Baril - 2023 - Suicidism A Theoretical Framework For Conceptualizing Suicide
Baril - 2023 - Suicidism A Theoretical Framework For Conceptualizing Suicide
Baril - 2023 - Suicidism A Theoretical Framework For Conceptualizing Suicide
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Temple University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to Undoing Suicidism
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PART I
R ET HI N K I NG SU ICIDE
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CH APTER 1
SU ICIDISM
ANNA BORGES, a mental health advocate and writer for a number of media
outlets, came out in 2019 as someone who experiences “passive suicidality,”
the experience of having, based on her definition, suicidal ideation without
actively attempting to complete a suicide. In addition to the courage required
for such a public coming out—knowing that suicidal people suffer stigmati-
zation, exclusion, marginalization, pathologization, incarceration, and forms
of criminalization—Borges’s essay is noteworthy for its identification of some
of the worries, fears, and consequences, such as surveillance and stigma, that
surround suicidality and that often lead to the silencing of suicidal people.
Borges is not the only public personality to discuss suicidality. Indeed, inter-
est in mental health issues has led many public figures and artists to come
out as suicidal individuals and share their experiences.1 In the same year,
Anna Mehler Paperny, a reporter for Reuters in Toronto and the author of a
2019 memoir, Hello I Want to Die Please Fix Me, published excerpts of her
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
42 | CH APTER 1
book in the Canadian magazine The Walrus. Introducing the text, she states
(2019b, 49):
For ages, the dictate has been not to write honestly about suicide—
not to mention even the word, never mind methods, lest, in referenc-
ing it directly, you prompt suicidal spirals in others. But you can’t
tackle the endless abyss of wanting to die on tiptoes; that just leaves
you with the half-hearted interventions we’ve pretended are the best
society can do. I need to be faithful to the experience. This is how I
felt, and this is how I acted; this is what people in despair are driven
to do. These are the people we fail in myriad ways, and this is the
cost of that failure.
This “failure” is the failure to truly listen to suicidal people and to openly
discuss suicidality. Like Borges, Paperny names her concerns about being
honest about her suicidal ideation, based on her first-hand experience of be-
ing brought by police officers to the hospital against her will, being badly
treated during her hospitalization, and being physically restrained after sui-
cide attempts.
North American media is replete with horrific stories of suicidal people
facing inhumane treatment after expressing their suicidal ideation, from be-
ing hospitalized and drugged against their will to being handcuffed and shot
by police officers called to suicidal “crisis scenes.” It is worth noting that
police brutality is also deeply informed by racial and (dis)ability power rela-
tions, since it targets particularly those who are racialized, disabled, Mad,
and neurodivergent (Puar 2017). Such stories confirm what some studies
have shown to be the harsh realities faced by suicidal individuals (Stefan
2016; Szasz 1999; Webb 2011). These stories illustrate that, despite the public
discourses of support, compassion, and care surrounding suicidality, suicidal
individuals who reach out for help often do not always find the compassion
promised (Fitzpatrick 2020; Jaworski 2020; Radford, Wishart, and Martin
2019; White 2020b; White and Morris 2019). Through the discourses of
risk, surveillance, and the protection of vulnerable people from themselves,
incarceration and violations of basic human rights are considered justifiable.
While it is not my intention to provide a statistical analysis of how many
suicidal people suffer traumatic experiences when revealing their suicidal
ideation, I argue that a few instances of inhumane treatment are already too
many. Additionally, such traumatic experiences haunt the public imagination
and prevent people from discussing their suicidal ideation.
While the topic of suicide is often discussed, a widespread but unspo-
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 43
ken phenomenon that isolates and silences suicidal people remains unex-
amined. It is a “problem that has no name,” to borrow an expression from
Betty Friedan (1963), who attempted to theorize women’s oppression at a
time when conceptual feminist tools were still underdeveloped. In our era
of intersectional analyses, when long lists of oppressions have been theorized
and denounced, including sexism, racism, colonialism, classism, ageism, cis-
genderism, heterosexism, sizeism, ableism, and sanism, to name but a few
(Crenshaw 1989; Hill Collins 2000), one form of oppression remains absent
from such lists: the oppression of suicidal people, or what I call structural sui-
cidism. Although anti-oppression activists/scholars address suicide, they do so
in efforts to prevent suicides rather than to theorize the oppression endured
by suicidal people. The absence of this oppression from discussions of suicid-
ality is so profound that the oppression has yet to be named. After reflecting
on the realities faced by suicidal people, I sought a term that could capture
this oppression. I faced a conceptual desert or, as I demonstrate later, a form
of hermeneutical injustice. The fact that no term existed to discuss this op-
pression is quite revealing. By borrowing from other terms, such as sexism
and ableism, I coined the neologism suicidism in 2016–2017. While Merriam-
Webster’s Dictionary has included the term suicidism since 1913, its definition,
as “the quality or state of being suicidal,” differs radically from mine and is
not widely used these days.2 My use of the term suicidism refers to “an op-
pressive system (stemming from nonsuicidal perspectives) functioning at the
normative, discursive, medical, legal, social, political, economic, [religious],
and epistemic levels, a system in which suicidal people experience multiple
forms of injustice and violence” (Baril 2018, 193; my translation). Suicidist
violence is pernicious among anti-oppression activists/scholars because it is
framed as protecting vulnerable people from themselves. Furthermore, sui-
cidism is intertwined with ableism and sanism because it often mobilizes
arguments about “mental capacity” to revoke people’s agency. However, sui-
cidism should not be reduced to ableism and sanism, as I illustrate later, be-
cause suicidist norms and structures are at work regardless of whether ableist
and sanist perspectives are deployed to oppress suicidal subjects. Therefore,
suicidism is distinct from, though interlocked with, other systems of op-
pression. The thesis defended in this chapter is simple but radical: Suicidal
people suffer individually and collectively from suicidist oppression, and this
oppression remains unproblematized in current interpretations of suicidality,
including those grounded in anti-oppressive and social justice approaches.
