Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Public Economics

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 538

Public Economics

Gareth D. Myles

October 2001
ii
Contents

Introduction xiii

I Foundations 1
1 Intro duction 3
1.1 Public economics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
1.2 Motivation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5
1.3 E¢ciency versus equity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
1.4 Information . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7
1.5 Methodology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
1.6 Preview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9
1.7 Public sector income and expenditure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
1.8 Notation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16

2 General Equilibrium and Welfare Economics 19


2.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
2.2 The Arrow-Debreu economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
2.2.1 The institutional framework . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
2.2.2 Commodities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
2.2.3 Consumers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22
2.2.4 Producers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25
2.2.5 Equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
2.2.6 Walras’ law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28
2.2.7 Normalizations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
2.2.8 Relaxation of strict convexity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30
2.2.9 Existence of equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32
2.2.10 Analysis of policy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33
2.2.11 Core of the economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
2.2.12 Net trades . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37
2.3 Welfare properties of competitive equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . . 38
2.3.1 Basic de…nitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
2.3.2 The First Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
2.3.3 The Second Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41

iii
iv CONTENTS

2.4 A critical appraisal . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45


2.4.1 Lump-sum transfers and taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
2.4.2 The institutional assumptions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
2.4.3 Pareto optimality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
2.5 Interpersonal comparisons and social welfare . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
2.5.1 Interpersonal comparability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
2.5.2 Social choice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
2.5.3 Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function . . . . . . . . . 58
2.6 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59

3 Topics in Measurement 61
3.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61
3.2 The measurement of income . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62
3.3 Equivalence scales . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63
3.3.1 Minimum needs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 64
3.3.2 Engel and Rothbarth . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 64
3.3.3 Prais and Houthakker . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67
3.3.4 Barten . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67
3.3.5 General case . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69
3.3.6 In practice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 71
3.4 The measurement of inequality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72
3.4.1 Basic de…nitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 73
3.4.2 Statistical measures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 74
3.4.3 Statistical measures and welfare . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78
3.4.4 Generalised Lorenz Curves . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82
3.4.5 Welfare-theoretic indices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 83
3.4.6 Axiomatic inequality measures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 86
3.4.7 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 88
3.5 The measurement of poverty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 88
3.5.1 Relative or absolute? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 89
3.5.2 The poverty line . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 90
3.5.3 Standard measures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 90
3.5.4 Axiomatic approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91
3.5.5 Variable poverty line . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95
3.6 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95

II Analysis in the competitive model 97


4 Commodity Taxation 99
4.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99
4.2 Methodology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100
4.3 The Ramsey rule . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101
4.3.1 The economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101
4.3.2 Derivation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102
4.3.3 Interpretation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104
CONTENTS v

4.3.4 Implications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106


4.3.5 Inverse elasticities rule . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 107
4.4 Extension to many-households . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108
4.4.1 The optimal tax rule . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108
4.4.2 Reduction to the Ramsey rule . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111
4.4.3 A cautionary note . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 112
4.5 Numerical results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113
4.5.1 Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113
4.5.2 Further results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 116
4.6 Generalising the production technology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117
4.7 Untaxed goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121
4.8 Uniform taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 124
4.9 Production e¢ciency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126
4.10 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 129

5 Income Taxation 131


5.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 131
5.2 The Mirrlees economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 132
5.2.1 The optimisation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 132
5.2.2 Basic structure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 133
5.2.3 The structure of utility . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 134
5.2.4 Self-selection . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 138
5.3 Characterisation of optimal tax function . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 140
5.3.1 The general problem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 140
5.3.2 Linear taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141
5.3.3 Nonlinear taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 144
5.3.4 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 153
5.4 Numerical results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 153
5.4.1 Simulations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154
5.4.2 Choice of speci…cation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 156
5.5 Extensions and omissions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 159
5.5.1 Income and commodity taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 160
5.5.2 Omissions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 162
5.6 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 163

6 Policy Reform 165


6.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165
6.2 The reform problem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165
6.2.1 Productive feasibility . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 166
6.2.2 Improving reforms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 169
6.3 Characterising possibilities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171
6.3.1 Solution via Theorems of the Alternative . . . . . . . . . 171
6.3.2 Geometric analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 172
6.3.3 Informational requirements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 176
6.4 Productive e¢ciency and maximising reforms . . . . . . . . . . . 177
6.4.1 The possibility of ine¢ciency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 178
vi CONTENTS

6.4.2 Interpretation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180


6.5 Lump-sum taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 181
6.6 The inverse optimum . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 182
6.6.1 Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 183
6.6.2 Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 184
6.7 Marginal social cost of taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186
6.7.1 Derivation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 187
6.7.2 Empirical application . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 188
6.8 Political Constraints . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 188
6.9 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191

7 Risk 193
7.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 193
7.2 General equilibrium with risk . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 194
7.2.1 Risk in the Arrow-Debreu economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . 194
7.2.2 E¢ciency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 196
7.2.3 Including time . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 197
7.2.4 Complete markets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 198
7.2.5 Comments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 199
7.3 Private and social attitudes to risk . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 200
7.3.1 Private attitudes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 200
7.3.2 Social attitudes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 202
7.3.3 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208
7.4 Household choice and taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208
7.4.1 Wealth taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 209
7.4.2 Income tax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 212
7.4.3 Imperfect loss o¤sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 214
7.4.4 Generalisations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 216
7.5 Labour supply and occupational choice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217
7.5.1 Labour supply . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217
7.5.2 Occupational choice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 218
7.6 Optimal taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 221
7.6.1 Private risk . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 221
7.6.2 Aggregate risk . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 224
7.7 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226

8 Corporate Taxation 227


8.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 227
8.2 Taxation of the …rm . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 228
8.2.1 Input and output taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 228
8.2.2 Pro…t tax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229
8.2.3 Personal taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 230
8.2.4 Why tax the corporation? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 230
8.3 Tax incidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 231
8.3.1 Tax incidence in the Harberger economy . . . . . . . . . . 231
8.3.2 Extensions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 237
CONTENTS vii

8.3.3 Taxation and …nance . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 240


8.3.4 Systems of corporate and personal taxation . . . . . . . . 241
8.3.5 Finance and investment with certainty . . . . . . . . . . . 242
8.3.6 Uncertainty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 249
8.4 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 254

III Relaxing the Assumptions 255


9 Public Goods 257
9.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 257
9.2 De…nitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258
9.2.1 Pure public goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258
9.2.2 Impure public goods and congestion . . . . . . . . . . . . 259
9.3 Optimal provision . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 259
9.3.1 Pure public good . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 260
9.3.2 Free disposal . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 262
9.3.3 With congestion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 262
9.3.4 Public input . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 263
9.4 Personalised prices and the Lindahl equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . 264
9.4.1 Simple model . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 265
9.4.2 A general treatment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 267
9.4.3 Core equivalence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 270
9.4.4 Cost-share equilibria . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 271
9.4.5 Comments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 272
9.5 Private provision of public good . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 272
9.5.1 Equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273
9.5.2 Pareto improvements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 275
9.5.3 Quantity of provision . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 276
9.5.4 The number of households . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 277
9.5.5 Invariance results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 279
9.5.6 Alternative formulations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 280
9.5.7 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 282
9.6 Finance by taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 282
9.6.1 Identical consumers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 282
9.6.2 Di¤erentiated households . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 286
9.6.3 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 287
9.6.4 De…nitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 288
9.6.5 Dominant strategies . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 289
9.6.6 Nash equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 294
9.6.7 Bayesian equilibria . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 296
9.6.8 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 296
9.7 Experimental evidence and market data . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297
9.7.1 Experimental evidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297
9.7.2 Market data . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 300
9.8 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 301
viii CONTENTS

10 Externalities 303
10.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 303
10.2 Externalities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 304
10.2.1 De…nitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 304
10.2.2 Representation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 305
10.3 Market ine¢ciency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 306
10.3.1 Equilibrium and ine¢ciency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 306
10.3.2 Pareto irrelevant externalities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 308
10.4 The Coase theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 309
10.4.1 The Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 309
10.4.2 Markets for externalities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 311
10.4.3 Non-existence of markets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 313
10.4.4 Bargaining . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 316
10.4.5 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 320
10.5 Welfare-improving changes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 320
10.5.1 Local results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 321
10.5.2 Global results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 323
10.6 Corrective taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 324
10.6.1 Non-uniform taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 325
10.6.2 Uniform taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 327
10.6.3 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 331
10.7 Tradeable licenses . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 331
10.7.1 Certain costs and bene…ts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 332
10.7.2 Prices versus quantities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 333
10.7.3 Nonlinear pricing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 335
10.8 Internalisation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 335
10.9 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 336

11 Imperfect Competition 337


11.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 337
11.2 Imperfect competition and general equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . 338
11.2.1 Objective and subjective demand . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 338
11.2.2 Price normalisations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 339
11.2.3 The economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 340
11.3 Imperfect competition and welfare . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 343
11.3.1 Failure of Pareto optimality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 343
11.3.2 Measures of welfare loss . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 344
11.4 Commodity taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 346
11.4.1 Tax incidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 347
11.4.2 Optimal taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 351
11.5 Ad valorem and speci…c taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 357
11.5.1 Tax incidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 357
11.6 Optimal combinations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 359
11.7 Production e¢ciency and the taxation of labour . . . . . . . . . 362
11.7.1 Production e¢ciency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 363
11.7.2 Taxation of labour . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 366
CONTENTS ix

11.8 Other forms of regulation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 367


11.9 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 368

12 Tax Evasion 371


12.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 371
12.2 The extent of tax evasion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 371
12.3 Evasion as a decision with risk . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 373
12.4 Optimal auditing and punishment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 376
12.5 Tax evasion and labour supply . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 377
12.5.1 Labour supply . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 378
12.5.2 Allocation of hours . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 378
12.6 Public goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 380
12.6.1 The valuation of public funds . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 381
12.6.2 Congestible public goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 382
12.7 Empirical evidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 385
12.8 Honesty and social norms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 387
12.9 Optimal auditing with an independent revenue service . . . . . . 389
12.10Tax evasion by …rms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 392
12.10.1 Competitive …rms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 392
12.10.2 Imperfect competition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 394
12.11Optimal taxation with evasion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 395
12.11.1 Commodity taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 395
12.11.2 Income taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 397
12.12Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 397

IV Introducing Real Time 399


13 Overlapping Generations Economies 401
13.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 401
13.2 Overlapping generation exchange economies . . . . . . . . . . . . 402
13.2.1 The Samuelson economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 403
13.2.2 Overlapping generations as Arrow-Debreu economies . . . 405
13.2.3 Existence of equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 407
13.2.4 Money, dynamics and indeterminacy . . . . . . . . . . . . 412
13.2.5 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 418
13.3 An aggregate production economy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 419
13.3.1 Consumers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 419
13.3.2 Production . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 420
13.3.3 Equilibrium . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 421
13.3.4 Steady State Solution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 424
13.3.5 Golden rules . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 425
13.3.6 Pareto optimality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 428
13.4 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 429
x CONTENTS

14 Social Security 431


14.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 431
14.2 Fully funded and pay-as-you-go . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 432
14.3 An optimal program . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 433
14.4 Some extensions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 436
14.4.1 Labour supply and retirement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 436
14.4.2 E¤ect on savings and capital . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 441
14.4.3 Ricardian equivalence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 443
14.4.4 Demographics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 445
14.5 Determination and justi…cation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 447
14.5.1 Voting equilibria . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 447
14.5.2 Altruism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 449
14.5.3 Myopia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 452
14.5.4 Uncertainty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 454
14.6 Lifetime uncertainty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 459
14.6.1 Symmetric information . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 460
14.6.2 Adverse selection . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 462
14.6.3 Moral hazard . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 466
14.7 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 467

15 Debt and Taxes 469


15.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 469
15.2 The e¤ect of debt . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 470
15.2.1 External and internal debt . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 470
15.2.2 E¤ects of debt . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 471
15.3 Optimisation of debt and lump-sum taxes . . . . . . . . . . . . . 477
15.3.1 Lump-sum taxation and debt . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 478
15.3.2 Optimal lump-sum taxation and debt . . . . . . . . . . . 480
15.3.3 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 482
15.4 Debt neutrality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 483
15.4.1 Two special cases . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 484
15.4.2 Intergenerational altruism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 485
15.4.3 Generalisations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 490
15.5 Income and interest taxation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 492
15.6 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 496

16 References 499
Preface

This is lightly edited version of the …rst edition that has beenconverted to Tex
from Word. Since this has necessitated re-typing all of the maths, errors may
have been introduced. You are welcome to use it provided you report any typing
errors you discover to G.D.Myles@ex.ac.uk so that I can put things right.
I would also welcome any comments you may have which could improve the
second edition. I will be adding exercises and additional chapters on voting,
rent seeking, political economy, clubs and local public goods, and international
issues in taxation.

xi
xii PREFACE
Introduction

Do I really need an introduction here?

xiii
xiv INTRODUCTION
Part I

Foundations

1
Chapter 1

Introduction

1.1 Public economics


In the broadest interpretation, public economics is the study of economic policy,
with particular emphasis upon taxation. The subject therefore encompasses top-
ics as diverse as responses to market failure due to the existence of externalities
and the determination of optimal social security policies. This characterization
re‡ects an extension of the scope of public economics from its initial emphasis
upon the collection and disbursement of government revenues to its present con-
cern with all aspects of government economic intervention. The intention of this
book is to provide an introduction to the vast literature of public economics,
emphasizing the foundations upon which future research can be laid
Public economics has a long history as a discipline within economics and
many eminent economists have written on the subject. For example, Ricardo
(1817) discussed the e¤ects of public debt, the incidence of taxation in imper-
fectly competitive markets was analyzed by Cournot (1838), Edgeworth (1925)
considered the e¤ects of taxation on multi-product …rms and Pareto (1909) set
out the foundations for making social decisions. The explanation for this in-
terest in public economics is no doubt contained in the close connection of the
analysis with policy and application, which are the ultimate inspiration of most
economists. Exposing a theoretical construction to policy analysis also high-
lights its value and provides a test of its relevance. However, it is also true that
before a good policy can be designed an adequate theory must be developed.
One of the challenges of public economics is that much of the subject area is
still in its infancy with considerable work still to be done.
Although a number of partitions could be used to break down the subject
matter of public economics into convenient portions, the most instructive divi-
sion is between that of determining the e¤ects of alternative policies and that
of determining the optimal policy. This division represents the distinction be-
tween the exercise in positive economics involved in calculating the change in
equilibrium caused by the introduction of a policy and the normative exercise

3
4 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

of evaluating, in terms of welfare, the outcome of policy. To achieve the …rst


objective requires a theory that describes how economic agents choose their ac-
tions and how these actions are a¤ected by changes in policy. The individual
agents must then be combined to form an economy and a theory of equilibrium
provided for this economy. The evaluation of policy, and the choice of optimal
policy, necessitates the speci…cation of an objective for the policy maker that
is capable of providing a measure of the performance of each policy based on
the relevant features of the equilibrium resulting from the policy. This evalua-
tion process represents an application of normative economics. The success of
public economics has largely followed from the systematic application of these
methods.
The theory that is described in the following chapters has developed mainly
since 1970 and has built upon developments in microeconomics, macroeco-
nomics, general equilibrium theory and game theory. One of its characteristic
features is the use of duality techniques to allow problems to be phrased in the
manner most amenable to solution. These techniques permit optimization ex-
ercises to be phrased in terms of the natural choice variables. In this context,
the work of Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) was of fundamental importance in
introducing these methods into public economics. The use of duality theory has
also allowed many problems to be studied with great generality and has often
overcome the need to impose restrictive sets of assumptions. A second charac-
teristic feature is the consistent use of general equilibrium theory to provide a
rigorous foundation for the policy analysis. A general equilibrium analysis of
policy captures both the direct e¤ects of policy and the secondary e¤ects. As
the latter may well outweigh the former, a convincing policy analysis cannot
be conducted except within a general equilibrium context. These underlying
methods of duality and general equilibrium provide the cohesion to what at
…rst glance may appear to be a number of disparate topics.
An emerging trend in the public economics literature has been the use of nu-
merical methods. These have taken the form of both simulations of economies
in order to test their behavior and the evaluation of policy proposals using em-
pirical data. The latter technique indicates a promising convergence between
theory and application and is clearly a direction in which the subject will con-
tinue to move. Although this book is primarily intended to be a text on the
theory of public economics, numerical results are given prominence due to their
obvious importance.
The dominant setting for the analysis of public economics is within the
mixed economy so that individual decisions are respected but the government
intervenes to a¤ect these choices. The design of policy can then be interpreted
as the manipulation of individual choices by the choice of policy parameters so
as to arrive at an equilibrium preferred to that which would arise in the absence
of policy. This makes the results of the studies applicable to most developed
economies and concurs with the present ascendancy of such a form of economic
organization. To provide a benchmark from which to judge the outcome of the
economy under alternative policies the perfectly controlled command economy
with an omniscient planner is often employed. Naturally, this usage of the
1.2. MOTIVATION 5

command economy implies no claim that such perfect control is possible, or


even desirable.

1.2 Motivation
The motivation for the study of public economics follows naturally from the
observation that unregulated economic activity does not lead to a socially opti-
mal outcome. At a very basic level, an economy could not function e¤ectively
if there were no contract laws since this would inhibit satisfactory exchange. In
addition, although the anarchic equilibrium that would occur without contracts
may be in the core of the economy, it need not be particularly stable (Bush and
Mayer (1974)). It must therefore be accepted that no economy could operate
without law enforcement and that in order for organized economic activity to
take place, there must be a clearly de…ned and enforced set of contract laws.
These laws cannot be policed free of cost. There is also a need for the enforce-
ment of more general criminal laws and for the provision of a means of defence
for the nation. These are also costly activities.
Consequently, even the minimal requirements of the enforcement of contract
and criminal laws and the provision of defence need the collection of revenue
to provide the required …nance. This is the case whether these services are
provided by the state or by private sector organizations. The coordination of
the collection of revenue and the provision of services to ensure the attainment
of e¢cient functioning of economic activity therefore provides a natural role
for a central state in any economy that wishes to develop beyond the most
rudimentary level. In addition, this reasoning also illustrates that to achieve
even the most minimal level of e¢ciency and organization of economic activity
some unavoidable revenue requirements are generated and require …nancing.
Having determined that the organization of economic activity must generate
a revenue requirement, one aspect of the role of public economics is to determine
how this revenue can be collected at the least cost to the economy. Although
the concept of least cost has several possible interpretations, both positive and
normative, under any interpretation the aim of the economic policy design would
be that of …nding an e¢cient means of revenue collection. Such design would
involve the identi…cation of feasible policy instruments from the set of possible
policies, the choice of policy instruments to be imposed from amongst those
that are feasible and the calculation of the optimal level of each instrument.
The issue of e¢ciency in policy design is a continuing and central theme of
public economics.
Moving beyond the basic requirements for organized economic activity, it is
arguable that there are other situations where state intervention in the econ-
omy has the potential to increase welfare. Unlike the basic revenue requirements
however, there will always be a degree of contentiousness about further inter-
vention motivated on these grounds. The situations where state intervention
may be warranted can be divided into two categories: those that involve market
failure and those that do not. With market failure, the argument for consid-
6 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

ering whether intervention would be bene…cial is compelling. For example, if


economic activity generated externalities, so that there is divergence between
private and social costs and the competitive outcome is not e¢cient, it may
be felt necessary for the state to intervene to limit the ine¢ciency that results.
This latter point can also be extended to other cases of market failure such as
those connected to the existence of public goods and of imperfect competition.
Where market failure does not occur, state intervention can be motivated
by the observation that although an equilibrium may be e¢cient it need not
be optimal according to the state’s welfare criterion. Such a situation may
arise if the equilibrium of the economy is characterized by widespread poverty
and an inequitable distribution of income. In such circumstances, the level of
economic welfare as viewed by the state may well be raised by a program of
income redistribution. Similar arguments can be applied to the provision of
state education, social security programs and compulsory pension schemes. It
should be stressed that such potential increases are with respect to normative
assessments of welfare, unlike the positive criteria lying behind the concept of
economic e¢ciency.
In the cases of both market failure and welfare-motivated policies, policy
intervention concerns more than just the e¢cient collection of revenue. The
reasons for the failure of the economy to reach the optimal outcome have to be
understood and a policy that can counteract these has to be designed. It must
also be recognized that the actions of the state, and the feasible policies that it
can choose, are often restricted by the same features of the economy that make
the competitive outcome ine¢cient. In each case, policy intervention can only
be justi…ed by proving that the state can actually improve upon the market.
That it can always do so should not be taken for granted. Extending the scope
of the public economics to address such issues provides the breadth to public
economics.

1.3 E¢ciency versus equity


In conducting an economic policy the state will generally have two con‡icting
aims. On the one hand, it will aim to implement the policy with the minimum
loss to society. The use of policy will cause a loss due to the resources used in
the implementation process and from the economic distortions that the policy
will cause. Minimizing these losses is the e¢ciency aspect of policy design.
Conversely, the state may also feel that it is desirable to intervene in the economy
in order to attain a more equitable distribution of the economy’s resources. This
is often accompanied by a corresponding reduction in the degree of concern for
the aggregate level of economic activity. This motivation represents the equity
side of policy design.
Due to their distinct natures, it is inevitable that the aims of equity and
e¢ciency regularly con‡ict. It is often the case that the e¢cient policy is highly
inequitable whilst the equitable policy would introduce into the economy signif-
icant distortions and disincentives. Given this fact, the design of optimal policy
1.4. INFORMATION 7

can be seen as the process of reaching the correct trade-o¤ between equity and
e¢ciency ob jectives. This optimum trade-o¤ will depend upon the concern for
equity that is expressed in the objectives of the policy maker. In many analyses
of policy problems, the resolution of the trade-o¤ between equity and e¢ciency
is the ma jor determinant of the resulting policy program, with aspects of the
policy being attributable to one or the other. This distinction is often a helpful
way in which to think about optimality problems and their solutions. It is worth
stressing that the con‡ict between equity and e¢ciency does not always arise.
For example, in some instances of uncertainty, such as the provision of social
insurance discussed in chapter 8, the two aims of e¢ciency and equity may not
be competing.
To illustrate this discussion, a simple example of the con‡ict between eq-
uity and e¢ciency can be found in the optimal taxation of commodities. Under
assumptions that will be described later, it is e¢cient to tax goods with low
elasticities of demand, as shown by the well-known inverse elasticity rule, since
this introduces the least distortion into the pattern of demand. However, goods
with low elasticities of demand tend to be necessities that are consumed dispro-
portionately by less well-o¤ households. Taxing these goods highly would then
cause a proportionately greater reduction in the welfare of poor households. The
proposed tax program is therefore highly inequitable and equity criteria would
shift the taxes onto goods consumed by higher income groups. The Diamond-
Mirrlees tax rule that is developed in Chapter 5 shows how this con‡ict between
e¢ciency and equity is resolved.
In this context, it is worth adding one …nal note concerned with modelling
techniques. A standard simpli…cation that will be employed on a number of
o ccasions in this book is to work with one-consumer economies or with economies
composed of a population of identical consumers. In such economies there can
be no distributional issues, so the resulting policy recommendations are based
only on considerations of e¢ciency. This generally leads to results that can
be expressed much more clearly and precisely than would be possible if equity
considerations were present, which is of considerable assistance when an issue
is analyzed for the …rst time. In considering the practical value of such results,
the implications of introducing equity considerations must always be borne in
mind.

1.4 Information
The role of information is central to public economics. The availability of in-
formation to private agents determines the nature of the equilibrium without
policy intervention and the information set of the government determines fea-
sible policy instruments. If information de…ciencies, particularly asymmetric
information between agents in the economy, lead the market outcome to be in-
e¢cient, the state can only improve the outcome if it is not subject to the same
informational limitations.
As will be made clear in Chapter 2, the …rst-best outcome could be sustained
8 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

if the state levied lump-sum taxes that were contingent upon all economically
relevant characteristics of the agents in the economy. Naturally, some of these
characteristics will be private information and therefore not directly observable
by the state. If the state cannot induce the agents to truthfully reveal these char-
acteristics, then the lump-sum tax system that supports the …rst-best cannot
be implemented. Policy design then involves the optimal utilization of the avail-
able information. The outcome that is achieved will necessarily be second-best.
This simple example demonstrates the essential consequences of informational
restrictions and captures themes that will recur throughout the book.
Further examples are easily found. In the context of commodity taxation,
limited information prevents commodity taxes being di¤erentiated between con-
sumers. It also results in the use of an income tax levied upon the observable
income of households, rather than an ability tax on their unobservable earn-
ing potential. The optimal provision of public goods is also prevented by the
fact that the government cannot observe consumers’ willingness to pay for such
goods. The outcome in each of these cases is described in the relevant chapters.
Although asymmetries of information are at the heart of most of the analysis
that follows, their nature will rarely be made explicit. Instead, the nature of
information will be implicit in the assumptions that describe the structure of
the economies employed and the restrictions that are placed upon feasible policy
instruments. In considering results derived below, it will always be advantageous
to re‡ect upon the nature of the informational restrictions involved and the
consequences of their relaxation or strengthening.

1.5 Methodology
The method of analysis adopted within this book is invariably to consider pol-
icy within the context of a general equilibrium representation of the economy.
In Parts I to III of the book, the underlying framework is the Arrow-Debreu
economy and its extensions. The overlapping generations economy employed
in Part IV is a particular in…nite horizon version of the general formulation.
The general equilibrium perspective is maintained wherever it is feasible to do
so. This aim is not achieved in places such as when only partial equilibrium
treatments are available in the existing literature, or when a general equilibrium
treatment would only obscure the major issues.
A general equilibrium economy is undoubtedly the most appropriate frame-
work to adopt since it is the only means by which all the repercussions of a
policy may be captured. In contrast, concentration upon partial equilibrium
can lead to important consequences of policy being overlooked, particularly if
there are signi…cant adjustments in markets other than those forming the focus
of the analysis. However, partial equilibrium analysis is often useful as a means
of obtaining preliminary insights into a problem, but its limitations should never
be underestimated. Although most attention in the literature has been focused
upon competitive economies, with market imperfections are now being widely
used and policy analysis within such economies will also be considered.
1.6. PREVIEW 9

Within a general equilibrium context, changes in policy, or alternative poli-


cies, can be viewed as resulting in di¤erent equilibria for the economy. To treat
the question of optimality in policy choice, the equilibria for di¤erent policies
are contrasted via some welfare measure. The optimal policy is then de…ned as
the feasible policy yielding the greatest level of welfare. Since Pareto optimality
generally provides too incomplete a ranking of states to be of use as a guide
for policy, the welfare criterion that is used is typically a Bergson-Samuelson
social welfare function. This procedure naturally invokes questions about the
comparability of individual utilities and the formulation of welfare measures.
The analytical tools used in the book are generally fairly simple and the
mathematics rarely uses anything more di¢cult that the theory of constrained
maximization and comparative statics analysis. There are exceptions to this
rule. Separation arguments are used in Chapters 2 and 9. Chapters 6 and
15 employ the maximum principle, Chapter 7 employs a theorem of the al-
ternative and Chapter 13 touches upon nonlinear dynamic systems. Dynamic
programming is used in 15. Since a self-contained treatment of general equi-
librium analysis and welfare economics is given in Chapter 2, the economics
that is employed, but not otherwise introduced in the text, should be covered
by any advanced undergraduate or graduate course in microeconomics and in-
volves mainly standard duality results in producer and consumer theory. An
excellent source of reference for this material is Varian (1992).

1.6 Preview
Following the discussion of the methodology that will be employed, it is clear
that a necessary starting point is a review of the competitive general equilibrium
economy and the standard results of welfare economics. These represent the
content of Chapter 2. The chapter introduces the agents involved in the economy
and characterizes economic equilibrium. It also introduces a useful perspective
from which to view Walras’ law and formalizes the notion of how policy changes
are modelled. Emphasis is placed upon the institutional assumptions underlying
the competitive equilibrium economy since much of the subject matter of public
economics can be motivated by discomfort with the nature of the equilibrium
of the competitive market or by the failure of one or more of the institutional
assumptions. The Two Theorems of Welfare Economics are proved and a critical
analysis of their scope and relevance is provided. This naturally leads into a
discussion of the measurement of social welfare and the contrast between the
implications for interpersonal comparability of ordinal and cardinal utility.
In practice, if economists are to be concerned about equity it is necessary
to …nd measures that capture aspects of the distribution of welfare. Chapter
3 considers three topics that have been the subject of considerable interest.
Alternative methods of constructing equivalence scales are reviewed as a prelude
to developing measures of distribution. The measurement of poverty and of
inequality are then used to illustrate the axiomatic approach to measurement,
which speci…es the properties that an index should have and then constructs the
10 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

indices that have those properties, and the statistical approach which simply
uses readily accessible formulae. These three introductory chapters constitute
Part I of the book.
Part II is concerned with the analysis of …ve topics of fundamental impor-
tance for public economics which are conducted within the competitive economy.
Chapter 4 analyses the e¤ects of corporate taxation and the issues that need
to be taken into account in tax design. Chapters 5 and 6 consider the charac-
terization of optimal commodity and income taxes respectively. Both of these
chapters illustrate the resolution of the equity/e¢ciency trade-o¤ in the design
of policy and the consequences of government informational limitations. In ad-
dition to the theoretical analysis, the results of simulations and applications of
the methods to data are considered. The numerical results are useful since the
theoretical analysis leads only to characterizations of optimal taxes rather than
explicit solutions. Policy reform is the subject matter of Chapter 7 and the
link is drawn between the existence of improving reforms and non-optimality.
The question of production e¢ciency along the reform path is also considered.
Chapter 8 on public economics in the presence of risk completes part I I.
The focus of Part I II is upon the consequences of relaxing certain of the
institutional assumptions on which the competitive economy is based. Chapter
9 introduces public goods into the economy and contrasts the allocation that
is achieved in the private provision equilibrium with the optimal allocation.
Methods of …nancing public goods are also considered and this analysis has
close parallels with the chapter on commodity taxation. Private provision and
preference revelation are also addressed. The treatment of externalities in Chap-
ter 10 relaxes another of the institutional assumptions. It is shown why market
failure can occur and reviews alternative policy schemes designed to improve
e¢ciency. Imperfect competition and its consequences for commodity taxation
is the subject of Chapter 11. The measurement of welfare loss is discussed and
a general equilibrium economy with imperfect competition is developed. Em-
phasis is given to the incidence of taxation and the determination of optimal
taxes. A distinction is also drawn between the e¤ects of speci…c and ad valorem
taxes. Part I II is completed by Chapter 12 on tax evasion and administration.
Estimates of the size of the black economy are reviewed, the tax evasion decision
is modelled and the e¤ect of evasion and administration costs on optimal taxes
are determined.
Part IV concentrates upon intertemporal issues in public economics. The
…rst Chapter, 13, describes the overlapping generations economy that is the
main analytical tool of this part. The relationship between the overlapping
generations economy and the Arrow-Debreu economy is emphasized, as are the
di¤erent e¢ciency properties of the two economies. The concept of the Golden
rule is introduced for economies with production and capital accumulation. The
chapter also touches upon the dynamic adjustment process of the economy.
Chapter 14 analyses social security policy and relates this to the potential non-
optimality of the competitive equilibrium. Both the motivation for the existence
of social security programs and the determination of the level of bene…ts are ad-
dressed. The interaction between debt and taxation is the sub ject of Chapter
1.7. PUBLIC SECTOR INCOME AND EXPENDITURE 11

15. The e¤ects of government debt and the issue of debt neutrality are consid-
ered. Ricardian equivalence is linked to the existence of gifts and bequests. The
choice between the taxation of income and expenditure is also analyzed.

