SOL Basic 1
SOL Basic 1
SOL Basic 1
Sociology of Law
From the middle of the 19th century with the emergence of sociology as a distinct
discipline the sociological study of law progressed rapidly although it assumed
diverse forms. Marx and later Marxists undertook their critique of law as an ideology
that conceals class divisions at the same time as it promotes the interests of the
dominant class. A major work of Marxist scholar Karl Renner, 'The institutions of
Private law and their social functions,' examines how the functions of legal norms
which regulate property, contract, succession and inheritance change with changes in
the economic structure of capitalist society, yet without necessarily altering the
formulation of the legal norms themselves which thus come to obscure the significant
social relationships of developed capitalism. Many other sociologists like Comte,
Spencer and Maine were influenced by the German historical school of jurisprudence
founded by Savigny.
H.S Maine in his Ancient Law made a distinction between static and progressive
societies and argued that the movement of progressive societies has hitherto been a
movement from status to contract. He meant that the individual is steadily substituted
for the family as the unit of which civil laws take account. Maine considered that
these changes were brought about by non-legal factors since social necessities and
social opinion are always more or less in advance of law and he examined under three
headings legal fictions, equity and legislation the agencies by which in progressive
societies law is brought into harmony with society.
L.T Hobhouse in conformity with his general evolutionist approach dealt with the
development of law and justice from private redress and the blood feud, through the
stage of composition for offences to the stages of civilized justice. Hobhouse records
not only the establishment of the notion of individual responsibility but also the
influence of increasing class differentiation until recent times. He also discusses
2
changes in the character of punishment and examines the relations between law,
religion and morals.
Max Weber's studies of law showed a much clearer understanding of the nature of law
than those of earlier sociologists and they have had greater influence in the growth of
a sociological jurisprudence since Weber's conception of law as being concerned with
the adjustment of conflicting interests. Weber was also interested in the classification
of types of law and in the development of law in western societies. He conceived this
development as an increasing rationalization of law, accompanying the general
rationalization of life in industrial societies as a result of the growth of capitalist
economic enterprise and of bureaucracy. According to Max Weber law is an order the
validity of which is guaranteed by the probability that deviation will be met by
physical or psychic sanction by a staff specially empowered to carry out this sanction.
In modern civilized societies laws are enacted by the state to control the individual.
The transition from custom to law is just a part of the general rationalization in
modern society. Sumner has defined the term law as codified mores. Kant defined law
as a formula that expresses the necessity of an action. According to Green law is a
more or less systematic body of generalized rules balanced between the fiction of
performance and the fact of change governing specifically defined relationship and
situations and employing force or the threat of force in defined and limited ways.
According to Maclver and Page law is the body of rules that are recognized,
interpreted and applied to particular situations by the courts of state.
There is a marked disagreement among the scholars as to what the law is. There is no
single definition of law that will encompass preliterate legal arrangements like the
Code of Hammurabi and law in modern civilization. As Maclver puts it the law of the
savage is not our law. Those who take juristic view of law define it as the command
of the sovereign or the dictates of the state. Those taking the sociological view define
law as the rules of right conduct. The problem here is shall we keep the word law for
the specialized system with their codes; their apparatus for setting disputes and the
penalties for those who have broken the rules or shall we regard these as mere
specializations of a similar kind of control which may be found in unorganized forms
or in organized forms but without what we ordinarily think of as legal sanctions.
Those who hold the former view argue that jurisprudence makes it convenient to use
the word law in a specialized sense while the advocates of the latter view hold that
primitive people had something which may be called law and that the rules of
voluntary associations like trade union, club, university, family as much regulate the
behavior of man as the law of the land. Enactment or enforcement by the state should
not be considered essential elements of law. Pollock writes if we look away from such
elaborate systems as those of a late Roman Empire and of modern western
governments, we see that not only law with a great deal of formality has existed
3
before the state had any adequate means of compelling its observance and indeed
before there was any regular process of enforcement at all. This means that two views
may be taken of law. In a wider sense it included all the rules of conduct observed by
men as a matter of habit. It may mean the body of rules that are recognized or made
by the state and interpreted by the courts of the land. Custom becomes law when the
state is prepared to enforce it as a rule binding on citizens. The term law can be
interpreted as rules enacted or at least interpreted and enforced by special agencies of
the state. Main characteristics of law are
Laws are the general conditions of human activity prescribed by the state for
its members.
Law is law only if enacted by a proper law making authority. It is a product of
conscious thought: planning and deliberate formulation.
Law is definite, clear and precise.
Law applies equally to all without exception in identical circumstances
The violation of law is followed by penalties determined by the authority of
the state.
