Chapter II
Chapter II
Chapter II
Man as a Person
Introduction
General Objectives:
1. Discuss what are the philosophies of man
2. Distinguish man as a person
3. Distinguish personality from character
4. Explain moral habits and its moral significance
5. Differentiate virtues and vices
The method that we use in studying the nature of man and the meaning or condition
of being human is basically Christian. But this requires a lot of analytic presentation of
various views about man. Some of these views are pagan _ while others are atheist. Only
after presenting these views will we engage into a synthetic Inquiry of man.
All men have the same anatomical and physiological structure. Several philosophers
and scholars present different views on how to understand man as a person.
WHAT TO EXPECT
1. Biological
Man is a complex being who behaves uniquely as a result of his hereditary,
environmental, and cultural influences. He is curious; he imitates others and has his own
interests. Man reasons and improves the adaptive nature of his behavior in rational ways. He
makes and uses tools in a variety of ways. He is self-conscious, reflecting on his past and
future and on life and death. He makes mental abstractions, develops symbols and
communicates his ideas and knowledge through sign or oral language. Man has a sense of
appreciation for arts and beauty.
Man has his religion. He believes in a Divine Being, and has superstitions and beliefs
in animistic, supernatural, or spiritual things. A human being is a moral animal and has
developed himself through the influence of heredity, environment, and cultural factors. Thus,
man becomes an integral human being Created in the likeness of God.
2. Classical View
For the classical philosophers, man is a creature endowed with hierarchical virtues
whose nature is designed to serve as building blocks of society. Man is distinct from animals
as he is the sole being who possesses a physical body and a soul. Man‘s soul is composed
of intellect and will. From the point of view of Aristotle, man is a rational and a social being.
To him, man is not the center of the universe. He is only a part of it. He is born to be a part of
society. He is a political animal in the sense that outside the political organization or the
organized society, he is nothing. He is a beast who recognizes neither law nor social
structures.
3. Christian View
The Judaeo-Christian philosophers considered man as the ―image‖ of God." Genesis
1:27 (Holy Bible) states, ―God created man in mi own minim; in the image of God He created
him; male and female He created them.‖ This center on the notion that man is endowed with
divine attributes. These divine characteristics bring all men to a common bond forming
essentially one family. We share the same basis features that make us human and enable
us to know and to love one another. As is pointed out, biblical prophecy speaks of the
peaceful unity of all men.
4. Existentialist View
Teilhard de Chardin (1970) says that man is a being who knows what he knows.
Martin Heideger (cited by Palispis, 1995) believes that man is responsible not only for
himself but for all men. In his book Introduction to Philosophy, Engelber Van Crooverburg
(1963), as cited by Palispis (1995), mentions the following thoughts about man:
1. jen - the feeling of commensuration, which is the beginning of the virtue of human
heartedness.
2. yi -the feeling of shame and dislike, which is the start of righteousness.
3. Li- the feeling of modesty and yielding towards the good. This is the beginning of
ritual or propriety.
4. chin -the sense of right and wrong.
Man is naturally bestowed with the knowledge of what is right and what is wrong or
what is good and what is bad. These four beginnings of man differentiate him from the beast.
Man is expected to develop these four beginnings to become truly a man. Through the full
development of his nature, man cannot only know Heaven but also becomes one with
Heaven.
The only way for man to be happy is to free himself from the slavery of his
selfishness and inordinate sexual desires. Gautama Buddha says: ―Never in this world does
hatred cease by hatred. Hatred ceases by love... Let us live happily by not hating those who
hate us. Let us live free among men who hate. Let a man overcome anger by kindness, evil
by good, and hate by love.‖
To Confucius, life is not a delusion, a curse, or a misery. It is a living reality, a
blessing, a natural priceless right and opportunity to work together with your fellows for the
common good and attain happiness. He says that man‘s perfection and happiness is
realized and achieved in social life. He advocates harmony among men in society. The
social order predicted by Confucius is patterned after the natural order of things in the
universe and the moral order reflected and embodied in the life of the moral man. Confucius
states that the life of the moral man is an exemplification of the universal moral order. The
life of the vicious man is its contradiction.
