The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision - Findley e Scott
The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision - Findley e Scott
The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision - Findley e Scott
Legal Studies Research Paper Series
Paper No. 1023
June 2006
The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision
In Criminal Cases
Keith A. Findley & Michael S. Scott
This paper can be downloaded without charge from the
Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection at:
http://ssrn.com/abstract=911240
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
INTRODUCTION
See SCHECK ET AL., supra note 5, at 246 (finding eyewitness error in 84 percent of the
first sixty-two postconviction DNA exonerations); Gross et al., supra note 2, at 542
(finding eyewitness error in 64 percent of the cases identified in their study of 340
wrongful convictions between 1989 and 2003).
11. When investigators believe a suspect is the perpetrator, their inquiry shifts
from a fact-gathering “interview” to a confession-seeking “interrogation.” In many
departments, police are taught to “interrogate” suspects only when they are satisfied the
suspect is guilty; at that point the objective is obtaining a confession. Various
stratagems are then employed to break the suspect down psychologically and to induce
a confession. See infra Part II.C.1.
12. Martin, supra note 6, at 861.
13. See Peter J. Neufeld, The (Near) Irrelevance of Daubert to Criminal
Justice and Some Suggestions for Reform, 95 AM. J. PUB. HEALTH S107, S111 (2005)
(noting that “examiner bias” produces skewed results in forensic laboratories where, as
is common, “police . . . offer a detailed narrative of the crime and an inventory of
whatever other inculpatory evidence they have against the suspect on the request form
used to order a particular scientific test”); see generally D. Michael Risinger et al., The
Daubert/Kumho Implications of Observer Effects in Forensic Science: Hidden
Problems of Expectation and Suggestion, 90 CAL. L. REV. 1 (2002).
14. See Martin, supra note 6, at 848; George Castelle & Elizabeth F. Loftus,
Misinformation and Wrongful Convictions, in WRONGLY CONVICTED 17, 18-19, 24,
29-30 (Saundra D. Westervelt & John A. Humphrey eds., 2001).
15. Both scholarly and popular accounts of wrongful convictions have also
observed the problem of tunnel vision: “Perhaps the most common fault with criminal
investigations is their failure to explore all the possible suspects. When attention begins
to focus on a single individual, too often the detectives are called off the general hunt to
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
go after the single target. Tunnel vision sets in.” BILL KURTIS, THE DEATH PENALTY
ON TRIAL: CRISIS IN AMERICAN JUSTICE 33 (2004); see also Martin, supra note 6, at
849; James McCloskey, Convicting the Innocent, 8 CRIM. JUST. ETHICS 2, 56 (1989).
Even before the problem of wrongful convictions was widely recognized, the American
Bar Association (ABA) and the Association of American Law Schools (AALS)
described the process that can lead to tunnel vision. In a 1966 joint report, the two
organizations observed:
What generally occurs in practice is that at some early point a familiar
pattern will seem to emerge from the evidence; an accustomed label is
waiting for the case and, without awaiting further proofs, this label is
promptly assigned to it. It is a mistake to suppose that this premature
cataloguing must necessarily result from impatience, prejudice or mental
sloth. Often it proceeds from a very understandable desire to bring the
hearing into some order and coherence, for without some tentative theory of
the case there is no standard of relevancy by which testimony may be
measured. But what starts as a preliminary diagnosis designed to direct the
inquiry tends, quickly and imperceptibly, to become a fixed conclusion, as
all that confirms the diagnosis makes a strong imprint on the mind, while all
that runs counter to it is received with diverted attention.
AM. BAR ASS’N & ASS’N OF AM. LAW SCH., Report of the Joint Conference of the
American Bar Association and the Association of American Law Schools on
Professional Responsibility, 44 A.B.A. J. 1159, 1160 (1958) reprinted in THE LAWYER
IN MODERN SOCIETY 188, 189 (V. Countryman & T. Finman eds., 1966).
16. See STATE OF ILL., REPORT OF THE GOVERNOR’S COMMISSION ON CAPITAL
PUNISHMENT 20 (2002), available at http://www.idoc.state.il.us/ccp/ccp/reports/
commission_report/complete_report.pdf.
17. Steve Mills & John Biemer, Ford Heights 4 Inquiry Clears Cops,
Prosecutors, CHI. TRIB., Aug. 22, 2003, at 1.
18. In Canada, unlike most jurisdictions in the United States, the government
has responded to exonerations by holding extensive inquiries into what went wrong and
what might prevent such errors in the future. For a discussion contrasting that response
to the typical response in the United States, in which the exonerated are released
without official comment or inquiry, see Keith A. Findley, Learning from Our
Mistakes: A Criminal Justice Study Commission to Study Wrongful Convictions, 38
CAL. W. L. REV. 333, 338-39, 342-44 (2002).
19. See FPT HEADS OF PROSECUTION COMM. WORKING GROUP, REPORT ON
THE PREVENTION OF MISCARRIAGES OF JUSTICE 35 (2004), available at
http://canada.justice.gc.ca/en/dept/pub/hop/; Province of Manitoba, The Inquiry
Regarding Thomas Sophonow, http://www.gov.mb.ca/justice/publications/
sophonow/arnold/recommend.html (last visited Feb. 25, 2006).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
20. INNOCENCE COMM’N FOR VA., A VISION FOR JUSTICE: REPORT AND
RECOMMENDATIONS REGARDING WRONGFUL CONVICTIONS IN THE COMMONWEALTH OF
VIRGINIA 10 (2005), available at http://www.wcl.american.edu/innocenceproject/
ICVA/full_r.pdf?rd=1.
21. See Martin, supra note 6, at 850 (describing an example of tunnel vision
during the police investigation stage).
22. Id. at 849.
23. See infra Part II.B.2.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
A. Marvin Anderson
After a trial that lasted less than five hours, Marvin Anderson was
convicted of robbery, forcible sodomy, abduction, and two counts of
rape of a twenty-four-year-old woman in Hanover, Virginia, in 1982.24
In 2002, DNA testing proved that he did not commit the crime.25
Police investigators had focused on Anderson because the rapist, who
was African American, had mentioned to the victim that he had a white
girlfriend, and Anderson was the only black man police knew of who
was living with a white woman.26
Anderson did not fit the victim’s description of her attacker in
several respects; Anderson was taller than the man the victim described
and, unlike the attacker, Anderson had a dark complexion, no
mustache, and no scratches on his face.27 Nonetheless, investigators
obtained a photo of Anderson from his employer (he had no prior
record and hence no mug photo) and presented it to the victim in an
array of six to ten photos. Anderson’s photo was the only one in color,
and the only one with his social security number printed on it.28 The
victim selected Anderson’s photograph. Thirty minutes later, police
put together a live-person lineup that again included Anderson.29
Anderson was apparently the only person in the lineup whose photo had
also been included in the photo array.30 Police told the victim to “go in
and look at the people in the line up to see if she could pick out the
suspect,” and she again picked Anderson.31 Many of the procedures
used in Anderson’s identification process are now widely recognized as
suggestive or flawed in ways that can lead an eyewitness to mistakenly
identify an innocent person.32
There were other reasons to doubt the identification as well. DNA
testing was not yet available at the time, but a forensic scientist testified
that she had performed blood typing on swabs from both Anderson and
the victim and was unable to identify Anderson as the source of semen
samples collected in the rape kit.33 In addition, Anderson presented
four alibi witnesses, including his mother, his girlfriend, and two
neighbors, who all testified that they saw him outside his mother’s
house washing his car at the time of the attack.34 None of this
evidence, however, was enough to overcome the eyewitness
identification.35
Tunnel vision infected Anderson’s case from the beginning,
leading police, prosecutors, defense counsel, and eventually the jury
and reviewing courts, to minimize and discredit the alibi evidence, the
mismatch between the victim’s description of the perpetrator and
Anderson’s appearance, and the absence of physical evidence. Even
more significantly, the premature focus on Anderson meant that no one
pursued evidence that was available before trial that pointed toward the
true perpetrator.36 As the Virginia Innocence Commission concluded,
“[o]nce the victim identified Anderson, . . . the police did not pursue
additional leads.”37
The DNA testing that exonerated Anderson in 2002 identified the
true perpetrator—a man named Otis “Pop” Lincoln.38 The match to
Lincoln should not have come as a surprise. Lincoln’s name had been
circulating in the community as a likely suspect for some time prior to
Anderson’s conviction, but no one investigated him.39 Two friends of
the Anderson family said before trial that just before the rape they saw
Lincoln riding a bicycle toward the shopping center where the attack
occurred—a fact of particular significance because the attacker rode a
bicycle.40 Moreover, these witnesses heard Lincoln make sexually
suggestive comments to two young white girls, and then boast as he
rode past that he would force himself onto a woman if she refused his
advances.41 The owner of the bicycle that was used by the assailant
also said that Lincoln had stolen it from him approximately thirty
minutes before the rape.42 After Anderson was arrested, others in the
community reported to Anderson’s mother that Lincoln drove by her
house one day because he wanted to see “the young boy who was
taking his rap.”43 Moreover, unlike Anderson, Lincoln had a criminal
record for sexual assault and was awaiting trial for another sexual
attack at the time.44 Nonetheless, even Anderson’s defense lawyer
declined to investigate or call any witnesses who could have linked
Lincoln to the crime at trial.45
Eventually, six years later, at proceedings on Anderson’s
application for habeas corpus, Lincoln confessed fully to the crime in
court under oath and provided details of the attack.46 Nevertheless, the
same judge who presided over the original trial refused to credit
Lincoln’s confession, finding that it was untruthful.47 The Governor
subsequently refused to intervene and denied clemency.48 Anderson
remained in prison, and then on parole, for several more years until
DNA testing confirmed that Lincoln, not Anderson, was the attacker.49
Other aspects of the case also reveal just how stubborn erroneous
beliefs in guilt can be. Despite the weakness of the case against
Anderson, and the abundance of evidence that should have alerted
authorities to investigate Lincoln, the original prosecutor in the case
claimed that, from his perspective and until the exoneration, the
Anderson case was “the clearest case he had ever had.”50 Although
Anderson’s trial lawyer made numerous egregious errors, the trial court
was unwilling to grant a new trial on a claim of ineffective assistance of
counsel. The court concluded that it made no difference that: (1)
counsel had a conflict of interest because he had previously represented
Lincoln on a previous attempted rape charge; (2) although the lawyer
knew there was evidence against Lincoln, and admitted that he
suspected Lincoln, he failed to disclose his prior representation of
Lincoln, his suspicions about Lincoln, and his conflict of interest to
Anderson; (3) despite Anderson’s mother’s repeated pleas, the lawyer
failed to call Lincoln or the other witnesses who had watched Lincoln
harass the young women, make threats, and ride off on a bicycle
toward the crime scene just before the attack in this case; and (4) the
lawyer failed to ask that the bicycle ridden by the attacker on the day of
the rape be fingerprinted or introduced into evidence, even though the
bicycle was in police custody. The trial court found that all of this was
insufficient to meet the two-pronged test for ineffective assistance of
counsel.51
B. Steven Avery
police and prosecutors and should have been a prime suspect.53 Also
like Anderson, Avery was wrongly convicted because tunnel vision
prevented system actors from considering alternative theories about the
crime until DNA evidence finally proved in 2003 that Avery was
innocent, and that another man, Gregory Allen, was guilty.54 By then,
Avery had served more than eighteen years in prison.55
The rape and attempted murder in Avery’s case was committed in
broad daylight on a beach in Manitowoc County, Wisconsin, in 1985.56
While being treated in the hospital after the attack, the victim gave
police a description of her attacker and helped create a composite
sketch.57 Based on that description and sketch, local sheriff’s deputies
thought the attacker might be Avery.58 Law enforcement knew Avery
because Manitowoc was a small community, he had relatives who
worked in the sheriff’s department, he had previously been convicted of
two counts of burglary and one count of cruelty to an animal, and he
was being prosecuted at the time for allegedly forcing the wife of a
deputy off the road at gunpoint as part of an ongoing feud.59
The sheriff presented Avery’s photo to the victim as part of a nine-
photo simultaneous array, telling her that “the suspect might be in
there.”60 The victim later said that the sheriff’s statement led her to
“believe[] that the suspect’s photograph was included in the group of
nine photos.”61 However, a photograph of Allen, the true perpetrator,
was not included in the array and the victim instead selected Avery’s
photo.62 Three days later, after the victim had been informed that
police had arrested the man she identified, police conducted a live-
person lineup to confirm her identification.63 Avery was the only
53. Id.
54. Id.
55. Id. Two years later, Avery was charged with a subsequent rape and
murder of a young woman committed in October 2005. As of this writing, Avery has
not yet been tried on those charges. The new charges raise no questions about the
validity of the previous exoneration. Regardless of the outcome of the pending trial,
Avery’s wrongful conviction in 1985 remains an important case study in the problem of
tunnel vision.
