Historical Studies Today
Historical Studies Today
Historical Studies Today
STUDIES TODAY
Edited by
Felix Gilbert and
Stephen R. Graubard
Book Reviews
As befits their concern with change over time, historians hugely enjoy
analyzing the state and progress of their own profession. At least, that is
the impression conveyed by the steady stream of books on the subject.
Sometimes, as in Fritz Stern's Varieties of History (Cleveland, 1956), the
purpose is merely to show the novice how kaleidoscopic the melange
called "history" can be. At other times-when, for example, the
nonhistorian Ved Mehta produced his Fly and the Fly-Bottle (Boston,
1963)-the main aim seems to be the entertainment of the world at large.
More recently, however, particularly in the Times Literary Supplement's
"New Ways in History" issue (1966), John Higham, Leonard Krieger,
and Felix Gilbert's History (Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1965), Charles Tilly
and David Landes's History as Social Science (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,
1971), and Lee Benson's Toward the Scientific Study of History
(Philadelphia, 1972), the sights have been set somewhat higher. These
are either solidly researched analyses of recent and current work or
programs for the future. The difference between the two types is not
sharp, because the surveys indicating where scholarship has just been
usually imply (and often assert) where it ought to be going. Historical
Studies Today is no exception. The title is something of a misnomer,
unless "today" is given the broadest possible interpretation, because
most of the authors spend large sections of their essays on the
accomplishments of the last fifty or 100 years. The word "epigone" is
quite a favorite, as are such stalwarts as Michelet, Ranke, and Meinecke,
all of whom get as many or more mentions than Fernand Braudel. If, as
the jacket informs us, this is "an inside view of a discipline in ferment,"
it has certainly been brewing a long time. Yet that is the historian's
natural procedure for establishing current trends and future possibilities-
he probes as far back as possible so as to uncover origins. If, therefore,
the book gives a great deal of attention to historians both dead and yet
unborn while ostensibly exploring the present, it thereby epitomizes the
literature it represents. Equally typical is the absence of a clear and
distinct message, notwithstanding the avowed wish "to fill the gap which
exists between what people believe the historian is doing and what he is
really doing" (p. xxi). Over a dozen of the essays deal with branches of
the discipline defined either by subject matter (urban, local, social,
economic, intellectual, educational, scientific, political, and military
history) or by method (quantification, prosopography, archaeology, and
psychology). Two more are substantive articles, telling us little about the
state of the profession, though they do give us excellent examples of,
first, quantitative research (one essay on the French army in the
nineteenth century) and, second, of a new genre which,
drawing on the title of its chief journal, one can call Livre et societe
(an essay analyzing French reading habits on the eve of the Revolution).
These seem somewhat out of place, as do Arthur Schlesinger's spirited
but slightly strained defense of the historian as participant in great
events, and Jan Vansina's weighty but technical evaluation of African
oral history. Leaving aside these four contributions, which relate only
tangentially to the evaluation of contemporary scholarship that is the
book's main purpose, we are still confronted by an uncertain set of
recommendations. One message that comes through consistently is the
need to establish better relations with other disciplines. This is a banner
which everyone can wave, and yet the seriousness of the commitment is
open to question. If there is any sister department whose qualities
perfectly complement those of history, it is anthropology. Nevertheless,
only the two non-Western historians (Jan Vansina and Benjamin
Schwartz) refer to the subject at any length, and most of their remarks
are concerned with Claude L6vi-Strauss. Such influential figures as E. E.
Evans-Pritchard, Mary Douglas, and Clifford Geertz go completely
unmentioned. Modern psychology and psychoanalysis fare better,
because they are the subject of one article, but they receive significant
notice in only one other. And it is apparent that almost all the
contributors (some of whom treat "data" as a singular) are innocent of a
solid comprehension of statistics and the workings of the computer. One
writer goes so far as to suggest that quantification could be allowed in
small doses, because "a simple computer would do no harm" (p. 292).
Anybody possessed of minimal familiarity with these machines could
derive considerable amusement from the attempt to define "simple" in
that context: Not very clever? Easy to work? Ten fingers? The
misconception is fundamental. Nor will the article specifically devoted
to quantification advance the cause significantly. Its call for archives of
machine-readable material is admirable enough, though this is now a
well-worn plea. Historians have been making such appeals in the United
States for more than a decade, and despite their one spectacular success,
the archive of electoral and census statistics at the Inter-University
Consortium for Political Research in Ann Arbor, their more utopian
expectations (which are the ones repeated here) are now receding.
Instead, they are coming to appreciate that, in an age 'of dwindling'
research funds, resources will have to be accumulated very slowly, by
individual effort, and that it will be decades, rather than years, before
vast data banks, covering centuries and continents, open their doors. A
similar chimera is the forecast of a computer responsive to verbal
commands. As long as historians think of quantification in terms of
machines making old tasks easy, and ignore the powerful and
unprecedented advances in analysis that modern statistics makes
possible, they will not progress into the era of interdisciplinary research
that this volume envisions.
Significantly, the most elegant, informed, and stimulating article
about statistics (in fact, about the entire range of relations between
history and the social sciences) is by John Habakkuk, entitled
"Economic History and Economic Theory." Economists and economic
historians have had the longest experience of interdepartmental
exchanges, and it is thus not inappropriate that one of their number
should produce the subtlest and most
"This claim diminishes the value of all other branches of history and
necessarily evokes the opposition of their practitioners" (p. 155). Great
though the achievements of the Annales school have been, its pioneering
stage seems to be over, and until its apostles stop propounding absurdly
grandiose claims about the future of historical research, they will
continue to encounter reproofs such as Gilbert's, whose very moderation
commands agreement. On the evidence of Historical Studies Today, the
Vie Section does not have the best of the argument, and one only wishes
that the polemic could have been avoided. Nobody can deny the
enormous value of the French contribution to our discipline; but the
programmatic statements invite immediate, and in this case decisive,
rebuttal. Moreover, it is not the dispute over the merit of different kinds
of history that,is the book's chief contribution: it is the multiplicity itself
that the editors obviously wish to convey. To this end, they evidently
encouraged the preparation of introductory bibliographies in various
areas, and in this connection the articles by Manuel, Finley, Pierre
Goubert (on French local history), Thernstrom, Le Goff, and Vansina are
particularly useful. Two other articles, by Lawrence Stone on
prosopography (collective biography) and by John Talbott on the history
of education, are primarily reviews of the literature, and they should
become standard references. Both authors assess the development,
shortcomings, and accomplishments of the fields they survey, and
conclude on a mildly hopeful note. Stone even regards prosopography as
a potential catalyst "in the re-creation of a unified field out of the loose
confederation of jealously independent topics and techniques which at
present constitutes the historian's empire" (p. 134). Omitting the first
nine words, that last quotation could very well stand as the best
description of Historical Studies Today. Far from suggesting, in the
words of the preface, that the discipline may be in "crisis" (p. vii), the
book gives an impression of great liveliness and openness to new ideas.
