology or feminist approach to law” (Edwards
1990: 145). It is not our intention, nor do we have the competence, to
survey this entire body of work (see Chesney-Lind and Morash 2011;
Renzetti 2012; Downes et al. 2013; Smart 1990, 1977; Gelsthorpe
and Morris 1990; Valverde 1991; Carlen and Worrall 1987; Naffine
1987). Rather, as we said at the outset of the book, our intention is
to present work that exhibits itself as representative of a given genre
through selected, perspicuous examples. Our goal is, once again, to
show what professional sociology in its various guises can and does
contribute to our knowledge and understanding of crime.
That said, we recognize that criminology and this book itself are
open to the charge of sexism insofar as they found themselves on
the distinction between crime and tort (that is, between criminal
325
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
law and civil law), and between crime and mental illness, in order to
deal only with crime. For to the extent that the crime/tort distinc-
tion marks a further distinction between public and private wrongs,
and women’s lives and actions have been traditionally assigned to the
private sphere, as Smith argues above, then to deal with crime is to
deal overwhelmingly with men’s lives and actions, and to marginal-
ize women’s. Allowing for the regulation of women’s occupational,
reproductive and sex lives exercised traditionally by the criminal laws
of prostitution, abortion and rape, then control of women, it may be
argued, resides primarily in other areas of state jurisdiction, notably
the laws and practices regulating employment, welfare, health, and
family and matrimonial life (see, for example, Brophy and Smart
1985; Smith 1990: chapter 5). Nevertheless, as we have said, there is
a range of vigorous feminist contributions to the sociology of crime
– including articles in such journals as Feminist Criminology, Violence
Against Women, Women & Criminal Justice and the Canadian Journal
of Women and the Law – and it is to these that we selectively attend.
Although not so evident in actual criminological studies, the theo-
retical distinctions among inclusionist, separationist and transgressive
forms of emancipatory theory according to Cuff et al. (2016) are
paralleled for feminist criminological theory by Smart (1990) who
distinguishes empiricist feminism, standpoint feminism and postmod-
ern feminism. We endeavour to illustrate the first two in this chapter
and the third in the Introduction to Part IV.
As we said in the Introduction to Part III, the received picture
of “crime” amongst the general public, in the news media, in poli-
tics and in correctional criminology, what people generally mean
when they talk of crime or the “crime problem,” is one that identifies
“crime” with street crime. The corresponding picture of the “crimi-
nal” is of a person whose perceived habitat is the street, one who is
young, poor, male and black or aboriginal. Although they may be
men’s (invisible) companions, women and girls are generally absent
from the picture, except for specific areas of “crime”; namely, abor-
tion, prostitution, partner-killing and rape, or some notable departure
from expected behaviour such as “girl gangs.” In partner-killing and
rape, women and girls occupy that ambiguous position in which they
are at once both the victim and the offender (see Ferraro 2006: 1).
Whereas Marxist criminology focuses on explaining why the official
criminal is poor, and neocolonial perspectives focus on explaining
326
8: GENDER
327
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
328
8: GENDER
Since, under patriarchy, women and girls are not legal persons, but
rather the property of their husbands and fathers, their actions are not
their own, but those of their owners. (This parallels Smith’s analysis
of the role of the middle-class manager in the corporation as we
saw above: what he does becomes its actions.) Further, since, under
the patriarchal rule of the state, females are assigned to the realm of
the private, and criminal law does not cross the parlour threshold,
nothing done there constitutes crime. Thus, the actions of women
and girls are not criminalized (nor, of course, is male domestic vio-
lence). This explains, in a rather different fashion than Durkheim’s
account above (see “Feminist social theory”), the general absence
of women and girls from the received picture of crime. Let us then
consider why women are criminalized in relation to abortion and
rape.
Given that the state also has interests in maintaining the structures
of dominance based on class and race, its efforts to regulate and con-
trol women may give rise to contradictions (again, see Chapter 7) that
it then has to try and resolve through policy-making and law-making.
In the matter of abortion, since, under the patriarchal organization of
state societies, the primary function of women and girls is patriarchal
reproduction (sons! sons!), then controlling and regulating both their
fertility and sexuality is a critical task. But since this task is compli-
cated by the interest in having the right class and race of women
reproduce, contradictions can arise in practice as to the appropriate
policies to pursue.
329
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
The way that rape has been treated in the criminal justice system fol-
lows from the treatment of women as patriarchal property. The male
owner typically cannot be charged with committing a “crime” against
his wife and daughter since she is his property. Since a woman is not
a person, she has no legal status and no basis upon which to claim
legal protection. A “crime” against a woman is, then, a crime against
her owner. Patriarchy protects the owner of a woman by keeping her
outside the legal system.The owner of a woman can seek legal redress
from any man who damages her as he can with respect to damage
to any of his property; rape is thus a property offence. This explains
both the criminalization of rape, including the long sentences it has
traditionally carried, and the acute selectivity of its enforcement –
only respectable women, that is, valuable patriarchal property, can
get convictions. Other complainants are treated as if they themselves
are the problem, as Edwards’s (1990) analysis of nineteenth- and
twentieth-century UK practice so clearly shows. This viewpoint
may seem dated to some, but it is generally accepted that we are still
dealing with the historical residue of such institutionalized practices
across the Western world; and in other places, the subjugation of
women in general has only partially abated. Susan Brownmiller (in)
famously asserts a more radical position: rape is “a conscious process
of intimidation by which all men keep all women in a state of fear”
in that “rape became not only a male prerogative, but man’s basic
weapon of force against women” (Brownmiller 1975: 5). Whichever
analysis is correct, it remains the case that, despite an initial increase
in the reporting of sexual assault in the wake of legal changes in
response to the feminist critique, the rates of reporting, prosecuting
and convicting for sexual assault continue to vastly underrepresent
the self-reported figure. According to Canadian official statistics,
“of every 100 incidents of sexual assault, only 6 are reported to the
police” (SexAssault.ca: n. p.); other studies report a figure of about
330
8: GENDER
331
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
332
8: GENDER
333
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
334
8: GENDER
over the working class (and the middle class, although their
control is conceived differently), since these habits of abstinence
and puritanism are still crucial to maintaining a controllable labour
force and a manageable populace.
(Snider 1985: 348–349)
Sentencing studies
The same interest on the part of the state to keep the population
under control and to discipline it, which was revealed by Marxist
studies in Chapter 7 and again by Snider’s study of rape law reform
above, is repeated in the findings of sentencing studies with respect
to gender. As with the attribute of unemployment, both mitigation
and aggravation have been found. Thus:
335
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
336
8: GENDER
337
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
338
8: GENDER
339
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
340
8: GENDER
Maria Wowk was a student of Rod Watson, who was a student of Wes
Sharrock, who, with John Lee, more or less founded the Manchester
(UK) school of ethnomethodology, based on their reading of Garfinkel
and Sacks. Wowk applies Sacks’s work in MCA to an understanding
of how we, as members of society, use categories of gender and eve-
ryday knowledge of sexual politics as devices for particular practical
purposes in our interaction with one another.
341
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
DATA APPENDIX
(All names of people and places have been changed
in the interests of confidentiality)
.....
107 P Alright continue
108 S hhh I kept walking (.3) and (.8) I got to the
109 intersection (.2) of Brookland and Slade (1.0) when this
110 girl walked up to me (.6) and propositioned me
111 (1.0)
112 P what did she exactly say to you Lewis?
113 S you look like a tough guy (1.2) y'look like the member
114 of a gang
115 (1.2)
116 S I told her I’m not a member of a gang (.) I'm an
117 independent (.7) and she propositioned me again
118 (1.2)
119 S I asked her (.3) if she'd like to go to a party (.5)
120 she said yes
120a P what did she ask actually say to you
121 S hh hh
122 P ye you can word it (.) use rr (.3)
123 (.3)
124 S she asked me if I would like to get laid
125 P (some of the) words
126 (1.0)
127 P alright
128 (1.2)
129 P now (.) where was this intersection that you ran
130 into this girl
131 (.3)
132 S hh (.) Brookland and Slade (.5) right across from the
133 Fuller library
134 (.7)
135 P alright
..........
147 P alright (.2) (then) what happened after she (.) propositioned
148 (sound of movement)
149 you
150 (.6)
151 S well as I said I asked her if she'd like to go to a party
152 she said yes (.2) hh so I said well come on
153 P alright (.) and where did you go?
..........
171 P Okay (.) is er (.3) and what happened after you arrived (.)
172 with the girl at two ten Portland
173 (.3)
174 S arr there were several people that I knew
175 (1.2)
176 P could you give their names?
177 S arr this was (.) this one guy (.2) Walley (.3) another one
178 Ricky (.6) I don't know their last names
179 P alright
180 (.5)
342
8: GENDER
343
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Notice that he does this without himself using the name “slut”
or “tramp” to refer to her, thereby avoiding creating the impression
that he himself regularly associates with such disreputable types or
can tell one when he sees one. Rather, he can be seen to be claiming
innocence in the matter of such women. He uses the euphemisms
“propositioned” and “the girl got (.8) might say kind of (.2) pricky
(1.0) and er” (214–215), indicating reluctance to say in so many words
what the “girl” actually said. He quotes her actual, cruder words –
“asked me if I would like to get laid” (124) and “called me a prick
hh (.) a no good sonofabitch” (221–222) – only when solicited by P.
Moreover, his story of the encounter is one in which the events in
the narrative follow one another in the same order as they purport-
edly happened in the world, and in that narrative, the protagonist
is always the “girl.” She is presented as the one taking the initiative
in the encounter from walking up to him and propositioning him
to throwing the remainder of a bottle of beer at him. Insofar as one
who embarks on a course of action necessarily bears at least some of
the responsibility for how it turns out, S can be seen to be shifting
(some of) the responsibility for the outcome to the victim herself
through his use of this storytelling format. Moreover, he enhances that
blameworthiness by having it that she propositioned him.
In Wowk’s analysis, we can see how gender attributes and sexual poli-
tics are being used by a member of society in a particular interactional
context to achieve a practical end, here the shifting of responsibility
and blame for a death and thereby the mitigation of his guilt in its
occurrence. Rather than a theory of patriarchy (male dominance
of females) being used by the feminist sociologist to explain some
purportedly “given” facts about the gendered character of social life,
Wowk shows how the parties to the interaction, chiefly the suspect,
344
8: GENDER
PD1: On the face of it, it looks pretty bad. But investigating the
case comes up with some beautiful defences that I’m anxious to
go to trial on, if the DA is. Situation is this: she’s a 65-year-old
lady, speaks, uh, Castilian Spanish, she’s from Spain. Uh, she goes
into Davidson’s – Oh incidently, by way of background, for 20
years she’s worked in the Catholic Church of San Ramon as the
housekeeper for the nuns and the fathers and all this stuff, and
very religious, well known. I’ve interviewed half of San Ramon
concerning her background.Wonderful lady, no problem, 65 years
old. But on this particular occasion, she goes into Davidson’s, goes
into a fitting room, pins them up underneath her dress, and leaves.
(Maynard 1982a: 356)
Here PD1 explicitly invokes gender in the form of the morally speci-
fied term “lady,” the opposite, one might say, of “slut” or “tramp.” But
its meaning on this occasion of its use is not independent of the other
attributes used to describe the defendant; namely, her age, religiosity,
ethnicity and occupation. She’s not just a woman, but a very reli-
gious, 65-year-old, Castilian-Spanish-speaking lady who works as a
housekeeper at a Catholic church. Together these attributes establish
a type of person for whom shoplifting can be seen to be entirely
“out of character,” an anomaly. In subsequent talk, the PD explains
the anomaly by reporting that the defendant was taking pain-killing
drugs that can “cause a state of confusion, delirium, and put the per-
son in a situation where they’re just in a dream world” (1982a: 356).
Moreover, Maynard adduces data from another case to suggest what
role the mentioning of the defendant’s language capacity is playing
here. It is to project for the DA how the defendant will “look” in
345
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
court testifying “in his native tongue” where, as DA3 puts it in that
case, “Why is there that – that feeling that if they can’t speak the lan-
guage they can harbour no malice or – or criminal intent” (Maynard
1982b: 205).
In other words, we see gender here being adduced, in combina-
tion with other attributes, to project a type of person who is not
really a criminal, and who will not look like a criminal in court, for
the purpose of advancing a disposition (“PD1: Want it dismissed”
[Maynard 1982a: 356]) in an environment of negotiation. Like the
other attributes, gender is not being adduced abstractly, in a checklist
fashion, but, as we said in Chapter 7, selectively and contextually, by
the parties to the setting themselves, in relation to the activities in
which they are engaged.
346
8: GENDER
that Matoesian calls “resumptive repetition.” . . . [I]t illustrates that the outcome of rape-trials
cannot simply be accounted for by “patriarchy,” or by a speech-exchange system in which
lawyers have the right to ask questions. “Patriarchy” in ethnomethodological terms can be
understood as a diverse set of cultural understandings about the relationship between
men and women that are widely shared in society, and can become highly consequential
in rape trials . . . In this case, the cross-examination drew upon culturally-shared knowledge
about the relationship between the categories “women” and “rapists,” that would lead us
to expect that a woman would not go for a walk in the darkness with someone who had
just raped her friend. This kind of exchange may be decisive in determining the outcome
of other trials involving rape or sexual assault . . .
Source: Max Travers (1997b: 133): “Introduction to Part II” in M. Travers and J. F. Manzo, Law in Action.
Conclusion
What we are saying, then, is that in keeping with professional theo-
retical sociology in general, feminist criminology misses how gender
operates across the various moments of criminalization by relying
on the same taken-for-granted methods that members in the course
of everyday life use to see everyday life as gendered (Garfinkel 1967:
116–185; Kessler and McKenna 1978; Button 1991; see Francis et al.
to appear; Eglin 2002). The principal method in use is simply the
two-category set or membership categorization device consisting
of the categories male and female (even as the third category of
“transgendered” is being adopted). To this basic set of categories a
whole range of predicates may be and are attached as circumstances
warrant, and for the practical purposes that members and theorists
have. Such predicates can include attitudes, knowledge, competences,
etc., including relationships, say, of subordination. Insofar as academic
feminism arises from and seeks to carry forward the political move-
ment of women’s emancipation, then it is hard not to agree with
Sacks (see Box 3) that this two-category set has been and continues
to be an essential weapon in the conceptual armoury of that strug-
gle. It is our view, however, that it is precisely its recourse to this
membership categorization device that stands in the way of feminist
criminology being able to see how gender itself is made to work in
relation to crime and criminalization. We conclude by revisiting the
studies reviewed above in the light of this critical stance.
347
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
348
8: GENDER
349
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
This would apply then to Worrall’s observation that the attribute crimi-
nality is bound to the category male (or masculine). Sacks elaborates
as follows:
350
8: GENDER
Exercises
1. By consulting your local, provincial, state or national crime statis-
tics, document the gender distribution of total criminal offences,
crimes of violence and non-violent crimes for a recent five-year
or ten-year period. Describe the distribution for each of the three
categories. Break the distributions down by age category. Which
sub-population defined by gender and age is the most criminal
and the most violent? Which is the least?
2. Using the same or related statistical sources, document the attri-
tion through the criminal justice system of sexual assault, following
Johnson’s model in the chapter.
Review questions
1. How does feminist theory account for the general absence of
women from involvement in crime?
2. How does the feminist theory of patriarchy come to regard rape
as a property crime?
3. What was “contradictory” about the experience of women in
prison studied by Carlen (1983)?
4. Explain in your own words what Sacks (1992a) means by “knowl-
edge protected against induction.”
Further reading
Chesney-Lind, Meda and Merry Morash. Eds. 2011. Feminist Theories
of Crime. The Library of Essays in Theoretical Criminology.
Farnham, UK: Ashgate. For the full range of feminist thought on
crime not covered in this chapter.
Balfour, Gillian and Elizabeth Comack. Eds. 2014. Criminalizing
Women: Gender and (In)justice in Neo-Liberal Times. Second edition.
Halifax, NS and Winnipeg, MB: Fernwood Publishing.
351
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
352
9 Race
A black friend told me . . . that she selects her clothes so that she
doesn’t look threatening to white people.
(Richardson 2016: para. 7)
Perhaps by the time you are reading this book, the subject of this
chapter will have resumed its social position as one of those issues that
for the most part resides just below the surface of public conscious-
ness and discourse, though occasionally bursting into prominence
for a short time in connection with some horrific incident. At
the time of writing (2016), however, and as graphically illustrated
in the epigraphs above, race had been occupying the public con-
versation for some considerable time both in the English-speaking
world and in continental Europe. See, for example, the Winter 2016
issue of Canadian Dimension devoted to “Racism.” Or simply watch
this “traffic stop”: www.youtube.com/watch?v=3P9-BjYxTu8
(accessed 15 July 2016). According to the first comment on this
video, from August 2015, “Denver Police cleared all the officers of
wrongdoing and they remain on the force today. The Denver City
Council quietly approved an out of court settlement with the fam-
ily for [$]795,000.00.” African Americans are, once again, in their
centuries-long struggle to gain recognition of their basic humanity
from Europeans and their white colonial transplants, having to assert
that “Black Lives Matter,” and having to deal with the often rac-
ist response to that declaration. The following video is instructive:
353
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
www.youtube.com/watch?v=jQ_0bqWKO-k&list=PLnvZ3PbKAp
GM-hHuQ9lNc5oSKsusjn0Z6 (accessed 15 July 2016). Their resis-
tance is being directed particularly at the horrific killing of young
black men by police in the United States (Schenwar et al. 2016).