1.7 Public sector income and expenditure


The public sector plays an important role in the mixed economies of the ma jor
industrialized countries. To show quite how important, this section presents
some summary statistics concerning the size and structure of the public sector.
Whilst there are some well-recognized issues concerning the appropriate de…n-
ition of the public sector, these do not a¤ect the validity of the broad sketch
given here.
Table 1.1 shows the pattern of public sector total outlay as a percentage of
nominal GNP over the period 1978 - 1993 for seven of the major industrialized
countries from North America, Europe and Asia. For these countries, public
sector expenditure falls in the range of 30 - 55% of GNP with Japan and the
United States having the smallest public sectors and Italy and France the largest.
Even though the range is large, the public sector is signi…cant in every case.
Expenditure in Italy shows sustained growth through the period, as it does in the
U.S. but to a lesser extent. Other than these countries, the pattern is generally
one of the public sector being a constant proportion of GNP. This relative
stability over the recent past is in sharp contrast to the period of expansion of
the public sector experienced by the industrialized countries from 1890 through
to 1970.
The major implication of Table 1.1 is that it clearly justi…es the claim that
the public sector is signi…cant in the economies of the industrialized countries
and the mixed economies of these countries are characterized by substantial
government involvement. They are far from being free-market with minimal
government intervention. The size of the public sector alone is justi…cation for
the study of how it should best choose its means of revenue collection and its
allocation of expenditure. It is also worth noting that data on expenditure typ-
ically understates the full in‡uence of the public sector upon the economy. For
instance, regulations such as employment laws or safety standards infringe upon
economic activity but without generating any measurable government expendi-
ture or income.
Table 1.2 shows the proportion of Japanese government income derived from
various sources and the division of its expenditure. The chart for income shows
that direct taxation is the largest single component. Social security contribu-
tions and indirect taxation are the next largest and make fairly similar contribu-
tions to income. In terms of expenditure, social security spending is the largest
category followed by purchases of goods and services. Interest on public debt is
also a signi…cant item of expenditure.
A similar breakdown of income and expenditure is reported for the United
Kingdom in Table 1.3. Contrasted to Japan, the U.K. shows greater reliance
upon indirect taxation, with indirect taxation generating slightly more revenue
12 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

60

50
Government expenditure
United States
Japan
Germany
40
France
Italy
United Kingdom
Canada
30

20
1970 1980 1990 2000

Year

Figure 1.1: General government total outlay as % of nominal GDP

Division of income

Direct tax
Social security
Indirect taxes
Property income

Figure 1.2: Japanese Government Income 1991


1.7. PUBLIC SECTOR INCOME AND EXPENDITURE 13

Division of expenditure

Goods and services


Interest on public debt
Subsidies
Social security
Other transfers

Figure 1.3: Japanese Government Expenditure 1991

than direct taxation. The relative size of social security contributions is also
much less than in Japan. The relative sizes of the expenditure items are very
similar, although the U.K. spends more on goods and services but less on sub-
sidies. The social security item in Japan is equivalent in relative size to the
transfers in the U.K.
Tables 1.2 and 1.3 demonstrate the importance of direct and indirect tax-
ation in the collection of revenue for the U.K. and for Japan. Taken together,
these generate 73% of revenue in the U.K. and 63% in Japan. The third item of
income, social security contributions, are 17% of income in the U.K. and 27% in
Japan. These …gures support the prominence given to the design of commod-
ity taxation in chapter 5, income taxation in chapter 6 and social security in
chapter 14.
An alternative perspective on the relative importance of the three ma jor
categories of income is given in Table 1.4. This shows receipts as a percentage
of GDP for the U.S. and as an average for other OECD countries. For the U.S.,
consumption taxes are relatively less important than as shown for Japan and
the U.K. above and as against the average over OECD countries. However,
consumption tax receipts still equal over 4% of U.S. GDP. Social security taxes
raise twice the income of consumption taxes whilst income tax receipts represent
one tenth of GDP. In contrast, the OECD average shows rather more equality
between receipts from income and consumption taxes.
Table 1.5a shows the expenditure of the U.S. Federal Government broken
down into type and function, expressed as a percentage of total expenditure.
Similarly, Table 1.5b has the same breakdown for State and Local Government.
These tables reveal that the ma jor items of expenditure for Federal Government
14 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

Division of income

Direct tax
Social security
Indirect taxes
Property income

Figure 1.4: UK Government Income

Division of expenditure

Goods and services


Interest on public debt
Subsidies
Transfers

Figure 1.5: UK Government Expenditure


1.7. PUBLIC SECTOR INCOME AND EXPENDITURE 15

Figure 1.6: Comparison of Tax Yields

Other
Commercial activities
Net interest paid
Labour training
Economic development
Postal service
Transportation
Natural resources
Agriculture
Energy
Recreational and cultural
Housing and community service
Veterans benefits
Income support, social security
Health and hospitals
Education
Civilian safety
National defence
Space
International affairs
Central executive

0 10 20 30 40 50

(a) Federal Government

Figure 1.7:

are income support and social security, and defence. In contrast, the ma jor item
for State and Local Government is education followed by income support and
social security. Other than these, the most signi…cant items are the net in-
terest paid by the Federal Government and transportation and civilian safety
paid for by State and Local Government. The items can be placed into sepa-
rate categories representing the breakdown of public sector objectives: defence
expenditure is one of the minimal requirements; income support is evidence
of concern for equity; and education represents provision of a public good to
counter market failure.
Although brief, this review of statistics on the size and structure of public
sector income and expenditure has illustrated the signi…cant extent of public
sector intervention in the mixed economies of the industrialized countries. The
16 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

Other
Commercial activities
Net interest paid
Labour training
Economic development
Postal service
Transportation
Natural resources
Agriculture
Energy
Recreational and cultural
Housing and community service
Veterans benefits
Income support, social security
Health and hospitals
Education
Civilian safety
National defence
Space
International affairs
Central executive

-10 0 10 20

(b) State and Local

Figure 1.8: US State and Federal Expenditure

relative importance of alternative sources of revenue has been shown as has the
range of expenditure.

1.8 Notation
There are many symbols that have a constant meaning through the text. The
most important of these are listed below.
H number of households
m number of …rms
n number of goods
p i pre-tax price (of good i)
qi post-tax price
ti tax rate
R government revenue requirement
G public good supply
x h consumption plan (of household h)
X h consumption set
` h level of labour supply (when distinguished from other commodities)
! h initial endowment
I h lump-sum income
M h total income
- h wealth
T h lump-sum tax paid by h
1.8. NOTATION 17

® h marginal utility of income


¯ h social marginal utility of income
U h (¢) household utility function
V h (¢) indirect utility function
E h (¢) expenditure function
W (¢) social welfare function
y j production plan (of …rm j)
Y j production set
¼ j pro…t level
µ hj share of h in j
Xi aggregate demand (for good i)
Y i aggregate supply
Zi excess demand
E [¢] expectations operator
K t capital stock (in period t)
kt capital-labour ratio
rt interest rate
w t wage rate
In addition to these symbols, there are others which are more chapter-
speci…c.
The is one further notational convention that must be noted. Throughout
the text round brackets proceeded by a symbol always represent functions so
that f (x) denotes the function f of x. In contrast, square brackets denote
algebraic operations so that f [x] is read f times x. The only exception to this
rule is the expectations operator .
18 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION
Chapter 2

General Equilibrium and


Welfare Economics

2.1 Introduction
The competitive general equilibrium economy described in this chapter has been
developed over a considerable perio d of time and has been subjected to closer
study than any other form of economy. The earliest formal construction is
generally attributed to Walras (1874) and this was developed in the German
literature of the 1930s. These developments reached maturity in the seminal
contribution of Arrow and Debreu (1954) and in the monograph by Debreu
(1959); hence its common title of the Arrow-Debreu economy. The importance
of the Arrow-Debreu contribution was the demonstration that an equilibrium
existed for the economy under reasonable assumptions and the formal elabora-
tion of the welfare properties of equilibrium. This chapter provides an informal
but self-contained introduction to the Arrow-Debreu general equilibrium econ-
omy. The discussion emphasizes those aspects of the economy that are most
relevant to the study of public economics. Technical aspects of the economy
that are not strictly necessary for later analysis will be noted but, where there
is no harm from doing so, will not be discussed in detail. Formal treatments
of the issues dealt with here can be found in Arrow and Hahn (1971), Debreu
(1959) and Hildenbrand and Kirman (1988).
The Arrow-Debreu economy is studied for two primary reasons. Firstly, it
provides the analytical foundation for the economies analyzed in later chapters
which are often simpli…cations or modi…cations of the general framework. The
focus of Part I II of the book will be on the consequences of relaxing the assump-
tions on which the Arrow-Debreu economy is based so the results of this chapter
act as a benchmark from which to judge the e¤ects of the relaxation. The second
reason is that welfare properties of the economy, which are commonly known as
the Two Theorems of Welfare Economics, are used as the basis for claims con-
cerning the e¢ciency, and thus desirability, of the competitive outcome. These

19
20CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

theorems represent the formulization of Smith’s (1776) notion of the e¢ciency


of the invisible hand of competition and play a central role in welfare economics.
The First Theorem states that a competitive equilibrium is optimal, in a sense
to be made precise below, and the Second Theorem that any optimum can be
decentralized as a competitive equilibrium. An understanding of the economy
is therefore a prerequisite for appreciating the content and limitations of these
claims.
The Theorems provide the motivation for two alternative viewpoints upon
economic policy. One viewpoint would be to take the Theorems as evidence
that policy should always be attempting to move the economy as close to the
competitive ideal as possible. In this interpretation, the Theorems are seen as
prescriptive of what should be achieved. The alternative view is that the Two
Theorems provide a description of what could be achieved if the economy were
competitive and a demonstration of why it cannot, and possibly should not, be
achieved in practice. The cannot refers to assumptions of the economy that will
not be met in practice and the should not to distributional aspects of compet-
itive equilibrium. The mainstream of public economics combines parts of both
of these caricatured viewpoints. Many policy analyses take for granted the pre-
sumption that competitive behavior should be advocated and encouraged when
it leads to economic e¢ciency. However, its failings are also readily admitted
and policies designed to correct for them. Indeed, much of public economics
implicitly takes as its starting point the rejection of the practical value of the
Second Theorem.
The chapter begins by introducing the assumptions that describe the under-
lying framework of the economy and this is followed by discussions of Walras’
law, normalizations and the e¤ect of policy; all being of particular relevance for
the understanding of the techniques employed in public economics. A formal
demonstration of the Two Theorems and a critical discussion of their content
and implications is given. The criticism focuses upon the possibility of design-
ing and employing optimal lump-sum taxes, the assumptions underlying the
structure of the economy and on the limitations of the Pareto criterion. The
discussion of the Two Theorems leads naturally into a number of other basic
topics in welfare economics. The Pareto criterion is considered in detail and the
role of interpersonal comparisons of utility and the possibility of making such
comparisons are described. This is followed by a discussion of the formulation
of social welfare functions and the relation of these to the permissible extent of
interpersonal comparisons.

2.2 The Arrow-Debreu economy


This section introduces the constituent parts of the Arrow-Debreu economy,
de…nes an equilibrium and sketches a proof of existence. The role of price
normalizations and Walras’ law are emphasized for their importance in public
economics.
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 21

2.2.1 The institutional framework


The institutional framework consists of those assumptions that describe the ba-
sic structure of the economy. Included within this structure are the nature of the
agents that constitute the active participants in the economy and the descrip-
tion of the trading environment. Such assumptions need to be distinguished
from the technical assumptions (such as convexity and continuity) made upon
preferences and technology in order to prove theorems about the economy.
There are two agents in the standard Arrow-Debreu economy: consumers
(or households) and producers (or …rms). A third agent, the government, will be
included at a later stage. The households own initial endowments of goods and
have shares in …rms which yield dividend payments. They engage in trade to
maximize their satisfaction or utility. Producers use inputs to produce outputs
subject to the technological knowledge they have available. Their aim is to
maximize pro…t, which is the di¤erence between revenue and costs. All pro…ts
earned are distributed to shareholders.
It is assumed that all trade takes place at a given date. The possibility
of making contracts at the trading date for delivery at future dates allows the
introduction of time but the accounts for such contracts must be settled when
the contract is formed. Uncertainty can also be introduced by allowing contracts
to be written with delivery contingent upon the state of nature that arises, but
this will not be done formally until risk is considered in Chapter 8. More
importantly, no trade is permitted to take place except at equilibrium prices.
The essential requirement that must be satis…ed for the economy to be com-
petitive is that all agents treat prices as parametric. That is, in determining
their optimal action, the agents do not believe that their decision can a¤ect the
prices observed. Formally, this belief can only be consistent with reality when
agents are in…nitesimally small relative to the market (Aumann (1964)). Since
the economies that are considered below (with the exception of the overlap-
ping generations economy of Part IV) have a …nite number of consumers, Au-
mann’s conditions cannot be satis…ed and competitive behavior is imposed as
an assumption. The competitive assumption implies that there is no monopoly
power and hence no market distortions through price-setting. Households and
…rms are all taken to act as independent units and to interact only via the price
system. This ensures that there are no external e¤ects and no public goods.
These assumptions provide the basic framework of the Arrow-Debreu econ-
omy. They should not be viewed as immutable concepts but rather as a starting
point for the analysis. The eventual aim should be to choose the correct set of
assumptions that capture the economic reality of the situation of interest. The
analysis of Part III shows how this can be done by intro ducing external e¤ects,
public goods and imperfect competition.

2.2.2 Commodities
The concept of a commodity is central to the economy and the ‡exibility in
the de…nition of commodities gives the economy its breadth of interpretation.
22CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Commodities are simply de…ned as the set of goods that are available during the
operation of the economy. The de…nition brings with it the implication that at
the trading date all present and future commodities must be known to …rms and
households. This does not imply that all commodities are available for delivery
at the trading date because some contracts may only be written for delivery at
some future date. In this way, the economy can cope with the introduction of
new products and is consistent with the observation that the set of available
products tends to change over time.
It is assumed that there is a …nite number n of commodities for which trades
can take place. These commodities are indexed i = 1; :::; n. Each commodity
is distinguished by its location and its time of availability. Thus bread avail-
able for delivery today is a di¤erent commodity to bread available for delivery
tomorrow and bread available for delivery today in Coventry is a di¤erent com-
modity to bread available in Exeter. The list of commodities is intended to be
exhaustive and, as already noted, includes all presently available commodities
and all commo dities that will be available for delivery at some speci…ed future
date. A quantity of some, or possibly all, of the commodities is held as an initial
stock by each household; this is the household’s initial endowment. The initial
stock of a commodity is augmented by the productive activities of …rms if it is
an output and diminished if it is an input.
To each commodity is associated a price. For good i the price is denoted
p i. This price can be given two essentially identical interpretations. The …rst
interpretation is that p i is the number of units of numeraire that have to be
surrendered in exchange for one unit of commodity i, where the numeraire is
that good denoted as having unit price. The alternative interpretation is that
p i is the price in terms of some unit of account (ie. money). The distinction
between these de…nitions is that money may be a purely arti…cial construct,
whereas the numeraire is one of the commodities. For the functioning of the
economy, the interpretation does not actually matter. The structure of the
household’ and …rm’ decision problems that are described below make it clear
that it is only relative prices, ppji , that determine choices. Since these ratios are
independent of the interpretation of prices, the interpretation is irrelevant.

2.2.3 Consumers
Consumers are one type of economic agent in the economy. Each consumer
brings to the economy an initial endowment of goods and also holds sharehold-
ings in the …rms. The consumers use the income from the sale of the endowment
and from dividend payments to purchase their preferred choice of commodities.
These commodities are then consumed.
The number of consumers is …xed and is given by H. This can either be
interpreted as the number of individual consumers or as the broadest partition of
the set of consumers into distinct consumption units. In terms of the economies
used in public economics, the second interpretation is often adopted and, when it
is, a consumption unit can be viewed as a household rather than as an individual.
This is acceptable provided the household acts as if following a single ob jective.
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 23

In this book the terms household and consumer are interchangeable in Parts
I to III (with household invariably adopted) but are carefully distinguished in
Part IV.
Each of the H households, h = 1; :::; H has a consumption set, X h , that
describes feasible consumption plans. This should be distinguished from the
budget set, de…ned below, which describes a¤ordable consumption plans. As
an example of the kind of restriction that is embodied in the consumption set,
twenty-four hours of work per day and no food would not be regarded as a
feasible consumption plan and the consumption set would therefore not include
this plan. The consumption set is assumed to be convex.
Each household, h, also has a utility function that represents its preferences.
The adoption of utility functions to represent preferences is not restrictive since,
as shown by Debreu (1954a), the conditions necessary for a functional represen-
tation of preferences to exist are very weak. In fact, the required assumptions
are that preferences are re‡exive, transitive, complete and continuous. How-
ever, the comparability of utilities between households is more troublesome and
is discussed later in the chapter. The utility function is assumed to be strictly
quasi concave, so the set
© ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ª
xh : U h x h ¸ U h x^ h ; xh 2 X h ; (2.1)

is strictly convex for any x^h 2 X h . This assumption is equivalent to assuming


the preference order is strictly convex.
The utility function of household h is written
¡ ¢
U h x h1 ; :::; xhn ; (2.2)

where xhi is the consumption of good i by household h. If good i is supplied


by the household, as would be various forms of labour services, then x hi < 0.
Household h also has an initial allocation, or endowment, of the n goods given
by the vector
¡ ¢
!h ´ ! h1 ; :::; !hn : (2.3)

Included in this endowment is the stock of labour services that the household
can supply. The household is assumed to liquidate this endowment and to use
the resulting income to purchase desired commodities.
The shareholdings of household h in the m …rms in the economy are denoted

µ h1 ; :::; µ hj ; :::; µhm ; (2.4)

where each µ hj ¸ 0: Hence if …rm j makes a pro…t of amount ¼ j , household h


receives a dividend of size
µ hj ¼ j ; (2.5)
from …rm j. As all pro…ts are distributed, it must also be true that the …rm is
fully owned by households. Across all households, the individual shares must
therefore sum to 1, hence
24CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

H
X
µhj = 1; all j = 1; :::; m: (2.6)
h=1

In the framework of the basic competitive economy there is no market for these
shareholdings so they remain …xed at their initial values.
With these de…nitions it is now possible to describe the economic behavior
of the household. Each household h chooses a consumption vector
¡ ¢
x h ´ x h1 ; :::; xhn ; (2.7)

to maximize their utility function U h (¢) subject to the budget constraint


n
X n
X m
X
p ix hi pi ! hi + µ hj ¼ j ; (2.8)
i= 1 i=1 j=1

and subject to the consumption vector being feasible in the sense that it belongs
to the consumption set of h. The budget constraint simply requires that the
value of expenditure is not more than the value of the endowment plus dividends
received.
Under the maintained assumption of strict quasi concavity of the utility
function, the solution of the household’s maximization problem will result in a
demand function for each good, i, from household h . The demand of household
h for good i is written in the form
³ ´
x hi = x hi p; !h ; µ h ; ¼ (2.9)

where p; ! h ; µ h; ¼ are the variables that the household takes as parametric. As


already noted, if x hi > 0, good i is regarded as being consumed and if xhi < 0,
good i is regarded as being supplied. The corresponding outcome when the
assumption of strict quasi concavity is relaxed will be discussed in Section 2.9.
The important concept for the existence of equilibrium is the level of aggre-
gate demand from the consumption sector which is calculated by summing the
individual demands of households. Carrying out the summation, the aggregate
demand for good i is given by

H
X
Xi = x hi = Xi (p; !; µ; ¼) : (2.10)
h=1

As individual demands may be negative, it is clearly possible for the aggregate


demand for a good to be negative.
In this discussion of the household it has been implicit that a solution to
the utility maximization problem exists. Conditions that guarantee that this is
permissible will be given in the discussion of the existence of equilibrium.
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 25

Figure 2.1: A Typical Production Set

2.2.4 Producers
The producers in the economy are the …rms that take inputs and turn them
into outputs. Inputs may come from the initial endowments of households or
they may be intermediate goods that are produced by other …rms. Each …rm
is characterized by the technology that it has available and aims to maximize
pro…ts by their choice of a production plan.
The description of the individual …rms begins with the production technol-
ogy. Each …rm, j, is described by its production set, Y j , which represents the
technology of the …rm. This set describes feasible input-output combinations
that are known to the …rm. In other words, it is a list of all the alternative com-
binations of inputs and outputs of which the …rm has knowledge. An example
of a typical production set for a …rm operating in an economy with two goods
is illustrated in Figure 2.1.
Figure 2.1 has adopted the standard convention in general equilibrium theory
of measuring inputs as negative numbers and outputs as positive. The reasoning
behind this convention is that the use of a unit of a good as an input represent a
subtraction from the stock of that good available for consumption. In addition,
when aggregation takes place across …rms, the inputs of one …rm will cancel
with the output of another so that the aggregate represents net changes in the
stock.
The important features of Figure 2.1 that capture commonly made assump-
tions on the structure of production sets are that it is a strictly convex set
and the origin and the negative orthant are included in the set. In addition,
no strictly positive vector is in the production set. The inclusion of the origin
captures the possibility of inactivity on the part of the …rm; at some prices the
26CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

…rm may choose not to produce at all. Including the negative orthant can be
interpreted as allowing the …rms to freely dispose of inputs. Finally, a strictly
positive vector would represent the production of outputs with no use of inputs.
This cannot be permitted.
Consider the …rm shown in Figure 2.1 choosing the production plan described
by the vector y j = (¡2; 3). When faced with the price vector p = (2; 2), the
…rm’s level of pro…t, which is given by the inner product of the price vector and
the production vector, is

¼ j = py j = (2; 2) : (¡2; 3) = 2: (2.11)

The representation of pro…t as an inner product is mathematically convenient


and illustrates the value of the sign convention. In addition, dividing the inner
product into positive and negative components shows that the positive part
can be given the interpretation of sales revenue and the negative part becomes
production costs.
More generally, in an n-good economy, each …rm will choose a production
plan y j , where
³ ´
y j ´ y1j ; :::; y jn ; (2.12)

to maximize pro…t subject to y j being in the production set Y j . It is assumed


that the production set is strictly convex, this will be relaxed in Section 2.9.
The …rm thus solves the maximization problem

max
j
py j subject to yj 2 Y j : (2.13)
fy g

The maximization in (2.12) determines the …rm’s supply of each good, which
will be negative if the good is an input and positive if an output, as a function
of the price vector. Firm j’s supply function for good i is

y ji = yij (p) : (2.14)

As noted in the discussion of household demand, it is the level of aggregate


supply rather than individual …rms’ supply that is important for equilibrium
existence questions. Aggregate supply is formed from the supply decisions of
the individual …rms by summing across the …rms. This gives aggregate supply
as
m
X j
Yi = yi (p) = Y i (p) : (2.15)
j=1

Note that if good i is an input for some …rms and an output for others, the
sign convention results in these being cancelled out so that Y i (p) represents net
supply from the productive sector. The vector of aggregate supplies Y (p) =
(Y 1 (p); :::; Y n (p)) will have both positive and negative elements.
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 27

2.2.5 Equilibrium
The equilibrium of the economy occurs when demands and supplies are in bal-
ance. In such a state, each agent is able to carry out its planned action and
has no reason for wanting to modify its plan. The equilibrium state is impor-
tant because it is presumed to be the position that the economy will achieve.
However, why the economy should actually reach the equilibrium is not entirely
clear. It is sometimes argued that equilibrium is reached as the outcome of a
dynamic adjustment process but such dynamics …t very uncomfortably with the
static nature of the model. This issue is still subject to debate. The procedure
adopted here is to follow the tradition of focusing upon equilibrium both for the
above reason and because of the lack of any satisfactory alternative.
To permit a precise de…nition of equilibrium, …rst observe that the level of
pro…t of each …rm can be written as a function of the price vector by using the
supply function de…ned in (2.14) to write

¼ j = py j = py j (p) = ¼ j (p) : (2.16)


Hence, using (2.16) and the fact that w and µ are constant to eliminate them
as arguments of the functions, aggregate demand (2.10) can be written

Xi = Xi (p; ¼ (p)) = Xi (p) : (2.17)


Equation (2.17) expresses aggregate demand as a function of the price vector
alone. Next, de…ne the excess demand for good i, , as the di¤erence between
demand and supply, or
H
X
Zi (p) = Xi (p) ¡ Y i (p) ¡ ! hi : (2.18)
h =1

In reading (2.18) it should be recalled that the total supply of each good is the
sum of the initial endowment and the additional net output of the …rms. If
Y i (p) < 0 then the available quantity is less than the endowment due to some
of good i being used in the production process.
A natural de…nition of equilibrium is that demand must equal supply or
supply is greater than demand and the price is zero. The second part of the
de…nition re‡ects, for example, the possibility that the economy may be endowed
with a quantity of a good for which no household or …rm has any use. Phrasing
this in terms of excess demand, equilibrium occurs when excess demand is zero
or negative for all goods, with the price of a good being zero if its excess demand
is negative. Stated formally, a set of equilibrium prices satis…es

Zi (p) 0; i = 1; :::; n and if Zi (p) < 0; p i = 0: (2.19)


The use of excess demand is just a convenient alternative way of saying that
either demand equals supply or there is excess supply and the good is free.
The equilibrium is assumed to be found by adjustment of the price vector
until (2.19) is satis…ed. Any price vector that satis…es (2.19) is termed an
28CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

equilibrium price vector or a set of equilibrium prices. The existence question


is concerned with whether there is a solution to (2.19). However, even though
it can be shown that an equilibrium price vector will always exist under fairly
weak conditions, the question remains as to how such an equilibrium is reached
since there is no notion of price formation in the description of the economy.

2.2.6 Walras’ law


Walras’ law provides a result that carries signi…cant implications for the analysis
of the general equilibrium economy. Two di¤erent statements of the law will be
given, with the second having an important role in public economics.
Taking excess demand to be less than or equal to zero for the n goods
provides n equations in (2.19) to be solved simultaneously. However, the content
of Walras’ law is that these n equations are not independent and that only n ¡ 1
actually need to be solved. To show this result, …rst note that as each household
is satisfying their individual budget constraint and the …rms are distributing
their entire pro…t to shareholders, the value of each agents demand is equal to,
or less than, the value of their supply. Summing over all agents it must be true
that the aggregate value of demand cannot be greater than the aggregate value
of supply. Starting with the individual budget constraint

n
X m
X n
X
p ix hi µhj ¼ j + pi !hi ; (2.20)
i= 1 j=1 i=1

summing over all households gives

n
X m X
X H H X
X n
pi Xi µ hj ¼ j + p i! hi ; (2.21)
i=1 j=1 h =1 h=1 i=1

where the …rst term follows from the de…nition of aggregate demand. Now
recalling (2.6) and (2.16), (2.21) can be written

n
X n X
X m H X
X n
j
pi Xi pi yi + p i! hi : (2.22)
i=1 i=1 j=1 h=1 i=1

Using the de…nition of aggregate supply in (2.15), (2.22) can be expressed as

n
X m
X n
X H
X
p iXi (p) p iY i (p) + pi ! hi : (2.23)
i=1 j=1 i=1 h=1

or

n
X
p iZi (p) 0: (2.24)
i= 1
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 29

Equation (2.24) is the standard form of Walras’ law. In words, Walras’


law can be stated succinctly: the aggregate value of excess demand is non-
positive. It should be noted that Walras’ law holds for all price vectors, not
just equilibrium prices. In the important case in which all households are non-
satiated, so that they spend their entire income, there will be equality in (2.24)
and the value of excess demand will be precisely zero.
Assuming non-satiation and returning to the equilibrium conditions (2.19),
the equality form of Walras’ law implies that if n ¡ 1 markets have zero excess
demand so must the nth. Hence there are only n ¡ 1 independent equations in
(2.19) since the value of any n ¡ 1 imply the value of the nth. This may seem
to imply that there are only have n ¡ 1 equations to determine the n prices
so that an equilibrium price vector will generally not exist but, as it is only
relative prices that determine trade patterns, it is only necessary to solve for
n ¡ 1 relative prices.
Walras’ law does have another implication that has been exploited in pub-
lic economics. The statement above can be modi…ed to the following. If n
markets are in equilibrium and all agents but one are satisfying their budget
constraint, the remaining agent must also be satisfying its budget constraint.
The consequence of this statement in an economy with a government is that
if the n markets are in equilibrium and households are meeting their budget
constraints, the government must also be meeting its budget constraint. When
describing such an economy it is therefore optional to include the government
budget constraint as an equation and to consider equilibrium on n¡1 markets or
to specify equilibrium on n markets and leave the government budget constraint
to be implicitly satis…ed. Both of these approaches will be employed below.

2.2.7 Normalizations
It has already been noted that only relative prices matter in determining de-
mands and supplies; this is clear from studying the household and …rm maxi-
mization problems. This observation implies that there is a degree of freedom
in the measurement of prices since the scale of prices does not matter.
In proving the existence of equilibrium this freedom is invariably removed
by restricting prices to a suitable compact set that is capable of capturing all
feasible price ratios. The use of compactness provides a helpful restriction on
the set that has to be searched to …nd an equilibrium price vector. The most
commonly
Pn used compact sets are the simplex, so that P the prices must satisfy
n 2
i=1 pi = 1, or the unit sphere where the restriction i= 1 [pi ] = 1 must be
met.
When the Arrow-Debreu economy is used in public economics it is also nec-
essary to choose a normalization rule. Without such a rule, it is not possible
to assign any real meaning to rates of taxation since some basis is needed from
which to measure these. The normalization rule that is normally adopted is to
select a good as the numeraire and to set its price at unity and, often in addition
to this, to …x its rate of tax at zero. Other prices and taxes are then measured
relative to this. This procedure is used repeatedly below. Further discussion of
30CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Figure 2.2: Non-Uniqueness of Optimal Choice

normalizations is given in Chapters 5 and 11.