All of the contributors peer eagerly into the mists of the future, certain
that fascinating revelations lie immediately ahead. If they seem
equivocal about one of the chief paths to the future, interdisciplinary
research, and occasionally too confident about their own constructions
(notably serial history), they do not appear to doubt that the discipline
will be very different a few years hence. Even the one small note of
pessimism-Gilbert's concern about declining enrollments in history
courses-has been dispelled since the book was published, because the
latest figures from the American Historical Association indicate
enrollments rising once more.
To say that this book gives a good idea of current research in history
is not, however, to admit that its predictions are likely to be any better
than those of all the other "state of the art" books that the profession
keeps producing. Lest one be carried away by the prospect of a
discipline bursting at the seams with new paths, directions, or ways, it is
worth recalling another look into the future, which promised that history
is escaping from the limitations formerly imposed upon the study of the
past. It will come in time consciously to meet our daily needs; it will avail
itself of all those discoveries that are being made ... by anthropologists,
economists, psychologists and sociologists.... There is no branch of ...
science which has not undergone the most remarkable changes during the
last half century, and many new branches of social science … have been
added to the long list. It is inevitable that history should be involved in this
revolutionary process, but since it must be confessed that this necessity
has escaped many contemporaneous writers, it is no wonder that the
intelligent public continues to accept somewhat archaic ideas of the scope
and character of history.
The words are James Harvey Robinson's, and they were first
published in March 1912.
THEODORE K. RABB
Princeton University
Preface to the Issue "Historical Studies Today"
duction and distribution in the eighteenth century: one was legal, the
other was clandestine. Both, he argues, are crucial to our un derstanding
of the culture and the politics of the Old Regime. Darnton's essay, by
dwelling on both these universes, suggests a wholly new interpretation
not only of the Enlightenment, but also of the last years of the Ancien R?
gime. We have entered a new area not only in studying what individ uals
and groups thought but also in examining why they thought what they
thought. Frank Manuel, in his interpretation of "The Use and Abuse of
Psychology in History," accepts that there are historical precedents for a
serious historical interest in psychology that go back at least to the time
of Vico. However, it was not until the last decades of the nineteenth
century that a major breakthrough occurred. It was only with the
emergence of Freud that the ground was laid for a more fundamental
innovation in the use of psycho logical concepts in history. Though the
Freudian method of anal ysis was historical, no historian at the time
suspected its large po tential importance for historical scholarship. The
most subtle use of Freud, perhaps, Manuel says, has been made by Erik
Erikson. How ever, he questions whether Erikson's "ideal psychological
model of human development in eight stages" is in fact universally
applica ble. Has Erikson not drawn entirely on twentieth-century psycho
analytic experience? What relevance has such experience to other
cultures and periods? Moving from his study of Erikson's work, Manuel
considers the efforts by Sartre to develop portraits based on a
psychologized Marxist framework. He finds in Sartre's Flaubert "a
brilliant synthesis of Marxist and Freudian insights." Manuel ac cepts
that psychological history remains a dubious form of inquiry to many
who call themselves professional historians. This, however, cannot
obscure the great distance that has been traversed since the early part of
the century. Manuel is disposed to cast in his lot with the Freudian
"psychologizers." He says: "The new psychologies can open up whole
new areas of inquiry by encouraging the historian to ask some direct,
perhaps impertinent questions. The restriction of the method to
biography, where it has enjoyed at least partial acceptance, should not be
a lasting confinement. Historians will have to wrestle anew with
symbolic representation on a broad scale." M. I. Finley illustrates why it
is sometimes difficult to bring to bear on the study of history the
technical innovations and discov eries of other fields of scholarship.
Finley's report on the relation
This issue of D dalus could not have been undertaken without the
assistance of Professor Felix Gilbert, who has served as Guest Editor. A
great debt is owed to him, and also to Professor Lawrence Stone, who
assisted us in formulating many of the questions. An early meeting of a
small planning group took place at the Institute for Advanced Study at
Princeton; we are indebted to the Institute and to its Director, Dr. Carl
Kaysen, for providing a congenial set ting for profitable and stimulating
discussion. Finally, a particular debt is owed the Ford Foundation. A
grant from the Foundation
S.R.G.
Is Politics Still the Backbone
of History?
JACQUES LE GOFF
DIEDALUS
stitutes the economic structure of society, the concrete base on which
there rises a legal and political superstructure, and to which cer¬tain
forms of social consciousness correspond. The mode of pro¬duction
relating to material life determines the pattern of social, political and
intellectual life in general."' Without necessarily see¬ing in Marx's
attitude to politics, theoretical and practical (le politique and la
politique), the fundamental pessimism ascribed to it by some—usually
hostile—commentators," one may still con¬clude that a conception like
the "withering away of the state" is not likely to enhance the prestige of
anything to do with politics, political history included.
This might be thought a one-sided view, to be found only in a
historian misled by a specifically French tradition and an exag¬gerated
idea of the influence of Marxism. Not at all. Frenchmen have been
among political history's stoutest supporters." And Jo¬han Huizinga,
neither a Frenchman nor by any means a Marxist, in the course of his
work gradually moved away from political his¬tory. In The Task of
Cultural History' he accords it no more than a declining ascendancy,
based chiefly on the fact that it is both easy and clear. Since Huizinga
was not personally attracted by economic and social history, though he
noted their "irresistible rise,"" he soon turned his main efforts to the
establishing of a scientific cultural his¬tory.
Economics, society, and culture seem to have monopolized his-
torians' attention for the last half-century. Political history, the in¬sulted
and injured, even seems to have been drawn into the episte-mological
uncertainties arising from the attempt by certain schools of sociology to
blur the distinction between practical and theoretical politics. To
mention only two leading figures in present- day French sociology,
Alain Touraine has recently emphasized the "two-fold weakness" of
political analysis in the social sciences," and Edgar Morin points out the
"crisis" in politics owing to the in¬vasion of its field from all sides by
the techniques and sciences.'" Will the atomization of politics itself
entail a corresponding disintegra¬tion of political history, already driven
back on uncomfortable posi¬tions within its own discipline? To
understand the setbacks suffered by political history in the twentieth
century, we must analyze the factors that made it flourish before.
Its former ascendancy was doubtless linked to the predominat¬ing
form taken on, between the fourteenth and twentieth cen¬turies, first by
the society of the Ancien Regime and then by the
both were primarily concerned with showing the rise of the bour-
geoisie, they remained bogged down in political history. But the
"conquering middle classes" not only annexed political history in all its
glory—they also took as much delight as their predecessors in a
historical model which was monarchical and aristocratic: a typical
example of the cultural time-lag which makes a parvenu class affect
traditional tastes. Michelet is a solitary peak.
To take the case of France alone, not until the beginning of the
twentieth century did political history first withdraw and then succumb
before the blows of a new kind of history backed up by the new social
sciences—geography, and especially economics and sociology. Vidal de
la Blache, Francois Simiaud, and Emile Durk-heim were, whether they
realized it or not, the godparents of this new history. Its parents were
Henri Berr with the Revue de synthêse historique ( 1901 ), and even
more decisively Marc Bloch and Lucien Febvre with the Annales
d'histoire economique et so¬ciale.