Arabic/Muslim citizens of “Euro-world” (Europe, Canada and
the United States, Australia and New Zealand) continued to be the
victims of Islamophobia, including the grotesque, quasi-fascist pro-
nouncements of the Republican candidate in the 2016 US presidential
election. And throughout the world, but notably in Canada, Australia
and the United States, not to mention the Occupied Territories of
Palestine, the indigenous peoples of settler colonialist societies were
forcing on their white rulers the demand that they finally come to
terms with their racist pasts and presents. Official apologies, truth
and reconciliation commissions, plus other commissions of inquiry
into particular oppressions (residential schools, missing and murdered
aboriginal women, discrimination in the provision of child welfare
services) filled the airwaves. In all cases, lawsuits and criminal trials
kept the subject alive in the public mind. From university campuses
in the United States, United Kingdom and Canada, to the Canadian
RCMP, to the UK, US and Canadian governments themselves, major
institutions were having to address the stubborn refusal of “systemic
racism” and racist practices to go away.1
And yet the criminals in society are widely perceived by white,
hard-working, God-fearing, property-owning, tax-paying citizens
to be those who have been traditionally coloured as black, brown,
red, and in an earlier time, yellow. (If you are offended by the col-
our references here, listen to them in the last verse of the song
“Everyday People” by Sly and the Family Stone.) East Asians no
longer bear that stigma (so much), but the rest continue to do so.
These are the categories of person who are feared and from whose
imagined threats to its safety white society organizes to protect itself
(Reiman and Leighton 2013: 69; Kappeler and Potter 2005: 33–34).2
The popular/official street criminal is black (see the Introduction
to Part III), the popular/official terrorist brown, the popular/official
drag on society red. And there is evidence to support such views.
While Arabs/Muslims are subjected to special scrutiny only in rela-
tion to suspected involvement in terrorism, people of African and
aboriginal descent are significantly over-represented in the crimi-
nal justice system in general. From police apprehensions to court
354
9: RACE
African-Canadian experience
355
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
356
9: RACE
357
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
But then 140 years before 1995, the black Canadian abolitionist
Samuel Ringgold Ward writes,
358
9: RACE
exclusion of Jews and the turning away of the ship, the St Louis,
carrying Jewish refugees from the Nazis in 1939 and so on. Walker
(1997) tells the story of racism’s legal history in his “Race,” Rights
and the Law in the Supreme Court of Canada. An artistic version is ren-
dered in James Rolfe and George Elliot Clarke’s remarkable opera
Beatrice Chancy, while students should not pass up the Canadian soci-
ological classic, Africville by Clairmont and Magill (1999). Canadians
are better acquainted, it often seems, with the story of slavery in
the American South and the continuing racism entrenched in US
society.
359
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
for an aboriginal girl to party with, and when Betty Osborne refused,
they took her out of town and killed her. The inquiry found rac-
ism in the RCMP’s investigation of the case. The first suspects to
be rounded up were aboriginal youths, some of whom were taken
away for questioning without the consent of their parents. The non-
aboriginal suspects in the case were not subjected to the indignities
and insensitive treatment that the aboriginal people received at the
hands of the police. Racism and the racial segregation of the town
of The Pas were partly responsible for the silence of the people who
knew the identity of the assailants – a silence which resulted in the
16-year delay in bringing suspects to trial and which continued to
protect the identity of two of the four men involved in the crime.The
inquiry also identified racism in the jury selection process. Ultimately,
one man only was convicted of any crime (York and Roberts 1991a;
Valpy 2015).
The second case was that of the fatal shooting of aboriginal leader,
J. J. Harper, by a constable of the Winnipeg Police Department in
March 1988 (Sinclair 1999). The inquiry found negligence in the
investigation by the police department which was primarily con-
cerned with vindicating the police by constructing a version of events
in which Mr Harper could be blamed for his own death. In addition
to negligence, the inquiry found racism in the police department,
expressed in jokes and racist slurs (York and Roberts 1991b). The
report of the inquiry revealed that aboriginal people, while compris-
ing 11.8 per cent of Manitoba’s population, represented at least 50
per cent of its prison population. Two paragraphs from the report
summarize its findings:
360
9: RACE
361
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
The reporting evidently had its effect. Five months later, the then
recently elected liberal Canadian government was recognizing that
too many people were in prison and that thoroughgoing reform was
needed. Even as official violent crime rates fell to their lowest level
in 50 years, the number incarcerated in federal prisons had risen 17
per cent between 2006 and 2016 during conservative Prime Minister
Harper’s time in office. One participant in a group assembled by
the liberal Minister of Justice to brainstorm the issue summarized
the views of others at the meeting: “There’s too many people in
jail . . . There’s too many First Nations in jail.There’s too many people
with mental-health issues. There’s too many women in jail. There’s
too many vulnerable in jail.” (Fine 2016: para. 12).
362
9: RACE
363
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
the police and Sheriff ’s deputies have used excessive force in a dis-
turbing number of cases in recent years, often resulting in serious
injury or death . . . In many of the cases police accounts of what
happened were inconsistent with independent witness testimony
or medical evidence.
(Amnesty International 1992a: 21)
The type of force used includes hitting people on the head with
heavy metal flashlights or lead-filled straps known as “saps,” even
though hitting suspects on the head is generally prohibited. It
involves police dogs attacking people who have surrendered or
pose no threat, and not calling the dogs off when they should.
And sometimes it means using “tasers” [a gun that fires two darts
which give an electric charge on contact], described as having the
stopping power of a small gun.
(Amnesty International 1992a: 21)
364
9: RACE
and the hundreds of people who pleaded guilty and received criminal
records because of the broad discretion on arrests given to police and
the resulting overloaded court system.
Such policing of African Americans has been repeatedly studied
and commented on. For example, in the first three quarters of 2009, of
over 450,000 people stopped by officers of the New York City Police
Department, “an overwhelming 84 percent of the stops . . . were of
black or Hispanic New Yorkers” (Herbert 2010: para. 3). Nevertheless,
Street stops by Chicago police far surpass New York, ACLU finds
[headline] . . . The analysis of the department’s own data shows that
Chicago police stopped African-Americans at a disproportionately
higher rate than Hispanics and whites, especially in predominantly
white neighborhoods.
(Gorner 2015: para. 2)
One vehicle for such policing has been the so-called War on Drugs
which was discussed in Chapter 7 in relation to class. In his study
of the “ghetto underclass,” William Chambliss describes the conse-
quences of the War on Drugs in terms of the relationship between
race and criminalization in the United States in the 1990s. See Box 9.
The War on Drugs in the United States has produced another war as well: It is a war
between the police and minority youth from the ghetto . . . The chasm between black and
white in the United States grows deeper by the day, and the police, prosecutors, courts,
and prisons are the steam shovel digging it wider.
Young black men make up about 6 percent of the population but 40 percent of those
arrested for drug possession and trafficking and more than 50 percent of those convicted
of violating drug laws . . . The white male population, which is five times as large as the
black male population, accounts for only 37 percent of those convicted of drug offences,
despite the fact that, as national household surveys show, whites are more likely to use
illegal drugs than either blacks or Latinos. . . .
African American women and juveniles are particularly hard hit by the racially inequita-
ble enforcement of drug laws.The number of women in state and federal prisons increased
fourfold in the last twenty years of the twentieth century.The majority of female inmates are
365
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
in prison for drugs, and the impact of this on black families is staggering, since 75 percent
of the black female inmates are mothers. Discrimination in sentencing for black juveniles is
incomprehensible by any standard. The number of white juveniles in locked detention for
drugs has declined since 1985, whereas the number of non-white juveniles (mostly black)
in locked detention has increased by 259 percent.
Source: William Chambliss (1999: 88–90): Power, Politics, and Crime.
The United States has held the record for the world’s highest
known rate of incarceration for many years. Martin Walker, writing in
the Guardian Weekly (30 June 1991: 10), calls the US prison system “the
American Gulag.” The criminologist Nils Christie adopts the term
for the sub-title of his book Crime Control as Industry (1994, 2000).
In 1990, with one million prisoners in federal, state and county jails,
the United States had a rate of 426 prisoners per 100,000 population,
compared with South Africa at 33 per 100,000, the former Soviet
Union at 268 per 100,000, and Great Britain at 97 per 100,000. By
1993, the US rate had climbed to 532 prisoners per 100,000 popu-
lation (Christie 1994: 191). From 2002 to at least 2013, the United
States had the highest rate of incarceration in the world. According
to the tenth edition of the World Prison Population List compiled
by the International Centre for Prison Studies at the University of
Essex, in October 2013, the incarceration rate of the United States was
716 per 100,000 population. With about 4.4 per cent of the world’s
population, the United States housed about 22 per cent of the world’s
prisoners. The Centre’s data for the United States are drawn from
the US Bureau of Justice Statistics. The UK rate at that time was
148, Canada’s 118 (Walmsley 2013). According to the eleventh edi-
tion of the List, by October 2015, the US rate had dropped slightly. Its
incarceration rate was then second to the Seychelles (Walmsley 2015).
The United States imposes longer sentences than any other indus-
trialized country. In 1990, one quarter of the inmates of the federal
prison system were serving sentences of more than 15 years, one half
were serving sentences of more than seven years.
The US criminal justice system is devastating for African Americans.
In 1990, “one in four black men aged 20–29 is either in prison, on
probation, or on parole (compared to one in 16 for whites)” (Walker
1991: 10).
366
9: RACE
Walker explains that he uses the term “Gulag” because he sees par-
allels between Stalin’s imprisoning people because of their social class
and perceived threat to his system and the US treatment of African
Americans. “And there is an uncomfortable sense, even within the
American establishment, that the criminal justice system is racist in
practice, even when it claims to be neutral in principle” (1991: 10).
The point is that the criminal justice system has increasingly been
used as the main vehicle through which the United States handles its
social problems, a catch-all device which scoops up drug users, the
mentally ill, the homeless and other social “failures,” and puts them
out of sight and out of mind into the prison system. “Although we
ignore those at the top, the corporations and the privileged, the state
‘is intrusive and disciplinary at the bottom, when it comes to dealing
with the consequences of social divestment and economic deregula-
tion for the lower class’” (Leonard 2015: 33, quoting Wacquant 2009
[2004]: 83). Referring to Wacquant, Leonard continues:
He contends that race plays a central role here. Just as the criminal
is racialized in our imaginations, Wacquant points to three promi-
nent images found in the media and policy debates . . . the “welfare
queen,” the “teenage mother,” and the “deadbeat dad” (89). He notes
that, “All three were stereotypically portrayed as African-American
residents of the dilapidated inner city.”
(Leonard 2015: 33–34)
Sociology’s explanations
With the official facts of racial discrimination in the criminal justice
system broadly established as above, what does professional sociology
have to say about such criminalization based on race? How do sociol-
ogists go about trying to account, for example, for the criminalizing of
African Americans and the relative de-criminalizing of whites? Some
appreciation of the scope of theorizing about race can be gained from,
for example, Back and Solomos (2009), Theories of Race and Racism:
A Reader. Two broad positions can be identified within the structural
or critical conflict approach to the theoretical understanding of race.
The Marxist position treats race as an epiphenomenon of class, whereas
the neocolonial position treats race as its own analytically separate struc-
ture of dominance. The difference between the two positions, that is,
367
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Marxist accounts
In his useful review, Watson (1984) cites the work of Oliver Cox
(1948) as an example of the Marxist position:
Cox, an eminent black American sociologist, has argued that the situ-
ation of the vast majority of black Americans can best be understood
if we conceive them as being part of the propertyless American prole-
tariat in a capitalist economy . . . To understand the problem of black
Americans is to understand their position as proletarians . . . Broadly
speaking, says Cox, the black proletariat shared many of the eco-
nomic experiences of the white working class, owing to their being
in a similar overall social and economic position; both white and
black workers had to respond to changes in the capitalist labour
market. Revolts and protests of black people against their exploitation
both before and after slavery were very similar to the revolts, protests
and similar expressions of alienation of white people.
(Watson 1984: 54)
Thus, “the racial tensions between white and black proletarians were
part and parcel of an attempt by the dominant classes to divide the
368
9: RACE
369
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
370
9: RACE
“Because they sense that they’ve become the most vulnerable scape-
goats, the Central American community is rushing to register voters,
to encourage people to become active in local politics and to make
alliances” (1992: 15).
Another positive outcome to the rebellion, according to Davis, is
the politicizing of the gangs. Instead of continuing the endless cycle
of destructive gang warfare, Crips and Bloods were holding meetings
and gatherings, hundreds of them coming together as liberation fight-
ers instead of gang bangers. These meetings were violently broken up
by the police who, Davis asserts, “seem to fear gang unity above all
else” (1992: 17). Davis talks about the information-processing capa-
bilities of the Federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI) and local police
forces. The mass arrests following the rebellion depended upon the
databases on black and Latino youth that the LAPD and LASD had
put together over the previous decade, and also the FBI’s expertise in
analyzing video and photographic evidence. The FBI joined with the
police in demanding that the media and private individuals surrender
every negative and all videotape taken during the rebellion. Davis sees
the real danger with massive databases and information technologies as
being their application in the management of criminalized populations.
371
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
372
9: RACE
373
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Neocolonial accounts
Crudely put, it is as if the white court will not allow that the
Negro as a person is of sufficient complexity and worth to make
374
9: RACE
Postcolonial accounts
Sidney Willhelm (1994 [1986]) reviews both the class and neocolo-
nial models, and finds them both wanting. Both, he argues, rely on
the economic proposition that capitalism requires and exploits black
labour, whereas the goal of post-industrial capitalism is to elimi-
nate the need for labour altogether. “Instead of a transformation of
work, work is itself being destroyed; while the labour that is drawn
from the market is transformed, the need for labour is simultaneously
being curtailed” (Willhelm 1994 [1986]: 42). Only the assumption
that capitalism has moved into a new post-industrial, technological
phase, relying on automation to replace human labour, can explain
375
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
376
9: RACE
377
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
378
9: RACE
Example A1
P: Why did you shoot at this G{…}?
S: He’s a nigger.
Example A2
P: Well then did you know that you were shooting at G. . . or did
you shoot at him just because he was colored, period?
S: He’s a nigger.
P: And that’s why you shot him and er.
S: That’s why I shot him.
(Watson 1997 [1983]: 92)
379
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
The judge in the same case is reported to have “told jurors it would be
‘dangerous’ to convict the young man of first-degree murder . . . because
Ms. George ‘was indeed a prostitute’” (Roberts 1997: A9). Just as stark
is the parallel case from the Montreal Massacre in which the killer is
reported as saying to his victims before shooting them, “You are all a
bunch of feminists. I hate feminists” (Eglin and Hester 2003: 3).
Subordination can be carried out, however, without the use of
a racially marked category at all. Thus, Alvin Toussaint, an African-
American psychiatrist, reports how on the streets of Jackson, Mississippi
in 1966 he was approached by a white police officer and the following
exchange ensued.
380
9: RACE
381
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Like the cases treated in Chapters 7 and 8, that involving race con-
sidered by Maynard is one of a series negotiated by the attorneys at a
“pre-trial and settlement conference” with or without the presence
of a judge (J). “Although judges contributed to the discussion in a
few cases, essentially they ‘rubber stamped’ decisions made by the
attorneys” (Maynard 1982a: 349). Discussion includes naming the
defendant, the charge (by title or penal code section) and any prior
convictions.
382
9: RACE
J1: And now that brings us to Frank Bryan. Is he the poor chap
sitting out there all by himself?
PD2: Yeah he’s the sweet man with the nice smile. And this is a six
forty seven “f ” and a one forty eight.
(Maynard 1984: 144)
For the public defender, Frank Bryan is a nice guy whose only
offence was being drunk, fighting with his family, and cursing in
his own home. He was intruded upon there by police officers who
383
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
may have roughed him up during the arrest. He has a prior record
by virtue of being black and statistically more likely to encounter
the police. For the district attorney, the defendant is one who gave
the police much difficulty in making an arrest and who has a prior
conviction for the same kind of conduct. These different inter-
pretations buttress or provide the “reasonableness” of the original
positions that DA3 and PD2 take up, and their disparateness is
preserved as the negotiators, through bargaining sequences, reach
agreement on both charge and sentence.
(Maynard 1984: 113)
The race of the defendant is explicitly invoked in this case, but in such
a way as to mitigate the seriousness of the offence.The very argument
that professional sociologists doing critical studies of the CJS use to
point to racialized criminalization of blacks is here used by parties
to the setting itself to press for a light sentence. Race is a members’
concept. The deeper point is that while stereotyping is harmful, it is
hard to imagine how society could be possible without typification.
For this argument by Schutz, taken up by Sacks, see Kim and Berard
(2009: 268–270) and recall the quotations from Schutz in Chapter 1
of this book (“Members’ knowledge of crime”).
To repeat what was said in Chapter 7 and repeated in Chapter 8,
Maynard’s study confirms again what many studies before his have
attested; namely, that defendant attributes (typifications) are used in
prosecuting, defending and sentencing offenders. But what his eth-
nomethodological approach reveals that other approaches do not is
the selective and contextual use of such attributes by members of society
themselves, as this consideration of the role of race in Frank Bryan’s
conviction and sentencing shows.
Conclusion
Racial (or ethnic) emancipation is a political project. It responds to
discrimination that has been formally enshrined in laws, civil and
criminal, which themselves expressed and were embedded in wide-
spread and persistent, though arguably diminishing, racist public
sentiment and practice. As politics, it is understood as political. That
is, its expression in speech and writing is designed to persuade, to
educate, to agitate and organize or mobilize a constituency towards
384
9: RACE
385
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
Grand Chief Harper likened Ms. Harper’s defiance – she would not
die of her injuries – to that of her great-uncle Elijah Harper, the
late Manitoba politician who stood up in the legislature and said
“no” to the Meech Lake Accord. “This is the same thing Rinelle
did in the frigid waters [of Winnipeg’s Assiniboine River]. She was
attacked, beaten, left for dead,” he said. “She got back up from the
waters and she said, ‘No. This is not going to happen anymore’.”
(Carlson 2014: front page)
Exercises
1. Attempt to discover through official sources who is currently
being held in solitary confinement in the prisons of your province,
state or country. Compile a list of their names. Attempt to discover
their “racial” background as officially recorded. Nations’ prison
systems are overseen by official inspection bodies. In Canada it
is the Office of the Correctional Investigator. In the UK, it’s Her
Majesty’s Chief Inspector of Prisons. The United States appears
not to have a single national inspection body. Inspections appear to
be handled by each state. Possibly useful institutions at the national
(that is, federal) level include the Federal Bureau of Prisons and the
National Institute of Corrections. Amnesty International USA and
prisoners’ rights organizations may be helpful sources. The idea
is to see which “racial group” is currently most subjected to this
most “cruel and unusual punishment.” Keep detailed notes in your
notebook of the steps you took in this inquiry, the obstacles you
faced and any solutions that worked or didn’t work.