2.2.8 Relaxation of strict convexity


The assumption of strict convexity that has been made for preferences and
production sets results in the optimal choice for the household or …rm being
unique at any given set of prices. As prices vary, so does the unique choice, but in
a way that can be represented by a point-valued function. It is this observation
that permitted the use of demand and supply functions in the development
above. This section brie‡y explores the consequences of relaxing the assumption
of strict convexity.
If the utility function is assumed instead to only be quasi concave rather than
strictly quasi concave, which is equivalent to the underlying preferences being
convex, this allows the possibility that the indi¤erence curves may posses ‡at
sections. For example, a household who regards two goods as perfect substitutes
has indi¤erence curves which are straight lines. Similarly, a …rm’s production
set is convex rather than strictly convex, its boundary may be ‡at at some
points. The obvious example of this possibility is the constant returns to scale
technology for which the boundary is ‡at along any ray from the origin.
Whenever preferences or production sets have ‡at sections there will exist
price ratios at which the optimal choice will not be unique. This is illustrated
in Figures 2.2a and 2.2b. When such non-uniqueness arises the relationship
between prices and the optimal choice must be described by a set-valued function
or, as they are more commonly known in economics, a correspondence.
It should be apparent from Figure 2.2 that provided convexity is assumed,
the set of optimal choices will be convex. Furthermore, the de…nition of conti-
nuity for point-valued functions can be generalized to a de…nition for set-valued
functions. A correspondence ' (x) ; ' : x ! y, y compact, is said to be up-
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 31

Figure 2.3: Semi-Continuity

per semi¡ 0continuous


¢ at the point x0 if x q ! x 0 ; y q 2 ' (xq ) ; y q ! y 0 implies
¡ ¢
y 2 ' x . It is lower semi continuous at the point x0 if x q ! x0 ; y 0 2 ' x 0
0

implies there is y q such that y q 2 ' (x q ) ; y q ! y 0 , . A correspondence that


is both upper and lower semi continuous at x 0 is said to be continuous. The
distinction between upper and lower semi continuity is shown in Figure 2.3. The
bold lines and the area between them represent the graph of the correspondence.
In Figure 2.3a it can be seen how upper semi continuity allows explosion of the
graph at x 0 while lower semi continuity in 2.3b permits implosion.

The relevance of semi continuity is that if preferences are convex, and some
further technical assumptions are satis…ed, the resulting demand correspondence
is upper semi continuous. The aggregate demand correspondence is then upper
semi continuous as the sum of upper semi continuous functions. Similarly, if
the production set is convex then the supply correspondence, and the aggregate
supply correspondence, are upper semi continuous. Together, these result in
upper semi continuity of the excess demand correspondence. The interpretation
of Walras’ law is then that the value of any point in the image set of a price
vector must have non-positive value. This extension allows the important case
of constant returns to scale to be accommodated in the analytical framework.

To minimize the level of technical knowledge required to read this text, there
are very few places where correspondences are employed below. Instead, it is
typically assumed that su¢cient convexity is present to permit the employment
of point-valued functions. It should be borne in mind, however, that almost
all the results given can be extended to apply to correspondences and hence to
incorporate constant returns to scale.
32CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

2.2.9 Existence of equilibrium


The existence of an equilibrium for the competitive economy has been the sub-
ject of a long literature which is elegantly summarized in Debreu (1980). A
su¢cient set of conditions for equilibrium to exist are:
a) For each household preferences are continuous and convex, there is no
point of satiation in the consumption set and their endowment is interior to the
consumption set.
b) Each …rm may choose to be inactive.
c) The aggregate production set is closed and convex, contains the negative
orthant and satis…es irreversibility.
It should be noted that the conditions in (a) are su¢cient to imply the ex-
istence of a utility function that represents the preferences. The role of these
assumptions is to guarantee upper semi continuity of the excess demand corre-
spondence. Without such continuity, it would clearly not be possible to prove
the existence of an equilibrium as a supply-demand diagram for a single market
makes clear. The assumption of irreversibility states that if a production plan
y 6= 0 is feasible then the plan ¡y is not. This assumption is made to guarantee
that the set of feasible production plans for the economy is bounded.
A sketch of the existence argument for the two-good case can easily be given
when it is assumed that excess demand is a continuous function of the price
vector. To do this it is useful to restrict prices so that they sum to unity, hence
p 1 + p 2 = 1, which demonstrates the use of the simplex in price normalization.
Any price vector must therefore end on the line joining (1; 0) to (0; 1).
Now consider the price vector (1; 0) in Figure 2.4. Along the horizontal axis
of the …gure are measured the price of good 1 and the quantity of good 1. The
price and quantity of good 2 are measured on the vertical axis. Assume that
preferences satisfy non-satiation so that the equality form of Walras’ law can
be used and that the excess demand for each good becomes unbounded as its
price falls to zero. An investigation of the conditions that guarantee the second
assumption is given in Arrow and Hahn (1971). With non-satiation, equality in
the statement of Walras’ law in (2.23) implies that p and Z must be orthogonal
so that the angle between them is 90 o . For p close to (1; 0) excess demand
must then lie in quadrant A since the price of good 2 is close to zero and excess
demand for it must be positive. Denote this excess demand vector by Z(1¡e; e).
Consider next a price vector p = (e; 1 ¡ e) close to (0; 1). By the same
argument excess demand must lie in quadrant C since excess demand for good
1 must be positive. Denote this excess demand vector by Z(e; 1 ¡ e).
The argument is completed by considering the e¤ect of continuously changing
prices from p = (1 ¡ e; e) to p = (e; 1 ¡ e), which is a rotation of the price vector
upwards. It has already been assumed that the excess demand begins in A and
ends in C and excess demand has also been assumed to be a continuous function
of prices and to satisfy Walras’ law. Putting these facts together, the excess
demand vector must cross from quadrant A to C at some point in the rotation
of p. As excess demand is continuous and cannot enter quadrant B, it follows
that there must be at least one price vector for which excess demand is the zero
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 33

Figure 2.4: The Existence of Equilibrium

vector. It is otherwise not possible for excess demand to move continuously


from A to C.
The proofs of equilibrium in the n-good case given by Gale (1955) and Debreu
(1959) are essentially extensions of this brief sketch of the argument which
overlooks a number of technical di¢culties. In addition a formal proof of the
existence result requires the use of a …xed point theorem; a fact that was not
apparent in the argument given.

2.2.10 Analysis of policy


It is helpful at this point to consider the general method of analyzing policy
in the equilibrium economy set out above. A policy is considered to a¤ect the
maximization decisions of the economic agents and, by changing the solution
to the maximization, to a¤ect their behavior. The change in behavior is then
manifested by changes in demands and supplies and hence of the equilibrium.
To proceed formally, consider some set of L policy instruments whose values
are denoted by the vector » = (» 1 ; :::; » L ). These could be a list of tax rates
or supplies of public goods or any other such policies. It will then follow that
demands and supplies will depend upon the values of these policy instruments,
so that excess demand can be written

Z = Z (p; ») : (2.25)

Equilibrium prices will therefore depend on », as will the equilibrium quantities.


Thus
p = p (») ; X = X (») : (2.26)
Two alternative policies » and » 0 will generate, via the equilibrium prices, two
arrays of consumption levels
34CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Figure 2.5: Continuity of Equilibrium

© ª © ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ª
x1 (») ; :::; x H (» ) ; x1 »0 ; :::; xH »0 : (2.27)

These arrays can then be compared according to the chosen indicator of


economic performance, be it a welfare measure or a statistic such as total output.
Naturally the policy achieving the higher value on this indicator will be preferred
and out of any set of potential policies, that achieving the highest value will be
the optimal policy.
This procedure invites two further questions. Firstly, assuming that indi-
vidual households’ and …rms’ decisions are continuously dependent upon the
policy parameters, will it be the case that the equilibrium values will also be
continuously dependent upon the policy? It is evident that the use and analysis
of policy will be di¢cult if a small change in policy leads to a discrete jump
in the equilibrium values. Fortunately, the answer to this question is that the
equilibria are almost always continuous with respect to the policy parameters.
The formal de…nition of almost always can be found in Mas-Collel (1980a), but
advanced methods are needed to provide the formulization.
Diagrammatically, the claim amounts to stating that equilibria such as a
in Figure 2.5, which is such that any small policy change that moves Z(p; »)
downwards switches the equilibrium to b, are exceptional and that b, c and d
are the typical cases.
The exceptional nature of a can be judged by noting that slight modi…cations
of Z(p; ») will either remove the equilibrium at a entirely or lead to two equilibria
like c and d that are continuous in policy parameters. Therefore very few excess
demand functions out of the set of possible excess demands can generate such
equilibria and for practical purposes they can be ignored.
The second question is that of uniqueness of equilibrium: given any set of
policy parameters can we be certain that there is a single equilibrium? Un-
fortunately the answer to this is invariably no. Very strong restrictions are
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 35

required to ensure uniqueness, far stronger than can be justi…ed by standard


restrictions on preferences and technology. Such results as have been found in-
volve restrictions on the Jacobian matrix of the excess demand function and are
summarized in Arrow and Hahn (1971). The typical response to this di¢culty
is to simply assume uniqueness or at least not to worry about it. Although this
is unsatisfactory, there is little alternative.

2.2.11 Core of the economy


The concept of the core of the economy is derived from considering economic
activity as a cooperative game. This provides insights into the nature of the
competitive economy. To introduce the concept, consider an exchange economy
(so there is no production) consisting of H households. Each household has
an initial endowment of the n goods. Rather than conduct bilateral exchanges,
it is now assumed that the households form coalitions and allocate the total
endowment of each coalition amongst the members of that coalition. A coalition
can therefore be composed of between 1 and H households. At any time, a
household can belong to only one coalition.© ª
Given some allocation for the economy x 1 ; :::; H
© h ª , coalition S can improve
x
upon this allocation if there is some allocation x^ for h 2 S such that
P P
(i) h2S x^ h = h 2S !h ;
(ii) ^xh is preferred to xh by all h. © ª
Condition (i) asserts that the allocation x^ h is feasible for the coalition in
the sense that they can meet the allocation © from their ª initial endowment. If
such a coalition exists, then the allocation x 1 ; :::; xH would not be accepted
by the members of the coalition. Instead, they would rather form the coalition
and bene…t from the improved allocation. This process of potential coalition
formulation would continue inde…nitely unless their exist some allocations which
cannot be improved upon. The core of the economy is de…ned as the set of
allocations which cannot be improved upon by any coalition.
The …rst issue that arises is whether there are any allocations that are in
the core. That the core is non-empty is proved in the following theorem
© ª
Theorem 1 If x~ h is the equilibrium allocation for an Arrow-Debreu economy
© hª
with
© h ªendowments ! and p~ the corresponding equilibrium price vector, then
x~ is in the core of the economy.

Proof. Assume that the claim is not true© ªso that the exists some
© ª coalition
S that can improve upon the allocation x~ h with allocation x^ h© , hª 2 S.
P P
This implies, from (i) that ^h =
h2S x
h
h2 S ! . However, since x~h were
the optimal choices for the households in the economy at prices p~, condition
P (ii)
implies p~^xh > p~!h for all h 2 S. Summing this over h 2 S gives p~ h 2S x^h =
P
p~ h 2S !h . This contradicts feasibility and proves the theorem. jj
This theorem shows that allocations achieved a competitive equilibria are
in the core of the economy. That there generally exist allocations in the core
36CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Figure 2.6: Core of the Economy

that are not competitive equilibria can be seen in an Edgeworth box for a two-
household, two-good economy. The core of such an economy is that part of the
contract curve which is in the trading set and the competitive equilibria are
generally a subset of this. This is shown in Figure 2.6.
Introducing additional households into a two-household economy makes pos-
sible the formation of new coalitions and it is clear that some coalitions will be
able to improve upon allocations that are in the core of the two-household econ-
omy. For instance, if the economy of Figure 2.6 is enlarged by the addition of
a second type 1 household and a second type 2 household, the coalition of two
type 1s and one type 2 can improve upon the allocation labelled x. The limit
of this process is described in the Debreu-Scarf core convergence theorem.

Theorem 2 (Debreu/Scarf ) Consider an exchange economy with m types of


household and r households of each type. Assume the preferences of each type
of household satisfy insatiability (given any consumption plan x h there exists x~ h
strictly preferred to xh ), strong convexity and continuity and that the endowment
of each household is strictly positive. Then, if an allocation is in the core for all
values of r, it is a competitive equilibrium allocation.

Proof. See Debreu and Scarf (1963). jj


Theorem 2.2 establishes that as the size of the economy increases by replica-
tion, the core of the economy shrinks to the set of competitive equilibria. This
observation provides an additional motivation for considering the competitive
equilibrium as the relevant outcome in a large economy. Although replication
by increasing the number of each type of household may seem rather arti…cial,
it is not actually necessary in order to derive the conclusion that the core con-
verges to the set of competitive equilibria in the limit. As shown by Aumann
2.2. THE ARROW-DEBREU ECONOMY 37

(1964), for a continuum economy the core and the set of competitive equilibria
are identical.

2.2.12 Net trades


When taxation is introduced into the competitive economy, it becomes necessary
to be more careful about the actual trades that are carried out by households.
The preceding analysis was conducted as if the household liquidated their en-
tire endowment to obtain income and then purchased the consumption plan
they desired. This was the essence of the budget constraint in (2.7). Without
taxation, it is equivalent to think of the households as determining only net
trades in commodities, which are the quantities of each commodity they will
purchase over and above their initial endowment. For example, if a household
is endowed with 2 units of each of the two available goods and wishes to enjoy
the consumption plan (1; 3), their net trade pattern will be (¡1; 1) which will
be feasible provided the cost of the plan (¡1; 1) is less than or equal to zero.
All the arguments given above can be recast in terms of net trades simply by
subtracting the initial endowment from the demand functions determined in
(2.8).
Now consider commodity taxation in a competitive economy with no pro-
duction. Such taxes can only be levied upon the trades that are observed by
the government. When levied they have the e¤ect of driving a wedge between
the selling price of a commodity, p, and the purchase price, q, with the di¤er-
ence q ¡ p being the commodity tax paid. If a household h were to liquidate
their endowment it would be valued at p! h but would cost q! h to re-purchase.
If all taxes were positive, the value of the endowment would be less than its
cost. It follows from this observation that it pays the household to minimize
the number of purchases of commodities that are subject to positive taxes. For
such commodities it is only the net trades that will be observed and taxed. In
contrast, the household will attempt to maximize the supply of those commodi-
ties with negative taxes: the entire endowment will be sold at price p and some
bought back at q < p. This distinction between selling prices and purchase
prices introduces a kink into the budget constraint at the endowment point.
When …rms are introduced, the situation becomes slightly more complex.
Firms will always buy and sell at the prices p. If a household either buys from a
…rm or supplies a …rm they will transact at the prices q. When q > p the di¤er-
ence between the two is a tax on the household when buying from the …rm and a
subsidy to the household when supplying the …rm. In contrast, in a transaction
between households, the household supplying the good must receive price p and
the household purchasing must pay price q. The actual budget constraint of a
household then becomes dependent upon whether transactions are conducted
with …rms or with other households. To eliminate this di¢culty, the economies
studied in the following chapters implicitly assume that households only trade
with …rms so that they face prices q for all transactions. Although this is an
important restriction, it does make the analysis considerably more tractable.
38CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

2.3 Welfare properties of competitive equilib-


rium
Section 2 has described the structure of the competitive Arrow-Debreu economy
and has characterized its equilibria. That the economy can be shown to possess
an equilibrium under very weak assumptions can be judged as fairly remarkable.
What is even more surprising is that this equilibrium also has certain features
of e¢ciency; out of a system in which individual households and …rms are all
pursuing their independent objectives, a …nal state emerges that exhibits a
considerable degree of cohesion.
The belief that the competitive equilibrium has certain properties of opti-
mality appears to have been widely held for some considerable time prior to an
actual demonstration of the fact. The …rst proof of the result is generally at-
tributed to Barone (1935) and this line of analysis, involving the use of calculus
to characterize optima, reached its …nal form in Lange (1942). This approach
was, however, severely limited by its use of calculus and the assumptions of inte-
rior maxima and smoothness of functions. Employing convexity and separation
theory permits a more formal and more general proof of the Two Theorems.
The modern presentation began with the work of Arrow (1951a). Although of
great generality, the model of Arrow worked with an aggregate production pos-
sibility set rather than with individual pro…t-maximizing …rms. Debreu (1951)
presented similar results but with individual …rms. The Theorems were pre-
sented in what has become their …nal form in Debreu (1954b). An excellent
discussion of this line of work and its interpretation is contained in Koopmans
(1957), and Takayama (1985) is a good source for further discussion.

2.3.1 Basic de…nitions


The …rst step is to give a formal de…nition of a Pareto optimum. For this it is
necessary to de…ne the concept of a feasible array of consumption vectors.

De…nition 3 Feasibility
An array of consumption vectors fx1 ; :::; x H g is feasible if x h 2 X h , all h,
and there exists an array of production vectors fy 1 ; :::; y m g, each y j 2 Y j , such
that
x y + !; (2.28)
where

H
X m
X H
X
x= xh ; y = yj ; ! = !h: (2.29)
h=1 j=1 h=1

This de…nition states that a given allocation of consumption bundles to


households is feasible if it can be produced using the economy’s …xed initial
endowment and production technology.
Pareto Optimality can now be de…ned.
2.3. WELFARE PROPERTIES OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 39

© ª
De…nition 4 Pareto Optimality (P.O.) A feasible consumption array x^ h is
© hª
Pareto optimal if there does not exist a feasible array x¹ such that
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U h x¹ h ¸ U h x^ h ; h = 1; :::; H; (2.30)
with ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U h x¹h ¸ U h x^h ; for at least one h: (2.31)
© ª
Therefore ^xh is Pareto optimal if it is not possible to …nd an alternative
© ª
feasible array which gives every household at least as much utility as x^h and
gives strictly more utility to at least one household.
The competitive equilibrium described in section 2 can be given the following
formal statement.
£ © ª © ª¤
De…nition 5 Competitive Equilibrium (C.E.) An array p; x^ h ; ybj is a
competitive equilibrium if
m
X
x^ h 2 X h ; p^x^ h p^! h + µhj p^b
y j ; h = 1; :::; H; (2.32)
j= 1

ybj 2 Y j ; j = 1; :::; m; (2.33)


and ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ Pm h
(i) U h x^h ¸ U h xh for all x h 2 X h such that p^xh p^!h + j= 1 µj p
^byj ,
(ii) p^b
y j ¸ p^y j , all y j 2 Y j ,
(iii) x^ b y + !:

Equations (2.32) and (2.33) require households’ demands to be in their con-


sumption sets and …rms’ choices to be in their production sets. (i) implies that
the equilibrium choices of households maximize utility, (ii) that …rms maximize
pro…ts and (iii) that the equilibrium is feasible.

2.3.2 The First Theorem


To develop the First Theorem it is necessary to state a preliminary result. Let
household h have locally non-satiated preferences and let x^h be their chosen
consumption plan. Lemma 2.1 relating to the costs of preferred individual
consumption plans can then be proved.

Lemma 6 Let x^h be a locally non-satiating choice for household h at prices p^.
Then ¡ ¢ ¡ h¢
(i) U h xh > U h bx ) pbxh > pbbxh ;
¡ ¢ ¡ h¢
(ii) U x = U b
h h h h
x ) pbx ¸ pbb xh .

Proof. If (i) were false then clearly x h would have satis…ed the households
budget constraint and would have been chosen in preference to xbh . To prove (ii)
suppose pbx h < pbb
xh . Since b
x h is not a point of local satiation neither is x h . There
40CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

¡ h¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
then exists xeh at a distance of " from xh with U h e x > U h xh = U h xbh .
The distance " may be chosen small enough so that pbe pxbh . This contradicts
xh < b
the assumption that xb was the optimal choice. jj
h

With this background it is now possible to state and prove the First Theorem.
£ © ª © ª¤
Theorem 7 (The First Theorem of Welfare Economics) Let pb; x^ h ; ybj be
© ª £© h ª © j ª¤
a competitive equilibrium with no household satiated at xbh . Then bx ; b y
is a Pareto optimum.
£© hª © j ª¤
Proof. Suppose b x ; yb is not a Pareto optimum. Then there exists
£© ª © ª¤
xh ; y j with x h 2 X h , y j 2 Y j and
(i)x ¡y +¢!; ¡ h¢
(ii)U h xh ¸ U h b x all h;
¡ h¢ ¡ h¢
(iii)U x > U xb some h:
h h
PH PH
Given (ii) and (iii), (a) and (b) imply h=1 pbx h > h=1 pbb xh . Under local
nonsatiation (iii) of C.E. gives pbb
x = pbb
y +bp ! so it follows that pbx = pbby +bp!. Pro…t
maximization ((ii) of C.E.) implies p^ybj ¸ p^y j , all y j 2 Y j and, in particular,
that p^ybj ¸ py
^ j . Summing over j, p^yb ¸£©p^y.ªHence
© ª¤pbx > pby + b p! or pb [x ¡ y ¡ !].
From this inequality it follows that x h ; y j is not feasible thus proving
the theorem by contradiction. jj
To appreciate the generality of this theorem, it is worth reconsidering the
assumptions that were required in its proof. When this is done it can be seen
that all that was used, in addition to pro…t and utility maximization, was the
non-satiation of preferences, which is a very mild restriction, the existence of the
competitive equilibrium and …niteness of the number of goods and households.
Therefore, being based on such weak assumptions, the result cannot easily be
dismissed. The consequences of relaxing the assumption that the number of
goods and households is …nite are addressed by the overlapping generations
economy of Chapter 13 which shows how Pareto optimality can fail when both
are in…nite.
For a two household exchange economy, the First Theorem can be demon-
strated by using an Edgeworth box diagram. In Figure 2.7 the Pareto optima
are given by the tangencies of the indi¤erence curves and the locus of tangencies
determines the contract curve. A competitive equilibrium is given by a price line
through the initial endowment point, !, which is tangential to both indi¤erence
curves at the same point. The common point of tangency results in household
choices that lead to the equilibrium levels of demand. Such an equilibrium is
indicated by point e. It is clear that there is no other point which is preferred
by both households to point e. The equilibrium is therefore Pareto optimal.
In addition, it should be noted that the set of Pareto optima for an exchange
economy, given by the contract curve, generally consists of an in…nite set of
points.
The importance of the non-satiation assumption is shown in Figure 2.8 in
which household 1 has an area of satiation. Trading from !, the equilibrium
is at point e but this is not Pareto optimal since the satiated household would
2.3. WELFARE PROPERTIES OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 41

Figure 2.7: The First Theorem

be equally satis…ed with less consumption which would allow an increase in the
utility of the non-satiated household.

2.3.3 The Second Theorem


The Second Theorem is concerned with the converse of the First and its focus can
be summarized as follows: given a Pareto optimum, can a competitive economy
be constructed for which the Pareto optimum is a competitive equilibrium? In
terms of an Edgeworth box, the same question can be formulated as asking
whether it is possible to decentralize all points on the contract curve. Using
the diagram, it can be seen that this is possible in an exchange economy if
the households’ indi¤erence curves are convex. With convexity, the common
tangent at a Pareto optimum provides the equilibrium prices. To decentralize
the economy, a point on this budget line is chosen as the initial endowment
point.
This process is illustrated in Figure 2.9 where the Pareto optimum e is decen-
tralized by selecting ! 0 as the endowment point. Note that if the endowments
of the households are initially given by ! and the equilibrium at e is to be
decentralized, some transfer of endowment or, equivalently, of income will be
necessary.
The Second Theorem is now stated formally and its proof given.
£© h ª © j ª¤
Theorem 8 (The Second Theorem of Welfare Economics) Suppose that b x ; b y
is a Pareto optimum such that at least one household is not satiated. Then, with:
(a) convex preferences; (b) convex production sets; (c) the allocation xbh interior
to the consumption set £ of© h ,ª for
© all
ª¤h; and (d) continuity of preferences, there
exists pb 6= 0 such that pb; xbh ; ybj is a competitive equilibrium.
42CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Figure 2.8: The Non-Satiation Assumption

Figure 2.9: The Second Theorem in an Exchange Economy


2.3. WELFARE PROPERTIES OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 43

© hª
Proof. Assume that household 1 is not satiated at the allocation b x and
h ¡ h¢ © h ¡ h¢ ¡ h ¢ª ¡ h¢ © h ¡ ¢ ¡ h ¢ª
de…ne the sets C b h
x ´ x :U x >U b h x and C b
h x ´ x : U h xh ¸ U h b x .
Given assumption (a), these sets are convex for all h. Now n de…ne the convex set o
1¡ ¢ P ¡ h¢ P
Z by Z = C xb1 + H h=2 C
h
xb and the set W by W = w : w = ! + m j j
j=1 y ; y 2 Y
j
.
Since the individual production sets are convex, W , the set of© feasible
ª produc-
tion plans for the economy, is also convex. In addition, as b xh is a Pareto
optimum, it must not be feasible to produce a preferred consumption array,
thus no member of W is in Z.
The separating hyperplane theorem implies that there exists a vector b p such
that pbz ¸ pbwPfor all z in Z and w in W: By de…nition any Pm point in Z can be
H
written z = h= 1 xh and any point in W as w = ! + j=1 y j . Noting that
PH Pm
feasibility implies, ! ¸ h=1 x h ¡ j=1 y j , pbz ¸ pbw is equivalent to
" # " #
H
X H
X H
X H
X
h h j j
pb x ¡ xb ¡b
p y ¡ y
b ¸ 0; (2.34)
h=1 h= 1 h= 1 h=1

1 ¡ 1¢ ¡ h¢
for all x 1 2 C b x ; xh 2 C h bx , and y j 2 Y j . Now as the inequality in (2.34)
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
must hold for all x 1 ¡such
¢ that U¡ 1 ¢x 1 > U 1 xb1 , it must also hold in the ¡limit ¢
for any x1 with U 1 x 1 = U 1 b x1 . Hence (2.34) holds for all x h 2 C h b xh ,
and y j 2 Y j . Taking all but one of the x h ; y j equal to xbh ; b
y j , then (2.34) shows
that
¡ h¢
pbx h ¸ pbb
x h; for all xh 2 C h x
b , for all h; (2.35)

pby j ¸ pbybj ; for all y j 2 Y j , for all j: (2.36)

Inequality (2.36) shows that at the price system supporting the Pareto optimum
each …rm is maximizing pro…t (consider (ii) of C.E.).
To show that households are maximizing utility requires a¡ demonstration
¢ ¡ h¢
that pbx h ¸ pbb
x h implies there is no x h with pbxh = pbb
xh and U h x h > U h b x .
¡ ¢ ¡ h¢
Now assume that there is some x h such that pbxh = pbb xh and U h xh > U h b x .
h h h
From assumption
¡ ¢ (c) there
¡ h¢ also exists x
e with p
bxe < p
b x
b but (2.35) shows
that U h xeh < U h b x . Now take a convex combination of e x h and x h. As
preferences are continuous from assumption (d), this convex combination can
be made to satisfy
¡ h ¢ ¡ h¢
U h te
x + [1 ¡ t] xh > U h b x ; (2.37)

and
£ h ¤
x + [1 ¡ t] x h < b
pb te pxbh ; (2.38)

by ¡moving
¢ arbitrarily close to x h . This contradicts b
px h ¸ pbb
xh , for all x h 2
h h
C xb , all h. Hence the households must be maximizing utility and the price
vector decentralizes the Pareto optimum. jj
44CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Figure 2.10: Proof of the Second Theorem

Two points about the proof are worth noting. Theorem 2.4 implicitly as-
sumes that the households are given su¢cient income to purchase the opti-
mal allocation. In fact, household h must receive an endowment that satis…es
pb! h = pbb
x h. Secondly the reasoning of the proof is based on the fact that a price
vector that supports the sum of sets also supports the individual sets that form
that sum. This is illustrated in Figure 2.10.
Before proceeding further, it is worth emphasizing that the proof of the
Second Theorem required more assumptions than the proof of the First so there
may be situations in which the First Theorem is applicable but the Second is
not. For instance, an equilibrium may exist with some non-convexity in the
production sets of the individual …rms but the separation theorem can then not
be applied which prevents the proof of the Second Theorem.
A moment’s re‡ection is su¢cient to realize the importance to economic
policy of the Second Theorem. In designing policy, it is almost certain that a
policy maker would wish to achieve a Pareto optimum, otherwise welfare could
be increased at no cost. The theorem demonstrates that the objective of the
policy maker can be achieved by making the economy competitive, selecting
the equilibrium that is to be decentralized and providing each household with
su¢cient income to a¤ord their allocation. The only policy instrument employed
is a lump-sum redistribution of endowments to ensure that each household has
the required income. If this approach could be applied in practice, then economic
policy analysis reduces to the calculation and redistribution of the lump-sum
2.4. A CRITICAL APPRAISAL 45

taxes and the subject matter of public economics is completed.

2.4 A critical appraisal


There are several viewpoints from which the Two Theorems can be criticized.
Firstly, it is possible to question the practical value of the Second Theorem on
the basis of its requirement for lump sum transfers in implementing the decen-
tralizations. Secondly, it is possible to question the merit of Pareto optimality
as a method of judging the acceptability of a given equilibrium. In addition
it is also possible to consider the structure of the economy: is it an accurate
representation of reality and what are the consequences for welfare economics
of relaxing its assumptions?
This section will consider each of these issues. The use of lump-sum transfers
will be taken up …rst since these are central to applications of the Second The-
orem. This will be followed by an assessment of the structure of the economy
and the implications of this for the subject matter of the subsequent chapters.
The value of Pareto optimality as a criterion for social decision making is then
considered.