56. Id.
57. Id.
58. Id.
59. Id.
60. Id.
61. Hearings of the Wisconsin Assemb. Judiciary Comm. Avery Task Force,
2003-2004 Leg., Reg. Sess. (Wis. 2004) (statement of Penny Beerntsen) [hereinafter
Beerntsen Statement].
62. Id. at 1.
63. Memorandum from Peggy A. Lautenschlager to Mark Rohrer, supra note
52.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
person in the lineup whose photo had also been in the previous photo
array.64 Avery was also the shortest, youngest, and fairest person in
the lineup.65 Unlike Avery, a few of the people in the lineup wore
professional attire such as neck ties, and some wore glasses.66 Records
from the lineup indicate that one lineup member looked at Avery during
most of the lineup.67 Again, the victim picked Avery.68
The State bolstered its eyewitness evidence with circumstantial
evidence. Deputies swore that the night of the arrest they told Avery
only that he was being arrested for attempted murder, yet they claimed
Avery told his wife that he was being accused of attempting to murder a
“girl.”69 Despite the ambiguous nature of that evidence, the deputies,
the prosecutor, and, ultimately, the courts thought it was highly
incriminating that Avery seemed to know the gender of the victim.70 In
addition, to rebut Avery’s alibi—his claim that he had spent the day
pouring concrete with his extended family and friends—the State
offered evidence that the State Crime Laboratory could find no traces of
concrete dust on his clothing.71 The State also offered evidence that a
hair found on Avery’s tee shirt was microscopically similar to the
victim’s head hair.72
Avery’s defense was unusually strong. He presented sixteen alibi
witnesses who confirmed that he had been pouring concrete during the
day and then had taken his wife and five young children—including six-
day-old twins—to Green Bay, more than an hour’s drive away, for
64. Id.
65. Id.
66. Id.
67. Id.
68. Id.
69. Id.
70. See State v. Avery, 213 Wis. 2d. 228, 245, 570 N.W.2d 573, 581 (Ct.
App. 1997) (referring to the “powerful” evidence that Avery referred to the victim as a
female prior to being told the gender of the victim by the police).
71. Id.; Memorandum from Peggy A. Lautenschlager to Mark Rohrer, supra
note 52.
72. Microscopic hair analysis has been roundly criticized in recent years as
“junk science.” Postconviction DNA testing has shown that microscopic hair analysis
is frequently misleading or inaccurate. See Neufeld, supra note 13, at S107-8; Clive A.
Stafford Smith & Patrick D. Goodman, Forensic Hair Comparison Analysis:
Nineteenth Century Science or Twentieth Century Snake Oil?, 27 COLUM. HUM. RTS.
L. REV. 227 (1996) (discussing the questionable scientific foundation of microscopic
hair analysis). The Wisconsin State Crime Laboratory no longer performs microscopic
hair analysis, in part because DNA testing is so much more reliable. Telephone
interview by Keith Findley with Jerome Geurts, Director, Wis. State Crime Laboratory
(April 27, 2006).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
supper and to shop for paint.73 Instead of taking pause from this
evidence, the State sought a way to minimize its significance. The
prosecutor impeached the testimony of Avery’s family and friends as
biased.74 When Avery presented the testimony of unbiased witnesses—
the clerk and the manager at the Shopko store where Avery purchased
his paint in Green Bay—sheriff’s deputies sought a way around their
testimony. The clerk and the manager, who had not known Avery
previously, remembered him checking out because it was unusual to see
a family with five young children, including twins who were less than a
week old. And they produced the cash register tape showing that
Avery and his family had checked out at 5:13 p.m.—a little over an
hour after the victim claimed the attack had begun.75 Sheriff’s deputies
countered that they had done a timed drive from the location of the
assault to the Green Bay Shopko and had been able to make it to the
checkout line in fifty-seven minutes.76 But, as the Attorney General
concluded after investigating Avery’s wrongful conviction in 2003:
[T]he officers admitted that they went ten miles per hour over
the speed limit to reach those numbers and the officers did not
account for potential delays resulting from the presence of
five children, including six-day old twins, all of whom were
seen with Avery and his wife at the Shopko. Moreover, the
reenactment did not allow any time for picking up Avery’s
family and would therefore assume that Avery’s wife and five
children were at the beach somewhere or in the car while he
committed the assault.77
Simply put, tunnel vision prevented the deputies, the prosecutor, the
judge, and the jury from appreciating the implausibility of that
scenario.
Even more startling, however, the sheriff’s department and
prosecutor refused to consider or investigate the true perpetrator, even
though he was in their sights all along. Allen, who was identified as
the true perpetrator by a cold hit in the DNA database in 2003, was a
known sexual offender in Manitowoc County prior to this offense, and
his offenses were escalating.78 Two years earlier, the same prosecutor
79. Id.
80. Id. Finally, ten years after the 1985 assault, Gregory Allen was convicted
of a subsequent sexual assault of a woman in Green Bay, and was sentenced to sixty
years in prison. Meg Jones, Man Linked to Sexual Assault Transferred to Waupun,
MILWAUKEE J. SENTINEL, Sept. 26, 2003, at 3B, available at
http://www.jsonline.com/news/state/sep03/172525.asp.
81. Tom Kertscher, Police Were Watching Man Now Linked to Avery Case,
MILWAUKEE J. SENTINEL, Oct. 20, 2003, at 1A, available at
http://www.jsonline.com/news/state/oct03/178587.asp.
82. Id.
83. Memorandum from Peggy A. Lautenschlager to Mark Rohrer, supra note
52.
84. Id.
85. Kertscher, supra note 81.
86. Beerntsen Statement, supra note 61, at 7-8.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
87. State v. Avery, No. 86-1831-CR, 1987 WL 267394, *5 (Wis. Ct. App.
Aug. 5, 1987) (unpublished opinion).
88. Wisconsin Innocence Project, Case Profiles: Steven Avery,
http://www.law.wisc.edu/fjr/innocence/avery_Summary2.htm (last visited Mar. 28,
2006).
89. Id.
90. The tests done at that time could not exclude or include Avery because
they revealed genetic markers consistent with both the victim and Avery. See id.
91. State v. Avery, 213 Wis. 2d 228, 243, 570 N.W.2d 573, 580 (Ct. App.
1997).
92. Id. at 245, 570 N.W.2d at 581.
93. Tom Kertscher & Jesse Garza, DNA Clears Prisoner 17 Years Into His
Term, MILWAUKEE J. SENTINEL, Sept. 11, 2003, at 1A, available at
http://www.jsonline.com/news/racine/sep03/168842.asp.
94. Id.
95. Memorandum from Peggy A. Lautenschlager to Mark Rohrer, supra note
52.
96. See Kertscher & Garza, supra note 93.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
97. Steven A. Drizin & Richard A. Leo, The Problem of False Confessions in
the Post-DNA World, 82 N.C. L. REV. 891, 894 (2004).
98. Id.
99 . Saul M. Kassin & Gisli H. Gudjonsson, The Psychology of Confessions:
A Review of the Literature and Issues, 5 PSYCHOL. SCI. IN THE PUB. INT. 33, 34 (2004).
100. Drizin & Leo, supra note 97, at 894-95.
101. Id. at 895.
102. Id.
103. Id. at 895-96.
104. Id. at 896.
105. Kassin & Gudjonsson, supra note 99, at 60.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
from five boys to the rape of the Central Park Jogger.106 Four of those
five confessions were videotaped.107 But only the confessions were
recorded; the hours of interrogations that led up to the confessions were
not.108
Precisely what happened during the hours of unrecorded
interrogations was a matter of contention both before and at trial. The
boys and their parents claimed coercion, alleging that the police
slapped, yelled, and cursed at the boys, called them liars, and suggested
they would be released if they confessed.109 Police admitted lying to
the boys about fingerprint evidence, but denied any coercive tactics.110
The trial court credited the police version and held that the boys’
confessions were admissible at trial.111 Regardless of where the truth
about those interrogations lay, two things are clear: police and
prosecutors were focused on the boys as suspects, and they succeeded
in getting the boys to confess.
At trial, prosecutors also introduced evidence that hair consistent
with the victim’s hair was found on one of the boys’ clothing, along
with a bloody rock that prosecutors claimed the boys used to bludgeon
the jogger.112 All five boys were convicted of participating in the rape
of the jogger and other attacks committed in the park that night.113
In 2002, evidence began to emerge that the boys were innocent.114
In January of that year, a man named Matias Reyes confessed to
authorities that he raped the Central Park Jogger, and that he had acted
alone.115 It turned out that Reyes “was one of New York City’s most
notorious serial rapists.”116 In the months following the Central Park
attack, until his apprehension in August 1989, he had “terrorized the
Upper East Side, raping four women, one of whom, a pregnant
woman, he killed after raping her in front of her children.”117 DNA
subsequently confirmed the confession: Reyes’s DNA matched semen
on the jogger’s sock.118 Mitochondrial DNA testing of the hair found
on one of the boys’ clothing also showed that it probably was not the
jogger’s, and additional testing on the bloody rock showed the blood
and hair on the rock were not hers either.119 A subsequent investigation
by the district attorney’s office found no link between Reyes and any of
the five defendants.120 Moreover, the district attorney’s office
concluded that the confessions from the five boys were inconsistent
with one another on “virtually every major aspect of the crime,”121
were inconsistent with the objectively verifiable evidence, and were
demonstrably false in significant respects.122 Accordingly, the district
attorney’s office joined in a motion to vacate the convictions and the
court set aside all five convictions in December 2002.123
Despite this new evidence, former prosecutors and police involved
in the case sharply criticized the district attorney’s office for joining in
the motion to vacate the convictions.124 The police department
conducted its own investigation and issued a report that ultimately
supported the decision to vacate the convictions, but disputed many of
the district attorney’s conclusions, sought to discredit Reyes’s detailed
confession, and offered several theories to explain how the boys might
have committed the crime with Reyes.125
127. See THOMAS GILOVICH, HOW WE KNOW WHAT ISN’T SO: THE FALLIBILITY
OF HUMAN REASON IN EVERYDAY LIFE 33 (1991); RICHARD NISBETT & LEE ROSS,
HUMAN INFERENCE: STRATEGIES AND SHORTCOMINGS OF SOCIAL JUDGMENT (James J.
Jenkins et al. eds., 1980); Alafair S. Burke, Improving Prosecutorial Decision Making:
Some Lessons of Cognitive Science, 47 WM. & MARY L. REV. 8 (2006); Charles G.
Lord et al., Biased Assimilation and Attitude Polarization: The Effects of Prior
Theories on Subsequently Considered Evidence, 37 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL.
2098 (1979); Raymond S. Nickerson, Confirmation Bias: A Ubiquitous Phenomenon in
Many Guises, 2 REV. GEN. PSYCHOL. 175, 175 (1998); Yaacov Trope & Akiva
Liberman, Social Hypothesis Testing: Cognitive and Motivational Mechanisms, in
SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY: HANDBOOK OF BASIC PRINCIPLES 239, 239-70 (E. Tory Higgins
& Arie W. Kruglanski eds., 1996).