This chapter, which raises epistemological questions about dominant con-
ceptualizations of suicidality, is divided into four parts. The first part reviews
four predominant models of suicidality: medial/psychological, social, public
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
44 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 45
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
46 | CH APTER 1
scholar Scott J. Fitzpatrick (2014) points out, the seppuku (sometimes known
as hara-kiri) was inscribed in a meaningful ritualistic practice in feudal Ja-
pan. This example highlights the importance of understanding each practice
of self-accomplished death on its own and within its sociocultural and histor-
ical context: “Suicide is historical. Its meaning, methods, rates, and concepts
are not static but change over time [ . . . ]. Each and every suicide is located
within its own temporal nexus of cultural, social, personal, moral, and/or
political factors. In this view, knowledge of the prevailing cultural-historical
background becomes a necessary condition for understanding the individual
act of suicide [ . . . ]” (Fitzpatrick 2014, 225). The social construction of sui-
cide and its various meanings according to specific contexts (Douglas 1967)
allow for a multiplicity of discourses on suicide, as Fitzpatrick (2014, 228)
notes: “Conflicting views on the meaning of suicide can, and do, coexist.
Suicide has been variously described as rational, irrational, cowardly, honour-
able, brave, and weak.” In sum, conceptualizations of suicide and reactions
and attitudes toward suicide vary greatly across and within epochs and cul-
tures, an undeniable fact that helps cast the current dominant view of suicide
as a major problem as only one perspective among many others:
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 47
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
48 | CH APTER 1
and attempts, which had been construed as bad actions, were thus reframed
through a process of pathologization as symptomatic of an uncontrollable
subject “hijacked” by a disease of the mind or of the society. For example,
Hecht (2013, x) qualifies suicidality as a “monster” taking over a person. As
BayatRizi (2008, 97) explains:
The individual may have gained the right to kill himself, but in the
process, he lost the status of author of his own acts. If he killed him-
self, he was simply too incompetent to know what he was doing. The
old punishments were abandoned, but they were quickly replaced by
new preventative measures that nullify the subjective meanings of
suicide.
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 49
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
50 | CH APTER 1
spite the fact that, as pointed out by Houston (2009, 98), historically, “medi-
cal men involved with suicide were cautious about psychologizing.” In fact,
many of them were originally quite reluctant to offer psychological explana-
tions of suicide and were more focused on the physical aspects of suicidality,
at least until later in the nineteenth century (110). The “psy” disciplines and
expertise, as noted by sociologist Nikolas Rose (1999), became more impor-
tant in the twentieth century, to the point of being central in our current
ways of dealing with suicidality in medicine, law, public policies, interven-
tion, and many other spheres.
Within the “psy” disciplines, Edwin Shneidman, one of the most influ-
ential authors of suicidology and the man who named the field of study in
the 1960s, believes that the illness or disease of suicidal people is inscribed in
their psyche. Shneidman argues that suicidal individuals are suffering psy-
chologically and that this “psychache” is the main component of suicidality.
Defining some of his key concepts and neologisms, Shneidman (1993, x)
writes, “Suicidology simply defines the field of knowledge of suicide and the
practice of suicide prevention; psychache throws emphasis on the central role
of psychological pain in suicide (and suicide’s irreducible psychological char-
acter)” (emphasis in the original). Shneidman (42–45) argues that suicidality
stems from three important interrelated factors: (1) psychological pain, (2)
perturbation of the mind, and (3) pressures (called “press”) triggering and
affecting the individual. Contemporary suicidologists have followed Shneid-
man’s path. For example, scholar Thomas Joiner (2005), one of the most cited
authors in the field of suicidology today,8 suggests an interpersonal theory of
suicide, emphasizing the importance of relationships and arguing that suicid-
al ideation emerges when some basic human needs are unfulfilled, including
having a sense of belonging to a group or feeling useful. Joiner believes that
unmet relational needs are at the origin of suicidal ideation and that suicide
attempts result from the acquired ability to self-harm through progressive ex-
posure to self-injury. In that sense, while psychache is a fundamental element
in suicidality, it cannot explain it entirely.