2.4.1 Lump-sum transfers and taxes


The strong implications of the Second Theorem for policy design have already
been noted. However, the practical value of the Second Theorem is dependent on
the possibility of making the lump-sum transfers of endowments that it requires.
Without recourse to such transfers, the decentralizations would not be possible.
The exchange economy illustrated in Figure 2.11 makes clear the role and
nature of lump-sum transfers. The initial endowment point is denoted ! and the
Pareto optimum at point e is to be decentralized. This requires the endowment
point to be moved to a point on the budget line through e. Assume that the
new endowment point ! 0 leaves the distribution of good 2 constant. This move
can be supported by the transfer of xe11 units of good 1 from household 1 to
household 2. Trading from ! 0 will lead to the competitive equilibrium at e as
required.
Such a transfer of part of an endowment from one household to another is the
most basic form of a lump-sum transfer. The lump-sum nature of the transfer is
due to the fact that neither household can alter the size of the transfer by changes
in their behavior; there is simply no scope for such changes in the economy
described. The transfer is an optimal transfer if the resulting equilibrium at e
maximizes the policy maker’s objective function.
Although the lump-sum transfer above involved quantities of goods it can
be reinterpreted to introduce lump-sum taxes. If at the equilibrium e the prices
of the two goods are p 1 and p 2 , then the value of the transfer in Figure 2.11 is
p 1 xe11 . The notional income of household 1 prior to taxation is

M 1 = p 1 ! 11 + p 2 !12 : (2.39)
46CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Figure 2.11: The Use of Lum-Sum Transfers

Now, rather than actually redistributing quantities of the goods, the government
could tax household 1 an amount T 1 , T 1 = p1 xe11 , which reduces their income to

f1 = p 1! 1 + p 2 ! 1 ¡ p 1 e
M x11 ; (2.40)
1 2

and give household 2 an amount of income T 2 , = T 1 . If it is intended that the


equilibrium be attained at e then T 1 is the optimal lump-sum tax on household
1 and ¡T 1 is the optimal tax on 2, as this pair of taxes ensures the households
face the budget line through e.
The important point of this reinterpretation is that the tax scheme consisting
of the taxes©fT 1 ; ¡Tª1 g is equivalent in its e¤ect to the original transfer of
endowment ¡e x 11 ; e
x11 . This equivalence demonstrates that it is possible to
view the transfers needed to achieve the decentralizations as taking the form of
either real transfers of goods between households or as transfers of income in
the form of lump-sum taxes. This description of lump-sum taxes can be easily
generalized to an H household economy in which a chosen equilibrium would
be decentralized by a vector of lump-sum taxes

H
© 1 H
ª X
T ; :::; T ; T h = 0: (2.41)
h=1

Since these taxes sum to zero, they represent a simple redistribution of resources.
Lump-sum taxes have a central role in public economics due to their e¢-
ciency in achieving distributional objectives. It should be clear from the discus-
sion above that the economy’s total endowment is not reduced by the application
of the lump-sum taxes. This point applies to lump-sum taxes in general. As
2.4. A CRITICAL APPRAISAL 47

households cannot a¤ect the level of the tax by changing their behavior, lump-
sum taxes do not lead to any ine¢ciency. There are no resources lost due to the
imposition of lump-sum taxes and redistribution is achieved with no e¢ciency
cost. Having identi…ed the nature and value of optimal lump-sum taxes, the
question of their applicability is now considered.
In practice, the endowment of most households is simply their future labour
supply. Given this, it would be impossible to conduct lump-sum transfers of en-
dowments as a quantity of future labour cannot be transferred from one house-
hold to another without the reintroduction of slavery. It is therefore possible
to dismiss the idea of transferring quantities of goods, except in very particular
and inconsequential cases, and to focus upon the design of optimal lump-sum
taxes.
In order for a transfer, or tax, to be lump-sum the household involved must
not be able to a¤ect the size of the transfer by changing their behavior. It is clear
that lump-sum taxes can be used, for example by taxing each household some
…xed amount a lump-sum tax is imposed. Setting aside minor details, this was
e¤ectively the case of the U.K. poll tax. This example motivates the following
important observation. The e¢ciency of lump-sum taxation rests partly on the
fact that their imposition is costless but this was far from the case with the
U.K. poll tax. In fact, the di¢culties of actually collecting and maintaining
information on the residential address of all households made the imposition
of a uniform lump-sum tax prohibitively expensive. Therefore, although the
structure of lump-sum taxes makes them appear deceptively simple to collect,
this may not be the case in practice since the tax base, people, is highly mobile
and evasive.
However, the costs of collection are only part of the issue. What is the pri-
mary concern here is the use of optimal lump-sum taxes. Optimality requires
the tax to be based on all relevant economic characteristics and households must
not be able to alter these characteristics in response to the taxes. It may be
possible to di¤erentiate lump-sum taxes according to sex, age or eye-colour for
instance, but these are unlikely to be the relevant characteristics on which to
base the tax. For the exchange economy examples, the characteristics were the
endowments and preferences of the households. More generally they may be the
expected future labour incomes of the households or the determinants of each
household’s human capital. Such characteristics are unlikely to be directly ob-
servable by the government and either it must either rely on households honestly
reporting their characteristics or the characteristics must be inferred from the
actions of households. In the latter case, there is invariably scope for changes
in market behavior which implies the taxes are no longer lump-sum. When re-
ports are the sole source of information, unobserved characteristics cannot form
a basis for taxation unless the tax scheme is such that there is an individual
gain to truthful revelation.
As an example of the interaction between taxes and reporting, consider the
following. Let the system of lump-sum taxes be based on the characteristic IQ
level. If the level of tax was inversely related to IQ and if all households had
to complete IQ tests, then the tax system would not be manipulated since the
48CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

incentive would always be to maximize the score on the test. In contrast, if taxes
were positively related to IQ, a testing procedure could easily be manipulated
and the mean level of tested IQ would be expected to fall considerably. This
indicates the potential for misrevelation of characteristics.
These ideas have been developed formally by Mirrlees (1986) who presents
theorems on the (im)possibility of designing non-manipulable lump-sum tax
schemes. The central theorem considers a population of households who each
have the utility function
¡ ¢
U h = U h c1 x h1 ; :::; cn x hn : (2.42)

The households vary, however, in the values of the constants c = (c1; :::; cn )
that appear in the utility function. The preferences of each household are fully
described by their c vector. Since the cs are the only di¤erentiating characteristic
between households, any optimal set of lump sum taxes must be based on these
characteristics. Now assume that the government cannot observe the c vectors,
that households only truly report their characteristics when they do not lose by
doing so and that misrepresentation can only take place by a household claiming
that the values of the characteristics are above their true values.
With this formulation, a tax policy T = T (c) conditional on the characteris-
tics can only be administered, in the sense that it generates truthful revelation
from the households, if the …nal utility allocation U h = U h (T (c)) = U e h (c)
generated by the taxes is non-increasing in c. The following theorem shows
that Ue h (c) will be increasing in ci with the optimal tax policy if good i is nor-
mal. Since some goods must be normal, the policy optimal policy cannot be
administered.

Theorem 9 (Mirrlees) If the utility of each household is given by (2.42) and


social welfare is de…ned as
Z
¡ ¢
W = U h c1 xh1 ; :::; cn x hn ° (c1 ; :::; cn ) dc1 ; :::; dcn ; (2.43)

where ° (¢) is the distribution function of the cs, then with the optimal tax
policy that maximizes (2.43) given the economy’s endowment, U e h (c) is increas-
ing in ci if commodity i is always a normal good.

Proof. The optimum occurs when the marginal utility of income is identical
for all households. If this were not the case, transfers of income would raise wel-
fare. Inverting this reasoning, the marginal income required to obtain another
unit of utility must be the same for all households. Corresponding to the utility
function (2.42) is the expenditure function for h which takes the form
µ ¶
h h p1 pn h
E =E ; :::; ; U : (2.44)
c1 cn

Optimality then implies


E hU = ¥; (2.45)
2.4. A CRITICAL APPRAISAL 49

for some constant ¥. Di¤erentiating (2.45) with respect to ci gives

@Ueh pi
E Uh U ¡ E hU i 2 = 0; (2.46)
@ci ci
³ ´ ³ ´
or, since E hi = Â hi pc11 ; :::; pc nn ; U h where Âhi pc 11 ; :::; pcnn ; U h is the Hicksian or
compensated demand for good ifrom h,

@Ueh pi @Âhi
E Uh U = : (2.47)
@ci ci @U h

With a concave utility function E Uh U > 0 and the normality of good i implies
@Â h eh
i
@U h
> 0. Therefore the normality of goo d i implies @@c
U
i
> 0 at the optimum as
was to be proved. jj
This theorem shows why optimal lump-sum taxes may not be feasible. The
government cannot observe the relevant characteristics and relies on the house-
holds to reveal them. However, under the optimal tax policy it is not in the
household’s interest to truthfully reveal their characteristics. This theorem is
dependent upon the precise assumptions made but it is indicative of the general
results that emerge when policy relies on individual revelation of information.
The main points of the argument can now be summarised. To have any
content the Second Theorem relies on the use of optimal lump-sum transfers but
such transfers are unlikely to be available in practice or to satisfy all the criteria
required of them. The taxes may be costly to collect and the characteristics
upon which they should be levied may not be observable. When characteristics
are not observable, households may have incentives to make false revelations. It
is therefore best to treat the Second Theorem as being of considerable theoretical
interest but of very limited practical relevance.

2.4.2 The institutional assumptions


Before considering the concept of Pareto optimality, some comments are now
o¤ered on the assumptions underlying the model and the consequences for the
Two Theorems of their relaxation. The assumptions can be conveniently placed
into two categories: those whose relaxation is possible without destroying the
validity of the theorems and the others whose relaxation does so. Time and un-
certainty belong to the former category, although when they are introduced the
interpretation becomes less tenable. Public goods, externalities and monopoly
power, or imperfect competition generally, are …rmly in the latter.
In the presence of time and uncertainty the existence of su¢cient markets
permits a re-interpretation of the economy and the proof of Two Theorems
proceeds as above. However, the passage of time introduces the questions of
investment, savings and growth which cannot be addressed satisfactorily in the
Arrow-Debreu economy. Fortunately a number of more appropriate structures
are available. One of these, the overlapping generations economy, will be studied
in Chapter 13. Uncertainty introduces aspects such as the correct amount of
50CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

risk-taking and portfolio choice. This is an area of public economics that is being
developed particularly with respect to the normative implications of uncertainty
and the important aspects of this literature are reviewed in Chapter 8.
Turning to externalities, public goods and monopoly power, since any one
of these will remove the Pareto optimality of equilibrium, the Two Theorems
are no longer applicable to any economy in which they are present. However,
the theorems do show some properties of the state that could be achieved if the
externality etc. could be eliminated. The failure of the Two Theorems in these
cases can be viewed as providing the motivation for the analysis given in Part
II I.

2.4.3 Pareto optimality


Even when all the criticisms noted above are set aside, the Two Theorems
are still dependent upon the value of Pareto optimality as a welfare criterion.
For this reason, and also because Pareto optimality is regularly encountered
in public economics, it is worthwhile taking a closer look at Pareto optimality
and considering its implications and de…ciencies as a means of choosing between
economic states. From this perspective it is possible to assess the usefulness of
Pareto optimality as a criterion for guiding public policy.
The Pareto criterion was introduced by Pareto (1909) and given its name
by Little (1950). The motivation for its use was that it provided a means
of comparing economic states without requiring interpersonal comparisons of
utility; an issue that will be returned to below. To begin the discussion, it is
helpful to start with a restatement of Pareto optimality.
Consider a set of states, S = (s1 ; s2;: :: ) and a set H, indexed h = 1; :::; H, of
economic agents. Writing  h for the strict preference relation of household h
and ºh for at least as good as, then state s1 is Pareto preferred to state s2 if

s 1 º h s2 for all h = 1; :::; H; (2.48)


and
s1 Âh s2 for at least one. (2.49)
A preference order is then induced on the set of states by (2.48) and (2.49).
This preference order is denoted by  P , hence

s1 ÂP s 2 , (2.48) and (2.49): (2.50)

In addition, de…ne º P by
s1 º P s 2 , (2.48) (2.51)
State s1 is then de…ned as being Pareto optimal if there exists no other state
that is Pareto preferred to s1 . Formally, s1 is Pareto optimal if 9 no s2 2 S
such that s2 ÂP s1 . It is important to note that this general de…nition has
been in terms of two states and that no utility concepts were involved. This
demonstrates that Pareto optimality is a very broad concept and can be used
for far more than assessing allocations of utility.
2.4. A CRITICAL APPRAISAL 51

Now consider s1 and s 2 to represent di¤erent allocations of a …xed stock of


goods amongst the H agents. Then allocation s1 is Pareto optimal if there exists
no re-allocation that is Pareto preferred to s1 . In other words, starting from s1
it must be impossible to re-allocate the …xed stock of goods in manner which
makes one household better-o¤ without making another worse-o¤. Alternatively,
s 1 and s2 could represent two states with alternative political parties being in
power. Then s1 is Pareto preferred if no voter prefers party s2 and at least one
would strictly prefer party s1 .
With this background it is now possible to proceed to an assessment of Pareto
optimality. By considering even the simplest examples, it is not di¢cult to see
several de…ciencies of the Pareto criterion. First consider the division of a cake
between two people where both people like cake and their preferences satisfy
non-satiation. In such circumstances every division of the cake is Pareto optimal,
from the most inequitable to the most equitable. This claim follows from noting
that, starting from any division, there are no changes in the distribution that
satisfy (2.48) and (2.49). In other words, any reallocation that provides more
to one household must take it away from the other. The latter point illustrates
that situations exist in which the set of Pareto optima

fsi : si 2 S and 9 no sj 2 S such that sj ÂP sig ; (2.52)

is in…nite.
From this simple example it is possible to infer two de…ciencies of Pareto op-
timality. Firstly, extreme allocations may be Pareto optimal and, consequently,
although an equilibrium may be Pareto optimal there is no reason why anyone
should advocate it as good in any other sense. Secondly, it is possible for there
to be a multiplicity of Pareto optimal allocations even for this very allocation
problem. When the Pareto criterion does not provide a unique optimal alloca-
tion it is not be of much assistance as a social rule for choosing an allocation.
The points made in the cake division example are also relevant when consid-
ering allocations in a two-household exchange economy. The contract curve in
Figure ?? gives the set of Pareto optima and there is generally an uncountable
number of these optima, so the ordering ºP does not select a unique maximal
element. In addition, the competitive equilibrium may be as the one illustrated
in the bottom left corner. This is Pareto optimal but highly inequitable.
Another failing of Pareto optimality is that the ordering º P need not provide
a complete ranking of states in S. That is, there may be some pairs of states
which are incomparable under the Pareto criterion. Incomparability arises if, in
the move between two states s1 and s 2, some agent gains and another agent loses.
This is illustrated in Figure ?? where allocations s1 and s2 cannot be compared
although s 1 and s3 and s2 and s3 can. Such gains and losses are invariably a
feature of policy choices and much of policy analysis consists of weighing-up the
gains and losses. In this respect, the Pareto criterion is inadequate as a basis
for policy choice.
To summarise these arguments, Pareto optimality does not embody any
concept of justice and highly inequitable allocations may be optimal under the
52CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Figure 2.12: Pareto Optimal Allocations

Figure 2.13: Incompleteness of the Pareto Ranking


2.5. INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS AND SOCIAL WELFARE 53

criterion. In many situations, the set of Pareto optimal allocations is in…nite


and the criterion then provides little guidance for policy choice. Finally, the
Pareto criterion may not provide a complete ordering of states so that some
states will be incomparable under the criterion. The source of all these failing
is that the Pareto criterion avoids making interpersonal comparisons whereas it
is such comparisons that have to be made in most allocation decisions.

2.5 Interpersonal comparisons and social wel-


fare
Pareto optimality was originally proposed as a means by which it was pos-
sible to analyse the consequences of alternative allocations without requiring
interpersonal comparisons of welfare to be made and it is from this that the
failures of Pareto optimality emerge. To make further progress it is necessary to
consider the scope for comparability between the utility levels of di¤erent indi-
viduals. This section reviews alternative degrees of comparability and considers
the problem of aggregating individual preferences into social preferences.

2.5.1 Interpersonal comparability


If su¢ciently strong interpersonal comparisons are possible, statements such as:
“the welfare loss of agent i in the new allocation is more than o¤set than the
gain of agent j“ would be permissible. Given the relative weights attached to
individuals i and j in social preferences it would then be possible to make a
judgement on whether the change was socially bene…cial or not.
The …rst step in making such comparisons is the construction of a comparable
utility index to measure
© ª i’s and j’s welfare.
© ª If, for example, i gains in the move
from allocation x h to allocation xbh and j loses, with other households
una¤ected, the aim is to weigh the gain U ^ i ¡ U i against the loss U j ¡ U
^ j . Such
comparisons run against the spirit of the Pareto criterion which, as already
stated, was originally intended to replace such utility comparisons since these
were felt to be making judgements that were scienti…cally untenable; a viewpoint
expounded most strongly by Robbins (1932).
The issues motivating Robbins’ denial of interpersonal comparability can
best be understood by reviewing the development of utility theory. Nineteenth
century economists assumed that utility was something measurable and that it
was naturally comparable between individuals. As such, it followed that the
welfare of society could be inferred in some straightforward manner from the
welfare levels of the individuals forming that society. Reasoning of this form
provides the scienti…c basis for utilitarianism.
The notion of measurable and comparable utility began to be dispelled in
the early Twentieth century after the demonstrations by Hicks (1939) and oth-
ers that the entire theory of the household could be based on ordinal non-
comparable utility. In other words, since it was the household’s preference or-
54CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

dering that determined consumption choices, utility was only relevant as a conve-
nient functional representation of preferences, with no greater meaning attached
to it, and that given a utility function representing the preference ordering, any
increasing monotonic transformation of that utility function would also be an
equally valid representation of preferences. Ordinality and non-comparability
then became the accepted concepts. This acceptance left no scienti…c basis upon
which to justify the comparability of di¤erent household’s utility levels.
Ordinality means that if x 1 Âh x2 then it is given a higher utility number
but the actual relationships between the numbers assigned to di¤erent xs, for
instance the size of the di¤erence between any two, have no content. This,
consequently, prevented welfare comparisons between people and created the
necessity of developing concepts, such as Pareto optimality, that were free of in-
terpersonal comparisons. However the weaknesses of these criteria soon became
obvious and, following Scitovsky (1951), the trend since the 1960’s has been to
explore the consequences of re-admitting interpersonal comparability into the
analysis. Some economists, for instance Mirrlees (1971) and Ng (1985), have
argued most strongly for this, although there is some divergence of opinion on
the acceptable extent of comparability.
Between non-comparability and full comparability there are several interme-
diate cases that vary as to precisely how comparable are the utility levels. For
instance, the claim that one household has a higher level of utility than another
requires rather less comparability than claiming it has 15% more utility. Di¤er-
ent degrees of comparability carry obvious implications for the welfare measures
that can be based upon them.
The various degrees of comparability have been classi…ed by Sen (1977) and
Roberts (1980b). The starting point for the classi…cation is a utility function U h
for each household h and³ the set © ´of admissible transformations of this utility
¡ ¢
function. That is, Á = Á1 ; :::; ÁH 2 © if Áh U h is an equally valid utility
function for h. Alternative degrees of measurability and comparability then
appear as restrictions on the set ©. The alternatives that have been considered
in the literature, in increasing order of comparability, can now be stated as
follows.
(i) Ordinality and non-comparability (ONC)
Á 2 © is a list of H independent strictly monotonically increasing transfor-
mations.
This is the set of transformations that arises when utility is viewed only as
the representation of preference in conditions of certainty. It implies that there
can be no interpersonal comparability.
(ii) Cardinality and non-comparability (CNC)
¡Á 2¢ © is a list of H independent strictly positive a¢ne transformations:
Áh U h = ah + bh U h ; bh > 0:
When there is uncertainty involved in the decision-making environment CNC
can be justi…ed by appeal to the von Neumann and Morgernstern (1953) utility
representation theorem. Condition CNC demonstrates that cardinality, in itself,
does not carry any implications for interpersonal comparisons.
2.5. INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS AND SOCIAL WELFARE 55

(iii) Ordinality and level-comparability (OLC)


Á 2 ©¡is a¢ list of¡ H¢identical strictly monotonically increasing transforma-
tions: Áh U h = Á U h ; Á independent of h.
With OLC it is possible to rank the households in terms of their utility
levels, so that one household can be seen as having more or less utility than
another, but changes in utility levels cannot be compared across households.
This degree of comparability formalises what is probably intended by claims
that households have roughly similar preferences and can hence have their utility
levels compared.
(iv) Cardinal unit comparability (CUC)
Á 2 © is a list of H¡ strictly
¢ positive a¢ne transformations which di¤er only
in their constants: Áh U h = ah + bU h ; b > 0:
Although CUC does not allow comparability of welfare levels, since the con-
stant terms may di¤er, it does allow the comparability of gains and losses in
utility. This follows from the restriction of the utilities to the same units of
measurement.
(v) Cardinal full comparability (CFC) ¡ ¢
Á 2 © is a list of H identical strictly positive a¢ne transformations: Áh U h =
a + bU h ; b > 0:
CFC represents the maximum degree of comparability that is possible with-
out the introduction of a natural zero for utility since it allows comparison of
both levels and gains and losses. If a zero is introduced, the set of transforma-
tions then becomes
(vi) Cardinal ratio scale (CRS) ¡ ¢
Á 2 © is a list of H identical strictly positive linear transformations: Áh U h =
bU h ; b > 0.
Amongst these alternative degrees of comparability, only ONC and CNC are
formally justi…ed via representation theorems on preferences. Moving further
down the list requires an increasing degree of pure faith that the procedure is
justi…ed. The next section relates the degree of comparability to permissible
welfare criteria.

2.5.2 Social choice


In moving from individual to social preferences the basic problem is one of ag-
gregation. From the individual preference relations must be constructed a social
preference relation that satis…es certain attractive criteria. What aggregation
procedures are possible depends critically on the level of comparability assumed.
The starting point for the literature on social choice was Arrow’s (1950,
1951b) impossibility theorem. Arrow considered a set S of states and H indi-
vidual preference orderings ºh , h = 1; :::; H, over S and attempted to construct
from these a social welfare function, F , that would determine the social order-
ing, º, of S for any set of individual orderings, so º= F (fºh g). An ordering
is de…ned here as being complete, re‡exive and transitive. Conditions that may
be imposed upon such a social welfare function include the following.
56CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

Unrestricted domain (U ): The domain of F includes all logically possibly


H-tuples of individual orderings of S.
Independence of irrelevant alternatives (I ): The restriction of º to the pair
fs1 ; s2 g, si 2 S, i = 1; 2, is a function
¡© only of theª¢ restrictions of individual
preferences to that pair º jfs1;s2 g = F ºh jfs1;s2 g .
Weak Pareto principle (P): For any pair fs1 ; s2 g if s1 ºh s 2 for all h, then
s1 º s2 .
Non-dictatorship (D): There must be no individual h such that for all indi-
vidual preference orders, for each ordered pair s 1 ; s2 , si 2 S, i = 1; 2, s1 Âh s 2
implies s 1 Â s2 ..
From these conditions follows Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem.

Theorem 10 (Arrow) If H is …nite and S has at least 3 elements then there


is no social welfare function satisfying conditions U, I, P and D.

Proof. See Sen (1986).


The implication of this theorem is that a social welfare function does not exist
that can aggregate the individual preference orderings without con‡icting with
one, or more, of the conditions U, I, P or D. At the heart of this non-existence
result is the limited information contained in the individual preference order-
ings. This information is not su¢cient for the social ordering to be constructed
without violating one of the conditions. Following the …rst demonstrations of
this theorem, attempts were made to derive possibility results by weakening the
conditions U, I, P and D and relaxing the requirement of transitivity for the
social ordering. None of these relaxations provided a convincing path out of the
impossibility.
An alternative approach is to allow greater information about individual
preferences, in particular to consider the consequences of alternative forms of
interpersonal comparability. That admitting interpersonal comparability in-
creases the scope for making consistent welfare judgements, and generates Pos-
sibility Theorems, has been demonstrated by Roberts (1980a,b) and Sen (1977).
The formal method is to consider a social welfare functional that determines the
social ordering over
¡© S for
ª¢ any given H-tuple of individual utility functions over
S, that is º= F U h . The conditions U, I P and D can be translated into
equivalent restrictions on the social welfare functional. The degree of inter-
personal comparability then determines the permissible transformations of the
individual utility functions. For example, with ONC the same ordering must
be generated whatever monotonic ³n transformations are applied to the individual
¡© ª¢ ¡ ¢o´
utilities or º= F U h =F Áh U h for any set of monotonic transfor-
n o
mations Áh . Since ONC is equivalent to the information content in Theorem
2.6, the translation of that theorem applies directly.
When further information is introduced, possibility theorems can be proved.
Taking ordinal level comparability (OLC) …rst, since this is su¢cient to permit
the ranking of individuals in terms of utility levels, it also permits social welfare
functionals that are de…ned as the welfare of the hth individual in the ranking
2.5. INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS AND SOCIAL WELFARE 57

for any h. One special example of such a welfare function is the Rawlsian or
max-min given by
© ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ª
W = min U 1 x1 ; :::; U H x H : (2.53)

With unit comparability it is possible to asses the gains and losses between
individuals. Furthermore, once one set of the constants appearing in the utility
function are speci…ed, it is meaningful to consider the sum of utilities as a welfare
criterion. Formally, CUC implies that the welfare functional

H
X
W = ah U h ; ah > 0; (2.54)
h= 1

is permissible. If the welfare functional is also assumed to satisfy the condition


of anonymity given byn o
© ª
Anonymity (A): if U e h is a re-ordering of the utility vector U h , then

³n o´ ¡© ª¢
F eh
U =F Uh ; (2.55)

then the constants ah in (2.54) cannot vary with h so that the welfare functional
reduces to the standard utilitarian form
H
X ¡ ¢
W = U h xh : (2.56)
h=1

Full comparability leads to the class of welfare functionals determined by


¡ ¢
W = U (x) + g U (x) ¡ U (x) ; U (x) (2.57)
H ¡ ¢
¡ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢¢ X U h
x h
= U 1 x 1 ; :::; U H xH ; U (x) = ; (2.58)
H
h= 1

where g(¢) is homogeneous of degree 1. An example of such a welfare functional


is
© ª
W = U (x) + ° min U h (x) ¡ U (x) ; (2.59)
which is Utilitarian for ° = 0 and Rawlsian for ° = 1. Finally, CRS leads to

W = W (U (x)) ; (2.60)

where W (¢) is a homothetic function. When anonymity is also imposed, the


social welfare functional becomes

XH £ h ¡ h ¢¤1¡À
U x
W = : (2.61)
h =1
1¡À
58CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS

2.5.3 Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function


The Bergson-Samuleson social welfare function was …rst introduced into eco-
nomics by Bergson (1938) since which there has been considerable controversy
over its correct interpretation and its validity. The general Bergson-Samuelson
social welfare function is de…ned as a function of the state W = W (s i), where
si 2 S, and is intended to represent the social preference ordering. If the social
welfare function is neutral towards non-utility features of the states it is evalu-
ating, so that only the utility levels of the individuals matter for social welfare,
then the Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function takes the form
¡ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢¢
W = W U 1 x 1 ; :::; U H x H ; (2.62)

There has been much discussion of the relationship between the social welfare
function in the sense of Arrow and that of Bergson-Samuelson. Samuelson
(1977) asserts that a Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function can be con-
structed even when the utility levels are ordinal and non-comparable. If such a
social welfare function is expected to hold for all possible preference orderings,
then Theorem 3.4 shows that it must violate one (or more) of U, I, P and D. One
potential route out of this impasse was to suggest that the Bergson-Samuelson
social welfare function needs to hold only for the given set of preference orders
that characterise the economy under consideration. In this case, condition U
is not applicable. This restriction to the given set of preferences represents the
single-pro…le approach to social choice where the social ordering only has to
satisfy the speci…ed criteria for a single-pro…le of preference orders. In con-
trast, the Arrow theorem is characteristic of the multi-pro…le approach where
the ordering must be constructed for any possible set of preference orderings.
Unfortunately, the restriction to single-pro…les does not avoid the impossibility
result. As shown by Kemp and Ng (1976) and Roberts (1980c) the impossibility
result remains intact when the requirements of the social ordering are translated
to the single-pro…le context.
The use of a Bergson-Samuleson social welfare function therefore implies the
adoption of comparability assumptions on individual utilities. Accepting this,
the maximisation of a Bergson-Samuelson social welfare functions is invariably
adopted as the objective of policy in public economics. In such exercises it is
usually assumed that the social welfare function satis…es the Pareto criterion
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ ¢¢ ¡ ¡ ¢¢
U h x^ h ¸ U h x~ h , all h implies W U h x^ h ¸ W U h x~h ; (2.63)

and, when the social welfare function is di¤erentiable, that

@W @2W
h
¸ 0 and 0: (2.64)
@U @U h2
The assumption on the second derivative is often strengthened to that of strict
concavity or strict quasi-concavity. Unfortunately, as is discussed further in
Chapter 4, this does not always guarantee second-order conditions will be sat-
is…ed when the welfare function is used as the objective in a maximisation.
2.6. SUMMARY 59

Figure 2.14: Social Indi¤erence Curves

For a given value of W (¢) it is possible to draw its level sets, typically called
social indi¤erence curves, as in Figure 2.14.
The convexity of these was the subject of discussion in the 1950’s. Gorman
(1959b) demonstrated the important result that convexity in itself does not
require interpersonal comparability.

2.6 Summary
The aim of this chapter was to introduce the Arrow-Debreu economy and to
review a number of fundamental issues in welfare economics. This material
underlies much of the analysis in the following chapters, providing both the
analytical method and a baseline against which changes can be assessed.
The Two Theorems, which characterise the e¢ciency properties of the com-
petitive economy, were described and proved. Although the Theorems have
strong implications, it was argued that they both are limited in their value; the
First Theorem due to the weakness of Pareto optimality and the Second because
of its reliance upon lump-sum taxation. It was argued that criteria for judging
between economic states that did not employ interpersonal comparisons were
too weak to be of practical usefulness. If comparability is permitted, stronger
criteria are possible.
There are two major conclusions to be drawn from the discussion. Firstly,
the limitations of the Two Theorems provide a natural point of departure for
the study of public economics. Secondly, if decisions about economic policy are
to be taken on welfare grounds, it is necessary that interpersonal comparisons
must be made.
60CHAPTER 2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM AND WELFARE ECONOMICS
Chapter 3

Topics in Measurement

3.1 Introduction
The previous chapter has reviewed the theory and concepts involved in the
measurement of welfare and the motivations for adopting these approaches. The
welfare judgements that emerged from that analysis were based unavoidably
upon utility concepts and this basis is found by many to be objectionable. In
response to this, alternative means of assessing the economic outcome that rely,
in the main, on observable and measurable quantities are now discussed. At
…rst sight these appear to be rather more tangible concepts than those of utility
and social welfare. Most of what is said below applies equally to a range of
economic indices far broader than just those considered here.
The chapter begins with a discussion of the de…nition of income which is
the basic observable and measurable quantity from which indices of inequal-
ity and poverty are formed. Although there is little doubt about the meaning
of income in a world of certainty, it is rather less well speci…ed when there is
uncertainty about the values of future variables. The distinctions between the
available de…nitions of income are clari…ed and their relative merits noted. Data
on household incomes, though, cannot be used directly in the construction of
economic indices since the households will di¤er in their size and composition
and, consequently, in their requirements. This observation motivates the consid-
eration of equivalence scales, which are a means of adjusting observed household
incomes to take account of household composition e¤ects and to provide a set
of comparable income measures.
This is followed by a review of the measurement of inequality. The link is
drawn between statistical measures and their implied so cial welfare functions.
This motivates the consideration of explicit welfare-based measures and axiom
systems. A similar approach is taken to the measurement of poverty. It is worth
noting at the outset that the ma jor theme to emerge from the discussion is that
the construction of a successful index requires the welfare assumptions on which
it is based to be made explicit.