2. Note any instances of the everyday use of the language of race
you observe during your course of study, particularly if they arise
in the context of talk about crime. Consider them in light of the
grammar section of the chapter.
386
9: RACE
Review questions
1. What are the similarities and differences between Marxist and
neocolonial accounts of race? How could they be used to explain
the differential stopping and carding of black and white people by
police? Which approach do you favour, and why?
2. How does the postcolonial account of race differ from the Marxist
and neocolonial accounts? What aspects of the experience of racial-
ized minorities with the criminal justice system does it explain
better than the other two theoretical approaches?
3. Including his cases from Chapters 7 and 8, say what you take it
Maynard (1984) means when he says that lawyers’ use of defendant
attributes such as class, gender and race is selective and contextual.
If this analysis is correct, what sociological significance does it
have?
Further reading
Back, Les and John Solomos. Eds. 2009. Theories of Race and Racism:
A Reader. Second edition. Routledge Student Readers. London,
UK and New York: Routledge. For more extensive coverage of the
range of theories than is provided in this chapter.
Chan, Wendy and Dorothy E. Chunn. 2014. Racialization, Crime, and
Criminal Justice in Canada. Toronto, ON: University of Toronto
Press. The book also includes consideration of immigration,
poverty and mental illness, and inter-sectionality.
Hester, Stephen and William Housley. Eds. 2002. Language, Interaction
and National Identity: Studies in the Social Organisation of National
Identity in Talk-in-Interaction. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. Although
focused neither on race nor crime, the book presents detailed
investigations of how persons actually use national identity in their
talk, the interactional uses to which such expressions are put, and
the interactional consequences of such identity talk.
Notes
1 For example, Jeff Outhit, “Racism entrenched in university campuses,
forum told,” Waterloo Region Record, 21 March 2016: www.therecord.
com/news-story/6400143-racism-entrenched-in-university-campuses-
forum-told/ (Accessed 22 March 2016).
387
PART III: POLITICALLY CHALLENGED
2 See El Jones, “You have to fight for your right to party: A brief his-
tory of Halifax bars and racism.” Halifax Examiner, 7 May 2016: www.
halifaxexaminer.ca/featured/you-have-to-fight-for-your-right-to-party/
(Accessed 8 May 2016).
3 Stephen Lewis was a former leader of the Ontario New Democratic Party.
He was later appointed Canada’s Ambassador to the United Nations, after
which he became an inveterate campaigner on behalf of those suffering
from AIDS in Africa.
4 Kitchener-Waterloo Record, 2 November 1990, B2.
5 The transcript is taken from Watson (1984: 63), who simplifies it from
Speier (1973: 188), who cites Ervin-Tripp ([published as] 1972: 218),
who cites the original by Poussaint (1967). Speier and Watson both pro-
vide brief analyses of the interaction, while Poussaint himself describes
the episode more fully. The analysis presented here is drawn from Eglin
(2013c).
388
PART IV
Epistemically
undermined
Introduction
391
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
he is making here, the reader may profit from returning to the discus-
sion of the meaning and use of official crime statistics in Chapter 2
where we first quoted this sentence.
The political challenge to both positivistic and interpretative sociolo-
gies does not so much question the basis of their claims to knowledge
as contest the assumption that truth can be pursued independently
of politics. Science and politics cannot be separated, according to this
view, as is evident in the class, gender and racial biases to be found in
the content and form of such inquiries, so the argument goes. Inquiry
not directed to the emancipation of oppressed groups is either ideo-
logical or pointless. The point is to reconstruct society as a whole,
free of oppression, rather than seeking to reform it in piecemeal
fashion.
The postmodernist (PM) and poststructuralist (PS) turn does not so
much repudiate the interpretative and political challenges to posi-
tivistic inquiry as radicalize them in such a way as to undermine the
whole Enlightenment enterprise. The pursuit of true knowledge is
not just not value-free. It is itself a power play. Knowledge is not sepa-
rate from power: “behind the will to knowledge [is] a will to power”
(Seidman 2013: 165, channelling Nietzsche). The aim of inquiry is
not to progressively construct or radically reconstruct society, but to
deconstruct all claims to authority. “Poststructuralism is a kind of per-
manent rebellion against authority; that of science and philosophy but
also of the church and the state. Its strategy of linguistic and political
subversion is called ‘deconstruction’” (2013: 165).
392
INTRODUCTION
393
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
394
INTRODUCTION
By the 1990s the women’s movement had lost much of the impe-
tus it had had in previous decades; the separationist position in
particular had lost much of its force. In this context the transgres-
sive arguments of the postmodernists pointed in a more practical
and pragmatic direction, suggesting accommodation to and alli-
ance with other forms of identity politics . . . For these feminists,
the ideals of the gay and lesbian movement are integral to their
conceptions of feminism, especially since gay and lesbian theory
had, by the 1990s, arrived at the same postmodernist perspective.
Consequently, postmodern feminism and queer theory are both
politically aligned and theoretically contiguous.
(Cuff et al. 2016: 374)
395
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
396
10 Power
The text of the epigraph above, with its colourful graphic design
restored, and in both official Canadian languages, appeared unbid-
den in the author’s inbox (the accompanying message informing him
that he is on the agency’s mailing list) on 20 September 2016. That
it so appeared in his inbox, that it comes from a governmental body,
that it concerns the prevention of crime and that its announcements
are about inquiries which are informed by economics and social
work make it grist for the mill of Foucauldian analysis of discourse,
discipline and power. To be more precise, the text invites considera-
tion in terms of Foucault’s concept of governmentality, which, while
appearing later in Foucault’s work than the previous three concepts,
nevertheless incorporates them (though Garland [1997: 193–195]
sees some confusion among the concepts appearing in the earlier and
later works). The bulk of this chapter and the theoretical aspects of
the next one are devoted to Foucault and his effect on criminology.
But before we introduce those of his ideas that have been taken up
in criminology, we consider his place in relation to poststructuralism
397
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
398
10: POWER
399
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
400
10: POWER
401
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
The task is to reveal the wild, open and disorderly character of language
and to oppose the violence of ideological closure. In seeking definitive
accounts of “reality,”Western thought shows itself to be a violent and
repressive enterprise. Revealing this about it then becomes an act of
political opposition. Postmodernism and poststructuralism see their
intellectual activities as intensely political since, in effect, everything is
political (Fish 2008: 174; see Eglin 2013b: prologue).
As we will see with Foucault, poststructuralism is concerned to
locate ideas historically. It holds to the relativist idea that what is
thinkable is tied to historical circumstance. Ideas arise in relation
to societal practices that are current at a given time. “There is an
underlying matrix of presuppositions which confines the mind in a
given period and makes only certain kinds of thoughts thinkable.This
matrix is what Foucault terms the episteme” (Cuff et al. 2016: 245). If
this is so, however, it must mean that the kind of society in which it
is possible to think outside the box of Enlightenment thought must
itself have changed in order for these new thoughts to be thinkable.
If Enlightenment thought is characteristic of modern (as opposed
to pre-modern, classical or medieval) society, then it must be the
case that we are living in a form of postmodern society with a new
episteme. In the work of Jean-François Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard and
other postmodernists, we find the position being taken that not only
theorizing has become postmodern, but society itself has entered a
stage of postmodernity. As such, it is now possible, now thinkable, to
undermine the Enlightenment episteme.
The consequences for criminology of these largely philosophical
developments have been, as might be expected from the previous
discussion, two-fold. On the one hand, practitioners have sought to
adopt the language and theoretical outlook of PS and PM to ana-
lyze crime and criminalization; and on the other hand, they have
looked for empirical evidence of postmodernity in the character
of contemporary crime and criminalization. Readers tempted by
402
10: POWER
At the end of Discipline and Punish, Foucault (1977 [1975]: 303) asks,
“how were people made to accept the power to punish, or quite
simply, when punished, tolerate being so?” It’s an arresting question.
Why do we accept, to the extent that we do, that other people, usually
in uniform, can take our money in fines, imprison us and/or impose
other conditions on us that limit our freedom to act? The question
is all the more arresting when it is acknowledged that the standard
liberal-democratic answer – that as citizens we “signed a contract”
with the state to give up force and fraud in exchange for protection
and control by law backed by sovereign power – is empty of content.
None of us ever signed such a contract, explicitly or implicitly, either
as individuals or via social groups of which we are members, nor did
our predecessors. Moreover, the slightest observation of or reflection
on the social distribution of punishment reveals quite plainly that “the
jails are full of petty thieves, and all the while the grand thieves are
running the country” (Howard Zinn [1970], quoted in Chapter 7).
403
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
404
10: POWER
405
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
406
10: POWER
407
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
408
10: POWER
409
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
410
10: POWER
Post-Foucault studies
411
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
412
10: POWER
413
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Garland goes on to point out how these three forms of power with
their corresponding types of subject uneasily co-exist. Each of them is
associated with particular laws, bodies of knowledge, institutionalized
practices and professions (the judiciary, social work establishment,
crime prevention agencies).They don’t stand to one another as phases
in an historical progression, nor do they have a coherent relationship
414
10: POWER
The social historian Joan Sangster here reports a study of the “pro-
cess of sexual regulation” under the Female Refuges Act (FRA) of
Ontario between 1920 and 1945. The Act, which lasted from 1897
to 1958, and was specifically for girls/women between the ages of
16 and 35,“provided for low-security correctional institutions, where
women were offered shelter, work, and reform as an antidote to
‘unmanageability and incorrigibility’” (Sangster 1996: 240; see also
Sangster 2001). After 1919,
415
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
leading an idle and dissolute life.” All that was needed was a sworn
statement about the woman’s incorrigibility: no formal charge was
needed, and hearings were in private.
(Sangster 1996: 240)
The maximum sentence was two years, minus a day. In other words:
From 1920 to the late 1950s these provisions in the FRA allowed
parents, police, welfare authorities, and the Children’s Aid Society
(CAS) to use incarceration as a means to regulate the sexual and
moral behavior of women perceived to be “out of sexual control.”
For rebellious teenagers already serving time in industrial schools,
the act could increase their punishment by sending them to the
Mercer Reformatory for Women as soon as they were fifteen or
sixteen years old, for up to two more years.
(Sangster 1996: 240)
Using institutional records and FRA case files, Sangster aims “to
uncover the dominant definitions of idle and dissolute used by the
court” (1996: 241); how the definitions were applied to distinguish
the sexuality of bad girls from that of good girls; how those incarcer-
ated were turned into criminals, pathologized and treated; what the
process reveals about its patriarchal, class and ethnic dimensions; and
whether and to what extent the girls/women rejected the construc-
tion of them as immoral. In theoretical terms, she casts her inquiry in
the context of the literature dealing with the debates over social con-
trol, social censure and moral regulation involving various Marxist,
feminist and poststructural positions. She favours a Foucauldian,
poststructuralist approach using the concept of moral regulation, not
least because it has brought studies of the regulation of gender and
sexuality to the fore (see, for example, Strange 1995).
416
10: POWER
Sangster characterizes the period between the two world wars as one
of concern on the part of middle-class reformers about working-class
women’s sexuality and reproduction, against a general background
of fear about women’s sexual assertiveness that was seen to threaten
more general social disorder. At the same time, working-class women’s
lives came under greater scrutiny through the disciplinary attention
of social workers, psychologists and doctors who were increasingly
involved with the courts. While legal reformers advocated family
courts, it was the case that:
The interwar years that Sangster examines were peak years for FRA
convictions, most of which fell on women under 21 years of age and
417
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
The data
As mentioned above, Sangster’s data are the court’s case files and
other institutional records. She resists an empiricist treatment of her
data by pointing out that the number of girls/women convicted
under the FRA was small in comparison to the number of women
imprisoned in general, and the records that supplied her data were not
always reliable sources of accurate information.What she argues they
do reveal, however, is the discourse in terms of which these women’s
sexual behaviour was assessed. That is, the files “highlight the polar-
ized constructions of good and bad femininity and sexuality created
and justified by those with medical and legal authority, and the way
in which women were measured against these ideals” (1996: 249).
418
10: POWER
what her sexual practices were, and the role she played in the family”
(Sangster 1996: 258–259).
The data reveal more about the perceptions of the police, CAS offi-
cials and magistrates than about the women themselves. The state
officials
Sangster continues:
419
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
opinion that they were immoral,“for some FRA women were simply
broken and unresponsive human beings: they were completely des-
titute, alcoholic, or disabled” (Sangster 1996: 271). A few talked back,
but only a few. According to Sangster, their rejection of the court’s
displeasure was less a proto-feminist one than a vague disgruntlement
with having to conform with prevailing norms. In prison they were
enjoined to emphasize “hard work, good manners and clean language,
and personal self-control and discipline” for “[b]ehind the language
of reform and personal change used by the reformatory was the stark
and brutal reality of discipline designed to coerce the woman’s psyche
and soul into a new mold” (1996: 271–272).
Conclusion
420
10: POWER
421
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
UK, and of Teun van Dijk who “was one of the first scholars to apply
critical discourse analysis to the study of the press” (2002: 19).
Critical Discourse Analysis (CDA) combines structural Marxism’s
critical analysis of culture with discourse analysis. Discourse analysis is
a form of structural linguistics that deals with units longer than a sen-
tence, but in CDA it also reflects the influence of poststructuralism in
the form of Foucault’s concept of discourse. Like Semiology, CDA is
an expression of the importance that culture and language have come
to assume in the contemporary human sciences. Like Semiology,
CDA deals in the “meanings and interpretations” associated with
images or textual expressions – in short, with “representations.” Many
studies in CDA have been about race. See particularly the works of
Teun van Dijk, who has been something of an entrepreneur for CDA,
producing anthologies and editing journals that feature studies in
this genre. See, for example, the journals Discourse & Society and Text.
Prior to publishing Discourses of Domination with Carol Tator,
Frances Henry (1999) produced a report on the same study that
was subsequently written up in the book. Focusing on the ideologi-
cal representation of race (rather than its material reproduction), she
examines in detail the form and content of two samples of news
stories, editorials and columns in The Toronto Star, the Toronto Sun
and The Globe and Mail from 1994 to 1997, one sample of articles
featuring Jamaicans and Vietnamese, and one comprising “all arti-
cles on all crimes committed by everybody” (1999: ii). She devotes
particular attention to a small number of case studies, most notably
the 1994 Just Desserts murder case that we take up in more detail
below. Her principal finding is that as a “result of the media attention
to crimes purportedly committed by people of colour, and espe-
cially Blacks, . . . crime becomes racialized” (1999: 135). Unlike white
crimes, those by blacks are used as occasions for generating negative
projections about blacks in general.They become vehicles for gener-
ating moral panics about “crime in society,” and societal crisis more
generally. Civilized (white) society is suddenly under threat from
blacks or Asians, immigrants or foreigners. Law and order need to
be reinforced. The offending parties need to be further controlled.
Criminalization and racialization become, for another first time,
inextricably intertwined.
For closer analysis, we turn to chapter 9 of Henry and Tator (2002),
entitled “The Racialization of Crime.” It presents the authors’ critical
422
10: POWER
Analysis
423
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Here, Henry and Tator note the use of further linguistic strategies,
including intertextuality and hedging. The latter, for example, involves
the use of the expression “for some” as a way to hedge a claim that
the reporters themselves appear to want to make. The authors go on
to attend to the placement of racial designators in some of the cov-
erage, to writers’ use of paraphrase, to the use of racial identifiers in
the context of reported positions being taken by significant players,
to the use of contrasts, and to which items occupy the topical place in
articles. The third and fourth steps in the analysis consist of further
CDA of Guns and the other and of Criminalizing immigration.
Finally, being “critical” by self-description, this form of inquiry is
intendedly directed at not only the description and analysis of the
forms of social action that it is studying, but at their evaluation in
moral and political terms. As a result, like this one, such analyses quite
often have the character of exposés.
424
10: POWER
425
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
426
10: POWER
427
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
are pressed to clarify the meaning of each utterance they make rapidly
run out of patience with their interlocutor. Why? Because:
428
10: POWER
in missing just what makes social life social. Dorothy Smith, here
defending her version of feminist standpoint theory against PS and
PM, has put this argument in somewhat different, if characteristic,
terms:
429
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Conclusion
430
10: POWER
Exercises
1. Take a field trip through your home, or workplace, or university
or college campus, or local shopping mall or neighbourhood. Try
and “see” all the ways such settings are crime-free by being “mor-
ally regulated” via “disciplinary power,” diffused throughout the
setting and administered, if at all, not by coercive agents (police,
security, laws), but by setting co-inhabitants themselves (including
you) in terms of their (your) own comportment and behaviour.
Take abundant notes. Speaking into a voice recorder as you go is
a useful way to proceed.
2. Construct a scenario in which the meaning of some bit of text
(spoken or written) is changed by changing its linguistic context;
that is, by adding some text that precedes or follows it. Try and
make it relevant to crime and criminalization.
Review questions
1. How does Derrida come to argue that determinate meaning is
inevitably political, the result of the exercise of power?
431
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Further reading
Ben-Moshe, Liat, Chris Chapman and Allison C. Carey. Eds. 2014.
Disability Incarcerated: Imprisonment and Disability in the United States
and Canada. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. For Foucauldian anal-
yses of the incarceration of people with disabilities.
Brock, Deborah,Amanda Glasbeek and Carmela Murdocca. Eds. 2014.
Criminalization, Representation, Regulation:Thinking Differently About
Crime. Toronto, ON: University of Toronto Press. Foucault’s con-
cept of governmentality is used to analyze and critique how crime
and criminalization are understood, reproduced and challenged.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall. (Reprinted in 1984 by Polity Press.) Chapter
Two, titled “Studies of the routine grounds of everyday activities,”
is essential reading as an antidote to PS and PM. It is the source of
the quote from Garfinkel in the grammar section of this chapter.
432
11 People?
433
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
434
11: PEOPLE?