128. Julius Caesar, for example, observed that “people easily believe that
which they want to be true.” Risinger et al., supra note 13, at 6 (quoting G. JULIUS
CAESAR, CAESAR’S COMMENTARIES ON THE GALLIC WAR 155 (Frederick Holland
Dewey ed., Translation Publishing Co. 1918) (51 B.C.E.) (“[H]omines fere credunt
libentur id quod volunt.”)).
129. Risinger et al., supra note 13, at 12-26.
130. Id.
131. Id.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
1. CONFIRMATION BIAS
132. Id.
133. Id.
134. Id. at 14 (quoting WILLIAM JAMES, THE PRINCIPLES OF PSYCHOLOGY,
1890, ch. 13, reprinted in 53 GREAT BOOKS OF THE WESTERN WORLD 318 (Robert
Maynard Hutchins ed., 1952)).
135. NISBETT & ROSS, supra note 127, at 169-71; Nickerson, supra note 127, at
175; Trope & Liberman, supra note 127, at 239-70.
136. GILOVICH, supra note 127, at 33; Burke, supra note 127, at 8; Lord et al.,
supra note 127, at 2098; Nickerson, supra note 127, at 177.
137. CATHERINE FITZMAURICE & KEN PEASE, THE PSYCHOLOGY OF JUDICIAL
SENTENCING 30 (1986); Nickerson, supra note 127, at 179.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
158. Nickerson, supra note 127, at 179. All writers on the general theory of
investigation appear to agree that looking for disconfirming evidence is the preferable
way to structure an investigation if the goal is to maximize accuracy. See Risinger et
al., supra note 13, at 6. As Sir Frances Bacon wrote in 1620, “it is the peculiar and
perpetual error of the human understanding to be more moved and excited by
affirmatives than negatives, whereas it ought duly to be impartial; nay, in establishing
any true axiom, the negative instance is the most powerful.” Id. (quoting FRANCIS
BACON, NOVUM ORGANUM, BOOK I, 109, point 46 (1620), reprinted in 30 GREAT
BOOKS OF THE WESTERN WORLD 110 (Robert M. Hutchins ed., 1952)).
159. See id.
160. See Nickerson, supra note 127, at 179.
161. Burke, supra note 127, at 9-10.
162. GILOVICH, supra note 127, at 36.
163. Id.
164. Id.
165. See id.
166. Nickerson, supra note 127, at 178.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
people tend to interpret data in ways that support their prior beliefs.167
Empirical research demonstrates that people are “incapable of
evaluating the strength of evidence independently of their prior
beliefs.”168 This process of selective information processing has been
studied extensively, and the findings have been replicated in many
contexts.169 In part, the research shows a general tendency to
“overweight positive confirmatory evidence” and “underweight
negative discomfirmatory evidence.”170 In other words, “people
generally require less hypothesis-consistent evidence to accept a
hypothesis than hypothesis-inconsistent evidence to reject a
hypothesis.”171
Social scientists have attributed this phenomenon, at least in part,
to motivational factors.172 When presented with information that
challenges their beliefs, people are motivated to defend those beliefs in
a way that reinforces their initial viewpoint.
177. Id.
178. Id. at 84.
179. Id.
180. Nickerson, supra note 127, at 181; see GILOVICH, supra note 127, at 15-
18.
181. Nickerson, supra note 127, at 181.
182. Id.
183. Id. at 187.
184. Id.; Burke, supra note 127, at 13; Joel D. Lieberman & Jamie Arndt,
Understanding the Limits of Limiting Instructions: Social Psychological Explanations
for the Failures of Instructions to Disregard Pretrial Publicity and Other Inadmissible
Evidence, 6 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 677, 691 (2000).
185. Nickerson, supra note 127, at 187.
186. Id.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
187. Id.
188. Id. at 188.
189. Id. at 187-88.
190. Id. at 188.
191. Id.
192. Id.
193. Id. at 181; Burke, supra note 127, at 13; Lee Ross, Mark R. Lepper &
Michael Hubbard, Perseverance in Self-Perception and Social Perception: Biased
Attributional Processes in the Debriefing Paradigm, 32 J. PERSONALITY & SOC.
PSYCHOL. 880, 882 (1975).
194. Nickerson, supra note 127, at 188.
195. See id.; Burke, supra note 127, at 14.
196. See Daniel S. Medwed, The Zeal Deal: Prosecutorial Resistance to Post-
Conviction Claims of Innocence, 84 B.U. L. REV. 125, 129 (2004).
197. See id. According to Medwed, empirical evidence shows that prosecutors
have consented to DNA tests in less than 50 percent of the cases in which testing later
proved innocence. Id. Medwed has expressed alarm at the “qualitative evidence of
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
200. Scott A. Hawkins & Reid Hastie, Hindsight: Biased Judgments of Past
Events After the Outcomes Are Known, 107 PSYCHOL. BULL. 311, 311 (1990); Ulrich
Hoffrage, Ralph Hertwig & Gerd Gigerenzer, Hindsight Bias: A By-Product of
Knowledge Updating?, 26 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL.: LEARNING, MEMORY &
COGNITION 566, 566 (2000); Erin M. Harley, Keri A. Carlsen & Geoffrey R. Loftus,
The “Saw-It-All-Along” Effect: Demonstrations of Visual Hindsight Bias, 30 J.
EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL.: LEARNING, MEMORY & COGNITION 960, 960 (2004);
FITZMAURICE & PEASE, supra note 137, at 32.
A host of other psychological phenomena are also at work in ways that interfere
with rational assessment of data. Those phenomena include “anchoring effects”
(referring to the fact that estimates people make of points along a continuum are
influenced by preexisting or predetermined but task-irrelevant data); “role effects”
(referring to the fact that asking people to adopt a particular function or perspective
affects the way they seek and perceive information); “conformity effects” (reflecting
that people tend to conform to the perceptions, beliefs, and behavior of others); and
“experimenter effects” (referring to the tendency of subjects in an experiment to alter
their behavior in response to an experimenter’s behavior). For a discussion of these
and related phenomena, see Risinger et al., supra note 13, at 12-21.
201. Harley, Carlsen & Loftus, supra note 200, at 960.
202. Hawkins & Hastie, supra note 200, at 311.
203. Ian Weinstein, Don’t Believe Everything You Think: Cognitive Bias in
Legal Decision Making, 9 CLINICAL L. REV. 783, 800 (2003).
204. Id.
205. Id.
206. Id. at 800-01.
207. Harley, Carlsen & Loftus, supra note 200, at 960.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
208. Id.
209. See Lieberman & Arndt, supra note 184, at 692.
210. Id.
211. See Harley, Carlsen & Loftus, supra note 200, at 960.
212. See Amy L. Bradfield, Gary L. Wells & Elizabeth A. Olson, The
Damaging Effect of Confirming Feedback on the Relation Between Eyewitness
Certainty and Identification Accuracy, 87 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 112, 112-13 (2002).
213. Id. at 113.
214. Id.
215. See id. at 112-13; Gary L. Wells & Amy L. Bradfield, “Good, You
Identified the Suspect”: Feedback to Eyewitnesses Distorts Their Reports of the
Witnessing Experience, 83 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 360, 360-62 (1998).
216. Harley, Carlsen & Loftus, supra note 200, at 966.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
suspect in a live lineup, the witness would likely replace the original,
low-quality memory of the suspect with a clearer image from the
identification procedure.217 Given that the witness really had a very
poor memory of the perpetrator, the witness very well could be
mistaken in the identification.218 But, especially if given confirming
feedback, the witness might then draw on the cleaned-up memory of the
perpetrator together with the confirming feedback to overstate both the
quality of the original viewing conditions and the confidence—the
inevitability—of the ultimate identification.219 In hindsight, the
identification will appear as if it was always inevitable and was based
upon clear memories and an excellent opportunity to view the
suspect.220
Third, a reiteration effect is also linked to hindsight bias.221
Studies have established that confidence in the truth of an assertion
naturally increases if the assertion is repeated.222 This increase in
confidence from repetition is independent of the truth or falsity of the
assertion.223 Accordingly, the longer that police and prosecutors (and
witnesses) live with a conclusion of guilt, repeating the conclusion and
its bases, the more entrenched their conclusion becomes, and the more
obvious it appears that all evidence pointed to that conclusion from the
very beginning.224 As a result, the reiteration effect makes it
increasingly difficult for police and prosecutors to consider alternative
perpetrators or theories of a crime.225
Closely related to hindsight bias is outcome bias.226 Like hindsight
bias, outcome bias involves a process in which people project new
knowledge—outcomes—into the past without any awareness that the
outcome information has influenced their perception of the past.227 But
outcome bias differs from hindsight bias in that outcome bias does not
refer to the effect of outcome information on the judged probability of
an outcome, but to its effect on the evaluations of decision quality.228
In other words, outcome bias does not reflect hindsight judgments about
how likely an event appears to have been, but hindsight judgments
about whether a decision was a good or bad one.229 For example, in a
medical context, subjects are more likely to judge the decision to
perform surgery as a bad decision when they are told that the patient
died during surgery than when told that the same patient survived the
surgery.230 While at a naïve level this might seem intuitively
reasonable, decision analysts teach that, rationally,
criminal cases are quite rare.235 Even where courts find error, they
frequently forgive the error under the harmless error doctrine.236 With
hindsight knowledge that a jury found the defendant guilty beyond a
reasonable doubt, judges are likely to be predisposed to view the
conviction as both inevitable and a sound decision, despite a procedural
or constitutional error in the proceedings.237 To some extent, placing
the burden of proving the harmless nature of an error on the beneficiary
of the error—in criminal cases, requiring the government to prove
harmless error beyond a reasonable doubt238—might be intended to
mitigate the effects of hindsight and outcome biases. Nonetheless,
courts routinely find significant errors harmless,239 and that is partly
because hindsight bias and outcome bias work in tandem with other
values, such as a desire to respect finality and avoid wasteful retrials of
obviously guilty defendants.
All of these cognitive distortions help to explain the reluctance of
the appellate courts in Avery’s case to recognize the flaws in the
eyewitness identification procedures used in his case, or even to
recognize that the evidence against him was weak and his alibi defense
was unusually strong.240 Now, in hindsight, with the benefit of both
greater understanding of the nature of eyewitness identification error
and the knowledge from DNA testing that Avery was actually innocent,
it seems apparent that the eyewitness procedure was flawed, that the
conviction was suspect, and that the case was close from the beginning.
(Of course, in fairness, we cannot overlook the fact that hindsight bias
likely makes Avery’s innocence look all the more apparent to us now
than it might have at the time. But that does not negate the fact that
hindsight bias appeared to impair the judgment of the courts that
reviewed Avery’s case before his exoneration.)
241. See Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 686-87 (1984) (holding that
errors by defense counsel that constitute both deficient performance and prejudice to the
defense violate the Sixth Amendment right to counsel); Brady v. Maryland, 373 U.S.
83, 86-87 (1963) (holding that due process is violated when the government withholds
exculpatory, material evidence).
242. See infra Part II.C.3.b.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
243. See, e.g., Franklin Strier, Making Jury Trials More Truthful, 30 U.C.
DAVIS L. REV. 95, 142-51 (1996) (comparing the truth-seeking strengths of the
adversarial and inquisitorial models). Others have also observed that adversarial
adjudication places a high priority on dispute resolution and party participation, while
inquisitorial systems place a higher priority on accuracy. See Darryl K. Brown, The
Decline of Counsel and the Rise of Accuracy in Criminal Adjudication, 93 CAL. L.
REV. 1585 (2005); Daniel Givelber, The Adversary System and Historical Accuracy:
Can We Do Better? in WRONGLY CONVICTED 253, 253-54 (Saundra D. Westervelt &
John A. Humphrey eds., 2001).