Although the medical model tends to focus on individual, curable pa-
thologies, some proponents nonetheless recognize to some extent the role that
social, environmental, political, and cultural factors may play in suicidality.
This perception was the case for some of the early medical conceptualizations
of suicidality, such as those developed by Jean-Pierre Falret (1822), which
combined internal and hereditary factors with external ones (Houston 2009,
93). More than a century later, Shneidman (1993, 3), for example, has built
his theory of suicidality on two main arguments: “The first is that suicide is
a multifaceted event and that biological, cultural, sociological, interpersonal,
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 51
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
52 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 53
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
54 | CH APTER 1
tice model share so many postulates, assumptions, and affinities that they are
often conflated, including by me in the past. In my previous work, following
numerous authors, I discuss these two models indistinguishably; only later,
while reading Suicide and Social Justice, edited by scholars Mark E. Button
and Ian Marsh (2020), did I become aware of the differences between the
two. While the social and the social justice models interpret suicidality based
on social forces and factors, the former inherits its assumptions from the sci-
entific positivist tradition insisting on the importance of objectivity, quan-
titative data, and sociological generalizations (with a few exceptions), while
the latter offers contextualized explanations of suicidality focusing on the
importance of qualitative research and proposing critical analyses of suicidal-
ity and its relationship to marginalized communities. As Button and Marsh
(2020a, 2) explain, the social model of suicidality derives from a traditional
sociological perspective and focuses on “social determinants of health,” of-
ten brushing aside the political analysis and actions promoted by the social
justice model. Button (2020, 89) shows how the objectivity, neutrality, and
positivist stance often adopted by sociologists adhering to the social model
lead to a depoliticized response to suicidality:
Sociologists (still following Durkheim after all these years) are cer-
tainly right to point to the social forces that undermine human well-
being, but until these social forces are traced to the political struc-
tures and agents that bear partial responsibility for them, and until
citizens and leaders close the door on willful blindness and bad faith
about the relationship between policy regimes and the distribution
of vulnerability to suicide, suicide will remain a public health crisis
without an adequate political level of analysis and response.
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 55
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
56 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 57
In the same spirit, some scholars, such as Lani East, Kate P. Dorozenko,
and Robyn Martin (2019, 6), argue that public health discourses on suicide
are morally charged and often blame the victims, pointing out their individ-
ual problems and their lack of “coping abilities.” In sum, as we can see from
these critiques of the public health model, while this approach continues to
blur the lines between the various models of suicidality and would have, in
theory, much to contribute to a conceptualization of suicidality from a nu-
anced and complex point of view, critical suicidologists argue that this prom-
ise is unmet. A cooptation of the public health model by the medical model
seems to be at work—hence the development of other models, such as the
social justice model presented in the following section.
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
58 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 59
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
60 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 61
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
62 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 63
as such, scholar Simone Fullagar (2003) discusses how suicides are seen as
forms of loss and waste in capitalist and neoliberal societies that aim to maxi-
mize profit and productivity. Fullagar (292) also shows how this context fuels
moralization and the usage of negative vocabulary: “Suicide as waste is im-
plicated in a whole moral vocabulary about living and dying—tragically sad,
incomprehensible, unforgivable, pathological, abnormal, unstable, irrespon-
sible, selfish, morally reprehensible.” This neoliberal context, in which deaths
by suicide are considered a “waste,” also perpetuates what I call an “injunction
to live,” discussed later in this chapter.
While an increasing number of scholars are calling for the abandonment
of the sinful and criminal vocabulary related to suicidality, including expres-
sions such as “committing suicide,” suicidality is still discussed in stigmatiz-
ing and negative terms, even by authors who want to destigmatize it. From a
more clinical perspective, Domenico De Berardis, Giovanni Martinotti, and
Massimo Di Giannantonio (2018, 2) state:
The suicide is always a plague for the population at risk and one of
the most disgraceful events for a human being. Moreover, it implies a
lot of pain often shared by the relatives and persons who are close to
suicide subjects. Furthermore, it has been widely demonstrated that
the loss of a subject due to suicide may be one of the most distress-
ing events that may occur in mental health professionals resulting in
several negative consequences [ . . . ].