Raymond Aron has shown in his essay on Thucydides how closely
political history is linked to narrative and event.14 The An-nales school
loathed the trio formed by political history, narrative history, and
chronicle or episodic (evenementielle) history. All this, for them, was
mere pseudohistory, history on the cheap, a superficial affair which
preferred the shadow to the substance. What had to be put in its place
was history in depth—an economic, social, and mental history. In the
greatest book produced by the Annales school, Fernand Braudel's La
Mediterrange et le monde mediterraneen a rópoque de Philippe 11
( 1959 ), political history is relegated to part III, which far from being
the culmination of the work is more like the bits and pieces left over.
Once the back¬bone of history, political history has sunk to being no
more than an atrophied appendix: the parson's nose of history.
But political history was gradually to return in force by borrow¬ing
the methods, spirit, and theoretical approach of the very social sciences
which had pushed it into the background. I shall try to sketch this recent
comeback by taking medieval history as an ex-ample.15 Sociology and
anthropology's first and chief contribution to political history was to
establish as its central concept and aim the notion of "power" and the
facts relating to power. As Raymond Aron has observed, this notion and
these facts apply to all so¬cieties and all civilizations: "The problem of
Power is eternal, whether the earth is worked with a pick or with a
bulldozer."16
REFERENCES
1. Cited by Marc Bloch, Apologie pour l'histoire, ou metier d'historien, 4th ed.
(Paris: Colin, 1961), p. 90.
2. Ibid., p. 78.
3. Cited by P. Wolff, "L'etude des economies et des societes avant l'ere statistique,"
in C. Samaran, ed., L'histoire et ses ingthodes, Encyclopedie de la Pleiade, 11 (Paris:
Gallimard, 1961), p. 847.
4. For example, on page 4 of the introduction to the interesting volume on Le
Modalisme, a special number of Recherches internationales a la lumiêre du marxisme,
no. 37 ( June 1963), the editors write "We have primarily included studies dealing with
economic and social relations, with a few excursions into the field of institutional or
cultural superstructures."
5. For example, the particularly hostile account given by J. Freund in L'es¬'
sence du politique (Paris: Editions Sirey, 1965), pp. 645ff. According to Freund,
political alienation for Marx is alienation supreme, absolute, and irretrievable.
6. Charles Seignobos wrote in 1924, in the preface to his Histoire politique
DiEDALTIS
symbolism of the crown in the Middle Ages, see pp. 336-383, "The Crown
as Fiction," in E. H. Kantorowicz, The King's Two Bodies: A Study in
Medieval Political Theology (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957).
23. "It is not by chance that the relic St. Louis brought to Paris and installed in the
chapel of his palace is a crown of thorns, doubly symbolic of king¬ship and of
sacrifice." Le Monde, April 29, 1970, p. 13.
24. Schramm, "Die Staatsymbolik des Mittelalters," pp. 200-201.
25. Robert Folz, L'idee d'empire en occident du Ve au XIVe siecles (Paris:
Aubier, 1953), p. 6.
26. On kingship in the early Middle Ages see especially J. M. Wallace-Hadrill,
The Long-Haired Kings (London: Methuen, 1962), and F. Graus, Volk, Herrscher and
Heiliger in Reich der Merowinger (Prague, 1965). For the Carolingian period, see the
recent study by W. Ullmann, The Carolingian Renaissance and the Idea of Kingship
(London: Methuen, 1969), which brings out especially well (p. 17) how then, "in
conformity to and in accordance with the basic premisses of the ecclesiological theme
and the wholeness of view, there was no conceptual distinction between a Caro-lingian
State and a Carolingian Church." Georges Duby stressed the im-portance of the royal
model within the feudal system at the international symposium, Problemes de
stratification sociale, 1986, published by R. Mousnier, Publications of the Faculte des
Lettres et Sciences Humaines de Paris, Sorbonne, 'Recherches," XLIII (Paris, 1968).
See K. Gorski, "Le roi-saint: probleme d'ideologie feodale," Annales: economies,
soci&es, civilisations (1969), pp. 370-376.
27. Atti dell' VIII Congresso Internazionale di Storia delle religioni (Florence,
1956).
28. Studies in the History of Religions, supplements to NVMEN IV, The Sacral
Kingship: La Regalita Sacra (Leyden, 1959). Out of fifty-six con-tributions, only four
are devoted to the Middle Ages in the West: M. Maccarrone, "Il sovrano `Vicarius Dei'
nell'alto medio evo," pp. 581¬594; M. Murray, "The Divine King," pp. 595-608; L.
Rougier, "Le caractere sacre de la royaute en France," pp. 609-619; and J. A. Bizet, "La
notion du royaume interieur chez les mystiques germaniques du XIVe siecle," pp. 620-
626.
29. E. H. Kantorowicz, Kaiser Friedrich der Zweite (Berlin: Bondi, 1927), and
Erganzungsband (Berlin: Bondi, 1931).
30. E. H. Kantorowicz, Laudes Regiae: A Study in Liturgical Acclamations and
Medieval Ruler Worship (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press,
1946).
31. E. H. Kantorowicz, The King's Two Bodies: A Study in Medieval Political
Theology (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957). See also the re¬views by R.
W. Southern in the Journal of Ecclesiastical History, 10 (1957), and B. Smalley in Past
and Present, no. 20 (November 1961).
DiEDALUS
derive from Marc Bloch, La societó feodale (Paris: Michel, 1939), vol. II, bk. 2, "Le
gouvernement des hommes." The theme also occurs in J. Dhondt, " `Ordres' ou
`puissances': l'exemple des etats de Flandre," Annales: economies, societes,
civilisations (1950), pp. 289-305.
38. See H. Grundmann, "Litteratus-Illitteratus: Der Wandlung einer Bildungs-
norm vom Altertum zum Mittelalter," Archiv fur Kulturgeschichte, 40 (1958), and his
"Sacerdotium-Regnum-Studium: zur Wertung der Wissen-schaft im 13. Jahrhundert,"
Archiv fur Kulturgeschichte, 34 (1951).
39. See my Les intellectuels au Moyen Age (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1957), for
an attempt to show how, between the end of the twelfth and the four-teenth century,
members of the universities moved from a socioprofessional position which was
corporative to one which placed them among the possessors of power.
40. The subject proposed by the French delegation to the International Uni-versity
Committee on History at the Thirteenth International Conference on Historical
Sciences in Moscow, August 1970. I believe Professor Lawrence Stone has a similar
project in mind for English universities in the modern era. This revival of interest in the
prosopographical method, a method of social history likely to favor the renewal of
political history, is evident in various sectors (see the late 1970 number of Annales:
economies, societes, civilisations).
41. Among G. Dumezil's many fascinating studies on the tri-functional ideology
of the Indo-Europeans, one of the most recent is Idees romaines (Paris: Gallimard,
1969), in which he poses various questions about western Europe in the Middle Ages.