244. Police are also concerned with a more literal form of tunnel vision: in
officer-involved shootings, officers commonly experience a sort of tunnel vision that
manifests itself by blocking out of the officer’s sensory realm some sights and sounds
other than those immediately surrounding the threat, usually a weapon. See WILLIAM
A. GELLER & MICHAEL S. SCOTT, DEADLY FORCE: WHAT WE KNOW 325 (1992). The
officer’s mind concentrates its attention on the immediate threat, to the exclusion of any
possible distractions. Id. This may or may not work to the officer’s advantage,
depending on what else is occurring outside the “tunnel.” Id. This sort of tunnel
vision is an intense and immediate psychological reaction to life-threatening stress. Id.
Accordingly, when discussing tunnel vision with police or reviewing the police
literature on tunnel vision, it is important that one recognize the distinction between the
figurative form with which this Article concerns itself and the literal form associated
with police use of force.
245. See NAT’L RESEARCH COUNCIL, FAIRNESS & EFFECTIVENESS IN POLICING:
THE EVIDENCE 227-28 (2004).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
246. See id.; Andrew D. Leipold, How the Pretrial Process Contributes to
Wrongful Convictions, 42 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 1123, 1159 (2005).
247. See Kenneth Dowler, Media Consumption and Public Attitudes Toward
Crime and Justice: The Relationship Between Fear of Crime, Punitive Attitudes, and
Perceived Police Effectiveness 10 J. CRIM. JUST. & POPULAR CULTURE 109, 111 (2003).
For a broader exploration of the nature and consequences of the police-media
relationship, see JARRET S. LOVELL, GOOD COP/BAD COP: MASS MEDIA AND THE CYCLE
OF POLICE REFORM (2003); Jerome H. Skolnick & Candace McCoy, Police
Accountability and the Media, 1984 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 521, 522.
248. By way of example, Madison (Wis.) Police Department detectives were
widely criticized for disbelieving a rape victim whose account ultimately proved likely
to be truthful. See Patricia Simms & Barry Adams, Abduction Story a Fake, WIS. ST.
J., Apr. 3, 2004, at A4. That criticism reportedly influenced police decisions in a
subsequent missing person case in which police detained a suspect in spite of reasons to
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
believe that the purported victim had concocted the crime, a belief ultimately proven to
be true. Id.
249. See JOHN E. ECK, MANAGING CASE ASSIGNMENTS: THE BURGLARY
INVESTIGATION DECISION MODEL REPLICATION 71-72 (1979).
250. FED. BUREAU OF INVESTIGATION, UNIFORM CRIME REPORTING HANDBOOK
78-81 (2004). Although participation in the Uniform Crime Reporting program is
voluntary, most police agencies do participate and, consequently, are held publicly
accountable to its figures.
251. Id. at 79.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
266. Id. at 111 (reporting survey data revealing that “[t]hose district attorneys
expressing a concern for conviction had, on the average, about twice as much
experience on the job as those who mentioned a concern for justice”).
267. Randolph N. Jonakait, The Ethical Prosecutor’s Misconduct, 23 CRIM. L.
BULL. 550, 551 (1997).
268. Green, supra note 262, at 641; see also Felkenes, supra note 263, at 113
(noting that most prosecutors cannot presume innocence because they believe it is
morally wrong to prosecute a person unless they are personally convinced of guilt);
Bennett L. Gershman, A Moral Standard for the Prosecutor’s Exercise of the Charging
Discretion, 20 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 513, 530 (1993) (arguing that prosecutors must be
morally certain of the defendant’s guilt).
269. See GILOVICH, supra note 127, at 37-44.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
270. Jonakait, supra note 267, at 553; see also Medwed, supra note 196, at
142.
271. Ninety-five percent of all convictions in both state and federal court are
obtained by way of a guilty or no contest plea. U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, STATE COURT
SENTENCING OF CONVICTED FELONS, 2000: STATISTICAL TABLES tbls.4.1 & 4.2 (2003);
U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, FEDERAL CRIMINAL CASE PROCESSING, 2001 tbl.5 (2003). The
trend toward resolving cases through guilty pleas is increasing. Ronald F. Wright,
Trial Distortion and the End of Innocence in Federal Criminal Justice, 154 U. PA. L.
REV. 79, 90 (2005).
272. See Jonakait, supra note 267, at 553.
273. Recent data indicates that 84 percent of federal criminal trials result in
guilty verdicts. See infra note 329.
274. Even with the advent of postconviction DNA testing, the vast majority of
innocent people go undetected, if for no other reason than the simple reality that most
criminal cases have no biological evidence that can yield dispositive DNA test results.
See Gross et al., supra note 2, at 531.
275. See Jonakait, supra note 267, at 554-55.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
276. Id. at 556 (“Since the prosecutor ‘knows’ that the right result is a
conviction, conduct that helps the jury reach a guilty verdict is appropriate.”). Defense
attorneys are in a different position; defense attorneys also know that most of their
clients are guilty, so for them a conviction is not always, or even frequently, viewed as
a miscarriage of justice. Id. at 555.
277. Id. at 559-62.
278. David S. Caudill, Professional Deregulation of Prosecutors: Defense
Contact with Victims, Survivors, and Witnesses in the Era of Victims’ Rights, 17 GEO.
J. LEGAL ETHICS 103, 105 (2003).
279. See F. Andrew Hessick III & Reshma M. Saujani, Plea Bargaining and
Convicting the Innocent: The Role of the Prosecutor, the Defense Counsel, and the
Judge, 16 B.Y.U. J. PUB. L. 189, 211 (2002).
280. Id. at 213.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
281. Keith A. Findley & John Pray, Lessons from the Innocent, WIS. ACAD.
REV., Fall 2001, at 33, 33.
282. Id. at 34; Ronald Earle & Carl Bryan Case, Jr., The Prosecutorial
Mandate: See That Justice Is Done, JUDICATURE, Sept.-Oct. 2002, at 69, 72.
283. Id.
284. Memorandum from Wendy Seffrood to John Pray, Wisconsin Innocence
Project (Nov. 9, 1999) (on file with authors).
285. Id. After his exoneration and release from prison, Ochoa completed his
undergraduate education, and then enrolled at the University of Wisconsin Law School,
where he worked for a year with the Wisconsin Innocence Project, the project that
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
helped secure his freedom. He graduated in May 2006. See Diane Molvig, Chris
Ochoa, 1L, WIS. LAW., May 2004, at 12.
286. See Stephen B. Bright, Counsel for the Poor: The Death Sentence Not for
the Worst Crime but for the Worst Lawyer, 103 YALE L.J. 1835 (1994) (recounting
recurrent inadequacies in attorneys provided for the indigent).
287. Michael McConville & Chester L. Mirsky, Criminal Defense of the Poor
in New York City, 15 N.Y.U. REV. L. & SOC. CHANGE 581, 762 (1986-1987).
288. Id.
289. Id. at 764.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
surveillance video catching the suspect in the act.296 These stages of the
process are then followed by offers of sympathy, understanding, and an
alternative “theme” that minimizes the moral seriousness of the act, and
that are designed to make the “doomed” suspect believe that confessing
is the most attractive option.297
The very notion of a Reid “interrogation,” therefore, expressly
embraces the foundational problems with tunnel vision—a premature
conclusion of guilt, and an unwillingness to consider alternatives.298 In
this context, however, the tunnel vision is not inadvertent, but
deliberate; police are taught that this is the way to advance their
investigation. Cognitive biases are openly encouraged.
This approach is problematic on multiple levels.299 To start, the
conclusion of guilt at this stage is necessarily tentative, and hence
potentially inaccurate. Police typically attempt to obtain confessions
because a confession is powerful evidence,300 and police are most
motivated to seek confessions in cases where they lack other sufficient
296. One study that examined 182 actual police interrogations concluded that
police used trickery involving false evidence roughly 30 percent of the time. See
Elizabeth F. Loftus, Editorial: The Devil in Confessions, 5 PSYCHOL. SCI. IN THE PUB.
INT., at i, i (2004).
297. See Saul M. Kassin, Christine C. Goldstein & Kenneth Savitsky,
Behavioral Confirmation in the Interrogation Room: On the Dangers of Presuming
Guilt, 27 LAW & HUM. BEHAV. 187, 188 (2003).
298. As one experienced police interrogator has put it, “When an interrogator
becomes married to a theory, he risks ignoring all contrary evidence or indications that
he could be wrong.” WARREN D. HOLMES, CRIMINAL INTERROGATION: A MODERN
FORMAT FOR INTERROGATING CRIMINAL SUSPECTS BASED ON THE INTELLECTUAL
APPROACH 4 (2002).
299. In addition to the problems discussed here, critics of the Reid Technique
have identified numerous other concerns, including that it encourages trickery and
deceit, which are illegal in many Western European countries and considered unethical
(even if justified) elsewhere; the tricks and deceit and high-pressure approach can cause
innocent as well as guilty people to confess; pressing suspects to confess may create a
“boomerang effect,” in which suspects who might otherwise confess might become
resistant if they feel they are being rushed or treated unfairly; bluffing can backfire
when police are caught fabricating evidence by a suspect who knows the purported
evidence cannot be true; by cutting off denials and explanations and asking questions
that can be answered in a few words, police risk that the confession reflects more what
they believe has happened than what actually has happened; and suspects who have
been pressured to confess may retain strong feelings of resentment towards police, even
afterwards. MEMON, VRIJ & BULL, supra note 291, at 63-64.
300. Mock jury studies show that confessions are among the most powerful
types of evidence, more persuasive to jurors than other evidence, including such potent
evidence as eyewitness identifications. Kassin, Goldstein & Savitsky, supra note 297,
at 187; Saul M. Kassin & Holly Sukel, Coerced Confessions and the Jury: An
Experimental Test of the “Harmless Error” Rule, 21 LAW & HUM. BEHAV. 27, 27
(1997).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
307. Kassin, Goldstein & Savitsky, supra note 297, at 189; Christian A.
Meissner & Saul M. Kassin, “He’s Guilty!”: Investigator Bias in Judgments of Truth
and Deception, 26 LAW & HUM. BEHAV. 469 (2002).
308. Leif A. Strömwall & Pär Anders Granhag, How to Detect Deception:
Arresting the Beliefs of Police Officers, Prosecutors and Judges, 9 PSYCHOL. CRIME &
LAW 1, 19-36 (2003).
309. Mann, Vrij & Bull, supra note 303, at 144; INBAU ET AL., supra note 290,
at 143-53.
310. Mann, Vrij & Bull, supra note 303, at 142, 144.
311. Id. at 144; DePaulo et al., Cues to Deception, 129 PSYCHOL. BULL. 74
(2003); MEMON, VRIJ & BULL, supra note 291, at 30-31 (stating that a review of more
than 100 studies reveals that “a typical nonverbal response during deception does not
exist”).
312. Mann, Vrij, & Bull, supra note 303, at 139; Saul M. Kassin & C.T.
Fong, “I’m Innocent!”: Effects of Training on Judgments of Truth and Deception in the
Interrogation Room, 23 LAW & HUM. BEHAV. 499, 499 (1999).
313. Mann, Vrij, & Bull, supra note 303, at 144.
314. Kassin, Goldstein & Savitsky, supra note 297, at 189; Meissner & Kassin,
supra note 307, at 478.
315. Saul M. Kassin, Christian A. Meissner & Rebecca J. Norwick, “I’d Know
a False Confession if I Saw One”: A Comparative Study of College Students and Police
Investigators, 29 LAW & HUM. BEHAV. 211, 222 (2005).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
316. Kassin, Goldstein & Savitsky, supra note 297, at 189; see also Leo, supra
note 258, at 91.
317. The case of Evan Zimmerman, a former client of the Wisconsin Innocence
Project, offers an example of questioning of this type that contributed to the murder
conviction of an individual whose conviction was subsequently reversed, and against
whom all charges were eventually dismissed at the prosecutor’s request. State v.