435
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
On 18 October 2001, the village of Bibi Mahru on the outskirts of Kabul was hit by an
American “precision” 500-pound bomb. It killed Gul Ahmad, 40, a Hazara carpet weaver,
his second wife Sima, 35, their five daughters and his son by his first wife, as well as two
children living next door. “We buried them together in the graveyard. We divided it with
separate gravestones but their bodies were all in pieces,” said Mr. Ahmad’s first wife, who
was living in another village at the time of the bombing.
Source: Michael Mandel (2004: 29): How America Gets Away With Murder.
436
11: PEOPLE?
Postcolonialism
“Just as feminism challenges definitions of gender, and queer theory
challenges conventional sexual categories, so postcolonialism seeks to
problematize the idea of ethnic difference and the relation between
dominant and subordinate cultures across the globe” (Cuff et al. 2016:
379). Postcolonialism criticizes classical social theory as “Eurocentric”
and not just ethnocentric. Classical social theory measures the colo-
nized in Western terms, and finds them wanting. It tells a story of the
Rise of the West that focuses on its success and highlights the failure
of the rest of the world to measure up. Taking for granted a view of
the world and its history from inside the European project, it sees the
rest of the world and its peoples as outside, and therefore as “other.”
A major question in the human sciences, then, has been to explain
how this state of affairs came about. How did the “West” in general
– Western Europe and its North American (Canada and the United
States in particular) and southern hemisphere (Australia and New
Zealand) transplants – achieve such strong “economic fundamentals”
and the economic prosperity and general social and human benefits
that they have afforded (see, for example, D’Aliesio 2011)? And how,
in cultural terms, has it represented to itself its difference from the
lands it has colonized and dominated?
The mainstream historical account of the Rise of the West or
the “European Miracle” explains it by reference to some intrinsic
437
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
438
11: PEOPLE?
439
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
440
11: PEOPLE?
441
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
442
11: PEOPLE?
The points she makes will reappear in the studies by King and
McHoul and Churchill which we review more fully below.
Genocide
The crime of destroying a people is called genocide. It is not our pur-
pose to survey what is now the burgeoning field of “genocide studies”
– see, for example, Women and Genocide (DiGeorgio-Lutz and Gosbee
2016) – but to draw out the elements of the postcolonial take on the
imperial subjection of indigenous peoples. To exemplify a straight-up
Foucauldian poststructuralist analysis, we review King and McHoul’s
(1986) study of the “discursive production of the Queensland [Australia]
Aborigine as subject.” For a less theorized, more documentary-
historical account, we rely on Churchill’s (1998) A Little Matter of
Genocide: Holocaust and Denial in the Americas, 1492 to the Present. Students
of the subject are recommended to read in addition major works by
indigenous or semi-indigenous scholars that have recently become avail-
able. These include An Indigenous Peoples’ History of the United States by
Roxanne Dunbar-Ortiz (2014) and The Colonial Problem: An Indigenous
Perspective on Crime and Injustice in Canada by Lisa Monchalin (2016),
the first indigenous woman in Canada to hold a PhD in Criminology.
Eduardo Galeano’s masterpiece, Memory of Fire (1985–1988), remains
an incomparable source. Its three volumes trace the stories of the
continuing conquest year by year from before 1492 to 1986.
443
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Ultimately, they say, citing Derrida, they are “writing about writing”
or “making a contribution to the political history of language” (1986:
22, emphasis in original). Recall the discussion of the significance of
writing to the PS/PM project in the Introduction to Part IV and in
the grammar section of Chapter 10. Because for PS/PM, language
is reality and discourse is power (or the claim is at least that the two
pair-parts in each binary cannot be separated), “It is our central, if
unstated, thesis that the forms of conceptualisation (i.e., the forms of
discourse) available to early colonial administrations in and of them-
selves constituted a field of power” (1986: 22, emphasis in original).
The discourses in question are those informing the texts of policy
documents used in the colonial administration of Queensland in late
nineteenth-century Australia as they pertained to the treatment of
Aborigines, the indigenous people of Australia. Such texts “are treated
as symptoms of how it was possible for an invading race to conceive
of those they attempted to conquer in the way they did” (1986: 22,
emphasis in original). It is through the discourses evident in the
texts “that one population knew how to dominate another” (1986: 22,
emphasis in original).
The authors identify three stages in the relationship of the European
settlers and the indigenous inhabitants: the stage of extermination
(1824–1908), the overlapping stage of protection and segregation
(1873–1957) and the stage of assimilation/multiculturalism (1957 to
the present). The first stage was characterized by “genocide, rape,
inter-breeding, ‘settling’ Aboriginal land, Christian conversion, the
spread of disease and so forth” (1986: 24). Such acts “tended to be
indiscriminate and brutal, involving as they did extensive slaugh-
ter and appropriation of traditional lands. There was no direct and
concerted legal/textual campaign aimed at the normalisation of
Aborigines until the 1890s” (1986: 25). It was at this time that officials
realized that “Aborigines could not be made to disappear physically”
(1986: 25). The authors’ concern, then, in this article is with the sec-
ond stage, that of protection and segregation, the principal vehicle of
which was the reserve.
444
11: PEOPLE?
During the “Oka Crisis” in Canada/Quebec in the summer of 1990, what Mohawks and
native leaders across Canada defined as a political act of self-defence by the armed forces
of a nation – the setting up and defending by armed Mohawk “Warriors” of barricades on
disputed land in the environs of Mohawk reserves at Kanesatake and Kahnawake, first to
prevent the expansion of an Oka municipal golf course onto claimed Mohawk land, and
second in protest against an assault on the first barricades by Quebec Provincial Police
– was counter-defined by the Prime Minister of Canada, the Premier of the Province of
Quebec, the Mayor of Oka and government officials generally as a series of criminal acts
445
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
of mischief, illegal possession of firearms, etc., by terrorists whose relationship to their people
was that of an “extremist minority suppressing dissent” (the Prime Minister, 28 August
1990). In short, one side defined the conflict in political terms as one between sovereign
entities where the applicability of the (criminal) laws of Canada was precisely what was at
issue; the other side defined the conflict in criminal-legal terms within the jurisdiction of the
Canadian state and constitution.
What does this mean in practice? To the extent that the definition of the situation as one
of criminal actions by a terrorist group can be sustained, then the relevant controlling agency
is the police. If, as happened, police resources are judged inadequate to maintain control and
bring the “criminals” to justice, then the army may be brought in. But their actions are then
seen as essentially police work; that is, assisting or replacing the police in the tasks of law-
enforcement. When police and/or army deploy high-powered weapons, including tanks and
helicopters, and fix bayonets to their rifles, when barricades are charged, persons terrorized,
food supplies interrupted, freedom of movement denied, freedom of assembly for peace
groups denied, freedom of the press restricted and so on, these actions are ones defined as
police work by civil authorities in the (ultimately national) interest of law and order. Or they
are counter-defined as acts of aggression, including invasion of sovereign territory and the
denial of human rights under the terms of international law as found in such documents as
the United Nations Charter and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. In the preamble
to the Universal Declaration, for example, armed struggle is recognized as a legitimate last
resort for oppressed groups seeking political recognition of their rights. Clearly, in the hands of
the powerful, the distinction between the “political” and the “criminal” is a powerful discursive
tool for shaping social reality.
Source: Adapted from Hester and Eglin (1992: 167–168): A Sociology of Crime, first edition.
What especially engage King and McHoul, in this study, are the
discursive signifying practices that animate one policy text in particu-
lar. This is Archibald Meston’s (1895) Queensland Aboriginals: Proposed
System for Their Improvement and Protection, a report submitted to the
Colonial Secretary. Meston was regarded at the time as “something of
an expert on matters Aboriginal” (King and McHoul 1986: 26) and
thought so himself. His report
446
11: PEOPLE?
“The focus of the analysis is the text of its report and its discursive
conditions of possibility . . . [It] aims to give primacy to its theoretical
object – the discourse” (King and McHoul 1986: 26). The concept
“conditions of possibility” is informed by Wittgenstein’s treatment
of concepts and criteria as linguistic tools embedded in forms of life,
and by Foucault’s methodological remarks:“the text’s signifying prac-
tices . . . are taken to be political formations in their own right” (1986:
26). Instead of seeking teleological – that is, causal/functional – rela-
tions between problem (Aborigines), policy (Meston’s proposal and
the Act) and practice (reservization), the analysis posits conjunctures
of materialist and textual practices: “it examines ways in which dis-
courses are transformed, incorporated and/or neutralized into each
other such that any policy text which they, thereby, generate can be
seen to systematically ‘form objects of which [it] speaks’” (1986: 26,
citing Foucault 1972 [1969]: 49).
Meston’s text
The authors ask, then, how Meston’s text handles the differences
among the interested accounts of officials, police, judges, anthropolo-
gists, missionaries, etc. that themselves instantiate discourses which
Meston’s text must navigate so as to produce a “composite discourse.”
How does the text manage the contradiction between its political
purpose and its a-political narrative? Where are the slippages between
“what it says” and “what it’s doing,” between its attitude of liberal
humanism and its political project of surveillance and control?
According to the authors’ “discourse on discourse,” the text var-
ies between regarding Aborigines as persons and as natural objects.
The authors present this as a “contradiction.” The text represents the
Aborigines as “of the land” but also having “owned the land” before
the Europeans arrived.The text has black and white voices. It contains
“a promise of justice and atonement,” but this is to be accomplished
“through work and utility” as if these “would return the noble savage
447
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
448
11: PEOPLE?
449
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Churchill himself puts it like this: from 1492 to 1892 when the
450
11: PEOPLE?
He continues:
The people had died in their millions of being hacked apart with
axes and swords, burned alive and trampled under horses, hunted
as game and fed to dogs, shot, beaten, stabbed, scalped for bounty,
hanged on meathooks and thrown over the sides of ships at sea,
worked to death as slave laborers, intentionally starved and frozen
to death during a multitude of forced marches and internments,
and, in an unknown number of instances, deliberately infected
with epidemic diseases.
(Churchill 1998: 1)
451
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
the United States, we will insert some details of the Canadian experi-
ence with genocide.
Although Churchill devotes two lengthy essays in the book to
criticizing this “U.S.-designed and highly truncated instrument” as
“effectively gutting [Raphael] Lemkin’s original [1944] conception of
genocide” (Churchill 1998: 368) and to proposing his own improved
version which includes physical, biological and cultural genocide,
treating each of the three types as “possessing equal gravity” (1998:
433), he nevertheless argues and documents in excruciating detail just
how the huge number of aboriginal deaths resulting from European
invasion and colonization was the outcome of the colonizers’ poli-
cies which conform precisely with the Convention’s definition of
genocide.
Thus, although the greater part of the “population collapse” of
indigenous people had occurred in the first hundred years of the
conquest, for the hemisphere as a whole, the entire period from 1492
to the present is characterized by what seems to be an unending series
of massacres. Students should check the index of Churchill’s book
under “massacres of American Indians.” The list is long. The same is
true for the entry under “Native American peoples,” many of which
no longer exist.The indigenous people were simply killed off in large
numbers, repeatedly.This took place in the course of the conquering
of their towns and villages and the taking over of their land, in the
wake of pitched battles or just plain massacres (the so-called “Indian
Wars”), or as a result of them being worked to death as slave labour
in mines and plantations, or being starved to death by the burning
of their (corn) fields or being denied sufficient food to survive, or of
being hunted for sport, or of being deliberately infected with fatal
diseases such as smallpox.
Churchill is particularly critical of the generally accepted view that
because the Indians had no immunity to European diseases, the huge
proportion of their total death toll from this cause was inadvertent
and thus not the responsibility of the invaders. He points out how
the utter devastation of aboriginals’ lives by the colonists and their
armies so reduced them physically, culturally and spiritually that their
susceptibility to disease was immeasurably heightened.
452
11: PEOPLE?
The story in Canada is not that different, and here too there has
been the charge of genocide (Davis and Zannis 1973; Palmater
2016), including by no less than the Chief Justice of the Supreme
Court of Canada, Beverly McLachlin (Fine 2015). However, in the
Chief Justice’s case, and in the view of the Truth and Reconciliation
Commission of Canada, it is “cultural genocide,” rather than geno-
cide proper, that may be said to have occurred (MacDonald 2015).
This is no doubt related to the fact that Canada’s Criminal Code
recognizes only clauses (a) and (c) of the UN Genocide Convention.
453
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Rather than physically exterminating the native peoples – but see sub-
section (c) below – Canadian officials after Confederation in 1867, in
parallel with the Americans and Australians, adopted the policy of so
assimilating them as to remove any trace of their “Indianness.” One
may wipe out a nation of people as effectively by removing their
identity as by killing them off bodily – “kill the Indian, spare the man”
(Churchill 1998: 245; 2004). A principal vehicle of this policy was the
residential school system. By removing aboriginal children from their
families and communities and confining them in the total institutions
454
11: PEOPLE?
In his Clearing the Plains: Disease, Politics of Starvation, and the Loss
of Aboriginal Life, James Daschuk (2013b) describes how the new
Government of Canada under John A. Macdonald ethnically cleansed
the indigenous people from the central plains (contemporary
Saskatchewan) by withholding food (see also Savage 2012).
455
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Twenty years ago, Saskatoon scholar Laurie Barron cautioned that stories of sexual and
physical abuse at Indian residential schools should be taken with a grain of salt; he thought
they were just too horrific to be believed in their entirety. But national leader Phil Fontaine’s
public admission of his abuse, the Royal Commission on Aboriginal People and the haunting
testimony presented recently to the Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Canada have
brought the horrors of the residential school system to the forefront of our consciousness.
We are often shocked, but we really shouldn’t be surprised.
Nor should we be surprised by the revelations in Dr. Ian Mosby’s article about the
medical experimentation on malnourished aboriginal people in northern Canada and in
residential schools. Rather than feed the hungry among its wards (even adult “Registered
Indians” were not full citizens until 1960), government-employed physicians used pangs of
hunger to further their research into malnutrition, in a plot reminiscent of the Tuskegee
experiment on African-Americans with syphilis, whose conditions were monitored rather
than treated.
Researching my own book forced me to reconsider many of my long-held beliefs about
Canadian history. A professor of mine at Trent University once explained that Canadian
expansion into the West was much less violent than that of the United States, because
in that country, “the person with the fastest horse got the most land.” By contrast, in the
Dominion’s march west, the land was prepared for settlement by government officials
before the flood of immigrants.
What we didn’t know at the time was that a key aspect of preparing the land was the
subjugation and forced removal of indigenous communities from their traditional territories,
essentially clearing the plains of aboriginal people to make way for railway construction
and settlement. Despite guarantees of food aid in times of famine in Treaty No. 6, Canadian
officials used food, or rather denied food, as a means to ethnically cleanse a vast region from
Regina to the Alberta border as the Canadian Pacific Railway took shape.
For years, government officials withheld food from aboriginal people until they
moved to their appointed reserves, forcing them to trade freedom for rations. Once on
reserves, food placed in ration houses was withheld for so long that much of it rotted
while the people it was intended to feed fell into a decades-long cycle of malnutrition,
suppressed immunity and sickness from tuberculosis and other diseases. Thousands
died.
Sir John A. Macdonald, acting as both prime minister and minister of Indian affairs during
the darkest days of the famine, even boasted that the indigenous population was kept on
the “verge of actual starvation,” in an attempt to deflect criticism that he was squandering
public funds.
456
11: PEOPLE?
Within a generation, aboriginal bison hunters went from being the “tallest in the world,”
due to the quality of their nutrition, to a population so sick, they were believed to be racially
more susceptible to disease. With this belief that aboriginal people were inherently unwell,
their marginalization from mainstream Canada was, in a sense, complete.
For more than a century, Canadians have been accustomed to reports of terrible hous-
ing conditions on reserves, unsafe drinking water, dismal educational outcomes and, at least
in Western Canada, prison populations disproportionally stacked with aboriginal inmates.
Aboriginal leaders and young people such as those who embraced the Idle No More
movement have been calling for Canadians to fundamentally acknowledge the injustices
and atrocities of the past and fix the problems that keep indigenous Canadians from living
the same quality of life as their non-aboriginal neighbours.
As the skeletons in our collective closet are exposed to the light, through the work of
Dr. Mosby and others, perhaps we will come to understand the uncomfortable truths that
modern Canada is founded upon – ethnic cleansing and genocide – and push our leaders
and ourselves to make a nation we can be proud to call home.
Source: James Daschuk (2013a: n. p.).
(though not only them) without their consent in Alberta and British
Columbia from 1928 to 1973.
457
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Recently published historical research says hungry aboriginal children and adults were once
used as unwitting subjects in nutritional experiments by Canadian government bureaucrats.
“This was the hardest thing I’ve ever written,” said Ian Mosby, who has revealed new
details about one of the least-known but perhaps most disturbing aspects of government
policy toward aboriginals immediately after the Second World War.
Mosby – whose work at the University of Guelph focuses on the history of food in
Canada – was researching the development of health policy when he ran across something
strange.
“I started to find vague references to studies conducted on ‘Indians’ that piqued my
interest and seemed potentially problematic, to say the least,” he said. “I went on a search
to find out what was going on.”
Government documents eventually revealed a long-standing, government-run experi-
ment that came to span the entire country and involved at least 1,300 aboriginals, most
of them children.
It began with a 1942 visit by government researchers to a number of remote reserve
communities in northern Manitoba, including places such as The Pas and Norway House.
They found people who were hungry, beggared by a combination of the collapsing
fur trade and declining government support. They also found a demoralized population
marked by, in the words of the researchers, “shiftlessness, indolence, improvidence and
inertia.”
The researchers suggested those problems – “so long regarded as inherent or heredi-
tary traits in the Indian race” – were in fact the results of malnutrition.
Instead of recommending an increase in support, the researchers decided that isolated,
dependent, hungry people would be ideal subjects for tests on the effects of different diets.
“This is a period of scientific uncertainty around nutrition,” said Mosby. “Vitamins and
minerals had really only been discovered during the interwar period.
“In the 1940s, there were a lot of questions about what are human requirements for
vitamins. Malnourished aboriginal people became viewed as possible means of testing these
theories.”
The first experiment began in 1942 on 300 Norway House Cree. Of that group, 125
were selected to receive vitamin supplements which were withheld from the rest.