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
64 | CH APTER 1
cause collateral damage and harm to others. Some authors use terms such
as survivors to refer to the relatives and friends of suicidal people, depicting
suicidality as something unthinkable and violent. In anti-oppressive social
movements/fields of study, we usually refer to “survivors” of sexual violence,
parental mistreatments, war, genocide, forced psychiatric treatments, and
so on. Those who “survive” have survived something violent that should
not have happened in the first place. I believe that we need to go further in
our reflections on the vocabulary we use to describe suicidality and adopt a
critical stance toward certain expressions that create the perception that sui-
cidal people are hurting their friends, relatives, health care professionals, and
society at large. Blaming the victim has not proven to be a good strategy to
help any group navigating difficult experiences. Although suicidality is not
currently officially punished or criminalized, forms of moralization are still
at work when it comes to the conceptualization of suicidality.
From representations of people who “survived” the suicide of a loved one,
to proponents of the medical model referring to the “horror” of suicidal acts
(Joiner 2005), to scholars who theorize suicide as “self-murder” and a form
of sociopolitical “killing,” suicide is often depicted as a negative and violent
act, which silences any other interpretations.26 Alternative strategies that go
beyond prevention remain relatively absent from discussions. As a result, not
only do the four models generally fail to recognize the suicidist oppression
faced by suicidal people; they also perpetuate it through what I call a suicidist
preventionist script. For example, Button (2020, 99) endorses coercive pre-
vention measures: “More broadly speaking, states that are politically serious
about suicide prevention will take steps to act on the ways that they act upon
persons: materially/economically; coercively though laws and regulations; and
discursively through norms and the perpetuation of shared social scripts.” One
of the most perverse effects of these models and their prevention goals is the
silencing of suicidal people. I argue in the following section that the voices of
suicidal people are mostly absent from these models and that these absences
prevent solidarity with them. Suicidism is like the ghost of suicidality’s theo-
rizations and prevention strategies—ubiquitous and pervasive, but never fully
visible, named, or recognized.
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 65
Unleash Power (ACT UP) to denounce the silence surrounding the HIV/
AIDS epidemic and the government inaction that led to more deaths each
week (Fung and McCaskell 2012).27 In a similar fashion, we often hear about
an epidemic of suicides. With eight hundred thousand completed suicides
each year at the international level, and many more suicidal ideations and at-
tempts (WHO 2014), public discourse insists that the phenomenon touches
almost everyone. In stark contrast to the indifference of the early years of the
HIV/AIDS crisis, we are constantly talking about suicidality—but not in a
way that invites suicidal people to “break the silence.” The slogan “Silence =
Death” may thus be resignified and redeployed for suicidality from a queer-
crip perspective. Indeed, despite the billions of dollars invested in prevention
campaigns that encourage suicidal people to reach out and speak out, these
people remain silent, and prevention strategies do not seem to be effective.28
The inefficiency of suicide prevention campaigns is evident in the fact
that most suicidal people in North America do not speak up and ask for help
(Bryan 2022; Lytle et al. 2018). Suicidology scholar David Webb (2011, 5)
openly discusses his own past suicidal experience, explaining why so many
suicidal people linger in silence before attempting suicide:
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
66 | CH APTER 1
to tell our stories, with all-of-me [sic] fully present, we need a space that is
safe. [ . . . ] All of me cannot be present when the biggest issue on my mind
at the time, my suicidal thoughts, are denied, rejected, or avoided” (emphasis
in the original). Stefan (2016, 107–108), who has interviewed many suicidal
subjects, concludes that suicidal people will not reveal their wishes to anyone
when they are determined to achieve their goal:
Statistics confirm this reality: Suicidal people hide to end their lives.31
Testimonials from suicidal people also confirm this reality (Krebs 2022).
For example, Cortez Wright (2018), a self-identified Black fat nonbinary
queer femme, shows how quickly suicidal people learn how to lie and “shut
up” about their suicidal ideation to avoid negative consequences, particularly
when they belong to marginalized communities: “I called a suicide-preven-
tion hotline, not quite realizing that sometimes ‘suicide prevention’ looks like
emergency vehicles and mandatory hospital stays when all you want, all you
need, is to talk. Making mostly false promises of personal safety, I ended the
phone call and learned to shut up about wanting to die.” This concealment
is particularly the case for those who live, like Wright, at the intersection of
many oppressions, since the interlocking effects of suicidism with racism,
heterosexism, cisgenderism, ableism, and so on have huge consequences on
their lives. As LeMaster (2022, 2) states, “I have been suicidal for most of my
life [ . . . ]. From this early age, I learned to mask suicidality and to re-route
those ‘bad feelings’ toward things ‘normal kids’ enjoyed [ . . . ]. The prescrip-
tion to be/come ‘normal’ (read: to embody the trappings of White cishetero-
sexist ableism), as a suicidal mixed-race Asian/White trans femme, simply
intensified the desire to disappear [ . . . ].” Research projects on innovative
programs to support suicidal people, such as discharged in Australia, which
offers peer support for trans people and guarantees a safe space to discuss
suicidality without the preoccupation of clinical forced interventions, also
support such statements (Radford, Wishart, and Martin 2019).