Zimmerman, 2003 WI App 196, ¶¶ 11-20, 266 Wis. 2d. 1003, ¶¶ 11-20, 669 N.W.2d
762, ¶¶ 11-20. In another case, Gary Gauger was convicted of murdering his parents
and sentenced to death based in part on evidence gathered after police persuaded him
that it was hypothetically possible he had committed the double murder during an
alcoholic blackout. See Center on Wrongful Convictions at Northwestern University
School of Law, http://www.law.northwestern.edu/depts/clinic/wrongful/exonerations/
gauger.htm. Gauger was subsequently exonerated after a federal grand jury in
Milwaukee indicted two members of a Wisconsin motorcycle gang known as the
Outlaws for thirty-four acts of racketeering, including the murder of Gauger’s parents.
One of the Outlaws, James Schneider, was caught in a secretly recorded conversation
admitting to the murder of the Gaugers. Id.
318. Other types of responses to questioning are similarly likely to be
interpreted by police as inculpatory if police begin with a presumption of guilt. In the
Zimmerman case, for example, police told Zimmerman (falsely) that they had an
eyewitness who saw him with the victim on the night of her murder. Zimmerman, 2003
WI App 196, ¶ 11. According to one detective, Zimmerman responded by saying:
“Nobody saw us.” Transcript of Trial at 166, State v. Zimmerman, No. 2001CF63
(Circuit Court Branch 2, Eau Claire County, May 16, 2001). A second detective
remembered Zimmerman as saying, “Who saw me?” Id. at 70. The detectives
interpreted Zimmerman’s response as an incriminating admission. On cross-
examination, the detectives conceded that, in fact, Zimmerman actually said, “Nobody
saw us because we weren’t together.” Id. at 172. They nonetheless minimized the
significance of the latter part of that statement, because they insisted that there was a
suspicious “pause” between the third and fourth words of that sentence. Id. at 173.
The detectives’ testimony raises significant questions about what in fact Zimmerman
said, and whether there was any real pause, or what any such pause, if it existed, might
have signified. To officers who presumed guilt, confirmation bias inevitably led them
to see a facially exculpatory statement as an incriminating response.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
324. Id.
325. Leo, supra note 258, at 96; see also Kassin & Gudjonsson, supra note
100, at 42 (noting that “laboratory experiments have . . . shown that behavioral
confirmation is the outcome of a three-step chain of events in which (a) a perceiver
forms a belief about a target person; (b) the perceiver unwittingly behaves toward that
person in a manner that conforms to that belief; and (c) the target responds in turn,
often behaving in ways that support the perceivers belief . . ..”).
326. Leo, supra note 258, at 96. For a discussion of how this “interviewer
bias” can distort the results of an interview or interrogation, see STEPHEN J. CECI &
MAGGIE BRUCK, JEOPARDY IN THE COURTROOM: A SCIENTIFIC ANALYSIS OF CHILDREN’S
TESTIMONY 79-80, 87-92 (1995).
327. See Michael J. Saks & D. Michael Risinger, Baserates, the Presumption
of Guilt, Admissibility Rulings, and Erroneous Convictions, 2003 MICH. ST. L. REV.
1051, 1056; see also HERBERT L. PACKER, THE LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL SANCTION 160
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
(1968) (“The presumption of guilt is what makes it possible for the system to deal
efficiently with large numbers, as the Crime Control Model demands.”); Felkenes,
supra note 263, at 112 (noting that surveys of prosecutors reveal that more than half do
not presume that a person is innocent until proven guilty, and that “[m]any believe that
once an accused reaches the trial stage, his guilt has been determined by the screening
processes of the police and prosecutor”); Daniel Givelber, Meaningless Acquittals,
Meaningful Convictions: Do We Reliably Acquit the Innocent?, 49 RUTGERS L. REV.
1317, 1326 (1997) (“The presumption of guilt, not the presumption of innocence,
permeates the criminal adjudicatory system.”).
328. Saks & Risinger, supra note 327, at 1062 (citing Thomas M. Ostrom,
Carol Werner & Michael J. Saks, An Integration Theory Analysis of Jurors’
Presumptions of Guilt or Innocence, 36 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 436 (1978)).
Risinger and Saks have gone on to observe that “[s]ome evidence exists to suggest that
jurors set their probabilities lower than they think they do,” and that jurors might
actually start with “assumptions close to zero (innocence), but to which they attach[]
very little weight, so that the presumption of innocence [is] abandoned as soon as the
first piece of inculpatory evidence [is] presented.” Id. As Professor Daniel Givelber
has explained, “Jurors apparently do not listen, evaluate and deliberate on the
assumption that the defendant is innocent unless the government proves otherwise.
Rather, jurors take the logical position that they are in equipoise concerning the
defendant’s guilt and will await the presentation of evidence before reaching a verdict.”
Givelber, supra note 327, at 1372.
329. Saks & Risinger, supra note 327, at 1060 n.33 (citing U.S. DEP’T OF
JUSTICE, SOURCEBOOK OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE STATISTICS 2001 tbl.5.17 (2002) (showing
the disposition of cases terminated in U.S. District Courts in the fiscal year 2000)).
330. Ronald F. Wright, Trial Distortion and the End of Innocence in Federal
Criminal Justice, 154 U. PA. L. REV. 79, 103 (2005).
331. See Steve Sheppard, The Metamorphoses of Reasonable Doubt: How
Changes in the Burden of Proof Have Weakened the Presumption of Innocence, 78
NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1165, 1170 (2003) (arguing that the proof required to convict has
shifted from a “certainty” standard to a much weaker one, in which juries are
instructed to acquit only if they can identify reasonable doubts, defined as specific and
articulable doubts).
332. See Lawrence M. Solan, Refocusing the Burden of Proof in Criminal
Cases: Some Doubt About Reasonable Doubt, 78 TEX. L. REV. 105 (1999) (finding
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
Aside from the possibility that these features of the trial process
are ineffectual at neutralizing tunnel vision, other features of the trial
experience expressly limit the ability to consider the possibility that
anyone other than the accused might have committed the crime, thereby
making some aspects of tunnel vision prescriptive. Regardless of how
or whether this is justified by other values (such as interests in
convicting the guilty or in efficiency and conservation of judicial
resources), rules that limit the availability or admissibility of
exculpatory evidence inevitably increase the risk of convicting the
innocent.333 A few examples of rules that directly limit the ability to
explore alternative case theories follow.
inconsistency and confusion among jurors, including that some jurors understand the
reasonable doubt standard to be less rigorous than civil standards, depending on the
wording of the instruction); Elisabeth Stoffelmayr & Shari Seidman Diamond, The
Conflict Between Precision and Flexibility in Explaining “Beyond a Reasonable
Doubt,” 6 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 769, 774-78 (2000) (discussing empirical studies
on the effect of the “beyond a reasonable doubt” standard).
333. For example, Professor Andrew Leipold has noted that rules that limit
pretrial release on bail, tolerate precharging delay, or minimize government disclosure
obligations, among others, limit the ability of criminal defendants to develop
exonerating evidence and hence contribute to wrongful convictions. Leipold, supra
note 246, at 1163. Leipold acknowledges that the “policy considerations that lead
courts and legislatures to accept the risks” of some of these procedures “are
legitimate,” but argues that the cost in terms of wrongful convictions must be
considered in assessing the value of such rules. Id. at 1163. Some evidence-limiting
rules are derived from a concern for reliability. Excluding “unreliable” defense
evidence (hearsay, for example) can indeed be justified by concern about the reliability
of the outcome of a trial. But it can be justified only if one is willing to accept that,
while excluding such evidence will on balance enhance the odds of finding the “truth,”
it will do so at the cost of prohibiting some innocent people from proving their
innocence. In a system where the risks of error are apportioned roughly equally
between the two opposing parties in a case (as in our civil system), such rules that
enhance “truth” in the aggregate make perfect sense. But in a system that ostensibly
places all of the risk of error on the government (as does the criminal justice system),
rules that limit evidence that in some cases might prove innocence are more
problematic. See Katherine Goldwasser, Vindicating the Right to Trial by Jury and the
Requirement of Proof Beyond a Reasonable Doubt: A Critique of the Conventional
Wisdom About Excluding Defense Evidence, 86 GEO. L.J. 621 (1998).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
the fact that the alternative perpetrator may have made threats
against the victim, or was seen with blood on his hands in the
vicinity of the crime, or had assaulted the victim two weeks
before the crime, have been deemed insufficient in the
aberrant . . . doctrine is probably still good law in Texas, Alabama and Kansas.”
McCord, supra note 336, at 927 (citing Erwin v. State, 729 S.W.2d 709, 714-15 (Tex.
Crim. App. 1987); Coral v. State, 628 So. 2d 954, 983 (Ala. Crim. App. 1992); and
State v. Peckham, 875 P.2d 257, 266 (Kan. 1994) (footnotes omitted)).
338. People v. Green, 609 P.2d 468, 480 (Cal. 1980) (citations omitted).
339. Santana v. State, 510 S.E.2d 916, 917 (Ga. Ct. App. 1999) (quoting
Klinect v. State, 501 S.E.2d 810, 814 (Ga. Ct. App. 1998)).
340. State v. Williams, 593 N.W.2d 227, 234 (Minn. 1999).
341. Some courts permit alternative perpetrator evidence where there is “direct
or circumstantial evidence linking the third person to the actual perpetration of the
crime.” Pyles v. State, 947 S.W.2d 754, 757 (Ark. 1997) (quoting People v. Kaurish,
802 P.2d 278, 295-96 (Cal. 1990)). Even in those cases, however, the circumstantial
evidence must directly link the alternative suspect to the offense.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
342. Ellen Yankiver Suni, Who Stole the Cookie from the Cookie Jar?: The
Law and Ethics of Shifting Blame in Criminal Cases, 68 FORDHAM L. REV. 1643, 1677
(2000) (citing State v. Robinson, 628 A.3d 664, 667 (Me. 1993); State v. Luna, 378
N.W.2d 229, 232 (S.D. 1985); State v. Stokes, 638 S.W.2d 7151, 723 (Mo. 1982)
(footnotes omitted)).
343. FED. R. EVID. 804(a) & (b)(3).
344. FED. R. EVID. 804(b)(3).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
surveys of judges, prosecutors, and defense lawyers); Peter F. Nardulli, The Societal
Cost of the Exclusionary Rule: An Empirical Assessment, 1983 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J.
585, 594, 595 tbl.2, 596, 597 tbl.7 (basing results on analysis of nearly 8000 trial court
files).
348. See supra note 10.
349. Manson v. Brathwaite, 432 U.S. 98, 111 (1977)
350. Id. at 111, 114; Neil v. Biggers, 409 U.S. 188, 199-200 (1972).
351. Those factors, according to the Supreme Court, include
the opportunity of the witness to view the criminal at the time of the crime,
the witness’ degree of attention, the accuracy of the witness’ prior
description of the criminal, the level of certainty demonstrated by the
witness at the confrontation, and the length of time between the crime and
the confrontation.
Biggers, 409 U.S. at 199-200. Most of those factors, however, are subjective and
reported by the witness, and hence subject to influence by the suggestiveness of the
procedure itself. See Benjamin E. Rosenberg, Rethinking the Right to Due Process in
Connection with Pretrial Identification Procedures: An Analysis and a Proposal, 79 KY.
L.J. 259, 275 (1991); Siegfried Ludwig Sporer, Eyewitness Identification Accuracy,
Confidence, and Decision Times in Simultaneous and Sequential Lineups, 78 J.
APPLIED PSYCHOL. 22, 23 (1998); Nancy Steblay et al., Eyewitness Accuracy Rates in
Police Showup and Lineup Presentations: A Meta-Analytic Comparison, 27 L. & HUM.
BEHAV. 523 (2003); Wells & Bradfield, supra note 215, at 360-76; Gary L. Wells &
Donna M. Murray, What Can Psychology Say About the Neil v. Biggers Criteria for
Judging Eyewitness Accuracy?, 68 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 347 (1983).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
352. See, e.g., State v. Dubose, 2005 WI 126, 285 Wis. 2d 143, 699 N.W.2d
582; Commonwealth v. Johnson, 650 N.E.2d 1257, 1260 (Mass. 1995); People v.