At the time, researchers calculated the local people were living on less than 1,500
calories a day. Normal, healthy adults generally require at least 2,000.
“The research team was well aware that these vitamin supplements only addressed a
small part of the problem,” Mosby writes. “The experiment seems to have been driven, at
458
11: PEOPLE?
least in part, by the nutrition experts’ desire to test their theories on a ready-made ‘labora-
tory’ populated with already malnourished human experimental subjects.”
The research spread. In 1947, plans were developed for research on about 1,000 hungry
aboriginal children in six residential schools in Port Alberni, B.C.; Kenora, Ont.; Shubenacadie,
N.S.; and Lethbridge, Alta.
One school deliberately held milk rations for two years to less than half the recom-
mended amount to get a ‘baseline’ reading for when the allowance was increased. At
another, children were divided into one group that received vitamin, iron and iodine
supplements and one that didn’t.
One school depressed levels of vitamin B1 to create another baseline before levels were
boosted. A special enriched flour that couldn’t legally be sold elsewhere in Canada under
food adulteration laws was used on children at another school.
And, so that all the results could be properly measured, one school was allowed none
of those supplements.
Many dental services were withdrawn from participating schools during that time. Gum
health was an important measuring tool for scientists and they didn’t want treatments on
children’s teeth distorting results.
The experiments, repugnant today, would probably have been considered ethically
dubious even at the time, said Mosby.
“I think they really did think they were helping people. Whether they thought they
were helping the people that were actually involved in the studies, that’s a different
question.”
He noted that rules for research on humans were just being formulated and adopted
by the scientific community.
A spokeswoman for Aboriginal Affairs Minister Bernard Valcourt said the current federal
government is shocked by the findings.
“If this story is true, this is abhorrent and completely unacceptable,” Andrea Richer said
in an email. “When Prime Minister [Stephen] Harper made a historic apology to former
students of Indian Residential Schools in 2008 on behalf of all Canadians, he recognized
that this period had caused great harm and had no place in Canada.”
Little has been written about the nutritional experiments. A May, 2000, article in the
Anglican Journal about some of them was the only reference Mosby could find.
“I assumed that somebody would have written about an experiment conducted on
aboriginal people during this period, and kept being surprised when I found more details
and the scale of it. I was really, really surprised.
“It’s an emotionally difficult topic to study.”
Not much was learned from those hungry little bodies. A few papers were published
459
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
– “they were not very helpful,” Mosby said – and he couldn’t find evidence that the Norway
House research program was completed.
“They knew from the beginning that the real problem and the cause of malnutrition was
underfunding. That was established before the studies even started and when the studies
were completed that was still the problem.”
Source: Bob Weber (2013: n. p.).
460
11: PEOPLE?
461
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
Churchill continues,
in truth, the practice probably finds its origins in the same wars of
pacification in Scotland and Ireland whence the English imported
the rest of their exterminationist techniques, albeit the entire rep-
ertoire mutated into more extreme form when transplanted to
North America.
(Churchill 1998: 180)
See Cornwallis above. Thus, not only scalping, but taking heads and
displaying them stuck on posts, was a preferred method of inducing
terror in the subjugated populace.
But, in the words of the epigraph to Chapter 5 in this book by
W. I. and D. S. Thomas, “if men define situations as real, they are
real in their consequences” (1928: 572). Thus, it did not matter that
462
11: PEOPLE?
463
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
464
11: PEOPLE?
465
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
466
11: PEOPLE?
467
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
criminally responsible for their own sad fate, and as an unwanted drag
on the progress of the rest. See, for example, Peter Edwards’s (2001)
account of the killing of Dudley George at Ipperwash, Ontario by
the Ontario Provincial Police and the attitudes and political practices
that informed that event.
Why did the native peoples not wipe out the invaders, given their
superior numbers initially? Churchill answers: “it did not and could
not occur to them . . . [No] known preinvasion indigenous people
pursued warfare by way of killing their opponents’ women, children,
and elders. Indeed, the terms of native warfare did not emphasize
killing at all” (Churchill 1998: 179).The genocide, racism and imperi-
alism that did not quite succeed in wiping out the indigenous peoples
of the Western hemisphere were and are the practices of the European
invaders and their descendants, my ancestors and perhaps yours.
468
11: PEOPLE?
469
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
everyday life are not straightforward and unambiguous but instead are
contests within complex social fields including local judicial officials,
state officials, local people, and the regulated group. Success is often
fragmentary” (1998: 35). It may be helpful at this point to re-read
the passage from Garland (1997: 202) that concludes Chapter 10 as a
reminder of what “politics” entails.
What is useful in King and McHoul’s analysis is that the exercise
shows that state officials did work at justifying their actions, and
reveals the terms in which they did the justifying, the sources of
those terms, and the notional conceptual problems that work posed
as the officials went about doing it. That demonstration and explica-
tion would have been more persuasive, perhaps, if the authors had
shown the reader at least samples of Meston’s proposal so that the
verisimilitude of their analysis could be made visible.
Conclusion
And the book runs on, years, centuries, till the moment comes
when our parents say the time of apportionment is now over. We
have what we need – our position well defended from every side.
Now, finally, everything can be frozen, just as it is. The violence
can stop. From now on, no more stealing, no more killing. From
this moment, an eternal silence, the rule of law.
(Shawn 1991: 48)
Exercises
1. Acquaint yourselves with the crimes your government is currently
committing internationally and internally by consulting the reports
of human rights organizations such as Amnesty International,
Human Rights Watch, Survival International, Rights Action, the
International Labour Organization and so on, as well as independ-
ent (“alternative”) media such as Democracy Now! or truthout.org in
the United States, rabble.ca in Canada and John Pilger in the UK.
(“Independent” here means not owned by governments or corpo-
rations.) Indigenous peoples typically have their own organizations
470
11: PEOPLE?
Review questions
1. What is poststructural about postcolonialism?
2. How does Merry (1998: 15) come to state that “[r]acial fears and
social images of disorder take solid form in a procession of con-
victed and incarcerated bodies”?
3. What is the relationship of discourse, policy and practice according
to King and McHoul’s (1986) Foucauldian analysis of Meston’s
proposal? Where does power/knowledge fit into the analysis?
4. How did the “conceptual practices of racism” provide the “condi-
tions of possibility” of genocide in the Americas?
5. What are the “conditions of possibility” of King and McHoul’s
(1986) poststructuralist analysis?
Further reading
Monchalin, Lisa. 2016. The Colonial Problem: An Indigenous Perspective
on Crime and Injustice in Canada. Toronto, ON: University of
Toronto Press.
471
PART IV: EPISTEMICALLY UNDERMINED
472
12 Conclusion
473
12: CONCLUSION
474
12: CONCLUSION
persons since World War II, not to mention the growth of armed
resistance in the name of Allah. Globalization’s deleterious effects are
generating huge movements of people from South to North, not just
refugees, but economic migrants and migrant labour, against which
we have been witnessing the unprecedented closing of borders, nota-
bly in some European countries, together with the rise of fascist or
anti-immigrant parties. The US empire continues to flex its mus-
cles both militarily and economically in support of the very global
capitalist system that is now increasingly seen as wrecking the planet.
Russia and China respond in kind. In pursuit of unchecked monetary
gain, through cheap labour and tax havens, a transnational capitalist
class increasingly off-shores both production and profits, thus making
more money from financial transactions than from actually producing
goods. According to Chernomas,
475
12: CONCLUSION
In War against the People: Israel, the Palestinians and Global Pacification,
Jeff Halper (2015) describes and analyzes in meticulous detail Israel’s
extensive contribution to sophisticated techniques of pacifying and
managing both perceived enemies and the “surplus” people gener-
ated by the global capitalist economy (recall Razack [2008] from
Chapter 11). Treating the Occupied Territories as a laboratory, Israel
and Israeli corporations have become expert in
A sociology of crime
Professional sociology has always responded to the tenor of the times,
whether in a spirit of positive scientific engagement or puzzled awe
or commitment to radical change or pessimistic undermining of
received truths. All of these attitudes can be found informing, if not
infecting, its approaches to the study of crime, criminality and crimi-
nalization, as I hope this book has demonstrated. Whether aligned
with correctional, interpretative, emancipatory or deconstructive
attitudes towards inquiry, professional sociologists of crime, one must
assume, have thought there was a value in exposing others, above all
university students and their colleagues in the profession, to their
thoughts – that in one way or another, it would be good for them.
And that pedagogical disposition presupposed that, after all, the world
476
12: CONCLUSION
would carry on and would be better for their work. In his Massey
Lectures, published as A Short History of Progress (2004), mentioned
above, Ronald Wright reviews the fate of a number of former civi-
lizations that rose to prominence and then collapsed, among them
Mesopotamia, the Incas and Easter Island. But in the conclusion to
his book, he points out that whereas each of those collapses gave way
to the rise of another civilization there or somewhere else, if “our”
civilization goes down, there will be none to replace it since “ours”
is global in extent. We are inextricably linked to one another clima-
tologically and economically. As I said at the outset of this chapter,
this does put a chill on the writing of a textbook for undergraduate
students. What good will it do them in the face of such a prospect?
What good will it do you?
To be a little more circumspect about the dystopian predictions,
perhaps it may be conceded that not all humans will be wiped out.
Some pockets of life, perhaps quite large ones, will survive the rising
temperatures, rising waters, violent storms, polluted oceans, deser-
tification, insect infestations, species die-offs and so on. They will
go on living, together, starting again in some sense. And if that is so,
there is no reason to suppose that they won’t (continue to) judge one
another’s conduct, find it wanting and want to sanction it. At just
that point, however, might it not be advantageous for those engaged
in this socializing endeavour to have thought about what they are
doing or are about to do? Were they to reflect on Durkheim’s (1982
[1895]) community of saints, or Comack’s (1985) analysis of race,
class and morality, or Sangster’s (1996) interrogation of conceptions
of women’s sexuality, or Churchill’s (1998) dreadful story of colonial
genocide, would it not give them pause, cause them to think twice?
Might then the chances of not repeating the follies of the past and
present be increased, if just a little? Perhaps “committing sociology”
is just what is required (Coutts 2013).
But then what of “grammatical respecification”? Why did Steve
want so much to radically revise the first edition of this book in a
thoroughly ethnomethodological way? What would be the benefit of
doing that? Certainly the motivation was intellectual in nature. The
idea was to show on what the foundations of professional sociology
rested, that they rested on the sense-making practices of ordinary, eve-
ryday life that everybody used and engaged in, members’ methods of
sociological inquiry. There is certainly a sort of anti-pretentiousness
477
12: CONCLUSION
involved. Yet, what possible good can come from that for people
struggling to survive, rebuild and maintain some semblance of civi-
lized life? What good is it now for those of us looking out across the
brink, trying to figure out what best to do now? “Garfinkel’s interest
in the specificity and ‘just-whatness’ of actions brackets normative
issues in favour of ‘how does this work’ questions about local social
order.The phenomena described by ethno/CA are neither good nor
bad: they just are” (Dingwall 2000: 901). Similarly, “Sacks did not set
out to study language or conversation but to discover how ordinary
things got done in a recognizably consistent and orderly fashion”
(Dingwall 2000: 893, citing Schegloff 1992a: xvi–xvii). So it is for the
studies of police work, lawyers’ work, jury deliberations and the use
of the convict code by inmates and staff of a halfway house reviewed
and replayed herein. Ethnomethodological studies reveal just how the
phenomena those activities produce, of which they consist, are made
observable and reportable as just what they are.
Furthermore, according to Dingwall (2000: 901), Sacks “once
remarked that a lot of revolutions could go on without ever chang-
ing everyday life very much.” In other words, members’ methods of
sociological inquiry, respecting the rule of practical circumstances to
which they are indexically and reflexively tied, will continue what-
ever. To point this out, however, can hardly be said to make any
practical difference to the task of deciding the fate of the world. It
has no practical purchase on the hard political and ethical choices of
vision, purpose and policy that are required now, if not to avert, then
to mitigate the coming disasters. That is indubitably true. Indeed, in
Wittgenstein’s famous dictum, like philosophy, grammatical respecifi-
cation “leaves everything as it is” (Sharrock and Anderson 1991: 62).
What, then, could be the point?
To be reminded of the interactional accomplishment of social facts,
of how phenomena are constituted as what they observably are as
social things, is to be brought back, perhaps for the first time, to just
what it is to be engaged in an activity as a course of action with
others. Such a realization invites awe at the fact that such socially
organized life exists at all. Wittgenstein is again illuminating beyond
the ordinary.To repeat a passage from Chapter 2, “Not how the world
is, is the mystical, but that it is” (Wittgenstein 2007 [1922]: 6.44,
p. 107). That socially organized life is possible at all is the amazing
thing. That the world is made social is the amazing thing. Moreover,
478
12: CONCLUSION
479
References
480
REFERENCES
www.amnesty.org/en/documents/amr51/076/1992/en/ (Accessed
19 July 2016).
Amnesty International. 1998. United States of America: Rights for All.
New York: Amnesty International USA.
Amnesty International. 2003. United States of America: Death by
Discrimination – The Continuing Role of Race in Capital Cases: www.
amnesty.org/en/documents/AMR51/046/2003/en/ (Accessed
19 July 2016).
Anderson, Digby G. and Wesley W. Sharrock. 1979.“Biasing the news:
Technical issues in ‘media studies’.” Sociology 13 (3): 367–385.
Anderson, Nels. 1923. The Hobo. Chicago, IL: Chicago University
Press.
Anderson, Robert J., John A. Hughes and W. W. Sharrock. 1985. The
Sociology Game: An Introduction to Sociological Reasoning. London,
UK: Longman.
Anderson, Septembre. 2016. “Today’s feminist problem? Black
women are still invisible.” The Globe and Mail, 9 March: www.
theglobeandmail.com/opinion/todays-feminist-problem-black-
women-are-still-invisible/article29082375/ (Accessed 18 July 2016).
Anderson, William C. 2016. “Charged with being alive: Terence
Crutcher and Keith Lamont Scott.” truthout.org, 24 September: www.
truth-out.org/news/item/37743-charged-with-being-alive-
terence-crutcher-and-keith-lamont-scott (Accessed 25 September
2016).
Angus, Ian. 2016. Facing the Anthropocene: Fossil Capitalism and the
Crisis of the Earth System. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Antaki, Charles and Sue Widdicombe. Eds. 1998. Identities in Talk.
London, UK: Sage.
Arrigo, Bruce A. and Heather Y. Bersot. Eds. 2014. The Routledge
Handbook of International Crime and Justice Studies. London, UK and
New York: Routledge.
Associated Press. 1991. “Study of 141-year-old corpse rules out
Taylor’s poisoning.” Kitchener-Waterloo Record, 27 June, B7.
Associated Press. 1992.“Chicago police tortured poor suspects, probe
says.” Kitchener-Waterloo Record, 8 February, H8.
Associated Press. 1995. “Victims of heat wave go to paupers’ graves.”
Kitchener-Waterloo Record, 26 August, D16.
Athens, Lonnie. 1980. Violent Criminal Acts and Actors. London, UK:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
481
REFERENCES
482
REFERENCES
483
REFERENCES
484
REFERENCES
485
REFERENCES
486
REFERENCES
487
REFERENCES
488
REFERENCES
489
REFERENCES
490
REFERENCES
491
REFERENCES
492
REFERENCES
493
REFERENCES
494
REFERENCES
Cresswell, Peter. 1975. Suicide and Crime. Milton Keynes, UK: Open
University Press.
Cribb, Robert and Marco Chown Oved. 2016. “York honours
Canadian named in the Panama Papers.” The Toronto Star, 21 June:
http://torontostar.newspaperdirect.com/epaper/showarticle.
aspx?issue=10382016062100000000001001&page=1&article=
5e3e4c90-1b30-41d5-b44a-6c7165f03995&key=76ntTyNiYrWr5
mFOqtsr0Q (Accessed 21 June 2016).
Croall, Hazel. 2011. Crime and Society in Britain. Second edition.
Harlow, UK: Pearson Education.
Cuevas Villalobos, Elizabeth. 2004. “Se instala casino de apuestas al
interior de la feria Cuernavaca . . . Opera casino ilegal en Feria
Cuernavaca 2004.” La Jornada Morelos, 13 April, 16, 8.
Cuff, Edward C. 1994. Problems of Versions in Everyday Situations.
Washington, DC: International Institute for Ethnomethodology
and Conversation Analysis; Lanham, MD: University Press of
America. (Originally published in 1980.)
Cuff, Edward C. and David W. Francis. 1978. “Some features of
‘invited stories’ about marriage breakdown.” International Journal
of the Sociology of Language 18: 111–133.
Cuff, Edward C. and George C. F. Payne. Eds. 1984. Perspectives
in Sociology. Second edition. London, UK: George Allen and
Unwin.
Cuff, Edward C., David W. Francis and W. W. Sharrock. 1990.
Perspectives in Sociology. Third edition. London, UK: Unwin
Hyman.
Cuff, Edward C., Alex J. Dennis, David W. Francis and W. W. Sharrock.
2016. Perspectives in Sociology. Sixth edition. London, UK and New
York: Routledge.
Curtis, Bruce. 2012. Ruling by Schooling Quebec: From Conquest to Liberal
Governmentality: A Historical Sociology. Toronto, ON: University of
Toronto Press.
Curtis, Bruce. 2016. “The missing memory of Canadian sociology:
Reflexive government and ‘the social science’.” Canadian Review
of Sociology 53 (2): 203–225.
D’Aliesio, Renata. 2011. “Canadians can’t complain: Better Life
Index.” The Globe and Mail, 24 May, A6.
Daschuk, James. 2013a.“When Canada used hunger to clear the West.”
The Globe and Mail, 19 July: www.theglobeandmail.com/opinion/
495
REFERENCES
when-canada-used-hunger-to-clear-the-west/article13316877/
(Accessed 25 September 2016).
Daschuk, James. 2013b. Clearing the Plains: Disease, Politics of Starvation,
and the Loss of Aboriginal Life. Regina, SK: University of Regina
Press.
Davis, Kingsley. 1937. “The sociology of prostitution.” American
Sociological Review 2 (5): 744–755.