Two examples of initial research in this field are J. Batany, "Des 'Trois Fonctions' aux
'Trois Etats'?" Annales: economies, societes, civilisations (1936), pp. 933-938, and J.
Le Goff, "Note sur societe tripartie, ideologie monarchique et renouveau economique
dans la chretiente du IXe au XIIe siecle," in T. Manteuffel and A. Gieysztor, eds.,
L'Europe aux IX-XIe siecles (Warsaw, 1968), pp. 63-71.
42. One of the works inspired by this particular question is Joan Evans' inter-
esting Art in Medieval France, 987-1498: A Study in Patronage ( London: Oxford
University Press, 1948).
43. E. Panofsky, Gothic Architecture and Scholasticism ( New York: Meridian,
1957). A more traditional view is given in R. Branner, St. Louis and the Court Style in
Gothic Architecture (London: Zwemmer, 1965).
44. On the significance of Botticelli's Primavera see P. Francastel, La realite
figurative (Paris: Gonthier, 1965), p. 241, "La fete mythologique au Quattrocentro,"
and p. 272, "Un mythe politique et social du Quattrocento." See Ernst Gombrich,
Botticelli's Mythologies: A Study of the Neoplatonic Symbolism of Its Circle, in
Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Insti¬tutes (1945). P. Francastel has developed
these ideas in La figure et le lieu: l'ordre visuel du Quattrocento (Paris: Gallimard, 1967
).
45. See R. Manselli, L'eresia del male ( Naples: Morano, 1963), and "Les 18
E. J. HOBSBAWM
DADALUS
( 2 ) The history of society is, among other things, that of specific
units of people living together and definable in sociological terms. It is
the history of societies as well as of human society ( as distinct from,
say, that of apes and ants), or of certain types of society and their
possible relationships ( as in such terms as "bour¬geois" or "pastoral"
society), or of the general development of humanity considered as a
whole. The definition of a society in this sense raises difficult questions,
even if we assume that we are de¬fining an objective reality, as seems
likely, unless we reject as illegit¬imate such statements as "Japanese
society in 1930 differed from English society." For even if we eliminate
the confusions between different uses of the word "society," we face
problems ( a ) because the size, complexity, and scope of these units
varies, for example, at different historical periods or stages of
development; and ( b ) because what we call society is merely one set of
human interrela¬tions among several of varying scale and
comprehensiveness into which people are classifiable or classify
themselves, often simultane¬ously and with overlaps. In extreme cases
such as New Guinea or Amazon tribes, these various sets may define the
same group of people, though this is in fact rather improbable, But
normally this group is congruent neither with such relevant sociological
units as the community, nor with certain wider systems of relationship of
which the society forms a part, and which may be functionally essential
to it ( like the set of economic relations ) or nonessential ( like those of
culture ).
Christendom or Islam exist and are recognized as self-classifi-cations,
but though they may define a class of societies sharing certain common
characteristics, they are not societies in the sense in which we use the
word when talking about the Greeks or modern Sweden. On the other
hand, while in many ways Detroit and Cuzco are today part of a single
system of functional interrelationships ( for example, part of one
economic system ), few would regard them as part of the same society,
sociologically speaking. Neither would we regard as one the societies of
the Romans or the Han and those of the barbarians who formed, quite
evidently, part of a wider system of interrelationships with them. How
do we define these units? It is far from easy to say, though most of us
solve—or evade— the problem by choosing some outside criterion:
territorial, ethnic, political, or the like. But this is not always satisfactory.
The problem is more than methodological. One of the major themes of
the history of modern societies is the increase in their scale, internal
homo
kinship structure than social historians might have shown without this
stimulus, though a modest demonstration effect from social
anthropology ought not to be neglected. The nature and prospects of this
field have been sufficiently debated to make further dis¬cussion
unnecessary here.
Urban history also possesses a certain technologically deter¬mined
unity. The individual city is normally a geographically lim¬ited and
coherent unit, often with its specific documentation and even more often
of a size which lends itself to research on the Ph.D. scale. It also reflects
the urgency of urban problems which have increasingly become the
major, or at least the most dramatic, problems of social planning and
management in modern industrial societies. Both these influences tend to
make urban history a large container with ill-defined, heterogeneous,
and sometimes indis¬criminate contents. It includes anything about
cities. But it is clear that it raises problems peculiarly germane to social
history, at least in the sense that the city can never be an analytical
framework for economic macrohistory (because economically it must be
part of a larger system ), and politically it is only rarely found as a self-
contained city state. It is essentially a body of human beings living
together in a particular way, and the characteristic process of
urbanization in modern societies makes it, at least up to the pres¬ent, the
form in which most of them live together. The technical, social, and
political problems of the city arise essentially out of the interactions of
masses of human beings living in close proximity to one another; and
even the ideas about the city ( insofar as it is not a mere stage-set for the
display of some ruler's power and glory) are those in which men—from
the Book of Revelation on—have tried to express their aspirations about
human communities. Moreover, in recent centuries it has raised and
dramatized the problems of rapid social change more than any other
institution, That the social his¬torians who have flocked into urban
studies are aware of this need hardly be said.11 One may say that they
have been groping toward a view of urban history as a paradigm of
social change. I doubt whether it can be this, at least for the period up to
the present. I also doubt whether many really impressive global studies
of the larger cities of the industrial era have so far been produced,
con¬sidering the vast quantity of work in this field. However, urban
history must remain a central concern of historians of society, if only
because it brings out—or can bring out—those specific aspects
REFERENCES
1. See the remarks of A. J. C. Rueter in IX congrês international des sciences
historiques (Paris, 1950 ), I, 298.
2. R. H. Tawney, Studies in Economic History (London, 1927), pp. xxiii, 33-34, 39.
3.J. H. Clapham, A Concise Economic History of Britain (Cambridge, Eng.:
University Press, 1949 ), introduction.
4. Two quotations from the same document (Economic and Social Studies
Conference Board, Social Aspects of Economic Development, Istanbul, 1964) may
illustrate the divergent motivations behind this new pre-occupation. By the Turkish
president of the board: "Economic development or growth in the economically retarded
areas is one of the most important questions which confronts the world today . . . Poor
countries have made of this issue of development a high ideal. Economic development
is to them associated with political independence and a sense of sovereignty." By
Daniel Lerner: "A decade of global experience with social change and economic
development lies behind us. The decade has been fraught with efforts, in every part of
the world, to induce economic development without producing cultural chaos, to
accelerate economic growth without disrupting societal equilibrium; to promote
economic mobility without subverting political stability" ( xxiii, 1 ).
5. Sir John Hicks's complaint is characteristic: "My 'theory of history' . . . will be a
good deal nearer to the kind of thing that was attempted by Marx .. . Most of [those
who believe ideas can be used by historians to order their material, so that the general
course of history can be fitted into place] .. . would use the Marxian categories, or some
modified version of them; since there is so little in the way of an alternative version
that is available, it is not surprising that they should. It does, nevertheless, remain
extraordinary that one hundred years after Das Kapital, after a century during which
there have been enormous developments in social science, so little else should have
emerged." A Theory of Economic History (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), pp. 2-3.