Adams, 423 N.E.2d 379 (N.Y. 1981).
353. See Herrera v. Collins, 506 U.S. 390 (1993). In Herrera, the Court held
that, except perhaps in the most extraordinary circumstances, a freestanding claim of
actual innocence, without an accompanying claim of procedural error, does not raise a
constitutional due process issue. Id. at 399.
354. 443 U.S. 307 (1979).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
359. See id. at 1171 (noting that courts increasingly rely on a “guilt-based
approach” to harmless error, rather than an “effect-on-the-verdict approach”); Garrett,
supra note 237, at 58-60.
360. Garrett, supra note 237, at 59.
361. Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 687 (1984).
362. Brady v. Maryland, 373 U.S. 83, 87 (1963).
363. Stephanos Bibas, The Psychology of Hindsight and After-the-Fact Review
of Ineffective Assistance of Counsel, 2004 UTAH L. REV. 1, 2.
364. See Bright, supra note 286, at 1843-44, 1846.
365. Judge Richard Posner has observed: “I can confirm from my own
experience as a judge that indigent defendants are generally rather poorly represented.”
Richard A. Posner, The Cost of Rights: Implications for Central and Eastern Europe—
and for the United States, 32 TULSA L.J. 1, 14 (1996).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
366. Richard Klein, The Emperor Gideon Has No Clothes: The Empty Promise
of the Constitutional Right to Effective Assistance of Counsel, 13 HASTINGS CONST.
L.Q. 625, 632 (1986).
367. See Jeffrey L. Kirchmeier, Drink, Drugs, and Drowsiness: The
Constitutional Right to Effective Assistance of Counsel and the Strickland Prejudice
Requirement, 75 NEB. L. REV. 425 (1996); Bright, supra note 286, at 1843.
368. 373 U.S. 83, 87 (1963).
369. A “reasonable probability” is a “probability sufficient to undermine
confidence in the outcome.” United States v. Bagley, 473 U.S. 667, 682 (1985)
(quoting Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 694 (1984)).
370. Stephanos Bibas, The Story of Brady v. Maryland: From Adversarial
Gamesmanship Toward The Search for Innocence?, in CRIMINAL PROCEDURE STORIES
(Carol Steiker ed., 2005) (“Adversarial-minded prosecutors are poorly suited to do that
job.”); Givelber, supra note 327, at 1389. Givelber has noted that prosecutors cannot
reasonably be expected to assess materiality because:
[o]nly the unusual prosecutor will believe: (a) the defendant is guilty; (b)
the jury will so find in light of all the evidence in the prosecutor’s
possession; and (c) the potentially exculpatory but undisclosed evidence in
the prosecutor’s possession is material in the sense that there is a reasonable
probability that it will change the outcome of the case.
Id.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
not know about them; violations can be litigated only if the defense
learns of the nondisclosed information through some fortuity that
usually occurs sometime after trial.371 Moreover, the Supreme Court
has held that the Brady duty does not apply, at least regarding
exculpatory impeachment evidence, unless the defendant goes to trial.372
Yet 95 percent of all cases are resolved by a guilty or no contest plea.373
And, as the Brady dissenters pointed out, the Brady test oddly imposes
a retrospective analysis on decisions that must be made prospectively,
pretrial.374 Brady asks reviewing courts to determine after trial whether
the withheld evidence might have made a difference to the outcome of
the trial in light of all evidence presented at trial.375 Yet the prosecutor
must determine the materiality of the evidence prior to trial, before
hearing any of the trial evidence or exposure to the defense presented at
trial.376 Not surprisingly, empirical evidence confirms what these
considerations suggest: Brady claims are rarely successful. An analysis
of 210 Brady and related claims in cases decided in 2004 found that 83
percent were unsuccessful.377
For these reasons, Brady and other such burden-shifting doctrines
should be reexamined.378 The dissenters in United States v. Bagley
might have had it right when they insisted that the prosecution should
be required to turn over to the defense all evidence “that might
reasonably be considered favorable to the defendant’s case,” not just
evidence the prosecutor deems “material.”379 Given the pressures of
Id. (quoting Daniel J. Capra, Access to Exculpatory Evidence: Avoiding the Agurs
Problems of Prosecutorial Discretion and Retrospective Review, 53 FORDHAM L. REV.
391, 428 (1984)).
380. See INNOCENCE COMM’N FOR VA., supra note 20, at 95 (noting the need to
balance a prisoner’s interest in access to a forum to test the fundamental correctness of
his conviction against the government’s “interest in the finality of its criminal justice
proceedings”).
381. For a thorough summary and analysis of the barriers to obtaining
postconviction relief on a claim of actual innocence, see Daniel S. Medwed, Up the
River without a Procedure: Innocent Prisoners and Newly Discovered Non-DNA
Evidence in State Courts, 47 ARIZ. L. REV. 655 (2005). Medwed has argued that to
protect the rights of innocent defendants to establish their innocence, states should:
(1) refashion their procedures to minimize the chance newly discovered
non-DNA evidence claims will be rejected due solely to procedural default;
(2) construct each remedy so as to enhance the likelihood that viable claims
will be heard in open court in front of an unbiased judge; and (3) utilize a
de novo standard of review for appellate courts in assessing summary
denials of motions for post-trial relief based on newly discovered evidence,
i.e., cases where the trial court declines to hold an evidentiary hearing on
the merits of an innocence claim prior to rejecting it.
Id. at 661.
382. See James S. Liebman, An “Effective Death Penalty”? AEDPA and Error
Detection in Capital Cases, 67 BROOK. L. REV. 411, 416 (2001); Lyn S. Entzeroth,
Struggling for Federal Judicial Review of Successive Claims of Innocence: A Study of
How Federal Courts Wrestled with the AEDPA to Provide Individuals Convicted of
Non-Existent Crimes with Habeas Corpus Review, 60 U. MIAMI L. REV. 75 (2005).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
constraints are beyond the scope of this Article. For our purposes, the
point is simple: severe limitations on considering innocence in
postconviction procedures further prescribe tunnel vision. Whether or
not justified by countervailing interests in finality, they impose a cost
on the wrongly convicted that must be included in an assessment of
tunnel vision in the criminal justice system.
4. CONCLUSION
A. Doctrinal Reform
383. Others have made compelling arguments that the Brady and Strickland
doctrines require repair. See supra notes 370-79 and accompanying text.
384. See supra Part II.C.2.a.
385. “Curiously, although this body of law raises basic issues of both criminal
and evidence law, it has remained virtually unexplored by scholars and has been rarely
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
Both rules have been defended on the basis that such alternate-
suspect evidence is “too easily fabricated falsely for the purpose of
deceiving.”387 Perhaps more significantly, the direct connection
doctrine in particular is defended by the contention that, unless
alternate-perpetrator evidence is strong and direct, it is likely to distract
and confuse the jury, waste judicial resources, and invite jury
speculation.388 While these are legitimate and weighty concerns as a
general matter, it is far from clear why they should apply with
particular force when the defense offers evidence of an alternate
suspect. Commenting on the special burden imposed by such rules on
the admissibility of exculpatory evidence offered by the accused,
Professor James Joseph Duane has observed: “This asymmetry in favor
of the Government is logically and morally indefensible, and flies in the
face of the constitutional imperative that ‘[i]n the administration of
criminal justice, our society imposes almost the entire risk of error
upon itself.’”389
subjected to any significant scrutiny by the very courts that promulgate and rely upon
it.” McCord, supra note 336, at 919. Indeed, until recently, McCord’s 1996
Tennessee Law Review article stood as one of the only scholarly pieces that analyzed
the direct connection doctrine. Recently, Ellen Suni has added a significant article to
that literature. See Suni, supra note 342.
386. The statement against penal interests exception to the hearsay rule has
received somewhat more scholarly attention, much of it critical of the asymmetry
between evidence offered by a criminal defendant, and evidence offered by the State or
for purposes other than to exculpate the criminally accused. See, e.g., James Joseph
Duane, The Proposed Amendments to Federal Rules of Evidence 608(b) and 804(b)(3):
Two Great Ideas that Don’t Go Far Enough, 209 F.R.D. 235 (2002) (criticizing the
asymmetry); Peter W. Tague, Perils of the Rulemaking Process: The Development,
Application, and Unconstitutionality of Rule 804(b)(3)’s Penal Interest Exception, 69
GEO L. J. 851, 978-1011 (1981) (arguing that the corroboration requirement is
unjustified, unbalanced, and unconstitutional); Glen Weissenberger, Federal Rule of
Evidence 804: Admissible Hearsay from an Unavailable Declarant, 55 U. CIN. L. REV.
1079, 1113-28 (1987). But see John P. Cronan, Do Statements Against Interests Exist?
A Critique of the Reliability of Federal Rule of Evidence 804(b)(3) and a Proposed
Reformulation, 33 SETON HALL L. REV. 1, 14-24 (2002) (employing the “rational actor
theory” to criticize the very notion that people rationally make statements against
interest, and in particular arguing that statements against penal interest are suspect).
387. McCord, supra note 336, at 925, 930 (quoting State v. May, 15 N.C. (1
Dev.) 328, 333 (1833)); see also FED. R. EVID. 804 advisory committee’s note.
388. McCord, supra note 336, at 930
389. Duane, supra note 386, at 244 (quoting Addington v. Texas, 441 U.S.
418, 423-24 (1979)). Duane also points out that, not only is the rule asymmetric in that
it requires corroboration when a defendant offers a statement against penal interest, and
not when the government offers that same statement, but it is also asymmetric in the
sense that no similar corroboration rule exists when either party in a civil law suit
offers that statement, or when anyone offers a statement that might tend to subject the
declarant to only civil liability, but not also criminal liability. Id. at 245-49. In 2003,
after several years of work, the Judicial Conference Advisory Committee on Evidence
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
Rules proposed amendments to the Federal Rules of Evidence that would have
addressed some of this asymmetry, not by eliminating the corroboration requirement,
but by adding a corresponding requirement that statements against penal interest offered
against the accused (that is, by the Government) must be “supported by particularized
guarantees of trustworthiness.” Daniel J. Capra, Amending the Hearsay Exception for
Declarations Against Penal Interest in the Wake of Crawford, 105 COLUM. L. REV.
2409, 2433 (2005). That language was proposed to satisfy the confrontation clause
requirements imposed by Ohio v. Roberts, 448 U.S. 56 (1980). Capra, supra, at 2439-
40. The amendments were forwarded to the Supreme Court, but before the
amendments were adopted the Court decided Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36
(2004). Crawford changed the Court’s confrontation clause jurisprudence, and those
changes scuttled the proposed amendments. Capra, supra, at 2426.
390. 5 JOHN H. WIGMORE, EVIDENCE IN TRIALS AT COMMON LAW § 1477, at
358-59 (Chadbourn ed. 1974); see also CHARLES T. MCCORMICK, MCCORMICK ON
EVIDENCE § 278, at 822-23 (Edward W. Cleary ed., 3d ed. 1984) (“Wigmore rejects
the argument of the danger of perjury since the danger is one that attends all human
testimony . . . .”); Donnelly v. United States, 228 U.S. 243, 277-78 (1913) (Holmes,
J., dissenting) (“[N]o other statement is so much against interest as a confession of
murder; it is far more calculated to convince than dying declarations, which would be
let in to hang a man . . . .”). Justice Holmes, however, nonetheless went on to
advocate for a corroboration requirement for statements against penal interest offered
by a criminal defendant. Id. at 278.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
391. See Daubert v. Merrill Dow Pharms., Inc., 509 U.S. 579, 597 (1993).
392. ROB WARDEN, THE SNITCH SYSTEM: HOW INCENTIVISED WITNESSES PUT
38 INNOCENT AMERICANS ON DEATH ROW (2002), available at
http://www.law.northwestern.edu/depts/clinic/wrongful/documents/Snitch.htm.