61
62 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

3.2 The measurement of income


Many of the indices that measure economic well-being, including those of in-
equality and poverty, are formed from data on incomes on the grounds that
income is the means to achieve welfare. Given this important role, it is nec-
essary that the income statistics should provide accurate data. This will be
achieved if there is precise collection of information, which is a topic that will
not be pursued here, and the correct de…nition of what is to be measured is
employed. It is the latter aspect that is the sub ject of this section.
In the static and deterministic economy of Chapter 2 a household’s income
can be unambiguously de…ned. If the household enters the economy with a zero
stock of goods and is given its endowment and list of shareholdings after entry,
then its income, for any given price vector, is the value of the endowment plus
dividend income. De…ned in this way, income is the value of consumption that
can be undertaken whilst leaving the household with the same stock of goods,
which was zero, at the end of the economy as it had at the start of the economy.
The de…nitions of income below will also try to apply this reasoning, but only in
the deterministic setting can it be applied without di¢culty of interpretation.
Fisher (1930) proposed the view that income was formed by the set of plea-
surable experiences that the consumer enjoyed over the period in which income
was to be measured. This was based on the view that neither the actual receipt
of money or the purchase of goods represented the end product of economic
activity; it was actual consumption that played this role. The di¢culty of this
approach is that it leads to income as an unmeasurable and purely personal
construct. As an approximation, Fisher suggested that the level of expenditure
in the period, less the disutility of any labour performed, should be the measure
of income since it is from expenditure that consumption results. Unfortunately,
even this approximation cannot be directly calculated due to its inclusion of the
disutility of labour.
An alternative de…nition provided by Hicks (1939) constitutes what is gen-
erally taken as the standard de…nition of income. In Hicks’ words “income is
the maximum value which a man can consume during a week and still expect
to be as well-o¤ at the end of the week as he was at the beginning“ (Hicks
1939, p. 172). This de…nition embodies both the consumption aspect empha-
sised by Fisher (1930) and reduces to the stock-of-goods measure in a static
and certain environment. The di¢culties of applying this de…nition follow from
the inclusion of the word expect and from the consequent forward-looking na-
ture of the de…nition. The de…nition does not make it clear whose expectations
are referred to and how to resolve di¤erences in expectations, nor does it show
how the possibility of false expectations should be accommodated. A literal
application of the de…nition would not count windfall gains as income, since by
de…nition they are not expected, although they unarguably raise the potential
level of consumption. For these reasons, the Hicks de…nition of income does not
command universal acceptability.
In contrast, Simons (1938) adopts the position that a workable and calcula-
ble de…nition is preferable to one that is formally correct but non-operational.
3.3. EQUIVALENCE SCALES 63

Simons’ de…nition is backward-looking, measuring income in retrospect. In full,


the de…nition is that “Personal income may be de…ned as the algebraic sum
of (1) the market value of rights exercised in consumption and (2) the change
in the value of the store of property rights between the beginning and end of
the period in question“ (Simons 1938 p. 50). This can easily be applied and
does not involve expectations so removing some of the drawbacks of the Hicks
formulation. As Simons required, it provides an operational de…nition.
These alternative de…nitions highlight the distinctions between ex ante and
ex post measures of income. In practice, tax assessments adopt the backward-
looking viewpoint and measure income as all relevant payments received over
the relevant period. The de…nition of income for the purposes of tax codes does
not precisely satisfy any of the de…nitions given above. For instance, capital
gains if not realised during the perio d in question are not usually measured as
income. Such observations have motivated the concept of the comprehensive
income tax, under which income from all sources would be treated equally. This
would accord with the de…nitions of income given above. In practice, though,
the ideal measure of income cannot be achieved so preventing the application
of a truly comprehensive income tax. The systems that do arise can then be
viewed as deriving from the resulting second-best problem. For the purposes of
the following chapters, the fact that much of the analysis is conducted within
certain environments eliminates the problems of de…nition. When uncertainty
is explicitly introduced, care will be taken to highlight the measure of income
adopted.

3.3 Equivalence scales


The income level of a household is often treated as a proxy for its level of
welfare since, at the very least, income is the means to achieve welfare. The fact
that households di¤er in make-up and composition implies that if the welfare
levels of two households are to be compared it will not generally be su¢cient,
taking environmental variables etc. as constant, to simply compare their income
levels. To make the issue concrete, a household of one adult with no children
needs less income to achieve a given level of welfare than a household with two
adults and two children. The question is then, of course, how much less income?
Equivalence scales are a means of adjusting measured incomes into comparable
quantities.
The typical causes of di¤erentiation between households are the number of
adults and the number and ages of their dependants; the relevant features of such
di¤erentiation are typically referred to as demographic variables. The general
problem in designing equivalence scales is to achieve the adjustment of observed
income to take account of demographic di¤erences. The discussion begins with
an approach based on identifying the minimum needs that a household requires
in order to survive at some chosen level of welfare, typically a level on or just
above that identi…ed as implying poverty. This method represents more of
an expert judgement of equivalent incomes than an application of economic
64 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

theory. Following this, the methods of Engel and Rothbarth are considered,
both of which employ restrictive assumptions on the underlying preferences of
households. Relaxing these assumptions then leads into the Barten method and
its generalisation.

3.3.1 Minimum needs


The calculation of equivalence scales based upon minimum needs can be traced
back to at least Rowntree (1901). Such scales are calculated by determining the
cost of an identi…ed bundle of goods and services that are seen as representing
the minimum needs for the household. The exact bundle will di¤er between
households of varying size. In the work of Rowntree the set of goods included
in the minimum needs were food, rent and rates, and household sundries.
There have been many studies since that of Rowntree employing this method-
ology and some illustrative numbers are given in Table 3.1 below. In each case a
household with zero children is assigned the index of 100 and other compositions
are measured relative to this. Hence with the Beveridge scale, a single child is
seen as requiring an increase in the income of a couple of 22% in order for the
same minimum level of consumption needs to be attained.

Rowntree (1901) Beveridge (1942) US Poverty Scale (1942)


Single Person 60 59 78
Couple 100 100 100
+1 child 124 122 123
+2 children 161 144 152
+3 children 222 188 208
Note: For the Beveridge scale, children are taken to be in the 5-9 age group
Table 3.1: Minimum Needs Equivalence Scales

Table 3.1 demonstrates that these equivalence scales assume that there are
returns to scale in household size so that, for example, a family of two adults
does not require twice the income of a single person. The ma jor shortcomings of
this method of computing equivalence scales are that by focusing on the cost of
obtaining a minimum level of consumption they are inappropriate for applying
to incomes above the minimum level and, sine they do not take account of
optimisation by the households, they cannot be claimed to measure the true
economic cost of demographic di¤erences.

3.3.2 Engel and Rothbarth


The next two methods of computing equivalence scales both have a basis in the
theory of household optimisation. They follow from the following observation: if
the welfare level of a household can be judged by its consumption of some speci…c
commodity, then equivalent incomes are those which lead di¤erent households
to consume the same quantity of the commodity. The distinction between the
two scales is in the commodities they select as relevant for the comparison.
3.3. EQUIVALENCE SCALES 65

Figure 3.1: Construction of Engel Scale

Engel

The Engel (1895) approach to equivalence scales rests on the hypothesis that
the welfare of a household can be measured by the proportion of its income that
is spent on food. In particular, Engel’s law asserts that the food share of expen-
diture falls as income, and hence welfare, rise. If this is accepted, equivalence
scales can be constructed for demographically di¤erent households by calculat-
ing the income levels at which their expenditure share on food is equal. This
is illustrated in Figure 3.1 in which the expenditure share on food as a func-
tion of income is shown for two households with demographic characteristics d1
and d2 . Using the Engel method, incomes M 1 and M 2 are equivalent and the
2
equivalence scale is given by the ratio MM1
.
There are two shortcomings to this approach. Firstly, although its content
may be empirically true, this alone does not provide a basis for making welfare
comparisons. Secondly, even if welfare conclusions can be inferred via Engel’s
law, it can be argued that the Engel method overestimates the cost of additional
children for a household. Nicholson (1976) argues that a child is largely a food-
consuming addition to a household. If, after the addition of a child, a household
is compensated su¢ciently to restore the share of food in its expenditure to
its original level, this would represent over-compensation with respect to other
commodities. Deaton and Muellbauer (1986) provide a formalisation of this
argument.
The approach of Engel has been extended to the more general iso-prop
method in which the expenditure shares of a basket of goods, rather than sim-
ply food, becomes the basis for the construction of scales. Seneca and Taussig
(1971) employ a basket consisting of food, housing, clothing and transportation
and …nd that this provides less compensation than the Engel method at low in-
66 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

Figure 3.2: Rothbarth Equivalence Scale

comes but more compensation at high incomes. However, considering a basket


of goods does not overcome the theoretical shortcomings of the Engel method.

Rothbarth
The procedure of Rothbarth (1943) selects for attention a set of goods that are
consumed only by adults, termed adult goods, and such that the expenditure
upon them can be treated as a measure of welfare. If these goods also have
the property that changes in demographic characteristics only a¤ect their de-
mand via income e¤ects, then the extra income required to keep their consump-
tion constant when household composition changes can be used to construct
an equivalence scale. Typical examples of such goods that have been used in
practice are tobacco and alcohol.
For the chosen consumption level x, the procedure is illustrated in Figure 3.2
with three Engel curves representing di¤erent household compositions. On the
basis that they generate the same level of demand as family composition changes,
the Rothbarth procedure would assert that M 1 , M 2 and M 3 are equivalent
incomes and the equivalence scale would be constructed from their ratios.
There are a number of di¢culties with this approach. It rests upon the
hypotheses that consumption of adult goods accurately measure welfare and
that they are a¤ected only via income e¤ects; theoretically both hypotheses are
asserting separability between the utility from adult goods and that from goods
which are a¤ected by demographic characteristics. These hypotheses could be
refuted by empirical evidence and, as noted by Cramer (1969), the typical adult
goods, alcohol and tobacco, are empirically unresponsive to income e¤ects. In
addition, it is not clear that their demand is una¤ected via changes in demo-
graphic characteristics. The evidence reported in Deaton, Ruiz-Castillo and
Thomas (1989) supports these doubts about the method’s validity. Further-
3.3. EQUIVALENCE SCALES 67

more, the ratios of M 1 to M 2 and M 3 will depend upon the level of demand
chosen for the comparison except in the special case in which the Engel curves
are straight lines through the origin, so that utility is homothetic, and the ra-
tios may vary for di¤erent goods. This leads into a further aggregation problem
of forming some total ratio out of the ratios for each good. These observations
suggest that the formulation of equivalence scales should be more closely related
to consumer preferences.

3.3.3 Prais and Houthakker


The approach to equivalence scales based on the Engel curve has been extended
by Prais (1953) and Prais and Houthakker (1953) and investigated more re-
cently by Muellbauer (1974) and McClements (1977). This method begins by
specifying the Engel curve for good i as
µ h¶
x hi h M
= xi ; i = 1; :::; n; (3.1)
ai
e a0
e

where eai, i = 1; :::; n, is a function of the vector of demographic characteristics


d = (d1 ; :::; dm ) that describe the household. For example, d1 could the number
of children under 1 and d2 the number between 1 and 3. The income de‡ator is
then a function of the e ai . In this speci…cation of the Engel curve, real income and
the e¤ective consumption level of each good are obtained by de‡ating by terms
determined by household composition. This provides two channels through
which household composition can a¤ect demand.
From (3.1) the e¤ect of a change in characteristic k of household composition
upon demand can be expressed in elasticity terms as

dk @x hi d @eai M h @x hi dk @e
a0
h
= k ¡ h : (3.2)
x i @dk ei @dk
a x i @M h ea0 @dk
Pn @xh Pn pj xh
j M
h @xh
The budget identity j=1 p j @ djk = 0 and the condition that j=1 M h xh
j
h =
j @M
Pn pj xhj dk @eaj
1 imply deak0 @e
a0
@d k = j=1 M h ea j @d k . Substituting into (3.2) gives

Xn ¸ n
dk @x hi dk @e
ai M h @x hi X pj x hj dk @eaj
= ¡ : (3.3)
x hi @dk ei @dk
a
j=1
xhi @M h j=1 M h e aj @dk

In principle, (3.3) provides a basis for empirically estimating the e¤ects of house-
hold composition on demand elasticities. An example of an empirical application
of (3.3), which forms the basis for the equivalence scales used by the Department
of Social Security in the UK, can be found in McClements (1977).

3.3.4 Barten
Since the shortcomings of the methods discussed so far are due to their lack of
choice-theoretic foundation, the value of building equivalence scales from a basis
68 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

in utility theory is clear. Although each of the methods so far can be interpreted
in terms of the restrictions they place on preferences, see Muellbauer (1977) and
Coulter et al. (1992), this was not explicit in their original motivation. The …rst
attempt at making preference restrictions explicit can be attributed to Barten
(1964) who approached the derivation via the direct utility function. Extensions
of the method using duality can be found in Gorman (1978) and Muellbauer
(1974).
It has been noted that some goods may not be consumed by children, the
adult goods of Rothbarth, whilst children consume relatively large proportions
of goods such as food. This observation motivates letting a household of type
d be equivalent to ai(d) adults for the consumption of good i; i = 1; :::; n. The
household’s utility is then
µ h ¶
x1 xhn ¡ ¢
Uh = Uh 1
; :::; n
= U h x^h1 ; :::; x^ hn ; (3.4)
a (d) a (d)
xh
where x^ hi = ai (d)
i
. The behaviour of the household is determined by choosing
¡ h ¢ ¡ ¢
the quantities P x^ 1 ; :::; x^ hn to maximise U h x^h1 ; :::; x^ hn subject to the budget con-
n
straint M h = i=1 pbi ^xhi , where pb = (b p 1 ; :::; pbn ) is the demographically adjusted
price vector with pbi = p iai (d). The form of this price vector and budget con-
straint motivates the observation that lies at the heart of this approach “When
you have a wife and a baby, a penny bun costs threepence“ (Gorman (1978) p.
9). ¡ ¢
h h h
Solving the ¡maximisation gives the demand ¢ functions x
^i = x^ i p
b ; M or
x hi = ai (d) ^xhi p 1 a1 (d) ; :::; pn an (d) ; M h . The latter of these shows how a
change in composition has two e¤ects upon demand. It a¤ects demand directly
via the equivalence term ai (d) and indirectly via the equivalence terms a¤ecting
the demographically adjusted prices. This speci…cation should be contrasted to
(3.1). In elasticity form the e¤ect of a change in demographic characteristic k
upon demand for good i is
n
X p j @b ¸ ¸
dk @xhi @ai dk h
i xi dk @a j
= + a : (3.5)
x hi @dk @dk ai
j=1
xhi @p j aj @dk

Equation (3.5) provides a basis for empirically estimating the e¤ects of house-
hold composition on demand elasticities and an application can be found in
Muellbauer (1977).
Contrasting (3.5) to (3.3) di¤erences emerge only in the …nal term. If the
Slutsky equation for the e¤ect of a change in the price of good j on the demand
for good i is multiplied by xp jh it becomes
i

p j @xhi p j @Âhi M h @xhi p j x hj


= ¡ ; (3.6)
x hi @p j x hi @p j xhi @M h M h

where Âhi is the compensated demand for good i from household h. The spec-
@Â h
i…cations in (3.3) and (3.5) can then be seen to be identical if i
@ pj
= 0 so that
3.3. EQUIVALENCE SCALES 69

the compensated demand for goo d i is independent of the price of good j. The
two methods are therefore equivalent when the compensated demands depend
are independent.
To construct the¡ equivalence ¢ scale, the expenditure function dual to the
utility function, U h x^h1 ; :::; x^ hn , can be de…ned by
¡ ¢ © ¡ h¢ ª
E h pb; U h = min pb^xh subject to U h x
^ ¸ Uh ; (3.7)

Using the de…nition of demographically adjusted prices it follows that


¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
E h pb; U h = E h p1 a1 (d) ; :::; pn an (d) ; U h ; (3.8)

so the expenditure function captures all the demographic information via the
h
equivalence terms ai(d). For some give level of welfare, U , the equivalence
scale for two-household compositions db and de is given by
³ ³ ´ ³ ´ h´
E h p 1 a1 db ; :::; p n an db ; U
³ ³ ´ ³ ´ h´: (3.9)
E h p 1 a1 de ; :::; p n an de ; U

If the speci…cation in (3.4) is correct, (3.9) provides an exact equivalence scale


in the sense that it measures the true economic cost of demographics. Its form
also makes apparent how equivalence scales will generally be dependent upon
h
the price level and the base level of welfare, U , at which the comparison is
made. Equivalence scales that are independent of the base level of utility will
be considered in the next section.
For the two good case , this procedure is illustrated in Figure 3.3. The out-
ward shift of the indi¤erence curve is caused by the increase in the number of
family members requiring an increase in household consumption to keep house-
hold utility constant. The extent to which the budget line has to be shifted
outward determines the extra income required to compensate for the change in
demographic characteristics.
The Barten approach provides a model of household welfare formation that
is empirically implementable. The speci…cation of utility chosen is a particularly
precise one but has been rejected as inappropriate in some econometric tests,
see Muellbauer (1977). In common with all the methods discussed so far, it
also treats the demographic variables as lying outside the control of the house-
hold. In some circumstances this may be appropriate; the consequences of this
assumption and the e¤ect of relaxing it are considered in the next section.

3.3.5 General case


The preceding equivalence scales were constructed upon the implicit assumption
that the demographic variables were exogenous and were not an object of choice
by the household; in the terminology of Pollak and Wales (1979) they were
conditional scales. If the demographic vector, or some components of it, a¤ect
70 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

Figure 3.3: The Barten Scale

utility directly rather than just through its interaction with consumption, an
unconditional equivalence scale is required. To see the distinction, let utility
take the form
¡ ¡ ¢ ¢
U h = © U xh ; d ; d : (3.10)

An estimation procedure based upon observed market demand ¡ ¢ will only be


able to infer information on the separable component U x h; d and will not
uncover the function © (¢). Unfortunately, for welfare comparisons and for the
construction of equivalence scales, the function © (¢) is required.
The relevance of the distinction between conditional and unconditional equiv-
alence scales is critically dependent upon whether the demographic vector enters
the utility function. If it does not, there is no distinction between the two and
the previous approaches are valid. When it do es, Blundell and Lewbel (1991)
prove that demand data observed in a single price regime can provide no in-
formation on equivalence scales. There are three responses to this. The …rst
is simply to use the demand¡ ¢data to construct cost functions relating to the
component of utility U x h ; d and use these to form cost of living indices for
demographically di¤erent groups. These cannot be used to make welfare com-
parisons. An alternative procedure is to impose a convenient form upon the
function © (¢) and proceed as if this were the correct form. Whether the im-
posed form is correct will not be testable. Finally, it may be possible to employ
evidence other than demand data that sheds some light upon preferences over
demographic variables. None of these alternatives provides an exact solution to
the identi…cation problem.
¡ ¡ ¢ ¢
Given the utility function U h = © U x h; d ; d , let the corresponding ex-
3.3. EQUIVALENCE SCALES 71

penditure function be
¡ ¢ © ¡ ¡ ¢ ¢ ª
E h p; d; U h = min pxh subject to © U xh ; d ; d ¸ U h : (3.11)

As in (3.9), the equivalence scale for two demographic compositions db and de is


de…ned by ³ ´
b Uh
E h p; d;
³ ´: (3.12)
e Uh
E h p; d;

A desirable property for an equivalence scale to possess is for it to be in-


dependent of the level of utility at which it is evaluated since this permits the
same equivalence scale to be used to adjust all levels of income. If the equiva-
lence scale satis…es this property, it is said to be independent of base. For the
equivalence scale in (3.12) to be independent of the base level of utility, Lewbel
(1989, 1991) has shown that the cost function must be of the form
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
E h p; d; U h = F (p; d) G p; U h : (3.13)

The su¢ciency of this condition can be seen by forming the ratio in (3.12) to
obtain the equivalence scale ³ ´
F p; db
³ ´; (3.14)
F p; de

which is independent
¡ ¢ of the base level of utility. Two
¡ special
¢ cases
¡ ¢arise from
(3.13). If G p; U h is independent of p, hence G p; U h = G U h , the cost
function represents homothetic preferences. When F (¢) is independent of p the
underlying utility function takes the form
µ h ¶
h x
U =U ; (3.15)
f (d)

which is a special case of the Barten model.


The main conclusion to be drawn from this analysis is that equivalence
scales are only independent of the base level of utility if the cost function is
separable between utility and demographic characteristics. Whether this is true
in practice, and if it were many applications of equivalence scales would receive
theoretical justi…cation, is a matter of empirical testing. Evidence to date,
namely that of Blundell and Lewbel (1991), rejects the independent of base
assumption.

3.3.6 In practice
There have been many equivalence scales constructed (Buhmann et al (1989) list
34 and their study is not comprehensive) and so it is necessary to …nd a simple
means of summarising their content. Buhmann et al. (1989) suggest that an
72 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

acceptable approximation of existing equivalence scales is to write equivalised


incomes as
h
fh = M " ;
M (3.16)
[dh ]
where the demographic variable, dh , now measures only the number of family
members and the elasticity, ", varies between 0 and 1. Four types of equivalence
scales are then identi…ed. Expert statistical scales are designed for statistical
purposes such as counting the number above or below a given standard of liv-
ing. Their typical value of " is 0.75. Expert programme scales are designed
to assist with welfare programmes and have a typical value of " of 0.55. Both
these expert scales are constructed in the manner of the Beveridge scale where
an outside judgement is made on needs. Consumption scales are based on ob-
served expenditures and lead to an average " value of 0.36. Finally, subjective
scales, constructed on the basis of questionnaire evaluations of income, have the
smallest " of 0.25.
There is considerable variation in these scales which is linked to the means
of construction and the purpose for which the scale is required. The expert
statistical scales assign the largest increase in cost for increases in family size
and give little weight to potential economies of scale in consumption. Conversely,
the subjective scales …nd the greatest economies of scale but, being based on
consumers’ own perceptions of their welfare status, are not free from reporting
bias.
In assessing these methods of constructing equivalence scales, it should
be noted that the minimum needs and the Engel/Rothbarth approaches are
straightforward but as a consequence are not without their faults. The exact
measures capture precisely what the other two are attempting to approximate
but correspondingly are more di¢cult to calculate. It should also be noted
that by basing the exact measures upon utility analysis, they are subject to
the di¢culties concerning interpersonal comparability discussed in Chapter 2
and dependent on the appropriateness of the utility maximisation assumption.
Furthermore, there is also the di¢culty of imposing a single, well-de…ned, util-
ity function such as (3.10) as representation of a household’s preferences. The
household utility function must represent the aggregation of the preferences of
the individuals constituting the household but, although on a smaller scale, such
aggregation is subject to the di¢culties already noted for social preferences in
Chapter 2. This observation raises obvious questions about the interpretation
of (3.10).

3.4 The measurement of inequality


Given a set of income levels for the households in an economy, or a speci…ed sub-
group of an economy, adjusted by an appropriate equivalence scale, an obvious
question for anyone who has any concern for distributive justice is to ask how
equally distributed is income in that economy or sub-group. Income inequality
may be of interest in its own right or it may be relevant because of its perceived
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 73

consequences. In either case, in order to meaningfully discuss inequality, it must


…rst be necessary to measure it.
There are many measures of inequality that can be employed and all have
features to commend them. Broadly speaking, measures of inequality can be
divided into three groups. The …rst group are those measures that can be
termed statistical and, as such, are typically standard statistical indices applied
to inequality. The welfare measures constitute the second group and take as
their starting point an explicit formulation of social welfare from which the
inequality measure is developed. This division does not imply that statistical
measures have no welfare implications; in fact, a fundamental observation in the
theory of inequality measurement was the recognition of their implicit welfare
assumptions. The …nal category of measures can be termed axiomatic. These
are derived by specifying properties that it is thought a satisfactory measure
should possess and deriving all measures that satisfy those conditions.
After providing basic de…nitions, the most relevant of the statistical mea-
sures are noted. This is done both for completeness and because a number of
these measures feature in the ensuing analysis. The connection between social
welfare and statistical measures is then clari…ed and this is followed by discus-
sion of explicitly welfare-based indices. The axiomatic derivation of inequality
measures is then reviewed. As a …nal point, the discussion is given in terms
of the measurement of income inequality. However, the measures that are de-
scribed can be applied to the measurement of the inequality of any vector or
distribution of observations be it data on wages, wealth, welfare or even non-
economic data such as weights. The only distinction between these applications
are the properties that it may be desirable for the index to possess.

3.4.1 Basic de…nitions


Measures of income inequality can either be de…ned in terms of discrete or
continuous distributions of income. Although the former is correct in an obser-
vational sense, the latter often allows simpler derivation of results and is a valid
approximation for large populations. Most attention will be paid below to the
discrete case but the continuous case will be used where appropriate.
With a discrete distribution of income, it is assumed that there are H house-
holds labelled h = 1; :::; H with the labelling chosen so that their incomes, M h ,
form an increasing sequence. Hence

M1 M2 M3 ::: MH: (3.17)

The mean income, ¹, is de…ned by


H
1 X h
¹= M : (3.18)
H
h=1

For a continuous distribution, the basic data is a density function for income.
Denoting the edensity by °(M ) and assuming the support of this distribution to
74 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

£ ¤ RM
be 0; M , where M is the maximum level of income, so that 0 °(M )dM = 1,
the mean level of income is
Z M
¹= M °(M )dM : (3.19)
0

The basic task in inequality measurement is to assign a single number to the


distribution M 1 ; :::; M H that describes the inequality of the distribution and
permits alternative distributions to be ranked. Formalising this, given the set
of incomes M = fM 1 ; :::; M H g, an inequality measure is a function I(M ) such
f) > I(M
that if I(M c) then the income distribution M f is judged as having more
c
inequality than distribution M . Typically, a normalisation is adopted so that
+ ! [0; 1] with a value of 0 representing complete equality and 1 maximum
I : <H
inequality. For continuous £ distributions,
¤ the inequality
£ ¤measure is de…ned as the
functional I with I : C 0; M ! [0; 1], where C 0; M represents the space of
£ ¤
continuous distribution functions on 0; M . These de…nitions imply that the
inequality measure has to provide a complete ranking of income distributions.
Other than de…ning its range and domain, the form of the function I(M ) has
not been restricted. This permits the maximum freedom in the choice of I(M )
and allows its form to be restricted only by considerations directly relevant to
the measurement of income inequality.
Given an income vector M = fM 1 ; :::; M H g, an index that assigns the same
inequality to the vectors M and ¸M for any ¸ > 0 is termed a relative index.
Equivalently, I(M ) = I(¸M ) so a relative index is homogeneous of degree 0
in M . This property is not entirely innocuous. Its acceptance leads to an
interpretation of inequality as a relative concept in which a scaling up of all
incomes leaves inequality unchanged. An alternative view would be that an
addition of an equal amount to all incomes should leave inequality unchanged so
that I(M ) = I(M + ±) for all ± > ¡M 1 . The implications of these assumptions
are investigated further below.

3.4.2 Statistical measures


The statistical measures of inequality that are presented represent only a se-
lection from the many that exist. The selection is on the grounds of extent of
use in practice or theoretical relevance; Sen (1973) and Cowell (1977) discuss
further statistical measures.

The Lorenz Curve


The Lorenz curve has played an important role in the measurement of inequal-
ity since its introduction by Lorenz (1905) and constitutes a helpful graphical
device for presenting a summary of data on income distribution. Although not
an inequality index as de…ned above, Lorenz curves are considered here be-
cause of their use in illustrating inequality and the central role they play in the
motivation of other inequality indices.
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 75

Figure 3.4: Lorenz Curves as an Incomplete Ranking

The Lorenz curve is constructed by arranging the population in order of


increasing income and then graphing the proportion of income going to each
proportion of the population. If all households in the population had identical
incomes the Lorenz curve would then be the diagonal connecting the points
(0; 0) and (1; 1). If there is any degree of inequality, the ordering in which
the households are taken ensures that the Lorenz curve lies below the diagonal
since, for example, the poorest half of the population must have less than half
the proportion of income. For a continuous income distribution, the coordinates
(x; y) of the Lorenz curve are given by
µZ m Z ¶
1 m
° (M ) dM; M ° (M ) dM (3.20)
0 ¹ 0

as ¹ varies from 0 to M .
Although the Lorenz curves does not constitute an index of inequality in
the sense of assigning a number to the distribution, it can still be employed to
unambiguously rank some income distributions. As illustrated in Figure 3.4, if
the Lorenz curve for distribution B lies entirely outside that for distribution A,
distribution B can be seen to be less equal. In particular, B could have been
derived from A by transfers from poor to rich. In this case, A can be said to
Lorenz dominate B. If the Lorenz curves representing distributions A and B
cross, an unambiguous ranking of the two distributions cannot be derived from
the Lorenz curve alone. The concept of Lorenz domination therefore provides
only a partial ordering of income distributions.
A fundamental concept in the theory of inequality measurement is the Pigou-
Dalton Principle of Transfers which was …rst formulated by Dalton (1920). The
basis of this principle is that any transfer from a poor household to a rich one
must increase inequality. The principle can be de…ned formally as follows.

De…nition 11 (Pigou-Dalton Principle of Transfers) The inequality index must


decrease if there is a transfer of income from a richer household to a poorer
76 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

household which preserves the ranking of the two households in the income dis-
tribution and leaves total income remaining unchanged.

Any inequality measure that satis…es the Principle is said to be sensitive to


transfers. The Pigou-Dalton Principle is generally viewed as a condition that
any acceptable measure of inequality should meet and is therefore adopted in
most axiomatisations of inequality indices. Jenkins (1991) assesses the transfer
sensitivity of a number of statistical inequality measures. For the Lorenz curve,
a transfer of income from poor to rich moves the Lorenz curve further from the
diagonal. The Lorenz curve therefore satis…es the Pigou-Dalton Principle.

The Gini Coe¢cient


The Gini coe¢cient, attributed to Gini (1912), has been the subject of extensive
attention in the literature on inequality measurement, …nding both proponents
and opponents. This interest has lead to a thorough understanding of the impli-
cations of its structure and to extensions of the basic index. The Gini coe¢cient
has also seen considerable use in applied economics.
The basic Gini index, G, can be expressed in several alternative, but equiva-
lent, ways. The …rst method of expressing the Gini is the most straightforward
mathematically but in itself carries little obvious meaning. In this case, the Gini
appears as the following a¢ne function of a weighted sum of relative incomes
1 2 £ ¤
G = 1+ ¡ 2 M H + 2M H¡ 1 + ::: + [H ¡ 1] M 2 + HM 1 : (3.21)
H H ¹
The second formulation expresses the means by which the …rst was derived.
The Gini index considers all possible pairs of incomes and out of each pair
selects the minimum income level. Summing and normalising provides a formula
equivalent to (3.21) but demonstrating more clearly the process involved
H H
1 XX © ª
G = 1+¡ 2
min M i ; M j : (3.22)
H ¹ i=1 j=1

The …nal way of expressing the Gini coe¢cient exploit its relationship to the
Lorenz curve. As illustrated in Figure 3.5, the Gini index is equal to the area
between the Lorenz curve and the line of equality as a proportion of the area
of the triangle beneath the line of equality. If the area of the box is normalised
at 1, the Gini coe¢cient is then twice the area between the Lorenz curve and
the equality line. Expressed in this way, it can be seen that the Gini coe¢cient
can take values lying between 0 and 1. This de…nition of the Gini index makes
it clear that the Gini can be used to rank distributions when the Lorenz curves
cross since the relevant areas are always well de…ned. Since the measures are
all stronger than the Lorenz dominance criteria, they must each contain some
additional assumptions over and above those which are present in the Lorenz
curve comparisons. What this extra structure involves will be investigated below
when statistical measures are related to social welfare.
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 77
userdict
/mypsb
/psb
currentpoint
/newXScale
/newYScale
{} store
/psb
/md /picOriginY
/newHeight
pop
newHeight
newWidth
load
known{/CricketAdjust
/pse/newWidth
def
{} store
/mypse
266
145
exch
exch
div
div
exch
/pse
picOriginY
defdef
def
/picOriginX
picOriginX
load
truedef
def}{/CricketAdjust
sub def
sub
exch
pop
def
def false def}ifelse

Figure 3.5: Relating Gini to Lorenz

The Gini index is a relative index of inequality so that it is independent of


scale and it also satis…es the Pigou-Dalton This can be seen by considering a
transfer from household i to household j of ¢M with the households chosen so
that M i > M j . From the ranking of incomes this implies j > i. Then
¡2
¢G = [j ¡ i] < 0; (3.23)
H 2¹
as required. It is important to note that the e¤ect of the transfer on the index
depends only on the relative rankings of i and j in the income distribution. For
example, a transfer from i = 1 to j = 11 counts as much as one from i = 151
to j = 161. It might be expected that an index should be more sensitive to
transfers between households low in the income distribution but it is actually
most sensitive to transfers around the modal income.
A …nal relevant property of the Gini index is that the Gini can incorporate
the negative income observations which often arise in income data. Extensions
of the Gini index are analysed in Donaldson and Weymark (1980) and Weymark
(1979a).