Suicidal people do not speak because they fear the negative consequences
of doing so in a suicidist environment. Indeed, as empirical research shows,
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 67
suicidal people, like those considered “mad” and “crazy,” are institutional-
ized/incarcerated and drugged against their will, excluded from insurance
programs, are not hired for new jobs or fired from their current ones, are
expelled from university campuses, have their parenting rights revoked, are
seen as incapable of sound judgment and consenting to health care, and are
subject to other unfair treatments.32 To create safer spaces in which suicidal
people can express themselves, one of the first and most important steps is to
acknowledge the systemic oppression they experience and the microaggres-
sions they face. Without this recognition, a safer space is moot. Just as “safer
spaces” for disabled people that would deny the existence of ableism could
not be considered safe, safer spaces for suicidal people that ignore suicidism
and its various ramifications, such as its injunction to live and to futurity, are
not spaces that invite suicidal people to openly discuss their experiences. Al-
though some authors have suggested that an open-minded approach allowing
suicidal subjects to speak freely may be an effective method of prevention,33
the fact that such an approach has the ultimate goal of preventing as many
suicides as possible paradoxically sends the message that suicide is always a
bad choice. In sum, a suicidist preventionist script is at work in the various
models of suicidality, including the social justice approach. As scholars Lisa
M. Wexler and Joseph P. Gone (2016, 65) state in the volume Critical Suici-
dology, “The need and desire for effective suicide prevention is uncontested.
How to practice this best is the question.” It is exactly this “uncontested”
truth about the necessity of prevention that I question in this book, arguing
that the suicidist preventionist script relies on unexamined assumptions per-
ceived as truths that force suicidal subjects into silence.
Indeed, suicidal people are encouraged to share their emotions and sui-
cidal ideation but are quickly discouraged from pursuing any reflections that
would legitimize suicide as a valid option. In other words, distress, suicidal-
ity, and suicidal ideation may be explored, but suicide itself as an act remains
taboo. As a result, suicidal people must live and die in secrecy. Furthermore,
whatever explanations suicidal people may provide to justify their wish to
die are deemed irrational or illegitimate and construed as wishes that must
be eradicated through medical, psychological, or sociopolitical remedies. As
journalist Graeme Bayliss (2016) argues, suicidal people like him are in a
lose-lose situation regarding their self-determination and competence34 to
make decisions: “I don’t want to live, but the very fact that I don’t want to live
means I can’t possibly consent to die.” This silencing is especially paradoxical
in relation to contemporary discourses on suicidality and suicide prevention
campaigns, such as “Speak Up, Reach Out,” “Let’s Talk about It,” or “Let’s
Talk,” which urge suicidal people to share their thoughts. In other words,
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
68 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 69
I take sincere issue with the rapid dismissal of suicidal people’s perspec-
tives and voices in theorizations about their realities; such an attitude would
be considered offensive if similar discourses were held about women and the
irrelevance of their first-person accounts regarding women’s issues. Dariusz
Galasiński (2017, 174), who analyzes suicide notes from a critical suicidology
perspective, contends that sometimes such notes can be “deceptive, manipu-
lative or at least strategic [ . . . ] [and] be the last opportunity to score one, to
take revenge, to get one’s own back.” Galasiński rightly points out that sui-
cide notes, like any other texts, are not necessarily transparent and can have
“hidden” (175) agendas. While such notes should not be considered simple
truths, it is equally important not to dismiss the value of suicidal people’s
voices in their final attempts to communicate their reality. We should not
override their messages by filtering them through a suicidist lens of interpre-
tation. In other words, although we cannot take for granted that such mes-
sages tell the entire “truth,” we should refrain from imposing our own vision
on those notes.