8. Thus Marc Ferro's sampling of the telegrams and resolutions sent to Petro-grad in
the first weeks of the February revolution of 1917 is plainly the equivalent of a
retrospective public opinion survey. One may doubt whether it would have been
thought of without the earlier development of opinion research for nonhistorical
purposes. M. Ferro, La Revolution de 1917 ( Paris: Aubier, 1987).
7. At the conference on New Trends in History, Princeton, N. J., May 1968.
8. I do not regard such devices for inserting direction into societies as "in-
creasing complexity" as historical. They may, of course, be true.
9. P. Baran, The Political Economy of Growth ( New York: Monthly Review
Press, 1957 ), chap. 2.
10. For an English version of this important article, see Social Science Infor-
mation, 9 ( February 1970), 145-174.
11. Cf. "At stake in a broader view of urban history is the possibility of making
the societal process of urbanization central to the study of social change. Efforts should
be made to conceptualize urbanization in ways that actually represent social change."
Eric Lampard in Oscar Handlin and John Burch-ard, The Historians and the City
( Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1963 ), p. 233.
12. This work is in progress under the direction of Professor Sven-Ulric Palme at
the University of Stockholm.
13. For the possible divergences between reality and classification, see the
discussions about the complex socioracial hierarchies of colonial Latin America.
Magnus Miirner, "The History of Race Relations in Latin Amer-ica," in L. Foner and
E. D. Genovese, Slavery in the New World ( Engle-wood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall,
1969), p. 221.
14. See A. Prost, "Vocabulaire et typologie des familles politiques," Cahiers de
lexicologie, XIV ( 1969 ).
15. T. Shanin, "The Peasantry as a Political Factor," Sociological Review, 14
(1966), 17.
16. Class has long been the central preoccupation of social historians. See, for
example, A. J. C. Rueter in IX congres international des sciences historiques, I, 298-
299.
17. A. Dupront, "Problemes et methodes d'une histoire de la psychologie col-
lective," Annales: economies, societes, civilisations, 16 ( January–February 1981), 3-
11.
18. By "fitting together" I mean establishing a systematic connection between
different, and sometimes apparently unconnected, parts of the same syn-drome—for
example, the beliefs of the classic nineteenth-century liberal bourgeoisie in both
individual liberty and a patriarchal family structure.
19. We look forward to the time when the Russian Revolution will provide
historians with comparable opportunities for the twentieth century.
20. R. Braun, Industrialisierung und Volksleben ( Erlenbach-Zurich: Rentsch,
1960); Sozialer und kultureller W andel in einem liindlichen. Industriegebiet ... im 19.
und 20. Jahrhundert ( Erlenbach-Zurich: Rentsch, 1965). J. 0. Foster's thesis is being
prepared for publication.
21. Eric Stokes, who is doing this, is conscious of applying the results of work in
African history. E. Stokes, Traditional Resistance Movements and Afro- Asian
Nationalism: The Context of the 1857 Mutiny-Rebellion in India (forthcoming).
22. Centre Formation, Nation-Building and Cultural Diversity: Report on a
Symposium Organized by UNESCO ( duplicated draft, n.d. ). The sympo-sium was
held August 28–September 1, 1968.
23. Though capitalism has developed as a global system of economic interac-
tions, in fact the real units of its development have been certain territorial- political
units— British, French, German, U. S. economies—which may be due to historic
accident but also ( the question remains open) to the neces-sary role of the state in
economic development, even in the era of the purest economic liberalism.
Prosopography
LAWRENCE STONE
Origins
IN THE last forty years collective biography ( as the modern
his¬torians call it ), multiple career-line analysis ( as the social scientists
call it), or prosopography ( as the ancient historians call it) has
de¬veloped into one of the most valuable and most familiar techniques
of the research historian. Prosopographyl is the investigation of the
common background characteristics of a group of actors in history by
means of a collective study of their lives. The method employed is to
establish a universe to be studied, and then to ask a set of uni-form
questions—about birth and death, marriage and family, social origins
and inherited economic position, place of residence, educa-tion, amount
and source of personal wealth, occupation, religion, experience of office,
and so on. The various types of information about the individuals in the
universe are then juxtaposed and com-bined, and are examined for
significant variables. They are tested both for internal correlations and
for correlations with other forms of behavior or action.
Prosopography is used as a tool with which to attack two of the most
basic problems in history. The first concerns the roots of polit¬ical
action: the uncovering of the deeper interests that are thought to lie
beneath the rhetoric of politics; the analysis of the social and economic
affiliations of political groupings; the exposure of the workings of a
political machine; and the identification of those who pull the levers.
The second concerns social structure and social mobility: one set of
problems involves analysis of the role in society, and especially the
changes in that role over time, of specific ( usually elite) status groups,
holders of titles, members of professional asso-ciations, officeholders,
occupational groups, or economic classes; an-other set is concerned with
the determination of the degree of social
had the house in which the Stamp Act was passed and repealed, and
in which the Townshend Duties were enacted? How many of its
Members had been to the American Colonies, had connections with
them, or had an intimate knowledge of American affairs? Were any of
them American born?"15
Following this example similar questions about who rather than what
have been asked about such diverse questions in English historiography
as Magna Carta, the House of Commons, riots, the civil service, and the
Cabinet." The unstated premise is that an understanding of who the
actors were will go far toward explaining the workings of the institution
to which they belonged, will reveal the true objectives behind the flow
of political rhetoric, and will enable us better to understand their
achievement, and more cor¬rectly to interpret the documents they
produced.
The direction in which this attack on the conventional approach to
political institutions and policies would develop was powerfully
influenced by other important trends in the intellectual climate of the
period, of which the first and most important was cultural rela¬tivism.