Theil’s entropy measure


The entropy measure of Theil (1967) is drawn from information theory and,
in particular, the measurement of the average information content of a system
of information. Although there is little apparent economic motivation in the
construction of the entropy measure, it will appear below when decomposable
inequality measures are discussed.
The de…nition of the (normalised) Theil entropy index, T , is given by
H ¸ H
1 X Mh Mh 1 1 X Mh Mh
T = log ¡ log = log : (3.24)
log H H¹ H¹ H H log H ¹ ¹
h=1 h=1
78 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

In respect of the Pigou-Dalton criteria, the e¤ect of an income transfer, d",


between households i and j upon the entropy index is given by
¸
dT 1 Mj
= log i < 0; (3.25)
d" H¹ log H M

so that the entropy measure does satisfy the criteria. However, the change in
the index now depends on the relative incomes of the two households involved
in the transfer. Whether this form of sensitivity to transfers is the correct one
is again open to question.
This concludes the review of the statistical measures of inequality. At a
number of points in the discussion reference has been made to acceptable cri-
teria for an inequality index to possess and to whether the properties of the
indices, such as the manner in which they were a¤ected by transfers, were sat-
isfactory. Obviously, to judge whether criteria are acceptable or not requires
the existence of some underlying notion of distributive justice or social welfare.
Two questions then arise. Firstly, to what extent can income distributions be
compared without the need for an explicit welfare function and, secondly, do
the statistical measures of inequality have implied social welfare functions? The
answers to these questions constitute the subject of the next section.

3.4.3 Statistical measures and welfare


One of the signi…cant developments in the theory of inequality measurement
was the clari…cation of the link between statistical measures and social welfare.
There are two aspects involved in this link. The …rst concerns the extent to
which income distributions can be ranked in terms of inequality without speci-
fying a precise social welfare function and the link between such a ranking and
the statistical measures. The essential work in this respect was undertaken by
Atkinson (1970), Dasgupta et al. (1973) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1973).
The second aspect is rather more subtle and involves the construction of the
social welfare function implied by an inequality measure. This line of enquiry is
exempli…ed by the work of Blackorby and Donaldson (1978). Throughout this
section it is assumed that the income distributions to be ranked have the same
mean level of income.
To discuss the extent to which distributions can be ranked without specifying
a precise welfare function it is necessary to introduce a number of de…nitions.
A square matrix is said to be bistochastic if its entries are nonnegative and each
of its rows and column sum to 1. A permutation matrix is a bistochastic matrix
that has a single positive element in each row and column. For example the
matrix
2 3
0:5 0:2 0:3
4 0:1 0:6 0:3 5 ; (3.26)
0:4 0:2 0:4
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 79

is bistochastic and 2 3
0 1 0
4 1 0 0 5; (3.27)
0 0 1
is a permutation matrix. The permutation matrices form the extreme points of
the set of bistochastic matrices.
The relevance of these concepts are that given a bistochastic matrix Q and
an income vector M , the vector M f = QM represents an averaging of M , or
equivalently, could be obtained from M by a series of transfers from rich to
poor. If P is a permutation matrix, then M c = P M is obtained from M by
re-ordering the components of M .
Now consider a social welfare function
¡ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢¢ ¡ ¢
W =W f U 1 M 1 ; :::; U H M H = W M 1 ; :::; M H ; (3.28)

where W (¢) is increasing in its arguments. The welfare function is symmetric if

W (M ) = W (P M ) ; (3.29)

for all permutation matrices P and Schur-concave (or S -concave) if

W (QM ) ¸ W (M ) : (3.30)

The social welfare function is strictly S -concave if the inequality is strict for
all bistochastic matrices which are not permutation matrices. The assumption of
S -concavity is a natural one in the context of inequality since QM can obtained
from M by transfers from rich to poor and a welfare function that is sensitive
to distribution should increase with such transfers. Conversely, an inequality
index is S -convex if I (QM ) I (M ).
The interconnections between these concepts and the inequality indices al-
ready discussed are summarised in the following lemma due to Kolm (1969) and
Dasgupta et al. (1973).
³ ´ ³ ´
Lemma 12 Given two income vectors M ^ = M ^ 1; :::; M
^ H and M~ = M ~ 1 ; :::; M
~H ,
PH ^ h PH ~ h , which are ordered so that M ^1 ^2 ^H
with h=1 M = h =1 M M ::: M
and M ~1 M ~ 2 ::: M ~ H , then the following four conditions are equivalent:
(i) there exists a bistochastic matrix Q (which is not a permutation matrix)
such that ~ = QM ^;
PMk P P P
(ii) h= 1 M ^h ¸ k M ~ h for all k H and H M ^h = H M ~ h;
h=1 h= 1 h=1
~ can be obtained from M
(iii) M ^ by a sequence of transfers, with all transfers
from richer³to ´poorer households;
³ ´
(iv) W M ~ >W M ^ for all strictly S-concave functions W (¢).

Proof. The proof that (i) to (iii) are equivalent can be found in Berge (1963).
That (i) implies (iv) follows directly from the assumption of strict S -concavity.
This shows the equivalence of (i) to (iv). jj
80 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

The interpretation of this lemma rests on the observation that (ii) is simply
the statement that the Lorenz curve for distribution M ~ lies everywhere inside
^
that for M . The equivalence of this to (iv) then implies that all S -concave social
welfare functions will assign greater welfare to the distribution that is ranked
higher by the Lorenz criterion. Hence when a ranking can be derived by the
Lorenz criterion, this ranking will be agreed by all S -concave welfare functions.
To complete this discussion, it is noted that S -concavity is a weaker concept
than quasiconcavity; hence any symmetric quasiconcave function is S -concave.
Slightly di¤erent versions of this result can be found in Rothschild and Stiglitz
(1973) and treatment of the continuous case in Atkinson (1970).
The converse of Lemma ?? is that if the Lorenz curves for two distributions
cross, then quasiconcave social welfare functions can be found that will rank the
two distributions di¤erently.
Put together, the lemma and its converse show that the Lorenz dominance
criteria provides the most complete ranking of income distributions that is pos-
sible given only that social welfare is an S -concave function of incomes. To
provide a complete ranking when Lorenz curves cross requires more restrictions
to be placed upon the structure of the social welfare function. In addition, any
index of inequality is necessarily stronger than Lorenz dominance and, when it
can be derived from a social welfare function, is derived from a social welfare
function that has more structure than simply satisfying S -concavity (and may
not even satisfy that condition).
The preceding discussion has demonstrated that the statistical inequality
indices may represent social welfare functions with restrictive properties. To
formalise this link consider a social welfare function
¡ ¢
w = W M 1 ; :::; M H = W (M ) ; (3.31)
that is S -concave and increasing along rays, so that W (¸M ) > W (M ) ; ¸ > 1.
Corresponding to this social welfare function is its transformation, or distance,
function D (w; M ) de…ned by
½ µ ¶ ¾
M
D (w; M ) = max W ¸w : (3.32)
¸ ¸
The transformation function determines the maximum extent to which the in-
come vector in a given situation can be reduced while social welfare remains on,
or above, a target level. From its construction, it can be seen that D (w; M )
is homogeneous of degree 1 in M and strictly decreasing in w. The distance
function is also an implicit representation of the social welfare function since
solving

D (w; M ) = 1; (3.33)
generates the initial social welfare function.
Employing the transformation function, Blackorby and Donaldson (1978)
suggest as an index of equality (the converse of an inequality index) the function
E (w; M ) de…ned by
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 81

D (w; M )
E (w; M ) = ; (3.34)
D (w; ¹e)
where e is the vector (1,...,1). The interpretation of (3.34) is that it measures
the proportion total income can be reduced if it is distributed equally while
remaining on the same level surface of the transformation function. If the so-
cial welfare function is homothetic then D (w; M ) can be written in the form
D (w; M ) = µ (w) D ~ (M ) and the index is independent of the base level of wel-
fare or reference-level-free; in all other cases it will be dependent on its base. In
addition, if social welfare is homothetic then
³ ´ ³ ´ ³ ´ ³ ´
E w; M ~ ¸ E w; M ^ () W M ~ ¸W M ^ ; (3.35)

so that the index has normative signi…cance. It can also be shown that E (w; M )
is homogeneous of degree zero in M and S -concave in M .
To construct a social welfare function from an equality measure, note that
since D (w; M ) is homogeneous of degree 1 in M it follows that

D (w; ¹e) = ¹D (w; e) = ¹Ã (w) : (3.36)


Equation (3.34) can therefore be rearranged to give

D (w; M ) = Ã (w) ¹E (w; M ) : (3.37)


In (3.37), Ã (w) implies the form of the transformation function and is essentially
arbitrary except for the requirement that must be decreasing in w. If E (w; M )
is S -concave in M , so is D (w; M ). A social welfare function can then be
generated by solving D (w; M ) = Ã (w) ¹E (w; M ) = 1, with a social welfare
function for each à (W ). For this constructed welfare function, the implied
measure of equality is, of course, E (w; M ).
The connection of this result with statistical measures of inequality is given
in the Theorem 3.1.

Theorem 13 (Blackorby and Donaldson) If the index of equality is reference-


level-free then the implied social welfare functions are homothetic. Conversely, if
the social welfare function is homothetic then its measure of equality is reference-
level-free.

Proof. A reference-level-free equality index can be written E (W; M ) ´


E (M ) so that D (w; M ) = Ã (w) D (M ) = Ã (w) ¹E (M ). Solving around 1
¡ ¢ h i¡ 1
1
gives w = W (M ) = f D (M ) with f = Ã(w) . Hence f is increasing in w
and D (M ) is homogeneous of degree 1. This implies W (M ) is homothetic. If
¡ ¢
W (M ) is homothetic then W (M ) = Á W (M ) with W (M ) homogeneous of
degree©1. The transformation
¡ ¡ ¢¢ function
ª for W (M ) is then de…ned by D (w; M ) =
max¸ ¸ > 0 : Á W M ¸ ¸ w = Á 1¡1 W (M ) = Ã (w) W (M ) = Ã (w) D (M )
82 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

© ¡ ¢ ª
where D (M ) = max¸ ¸ > 0 : W M
¸
¸ w . D (M ) is homogeneous of degree
à (w)D(M ) D( M )
1 so that the index of equality can be written E (w; M ) = = ¹
=
à (w)D(¹e)
E (M ) where the normalisation D (e) = 1 has been employed. This proves the
equality measure is reference-level-free. jj
The proof of Theorem 3.1 provides the statement required for the construc-
tion of the social welfare functions underlying the statistical measures. It has
been shown that for reference-level-free indices, which all the statistical indices
given above are, the identity D (M ) = ¹E (M ) holds. Given E (M ) the trans-
formation function can be calculated from this identity and then solved to give
the social welfare function.
Blackorby and Donaldson show that the welfare functions corresponding to
the Gini and Theil entropy inequality indices are given respectively by

1 £ H ¤
WG (M ) = M + 3M H¡1 + ::: + [2H ¡ 1] M 1 ; (3.38)
H 2

and
" H
#
1 X
h h
W T (M ) = H¹ log H¹ ¡ M log M : (3.39)
H log H
h=1

The form of W G (M ) is particularly interesting since it shows that the Gini


coe¢cient is implied by a quasi-concave, but not strictly quasi-concave, and
homothetic so cial welfare function. This observation clari…es a number of the
issues raised in Newbery (1970) and Sheshinski (1972a) concerning the form
that the social welfare function consistent with the Gini must take. In addition,
it can be seen that none of these functions is obviously superior to the others
as a measure of social welfare.
This section has investigated the link between statistical measures of inequal-
ity and social welfare. The …rst lemma demonstrated that the Lorenz ranking
is consistent with that produced by any S -concave social welfare function so
that to proceed beyond the Lorenz criterion it is necessary to provide further
restrictions upon the social welfare function. The statistical measures can be re-
lated to social welfare functions that have properties stronger than S-concavity.
It was shown how equality measures could be constructed from a social wel-
fare function and how the converse construction could also be achieved. The
resulting forms of social welfare function for three of the statistical measures
could then be seen to embody very particular, and not necessarily acceptable,
assumptions.

3.4.4 Generalised Lorenz Curves


The relation between the Lorenz curve and the ranking introduced by a social
welfare function summarised by Lemma 3.1 concerned only the ranking of in-
come distributions with the same mean level of income. Analogous results for
the ranking of income distributions with di¤erent means have been derived by
Shorrocks (1983) using the Generalised Lorenz curve.
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 83

Assume that the social welfare function is of the form (3.31), is S -concave
and is non-decreasing in each income level so that all h. Given two income
distributions and , then it is clear that for any S -concave and non-decreasing
social welfare function if the Lorenz curve of lies inside that of and the mean
of is greater than that . To proceed beyond these su¢cient conditions, it is
necessary to introduce the Generalised Lorenz curve.
Generalised Lorenz curve
In the continuous case the coordinates of the Generalised Lorenz curve are
given by µZ m Z ¶
1 m
° (M ) dM; M ° (M ) dM ; (3.40)
0 ¹ 0
³ Ph ´
Mi
(and in the discrete case by Hh ; i=1 H .)
In the continuous case the Generalised Lorenz curve is a continuous curve
connecting (0; 0) to (1; ¹). The same is true in the discrete case if the discrete
points are connected by straight lines and the point for h = 1 is connected to
the origin.
Theorem 3.2 determines the relation between the ranking of income distrib-
utions with di¤erent means by the Generalised Lorenz curve and by the social
welfare function.
³ ´ ³ ´
Theorem 14 (Shorrocks) W M c ¸W M f for all non-decreasing S-concave
Ph Ph
ci
M fi
M
social welfare functions if and only if i=1
H
¸ i=1
H
so that the Generalised
Lorenz curve for M c lies inside that for M
f.

h
f
f by ff =M fh for h = 1; :::; H ¡ 1
Proof. To prove the “if“ part, de…ne M M
H
f
f =M fH + H [b
andµ M ¶ ¹¡e ¹]. As the social welfare function is non-decreasing,
³ ´ P h ci Ph f i
f
f ¸W M f . In addition, since b e M f
i=1 M
W M ¹=¹ e and i=1H ¸ H for all h,
³ ´ µ ¶ ³ ´
f
c lies inside that for M
f so W M c ¸W M f
f ¸W M f .
the Lorenz curve for M
Ph
Mi
To prove the “only if“ de…ne Wh (M ) = , h ³= 1;
i=1
h ´ :::; H, and
³ ´note
c
that Wh (M ) is S -concave and non-decreasing. Then W h M ¸ W h M f for
Ph Ph
ci
M fi
M
all h only if i=1H
¸ i=1H
.
This theorem demonstrates that a ranking of two income distributions with
di¤erent means can only be unambiguous if the Generalised Lorenz curves do
not intersect. It also shows that even if the Lorenz curves for two distributions
intersect, the condition on the Generalised Lorenz curve may still be satis…ed.

3.4.5 Welfare-theoretic indices


The discussion above has emphasised the unsatisfactory nature of the implicit
welfare assumptions that are embodied in statistical measures of inequality. A
84 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

response to this is to make the welfare judgements explicit by deriving the in-
equality measure from a speci…c social welfare function. One method of achiev-
ing this was discussed in the previous section; the present section considers the
method of equally distributed equivalent incomes suggested by Dalton (1920),
Kolm (1969) and Atkinson (1970). With this procedure, social concern for eq-
uity can be incorporated in the index by the choice of the utility of income func-
tion assigned to households and the function employed for aggregating household
utilities into social welfare.
To simplify, assume social welfare can be represented by a utilitarian social
welfare function
H
X ¡ ¢
W = U Mh ; (3.41)
h =1

where the household utility of income function, U (M ), is increasing and strictly


concave so that U 0 (M ) > 0 and U 00 (M ) < 0. Utility U (M ) can either be the
true cardinal utility function representing households’ preferences or it can be
chosen by the state as its evaluation of the utility of income to each household.
In this second interpretation, since social welfare is then obtained by adding the
individual utilities, welfare judgements can be captured in the choice of U (M ).
Increasing the concavity of the utility function e¤ectively places a higher weight
on low incomes. ¡ ¢
Before specifying a useful form of U M h , it is possible to derive the measure
of inequality proposed by Kolm (1969) and Atkinson (1970). De…ne M EDE as
the solution to
XH
¡ ¢
U M h = HU (M EDE ) : (3.42)
h =1

MEDE is called the equally distributed equivalent income and is that level of
income that if given to all households would generate the same level of social
welfare as the initial income distribution.
Using the de…nition of ME DE , the Atkinson-Kolm index is given by
M EDE ¹ ¡ M E DE
A = 1¡ = : (3.43)
¹ ¹
The concavity of the household utility function guarantees that index A is non-
negative. In addition, it is independent of the mean level of income and is
therefore a relative index.
For a two-household economy the construction of M EDE is illustrated in
Figure 3.6. The initial income distribution is given by M 1 , M 2 and this deter-
mines the relevant indi¤erence curve of the social welfare function. M EDE is
found by moving round this indi¤erence curve to the line of equal incomes. It is
clear the because of the concavity of the social indi¤erence curve ME DE is less
than the mean income, ¹.
The ‡exibility of this index lies in the freedom of choice of the utility of
income function and it is this function that determines the importance attached
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 85

Figure 3.6: The Equally Distributed Equivalent Income

to inequality by the index. One form of utility function that was proposed by
Atkinson (1970) is
M 1¡ " 0
U (M ) = ; U (M ) = M ¡" ; " 6= 1: (3.44)
1¡"
This function is isoelastic and concave if " ¸ 0. At " = 1 and " = 0. the function
takes the following form

" = 1 ) U (M ) = log M ; " = 0 ) U (M ) = M: (3.45)


The welfare judgements of the policy-maker are contained in the chosen value
of " since " determines the degree of concavity of the utility function. Increasing
" makes the utility function more concave and reduces the importance given to
high income in the determination of social welfare. Utility function (3.44) has
found numerous uses in applications of public economics.
The Atkinson-Kolm index is an attempt to make explicit the welfare judge-
ments that are contained within statistical measures of inequality. Although the
derivation above worked with a utilitarian social welfare function, this is not es-
sential and it can be seen that the de…nition of equally distributed equivalent
income applies to any form of welfare function. Within this framework, how-
ever, there is considerable ambiguity as to the distinction between the form of
social welfare and the form of individual utility. As noted, the utility of income
function can either be the true function capturing households’ preferences or it
can be the state’s evaluation of income to households. In the latter case, the
distinction between individual utility and social welfare becomes arbitrary.
86 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

3.4.6 Axiomatic inequality measures


The aim of the axiomatic approach to inequality measurement is to derive the set
of inequality indices that satisfy a chosen set of axioms. The axioms are chosen
to capture what are viewed as the desirable properties for an index to possess
and the set of derived indices will constitute all indices with those properties.
As the number of independent axioms is increased, the set of indices that satisfy
them will generally decrease. This is advantageous in focusing attention on a
reduced set of alternative indices and in clarifying which properties indices that
do not satisfy the axioms fail to possess.
A number of potential axioms have already been noted informally in the
above discussion. The …rst of these, and the least questionable, is the axiom
of symmetry. Letting the index of inequality, I (M ; H ), depend on the income
distribution, M , and population size, H, this axiom can be stated as
Axiom I1 (Symmetry)
I (M ; H) = I (P M; H) for all permutation matrices P .
This axiom has also been termed anonymity and requires that the inequality
measure is not a¤ected by the order in which households are labelled. The
second axiom usually invoked relates to S -concavity of social welfare and the
principle of transfers.
Axiom I2 (Transfer)
I (QM ; H ) < I (M ; H) for all bistochastic matrices which are not permuta-
tion matrices.
The direction of this inequality implies that the inequality measure is an
S -convex function of incomes.
Axioms other than I1 and I2 do not meet with universal approval. This
can either be on the grounds that they are not strictly necessary, which is the
case for the decomposability axioms introduced below, or because there exists
an alternative property to that expressed by the axiom which could be equally
justi…ed. Such is the case for the next axiom.
Axiom I3 (Relative)
I (¸M ; H) = I (M ; H ) for all ¸ > 0.
Axiom I3 captures the notion of inequality as a relative concept and states
that a proportional increase in all incomes should leave inequality unchanged.
This has been termed rightist by Kolm (1976). An alternative to Axiom I3 is
Axiom I3’ (Absolute)
I (M + ¿ e; H ) = I (M; H) for all ¿ such that M + ¿ e ¸ 0;
which has been termed leftist. An intermediate axiom between I3 and I3’,
termed ¹-invariance by Eichhorn (1988), is the following
Axiom I3” (Intermediate)
I (M + ¿ [¹M + [1 ¡ ¹] e] ; H) = I (M; H ) for all 0 < ¹ < 1 and M +
¿ [¹M + [1 ¡ ¹] e] ¸ 0:
Clearly, I3” would reduce to I3 if ¹ = 1 and to I3’ if ¹ = 0.
Fields and Fei (1978) and Foster (1983) note that many of the standard
statistical measures, including C, G, A, and T, satisfy axioms I1 - I3. This
point was implicit in the previous discussion. For the alternative axioms I3’ and
3.4. THE MEASUREMENT OF INEQUALITY 87

I3”, Eichhorn (1988) classi…es the set of functions that satisfy axioms I1, I2 and
one of I3 - I3”. This class of functions has the general form
µ ¶
¹M + [1 ¡ ¹] e M 1 + ::: + M H
I (M ; H ) = Á ; ® (M ) = ; (3.46)
¹® (M ) + [1 ¡ ¹] H
where Á (¢) is Schur-convex and satis…es Á (e) = 0. An application of these
alternative axioms can be found in P…ngsten (1986) where tax changes that are
inequality-neutral under the alternative criteria are identi…ed.
A second aspect of inequality measurement that has been pursued via the
axiomatic approach is that of decomposability. Let the population be divided
into subgroups 1; :::; g; :::; G with the population in each being H g . An inequality
measure is decomposable if total inequality can be found by a weighted sum of
the inequality within the subgroups and between the subgroups. De…ning M g
as the income vector within group g, ¹g as the mean income of group g and e g
as the vector of 1s with H g entries, decomposability is captured in the following
axiom
Axiom I4 (Theil Decomposability)
PG P Hg h
h=1 M
I (M1 ; :::; MG ; H) = g =1 w G G
g I (M g ; H)+I (¹1 e1 ; :::; ¹G eG ; H) ; w g = P H M h :
h=1
With this de…nition of decomposability, the weights are the ratio of the total
income in subgroup g to total income in the population. The following theorem
is proved in Foster (1983).

Theorem 15 (Foster) An inequality index satis…es axioms I1, I2, I3 and I4 if


and only if it is a positive multiple of T .
Proof. See Foster (1983).
The surprising conclusion of Theorem 3.3 concerns the emergence of Theil’s
entropy index, T , as the unique index that satis…es decomposability as de…ned
in I4. Although this index appears to have little economic motivation, it does
have receive convincing support from an axiomatic derivation. In contrast, other
indices which appear more appealing on the surface fail to satisfy the required
criteria. A more general result on decomposable indices is proved in Shorrocks
(1984). Replacing I4 by
Axiom I4’ (Decomposability) ¡ ¢
A decomposable index satis…es I (M 1 ; M 2 ) = A I (M 1 ) ; ¹1 ; H 1; I (M 2) ; ¹2 ; H 2
where A is continuous and strictly increasing in I (M 1 ) and I (M 2 ).
Shorrocks proves the following theorem.

Theorem 16 (Shorrocks) An inequality index satis…es I1, I2, I3, I4’ and if
and only if there exists a parameter c and function , continuous and strictly
increasing in I with such that

1 1
PH hh M h ic i
H c[c¡1] h= 1 ¹
¡ 1 if c 6= 0; 1;
PH h M h h
i
F (I (M ) ; H ) = H
1
h=1
M
¹ log ¹ if c = 1;
1
PH Mh
H h =1 log ¹ if c = 0:
88 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

Proof. See Shorrocks (1984).


The class of inequality measures identi…ed in Theorem 3.4 are termed Gen-
eralised Entropy indices and include the Theil index (3.28) as a special case. In
essence, the theorem shows that once decomposability is imposed, the class of
inequality measures reduces to the Generalised Entropy indices.
Further results on decomposable indices can be found in Bourguignon (1979)
and Shorrocks (1980) who consider alternative de…nitions of decomposability,
and Cowell and Kuga (1981). Pyatt (1985) provides a rather di¤erent set of
axioms which characterise the Gini index.

3.4.7 Summary
The section began with an introduction to statistical measures of inequality
which, at …rst sight, appeared to avoid the requirement for welfare analysis.
Closer inspection of these indices indicated that each embodied implicit wel-
fare assumptions and that their failings emphasised basic criteria that an index
should satisfy. The …rst point was developed by considering the metho dology
of Blackorby and Donaldson (1978) for generating inequality measures from so-
cial welfare functions and constructing underlying social welfare functions from
inequality measures. The examples given underline the belief that statistical
measures can have unsatisfactory welfare implications. One response to this
has been the suggestion that an explicit social welfare function should form the
basis of the inequality measure and an example of this approach, the Kolm-
Atkinson index, was described. The existence of basic criteria for an index to
satisfy has been developed into the axiomatic approach to inequality. Some of
the directions in which this can be taken were illustrated by the study of rela-
tive and absolute measures and decomposability. It was surprising to …nd that
decomposability led back to one of the statistical measures.

3.5 The measurement of poverty


The measurement of poverty involves may of the same issues as the measurement
of inequality and it can be argued, as most notably in Lewis and Ulph (1988),
that the two are simply di¤erent aspects of the same phenomenon. As with
inequality, it is easy to appreciate at an abstract level what constitutes poverty
and an increase in poverty but di¢culties arise once an attempt is made to
provide a quantitative representation.
The presentation of this section is somewhat similar to that on inequality.
After discussing competing notions of poverty and intro ducing the necessary
de…nitions, a number of standard poverty measures are discussed and the critical
discussion of these leads naturally into an axiomatic approach. The ma jor
distinction between the measurement of inequality and poverty is that the latter
necessitates the identi…cation of those households in poverty as distinct form
those which are not. Identi…cation, which is discussed in detail in Sen (1979),
is typically based on the idea of a level of income, termed the poverty line,
3.5. THE MEASUREMENT OF POVERTY 89

above which a household is no longer in poverty. The poverty line is therefore


of central importance in the measurement of poverty so that methods to de…ne
the poverty line and attempts to avoid some of its implications will both be
discussed.

3.5.1 Relative or absolute?


Before measuring poverty, it is …rst necessary to de…ne it. It is obvious that
poverty refers to a situation involving a lack of income and consequent low level
of consumption and welfare. What is not so clear is the standard against which
the level of income should be judged. Two possibilities arise in this context: an
absolute conception of poverty and a relative one. The distinction between these
has implications for changes in the level of poverty over time and the success of
policy in alleviating poverty.

Absolute poverty

The concept of absolute poverty assumes that there is some …xed minimum level
of consumption (or similarly of income) that constitutes poverty and that is
independent of time or place. Such a minimum level of consumption is often
taken to be a diet that is su¢cient to maintain health and provision of housing
and clothing. From this view, if the incomes of all households rise, there will
eventually be no poverty. Viewed as an absolute concept, it is possible for
poverty to be eliminated.
Although a concept of absolute poverty was probably implicit in early studies
of poverty, such as Rowntree (1901, 1941) and in the claims following Rowntree
and Lavers (1951) that poverty was no longer a problem, the appropriateness of
absolute poverty has since generally been rejected. In its place has been adopted
the notion of relative poverty.

Relative poverty
The concept of relative poverty is not a recent one; it is only the usage of the
concept that has been recently adopted. Its history can be traced back to at
least Adam Smith (1776) who frames the de…nition of relative poverty as the
lack of necessities, where necessities are de…ned as “what ever the custom of the
country renders it indecent for creditable people, even of the lowest order, to
be without“. It is clear from this de…nition that relative poverty is de…ned in
terms of the standards and norms of a given society at a given time. As the
standard of living of the society rises and more goods are required to be decent,
the income level required to be out of poverty must increase.
The notion of relative poverty has also been advocated more recently in
Townsend’s (1979) discussion of participation in society. This approach to
poverty considers whether the household possesses su¢cient resources to al-
low it to participate in the activities which are customary for the economy to
which it belongs. The ability to participate is clearly a relative concept and this
90 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

view captures much the same features as that of Smith. Relative poverty is also
embodied in the measurement of poverty in the U.K. and E.U.
The adoption of either an absolute or relative view of poverty does have
implications for how the poverty line is determined for a particular economy at
a particular time but is of most consequence for comparisons of poverty across
time or across economies and in the properties that it is felt a satisfactory
poverty measure should have. The latter aspect will become evident in the
speci…cation of axioms for poverty measures.

3.5.2 The poverty line


As already noted, the starting point for the measurement of poverty is to de-
termine a poverty line. The poverty line is de…ned here as that level of income
on or below which a household is de…ned as being in poverty. It should be
noted that this de…nition is not universally agreed and the poverty line is often
interpreted as the level of income just su¢cient to move the household out of
poverty. This procedure is somewhat arbitrary since it is di¢cult to accept such
a precise cut-o¤ between poverty and non-poverty. It is now standard practice
and is followed throughout almost all the literature.
In practice, poverty lines have often been determined by following the mini-
mum needs approach that was discussed in connection with equivalence scales.
As noted in Sawhill (1988), this is the case with the U.S. poverty line that was
set in 1965 and has been updated for in‡ation since. The practice in the U.K.
has been to set the poverty line as the level of income which is 120% or 140%
of the minimum supplementary bene…t level (see Callan and Nolan (1991)) but,
since this level of bene…t is itself determined by minimum needs, this amounts
to a minimum needs poverty line. In addition, since the level of bene…ts have
tended to rise with increases in average income, this embodies some aspects of
relative poverty.
An alternative approach that has also been used is the Engel method of
employing the proportion of income spent on food as an indicator of welfare
with those in excess of a critical proportion being deemed as living in poverty.
For examples of this approach see Rao (1981). Desai and Shah (1988) argue
that poverty should be measured by the distance of a household’s consumption
experience from the norm.
Obviously, these do not exhaust the possible methods of de…ning the poverty
line and debate about what constitutes the poverty line and how it changes over
time cannot be avoided.