Third, a more subtle form of oppression that contributes to the relative
absence of suicidal people’s voices in discussions around suicidality consists
in speaking for or in the name of suicidal people. Linda Martín Alcoff discusses
the importance of questioning the circumstances and ways in which we speak
for others. Without reducing the debates surrounding these issues to iden-
tity politics, and without trying to police who should be allowed to speak
in the name of others, Alcoff (1991, 24) proposes “four sets of interrogatory
practices” to guide ethical and respectful practices when speaking for, or in
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
70 | CH APTER 1
the name of, marginalized groups. My comment is less about who should
be allowed to speak about suicidality and more about how sometimes some
scholars discuss suicidality for or in the name of suicidal people. Fascinat-
ingly, even in a field characterized by critical thinking and a commitment to
anti-oppressive approaches, specialists of all kinds (e.g., scholars, health care
professionals, activists) often feel entitled to speak in the name of suicidal
people, having had little or no dialogue with the people concerned. For ex-
ample, most of the contributions to the two key edited collections highlight-
ing the social justice model, Suicide and Social Justice and Critical Suicidology,
are written by people who do not publicly self-identify as suicidal, despite the
editors’ stated aim to include “first-person perspectives” (Button and Marsh
2020, 10) and “the contributions of [ . . . ] those with lived experience of sui-
cidality” (White et al. 2016b, 9). In Critical Suicidology, only two contribu-
tions in the section “Insider Perspectives” constitute first-person voices of ex-
suicidal people, out of a total of thirteen chapters in the volume. Not only are
the majority of the contributions in this volume supplied by “outsiders,” but
giving priority to ex-suicidal people rather than to those who are currently
suicidal is an epistemological choice that influences the reflections presented
in the book.38 Despite the fact that some of the editors of this volume sensi-
tively insist in their own work on the importance of hearing directly from the
people primarily concerned by suicidality, the volume as it stands does not
include the voices of self-identified suicidal people. To use an analogy, if an
edited volume on trans health mainly featured authors publicly identifying
as cisgender, and the insider perspectives in the book were written by social
workers intervening with trans people, parents of trans people, and ex-trans
(or detrans) people, I would question the erasure of trans people’s voices. This
example is but one of the limits of current critical suicidology; while many
scholars sincerely want to invite more people into the conversation, the power
relations between suicidal and nonsuicidal people often remain intact.
To increase the number of first-person voices in critical suicidology, a few
researchers have begun to examine suicide notes from completed suicides.39
This groundbreaking approach provides key information about suicidality
from an insider perspective. While I applaud these initiatives, often emerg-
ing from historical perspectives, it would also seem beneficial to pay more
attention to these voices while people are still alive.40 In sum, in all four
models of suicidality, including the social justice model, the preventionist
goal raises the question of “Why suicide?” to answer the question of “How
can we prevent it?” The simplest solution would be to change the approach
focused on prevention to one focused on accompaniment and to ask suicidal
people the following questions: What are the biggest barriers and difficulties
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 71
you face? How can we help you? Surprisingly, most scholars still do not fol-
low the trend initiated by researchers studying people’s suicide notes in order
to place the voices of the people most concerned at the center of that field of
knowledge. While a few have started to do so, more work needs to be done.
While Marsh does not theorize suicidism and therefore does not say that
an analysis of madness would be incomplete without reference to suicidality,
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
72 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 73
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
74 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 75
live a long life and enjoy living it?” I believe that some, if not most, suicidal
people might answer this question positively. I contend that the wish for a
cure to suicidality is not necessarily suicidist, particularly not when coming
from the suicidal person, but it needs to be resituated in the broader context
of how suicidality is almost always framed as something to fix. Therefore,
even though some suicidal people want to be “fixed,” the assumption that all
suicidal people would answer affirmatively or, as McRuer says, to “assume in
advance that we all agree” is problematic. For many people, it is simply in-
comprehensible that someone could answer, “No, thanks, I don’t want to be
cured. I don’t want to be fixed. I don’t want to wait for the social revolution
that will eradicate the oppression that makes me suffer. . . . I just want to die
now. I have lived enough. I don’t care if my life is over. This is what I want.”
Like the Deaf, disabled, Mad, and crip people who have told and continue
to tell us that they don’t want the “ideal solutions” offered by mainstream
societies (e.g., cochlear implants, cures, or treatments) but instead want their
voices, perspectives, needs, and claims to be respected and supported (Clare
2009, 2017), suicidal people should not have preconceived solutions devised
by those who do not experience their reality imposed upon them. Further-
more, as Alison Kafer (2013, 29) mentions, by “focusing always on the better
future, we divert our attention from the here and now.” By insisting on the
promising futurity of suicidal people, we paradoxically erase their future as
some of them would like it to be (i.e., ended) and dismiss their voices, con-
cerns, perspectives, and wishes of nonfuturity. Following McRuer’s (2006,
10) statement on “ability trouble,” in the spirit of Judith Butler’s (1990) “gen-
der trouble,” I argue that suicidal people’s voices and claims, in this context,
pose a “life trouble” by unmasking compulsory aliveness imposed upon all
human beings. Additionally, as McRuer (2006, 31) contends about the en-
twined dimensions of compulsory heterosexuality and compulsory able-bod-
iedness, I argue that compulsory aliveness and compulsory able-bodiedness
and able-mindedness are deeply intertwined.