Intellectual Origin
The roots of the sociology of law can be traced back to the works of sociologists and
jurists of the turn of the previous century. The relationship between law and society
was sociologically explored in the seminal works of both Max Weber and Émile
Durkheim. The writings on law by these classical sociologists are foundational to the
entire sociology of law today. A number of other scholars, mainly jurists, also
employed social scientific theories and methods in an attempt to develop sociological
theories of law. Notably among these were Leon Petrazycki, Eugen
Ehrlich and Georges Gurvitch.
Émile Durkheim
4
Leon Petrazycki
Leon Petrazycki distinguished between forms of "official law," supported by the state,
and "intuitive law," consisting of legal experiences that, in turn, consist of a complex
of psychic processes in the mind of the individual with no reference to outside
authorities.
Petrazycki's work addressed sociological problems and his method was empirical,
since he maintained that one could gain knowledge of objects or relationships only by
observation. However, he couched his theory in the language of cognitive psychology
and moral philosophy rather than sociology. Consequently, his contribution to the
development of sociology of law remains largely unrecognized.
For example, Petrazycki's "intuitive law" influenced not only the development of
Georges Gurvitch's concept of "social law" which in turn has left its mark on socio-
5
legal theorising, but also the work of later socio-legal scholars. Among those who
were directly inspired by Petrazycki's work is the Polish legal sociologist Adam
Podgórecki.
In 1963, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that in all felony trials the accused must be
provided with legal counsel. The case of Gideon v. Wainwright (372 U.S. 355, 1963) was
widely celebrated as a David and Goliath story of the triumph of the rule of law: An
indigent defendant's handwritten petition had persuaded all nine justices of the Supreme
Court to provide a nationwide right to counsel (Lewis 1964). Shortly after Gideon's
victory, Blumberg (1967) published an empirical case study describing the actual work of
criminal defense attorneys. That study suggested that Gideon's case had little relevance to
the 90 percent of felony convictions that the prosecution wins not in a courtroom trial but
through informal plea bargaining. Moreover, the attorneys to whom the poor were now
constitutionally entitled, Blumberg contended, had over the years mutated from trial
advocates into bureaucratic cogs whose primary function was to assist the state in
processing legal files efficiently.
Blumberg's deconstruction of the legal myth of the centrality of criminal trials and
adversarial counsel exemplifies two central features of the sociology of law. First, that
field challenges legal formalism, the philosophy that the law stands above social life,
develops according to its own internal logic, and autonomously constrains or
facilitates social interaction. A sociology of law becomes essential once the law's
dependence on its social organizational context is recognized (for a defense of legal
formalism as a research agenda, see Watson 1985). Blumberg tried to show that the right
to legal representation is contingent on the economics of legal services and the networks of
dependency that link judges, prosecutors, and defense attorneys in ways that undermine
the abstract legal model of the adversarial contest. Second, Blumberg's case rests on
observations of legal practice rather than interpretation of the texts of cases and legislation,
the stock-in-trade of conventional legal scholarship. As empirical evidence continued to
accumulate, Blumberg's (1967) conclusions about the origins, causes, and consequences
of plea bargaining were qualified or supplanted; later research suggests that plea bargains
may be even more adversarial than trials ever were (Feeley 1997), that the relationship
between caseload pressure and plea bargaining is complex (Holmes et al. 1992), and that
the real role of the courtroom trial may be independent of its frequency of occurrence
because out-of-court negotiations are conducted "in the shadow of the law" (Mnookin and
Kornhauser 1979). Blumberg's study and the later work it inspired illustrate how the
sociology of law examines empirical evidence to understand how law is created, enforced,
and manipulated in the context of social organization.
The discipline of sociology does not hold a monopoly on efforts to unveil the connections
between law and society. In the twentieth century, Roscoe Pound, Jerome Frank, and other
legal scholars abandoned legal formalism and created new ways to understand the
differences between the "law in the books" and the "law in practice" (for a concise
overview of both developments, see Hunt 1978). Since the late 1970s, the critical legal
studies movement and its variants have emerged as a major competitor to legal formalism
in legal research and education (Kelman 1987). For example, Freeman (1978) examines
how major Supreme Court decisions on civil rights have shifted the bases for legally
defining discrimination from the consequences for the victims to the intentions of the
perpetrators. Freeman shows how the law's emphasis on the actor's intention constrains the
principle of equal protection and perpetuates inequality. While his conclusions are radical,
his method is identical to the legal formalists' practice of textual interpretation (Trubek
1984). Critical legal studies' doctrinal analysis—its reliance on interpretation of
constitutions, statutes, and judgments—has more affinity with literary criticism than with
sociological methodologies based on the observation of events. For an example of this
distinction, compare Klare (1978) with Wallace et al. (1988). Sociology of law is
distinguished more by its methods than by its theories or subject matter.