3.5.3 Standard measures


Prior to the recent interest in poverty measurement following the work of Sen
(1976), the number of available poverty measures was rather limited. E¤ectively,
the measurement of poverty would be based upon either the headcount ratio or
some variant of the income gap ratio. These measures are now discussed both for
3.5. THE MEASUREMENT OF POVERTY 91

their historical importance and because of the role they play in the development
of later measures.
It is …rst necessary to introduce the following notation that is used exten-
sively below. The poverty line is denoted by z, so that any income level below or
equal to z represents poverty. For a typical household, h, gh (M ; z) ´ z ¡ M h ,
is the income shortfall of household h and measures the extent to which the
household is below the poverty line. Given the poverty line z and an income
distribution M , the number of households in poverty is given by q = q (M; z).
The dimensionality of the income distribution vector determines the size of the
population, H, via the relation H = H (M ).
The headcount ratio measures the extent of poverty by counting the number
of households whose incomes are not above the poverty line. Expressing this as
a proportion of the population, the headcount ratio is de…ned by
q
E= : (3.47)
H
This measure of poverty was used by Rowntree (1901) and has been used in
many subsequent studies.
The major advantage of the headcount ratio is its simplicity of calculation.
Its major disadvantage is that it pays no attention to how far the households
fall below the poverty line and therefore gives no indication of how costly it
would be to alleviate the observed poverty. In addition, a transfer from a poor
household to one that is slightly richer does not change E if both households
remain on the same side of the poverty line and will actually reduce it if the
transfer takes the recipient’s income above z.
The aggregate poverty gap and the income gap ratio both take account of
how far below the poverty line are the incomes of the poor households. They
are de…ned respectively by
Xq
V = gh; (3.48)
h =1

and
q
X
1 gh
I = : (3.49)
q (M ; z) z
h= 1

Since both measures take account of income shortfalls, they do provide infor-
mation on the expenditure needed to eliminate poverty but, because they give
equal weight to all income shortfalls, they are not sensitive to transfers unless
the transfer takes one of the households out of poverty.

3.5.4 Axiomatic approach


As with inequality measurement, these criticisms of the basic measures indicates
the existence of beliefs about the properties that a poverty measure must have.
Having noted this, an axiomatic approach follows naturally. Two alternative
axiomatic developments will now be considered: the original derivation of Sen
(1976) and the axiom system of Foster, Greer and Thorbecke (1984).
92 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

Denoting a poverty measure as a function P (M ; z), a basic set of axioms


for poverty measurement begin with the focus axiom which restricts attention
to the incomes of those in poverty.
Axiom P1 (Focus)
c is obtained from M
If income distribution M f
³ ´ by ³a change
´ in incomes of
households above the poverty line then P Mf; z = P M c; z .
The second axiom expresses the requirement that measured poverty must
increase when the income level of any of the poor households falls. This axiom
is termed monotonicity.
Axiom P2 (Monotonicity)
c is obtained from M
If income distribution M f by reducing the income of
³ ´
h
household h, M < z, and all other incomes remain unchanged then P M f; z <
³ ´
P M c; z .
As discussed in connection with inequality, the level of poverty should not
be a¤ected by a re-labelling of the households. This property is captured by the
symmetry axiom.
Axiom P3 (Symmetry) ³ ´
c= PM
If income distribution M f for some permutation matrix then P M f; z =
³ ´
P M c; z .
These three axioms are perhaps the least contentious, although poverty mea-
sures that do not satisfy P1 have been considered, for example Beckerman (1979)
employs the aggregate poverty gap as a proportion of aggregate income. They
are, however, usually adopted as the basis of an axiomatic system. De…ning a
regressive transfer to be a transfer from a household to one with a higher income
level, the fourth axiom relates to the e¤ect of transfers upon measured poverty.
Axiom P4 (Transfer)
If income distribution Mc is obtained from Mf by a regressive transfer among
³ ´ ³ ´
the poor households then P M f; z < P M c; z .
This is the …rst form of the transfer axiom; an alternative will be introduced
below.
Taken together, any poverty measure that satis…es these axioms must be a
strictly decreasing and strictly S -convex function of the incomes of the poor
households. Since the poverty measure is S -convex, it must also agree with
the Lorenz criteria applied to incomes below the poverty line. It can be seen
that neither the headcount ratio nor the income gap ratio satis…es the Lorenz
dominance criterion of 4.2.1 and therefore do not satisfy axioms P1 - P4. To
proceed beyond the Lorenz criteria requires the addition of further axioms.

Sen measure

Let ¡ denote the set of households with incomes on, or below, the poverty line;
there are q of these. Sen (1976) proposes that the general form of a poverty
3.5. THE MEASUREMENT OF POVERTY 93

measure should be given by a multiple of a weighted sum of income gaps


X
P (M ; z) = A (M ; z) gh (M ; z) v h (M ; z) ; (3.50)
h 2¡

where the form of A (M ; z) and the weights vh (M ; z) are determined by addi-


tional axioms.
To derive the form of Sen’s measure, two additional axioms are imposed.
The symmetry axiom permits the q households to be ranked with the household
closest to the poverty line given rank of 1 and the poorest household, that
furthest from the poverty line, given rank q. Let the rank of poor household h
be given by rh (M ; z). The next axiom is
Axiom P5 (Ranked deprivation)
The weight assigned to household h is given by their ranking amongst the
poor: vh (M ; z) = rh (M ; z).
The …fth of Sen’s axioms is derived by arguing that when all the households
in poverty have the same income, the level of poverty is measured by the product
of the headcount ratio and the income gap ratio. This axiom acts much in the
way of a normalisation to determine A (M ; z). Expressed as an axiom
Axiom P6 (Normalisation)
If M is such that M h = M ; h 2 ¡, then P (M ; z) = E I.
From these axioms follows the Sen measure
X ¸¸
2 q
S= g h rh = E I + [1 ¡ I] Gp ; (3.51)
[q + 1] Hz q+1
h 2¡

where Gp is the Gini index of income inequality amongst the households below
the poverty line. Expressed in the latter form, this poverty measure can be
seen as combining a measure of the shortfall of income of the poor with one of
distribution of income between the poor.
The method of constructing this measure illustrates the alternative directions
that could be taken. The general form given is not the only possibility and
Takayama (1979) presents an example of an alternative form. Using the ranking
of the poor as the weights is also restrictive; an alternative to this will be
considered below. Finally, the normalisation axiom is also arbitrary and any
number of other possibilities could be chosen. Although having many features
in its favour, the poverty measure (3.51) cannot be assigned any particularly
special value since any variation in the particular axioms chosen would lead to
a di¤erent index and some of the axioms are not entirely compelling.

Decomposability
An important class of poverty measures that constitute an alternative to (3.51)
have been derived on the basis of decomposability amongst subgroups. To
motivate this discussion, consider the poverty measure given by
1 X 2
P (M ; z) = g : (3.52)
H z2 h2¡ h
94 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT

The measure given in (3.52) is an example of the general form of measure given
by (3.50) but with the weights given by the income gap rather than the ranking.
Given the composition of (3.51) in terms of the Gini index, it is interesting to
note that (3.52) can also be written
h i
P (M ; z) = E I 2 + [1 ¡ I]2 Cp2 ; (3.53)

where C p is the coe¢cient of variation of income amongst the poor. Hence


(3.52) also captures poverty by combining total income shortfall and an index
of distribution.
To allow the index to be decomposable amongst subgroups, aggregate mea-
sured poverty must rise if it increases for any subgroup. This requirement is
captured by the following axiom.
Axiom P5 (Subgroup monotonicity)
c is obtained from M
If income distribution M f by increasing poverty in sub-
group g without a¤ecting
³ ´ either
³ the´ number in poverty or incomes in other
f
subgroups then P M ; z < P M ; z .c
An argument that can be levied against the transfer axiom, P4, is that the
e¤ect of the transfer should be dependent upon the incomes of those involved
in the transfer. For instance, a transfer away from the lowest income house-
hold should have more e¤ect on measured poverty than a transfer away from a
household closer to the poverty line. This interpretation of the transfer axiom
is captured in axiom P4’.
Axiom P4’ (Transfer sensitivity)
It a transfer t > 0 of income takes place from a poor household with income
M h to a poor household with income M h + d, d > 0, then the magnitude of the
increase in poverty must be smaller for larger M h .
Although the poverty measure de…ned by (3.52) does not satisfy P4’, its
form suggests a class of measures that do. Consider the following extension of
(3.52)
1 X h gh i ®
P® (M ; z) = ; (3.54)
H z
h2¡

and note that P0 = H, P1 = H:I. As a increases, more concern is placed on


the lower income level households which leads to the following proposition.

Theorem 17 (Foster, Greer, Thorbecke) P ® satis…es monotonicity, P3, for


® > 0, transfer, P4, for ® > 1 and transfer sensitivity, P4’, for ® > 2. In
addition, P ® satis…es subgroup monotonicity, P7.

Proof. Obvious by inspection.


In applications to data, for instance to Kenya in Foster, Greer and Thorbecke
(1984), P® measures have proved popular. However, the U.K. practice has
been to remain with the headcount ratio, as has the U.S., despite its faults
and the limited information it conveys. It is, however, statistically robust and
corresponds to a concept of poverty based on minimum rights, on the latter see
3.6. CONCLUSIONS 95

Atkinson (1985). There is therefore a growing di¤erence between the …rst-best


practice of economists and that of government.

3.5.5 Variable poverty line


The notion of the poverty line conveys a switch out of poverty as a households
income crosses the line. Two obvious di¢culties exist with this notion. First,
it is di¢cult to accept such a precise line between poverty and non-poverty.
It would seem more natural for there to be a gradual move out of poverty
as income increased. Secondly, the precision of the poverty line also leads to
di¢culty in determining where it should lie since the level of poverty may be
critically dependent on the precise level chosen.
These di¢culties can be overcome by observing that often it is not the precise
level of poverty that matters but changes in the level of poverty over time and
across countries. In these instances the poverty value is not too important but
only the rankings. This suggest the procedure of calculating poverty for a range
of poverty lines (Atkinson (1987)). If poverty is higher today for all poverty
lines than it was yesterday, then it seems unambiguous that poverty has risen.
In this sense, the poverty line may not actually be of critical importance for the
uses to which poverty measurement is often put.

3.6 Conclusions
The chapter began with the aim of studying measures of the state of an economy
which were intended to be independent of welfare criteria. To allow income lev-
els to be comparable between households of di¤erent demographic composition
equivalence scales need to be constructed. Although these have been computed
upon the basis of minimum needs and observed expenditure on food, careful
examination revealed de…ciencies in such approaches. It was then shown that,
if the household acts in accord the theory of utility maximisation, exact com-
parisons could only be made by basing the scales upon a comparison of house-
hold expenditure functions and hence upon the underlying utility functions.
A broadly similar conclusion was reached with measures of both inequality and
poverty: statistical measures that appear welfare-free are actually founded upon
implicit assumptions concerning the form of the social welfare function. In any
case, a close examination of the methodology lead back to the need for welfare-
theoretic constructions.
The response to this …nding can either be to construct the required index
directly form a speci…ed utility or social welfare function, as in the Atkinson-
Kolm inequality index for example, or to specify the properties that the measure
must possess and derive the measure from these. This latter approach has gained
popularity in the literature on inequality and poverty and has also lead to some
surprising conclusions. There remains further research to be undertaken, not
least in re…ning the link between inequality and poverty.
96 CHAPTER 3. TOPICS IN MEASUREMENT
Part II

Analysis in the competitive


model

97
Chapter 4

Commodity Taxation

4.1 Introduction
This chapter is the …rst to consider policy analysis and to arrive at character-
isations of optimal policies. The ideas that it surveys have developed over a
considerable period, beginning with the seminal contribution of Ramsey (1927).
One important feature of this development is the gradual increase in generality
and the recent move towards applying the theoretical analysis to data. This has
moved the theory closer to practical application.
The initial literature on commodity taxation focused upon the following
simple problem. There is a given level of government revenue to be raised
which must be …nanced solely by taxes upon commodities: how should these
taxes be set so as to minimise the cost to society of raising the required revenue?
If a social welfare function is adopted to represent the state’s preferences, the
problem can be conveniently rephrased as that of choosing the commodity tax
rates to maximise social welfare subject to the revenue constraint.
The …rst solution to this problem was given by Ramsey (1927) following its
proposal to him by Pigou. This contribution appears to have been overlooked
for the following forty years during which time the less general inverse elastici-
ties rule became a standard feature of textbooks. The results of Ramsey were
rediscovered by Samuelson (1986) in a 1951 memo to the U.S. Treasury. The
theory of commodity taxation was given its modern form by Diamond and Mir-
rlees (1971) in an analysis that made much use of the emerging duality methods
and results in general equilibrium theory. Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) derived
both single-household and many-household tax rules and proved the Produc-
tion E¢ciency Lemma. Developments since the publication of Diamond and
Mirrlees have been concerned with the practical implementation of the methods
of that paper and in extensions of the basic economy away from the standard
competitive framework with constant returns to scale.
It should be noted that there are close connections between the theory of
commodity taxation and that of public sector pricing. In both cases the gov-

99
100 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

ernment is choosing the set of consumer prices that maximise welfare subject
to a constraint. Under the commodity taxation interpretation these prices are
achieved by setting the level of tax to be included in each consumer price whereas
with public sector pricing the prices are chosen directly. However the choice of
tax rate is equivalent to the choice of consumer price. In the context of public
sector pricing, the optimal prices are generally known as Ramsey prices. The
constraint on the optimisation with commodity taxation requires the raising of
a speci…ed level of revenue. With public sector pricing this can be reinterpreted
as the need to raise a given level of revenue in excess of marginal cost. The tax
rates of the commodity taxation problem then translate into the mark-up over
marginal cost in the public sector pricing interpretation.
The chapter begins by deriving the single-household Ramsey rule and pro-
viding an interpretation of this. It is then shown how the inverse elasticity rule
follows as a special case. The extension to many consumers is made and the
resolution of the equity/e¢ciency trade-o¤ is emphasised. This is followed by
a review of numerical calculations of optimal taxes based on empirical data.
Three more specialised topics are then considered: generalising the production
technology; the status of untaxed goods; and conditions guaranteeing the uni-
formity of taxes. A discussion of the Diamond-Mirrlees Production E¢ciency
lemma concludes the chapter.

4.2 Methodology
The analysis restricts the set of feasible policy instruments available to the gov-
ernment to commodity taxes. The use of optimal lump-sum taxes is assumed
to be prevented by the arguments covered in chapter 2: the relevant character-
istics for the determination of taxes are preferences and endowments but these
are private information and will not be truthfully revealed under the optimal
tax system. In contrast, the employment of commodity taxes requires only that
the government is able to observe trades in commodities, which is a far weaker
informational requirement. Although it may be possible for the government to
levy a uniform lump-sum tax, and in a one-household economy such a tax would
also be optimal, it is assumed for simplicity that such taxes cannot be employed.
In an economy where the households are not identical, their introduction does
not signi…cantly modify the conclusions.
The standard methodology in optimal commodity tax theory has been to
consider only linear taxes, either additive so that the post-tax price of good i is
given by p i + ti or multiplicative with post-tax price . In the competitive frame-
work of this chapter, the choice is immaterial. The analysis of income taxation
in Chapter 6 will present an analysis of nonlinear taxation. A social welfare
function is then maximised by choice of the tax rates and the …rst-order condi-
tions for this maximisation are manipulated to provide a qualitative description
of the optimal tax system. The qualitative description is then interpreted in
terms of e¢ciency criteria and the concern for equity embodied in the social
welfare function. Explicit formulae for taxes are rarely calculated and, indeed,
4.3. THE RAMSEY RULE 101

can only be calculated for a number of uninteresting special cases. In response


to this, numerical studies have been employed to provide concrete results.
There are two important points that need to be made here. Firstly, because
of the normalisation rules employed, the actual values of tax rates can be argued
to have little meaning. Instead, it is the real e¤ect of the tax system upon
the equilibrium quantities of each good that is relevant. This point is argued
forcefully in Mirrlees (1976) where the index of discouragement is introduced to
measure the e¤ect of taxes. The standard procedure of deriving the tax rates will
be followed in this chapter but the Mirrlees interpretation, which is introduced
formally below, should always be borne in mind. Secondly, the discussion of net
trades in 2.13 showed how a household’s budget constraint could be nonlinear
in the presence of commodity taxation. To avoid this, the economies of this
chapter assume that households trade only with …rms.

4.3 The Ramsey rule


The Ramsey rule is one of the oldest results in the theory of optimal taxation
and is probably the oldest formally stated result. It is derived from an analysis of
the simplest form of general equilibrium economy, that with a single household.
The single household basis implies that there can be no equity considerations in
the setting of tax rates so that the resulting tax rule describes an e¢cient tax
system. As the Ramsey rule forms the basis for later results, its derivation is
described in some detail.

4.3.1 The economy


The Ramsey rule is derived within the context of a competitive economy in
which there are available n consumption goods and a single form of labour.
Labour is the only input into production. In addition, each industry is assumed
to produce a single output using a constant returns to scale technology. There is
a single household or, equivalently, a population of identical households, whose
preferences can be represented by an indirect utility function.
The assumptions on production imply that for each good i there is coe¢cient
ci that describes the labour input necessary to produce one unit of that good.
With a wage rate w, the competitive assumption ensures that the pre-tax price
of good i is determined by

p i = ciw; i = 1; :::; n: (4.1)

The normalisation rule that is adopted is to choose labour as the numeraire


and to …x the wage rate at the constant value w. In conjunction with the
production assumptions and condition (4.1), this normalisation rule provides a
set of e¤ectively …xed pre-tax, or producer, prices for the consumption goods.
Labour is also untaxed; that this does not involve a further restriction on this
system will be demonstrated in Section 6.
102 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

Employing the competitive assumption again, post-tax or consumer prices


are equal to the pre-tax prices plus the taxes. For good i the consumer price qi
is
qi = p i + ti ; i = 1; :::; n: (4.2)
Writing xi for the consumption level of good i, the tax rates on the n consump-
tion goods must be chosen to raise the required revenue. Denoting the revenue
requirement by R, the revenue constraint can be written
n
X
R= ti xi : (4.3)
i=1

To ensure that there is an economy-wide balance in supplies and demands,


the formal interpretation of this constraint is that the revenue raised by the
government is used to purchase a quantity of labour with value R. This labour
is used by the state for some unde…ned purpose and does not produce any good
that is traded in the economy. One example that satis…es this assumption would
be the use of labour for defence purposes. The use of a revenue constraint, rather
than a production constraint, has been discussed in 2.7 and will be discussed
further below.
The preferences of the single household are represented by the indirect utility
function
U = V (q1 ; :::; qn ; w; I) : (4.4)
The form of (4.4) implies that the household consumes the goods produced and
supplies the labour used in production and by the state. The assumption of
constant returns to scale and competitive behaviour imply that the …rms earn
zero pro…ts. The household therefore receives no pro…t income and lump-sum
income, I, is zero.

4.3.2 Derivation
Employing the economy described above, the optimal tax problem can be sum-
marised by the maximisation
n
X
max V (q1 ; :::; qn ; w; I) subject to R = ti xi : (4.5)
ft1;:::; tng
i=1

The Lagrangean corresponding to (4.5) is given by


" n #
X
L = V (q1 ; :::; qn ; w; I) + ¸ ti xi ¡ R : (4.6)
i=1

From (4.6), the …rst-order necessary condition for the choice of tax rate on good
k is " #
X n
@L @V @xi
´ + ¸ xk + ti = 0; (4.7)
@tk @qk i=1
@qk
4.3. THE RAMSEY RULE 103

where the identities


@V @V @x i @x i
´ ; ´ ; (4.8)
@qk @tk @qk @tk
have been used. Equation (4.7) can be rearranged to give
" #
n
X
@V @xi
= ¡¸ x k + ti ; (4.9)
@qk @qk
i=1

and a similar condition must hold for all n of the goods. The interpretation
of (4.9) is that for all goods the utility cost of raising the tax rate on good k
should stand in the same proportion to the marginal revenue raised by the tax
rise. Expressed alternatively, additional tax revenue per unit of utility foregone
should be the same regardless of which tax rate is changed to generate that
extra revenue.
From Roy’s identity it follows that

@V @V
=¡ x k = ¡®xk ; (4.10)
@qk @I

where I is the household’s lump-sum income and ® is their marginal utility


of income. Lump-sum income, I, should be clearly distinguished from total
income, M , used previously since total income includes both lump-sum income,
income from the sale of endowment and labour income. Substituting (4.10) into
(4.9)
" n
#
X @x i
®x k = ¸ xk + ti : (4.11)
i=1
@qk

After rearrangement (4.11) becomes


n
X ¸
@xi ¸¡®
ti =¡ xk : (4.12)
i=1
@qk ¸

The next step in the derivation is to employ the Slutsky equation to note that

@x i @xi
= S ik ¡ x k : (4.13)
@qk @I

Substituting from (4.13) into (4.12) gives


n
X ¸ ¸
@x i ¸¡®
ti Sik ¡ xk =¡ xk: (4.14)
@I ¸
i=1

or
n
X ¸ Xn
¸¡® @xi
ti Sik = ¡ xk + tix k : (4.15)
i=1
¸ i= 1
@I
104 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

The right-hand side of (4.15) is now simpli…ed by extracting the common factor
x k which yields " #
Xn n
® X @xi
tiSik = ¡ 1 ¡ ¡ ti xk: (4.16)
¸ @I
i= 1 i= 1

The symmetry of the Slutsky substitution matrix implies that S ki = Sik . This
symmetry can be used to rearrange (4.16) to give the expression

n
" n
#
X ® X @x i
tiSki = ¡µx k ; µ = 1 ¡ ¡ ti : (4.17)
i=1
¸ i=1 @I

Equation (4.17) is the Ramsey rule describing a system of optimal commodity


taxes and an equation of this form must hold for all goods, k = 1; :::; n. It
is important to note that the value of q is independent of the particular good
chosen.
Finally, multiplying both sides of the Ramsey rule by tk and summing over
k gives
Xn X n
titk Ski = ¡µR: (4.18)
k=1 i= 1

As the Slutsky matrix is negative semi-de…nite, the left-hand side of (4.18) is


negative so that µ has the same sign as government revenue. Given the sign of
µ , it is now possible to provide a descriptive interpretation of the Ramsey rule.

4.3.3 Interpretation
To provide an interpretation of the Ramsey rule the focus upon the typical good
k is maintained. First note that, by de…nition of the substitution terms,

@Âk
Ski = ; (4.19)
@qi

where Âk is the Hicksian or compensated demand for good k. Consequently,


starting from a position with no taxes, and noting that is then the change in
the tax rate on good i,

ti Ski = ti k ; (4.20)
@qi
is a …rst-order approximation of the change in compensated demand for good k
due to the introduction of the tax ti , but with the property that the derivative
is evaluated at the …nal set of prices and at post-tax utility level. If the taxes
are small, this should be a good approximation. Extending this argument to
the entire set of taxes, it follows that
n
X
ti Ski; (4.21)
i=1
4.3. THE RAMSEY RULE 105

Figure 4.1: Interpretation of the Ramsey Rule

is an approximation to the total change in compensated demand for good k due


to the introduction of the tax system from an initial no-tax position.
In considering the value of this interpretation, note that because both utility
and prices change when the tax system is introduced, the actual change in
demand is given by ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
 k p; U 0 ¡ Âk p; U 1 ; (4.22)
where U 0 is the initial utility level prior to the introduction of commodity taxes
and U 1 the …nal level after taxation. The structure of the approximation is
illustrated in Figure 4.1.

Putting these points together and recalling that if R is positive then so is µ,


the Ramsey rule when written in the form
Pn
i=1 t i Ski
= ¡µ; k = 1; :::; n; (4.23)
xk

can be interpreted as saying that the optimal tax system should be such that the
compensated demand for each good is reduced in the same proportion relative
to the pre-tax position. This is the standard interpretation of the Ramsey rule.
The importance of this observation is reinforced when it is set against the
alternative, but completely unfounded, view that the optimal tax system should
raise the prices of all goods by the same proportion in order to minimise the
distortion caused by the tax system. What the Ramsey rule is approximately
saying is that it is the distortion in terms of quantities that should be minimised.
106 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

Since it is the level of consumption that actually determines welfare, it is not


surprising that what happens to prices is unimportant; they only matter so far
as they determine demands. In addition, the importance of working in terms of
quantities rather than prices is highlighted when it is recalled that prices can
only be determined up to a normalising factor. This point is discussed further
in Section 6.
This emphasis upon quantities suggests de…ning
Pn
ti Ski
dk = i=1 ; (4.24)
xk

where dk , the proportional reduction in demand, is Mirrlees’ (1976) index of


discouragement. The Ramsey rule states that the tax system is optimal when
the index of discouragement is equal for all goods.

4.3.4 Implications
The Ramsey rule only provides an implicit expression for the optimal tax rates
and precise statements cannot be made without further restrictions. However,
some general comments can be made. Accepting the approximation interpreta-
tion, this suggests that since the proportional reduction in compensated demand
must be the same for all goods it can be expected that goods whose demand
is unresponsive to price changes will bear higher taxes. Although broadly cor-
rect, this statement can only be truly justi…ed when all cross-price e¤ects are
accounted for. One simple case that overcomes this di¢culty is that in which
there are no cross-price e¤ects between the taxed goods; this limiting case will
be considered in the next section.
Returning to the general case, goods that are unresponsive to price changes
are typically necessities such as food and housing. Consequently, the implemen-
tation of a tax system based on the Ramsey rule would lead to taxes that would
bear most heavily on necessities, with the lowest tax rates on luxuries. This in-
terpretation has been demonstrated more formally by Deaton (1981) under the
assumption of weak separability of preferences. Put into practice, this struc-
ture of taxation would involve low income households paying disproportionately
larger fractions of their incomes in taxes. The inequitable nature of this outcome
is simply a re‡ection of the single household assumption: the objective function
of the maximisation does not care about equity and the solution re‡ects only
e¢ciency criteria.
The equilibrium determined by the set of optimal taxes is second-best com-
pared to the outcome that would arise if the tax revenue had been collected
via a lump-sum tax. This is because the commodity taxes lead to substitu-
tion e¤ects which distort the household’s optimal choices and lead to e¢ciency
losses. Although unavoidable when commodity taxes are employed, these losses
are minimised by the optimal set of taxes that satisfy the Ramsey rule.
Since the single-household framework is untenable as a description of reality
and leads to an outcome that would be unacceptable on the most minimal of
4.3. THE RAMSEY RULE 107

equity criteria, the value of the Ramsey rule is therefore primarily in providing
a framework and a method of analysis that can easily be generalised to more
relevant settings. Contrasting the Ramsey rule tax system with later results will
also highlight the consequences of the introduction of equity considerations.

4.3.5 Inverse elasticities rule


The inverse elasticities rule, discussed in detail in Baumol and Bradford (1970),
is derived by placing further restrictions on the economy used to derive the
Ramsey rule. To be precise, it is assumed that there are no cross-price e¤ects
between the taxed goods so that the demand for each good is dependent only
upon its own price and the wage rate. Invoking this assumption essentially turns
the general equilibrium model into one of partial equilibrium as it removes all
the interactions in demand and, as shown by Atkinson and Stiglitz (1980), the
inverse elasticities rule can be derived from minimising the excess burden of
taxation in a partial equilibrium framework. The independence of demands is
clearly a strong assumption and it is therefore not surprising that a clear result
can be derived.
To derive the inverse elasticity rule, equation (4.11) is taken as the starting
point. Hence " #
Xn
@x i
®x k = ¸ xk + ti : (4.25)
@qk
i=1

The assumption of independent demands implies that


@x i
= 0 for i 6= k: (4.26)
@qk

Employing (4.26), equation (4.25) reduces to


¸
@xk
®xk = ¸ x k + tk : (4.27)
@qk

Rearranging (4.27) and dividing by qk , where by assumption qk = p k + tk , gives


¸ ¸
tk ® ¡ ¸ xk @qk
= : (4.28)
p k + tk ¸ qk @x k

As
x k @qk 1
= d; (4.29)
qk @x k "k
where "dk is the price elasticity of demand for good k, (4.28) can be written
¸
tk ®¡¸ 1
= : (4.30)
pk + tk ¸ "dk

Equation (4.30) is the inverse elasticities rule. From inspection, it can be seen
that this states that the proportional rates of tax should be inversely related to
108 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

the price elasticity of demand of the go od on which they are levied. Recalling
the discussion in 3.4, this statement can be viewed as an extreme version of
the general interpretation of the Ramsey rule. Its implication is clearly that
necessities, which by de…nition have low elasticities of demand, should be highly
taxed. In this case it is a clearly de…ned result and it is not necessary to be
concerned with approximations. However the restrictiveness of the assumptions
invoked to arrive at (4.30) should not be understated.

4.4 Extension to many-households


The objective of this section is to extend the single-household economy of the
Ramsey rule to incorporate further, non-identical, households. This extension
naturally introduces equity considerations into the determination of the optimal
tax rates. The principal paper in this area is Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) in
which was presented the …rst integrated analysis of this issue. Other important
references are Diamond (1975) and Mirrlees (1975).
The variant of the Diamond-Mirrlees economy studied in this section is a
restriction of the general case and simply involves extending that used to de-
rive the Ramsey rule by adding further households. The restrictions on the
production technology are retained, so that labour remains the only input into
production and technology is constant returns to scale. The original Diamond-
Mirrlees analysis, which permits greater generality of the production technology,
will be described in Section 6. It is worth noting that the restrictions do not
signi…cantly a¤ect the form of the optimal tax structure.