Extending Sara Ahmed’s (2010) and Ann Cvetkovich’s (2012) arguments
on the deleterious effects on marginalized groups of the injunction to happi-
ness, I believe that we should analyze the impacts of the injunction to live and
to futurity and of compulsory aliveness on suicidal people, including those
who live at the nexus of multiple oppressions.47 Their effects are pervasive and
invasive, as evidenced by the treatments forced on suicidal people. Although
Mad scholars have not discussed the forced psychiatric treatments imposed
specifically on suicidal people (with the exception of Burstow 1992), the long
legacy of Mad activism and scholarship denouncing forced treatments for
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
76 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 77
ries (Battin 2015), despite the predominance of the preventionist script. For
example, Nelly Arcan (2004, 2008), a Canadian author and columnist who
died by suicide in 2009, endorses a position on suicide that differs from those
depicted so far. Arcan envisions suicide as a radical liberty, echoing a philo-
sophical view that has been expressed throughout history by philosophers
and writers, such as Simon Critchley (2019), who offers a nonmoralizing
view on suicide as a freedom and a choice that should not be condemned.
History is replete with philosophers (e.g., Seneca, Nietzsche, and Sartre) for
whom suicide was a possibility under specific circumstances or philosophical
schools of thought, such as libertarian or existentialist, which defend suicide
as a liberty or a right (Cholbi 2011; Marsh 2010b, 2016; Tierney 2006, 2010).
As philosopher Michael Cholbi (2017, section 3.4) contends, the right to
suicide is generally perceived as a right of noninterference instead of a right
involving active obligations and duties from others:
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
78 | CH APTER 1
the only available act of resistance is suicide.” Foucault also believes, beyond
this individual possibility of resisting power relations, that suicide could be
collectivized. Taylor (2014, 19) writes:
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 79
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
80 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 81
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
82 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 83
choice and decision, terms she uses abundantly in her book.55 Like Szasz, she
adopts a (neo)liberal and individualist approach,56 despite her repeated call
for structural approaches and community-led initiatives regarding suicide
prevention. She, like Szasz, uses the analogy of abortion and errs on the side
of private and individual actions and negative rights rather than universal
access to abortion (85, 246–247). Stefan believes that, like abortion, suicide
should not be medicalized but be a choice for individuals. But contrary to
her belief that access to abortion should be facilitated, Stefan believes that we
should limit access to the means to end one’s life.
Therefore, while insisting on the importance of destigmatizing suicide
and reducing fears around discussing suicidality, Stefan (240) paradoxically
states that one of the most effective factors in suicide prevention remains fear.
To facilitate suicide would be to encourage suicide, making it too easy to
complete. She even sometimes argues in favor of forms of criminalization: “It
[author’s position] would not preclude a society from banning or criminaliz-
ing suicide, attempted suicide, or assisted suicide. [ . . . ] Nor does it preclude
involuntary commitment for suicidality” (51). To prevent as many suicides
as possible, Stefan critiques current ineffective, coercive prevention strategies
and calls for the development of a “public health approach” (468) comprising
diverse social policies and multisectoral strategies. She contends that current
prevention strategies are probably producing more deaths by suicide than
they prevent because they shut suicidal people down instead of inviting them
to speak openly. She hopes that by destigmatizing suicide and diminishing
the forms of discrimination suicidal people face, we will create safer spaces
to allow people to share their feelings. She insists that prevention strategies,
which could include a variety of methods, such as spiritual intervention, peer
support, and limiting access to the means for suicide, should be based on
“human connection and patient, caring perseverance” (451).
In the “unified field theory of suicide” she offers in her conclusion, Ste-
fan argues that assistance in dying or in completing suicide should be illegal
(496) and that people should be helped to live and not to die (495):
People should have their own decisions about life and death respect-
ed, but they should get help, too—not help to die, but help to change
their lives into lives worth living. For the most part, [suicidal people]
know what they need: to stay in school, to get support taking care
of their children, to be taught a new perspective to frame their prob-
lems and solve them, to get a bit of a break and some rest, and to have
a community that sticks by them for the long, long haul, to have
someone listen. They know what they don’t need: involuntary hos-
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
84 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 85
Chapter 5. In this respect, my thesis differs radically from the positions of the au-
thors presented in this chapter so far. The notion of suicidism I develop here from
an anti-oppressive approach aims not only to critique and denounce the oppression
suicidal people face but also to end their oppression through structural remedies
and sociopolitical, legal, medical, economic, and epistemic transformations.
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
86 | CH APTER 1
that the only thing he is suggesting is an improved process for screening and
distinguishing different types of suicidal people to improve current suicide
prevention strategies.