Davis, Kingsley. 1959. “The myth of functional analysis as a spe-
cial method in sociology and anthropology.” American Sociological
Review 24 (6): 757–772.
Davis, Mike. 1992. “LA: The fire this time.” Covert Action Information
Bulletin, 41 (Summer): 12–21.
Davis, Mike with Sue Ruddick. 1988. “Los Angeles: Civil liberties
between the hammer and the rock.” New Left Review 170: 37–60.
Davis, Nanette J. and Clarice Stasz. 1990. Social Control of Deviance:
A Critical Perspective. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Davis, Robert and Mark Zannis. 1973. The Genocide Machine in
Canada. Montreal, QC: Black Rose.
DeKeseredy, Walter S. 2000. Women, Crime and the Canadian Criminal
Justice System. Cincinnati, OH: Anderson Publishing.
DeKeseredy, Walter S. 2011. Violence against Women: Myths, Facts,
Controversies. Toronto, ON: Toronto University Press.
DeKeseredy, Walter S. and Molly Dragiewicz. Eds. 2012. Routledge
Handbook of Critical Criminology. London, UK and New York:
Routledge.
de las Casas, Bartolomé. 1971. History of the Indies. New York: Harper
and Row. (Originally written in Spanish between 1527 and
1561.)
Delgado, Richard and Jean Stefancic. 2012. Critical Race Theory: An
Introduction. Second edition. New York and London, UK: New
York University Press.
De Mauro,Tullio. 1958.“Storia e analisi semantica di ‘classe’.” Rassegna
di Filosofia 7 (4): 309–351.
Demerson, Velma. 2004. Incorrigible. Waterloo, ON: Wilfrid Laurier
University Press.
Dennis, Alex, Rob Philburn and Greg Smith. 2013. Sociologies of
Interaction. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Derrida, Jacques. 1970. “Structure, sign, and play in the discourse
of the human sciences.” In R. Macksey and E. Donato (eds), The
496
REFERENCES
497
REFERENCES
498
REFERENCES
499
REFERENCES
500
REFERENCES
501
REFERENCES
medium=Newsletter&utm_source=Morning%20News%20
Update&utm_type=text&utm_content=MorningNewsUpdate&
utm_campaign=136848978 (Accessed 1 August 2016).
Finkelstein, Norman G. 2014. Method and Madness: The Hidden Story
of Israel’s Assaults on Gaza. New York: OR Books.
Fischer, Benedikt, Kari Ala-Leppilampi, Eric Single and Amanda
Robins. 2003. “Cannabis law reform in Canada: Is the ‘saga of
promise, hesitation and retreat’ coming to an end?” Canadian
Journal of Criminology and Criminal Justice 45 (3): 265–295.
Fish, Stanley. 2008. Save the World on Your Own Time. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Fishman, Mark. 1978. “Crime waves as ideology.” Social Problems 25
(5): 531–543. (Reprinted in Potter and Kappeler, 53–72.)
Fishman, Mark. 1980. Manufacturing the News. Austin, TX: University
of Texas Press.
Fitzgerald, Mike. 1977. Prisoners in Revolt. Harmondsworth, UK:
Penguin.
Fitzgerald, Richard and William Housley. Eds. 2015. Advances in
Membership Categorization Analysis. London, UK: Sage.
Fleming, Thomas. Ed. 1985. The New Criminologies in Canada: State,
Crime, and Control. Toronto, ON: Oxford University Press.
Foster, John Bellamy. 2015. “The new imperialism of globalized
monopoly-finance capital: An introduction.” Monthly Review 67
(3): 1–22.
Foucault, Michel. 1972. The Archaeology of Knowledge.Translated by A.
M. Sheridan Smith. London, UK:Tavistock. (Originally published
in French in 1969; Routledge Classics 2002.)
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison.
Translated by Alan Sheridan. London, UK: Allen Lane. (Originally
published in French in 1975.)
Foucault, Michel. 1983. “Afterword:The subject and power.” In H. L.
Dreyfus and P. Rabinow (eds), Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism
and Hermeneutics. Second edition. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press, 208–226.
Foucault, Michel. 1990. The History of Sexuality. Three volumes.
Translated by Robert Hurley. New York:Vintage. (Originally pub-
lished in French in 1976 and 1984.)
Foucault, Michel. 2002. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the
Human Sciences. Translated by Alan Sheridan. New York and
502
REFERENCES
503
REFERENCES
504
REFERENCES
505
REFERENCES
mexicos-missing-forty-three-one-year-many-lies-and-a-theory-
that-might-make-sense (Accessed 15 October 2016).
Goldman, Russell. 2007. “Excited delirium: Police brutality vs. sheer
insanity.” ABC News, 2 March: http://abcnews.go.com/Health/
story?id=2919037&page=1 (Accessed 15 December 2016).
Goldthorpe, John H. 1973. “Review article: A revolution in sociol-
ogy?” Sociology 7 (3): 449–462.
Goode, Erich and Nachman Ben-Yehuda. 2009. Moral Panics: The
Social Construction of Deviance. Second edition. Chichester, UK:
Wiley-Blackwell. (Originally published in 1994.)
Gordon, Colin. 1991. “Governmental rationality: An introduction.”
In G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller (eds), The Foucault Effect:
Studies in Governmentality. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Press, 1–51.
Gordon, Todd. 2010. Imperialist Canada. Winnipeg, MB: Arbeiter
Ring.
Gorner, Jeremy. 2015.“Street stops by Chicago police surpass NewYork,
ACLU finds.” ChicagoTribune, 23 March: www.chicagotribune.com/
news/ct-stop-and-frisk-chicago-police-met-20150323-story.
html (Accessed 7 August 2016).
Gottfredson, Michael R. and Travis Hirschi. 1990. A General Theory
of Crime. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Graham, Thomas. 2016. “Colombia’s ‘social cleansing’ phenome-
non: Exterminating people like bugs.” Colombia Reports, 21 April:
http://colombiareports.com/social-extermination-undesirables-
colombia/ (Accessed 5 January 2017).
Grahame, Kamini M. 1985.“Sexual harassment.” In C. Guberman and
M. Wolfe (eds), No Safe Place: Violence against Women and Children.
Toronto, ON: Women’s Press.
Gray, Herman S. 1989. “Popular music as a social problem: A social
history of claims against popular music.” In J. Best (ed.), Images of
Issues: Typifying Contemporary Social Problems. New York: Aldine de
Gruyter, 143–158.
Green, Melvin. 1986. “A history of Canadian narcotics control: The
formative years.” In N. Boyd (ed.), The Social Dimensions of Law.
Scarborough, ON: Prentice-Hall Canada, 24–40. (Originally pub-
lished in 1979 in University of Toronto Faculty of Law Review 37: 42–79.)
Greenwald, Glenn. 2015. No Place to Hide: Edward Snowden, the NSA
and the Surveillance State. New York: Penguin.
506
REFERENCES
507
REFERENCES
508
REFERENCES
Hammond, Andrew. 2015. “Global trends: Five years after the Arab
Spring, a world of economic discontent.” The Globe and Mail, 18
December, B4.
Harris, David A. 1997. “‘Driving while black’ and all other traffic
offenses: The Supreme Court and pretextual traffic stops.” Journal
of Criminal Law and Criminology 87 (2): 544–582.
Harris, Jerry. 2016. Global Capitalism and the Crisis of Democracy.
Atlanta, GA: Clarity Press.
Harris, Michael. 1986. Justice Denied: The Law versus Donald Marshall.
Toronto, ON: Macmillan.
Hart, Herbert L. A. 1965.“The ascription of responsibility and rights.”
In A. Flew (ed.), Logic and Language. First and second series. Garden
City, NY: Doubleday Anchor, 151–174. (Originally published in
1948–1949 in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.)
Hart, Herbert L. A. and Tony Honoré. 1985. Causation in the Law.
Second edition. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Hart, Ron. 2011. “Ecocide should be added to list of crimes against
humanity.” CCPA Monitor, September, 13.
Harvey, David. 2005. A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press.
Haveman, Roelof and Alette Smeulers. Eds. 2008. Supranational
Criminology:Towards a Criminology of International Crimes. Antwerp,
Belgium: Intersentia.
Hawkins, Richard and Gary Tiedeman. 1975. The Creation of Deviance:
Interpersonal and Organizational Determinants. Columbus, OH:
Charles E. Merrill.
Hayduk, Leslie A. 1976.“Formulations in police work: Some observa-
tions and related theoretical concerns.” Canadian Journal of Sociology
1 (4): 463–479.
Hayes, Kelly. 2015. “Sometimes we win.” truthout.org, 22 May.
Hearse, Phil. 2016. “Neoliberalism’s world of corruption.” The Bullet,
E-Bulletin No. 1245, 12 April: www.socialistproject.ca/bullet/
1245.php (Accessed 31 May 2016).
Hedges, Chris. 2016a. In “Who should Bernie voters support now?
Robert Reich vs. Chris Hedges on tackling the neoliberal order.”
Democracy Now, 26 July: www.democracynow.org/2016/7/26/
who_should_bernie_voters_support_now (Accessed 4 August
2016).
Hedges, Chris. 2016b. “Fooled again.” truthdig.org, 11 September:
509
REFERENCES
www.truthdig.com/report/item/fooled_again_20160911 (Accessed
3 October 2016).
Heffernan, Esther. 1972. Making It in Prison:The Square, the Cool, and
the Life. New York: Wiley-Interscience.
Henry, Frances. 1999. The Racialization of Crime in Toronto’s
Print Media: A Research Project. Unpublished report, School of
Journalism, Ryerson Polytechnic University, Toronto.
Henry, Frances and Carol Tator. 2002. Discourses of Domination:
Racial Bias in the Canadian English-Language Press. Toronto, ON:
University of Toronto Press.
Henry, Stuart. 2011. “Series preface.” In Lynch and Stretesky, 2011a,
ix–x.
Hepburn, John R. 1977.“Social control and the legal order: Legitimated
repression in a capitalist state.” Contemporary Crises 1 (1): 77–90.
Herbert, Bob. 2010. “Jim Crow policing.” The New York Times, 1
February: www.nytimes.com/2010/02/02/opinion/02herbert.
html (Accessed 17 July 2016).
Heritage, John C. 1984a. “A change of state token and aspects of its
sequential placement.” In Atkinson and Heritage, 299–345.
Heritage, John C. 1984b. Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology. Cambridge,
UK: Polity Press.
Heritage, John C. and David Greatbach. 1986. “Generating applause:
A study of rhetoric and response at party political conferences.”
American Journal of Sociology 92 (1): 110–157.
Herman, Edward S. and Noam Chomsky. 2002. Manufacturing Consent:
The Political Economy of the Mass Media.With a new introduction by
the authors. New York: Pantheon. (Originally published in 1988.)
Hester, Stephen. 1991.“The social facts of deviance in school: A study
of mundane reason.” British Journal of Sociology 42 (3): 443–463.
Hester, Stephen. 1992. “Recognising references to deviance in referral
talk.” In G.Watson and R. M. Sieler (eds), Text in Context: Contributions
to Ethnomethodology. Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 156–174.
Hester, Stephen. 2009. “Ethnomethodology: Respecifying the
problem of social order.” In M. H. Jacobsen (ed.), Encountering
the Everyday: An Introduction to the Sociologies of the Unnoticed.
Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 234–256.
Hester, Stephen. 2016. Descriptions of Deviance. International Institute
for Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis legacy website:
http://emca-legacy.info/hester.html (Accessed 27 December 2016).
510
REFERENCES
511
REFERENCES
512
REFERENCES
Hunter, Jennifer. 2014.“Race riots and how Mackenzie King made his
name.” The Toronto Star, 4 April: www.thestar.com/news/insight/
2014/04/04/race_riots_and_how_mackenzie_king_made_his_
name.html (Accessed 30 April 2016).
Hunter, Jennifer. 2015. “Rachel Holmes: Daughter of Karl Marx
turned his ideas into activism.” The Toronto Star, 20 June, IN2.
Hunter, Patrick. 2013. “Number of Blacks in Canadian prisons
troubling.” share, 4 December: sharenews.com/number-of-blacks-
in-canadian-prisons-troubling/ (Accessed 18 February 2016) .
Hutchinson, Phil, Rupert Read and Wes Sharrock. 2008. There Is No
Such Thing as a Social Science: In Defence of Peter Winch. Aldershot,
UK: Ashgate.
Hylton, John H. 1981. “The growth of punishment: Imprisonment
and community corrections in Canada.” Crime and Social Justice 15
(1): 18–28.
Ibarra, Peter and John I. Kitsuse. 1993. “Vernacular constituents of
moral discourse: An interactionist proposal for the study of social
problems.” In Holstein and Miller, 25–58. Also in Miller and
Holstein, 21–54.
Ignatieff, Michael. 1978. A Just Measure of Pain: The Penitentiary in
the Industrial Revolution, 1750–1850. New York: Pantheon. (New
edition published by Penguin in 1989.)
Ignatieff, Michael. 1983. “State, civil society and total institutions:
A critique of recent social theories of punishment.” In S. Cohen
and A. T. Scull (eds), Social Control and the State: Historical and
Comparative Essays. Oxford, UK: Martin Robertson, 75–105.
(Originally published in 1981.)
Ignatieff, Michael. 2009. The Rights Revolution. CBC Massey Lectures.
Toronto, ON: House of Anansi Press. (Originally published in
2000.)
Indigenous Foundations. “Sixties Scoop.” http://indigenous
foundations.arts.ubc.ca/home/government-policy/sixties-scoop.
html (Accessed 23 September 2016).
Irwin, John K. 1970. The Felon. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Irwin, John K. and Donald R. Cressey. 1962. “Thieves, convicts and
inmate culture.” Social Problems 10 (2): 142–155.
Jacobs, James B. 1974. “Street gangs behind bars.” Social Problems 21
(3): 395–409.
Jacobs, James B. and Jessica S. Henry. 1996. “The social construction
513
REFERENCES
514
REFERENCES
515
REFERENCES
516
REFERENCES
517
REFERENCES
518
REFERENCES
519
REFERENCES
Turn in the Philosophy, History, and Social Studies of Science. New York
and London, UK: Routledge, 93–113.
Lynch, Michael E. 2016. “Radical ethnomethodology.” Position
paper for workshop on radical ethnomethodology, Manchester
Metropolitan University, United Kingdom, 22–23 June.
Lynch, Michael E. and David Bogen. 1994. “Harvey Sacks’ primitive
natural science.” Theory, Culture and Society 11 (4): 65–104.
Lynch, Michael E. and David Bogen. 1997. “Sociology’s asociologi-
cal ‘core’: An examination of textbook sociology in light of the
sociology of scientific knowledge.” American Sociological Review 62
(3): 481–493.
Lynch, Michael E. and W. W. Sharrock. Eds. 2003. Harold Garfinkel.
Three volumes. Sage Masters of Modern Social Thought. London,
UK: Sage.
Lynch, Michael E., Simon A. Cole, Ruth McNally and Kathleen
Jordan. 2008. Truth Machine: The Contentious History of DNA
Fingerprinting. Chicago, IL and London, UK: University of Chicago
Press.
Lynch, Michael J. and Paul B. Stretesky. Eds. 2011a. Radical and Marxist
Theories of Crime.The Library of Essays in Theoretical Criminology.
Farnham, UK: Ashgate.
Lynch, Michael J. and Paul B. Stretesky. 2011b. “Introduction.” In
Lynch and Stretesky, 2011a, xi–xxix.
McBarnet, Dorothy J. 1981. Conviction: Law, the State and the
Construction of Justice. London, UK: Macmillan.
McCarthy, John D. and Mayer N. Zald. 1973. The Trend of Social
Movements in America: Professionalization and Resource Mobilization.
Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press.
McCleary, Richard. 1992. Dangerous Men: The Sociology of Parole.
Second edition. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
(Originally published by Sage in 1978.)
McCoy, Alfred. 1991. The Politics of Heroin: CIA Complicity in the
Global Drug Trade. Second edition. New York: Lawrence Hill.
MacDonald, David B. 2015. “Five reasons the TRC chose the words
‘cultural genocide’.” The Globe and Mail, 6 July, A12.
Macdonald, Nancy. 2016. “Canada’s prisons are the ‘new residential
schools’.” Maclean’s, 18 February: www.macleans.ca/news/canada/
canadas-prisons-are-the-new-residential-schools/ (Accessed 21
February 2016).
520
REFERENCES
521
REFERENCES
522
REFERENCES
523
REFERENCES
524
REFERENCES
525
REFERENCES
526
REFERENCES
527
REFERENCES
528
REFERENCES
529
REFERENCES
530
REFERENCES
531
REFERENCES
532
REFERENCES
533
REFERENCES
534
REFERENCES
535
REFERENCES
536
REFERENCES
Scahill, Jeremy and The Staff of The Intercept. 2016. The Assassination
Complex: Inside the Government’s Secret Drone Warfare Program.
London, UK: Serpent’s Tail.
Schatzki,Theodore R., Karin Knorr-Cetina and Eike von Savigny. Eds.
2001. The PracticeTurn in ContemporaryTheory. London, UK: Routledge.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1968. “Sequencing in conversational open-
ings.” American Anthropologist 70 (6): 1075–1095.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1972. “Notes on a conversational practice:
Formulating place.” In D. Sudnow (ed.), Studies in Social Interaction.
New York: Free Press, 75–119.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1991. “Reflections on talk and social struc-
ture.” In D. Boden and D. H. Zimmerman (eds), Talk and Social
Structure. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 44–70.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1992a. “Introduction.” In Sacks, 1992a, ix–lxii.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1992b. “Introduction.” In Sacks, 1992b, ix–lii.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1997.“Whose text? Whose context?” Discourse
and Society 8 (2): 165–187.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2007a. “A tutorial on membership categoriza-
tion.” Journal of Pragmatics 39 (3): 462–482.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2007b.“Categories in action: Person-reference
and membership categorization.” Discourse Studies 9 (4): 433–461.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2007c. Sequence Organization in Interaction: A
Primer in Sequential Analysis,Volume 1. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Schegloff, Emanuel A., Gail Jefferson and Harvey Sacks. 1977. “The
preference for self-correction in the organization of repair in
conversation.” Language 53 (2): 361–382.