In constantly doing what is good as commanded by his nature, man becomes one
with the natural law, is adjusted to the rhythm of the universe, and thus enjoys peace and
happiness. Confucius says ―Mans greatest achievement is to find the central clue to our
moral being that unites us with the universal order‖
Contemporary View
Man is said to be a multi-bejeweled crown of creation. He radiates the various
aspects and facets of his being which he alone possesses his physical, mental, moral,
spiritual, social, civic, economic, psychological, aesthetic, and sensual aspects. These gifts
are not mere adornments but are meant to serve a noble purpose: to serve for the
betterment and perfection not only. of himself but also of humanity. In the end, man will be
judged not only by his possession, power or influence but also by the nature of his work
(Montemayor, 1995)
Immanuel Kant Concludes that man is the only creature who governs and directs
himself and his actions. He sets up ends for herself and his purpose and freely orders
means for the attainment ‗of his aims. Every man is an END in himself and should never be
treated merely as a means as per the order of the Creator and the natural order of things
(Montemayor, 1995)
Man is a human being. As (a true human being-he has the power to become the best
among all creations. The Divine Providence created man in His own likeness; gifted him with
an intellect and will in order to know the truth and to make the right decisions. With the use
of these endowments, man has the capacity to learn and be educated in the right sense of
the word. Through education, man will be equipped with the necessary knowledge, skills,
and values needed as he explores the world of work. Through his values, ideals, intelligent
insights, and productive efforts, man has the capacity to become progressive (Baking, 1982).
Assessment
Lesson Outline
Also, personality can be described more specifically as "how a person affects others,
how he understands and views himself and his pattern of inner and outer measurable traits."
From this definition, it can be understood one's physical appearance and behavior affects
others. Understanding oneself means one is unique with a set of attitudes and values and a
self-concept. Finally, the pattern of measurable traits refers to a set of characteristics that the
person exhibits.
Assessment
Man is a creature of habits. He is born with a wide assortment of powers that open up
limitless horizons for development. Reason stands to the apex of the vast array of
potentialities. Man, if he must integrate all his powers in one wholesome personality, must
rely on the powers of reason. Man must for the habits of reason.
WHAT TO EXPECT
Benefit #1: Moral habits reduce our cognitive load. Moral habits automatize decisions
for us, freeing us from the time and effort of deliberating most everyday moral choices. As I
mentioned, without any such automatization, we would be mentally crippled. But more
broadly speaking, our moral habits allow us to both focus our attention on the more
interesting and complex aspects of life and act quickly.
Benefit #2: Moral habits dispose us to act morally. Good moral habits make virtuous
action easy and natural, and render vice difficult and unpleasant. In forming habits, we
condition our emotions to take pleasure in acting on principle and feel pain in acting against
principle. That emotional feedback naturally inclines us towards the right thing to do.
Benefit #3: Moral habits give us consistency between our words and our deeds.
Moral habits connect our abstract moral principles to the concrete moral choices we face
every day. As such, habits strengthen the bond between what we say and what we do. They
strengthen our integrity. However, integrity concerns more than the ―trickle-down‖ effect from
our principles to our actions. It also concerns the ―trickle-up‖ effect from our actions to our
principles. To put it bluntly, what we do affects what we think. If our actions are inconsistent
with our beliefs, we will change our beliefs in order to reconcile the two.
Assessment
1. _____ Habits are not acquired. They become very easy to change. They are
therefore relatively temporary.
2. _____ Moral habits do not reduce our cognitive load. Moral habits is affecting our
decisions, freeing us from the time and effort of deliberating most everyday moral
choices.
3. _____ Habits are established and maintained by replication means that we
automatize the actions by practicing them over and over again.
4. _____ Habits are largely prevailing and hidden patterns of action established and
maintained by repetition.
5. _____ Habits are formed in an instant. They result from constantly repeated actions.