A substantial number of historical case studies (e.g., Hall 1952) have traced the social
origins of substantive and procedural law. Sociology enters these investigations with a
broader comparative agenda, formulating and assessing general theories of the origin of
law. Chambliss's (1964) analysis of six centuries of vagrancy laws as a ruling-class
manipulation of criminal o control labor was a pioneer of contemporary efforts to pursue
this line of investigation. Hagan (1980) provides a representative overview of the
subsequent sociological analyses of the origins of alcohol and drug prohibition, sexual
psychopathology and prostitution laws, and probation. Humphries and Greenberg (1981)
produced one of the few sociological efforts showing the relationships among disparate
legal changes and linking those changes to their social bases. They explain the diffusion of
juvenile courts, probation, parole, and indeterminate sentences in terms of the shift in the
political domination of corporate versus competitive capital during the Progressive era. An
alternative approach to the study of the creation and diffusion of legal innovation looks to
cultural transmission and organizational linkages rather than to underlying economic or
social transformations. Grattet et al. (1998) show, for example, how the diffusion of hate
crime legislation appears to be influenced by interstate processes of diffusion rather than
by local conditions of the economy and society. Soule and Zylan (1997) similarly explore
structural and diffusion factors in the reform of Aid to Families with Dependent Children
(AFDC) eligibility rules. In terms of both theory and method, the sociology of law offers a
rich body of work that reveals the social foundations of change in the law.
9
The largest body of research in the field has been devoted to the examination of
discriminination in sentencing in criminal courts. Disparities in the type and duration of
sanctions vary markedly by class, race, and/or ethnicity, and gender. For example, with 5
percent of the general population, young African-American males account for nearly half
the admissions to state prisons. The initial research problem was to determine the extent to
which such disparities represent differential involvement in the kinds of crime that lead to
more severe sentences or reflect biases in discretionary decision making in the legal
system (for a succinct overview of this research, see Walker et al. 1996). The
sociologically relevant discoveries of this research include covariation in the extent of
discriminatory decision making with social location (see Myers and Talarico 1987).
widely recognized is the fact that in the decade after Brown, racial segregation in public
schools remained virtually unchanged. The sharpest challenge to conventional conceptions
of the social impact of law is Rosenberg's (1991) study of the effect of Supreme Court
decisions on school desegregation, abortion, reapportionment, and criminal procedure.
While current controversy centers on Rosenberg's thesis, several other research programs
address the conditions under which legal reforms engineer social change. Burstein (1985),
for example, specifies the contingencies that influenced the impact of civil
rights legislation on the economic position of minorities. Horney and Spohn (1991)
examine the impact of rape reform laws in six jurisdictions on several indicators of
prosecution. The measurable impact of legal reform proved to be limited, because of the
response of local court organizations to externally imposed change. Heimer (1995)
illustrates that similar complications appear when legal changes are imposed on hospital
work groups. Organizational responses occasionally facilitate rather than inhibit change.
Edelman et al. (1992), for example, found that personnel departments tend to exaggerate
the legal risks of noncompliance in equal-opportunity cases as a way to enhance their
power within the corporation.
A public defender explained to Sudnow (1965) that to work in such an office, one has to
know the law—and the ropes. Learning about the organizational ropes of courts, police
departments, and law offices has been the objective of a large body of contemporary
research in the sociology of law.
Many discoveries about procedure turn on the emergence of informal organizational rules
and relationships. Sudnow (1965) found that plea bargains were forged in a common
currency of offense seriousness that existed apart from the penal code's definitions of
crimes and punishments. Emerson (1969) showed how the legally relevant aspects of a
juvenile's offense and career are organizationally transformed into judgments of character,
11
which then become the real bases for determining verdicts and imposing sentences. This
work suggests that due process is a variable whose appearance and effects are shaped by
organizational contexts (see Dobbin et al. 1988).
The sociology of law can be distinguished from economics, psychology, and other social
science enterprises that have law as their subject matter principally in terms of its
integration of its investigations with general theories of social structure. The role of
general theory becomes apparent, for example, in comparisons of Japanese and U.S. legal
systems that "explain away Japan by attributing every finding to 'Japanese uniqueness'
[rather than] treat Japan as a point on a universal continuum" (Miyazawa 1987, p. 239).
The case for engaging in the search for such universal continua is made by Black (1976,
1997).