Greater familiarity with foreign countries through travel combined with
the growing volume of anthropological studies to re¬veal the
extraordinary range of cultural patterns that have been adopted by
different societies around the world. The educated pub¬lic became
uneasily aware that morals, laws, constitutions, religious beliefs,
political attitudes, class structures, and sexual practices dif¬fer widely
from one society to another, and this awareness in time led to a
recognition that there are few universal norms of human behavior or
social organization. The stress on environmental condi¬tioning as the
determining factor in creating this variety was all the greater because the
1920's and 1930's was a period when genetic explanations of cultural
differences were not treated with the seri¬ousness it now begins to
appear that they may possibly deserve."' Social Darwinism, which was a
powerful influence around the turn of the century, laid far more stress on
nurture than nature. More¬over, the Freudian psychologists, who soon
afterwards began to come into their own, also laid great stress upon the
role of nurture, with particular emphasis on childhood and early sexual
experience. It must be admitted, however, that Freudian psychology has
not been much use to the historian, who is usually unable to penetrate
the bedroom, the bathroom, or the nursery. If Freud is right, and if these
are the places where the action is, there is not much the his¬torian can
do about it. The subsequent modification of Freudian
like Beard, or by men like Sir Lewis Namier and Sir Ronald Syme,
who are ostensibly of a conservative frame of mind. Syme frankly
admitted of his own work that "The design has imposed a pessi-mistic
and truculent tone, to the almost complete exclusion of the gentler
emotions and the domestic virtues," while an early reviewer commented
with dismay of Namier's book that "The political system which it
describes is certainly not attractive, based as it was upon a possibly
enlightened but a certainly sordid self-interest." 19
Nor was this cynicism confined to attitudes toward individual
politicians; it also covered political systems. If revolutions mean no
more than substitution of one grasping and self-centered ruling elite for
another, if a handful of unscrupulous men steer the ship of state the way
they want, whatever the constitutional flag under which they sail, then
the difference between tyranny and democ¬racy becomes blurred, to say
the least. From this point of view the elitist school of historical
prosopographers of the 1930's was deeply affected by the contemporary
crisis of confidence in democracy. Namier deliberately set out to destroy
theories about a tyrannical conspiracy by George III against the British
constitution, and Syme appeared to remove any basis for moral
judgments about the de¬struction of the Roman republic by Augustus. In
1939 A. Momigliano applied to Syme his own description of Tacitus: "a
monarchist from perspicacious despair of human nature." 20 Robert
Dahl has rightly observed, however, that "for individuals with a strong
strain of frustrated idealism, it [elite theory] has just the right touch of
hard-boiled cynicism."21 The elite theorist and the elite historian tend to
be disappointed egalitarians, whose misanthropy springs directly from
outraged moral sentiment.
The attitude toward the workings of politics taken by the early
prosopographers appears to owe little to the writings of political
theorists. Marx himself stressed the role first of the feudal lords and then
of the bourgeoisie, and directed attention to the self-interest that guided
their actions. But the first fully-fledged elitist political theories came out
of Europe in the early twentieth century, with the writings of R. Michels,
G. Mosca, and V. Pareto. Although Michels was available in French,
Pareto and Mosca were not trans¬lated into English before the 1930's,
and there is no evidence that they had the slightest influence in historical
circles in the Anglo- Saxon world until that time. Namier, Merton, and
Syme were strongly anti-Marxist, and yet only Merton appears to have
been familiar with these non-Marxist elitist models. What we have,
there-
fore, is the development by political scientists of a full-blown theory
of rule by elites a generation before the historians set to work. But apart
from Merton the historians carried out their empirical studies based on
their own semiconscious assumptions about political be-havior, without
the benefit of the political theory which would have provided them with
the framework they needed. It is one of the more bizarre episodes of
intellectual history, a consequence of the slowness of the great European
social scientists to be translated into English, and of the isolation of
history from the other social sciences in the early twentieth century.
A key feature of the elitist interpretation of the historical process is
the deliberate and systematic removal of both party programs and
ideological passions from the center of the political stage, and their
replacement by a complex web uniting patrons with their clients and
dependents. For Roman history, this is expressly stated by Professors L.
R. Taylor and E. Badian.22 For English history Namier substituted the
"connection" for the party as the central organizing principle of mid-
eighteenth-century politics, K. B. McFarlane invented the phrase
"Bastard Feudalism" to represent not dissimilar patron-client
relationships which he believed could explain the fifteenth century,
while Sir John Neale borrowed the word "clientage" from the classical
historians to make sense of the Elizabethan political system. In a key
passage the latter wrote, "most of the gentry seem to have grouped
themselves in close or loose re¬lationships around one or other of the
few great men of the country . . . The grouping and interdependence of
the gentry, with its ac¬companying and constant struggle for prestige
and supremacy, permeated English life. It assumed the part played by
politics in our modern society, and in the country, is the main clue to
parlia¬mentary elections." 23 For some scholars, prosopography was not
merely a way of ignoring passions and ideas, it was adopted for the
specific purpose of neutralizing these disturbing and intractable
elements.
A fourth stimulus to elitist prosopography, which in turn rein-forced
the new awareness of the essential role played in politics by associations
of dependents, was the almost obsessive concern of the anthropologists
for the family and kinship, the full impact of which is only just
beginning to make itself fully felt in the historical profes¬sion today. It
was Namier's work on mid-eighteenth-century Eng¬lish politics which
first drew the attention of historians to the po-tentialities of family
arrangements and kinship links as political
have been devoted to elites. The most popular subject for prosopog-
raphy has been and still is political elites, but other groups which lend
themselves most readily to such treatment are members of cer¬tain high
status categories, such as civil servants, army officers, up¬per clergy,
intellectuals and educators, lawyers, doctors, members of other
professional bodies, and industrial and commercial entrepre¬neurs. The
only elements of the lower classes about whom something can be done
in anything more than a highly impressionistic way are persecuted
minorities, since police reports and legal records often supply much of
the necessary information, especially in societies with a long tradition of
heavy bureaucratic and police control like France. The odd result is that
the only groups of poor and humble about whom we can sometimes find
out a good deal are minority groups, which are by definition exceptional
since they are in revolt against the mores and beliefs of the majority.
The third limitation imposed by the evidence arises from the fact that
it is abundant for some aspect of human life and almost nonexistent for
others. The surviving records are concerned first and foremost with the
amount, type, ownership, and transmission of property. It is this which is
the prime concern of official and private legal records, official tax
records, and public and private administra-tive records, which together
form the vast bulk of the written mater¬ial of the past. There is thus a
strong bias toward treating the indi¬vidual as homoeconomicus, and to
study him primarily in the light of his financial interests and behavior,
since this is what the records illuminate in the greatest clarity and detail.
But economic interests may conflict, and even when the interest is clear,
it is impossible to be sure that this is the overriding consideration.
Moreover the split between the compromisers and the last-ditchers is
often more im¬portant politically than the split between clearly defined
economic interest-groups.25
After economic interests, the second item of information that is
relatively easy to discover about a person is his family background and
connections. Among the upper classes marriage has been used in the past
to provide young men with useful friends and contacts, as well as to
merge properties and so create great territorial estates. Family ties have
also played an important part in the construction of political groups and
parties at all times from the Middle Ages to the eighteenth century and
beyond. One has only to think of the Howards and Dudleys in sixteenth-
century England, the Villiers in the early seventeenth century, the
Pelhams in the eighteenth, and
DiEDALIJS
the Cecils and Cavendishes in the late nineteenth and early
twen¬tieth, to recognize the continuing importance of this factor. But
this does not answer the question of how far it is safe to pursue this line
of reasoning, for the cementing role of kinship clearly varies from place
to place, from time to time, and from social level to social level. There
are countless examples in history of members of the same family who
have disagreed among themselves, often with ex¬treme violence.
Moreover, even when kinship ties were strong and can be shown to have
been so, there are limits to the meaningful pursuit of genealogical links.