Schenkein, James N. Ed. 1978. Studies in the Organization of
Conversational Interaction. New York: Academic.
Schenwar, Maya, Joe Macaré and Alana Yu-lan Price. Eds. 2016. Who
Do You Serve, Who Do You Protect? Police Violence and Resistance in
the United States. A Truthout Collection. Chicago, IL: Haymarket
Books.
Schneider, Joseph W. 2008.“Saving social construction: Contributions
from cultural studies.” In Holstein and Gubrium, 2008a, 733–751.
Schur, Edwin M. 1973. Radical Non-Intervention: Rethinking the
Delinquency Problem. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Schutz, Alfred. 1962a. “Concept and theory formation in the social
sciences.” In A. Schutz, Collected Papers 1: The Problem of Social
537
REFERENCES
538
REFERENCES
539
REFERENCES
540
REFERENCES
541
REFERENCES
542
REFERENCES
543
REFERENCES
544
REFERENCES
Taylor, Ian, Paul Walton and Jock Young. 1973. The New Criminology:
For a Social Theory of Deviance. London, UK: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Taylor, Laurie. 1972. “The significance and interpretation of replies
to motivational questions: The case of sex offenders.” Sociology 6
(1): 23–39.
Taylor, Sandie. 2016. Crime and Criminality: A Multidisciplinary
Approach. London, UK and New York: Routledge.
Tepperman, Lorne. 1977. Crime Control: The Urge Toward Authority.
Toronto, ON: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.
Thomas, William I. 1923. The Unadjusted Girl: With Cases and
Standpoint for Behaviour Analysis. Boston, MA: Little, Brown.
Thomas, William I. and Dorothy Swaine Thomas. 1928. The Child in
America: Behaviour Problems and Programs. New York: Knopf.
Tierney, Kathleen J. 1982.“The battered women movement and the crea-
tion of the wife beating problem.” Social Problems 29 (3): 207–220.
Tilley, Nick. 2012. “Review of Policing Problem Places: Crime Hot
Spots and Effective Prevention by A. A. Braga and D. L. Weisbrud.”
Contemporary Sociology 41 (2): 184–185.
Tisdale, Sallie. 1998. “Outlaw acts: Let me tell you about the crime I
committed . . .” The Globe and Mail, 13 June, D3.
Tonry, Michael. 2014a. “Why crime rates are falling throughout the
Western world.” In Tonry, 2014b, 1–63.
Tonry, Michael. Ed. 2014b. Why Crime Rates Fall and Why They Don’t.
Crime and Justice,Volume 43. Chicago, IL and London: University
of Chicago Press.
Travers, Max. 1997a. “Introduction to Part I.” In Travers and Manzo,
19–24.
Travers, Max. 1997b. “Introduction to Part II.” In Travers and Manzo,
133–136.
Travers, Max and John F. Manzo. Eds. 1997. Law in Action:
Ethnomethodological and Conversation Analytic Approaches to Law.
Aldershot, UK: Dartmouth/Ashgate.
Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Canada. 2015. “Calls to
action.” In Honouring the Truth, Reconciling for the Future: Summary of
the Final Report of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Canada.
Electronic monograph in PDF format, 319–337: www.trc.ca/
websites/trcinstitution/index.php?p=890 (Accessed 28 April
2016).
545
REFERENCES
546
REFERENCES
547
REFERENCES
548
REFERENCES
549
REFERENCES
550
REFERENCES
35804-how-capitalism-and-racism-support-each-other (Accessed
31 July 2016).
Wood, Lesley J. 2014. Crisis and Control: The Militarization of Protest
Policing. Toronto, ON: Between the Lines.
Woolgar, Steve and Dorothy Pawluch. 1985. “Ontological gerry-
mandering: The anatomy of social problems explanations.” Social
Problems 32 (3): 214–227.
Worrall, Anne. 1990. Offending Women: Female Lawbreakers and the
Criminal Justice System. London, UK: Routledge.
Wotherspoon, Terry and Vic Satzewich. 2000. First Nations: Race,
Class, and Gender Relations. Regina, SK: Canadian Plains Research
Centre, University of Regina. (Originally published in 1993 by
Nelson Canada.)
Wowk, Maria T. 1984. “Blame allocation, sex and gender in a mur-
der interrogation.” Women’s Studies International Forum 7 (1):
75–82.
Wowk, Maria T. and Andrew P. Carlin. 2008. “Depicting a liminal
position in ethnomethodology, conversation analysis and member-
ship categorization analysis: The work of Rod Watson.” Human
Studies 27 (1): 69–89.
Wright, Eric O. 1997. Classes. New York:Verso. (Originally published
in 1985.)
Wright, Ronald O. 1992. Stolen Continents: The “New World” through
Indian Eyes since 1492. New York: Penguin Viking.
Wright, Ronald O. 2004. A Short History of Progress. Toronto, ON:
House of Anansi Press.
Yew, Madhavi Acharya-Tom. 2014. “Jian Ghomeshi allegations
leave Iranian-Canadians feeling sad and betrayed.” The Toronto
Star, 10 November: www.thestar.com/news/gta/2014/11/10/
jian_ghomeshi_allegations_leave_iraniancanadians_feeling_sad_
and_betrayed.html (Accessed 24 July 2016).
York, Geoffrey. 1989. The Dispossessed: Life and Death in Native Canada.
Toronto, ON: Lester and Orpen Dennys.
York, Geoffrey and David Roberts. 1991a. “RCMP role in Osborne
case condemned.” The Globe and Mail, 30 August, A4.
York, Geoffrey and David Roberts. 1991b.“Police lied to save officer,
jurists find.” The Globe and Mail, 30 August, A4.
York, Geoffrey and David Roberts. 1991c. “Judges urge separate
native justice system: Treatment of Indians by legal system an
551
REFERENCES
552
REFERENCES
553
Index
Page numbers in italics refer 156, 158, 161, 265, 273, amplification of crime
to boxed features. 310, 312 166–70
administration of objectivity Angus, Ian 473
(dis)ability 31, 33, 242, 256, 223–5 anomie see Durkheim;
405 administrative criminology Merton
aboriginal people 244, 278, 42–5, 265; and statistical Arabs 354, 440–41
326–7, 354, 368, 379, correctionalism 46–51; Atkinson, J. Maxwell 155
385; Aboriginal Justice see also correctional attitude: common-sense 14;
Inquiry of Manitoba criminology ethnomethodology xi–xii;
359–61; Australian Afghanistan 435–6, 436, 474 of everyday life 21, 77,
433, 443–50, 457, 463, African-Americans: civil 210; natural 21, 46, 275;
468; Canadian 65, rights movement 242; scientific 14, 46, 276;
355, 357–8, 375, 456–7, contemporary experience theoretic 210
458–9; contemporary of racist law enforcement Atwood, Margaret 474
experience 359–62; 362–7; criminalization of Austin, John L. 120, 194
genocide in the Americas 372; history 369; studies
434, 443, 450–68, 477; 242; Tuskegee experiment Bailey, Moya: “misogynoir”
missing and murdered 456; see also “Black Lives 394
aboriginal/indigenous Matter”; “Driving While battered women: battered
women xi, 2, 65, 354; Black”; slavery wife defence 138, 139;
Royal Commission African-Canadians: battered wife syndrome
on (RCAP) 361, 455, contemporary experience 138; charging practices
456; see also Truth of racist law enforcement 60–1; movement 139;
and Reconciliation 355–9; see also “Black shelters 4, 106; social
Commission of Canada Lives Matter”; “Driving construction of the wife
abortion 3, 138, 334; see also While Black”; slavery beating problem 138–41,
Petchesky Althusser, Louis 258 145; see also Loseke
actor’s point of view 118, American Sociological Becker, Howard S.:
173, 194 Association (ASA) 52, 76, becoming a marijuana
administration (government, 103–4 user 109, 167;
public, social, state) 33, 46, Amnesty International: contradiction in model of
51, 58, 62, 72, 74, 79–81; reports on racism in the types of deviant behaviour
colonial 444, 467–9 US criminal justice system 154–5, 160, 169, 189–91,
administration of justice 95, 362–4, 375 229, 231; labelling theory
554
INDEX
of deviance 122–3; Canadian Centre for Justice 264; see also crime,
Marihuana Tax Act 128; Statistics (CCJS) 50, 63–6 state-organized
moral entrepreneur 124, Canadian narcotics Chernomas, Robert 475
128; resort to quantitative legislation 129–36, 262; Chicago School of
measurement 155; values see also Comack; Small Sociology 55, 56, 153
133; see also Pollner capitalism 247–313, 335; child abuse 9, 137;
Bell, Daniel 59 contradictions of 254, construction of 127, 128,
Bentham, Jeremy: classical 257, 258, 300; corporate 138, 143, 144
criminology 294; 319–24; entrepreneurial Chinese: consorting with
panopticon 56, 406 321; and global warming men 418; Exclusion Act
Berger, Peter L. 41, 84–5, 261, 473–4; and 358; gangs 423; opium
177; and Luckmann 122 imperialism 438; industrial 129–32, 267–72, 448;
Best, Joel: “contextual” versus 247, 253, 269, 275, 313; police stops of male 356;
“strict” constructionism inequality endemic to “question” 269–71, 369
143; leading figure in 250; mercantile 465; Chomsky, Noam 80, 242,
constructionist studies neoliberal 260, 299; 247, 255, 277, 280–1, 436,
127 post-industrial 375–6; and 438, 462
Bittner, Egon 66–8, 79, 161, racism 369, 373; a system Christie, Nils: genocide 376;
232, 272, 306; the police of forced labour 249, 260; growth of imprisonment
on skid row 211–15 a totalizing process 256; 280, 282, 366; gulag 366;
“Black Lives Matter” 3, 353, welfare state 260 surplus population 278
372 carceral archipelago 404 Churchill, Ward see
Blaut, James M. 438, 450, career: criminal 182, 185; aboriginal peoples:
467 delinquent 176; deviant genocide in the Americas
Blumberg, Abraham 178–81 166; Matza’s steps 186; Cicourel, Aaron V.:
Blumer, Herbert: core moral 35, 183; of a statistic ambivalence 154; juvenile
theoretical premises 70, 145; of a suspect’s justice 174, 204; see also
151–2; influence of Mead statement 204 Kitsuse
120,156; sociological Carlen, Pat: on women’s claims-making 31, 32, 33,
analysis and the imprisonment 337–9, 348 124–49
“variable” 155; symbolic cell phone 1, 372, 381, 409, class 31, 32, 33, 61, 156,
interactionism 116, 122, 410 247–313; analysis 255;
126 Central Intelligence Agency conflict 262, 266–7,
Bogen, David 11, 13, 15, (CIA) 2, 435 270–1, 299; race and
143–9, 191, 202 Center for Research on gender 241–5, 261,
Bottomley, A. Keith 51–2, Criminal Justice 263, 270; 282–3, 374, 392–3, 420,
276 see also policing the slave 425; struggle 242, 255,
Box, Steven 53–4, 92, 94, economy 260, 291, 439; underclass
97–8, 155, 184–8, 284–5, chain of custody 223–5 276–7, 331, 334, 365,
299, 335–6 Chambliss, William 155; 376; see also criminal
Brexit 248, 250, 277 early 134; great Marxist classes; dangerous classes;
“broken windows” theory sociologist of crime 13; grammar of Marxist
56 political economy of criminology; sentencing
Brownmiller, Susan 328, 330 opium and heroin 268; classical criminology 294
Butler, Judith: “performative” protection of property Clemmer, Donald 183–4,
conception of gender and personal security 232
identity 395 273; race and the War cocaine 129, 131–4, 147,
Button, Graham 349; see also on Drugs 365, 365–6; 272, 435; crack 2, 129;
Sharrock structural contradictions epidemic 144
555
INDEX
556
INDEX
557
INDEX
the clarification of moral Ferraro, Kathleen J. 60, 141 homicide 374–5; the rule
boundaries “Fifth Freedom” 438 of practical circumstances
ethnic cleansing 457 Foucault, Michel 9, 63, 92, 206–9, 478; Studies in
ethnomethodology xi–xiii, 258, 288, 294; disciplinary Ethnomethodology 66,
18, 23, 30, 32, 121, 155, power 294, 403–9; 116, 198, 208; studies
192, 198–238, 317, 324, Discipline and Punish of the routine grounds
425; antiadministrative 56–7, 398, 403–9, 410, of everyday activities
politics of 72, 479; 449; discourse 397, 420, 427–8; the “this’s” 77, 479;
and crime 71, 202–5; 421–2; episteme 402; worldwide social science
compared to symbolic governmentality 57, movement 42; see also
interactionism 151, 158, 410–15; and the dope
173, 202; diversity of “homosexual” 395–6; Garland, David 13, 44, 58,
200–2; “interpretation” knowledges 411, 413, 397–8, 409, 410–15, 426,
unfortunate in relation 415, 430, 449; power 430–1
to 121; An Invitation to 397–431; power/ gay–straight binary see
Ethnomethodology 23; knowledge 33, 403, 405; homosexual–heterosexual
Manchester School of subjectification 409, binary
120, 341; mislabelled as 410, 415; technologies gender xiii, 19, 31, 32, 33,
“constructionist” 142; of practice 426; see also 48–9, 76, 80, 106, 108,
and power 425–6; see also King and McHoul; 242–3, 244, 256, 265, 283,
documentary method of poststructuralism 316–51, 379, 392, 416–17,
interpretation; Garfinkel Francis, David 20, 23–30, 437; categories 245, 394;
“European Miracle” see West 83n5, 145–6, 192, 199 in feminist criminology,
Europeans 275, 353, 358; Frankfurt School 255, 408 grammar of 340–7; in
conquest 436–70; project functionalism 30, 45, 86–8, plea-bargaining 345–6; as
437–8 133, 200; consensus a principle of inquiry 318;
“excited delirium syndrome” 116, 125–6, 319; in see also Butler; Maynard;
55 Foucault 408; grammar of patriarchy; sentencing;
Eysenck, Hans J. 53–4 103–8; Marxist 251, 262; Wowk
structural- 241; see also genocide 435, 443–68; in
Fanon, Frantz 439 Parsons; violence in ice the Americas 450–68,
feminism 30, 243, 256, hockey 477; in Canada 453–60;
394, 437; academic 347; functions of crime 88–101, conditional 376; cultural
empiricist 326, 328, 310–13; see also prison; 453; see also Willhelm
348; first-wave 316; punishment Giallombardo, Rose 339
fourth-wave 316; Marxist Giddens, Anthony 42, 43, 88,
320, 324; maternal 136, Gabor, Thomas 5, 75 252, 309, 425
316; postmodern 326, Galeano, Eduardo 443 Giroux, Susan Searls 376
349, 394–5; second-wave Garfinkel, Harold 11, 16, global warming see
316, 317; standpoint 326; 19–21, 22, 61, 78, 116–17, capitalism
third-wave 316; women’s 120, 122, 141, 198–200, globalization 247, 250, 281,
movement and 316–17 229, 341, 391, 427, 478–9; 475; Marx and Engels on
feminist criminology documentary method 248
325–39, 347; see also of interpretation 306; Goffman, Erving 33, 35,
gender “good” organizational 179, 183, 187, 203, 232,
feminist sociological analysis reasons for “bad” clinic 324
319–25 records” 66–9, 232; jurors’ Ghomeshi, Jian 385
feminist theory 32, 317–19 decision-making 201, 205, grammatical explication of
feminization of poverty 327 209–10, 221; race and social action 19–21
558
INDEX
grammatical respecification Hester, Stephen xi–xv, 18, Indians 376, 379–80, 454,
xii, 30, 424, 477–8 20, 23–30, 192, 198, 199, 456, 458–9, 461, 462,
Gramsci, Antonio: hegemony 201, 206, 380, 386, 445–6; 464–6; massacres of
258, 279 see also Montreal Massacre American 450, 452;
green criminology 32, 250, heterosexual(ity): men 421; see also aboriginal peoples;
474 relationships 184; see also Sand Creek massacre
Green, Melvin: discourse inequality 44; economic 250,
criminalization of drugs Hispanics 144, 186, 280, 358, 260, 278, 373, 474;
changing public morality 363, 365 in sentencing 283–5
135 historical relativism 464 international law 435, 446,
Gusfield, Joseph 7, 62, 95, Homans, George 12, 104, 464; UN International
101, 128, 140, 336 141 Law Commission 474
Homolka, Karla 11, 327 inter(-)sectionality 31, 256
Hacking, Ian: Kant the great homosexual–heterosexual intertextuality 401, 424
pioneer of construction binary 396; see also Iran-Contra congressional
120; making up people discourse hearings 225–8
412 homosexual(ity) 105, 128, Iraq 306, 436, 474
Hagan, John: corporate 332–4, 340, 379, 395, 430 Islamic State 406
advantage 283; focus human/nonhuman status Islamophobia 354
of narcotics legislation 245, 256, 465 Israel and the Palestinians 8,
on disreputable poor Hunt, Jennifer: police use 267, 441, 463, 475–6;
276; labelling theory of “normal force” 161–6, see also Palestine
as conflict theory 156; 193, 194, 212, 364
narcotic addicts 130; Hussein, Saddam 55, 306 Jacobs, James B. 186, 232
offender-related factors Husserl, Edmund 120, 399 Jayyusi, Lena 192, 441
in sentencing 282; rate at Hutchinson et al.: Derrida Jefferson, Gail 202, 217
which police lay criminal 400–1, 428; difference Jenkins, Philip 127, 129;
charges 214 between interpreting “contextual” versus
Hale, Sylvia 325 and grasping a rule 121; “strict” constructionism
Halkowski, Timothy see role harmless policy studies 64; 143
as an interactional device no such thing as a social Jews 105, 130, 359, 461
Hall, Stuart 421 science 74; postmodernists Jones, El 358
Halper, Jeff 439, 476 as disappointed realists 428 jury deliberations 205,
Harper, Elijah 386 478; see also Garfinkel;
Harper, J. J. 360 identity politics 243–4, 256, Pomerantz and Sanders
Harper, Canadian Prime 256, 379, 395 juvenile delinquency 43,
Minister Stephen xi, 1, 2, Idle No More 261, 457 128; lower-class 56; see also
362, 459 Ignatieff, Michael 287, 290, crime
Harper, Rinelle 377, 385–6 294–6
Hedges, Chris 376–7, 474 imperialism 292, 435–7, Kant, Immanuel 120, 465
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm 438–41, 468; see also Kappeler,Victor E. and
Friedrich 399 Schegloff Gary Potter 12; crime
Henry, Frances 422; imprisonment 282, 284; mythology 144
and Carol Tator 398; comparing women’s and Katz, Jack 273
racialization of crime in men’s 339–40; impact King, D. A. and Alec W.