393. For a description of how jailhouse snitches manufacture their evidence,
see Steven Mills & Ken Armstrong, The Inside Informant, CHI. TRIB., Nov. 16, 1999,
at A1.
394. Scheck, Neufeld & Dwyer’s analysis of the first sixty-two DNA
exonerations found that jailhouse snitch testimony played a part in 21 percent of the
cases. SCHECK ET AL., supra note 5, at 156. A more recent analysis of the first 111
cases in which a person sentenced to death was released based on evidence of innocence
found that jailhouse snitch testimony was the leading cause of the wrongful convictions
in that category of cases, present in 45.9 percent of the death row exonerations.
NORTHWESTERN UNIV. SCH. OF LAW, CENTER ON WRONGFUL CONVICTIONS, THE
SNITCH SYSTEM: HOW SNITCH TESTIMONY SENT RANDY STEIDL AND OTHER INNOCENT
AMERICANS TO DEATH ROW 3 (2004-2005), available at
http://www.law.northwestern.edu/wrongfulconvictions/documents/SnitchSystemBooklet
.pdf.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
395. The case of Wilton Dedge, who spent twenty-two years in prison for a
rape that DNA testing eventually proved he did not commit, is illustrative. See
Editorial, It’s Time to Right the Wrong, THE LEDGER (Lakeland, Fla.), Mar. 29, 2005.
The State’s case against Dedge was suspect from the beginning. Id. The primary
evidence against Dedge included an eyewitness identification and microscopic hair
comparison testimony. Id. But the victim originally said her attacker was about six
feet tall, 160 pounds and had a receding hairline, while Dedge was only five-foot-six,
weighed 125 pounds, and had a full head of hair. Id. Moreover, Dedge, who had no
criminal record, had eight witnesses who placed him at work at the time of the rape.
Id. After Dedge’s first conviction was reversed on appeal, prosecutors responded by
presenting, at his second trial, the testimony of a seven-time convicted felon who said
Dedge confessed to him while the two were locked up together. Id. The snitch
received a significant reduction in his sentence in return for his testimony. Id. Dedge
was convicted again, and remained in prison until DNA testing finally proved his
innocence. Id.; see also Innocence Project, Case Profiles: Wilton Dedge,
http://www.innocenceproject.org/case/display_profile.php?id=149 (last visited Mar.
28, 2006).
396. Numerous studies and governmental inquiries have proposed limitations
on jailhouse snitch or informer testimony. See, e.g., STATE OF ILL., supra note 16, at
119-24; Province of Manitoba, supra note 19, at 6-7. Little has been done, however,
to implement such recommendations. Several courts have also attempted to remedy the
problem, but their attempts have been quickly reversed. See, e.g., Dodd v. State, No.
F-97-26 (Okla. Crim. App. July 22, 1999) (imposing a pretrial “reliability” hearing to
screen out unreliable snitch testimony), reh’g granted vacating and withdrawing
opinion, No. F-97-26 (Okla. Crim. App. Oct. 6, 1999), new opinion issued in 2000
OK CR 2, ¶ 2, 993 P.2d 778, 784 (requiring discovery related to snitches, but no
“reliability hearings”); United States v. Singleton, 144 F.3d 1343, 1346 (10th Cir.
1998) (holding that, under 18 U.S.C. § 201(c)(2), no party, including the government,
can offer incentivized testimony), rev’d en banc, United States v. Singleton, 165 F.2d
1297 (10th Cir. 1999) (holding that the government is exempt from the prohibition
against offering inducements to witnesses).
397. FED. R. EVID. 403 provides that relevant evidence “may be excluded if its
probative value is substantially outweighed by the danger of unfair prejudice, confusion
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
406. Indeed, Professor Katherine Goldwasser has argued that, because of our
constitutional preference for erring on the side of acquittal rather than wrongful
conviction, Rule 403 balancing ought not be used to exclude exculpatory defense
evidence, at least without exceptionally powerful factors that overwhelm the probative
value of the evidence. Goldwasser, supra note 333.
407. See, e.g., State v. Denny, 120 Wis. 2d. 614, 623, 357 N.W.2d 12, 17
(1984) (“[E]vidence that simply affords a possible ground of suspicion against another
person should not be admissible. Otherwise, a defendant could conceivably produce
evidence tending to show that hundreds of other persons had some motive or animus
against the deceased—degenerating the proceedings into a trial of collateral issues.”).
408. McCord has identified eight jurisdictions that “seem to rely on the
standard balancing of probative value versus unfair prejudice (or other relevancy
determinations),” three that add a “capable-of-raising-a-reasonable-doubt approach”
without equating it to the direct connection doctrine, and one that directly rejects the
direct connection doctrine “as setting too high a standard.” McCord, supra note 336,
at 937-38.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
On the other hand, it might be that the direct connection rule has
the opposite effect on investigator and prosecutor decision-making.
That is, investigators and prosecutors might feel more confident
exploring alternate suspects knowing that the rule makes it unlikely that
defendants will be permitted to introduce third-party perpetrator
evidence detrimental to the case against the primary suspect. Further
research would be useful to better understand the actual effect of the
rule on investigative decision-making.
In either event, there might be “significant systemic benefits” to
eliminating the direct connection doctrine “even in cases of relatively
strong evidence of guilt and weak alternative perpetrator showings.”413
As Suni has explained,
the Court addressed South Carolina’s particularly draconian version of the direct
connection doctrine. 126 S. Ct. 1727 (2006). In Holmes, the South Carolina Supreme
Court had held that a defendant may not introduce proof of third-party guilt if the
prosecution had introduced forensic evidence that, if believed, strongly supported a
guilty verdict. Id. at 1730. While acknowledging the widely accepted general
limitations on third-party-perpetrator evidence, which the U.S. Supreme Court
characterized as a specific application of the Rule 403 balancing test, the Court held
that South Carolina’s variation of the rule went too far and violated the defendant’s
constitutional right to present a defense. Id. at 1734-35. The Court noted that, under
South Carolina’s rule, if the prosecution appeared to have a strong case, no third-party
guilt evidence, no matter how powerful or direct, was admissible. Id. This, the Court
said, “does not rationally serve the end that the [direct connection doctrine was]
designed to promote, i.e., to focus the trial on the central issues by excluding evidence
that has only a very weak logical connection to the central issues.” Id. at 1734. The
Court was also troubled by the asymmetry created by the South Carolina rule: “The
rule applied in this case is no more logical than its converse would be, i.e., a rule
barring the prosecution from introducing evidence of a defendant’s guilt if the
defendant is able to proffer, at a pretrial hearing, evidence that, if believed, strongly
supports a verdict of not guilty.” Id. at 1734-35.
419. Oldfather, supra note 357, at 439-40, 449-66.
420. Id. at 459.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
421. Id.
422. Id. at 451.
423. Id.
424. Id. at 454-56.
425. Id. at 457. In this way, Oldfather has argued that a transcript “facilitates
a mode of thinking that is more consistent with the ideal of legal thought.” Id. at 456.
426. Id. at 459-63.
427. Id. at 463-66.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
claims in cases where innocence and guilt are the central concern, at
least where the evidence relied upon to convict is a type that appellate
courts are institutionally capable of reviewing. Oldfather has noted
that, while courts “almost never reverse convictions” on sufficiency
grounds in criminal cases,428 they take a much more active role in
reviewing sufficiency of the evidence in civil cases. An analysis of 208
cases in which a court addressed challenges to the sufficiency of the
evidence to support a jury verdict in civil cases revealed that courts
found the evidence insufficient in at least one sense in 102, or 49
percent, of the cases.429 Other empirical data is consistent with that
finding.430 Logically, one would expect to see greater scrutiny of facts
in criminal cases than civil cases. In civil cases, facts are decided by
the preponderance of the evidence, so significantly less evidence should
be required to support a factual determination than in criminal cases,
where proof must be established beyond a reasonable doubt. In
criminal cases, the higher burden of proof places the risk of error on
the government, while in civil cases the preponderance standard
apportions the risk of error roughly equally between the litigants.
While one would therefore expect to see greater involvement in
reviewing sufficiency of the evidence in criminal cases, and less in civil
cases, the data reveal just the opposite: “The problem is that the courts
have their allocation of resources backwards.”431
Appellate standards of review therefore should be reevaluated, at
least concerning issues related to the reliability of the guilt
determination. Oldfather has suggested that appellate review should be
recalibrated to incorporate the notion of institutional competence at the
case-by-case level, so that the degree to which an appellate court
reviews the facts would turn in part in each case on the court’s
assessment of its institutional capacity to review the type of factual
determination or evidence at issue.432 Oldfather has suggested that
courts should have to consider in each case “whether the nature of a
particular sort of evidence in a particular case is such that the appellate
433. Id. at 509. Appellate courts in some states have historically engaged in
more aggressive review of some sufficiency-of-the-evidence claims in criminal cases,
particularly those related to circumstantial evidence. See, e.g., Stephen L. Richards,
Reasonable Doubt Redux: The Return of Substantive Criminal Appellate Review in
Illinois, 34 J. MARSHALL L. REV. 495, 515-21 (2000-2001) (tracing the historical
practice in Illinois of reviewing sufficiency-of-the-evidence claims in cases that turn on
particular types of evidence, including circumstantial evidence); Elizabeth A. Ryan,
The 13th Juror: Re-evaluating the Need for a Factual Sufficiency Review in Criminal
Cases, 37 TEX. TECH. L. REV. 1291, 1294 (2005) (criticizing a Texas law providing for
more searching review of factual sufficiency claims than required by Jackson v.
Virginia).
434. See Rosenberg & Rosenberg, supra note 404, at 1416 (arguing that
appellate courts should review evidence independently for reasonable hypotheses of
innocence in circumstantial evidence cases, given that in such cases “guilt is
based . . . on inferences from the evidence, and the [appellate] court is in as good, if
not better, position to assess the rationality of these inferences and whether they
establish guilt beyond a reasonable doubt”).
435. Risinger, supra note 356, at 1331-33.
436. Id. at 1332.
437. See JAMES J. FYFE ET AL., POLICE ADMINISTRATION 467-78 (5th ed. 1997).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
438. See John F. Easton & Walter Mayer, The Rights of Parties and Civil
Litigants in an NTSB Investigation, 68 J. AIR L. & COM. 205, 214-17 (2003).
439. Most inquiries into to the problem of wrongful convictions, and
specifically to tunnel vision, call for better education of police and prosecutors. The
Illinois Commission on Capital Punishment, for example, specifically recommended
that police investigators should receive periodic training in the following areas: (1) the
risks of false testimony by in-custody informants (“jailhouse snitches”), (2) the risks of
false testimony by accomplice witnesses, (3) the dangers of tunnel vision or
confirmatory bias, (4) the risks of wrongful convictions in homicide cases, (5) police
investigative and interrogation methods, (6) police investigating and reporting of
exculpatory evidence, (7) forensic evidence, and (8) the risks of false confessions.
STATE OF ILL., supra note 16, at 40; see also ABA CRIMINAL JUSTICE SECTION, AD HOC
INNOCENCE COMM. TO ENSURE THE INTEGRITY OF THE CRIMINAL PROCESS, ACHIEVING
JUSTICE: FREEING THE INNOCENT, CONVICTING THE GUILTY 95 (Paul Giannelli &
Myrna Raeder eds., 2006) [hereinafter ABA REPORT] (calling for police training that
includes “presentation and discussion of actual cases where illegal, unethical, or
unprofessional behavior led to the arrest, prosecution, or conviction of an innocent
person, thus compromising public safety”); MINISTRY OF THE ATTORNEY GEN. OF ONT.,
REPORT OF THE KAUFMAN COMMISSION ON PROCEEDINGS INVOLVING GUY PAUL MORIN
26 (2005), available at http://www.attorneygeneral.jus.gov.on.ca/english/about/
pubs/morin/morin_recom.pdf (recommending training about tunnel vision); Burke,
supra note 127 (arguing for increased education for prosecutors about cognitive biases);
Medwed, supra note 196, at 170 (arguing for better education to help prosecutors
“transform[] the theoretical underpinnings of their ethical obligations to do justice in the
postconviction sphere into a reality of everyday practice”); Fisher, supra note 262, at
201-02 (calling for a better definition of and education about prosecutors’ “quasi-
judicial role”); Richard A. Leo, False Confessions: Causes, Consequences, and
Solutions, in WRONGLY CONVICTED 36, 48 (Saundra D. Westervelt & John A.