Two diligent prosopographers working on the Long Parliament of 1640
tracked down genealogical connec¬tions which related the radical John
Hampden to eighty fellow M.P.'s, but unfortunately these kin turned out
to be of widely vary¬ing political and religious opinions. When the
authors found that by going back far enough they could find a kinship
connection be¬tween Charles I and Oliver Cromwell, they realized that
they had perhaps passed beyond the outer limits of utility of this
particular line of inquiry. Similar doubts have been recently expressed
about the role ascribed by the prosopographical school to kinship in
clas¬sical Rome.26
Errors in the Classification of the Data
Meaningful classification is essential to the success of any study, but
unfortunately for the historian every individual plays many roles, some
of which are in conflict with others. He belongs to a civilization, to a
national culture, and to a host of subcultures— ethnic, professional,
religious, peer-group, political, social, occupa¬tional, economic, sexual,
and so on. As a result, no one classification is of universal validity, and a
perfect congruence of classifications is quite rare. Status categories may
bear little relation to wealth, and also may vary in their importance over
time. Class categories based on wealth may not reflect social realities,
may be almost impossible to identify, and may be even more impossible
to compare over time; professional categories may cut through both
status and class lines and run vertically up and down the social system;
power categories, such as political offices, may vary over time in the
social status at-tached to them, in the power they wield, and in the
income they produce.
The second danger which threatens every prosopographer is that he
may fail to identify important subdivisions, and may thus be
erence to Namier that "human beings are the carriers of ideas, as well
as the repositories of vested interests."35
Despite some later disclaimers, there can be little doubt that in
practice both Namier and Syme attached little importance to any ideal or
prejudice which ran counter to the calculations of self- interest. The
attention paid by these historians to the tactics rather than the strategy of
politics presupposes a society without convic¬tion in which
manipulation and wire-pulling are more important than issues of
principle or policy. It so happened that the mid- eighteenth century, upon
which Namier first focused his attention, was a period in English history
unusually devoid of major issues of controversy, and a period when the
political actors formed an unusually homogeneous group: he thus chose,
by accident or design, a period and a class which were especially
susceptible to analysis by the methods he adopted. But some of his
followers have found, to their cost, that it is not always safe to carry the
same assumptions forwards and backwards in time. Robert Walcott tried
to use the. model for the reign of Queen Anne, with results that are now
gen¬erally recognized to have been little short of disastrous.36 One may
also wonder whether Oliver Cromwell's failure successfully to man¬age
his Parliaments can really be explained by his lack of tactical skill, as
Professor Trevor-Roper argues, or whether disagreement over
fundamental constitutional and religious issues between the military and
the civilians, and between Independents, Presbyterians, and Anglicans,
put a settlement quite out of reach of even the most shrewd and
assiduous manipulator of men.37 One may therefore con¬clude that the
explanatory power of the interest-group theory of politics, which has
tended to be associated with the elitist proso¬pographical approach, is
much greater at some periods and in some places than it is at and in
others. The fewer the major political issues, the lower the ideological
temperature, the more oligarchic the political organization, the more
likely it is to provide a con¬vincing historical interpretation.
Another limitation of the prosopographical school of historians is that
its members sometimes unduly neglect the stuff of politics, the
institutional framework within which the system functions, and the
narrative of how political actors shape public policy. "We are given a
story that becomes silent or curiously neglectful as it touches the very
things that government and Parliaments exist to do," com¬plained Sir
Herbert Butterfield. He concluded harshly that: "There is little interest in
the work of ministers within their departments; in
DADALUS
greater knowledge of who the Puritans were, though much work still
remains to be done on Puritan merchants, dons, schoolmasters, clergy,
and nobles.47 On the other flank a very careful statistical and
geographical comparison of Catholics in the 1560's and Catholics in the
1580's has proved conclusively, as no other method could, that the late
Elizabethan development of Catholicism was a gentry-based revival
stimulated by the missionary activities of the seminary priests, and not a
survival of popular pre-Reformation Catholicism.48
Social history, which is concerned with groups rather than indi-
viduals, ideas, or institutions, is a field to which prosopography prob-
ably has most to contribute. Attempts to generalize about social change
in advance of either detailed local studies or global statistics based on
serious archival research lead to the kind of impasse into which the
famous "gentry controversy" got itself stuck twenty years ago, during
which rival hypotheses about broad social movements between 1540 and
1640 and their relationship to the revolution were bandied about on the
basis of craftily selected examples whose typicality was altogether
unknown. Since that time there have ap-peared several local studies of
groups of gentry, and one general study on the aristocracy, which
together go some way to eliminate certain hypotheses and to put
statistical weight behind some others."
For example, as a result of many years of very careful work upon the
gentry of Yorkshire, it has been shown that of those gentry of the
country who were in economic decline before the war and who took
sides, three quarters joined the royalists and only one quarter the
parliamentarians.50 If this is true across the country, it disproves
Professor Trevor-Roper's hypothesis that the radicals on the parlia-
mentary side represented the declining "mere gentry." The same study
also brings out the importance of Puritanism among so many
parliamentarians and of Catholicism among a significant number of
royalists. It adds one more nail to the coffin of the old Marxist the-ory,
tentatively supported by R. H. Tawney and J. E. C. Hill, that the civil
war was a conflict between capitalist entrepreneurial land¬lords and old-
fashioned rentiers. In this case, detailed prosopo¬graphical analysis has
put to the test—as nothing else could—the many theories of the social
causes of the revolution, and has begun to sift truth from falsehood
among them.51
As one might expect, the greatest concentration of prosopograph¬ical
energy has been directed toward the political elite, and in par¬ticular
toward the M.P.'s. The late nineteenth- and early twentieth-
for handling just the sort of material that prosopography throws up.
The correlation of numerous variables affecting large masses of data,
assembled on a uniform basis, is precisely what the computer can do
best; it is also what is most laborious, and in many cases virtually
impossible, for even the most mathematically-minded of historians
working without. electronic aids. It is painful to admit that the advent of
a technical gadget should dictate the type of histori¬cal questions asked
and the methods used for solving them, but it would be adopting the
posture of the ostrich to pretend that this is not happening now, and will
not happen on an even greater scale in the years to come.
It must be admitted that there are some serious dangers inherent in the
very success and popularity of prosopography. The first is that the really
large undertakings, like Sir John Neale's work on Elizabethan
Parliaments, Professor W. K. Jordan's on charitable giv-ing, or Sir Lewis
Namier's even grander History of Parliament pro-ject, must be carried
out by teams of researchers, assembling data on the lines laid down by
the director. This material is then studied, collated, and eventually
published by the director, to whom alone the credit goes." Collective
research is already fully accepted by the physical scientists as a familiar
and necessary process, but it in¬volves a degree of intellectual peonage
by students and junior fac¬ulty to the professor, which many scholars
bred in the older individ¬ualistic and independent tradition of
historiography find disturbing. The second danger is that instead of
coming together, the mass and the elitist schools will specialize more
and more on their different approaches, the one becoming more
scientific and quanti¬tative and the other more impressionistic and
devoted to individual examples inadequately controlled by random
sampling. This would be a disaster for the profession, since it would
spell the end of fruit¬ful cross-fertilization. The danger has been greatly
increased by the advent of the computer, which has been embraced by
the more statistically-minded with all the undiscriminating enthusiasm of
the nymphomaniac, and rejected by the less scientific partly from
in¬tellectual prudery, and partly from complacent ignorance of what
pleasures they are missing. The availability of the computer will
increasingly tempt some historians to concentrate their energies on
problems that can be solved by quantification, problems which are
sometimes—but by no means always—the most important or
inter¬esting ones. It will also tempt them to abandon sampling
techniques, which are frequently perfectly adequate for their purposes,
and to
REFERENCES
1. The word prosopography has a long history; its first known use is in 1743. C.
Nicolet, "Prosopographie et histoire sociale: Rome et Italie a l'epoque republicaine,"
Annales: economies, societes, civilisations, no. 3 (1970), n. 3 (I am indebted to the
editors of Annales for a sight of this article in proof). It provides a concise and accurate
term for an increasingly com¬mon historical method, and is already in standard use by
one group in the profession. It therefore seems very desirable that it should pass into
every¬day use among modern historians.