Toronto’s print media of 186–8; punishing McHoul: schooling as
421–4 the dangerous classes technique of power 411;
Henry, Stuart 53 287–301; see also Christie; discursive production of
Hepburn, John R. 311–12 symbolic interactionism the Queensland Aborigine
559
INDEX
as subject 433, 443–50; Leonard, Eileen B. 274, 367 Marxist sociology 13, 35,
see also postcolonialism Lévi-Strauss, Claude see 242–3, 250–1, 255, 257,
King, Mackenzie: Deputy structural anthropology 261–2, 282; structures of
Minister of Labour 267, Lewis, Stephen 356 dominance 256, 312, 329
271; moral entrepreneur Lombroso, Cesare 53–4 Marxist theory of the state:
about drugs 131–2, 266 Los Angeles riots see Davis instrumentalist versus
King, Rodney 356, 363–4 Los, Maria 332–3 structuralist views 257–9,
Kitsuse, John I.: official Loseke, Donileen 127; 263–5, 266, 269, 282–3,
statistics (with Cicourel) “experts” on battered 289–90, 294–5, 299–300,
154; see also Spector, women (with Cahill) 141 310
Malcolm and John I. Louch, A. R.: misconstruing Matoesian, Gregory M.:
Kitsuse of moral reasoning as on “detailing-to-death” in
Klein, John F. 179 causal hypothesis 110; a rape trial 346–7
Klein, Naomi 261, 474, social integration 109 Matza, David 51, 62, 115,
475–6 Lynch, Michael E. 11, 13, 116; ban and transparency,
knowledge: common- 15, 19, 20, 21, 72, 73, apprehension and labelling
sense and scientific 118, 120, 141–2, 146, 169–72; incarceration and
10–15; of the layperson 147, 148, 191, 199, post-prison stigmatization
and of the professional 200, 202, 204, 205, 186–8
12–15; protected against 421, 479; determining Maybee, Janet 95–6
induction 349–51; see also crime through DNA Maynard, Douglas W. 204,
commonsense knowledge fingerprinting 221–5 302; use of defendants’
of social structures; attributes in plea-
members’ knowledge of Macdonald, Prime Minister bargaining 305–7; use of
crime John A.: ethnic cleansing gender in plea-bargaining
Komagata Maru 130 455, 456; national policy 345–6, 348; use of race in
Komter, Martha L. 204 270 plea-bargaining 382–4
McNamara, Robert S.80 Mead, George Herbert 115,
labelling theory 166–70; “malignant narcissism” 55 120, 156
grammar of 189–94 Manning, Peter K.: on Egon Meat is Murder 1, 3, 47, 124,
language: game 19, 21, 192, Bittner 215 148, 398, 400
426–8; goes on holiday 19, Marihuana Tax Act 128 media 44, 64, 76, 104, 127,
30, 58, 143; mastery of marijuana 1, 3, 4, 65, 109–10, 167, 205, 255, 259, 265,
natural 20, 469; ordinary 129–134, 136, 147, 167–8, 367, 371, 377; elite 253;
30, 78, 191, 194, 302, 425; 172, 192, 279, 334 mass 139–40, 253, 270;
philosophy 19, 116, 120; Marshall, Donald 207 news 23, 33, 50, 59, 123,
region of 9 Marx, Karl 35, 241, 242–3, 144, 326; social 50, 317,
Latinos 365, 370–1 245, 254, 264, 309, 377, 359; studies 117, 309;
Lazarsfeld, Paul 12, 48 405, 408, 438–9; on the see also dope; Henry
Lee, John R. E. 341 criminal 100–1; theory of and Tator; membership
left idealism 155, 263, 265 society 251–4 categorization analysis;
left realism 155, 263, 265, Marxism 30, 243, 250–2, Montreal Massacre
310 263, 317, 425, 437; Meehan, Albert J. 69–71,
Lemert, Edwin M.: neo- or Western 254–9; 145, 206, 382
on de-criminalizing structural 258, 259, 422; Melossi, Dario and Massimo
marijuana 167–8; labelling see also capitalism Pavarini: development of
theory 168; primary and Marxist criminology 80, the prison 287, 289, 293
secondary deviation 250–1, 262–301, 311, 326; members’ knowledge of
169 grammar of 301–10 crime 9, 10–15
560
INDEX
561
INDEX
problem 80, 277, 285, prostitution 1, 6, 101, 128, crisis centres 4; marital
299, 312; surplus 129, 278, 136–8, 326–7, 331–2, 336, 125; unfounding of 59;
280–1, 299, 368, 376–7 341, 380 see also Matoesian; sexual
positivistic (inquiry, Protestant Ethic 90, 438 assault
methodology, social psychiatry 174, 312, 407; rational choice theory 56,
science) 19, 48, 51, 61, anti- 241; clinic 66–8; 413
116, 121, 131, 153–5, illness 68; reports 178 Razack, Sherene H. 439
155–6, 232, 288, 349, 392; punishment: functional value realism: commonsense 154;
see also sociology of 93–4, 96; capital 3, 125 naïve 147, 191; see also
postcolonialism xiii, 30, 32, Hutchinson et al.; left
243, 368, 377, 394, 396, queer 379; studies 349; realism
433, 437–41, 468–70; theory 243, 394–6, 437 reality: disjunctures 191;
accounts 375–7; analysis Quinney, Richard 134, 155; members’ reality analysis
442, 455; grammar of paradigm case of Marxist 192–4; social construction
discourse in poststructural instrumentalism 263; of 122, 147, 192; see also
450, 468–70 special conception of Pollner
postmodern criminology 403 society 308 Reiman, Jeffrey 248–9, 249,
postmodernism xiii, 30, 32, 273; and Paul Leighton
319, 398, 402, 424–9, 469; race 353–86; critical race 244, 377
see also power theory 368, 385, 421; Reinarman, Craig: moral
postmodernity 402 emancipation 384–5; panic over crack cocaine
poststructural criminology grammar of 377–84; (with Levine) 129, 134,
403 membership categories 272; see also Mothers
poststructuralism xiii, 30, 32, 379–81; problem 271; Against Drunk Driving
63, 141, 258, 259, 265, profiling 356, 382; Reiner, Robert: on Egon
319, 392, 397, 398–403, relevance of place 381–2; Bittner 214–15
424–9, 439, 463, 469; science 54; studies 30, 32, reserve 444, 445, 447–9, 455,
see also postcolonialism; 242; see also Chamblis; 456–8, 460, 466, 468
power class; Cox; death penalty; reserve army of unemployed
Potter, Garry 474 Garfinkel; Maynard; labour 369
Poulantzas, Nicos 258 Murphy; sentencing residential schools 354,
Poussaint, Alvin Dr. 380–1, racialization 385; of crime 454–5, 456, 457, 459
388n5 355, 398; see also Henry rights: civil and political 357;
power 397–431; grammar of and Tator human 41, 277, 283, 306,
power in poststructuralism racism 85, 129, 256, 353, 381, 435–7, 446, 457, 474;
and postmodernism 359, 367, 369, 373, property 277; revolutions
424–9; see also Foucault 375, 378, 381, 450, 90; to self-government
practical reasoning 18, 24, 460–5, 468; systemic 361; see also sociology;
29, 31, 32, 77–8, 198–238, 354, 374; white 385; see Universal Declaration of
391; see also members’ also aboriginal people, Human Rights
methods African-Americans, risk: management 44,
pragmatism 116, 120 African-Canadians; 412–13; perceived 213;
prison: crisis in the UK Commission on Systemic society 57
297–301; functions of Racism in the Ontario Rock, Paul 56
296–7; subculture 232; Criminal Justice System role: as an interactional
see also Melossi and Radzinowicz, Leon 52, 276, device 225–8; role-taking
Pavarini; population; 378 157, 160, 194; as a set of
Rusche and Kirchheimer; rape 128, 138, 165, 223, 274, expectations about how
symbolic interactionism 326–7, 329, 419, 441, 444; to act 87, 102, 154
562
INDEX
Roshier, Bob 94, 96–7 118–20, 120, 122, 206, situations of choice
routine activities theory 56, 229, 384 (with Watson) 210;
413 science and technology de-criminalizing drugs
Ruiz, Elena 399 studies 63, 120, 201 136; deviant activities
rule 19, 25, 28–9, 94, 108, security state 260, 280 75; Durkheim and the
118–19, 121–6, 128, Searle, John 145–6 necessity of crime 93, 96,
202, 209–10, 233, 479; self-report and victimization 125; functional analysis
-breaking behaviour 154, surveys 62, 74 108; Garfinkel on legal
189–90; of the game semiology 41, 422 concept of guilt 210–11;
101–3; -governed versus sentencing 178–81, 348; and Manchester School of
-using 200–1; -makers class 282–7; and gender Ethnomethodology
296; of law 207, 311, 335–6; and race 366, 374 120, 341; members’
373, 381, 470; of the sequential analysis (SA) see ethnographic work
fathers 317, 328; see also conversation analysis (with Turner) 17; power
Garfinkel; Hutchinson sex 137, 241, 245, 282, 303, (with Button) 425–7;
et al. 305, 326, 332, 340, 357, social construction’s
Rusche, Georg and Otto 381, 394; interracial 131; debunking role (with
Kirchheimer: punishment life 336; -role behaviour Coleman) 144; social
and social structure 335; see also Wowk problems versus
287–95 sexism 105, 137, 256, 317, sociological problems 44;
Russia 254, 436, 475, 476 325 sociology of education,
Ryle, Gilbert 10, 120 sexual: abuse 138, 455, 456; adapted from (with
active women 442; assault Button) 348; sociology’s
Sacks, Harvey 11, 12, 78, 1, 3, 4, 49, 138, 237, 317, misbegotten dualisms
106–7, 141, 174, 304, 384, 330–5, 336, 347, 351–2, (with Watson) 146;
478; order at all points 359; categories 437; summarizing Lemert 168;
199; see also knowledge deviants 164; harassment what being in control
protected against 138, 317; identity 317, means 283; Wittgenstein
induction; membership 396; mores 311; offences (with Anderson) 478;
categorization analysis 90, 273, 331; offenders’ see also dope
(MCA); sequential analysis accounts 173; orientation Shawn, Wallace xiv, 433, 450,
(SA) 31, 33, 242, 255, 355, 379; 470
Said, Edward W. 439–41 partner 10; politics 341, Sim, Joe 267, 297–300
Sales, William Jr. 369 344–5; promiscuity 76, “Sixties Scoop” 457
Sand Creek massacre 453, 129; psychopathy 128; slavery 125, 302, 328, 376,
461 stereotypes 136; violence 442, 448; African 292,
Sanders, Bernie 248, 250, 261 385 460, 467; black 358,
Sangster, Joan: moral sexuality 328–30, 331, 442; 359, 368; galley 292;
regulation of girls’/ History of 403; see also indigenous 451–2, 465,
women’s sexuality 398, moral regulation of 467; mode of production
415–21, 477 women’s sexuality 373; rebellion 369; wage
Saussure, Ferdinand de 259, Shapiro, Michael 284 255, 275, 302; white 137;
398–400 Sharrock, W. W.: common- see also policing the slave
Scalping Proclamation 454 sense and scientific economy
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 202; attitudes (with Anderson) Small, Shirley J.: conflict
theoretical imperialism 14–15; common-sense theory 156; development
308 understandings (with of Canadian narcotics
school-to-prison pipeline 96 Button) 15; decision- legislation 129–34, 135,
Schutz, Alfred 13–14, making in commonsense 266, 271
563
INDEX
Smart, Carol 156, 326, 328, social problems 126–7, Hunt; labelling theory;
335, 348–9 133, 134, 148; critique of plea-bargaining
Smelser, Neil J. 319, 320 Becker 155; value-conflict
Smith, Dorothy E. 20, theory 156 tax havens 250, 287, 475
313, 325, 329, 426, 441; Spitzer, Stephen 311, 312; Taylor, Sandie 53–5
critique of post-als 429, “social dynamite” and techniques of neutralization
469; feminist standpoint “social junk” 277–8 161, 172
theory 324, 325, 429; Spivak, Gayatri 441 television licence evasion see
women, the family and Stamp, Josiah 46, 58, 71 Pantazis
corporate capitalism Stannard, David 450 terrorism 1, 3, 8–9, 273,
319–25 state 46–81; and 354, 406, 446, 462–3;
Snider, D. Laureen 286, crime statistics and anti-terrorism act 8, 273;
310–11, 312, 415; and correctionalism 79–81; international 435; state 6,
West 286; women and meaning and use of 435; threat of 278–81; War
rape 312, 330–5, 349 official crime statistics on Terror 125, 149, 474
social constructionism 30, 33, 58–74; see also texts 393, 400–2, 422, 427;
32, 122–3, 126, 128, 134, administration see also intertextuality
199, 241; grammar of Stawarska, Beata 259, 399 the “this’s” 77, 479
141–7; see also Spector and Stote, Karen 455 Thomas, William I. and
Kitsuse structural: anthropology 259, Dorothy S. 151, 195, 462
social theory 141, 254, 393, 400; determinism 57, 116; Tierney, Kathleen J. see
433; classical 437; see also linguistics 259, 400, 422; battered women
feminist theory theorizing 200; see also Tilley, Nick 53, 56
social work 79, 80, 108, 127, Marxism Tonry, Michael 87: why
139–41, 297, 397, 407, structuralism 259, 398–400 crime rates are falling
411, 414, 417, 419 “subaltern studies” 441 throughout the Western
socialization 16, 184; Sudnow, David 175, 181–2, world 86, 90–1
inadequate 423 204, 306 torture 2, 125, 162, 362,
society 84–110; individual suicide 12, 42, 44, 57, 69, 78, 406, 434; Chicago Police
and 85; modern 405–7; 80, 88–9, 154, 229, 466 362–3
see also postmodernity surveillance 56, 169, 188, transportation 292
sociology 1–35; Canadian 281, 337–9, 371, 382, Travers, Max 203, 346, 347
89; committing xi, 477; 406–9, 444–9, 466, 475; Trump, Donald 237, 248,
emancipatory 242–4, state 8, 260 250, 261, 271, 282
349, 385; “folk” 233; Sutherland, Edwin H. 52, Truth and Reconciliation
functionalist 32, 320; 55–6, 75, 161, 171–2, 434 Commission of Canada
historical 97, 406; human Sykes, Gresham M. 184–5, (TRCC) 65, 354, 453, 455,
rights 42; interpretative 232 456
115–23; lay 14, 21, 36, symbolic interactionism: typification 173, 176, 306,
118, 200, 221; malestream accounts in social action 377, 384
318; positivistic 41–5; (justifications and excuses)
quantitative 12; the two 171–7; content and role unintended consequences
sociologies 15–19; see also of prisoner subcultures 91, 104, 135, 271, 409,
Marxist sociology 183–6; and the courts 438
sociology’s abiding trilogy 170–82; and the police United Nations Charter 435,
241 158–66; and the prison 446
Socrates 87, 99 182–8; and the self 156–8; Universal Declaration of
Spector, Malcolm and John varieties of 153–6; see Human Rights 381, 437,
I. Kitsuse: constructing also Blumer; Emerson; 446
564
INDEX
vagrancy 264, 273, 295, 327, 117–18, 122, 134, 152, women: aboriginal 60–1,
331 154, 242, 256, 349, 408–9, 455; criminalization of
Van Maanen, John 96, 163 426, 430, 438; action 327; emancipation 347;
variable analysis 121, 154, theory 152 experience 105, 318, 394;
155, 156; critique of 349 West(ern) 84; civilization 89; movement 136, 139, 242,
violence against women 9, cultural assumptions 441; 279, 332, 394, 395, 434;
12, 105–8, 126, 128, 326, East/West opposition 440; see also aboriginal people;
434, 466; constructing Europe 467; hemisphere battered women; Carlen;
the problem of 136–41; 468; history 411, 449; and feminism; rape; Sangster;
see also battered women Islam 267; Rise of the 91, Snider; violence against
violence in ice hockey see 437–9, 467; thought 402; women
Colburn triumph of the 438, 450; Woolgar, Steve and Dorothy
world 90–1, 275, 317, 330, Pawluch: ontological
Wacquant, Loic 367 355; see also Europeans; gerrymandering 144–5,
Walker, James W. St. G. 358, imperialism 385,
359 Wieder, D. Lawrence 199, Worrall, Anne 316, 327, 349,
Wallerstein, James S. and 201; telling the convict 350
Clement J. Wyle 5, 75 code 183, 184, 185, 232–6 Wowk, Maria T. 206, 215;
War on Drugs 3, 92, 129, Wilkins, Leslie T. 166 sex and gender in a
149, 279–80, 365; see also Willhelm, Sidney M.: murder interrogation
Chambliss prelude to genocide? 341–5
War on Terror see terrorism 375–7 Wright, Ronald 474, 477
Ward, Samuel Ringgold 358 Williams, Raymond 85, 303
Watson, D. R. (Rod) 24, 26, Wilson, James Q. 273 Young, Jock 44, 52, 155–6,
146, 210, 304, 341, 368–9, Winch, Peter 9, 74, 117–20, 265
374, 379, 388n5; eliciting 120
confessions in murder Wittgenstein, Ludwig 10, 15, Zatz, Marjorie 13, 264
interrogations 206, 19–21, 72, 118, 120, 141, Zimmerman, Don H. 117,
215–21, 229 146, 192, 201, 303, 428, 202, 204
Weber, Max 16, 41, 90, 115, 447, 478 Zinn, Howard 249, 403
565