On another note, in a post on the now-closed HuffPost Contributor plat-
form and titled “How Being Black & Queer Made Me Unapologetically Sui-
cidal,” activist/scholar T. Anansi Wilson (2016) situates their depression and
desire for death as resulting from systemic forms of violence and structural
oppressions, including racism, classism, and heterosexism. Wilson affirms that
living, or living in sufficiently decent conditions, is a privilege that margin-
alized groups lack. Like authors who approach suicide from a social justice
perspective, Wilson frames suicide as a form of self-murder resulting from the
slow death imposed on marginalized groups. Yet contrary to many proponents
of the social justice model who inscribe their work in a preventionist script,
Wilson (2016, para. 7) contends that suicide could become the queer action
par excellence, a revolutionary act of rebellion against oppressive systems:
Wilson invites us to think about how, in this colonialist, racist, and capi-
talist culture in which some bodies are disposable, suicide could be concep-
tualized as an individual and collective form of resistance to the commodi-
fication and exploitation of the bodies and lives of marginalized groups. As
we can see from the excerpt, the author of this post does not romanticize
suicide but offers an alternative view on suicide, one that goes beyond its
dominant conceptualization as a bad choice for marginalized subjects. Al-
though Wilson adopts an anti-oppressive approach, the conceptualization of
suicide as a revolutionary act still relies partially on an individualist notion
of choice. Wilson’s work is not apolitical—quite the contrary—but, in their
text, death by suicide remains a private action, not one that entails positive
rights for suicidal people. In the spirit of the feminist tradition, I believe that
the personal is political and that the act of suicide should never be seen as
an individual decision to be enacted alone; rather, it needs to be collectiv-
ized and politicized—not only to reveal the connections between suicidality
and sociopolitical structures but also to develop accountable and collective
responses to suicidal people, as I hope to do here.
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 87
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
88 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 89
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
90 | CH APTER 1
Going even further, I would suggest that current “well-meant acts” to-
ward suicidal people, be they theorizing suicidality, preventing suicidality, or
helping suicidal people—regardless of which model of suicidality is used—
often represent subtle (and sometimes not too subtle) forms of suicidism, a
type of violence with deep roots and negative consequences in the lives of
suicidal people. In other words, to paraphrase Medina, it could be shocking
to hear that suicide prevention is often ineffective and counterproductive, as
it is the source of the problem it tries to eradicate. It is difficult to understand
from a suicidist gaze that the well-intended acts meant to prevent suicidal
people from taking their lives are experienced by suicidal people as traumatic
and violent. When discussing my thesis and arguments about suicidality with
various audiences, I am often confronted with the following reality: While
people adhere quickly and almost unanimously to my opening argument
critiquing current models of suicidality and prevention strategies that fail
suicidal people, many resist my argument that we need to support suicidal
people in their quest for death. Indeed, most of my interlocutors are astound-
ed by the cruel treatment and forms of discrimination suicidal people face
and are outraged to learn about the difficult reality of being a suicidal person
in a suicidist society. In that sense, the majority of my interlocutors easily accept
my argument about the existence of suicidism. My theoretical framework on
suicidism has even recently attracted the attention of many scholars,60 lead-
ing organizations, associations, and groups working in the field of suicide
prevention, demonstrating that part of my thesis is increasingly recognized,
even by those endorsing a preventionist stance. However, people are quite re-
luctant when it comes to my subsequent argument about developing an account-
able response to ending suicidism that would involve positive rights as well as
social policies, accompaniment measures, and support for suicidal people. Many
come to see me after conference presentations to tell me that, while they ad-
here to my theory and they believe that it would be coherent and logical for
them to support suicidal people in a way similar to how they support other
marginalized groups, they are “blocked” at the affective level. The experi-
ence of having suicidal thoughts themselves, having a loved one who died by
suicide, or thinking about accompanying a loved one in their suicide makes
people uncomfortable. A recognition of the oppression suicidal people expe-
rience has started to emerge in the public sphere, but, simultaneously, there
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 91
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
92 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 93
compulsory aliveness were not available to help make sense of the suicidal
experience outside the preventionist script. Even when suicidal people suc-
ceed in theorizing their realities outside the dominant suicidist framework,
nonsuicidal people, health care professionals, and various activists/scholars
practice “willful hermeneutical ignorance” (Pohlhaus 2012, 715), which con-
sists of rejecting the new ideas, perspectives, and conceptual tools elaborated
by suicidal people. In this case, willful hermeneutical ignorance would in-
volve denying or dismissing the importance of structural suicidism and its
negative impacts on suicidal people. It could also consist of delegitimizing the
requests made by some suicidal people—for example, for suicide-affirmative
health care—on the pretext that they are too mentally incompetent or too
alienated by oppressive systems to decide for themselves. Third, hermeneuti-
cal injustice is partly founded on suicidal subjects’ experience of hermeneu-
tical marginalization. As demonstrated earlier, suicidal people are not (or
rarely) invited to contribute to knowledge construction on suicidality, both
in suicidology and in critical suicidology. This marginalization makes the
theorizing of suicidist oppression even more challenging for suicidal people,
who are often excluded from spaces and venues where we critically reflect
on suicidality. Hermeneutical marginalization feeds hermeneutical injustice,
and hermeneutical injustice accentuates hermeneutical marginalization.
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
94 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 95
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
96 | CH APTER 1
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
S uicidism | 97
This content downloaded from 113.211.211.90 on Mon, 27 Nov 2023 05:43:16 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms