HempelEnzyklopdie 2015
HempelEnzyklopdie 2015
HempelEnzyklopdie 2015
net/publication/275547630
CITATIONS READS
0 1,196
1 author:
Gereon Wolters
Universität Konstanz
79 PUBLICATIONS 194 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Gereon Wolters on 28 April 2015.
Gereon Wolters
Universität Konstanz
FB Philosophie, Fach D 15
D-78457 Konstanz
Germany
Phone: 0049-(0)7531 -88 2636(office)
-2827 186 (home)
Fax -88 2502 (office)
2
that dominated much of American philosophy in the second third of the twentieth
century and has been a principal source of present day analytical philosophy. In
the spirit of logical empiricism Hempel aimed at a scientific philosophy with the
sciences, including the social sciences. His most important contribution in this
respect is what can be regarded the first theory of scientific explanation. This
law of nature, probability, type etc. Both the internal failure of this program and the
1. Biography
Hempel went to Vienna to study with Moritz Schlick and, particularly, Rudolf
Carnap. Both of them, together with the mathematician Hans Hahn and the
3
economist Otto Neurath and others, had founded in 1923 the ‘Vienna Circle’
(‘Wiener Kreis’), that was to become the nucleus of logical empiricism. After his
return to Berlin in 1930 Hempel entered teacher’s training and teaching and
worked at the same time with Hans Reichenbach, head of the ‘Berlin Group’ of
After graduation in 1934 Hempel preferred to leave Nazi Germany and went to
1937/38 Hempel worked for a year as research associate with Carnap in Chicago,
and again went back to Brussels until he found a post of instructor at City College,
New York in 1939. The academic year 1940 to 1941 saw him at Queens College,
New York, from where he went as associate professor to Yale in 1948. In 1955
2. Major Contributions
the ‘universality thesis’, i.e. the thesis that the social sciences do not, and should
not, use methods that are essentially different from the methods of empirical
premises (‘explanans’) at least one (general) scientific law L1 as well as initial and
describing the event in question. We thus obtain the following model of ‘deductive-
E the explanandum
In case the explanandum contains essentially a statistical law (e.g. for all x:
given for some b) the explanatory argument does not deliver a deduction of the
explanandum statement E but rather gives inductive support for E, i.e. the
In simplified form (one statistical law, one boundary condition) we thus obtain the
In the case of I-S-explanation one must further assume that the explanans
is maximally specified, i.e. the explanans must contain all available information
that is possibly relevant for the explanation of the explanandum E. Or, in other
5
words, the explanandum must contain all pertinent statistical laws and those
special facts that can be connected with the E-event by statistical laws. I-S-
explanations thus relate to the body of scientific knowledge at a given time, i.e.
generality than the one(s) in the explanandum one obtains the reduction of a law
or theory in the first case (e.g., explaining the law of free fall by means of the law
adequate prediction yields also an adequate explanation, for symptoms are often
adequate for a prediction, but not for the corresponding explanation. So is, for
example, a sudden fall of the barometer (together with suitable laws) sufficient for
predicting a thunderstorm, but it does not explain it, since the fall of the barometer
is not the cause of the thunderstorm, but rather a symptom of its arrival.
these fields likewise aim at showing that the event in question was to be expected
on the basis of antecedent and boundary conditions and general laws. In history
those general laws are usually taken from psychology, sociology, economics, the
natural sciences etc. Hempel leaves the question open whether genuine historical
laws exist. Normally explanations in history and sociology fail to include an explicit
statement of the laws they presuppose. This failure is due to the fact that those
laws are part of folk psychology and seem to be tacitly taken for granted. Apart
from that it is difficult to formulate in a sufficiently exact way the underlying general
assumptions about e.g. the outbreak and course of revolutions. Furthermore, most
of the regularities in the social sciences are statistical. Therefore one can expect
the social from the natural sciences is neither sufficient, nor necessary for
of such a personality.
early cooperation with Paul Oppenheim and consists basically in the application of
development of a science from its initial descriptive ‘natural history’ stages to its
(e.g., human beings) into subclasses (e.g., beings that suffer from certain mental
the membership in that subclass. Hempel speaks also of ’classificatory types’. The
concept applies (e.g., schizophrenics). The characteristics that form the defining
well as scientific concepts in general have to fulfill two requirements. They have:
(a) to be objective; and (b) to have systematic import. Objectivity is attained first by
using operational criteria and (often only partial) operational definitions in a large
with valuation overtones. Scientific concepts have systematic import if they lend
some subclass or it does not, comparative concepts admit of more or less with
respect to a certain trait (e.g., x is warmer than y with respect to cold-hot)). They
lead to (quasi) linear orderings as soon as one includes the relation of coincidence
8
(e.g., x is equally warm as y). Hempel calls the extremes of such orderings
‘ordering types’. The next step would consist in giving these linear orderings a
For Hempel the ‘ideal types’ that have become popular in the social
sciences since Max Weber are neither classificatory nor ordering types. Ideal
behavior, a capitalist society, a religious sect. Accordingly ideal types must rather
their lack of clarity and precision there thus are also with respect to ideal types no
subsequent studies of this topic must be referred’ (Salmon 1998, p. vii). His
American Psychiatric Association (Houts 2001). His later work reflects the
(particularly T.S. Kuhn’s work) that put a strong emphasis on the historical and
Bibliography
Keywords
analytical philosophy
concept formation
classificatory concepts
comparative concepts
quantitative concepts
covering-law model
explication
Hempel-Oppenheim Model
Ideal types
logical empiricism
methodology
prediction, structural identity with explanation
rational reconstruction
scientific explanation
deductive-nomological (D-N) explanation
inductive-statistical (I-S) explanantion
unity of science
Vienna Circle
Abstract
Carl Gustav Hempel was a leading figure of the logico-empiricist
movement, originating in the 20s of the last century in Vienna and Berlin. He is
particularly famous for his work on scientific explanation that led to the ‘Hempel-
11
Cross References
Empiricism, history of
Explanation: Conceptions in the Social Sciences
Ideal Type: Conceptions in the Social Sciences
Idealization
Abstraction and Ideal Types
Kuhn, Thomas S.
Logical Positivism and Logical Empiricism
Mathematical Models in Philosophy of Science