2. H. D. Lasswell and D. Lerner, World Revolutionary Elites: Studies in
Coercive Ideological Movements (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1965 ).
3. D. A. Rustow, "The Study of Elites," World Politics, 18 ( 1966).
4. Nicolet, "Prosopographie et histoire sociale."
5. Joshua Wilson, Biographical Index to the Present House of Commons
(Lon¬don, 1806 ); A. Collins, The Peerage of England ( London, 1714 ); A. Collins,
The Baronetage of England (London, 1720); J. Burke, The Com¬moners of Great
Britain and Ireland (London, 1833-1838); W. F. Hook, Lives of the Archbishops of
Canterbury (London, 1860-1876 ); G. Hennessy, Repertorium Ecclesiasticum
Parochiale Londinense ( London, 1898); J. Campbell, Lives of the Lord Chancellors
( London, 1845-1847); J. Camp¬bell, Lives of the Chief Justices (London, 1849 ); E.
Foss, Biographia Juridica, A Biographical Dictionary of the Judges of England . . .
1066¬1870 (London, 1870); H. W. Woolrych, Lives of Eminent Sergeants-at¬Law
(London, 1869 ); C. Dalton, English Army Lists, 1661-1714 (London, 1892-1904 ); C.
Dalton, George the First's Army, 1716-1727 (London, 1910); J. Campbell, Lives of the
Admirals (London, 1742-1744 ); J. Charnock, Biographia Navalis (London, 1794-
1798); W. Munk, Roll of the Royal College of Physicians of London (1861); A. B.
Beaven, Aldermen of the City of London (London, 1908-1913); J. Gillow,
Bibliographical Dictionary of English Catholics, 1534-1902 (1885-1902); D. C. A.
Agnew, Protestant Exiles from France in the Reign of Louis XIV ( Edinburgh:
Huguenot Society, 1886); J. and J. A. Venn, Alumni Cantabrigienses ( Cambridge,
Eng., 1922-1954 ); J. Foster, Alumni Oxonienses ( Oxford, 1891-1892 ).
6. Charles A. Beard, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the
United States (New York: Macmillan, 1913 ).
7. Ibid. (1935), pp. 73, 324, xii-xiv.
8. A. P. Newton, The Colonising Activities of the English Puritans ( New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1914).
9. It was not followed up until the publication of J. H. Hexter, The Reign of King
Pym ( Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1941).
10. M. Gelzer, Die Nobilitiit der riimischen Republik ( Leipzig-Berlin: B. G.
Teubner, 1912); F. Munzer, Riimische Adelsparteien and Adelsfamilien ( Stuttgart,
1920 ).
11. John Raymond, New Statesman (October 19, 1957 ), pp. 499-500.
12. Some examples are published in D. K. Rowney and J. Q. Graham,
Quanti¬tative History (Homewood, Ill.: Dorsey Press, 1969), part VI.
13. The leaders of this intellectual revolution were the French, Marc Bloch and
Lucien Febvre.
1660," Ph.D. diss., Oxford, 1949; P. Tyler, "The Status of the Elizabethan Parochial
Clergy," Studies in Church History, 4 ( 1957 ).
47. There is a good deal of incidental prosopographical material in P. Collinson's
great book, The Elizabethan Puritan Movement ( London: Cape, 1967). P. S. Seaver,
The Puritan Lectureships ( Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1970), chaps. 5, 6.
48. A. G. Dickens, "The First Stages of Romanist Recusancy in Yorkshire, 1580-
1590," Yorkshire Archaeological Journal, 35 ( 1941). See also J. Bossy, "The Character
of Elizabethan Catholicism," Past and Present, 21 ( 1962); B. Magee, The English
Recusants ( London: Burns, Oates, and Washbourne, 1938 ).
49. For a summary of the controversy see L. Stone, Social Change and
Revolu¬tion in England, 1540-1640 ( London: Longmans, 1965 ), pp. xi-xxvi; M. E.
Finch, The Wealth of Five Northamptonshire Families, 1540-1640 ( Ox¬ford:
Northamptonshire Record Society, 1956); Cliffe, The Yorkshire Gentry; H. A. Lloyd,
The Gentry of South-West Wales, 1540-1640 ( Cardiff: University of Wales Press,
1968 ); Stone, The Crisis of the Aristocracy. In the last few years some twenty doctoral
theses have been or are being written on groups of gentry in various counties.
50. Cliffe, The Yorkshire Gentry, p. 354. These percentages and the conclusions
drawn from them are mine, not Dr. Cliffe's.
51. Prosopography has also undermined another hypothesis about the causes of
the Civil War, namely H. R. Trevor-Roper's claims about the role of the bureaucracy.
G. E. Aylmer, "Office-holding as a Factor in English History, 1625-42," History, 44
( 1959 ).
52. Unpublished theses by pupils of Sir John Neale, a brilliant synthesis and
interpretation of whose findings is set out in his Elizabethan House of Commons. T. L.
Moir, The Addled Parliament of 1614 ( Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1958); Keeler, The
Long Parliament; Brunton and Pennington, Mem¬bers of the Long Parliament; P. J.
Pinkney, "The Cromwellian Parliament of 1656," Ph.D. diss., Vanderbilt, 1962; M. E.
W. Helms, "The Convention Parliament of 1660," Ph.D. diss., Bryn Mawr, 1963.
53. Everitt, The Community of Kent, p. 143; V. Pearl, London and the Out-break
of the Puritan Revolution ( London: Oxford University Press, 1961), p. 180; R. G.
Howell, Newcastle upon Tyne and the Puritan Revolution ( Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1967 ), pp. 171-173. The old elite held on in Suffolk. See A. Everitt, Suffolk and the
Great Rebellion, 1640-1660, Suffolk Record Society, 3 (1960 ).
54. Distinguished elite studies by American scholars in American history in-
clude: J. T. Main, The Upper House in Revolutionary America, 1763-1788 ( Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press, 1967); D. J. Rothman, Politics and Power: The United
States Senate, 1869-1901 ( Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1966); S. H.
Aronson, Status and Kinship in the Higher Civil Service ( Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1964 );