Humphrey eds., 2001) (calling for better training to help police understand the
psychology of interrogation and suspect decision-making, and improve the ability of
police to recognize and prevent false confessions).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
440. Bibas, supra note 363, at 5; Richard M. Kurtz & Sol L. Garfield, Illusory
Correlation: A Further Exploration of Chapman’s Paradigm, 46 J. CONSULTING &
CLINICAL PSYCHOL. 1009 (1978); Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky, Subjective
Probability: A Judgment of Representativeness, in JUDGMENT UNDER UNCERTAINTY:
HEURISTICS AND BIASES 32 (Daniel Kahneman et al. eds., 1982).
441. Hawkins & Hastie, supra note 200, at 312; Harley, Carlsen & Loftus,
supra note 200, at 960, 963.
442. Hawkins & Hastie, supra note 200, at 314.
443. Id. at 318 (citing Hal R. Arkes et al., Eliminating the Hindsight Bias, 73
J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 305 (1988); Charles G. Lord et al., Considering the Opposite: A
Corrective Strategy for Social Judgment, 47 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 1231
(1984)).
444. Nickerson, supra note 127, at 188.
445. Id.
446. Id.
447. Lieberman & Arndt, supra note 184, at 691.
448. Id.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
1. POLICE
449. See infra notes Parts III.D.1.c., e. & f., and Parts III.D.2.c. & d.
450. See infra Part III.C.1. & 2.
451. See, e.g., Thomas M. Williamson, From Interrogation to Investigative
Interviewing; Strategic Trends in Police Questioning, 3 J. COMMUNITY & APPLIED SOC.
PSYCHOL. 89, 89 (1993).
452. See id. at 90 (“Within the adversarial system, it is Police questioning
which is the most important inquisitorial element.”). Others have noted that in a
similar way, to some extent innocence projects, with their focus on utilizing DNA to
obtain the truth, whatever it might be, operate as an inquisitorial layer at the conclusion
of the adversarial criminal process. See Ralph-Pierre Grunewald, The Role of
Innocence Projects in American Criminal Procedure (2005) (unpublished LL.M. thesis,
University of Wisconsin-Madison) (on file with authors).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
462. Richard Leo has urged that, when evaluating confessions, “police
investigators and prosecutors should routinely review and analyze the statements they
take in a genuine effort at external corroboration.” Leo, supra note 258, at 100. Leo
says that review should include consideration of three factors. Police and prosecutors
should: 1) analyze the conditions under which statement was made and the extent to
which coercive forces were present; 2) analyze the extent to which the statement
contains details that are internally consistent and consistent with known crime facts; and
3) look for the source of details of the confession, that is, examine whether the
statement contains details knowable only by the perpetrator. Id. In their article
published in this symposium issue of the Wisconsin Law Review, Leo and his co-
authors go a step further and argue that admissibility of confession evidence at trial
should turn on weighing three factors: 1) whether the confession contains nonpublic
information that can be independently verified that would only be known by the true
perpetrator or an accomplice and cannot likely be guessed by chance; 2) whether the
suspect’s confession led the police to evidence about the crime that the police did not
already know; and 3) whether the suspect’s postadmission narrative ‘fits’ (or fails to fit)
with the crime facts and existing objective evidence. Richard A. Leo et al., Bringing
Reliability Back In: False Confessions and Legal Safeguards in the Twenty-First
Century, 2006 WIS. L. REV. 479.
463. Tom Kertscher, Reno Advocates for Use of a Judicial Checklist,
MILWAUKEE J. SENTINEL, Apr. 23, 2004, at 7B, available at
http://www.jsonline.com/news/state/apr04/224261.asp; see also Stanley Z. Fisher, The
Prosecutor’s Ethical Duty to Seek Exculpatory Evidence in Police Hands: Lessons
From England, 68 FORDHAM L. REV. 1379, 1435 (2000) (noting that English law
provides “checklists of potentially exculpatory evidence—such as notebook entries, first
descriptions by potential witnesses, information from tapes or telephone records, [and
the] defendant’s explanation of an offense,” which police must keep, turn over to the
prosecutor, and, if appropriate, disclose to the defense).
464. If police had listed all possible suspects and the results of the
investigations into them in the Steven Avery case, for example, and if that information
had then been disclosed to the prosecution and then the defense, the name of Gregory
Allen (the true perpetrator) would have come to light much sooner in the case (because
he was indeed a known suspect early in the investigation, but was never pursued), and
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
1. PHYSICAL EVIDENCE
2. TESTIMONIAL EVIDENCE
466. MEMON, VRIJ & BULL, supra note 291, at 66-67; John Pearse & Gisli H.
Gudjonsson, Police Interviewing Techniques at Two South London Police Stations, 3
PSYCHOL. CRIME & L. 63, 63 (1996).
467. MEMON, VRIJ & BULL, supra note 291, at 67. To various degrees, other
European countries also encourage nonconfrontational interrogation techniques.
German law, for example, provides that “the accused must be given every opportunity
to remove any suspicion against him and to point to out those circumstances which are
favourable to his defence.” Barbara Huber, Criminal Procedure in Germany, in
COMPARATIVE CRIMINAL PROCEDURE 118 (John Hatchard et al. eds., 1996).
468. Williamson, supra note 451, at 90, 97-98.
469. Id. at 90. Williamson describes the model in this way:
The role of investigative interviewing is to obtain accurate and reliable
information from suspects, witnesses or victims to discover the truth about
matters under Police investigation. Investigative interviewing should be
approached with an open mind. Information obtained from the person who
is being interviewed should always be tested against what the interviewing
Officer already knows or what can reasonably be established.
Id. at 98.
470. Id. at 65.
471. Pearse & Gudjonsson, supra note 466, at 65.
472. Id.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
1. POLICE
486. STATE OF ILL., supra note 16, at 22. Similarly, the Virginia Innocence
Commission, after reviewing proven wrongful convictions in that state, recommended
that, to counter tunnel vision,
[l]aw enforcement agencies should train their officers to document all
exculpatory, as well as inculpatory, evidence about a particular
suspect/individual that they discover and to include this information in their
official reports to ensure that all exculpatory information comes to the
attention of prosecutors and subsequently to defense attorneys.
INNOCENCE COMM’N FOR VA., supra note 20, at 73.
487. STATE OF ILL., supra note 16, at 22. These recommendations were based
in large part on the British Criminal Procedure and Investigations Act of 1996. Id. at
20 (citing Fisher, supra note 463).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
2. PROSECUTORS
d. Counterarguing
Once the decision to charge is made, cognitive biases make it
difficult to see alternative conclusions about a case. Although the task
becomes more difficult at that point, prosecutors need to understand the
importance of striving for objectivity. Because the research into
cognitive biases suggests that being compelled to argue against one’s
own position is one of the more effective means of countering one’s
E. Transparency
502. See, e.g., INNOCENCE COMM’N FOR VA., supra note 20, at 68.
503. “The defendant is the actor in our system who has the true stake in
preventing, exposing, and mitigating prosecutorial misconduct and making sure the
adversary system works as intended.” Jonakait, supra note 267, at 567.
504. See Mary Prosser, Reforming Criminal Discovery: Why Old Objections
Must Yield to New Realities, 2006 WIS. L. REV 541. More expansive discovery is also
a frequently cited measure to protect against wrongful convictions. See, e.g.,
INNOCENCE COMM’N FOR VA., supra note 20, at 3, 59-68 (recommending “formal
discovery rules to mandate open-file discovery procedures”); Jonakait, supra note 267,
at 567; Brown, supra note 243, at 1619. Professor Jenny Roberts has argued that fuller
discovery is necessary not only as a matter of due process, but also because “restrictive
discovery rules block the delivery of effective assistance of counsel when defense
counsel has insufficient information to investigate the case.” Jenny Roberts, Too Little,
Too Late: Ineffective Assistance of Counsel, the Duty to Investigate, and Pretrial
Discovery in Criminal Cases, 31 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 1097, 1100 (2004).
505. Although, as noted above, defense counsel are also conditioned to believe
that their clients are guilty, see supra Part II.B.3, they at least are subject to
considerable countervailing pressures, not to mention ethical obligations, that make
them better situated than police or prosecutors to approach a case with an alternative
perspective.
506. Brown, supra note 243, at 1596.
507. Id. at 1622.
508. Id.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
509. Id. at 1623-24. Brown has noted that this approach distinguishes the
typical American system from many European inquisitorial systems: “narrow discovery
rules in adversarial systems make factual accounts reliable by redundant investigations,
[while] this European model puts more emphasis on multiple scrutiny of a single file.”
Id. at 1625.
510. Leo, supra note 258, at 99.
511. Stephanos Bibas has argued that greater transparency is needed throughout
the criminal justice system, particularly to make the system more understandable and
accessible to victims and the public, and to make insiders like police, prosecutors, and
judges more accountable. Stephanos Bibas, Transparency and Participation in Criminal
Procedure, 86 N.Y.U. L. REV. (forthcoming June 2006). As an example that is
particularly germane here, Bibas has noted that “[v]ideotaping police interrogations and
searches, and mandatory record-keeping, could improve monitoring and credibility.”
Id.
512. See Thomas P. Sullivan, Electronic Recording of Custodial Interrogations:
Everybody Wins, 95 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 1127, 1131-35 (2005).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
created with the goal of getting a suspect to confess,” the real objective
is to gather information and “to keep[] the suspect talking (even if only
to tell lies).”519
Such new methods of interrogation, which are similar to the new
“investigative interviews” in England (which were also developed after
police began recording their interrogations), reveal that the
transparency brought by electronic recording has not just provided
fuller information to the judicial proceedings, but has also more directly
mitigated the cognitive biases that might otherwise impede the search
for the truth. In this way, Dr. Richard Leo has noted, “the presence of
a camera, and the scrutiny it implies, may help to increase the
diagnostic value of interviews and interrogations and protect the
innocent from false confessions.”520
F. Institutional Reforms
2. PROSECUTION
examiners adhered to the original conclusion, calling the prints a match. Expectation
effects caused by the insertion of non-domain-specific information altered the
conclusions of these examiners. Itiel Dror, David Charlton, & Ailsa E. Péron,
Contextual Information Renders Experts Vulnerable to Making Erroneous
Identifications, 156 FORENSIC SCI. INT. 74 (2006).
530. Earle & Case, supra note 282, at 73. Prosecutors Brian Case and Ronnie
Earle, however, reflecting on their experience facilitating the exoneration and release of
several innocent men in their jurisdiction, found that the fear was unfounded:
Ronnie Earle readily confessed astonishment at the public reaction [to the
exonerations], having been convinced that mistakes of such horrendous
moment as convictions of innocent men would result in his being thrown
ignominiously out of office. Acknowledgement and remedy seemed to
matter to the public more than the game of Gotcha often played out on
political fields.
Id.
531. Id.
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.
CONCLUSION
532. Id.
533. Medwed, supra note 196, at 175.
534. See Lissa Griffin, The Correction of Wrongful Convictions: A
Comparative Perspective, 16 AM. U. INT’L L. REV. 1241 (2001); David Horan, The
Innocence Commission: An Independent Review Board for Wrongful Convictions, 20
N. ILL. U. L. REV. 91 (2000); Findley, supra note 18, at 347.
535. See Christine C. Mumma, The North Carolina Actual Innocence
Commission: Uncommon Perspectives Joined by a Common Cause, 52 DRAKE L. REV.
647, 654 (2004).
Reprinted with permission of the Wisconsin Law Review, further reproduction forbidden without permission.