6. _____ Dominance means that we perform the habitual actions. In almost every case
that we pick up the ends of our shoelaces, we tie our shoelace and comb our hair.
7. _____ having no habits, making all moral decisions consciously and deliberately, is
simply an option.
8. _____ Good moral habits make virtuous action not easy and natural, and render vice
difficult and unpleasant.
9. _____ Moral habits arise out of a commitment to particular moral principles.
10. _____ Moral habits connect our concrete moral principles to the abstract moral
choices we face every day.
Lesson 4. Intellectual Virtues and the Effects of Vices
People‘s virtues are a subset of their good qualities. They are not innate, like
eyesight, but are acquired by practice and lost by disuse. They are abiding states, and they
thus differ from momentary passions such as anger and pity. Virtues are states of character
that find expression both in purpose and in action. Moral virtue is expressed in good
purpose—that is to say, in prescriptions for action in accordance with a good plan of life. It is
expressed also in actions that avoid both excess and defect. A temperate person, for
example, will avoid eating or drinking too much, but he will also avoid eating or drinking too
little. Virtue chooses the mean, or middle ground, between excess and defect. Besides
purpose and action, virtue is also concerned with feeling. One may, for example, be
excessively concerned with sex or insufficiently interested in it; the temperate person will
take the appropriate degree of interest and be neither lustful nor frigid.
WHAT TO EXPECT
Lesson Outline
Virtues may pertain to intellect or to the will. Those that pertain to the intellect are
called intellectual virtues. They help man acquire knowledge and perfection on that aspect
only. Those that pertain to the will are called moral virtues. They dispose the will towards
proper conduct and contribute to the perfection of the whole person.
Understanding, science and wisdom pertain to speculative intellect. Art and prudence
pertain to practical intellect.
1. Justice is the virtue which inclines us to render to another what is due to him. The
biblical just man is one who respects himself, worships God and helps others.
2. Fortitude is the virtue which gives us the strength in facing dangers and vicissitudes
of life. In Filipino we refer to it as tatag ng kalooban so that we describe a man of
fortitude as matibay, matatag, or malakas ang loob.
The Vices
A vice is the habit of doing an evil acquired through the repetition of an evil act. One
single act of immorality does not constitute an immoral habit. But it is no less imputable to
the subject. So much for the expression -―We don‘t hate the sinner but the sin" .The fact is
that every evil act speaks ill of the Character of the person acting.
Assessment
1. Based on your own understanding, point out the difference/s between intellectual
and moral virtues.
2. Give a certain vice that you have and explain its effects to both your personal life
and education.
Fill-in the blanks. Give the correct answer on what the statement pertains to
1. _____________ is the virtue which helps us regulate our passions and our use of
earthly goods.
2. _____________ is the habit of ultimate causes, such as, being aware that the
ecosystem binds both man and lower creatures.
3. _____________ which is the habit of doing or choosing from alternative values, such
as saving for the ―rainy days‖.
4. _____________ which is the habit of the first principles, such as, ―do good and avoid
evil‖, ―the whole is greater than the sum of any of its parts‖;
6. _____________ is the habit of making or producing things, such as, paintings, music,
sculpture;
7. _____________ the habit of doing an evil acquired through the repetition of an evil
act.
8. ____________ is the virtue which gives us the strength in facing dangers and
vicissitudes of life.
9. ____________ is the habit of proximate causes, such as, concluding from the facts
of experience or inference;
10. ____________ are states of character that find expression both in purpose and in
action.
Chapter Summary
Articulo & Florendo. 2003. Values and Work Ethics. Philippines: Trinitas Publishing, Inc.
Augustine, (1995). De doctrina Christiana. Edited and translated by R.P.H. Green.
Oxford Clarendon.
Babor. 1999. ETHICS: The Philosophical Discipline of Action First Edition. Manila: Rex
Bookstore, Inc.
Hursthouse, Rosalind. On Virtue Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.
–––. "Virtue Theory and Abortion," in Virtue Ethics. Edited by Roger Crisp and
Michael Slote. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997, pp. 217-239