4.4.1 The optimal tax rule


The economy is assumed to consist of H households. Each household h is
described by an indirect utility function
¡ ¢
U h = V h q1 ; :::; qn ; w; I h : (4.31)

These functions vary amongst the households. If they did not, the economy
would reduce to that of a single household since lump-sum incomes are all zero
under the assumption of constant returns to scale. Labour remains the untaxed
numeraire with wage rate w and all households supply only the single form of
labour service.
Writing x h1 ; :::; xhn for the consumption demands from h, the revenue con-
straint is given by
Xn XH
R= tix hi : (4.32)
i=1 h =1

Social welfare is determined by a Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function


which is de…ned on the vector of indirect utilities
¡ ¢
W = W V 1 (¢) ; :::; V H (¢) : (4.33)
4.4. EXTENSION TO MANY-HOUSEHOLDS 109

Combining (4.32) and (4.33), the optimal set of commodity taxes solve the
maximisation problem

¡ ¢ n X
X H
max W V 1 (¢) ; :::; V H (¢) subject to R = tix hi: (4.34)
ft1;:::; tng
i=1 h=1

Two alternative presentations of the solution to (4.34) are now given. The …rst
solution follows closely that of Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) and emphasises
e¢ciency and equity aspects. The second solution parallels the Ramsey rule
and has formed the basis for numerical implementation.
From the Lagrangean for the maximisation, the …rst-order condition for the
choice of the tax rate on good k, is
H
" H n XH
#
X @W @V h X X @x hi
h
+¸ xk + ti = 0: (4.35)
@V h @qk i=1
@qk
h=1 h=1 h=1

Using Roy’s identity the …rst term of (4.35) can be written


H
X H
X
@W @V h @W h h
= ¡ ® xk : (4.36)
@V h @qk @V h
h=1 h= 1

Now de…ne
@W h
¯h = ® : (4.37)
@V h
¯ h is formed as the composition of the e¤ect of an increase in household h ’s
utility on social welfare and the marginal utility of income for h. It can be
interpreted as the increase in social welfare resulting from a marginal increase
in the income of household h. Following Diamond and Mirrlees (1971), ¯ h is
termed the social marginal utility of income for household h.
Employing the de…nition of ¯ h , (4.35) becomes
H
" H n X H
#
X X X @x hi
h h h
¯ xk = ¸ xk + ti : (4.38)
h=1 h=1 i=1 h=1
@qk

Substituting from the Slutsky equation

@x hi h @xh
= Sik ¡ xhk ih ; (4.39)
@qk @I
into (4.38) and rearranging gives the tax rule
PH hP i
Pn PH PH n @xh
x hk
i= 1 ti @I h
h h h i
i=1 h= 1 t i Ski 1 h =1 ¯ x k h=1
PH = PH ¡1+ PH : (4.40)
h ¸ h
h=1 x k h=1 x k h=1 x hk

In (4.40), the left-hand side has an equivalent interpretation to that of the


Ramsey rule: it is approximately the proportional change in aggregate compen-
sated demand for good k and is the generalisation of the discouragement index
110 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

of (4.24). When a positive amount of revenue is to be raised, it is natural to


assume that the level of demand will be reduced by the tax system, so that the
left-hand side of (4.40) will be negative. As with the approximation involved
with the interpretation of the Ramsey rule, this has two sources of error. Firstly,
real incomes change in moving to the system of optimal taxes and, secondly, the
gradient of the demand functions are unlikely to be constant.
The right-hand terms indicate that the reduction in demand should be
smaller when: (i) demand for good k is concentrated amongst individuals with
high values of ¯ h , these are the consumers regarded as socially important and
(ii) demand is concentrated amongst those whose tax payments change consid-
erably as income changes. The …rst of these points can be seen as re‡ecting
equity criteria. An individual will have a high value of ¯ h when their personal
marginal utility of income, ® h, is large and when their social welfare weight
@W
@V h
is also large. If the social welfare function is concave, both of these will
be satis…ed by low utility households with low incomes. Hence the implication
is that concern for such households will reduce the rates of tax levied on the
goods they consume. The remaining term is related to the e¢ciency aspects
of the tax system. If taxation were to be concentrated on goods consumed by
those whose tax payments fell rapidly with reductions in income, then increased
taxation, and consequently greater distortion, would be required to meet the
revenue target.
The optimal tax rule (4.40) can be expressed in an alternative form that is
closer to that of the standard Ramsey rule. To do this, (4.40) is rearranged to
give
n X H
" PH n
" H ##
X ¯ h h
x X X @xh
i h
ti Shik = ¡ Hx k ¡ h=1 k
¡ ti x ; (4.41)
¸ @I h k
i=1 h =1 i=1 h=1

where PH
h=1 x hk
xk = ; (4.42)
H
is the mean level of consumption of good k across the households.
Now de…ne
n
¯ h X @xhi
bh = + ti h ; (4.43)
¸ i=1
@I

where b h is Diamond’s (1975) net social marginal utility of income measured in


terms of government revenue. It is net in the sense that it measures both the
gain in social welfare ¯ h due to an increase in income to h and the increase in
tax payments of h due to this increase in income. From reviewing its de…nition,
it can be seen that b h involves both equity and e¢ciency e¤ects. Using de…nition
(4.43), equation (4.41) can be rearranged to give
Pn PH "H
#
h X bh x hk
i=1 h =1 t i Sik
PH =¡ 1¡ : (4.44)
x hk H xk
h=1 h=1
4.4. EXTENSION TO MANY-HOUSEHOLDS 111

Tax rule (4.44) shows that the reduction in aggregate compensated demand
for the kth commodity due to the introduction of the tax system should be
inversely related to the correlation between b h and x hk . In other words, to the
extent that the values of b h re‡ect equity concerns, equity implies that goods
consumed by those with high b h s should be less discouraged or, e¤ectively, they
should have lower taxes. In general, the reduction in demand is smaller: (i) the
more the good is consumed by individuals with a high bh ; (ii) the more the good
is consumed by individuals with a high marginal propensity to consume taxed
goods.
The two forms of the optimal commodity tax rule for a many-household
economy in (4.40) and (4.44) illustrate aspects of the e¢ciency/equity trade-
o¤ by the manner in which the reduction in demand for a good is related to
the social importance of the major consumers of that good and their general
contribution to the tax revenue. The rules also demonstrate that the ma jor
feature of the Ramsey rule, the focus upon changes in quantities, is maintained
in the general setting.
As with the Ramsey rule, the results do not give an explicit statement of
the structure of taxes but only provide a characterisation of the consequences of
the optimal system. This lack of clear results provides some of the motivation
for the numerical studies reviewed in Section 5. That section will also consider
the information required to implement the optimal tax rule.

4.4.2 Reduction to the Ramsey rule


The tax rule given in the form of (4.44) is useful for discovering when the
many-household rule actually collapses to the standard Ramsey rule. In such
circumstances the equity criteria are eliminated. The two examples below il-
lustrate that this can occur either because all households are given the same
social valuation or because the tax system is unable to discriminate between
households. The latter reason motivates an alternative interpretation of the tax
problem as one of inferring the status of the households from the signals they
provide in their choice of demands.
Example 1 : b h = b all h = 1; :::; H.
In this case the bracketed term in (4.44) becomes
" H
# " H
#
X bh x hk b X x hk
1¡ = 1¡ = [1 ¡ b] : (4.45)
H xk xk H
h=1 h=1

As (4.45) is independent of k, it implies that the proportional reduction in


demand will be the same for all goods. Recalling the interpretation of b h , this
will occur if all households are valued equally and have the same propensity
to pay tax or, most unlikely, the valuation and propensity sum to the same
for all households. In either case, the equity considerations are e¤ectively lost
and the solution returns to that describing an e¢cient tax system. It must be
emphasised that the value of b h is endogenous to the system.
xh
Example 2: k
xk is the same for all k.
112 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

This condition implies that no good is consumed disproportionately by rich


and poor, a situation that will arise whenever households have identical Engel
curves and these are lines through the origin. When this occurs there is no
method of subsidising high b h people that doesn’t also subsidise low bh since all
households have the same expenditure patterns and pay the same proportion of
income in tax. It should be noted that identical linear Engel curves aggregat-
perfectly hence the economy acts as if it were a single household. As above, it
h
should be stressed that the value of xxkk is determined endogenously.
This result also highlights that the commodity tax problem can be viewed
as one of signal extraction. From the purchases of each household the state is
attempting to infer the household’s preferences and endowment in order that it
be taxed according to its circumstances. However, when the purchases carry no
information, as in the case above, no signal can be extracted and redistribution
fails. Without any redistributive aspect, the taxes must be chosen to meet
e¢ciency criteria only.
An example of an economy that has these properties is one in which all
households have identical Cobb-Douglas preferences and di¤er only in lump-
sum incomes. It is not speci…ed how these lump-sum incomes arise but they
could be due to the operation of a non-uniform (but non-optimal) lump-sum
subsidy system by the government. Assuming each household has the utility
£ ¤Á P
function U h = ¦ni= 1 x hi i ¡ `, where ` is labour supply and ni=1 Ái = 1, the
demand for good k from household h is
£ ¤
h
Ák I h + w
xk = ; (4.46)
qk

and
H £ ¤ H £ ¤
1 X Ák I h + w Ák X I h + w Á £ ¤
xk = = = k I+w : (4.47)
H qk qk H qk
h= 1 h =1

Thus calculating the ratio of the demand of household h to the mean level of
demand provides the expression
£ h ¤
x hk I +w
= £ ¤ ; all k = 1; :::; n; (4.48)
xk I +w

which clearly satis…es (ii).

4.4.3 A cautionary note


To this point the analysis has proceeded on the implicit assumption that the
…rst-order conditions for the maximisations in (4.5) and (4.34) accurately char-
acterise the solution. However this need not always be the case. It is a standard
result that an indirect utility function representing convex preferences will be
quasi-convex in prices. That is, the set of prices that lead to less than a speci…ed
4.5. NUMERICAL RESULTS 113

level of utility is a convex set. In addition, with linearity in labour supply the
indirect utility function may even be strictly convex, see Varian (1984). This
poses di¢culties for many maximisations in public economics.
For the Ramsey rule, the objective function was the household’s indirect
utility function and hence was quasi-convex. In the many-household economy,
the objective was some concave function of the vector of indirect utility func-
tions. Despite the concavity of social welfare in utility it need not be concave in
the choice variables, the tax rates, due again to the quasi-convexity of indirect
utilities. In addition, the set of tax rates that generate at least the required
revenue may not be a convex set.
For these reasons the standard su¢ciency conditions of quasi-concave pro-
gramming cannot be appealed too so there is no guarantee that the …rst-order
conditions actually describe a maximum. This problem occurs throughout pub-
lic economics where many maximisations are ill-conditioned and has been ex-
plored extensively by Mirrlees (1986). This problem is often put to one side
and it is simply assumed that the …rst-order conditions will correctly describe
the optima. Although unsatisfactory, there is typically little alternative to this.
Some comfort can be taken in the present circumstances by appealing to the
work of Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) who prove that their …rst-order conditions
do represent the solution to the optimal commodity tax problem.

4.5 Numerical results


Numerical analysis of optimal tax rates has become popular for two reasons.
Firstly, the tax rules derived above suggest general observations about the struc-
ture of optimal taxes but they do not have precise implications. Numerical
analysis can be seen as providing a check on the interpretations and a means of
investigating them further. Secondly, the motive for the analysis is to provide
practical policy recommendations. To do this, the tax rules must be capable of
being applied to data and the values of the resulting optimal taxes calculated.
Numerical studies in this context represent the development of a technology for
carrying out this program of work.

4.5.1 Applications
A series of papers by Ray (1986a), Murty and Ray (1987) and Srinivasan (1989)
have presented progressively more re…ned estimates of optimal commodity taxes
for the many-household economy based on data from the Indian National Sample
Survey. To calculate the optimal tax rates, the …rst step is to specify the social
welfare function. The procedure used for this is based on the work of Atkinson
(1970), which was discussed in Chapter 3, and involves adopting an additive
social welfare function and de…ning a social utility of income function for each
household. Together these give the social evaluation of income to the household.
Denote the aggregate expenditure of household h, which is assumed to be
114 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

equal to income, by ¹h and let the social utility of income to h be given by


( 1¡º
)
K [ ¹h ]
Uh = 1¡º
; º 6= 1; (4.49)
K log ¹h ; º = 1;

@W
for some positive K. With the additive social welfare function @V h
= 1 so the
marginal social utility of income to h, ¯ h , is given by

@U h £ ¤ ¡º
¯h = h
= K ¹h : (4.50)

The households are then ranked according to their expenditures, with the low-
est expenditure household …rst in the ranking. Setting ¯ 1 = 1 for the lowest
expenditure household in the data set, it follows that
¸º
h ¹1
¯ = : (4.51)
¹h

Equation (4.51) implies that as ¹h increases relative to ¹1 , ¯ h declines monoton-


ically at rate º . Since a higher value of º reduces ¯ h relative to ¯ 1 for all h > 1, º
can be seen as the concern for equity as expressed in the social welfare function,
with high values representing the greatest concern for equity.
The advantage of this method of de…ning the marginal social utilities is that
the ¯ h s are …xed exogenously and can be determined by the observed expendi-
ture levels in the data set. In addition, the concern for equity is clearly expressed
and can be varied parametrically. However, it is important to note that (4.50)
is imposing a very particular structure on the product of social preferences and
individuals’ utilities of income, a point that can be appreciated by reconsidering
the de…nition in (4.37). Furthermore, it is denying the endogeneity of income
and hence expenditure.
Given the speci…ed structure of the ¯ h s, the optimal tax rates are determined
from the equations
H
" H n X H
#
X h h
X X @xhi
h
¯ xk = ¸ xk + ti ; k = 1; :::; n; (4.52)
@qk
h= 1 h=1 i= 1 h=1

and
n X
X H
R= tix hi ; (4.53)
i=1 h =1

which were derived above as (4.38) and (4.32) respectively. To apply these
equations to data, it is necessary to have knowledge of individual demands and
the demand derivatives. To obtain these, a demand system is speci…ed and then
estimated for the data set. The demand functions estimated are then substituted
together with the de…nition of ¯ h into (4.52) and (4.53). The resulting n + 1
equations are then solved for the n tax rates and the Lagrange multiplier.
4.5. NUMERICAL RESULTS 115

The …rst paper to adopt this approach was Ray (1986a). In that paper the
n + 1 equations in (4.52) and (4.53) were taken as simultaneous equations with
the demand levels and demand derivatives held constant at their initial levels.
This constancy implies that the tax rates given by solving the equations are not
fully optimal but only optimal conditional upon the constant demands. A more
advanced approach is given in Murty and Ray (1987) which incorporates the
e¤ects of the taxes on demand and uses an iterative procedure to solve for the
optimum. The demand system used in Murty and Ray (1987) is based on the
indirect utility function
Pn ®1 ®2
¹®
h ¡ i=1 ° i pi wh
V h (¢) = ®¯ ®¯
: (4.54)
¦nk=1 pk k w h 0

The form of this function permits the evaluation of various separability assump-
tions via the values of the estimated parameters. There is separability between
goods and leisure in utility if ® 2 and ¯ are both zero and non-separability be-
tween di¤erent goods when ® 1 di¤ers from unity. The tax rates were calculated
on the basis of the estimated values of the parameters °i ; ¯ i; ® 1 given in Ray
(1986a), ¯ 0 was set to zero and the value of ® 2 was assumed.
De…ning µ to be the wage as a proportion of expenditure, the value of which
is imposed upon the analysis, a sample of the results of Murty and Ray (1987)
are given in Table 4.1 for À = 2 and ® 2 = 0:025:

Item µ = 0:05 µ = 0:1


Cereals -0.015 -0.089
Milk and milk products -0.042 -0.011
Edible oils 0.359 0.342
Meat, …sh and eggs 0.071 0.083
Sugar and tea 0.013 0.003
Other food 0.226 0.231
Clothing 0.038 0.014
Fuel and light 0.038 0.014
Other non-food 0.083 0.126
Table 4.1: Optimal tax rates

Table 4.1 illustrates that redistribution takes place via these optimal taxes
since cereals and milk products, both basic foodstu¤s, are subsidised. Such
redistribution is a re‡ection of the concern for equity embodied in a value of
º of 2. In addition, the results are not too sensitive to the choice of µ which
could not be estimated from the data set. However, the analysis is limited by
the degree of aggregation that leads to the excessively general other non-food
category.
Ray (1986b) also used this framework to analyse the redistributive impact
of Indian commodity taxes. The method employed was to calculate the total
payment of commodity tax, T h , by household h relative to the expenditure of
116 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

that household. The net gain from the tax system for h can then be de…ned by

Th
¡ : (4.55)
¹h
h
The household is gaining from the tax system if ¡ T¹ h is positive since this
implies a net subsidy is being received. Contrasting the gains of household h
from the existing tax system with those of the optimal system then provides
an indication of both the success of the existing system and the potential gains
from the optimal system. For demand estimates based on a linear expenditure
system, the calculations for the existing Indian tax system give the gains noted
in Table 4.2.

Rrual Urban
h h
Expenditure level ¡ T¹ h ¡ T¹h
Rs. 20 0.105 0.220
Rs. 50 0.004 0.037
Table 4.2: Redistribution of Indian commodity taxes

The expenditure levels of Rs. 20 and Rs. 50 place households with these
incomes in the lower 30% of the distribution. In this case there is a net gain to
households at both income levels from the tax system with the lower expenditure
householder making a proportionately greater gain.
From Ray (1986a) the redistributive impact of the optimal tax system for a
household with expenditure level , where is mean expenditure, is given in Table
4.3.

º = 0:1 º = 1:5 º = 5
¡ T¹ 0.07 0.343 0.447
Table 4.3: Optimal redistribution

For º = 1:5 or more, it can be seen that the potential gains from the tax
system, relative to the outcome that would occur in the absence of taxation, are
quite substantial. Therefore it can be seen that with su¢cient weight given to
equity considerations the optimal set of commodity taxes can e¤ect signi…cant
redistribution and that the existing Indian tax system does not attain these
gains.

4.5.2 Further results


Atkinson and Stiglitz (1972) calculated the optimal tax rates satisfying the
Ramsey rule for a single household economy. Two demand systems were con-
sidered: the direct addilog with the parameters and data taken from Houthakker
(1960); and the linear expenditure system calculated by Stone (1954). In both
cases, additive separability in labour supply was assumed. The results sup-
port the interpretation of the Ramsey rule in 3.3: food and rent (necessities)
bear the highest tax rates and durable goods (luxuries) the lowest and the
4.6. GENERALISING THE PRODUCTION TECHNOLOGY 117

optimal tax system is non-uniform. Deaton (1977) presents numerical results


that rely on an aggregation argument and therefore fall somewhere between the
single-household and a true many-household economy. The ma jor …nding of the
analysis is that the tax rates move further from uniformity as the concern for
equity increases.
A further calculation of optimal commodity taxes can be found in Ebrahimi
and Heady (1988) which, following Deaton and Stern (1986), augments the
standard analysis by including publicly observable demographic characteristics.
The observability of the demographic variable, which is the number of children
in the household, allows lump-sum tax payments to be based upon them and
the tax system consists of commodity taxes, a lump-sum payment independent
of demograhics and a child bene…t, with the child bene…t potentially variable
according to childrens’ age. The data for the calculation are taken from the
1981 U.K. Family Expenditure Survey and relate to 2126 households with two-
adults but various numbers of children. The computational procedure is based
on an algorithm for …nding the …xed point of a mapping that was described in
Heady and Mitra (1980). The results illustrate again that optimal taxes will
be non-uniform. This remains true even with the considerable ‡exibility in the
setting of lump-sum transfers permitted by the use of the lump-sum transfer
and two distinct child bene…ts. The tax rates, the lump-sum transfer and the
bene…ts are all large in value relative to the taxes and transfers seen in practice.
An alternative approach to computation is given in Harris and McKinnon
(1979) who develop an algorithm for solving the necessary conditions for opti-
mal taxes. The algorithm …nds the …xed point of a mapping and is applicable
even when supply is a set-valued function of prices rather than a point-valued
function. Although Harris and McKinnon present the results of some simula-
tion experiments, their algorithm does not yet appear to have been applied to
empirical data.
The results above indicate conclusively that the optimal tax rules can be
operationalised, albeit in somewhat restricted settings. The numerical analyses
all have small commodity groupings and none truly solves the problem in its
full generality since producer prices are generally taken as …xed. However the
results do show that progress is being made and illustrate a fruitful direction
for future research.

4.6 Generalising the production technology


The economies analysed in Sections 3 and 4 assumed that labour was the only
input into production and that there were constant returns to scale. These
assumptions were adopted to provide the simplest basis on which to develop the
results. Both assumptions can be relaxed and this section brie‡y considers the
consequences of so doing.
Retaining the assumption of constant returns but allowing all goods to be
potential inputs into production alters the method of analysis but does not a¤ect
the structure of the results derived. The argument in this case, developed in
118 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

Diamond and Mirrlees (1971), relies on the disconnection between households


and …rms. As there are constant returns to scale, all …rms earn zero pro…ts and
households’ incomes are derived solely from the sale of goods. All these sales
take place at consumer prices, q. Hence households’ actions are determined only
by consumer prices. In contrast, …rms transact at producer prices, p, and are
not in‡uenced in their decisions by the consumer price level. E¤ectively, the
two sets of prices can be chosen separately and the di¤erence between the two
determines the tax rates.
Expressed formally, the government can face households with a price vector
(q1 ; :::; qn ) which then entirely determines their actions. Aggregating the indi-
vidual …rms’ production sets determines the economy’s production possibility
set. The choice of a producer price vector (p 1 ; :::; pn ) then determines supply
as the pro…t maximising choice at these prices over all points in the aggregate
production possibility set. Since constant returns to scale are assumed, pro…t
maximisation determines a supply correspondence rather than a supply func-
tion. For the reasons noted in the discussion of the Second Theorem of Welfare
Economics, it is not necessary to worry about the maximisation of individual
…rms. Summarising this discussion, the behaviour of the agents in the economy
is described by
n
X n
X
h
¡ h¢ h
Households : max
h
U x subject to q i x i = qi! hi ; (4.56)
fx g
i=1 i=1

with optimal choices

xhi = x hi (qi) ; i = 1; :::; n; h = 1; :::; H; (4.57)

and
Production: max py subject to y 2 Y ; (4.58)
fyg

where Y is the aggregate pro duction possibility set, with supply correspondence

y (p) : (4.59)

Equations (4.63) and (4.65) capture the independence of household choices from
the producer price vector and of the production choice from consumer prices.
From the maximisations (4.62) and (4.64) it should be noted that both
demands and supplies are homogeneous of degree zero in the relevant price
vectors. This implies

Xi (q) = Xi (¸q) ; 8¸ > 0; i = 1; :::; n; (4.60)

and
y (p) = y (¸p) ; 8¸ > 0: (4.61)
.Given a set of producer and consumer prices, the tax rates are determined
implicitly by the identity
t = q ¡ p: (4.62)
4.6. GENERALISING THE PRODUCTION TECHNOLOGY 119

However, the homogeneity in (4.66) and (4.67) implies that an equivalent tax
system to that in (4.68) is given by

t0 = Áq ¡ ½p; (4.63)

for any Á; ½ > 0. The equivalence of t and t0 follows from noting that the prices
supporting both tax systems elicit the same production choice and the same level
of demand from consumers. In this sense, the values of the tax rates themselves
are of limited interest since these are only determined up to the choice of the
arbitrary constants Á; ½.
This degree of freedom in the choice of tax rates is the basis upon which
Mirrlees (1976) argues for considering the index of discouragement and its gen-
eralisations, which are de…ned in terms of quantities rather than prices, since
it is the e¤ect upon equilibrium quantities that is the real property of the tax
system. It should be recalled that it was reasoning in terms of quantities that
provided the basis for the interpretations of the tax rules given above. The
indeterminacy in the values of the tax rates is usually resolved by adopting the
standard normalisation rule of setting the tax on one of the goods to zero. This
is e¤ectively what was done with the wage rate above, which is why there was
no loss of generality in using that assumption. There has been much confusion
on this point, see particularly the remarks of Mirrlees (1976) which attempt to
provide clari…cation and the discussion in Section 7.
Returning now to the analysis of the more general economy, the optimal
tax system is found by choosing the consumer price vector q to maximise wel-
fare sub ject to there being some producer price vector p that will generate the
appropriate level of supply from …rms in order to match demand with supply,
with demand being the sum of household and government demand. As this pro-
cedure guarantees that all markets are in equilibrium, the government budget
constraint does not need explicit recognition; see 2.6. Writing the production
possibility set in implicit form as

F (X(q) + x G ) 0; (4.64)

where x G is the …xed vector of government demands, the Diamond and Mirrlees
formulation is summarised by the maximisation
¡ ¢
max W V 1 (¢) ; :::; V H (¢) subject to F (X(q) + x G ) 0: (4.65)
fqg

With pro…t maximising behaviour, producer prices can be determined by noting


that they will be proportional to the normal to the production possibility set
at the equilibrium point. Such a price vector will guarantee zero pro…t for the
…rms. Hence p is proportional to rF evaluated at X(q) + x G . Although this
problem appears distinct from that described in (4.34), it does have the same
solution which is given by (4.40) or (4.44).
If the assumption of constant returns to scale is relaxed and decreasing
returns are permitted, those …rms with decreasing returns will earn positive
pro…ts. If pro…ts are assumed to be taxed at a rate of 100% then all …rms’
120 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

pro…ts are returned to the government and the separation between households
and …rms remains. The optimal tax problem is then still described by (4.71),
with suitable assumptions on the production possibility set, and the Diamond-
Mirrlees results still apply. When pro…ts are not taxed at 100%, some pro…t
income will accrue to households through their shareholdings in …rms. Once
this occurs, the separation between households and …rms no longer applies.
To show the e¤ect of pro…ts, the simplest case is chosen and it is assumed
that pro…ts are entirely untaxed. Pro…ts will then be distributed to households
in accordance with the distribution of shareholdings and will modify the typical
household’s decision problem to
n
X n
X m
X
¡ ¢
max U h x h subject to qi x hi = qi ! hi + µ hj ¼ j : (4.66)
fxhg
i=1 i=1 j=1

Since the pro…t levels of the …rms are determined by producer prices, as shown
in (2.15), the solution of (4.72) is now dependent upon p so the household is
a¤ected by the level of producer prices. Household demands are therefore given
by

xhi = x hi (q; ¼) = x hi (q; p) ; i = 1; :::; n; h = 1; :::; H; (4.67)


since ¼ must depend on p and q. As shown by Munk (1978), this dependence
necessitates that a di¤erent solution procedure is employed.
To derive the single-household tax rule in this case, …rst let the aggregate
production constraint be written in the form

F (y) = y 1 ¡ f (y 2 ; :::; y n ) = 0: (4.68)

Pro…t maximisation subject to this constraint implies that


@f
pi = ¡p1 : (4.69)
@yi
Using (4.73), the demands from the single household can be written

x i = xi (q; ¼) ; (4.70)

where ¼ is the aggregate level of pro…t given by ¼ = py.


Now assume that the government demands a …xed vector x G of commodities.
Equilibrium occurs when demands equal supplies or

x + x G = y + !: (4.71)

From (4.77)
y = x + x G ¡ !: (4.72)
Now using (4.75), (4.76), (4.78) and the de…nition of aggregate pro…t gives the
equations
Xn
£ ¤
¼= p i x (q1 ; :::; qn ; ¼) x G ¡ ! ; (4.73)
i=1
4.7. UNTAXED GOODS 121
¡ ¢
@f x 2 (q; ¼) + xG G
2 ¡ ! 2 ; :::; x n (q; ¼) + x n ¡ !n
pi = ¡p1 ; i = 2; :::; n: (4.74)
@y i
Normalising p 1 at unity, the n equations in (4.79) and (4.80) will be su¢cient,
when the conditions of the implicit function theorem are satis…ed, to provides
solutions
p i = pi (q) ; i = 2; :::; n; ¼ = ¼ (q) ; (4.75)
for the producer prices and the pro…t level conditional upon the vector of con-
sumer prices. Any consumer price vector, q, that satis…es the market equilibrium
condition
x (q; ¼ (q)) + x G = y (p (q)) + !; (4.76)
where p (q) is the vector (p 1 ; p 2 (q); :::; pn (q)), is an admissible price vector. The
set of admissible equilibrium consumer price vectors is denoted Q.
With this formulation, the optimal tax problem involves choosing the vector
of consumer prices to solve the maximisation

max V (q; ¼ (q)) subject to [q ¡ p (q)] x (q; ¼ (q)) = p (q) xG and q 2 Q;


fqg
(4.77)
where the …rst constraint in (4.83) is the government budget constraint. Di¤er-
entiating and using Roy’s identity, the optimal tax rule is
n
X ¸ ¸
@x i @xi @¼ ¸¡® @¼
ti + = ¡xk + ; k = 1; :::; n: (4.78)
@qk @¼ @qk ¸ @qk
i= 1

Hence the reduction in demand is now related to the e¤ect of consumer prices
upon pro…ts. Further analysis of this result can be found in Munk (1978).

4.7 Untaxed goods


The role of normalisation procedures and of the untaxed good was discussed at
some length in the previous section. The importance of applying normalisations
correctly has been emphasised in the literature on optimal commodity taxation
by the number of cases in which they have been misunderstood. This section
notes the misunderstandings that have arisen and illustrate their origins.
It has been shown that in an economy with constant returns to scale, con-
sumer and producer prices can be normalised separately and that the standard
procedure is to make one good the numeraire and set its consumer and producer
prices equal. This normalisation also has the e¤ect of setting the tax on that
good to zero. The latter fact is clearly seen to be of no consequence whatsoever
since the zero tax is just a result of the normalisation rule. In particular, the
zero tax carries no implications about the nature of the good nor about the abil-
ity to tax that good. This follows since the good with zero tax can be chosen
arbitrarily from the set of available goods.
Unfortunately, this reasoning has not been as clearly appreciated in some
of the literature as it should have been. The reason for this has been the
122 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

convention, as adopted in sections 3 and 4 of this chapter, of taking labour, as the


untaxed commodity. Since labour is often viewed as the negative of leisure, it has
been inferred from this that, since leisure cannot be measured in the same way
that purchases of other commodities can, the zero tax on leisure is a restriction
on the permissible tax system brought about by an inability to tax leisure. In
addition, the further inference is usually made that the optimal tax system
aims to overcome the missing tax on leisure by taxing goods complementary to
leisure. Particular examples of this are found in Corlett and Hague (1953) “By
taxing those goods complementary with leisure, one is to some extent taxing
leisure itself“ (p.26) and Layard and Walters (1978) “The theory of second
best tells us that it we cannot tax leisure, we can do better than by taxing
all other goods equiproportionately.“ (p.184). Many other instances of similar
statements could easily be given. This, of course, is a false interpretation. When
real restrictions upon the permissible range of tax instruments are introduced
the results obtained are a¤ected. A number of such restrictions are considered
in Munk (1980) where it is shown that the resulting optimal tax structure is
sensitive to the precise restrictions imposed.
A further mistake that has arisen in this context can be found in Dixit (1970)
and Lerner (1970). In a single-household economy, any required revenue can be
raised most e¢ciently by a lump-sum tax on the household equal to the value of
the revenue. Noticing this, it has been suggested that a set of commodity taxes
which raise the price of all goods by the same proportion will have the same
e¤ect as the lump-sum tax and therefore that when all goods can be taxed, the
optimal system has the same proportional tax on all goods. This conclusion is
clearly in contrast to that of the Ramsey rule. The mistake in the reasoning
was pointed out by Sandmo (1974) who demonstrated that such a proportional
tax system would raise no revenue. This follows since households both demand
goods and supply labour. A proportional tax then taxes demands but subsidises
supplies and, since the value of household demand equals the value of supply,
the proportional tax is just o¤set by the proportional subsidy. E¤ectively, the
proportional tax on all commodities is just a rescaling of the consumer price
vector which does not a¤ect household choices.
Returning to untaxed goods, as the analysis that will now be given shows,
it is correct to state that if leisure is untaxed then goods complementary with
leisure should be taxed more highly but it is not correct to infer from this either
that not taxing leisure is a restriction on the system or that the taxes aim to
compensate for the missing tax. Taking the Ramsey rule as de…ned in (4.17) for
a two-good and labour economy gives the necessary conditions for an optimal
tax system of
t1 S11 + t2 S12 = ¡µx 1 ; (4.79)

t1 S21 + t2 S22 = ¡µx 2 : (4.80)


Solving these equations, the tax rates are implicitly characterised by
¸
µ
t1 = [S12 x 2 ¡ S22 x 1 ] ; (4.81)
S
4.7. UNTAXED GOODS 123
¸
µ
t2 = [S21 x 1 ¡ S11 x2 ] ; (4.82)
S
where S = S11 S22 ¡ S12 S21 can be assumed to be negative by the negative semi-
de…niteness of the Slutsky matrix. Now de…ne the elasticity of compensated
demand by
qj S ij
"cij = ; (4.83)
xi
and note that by dividing (4.87) by (4.88), multiplying by qq21 and normalising
both producer prices at unity (which can be done by selecting the units in which
the commodities are measured), provides the relation
t1
1+t1 "c12 ¡ "c22
t2 = : (4.84)
1+t2
"c21 ¡ "c11

Representing leisure by good 0, it follows from Euler’s theorem and the


homogeneity of degree 1 of the expenditure function in prices that
2
X
qj Sij = 0; (4.85)
j=0

and hence that after dividing by x i

"ci0 + "ci1 + "ci2 = 0: (4.86)

Therefore (4.90) can be written in the form


¸
t1 t2 ¡ [" c11 + "c22] ¡ " c10
= : (4.87)
1 + t1 1 + t2 ¡ [" c11 + "c22] ¡ " c20

Equation (4.93) states that if the two goods stand in the same relation
to labour, so that "c10 = " c20 , then they should be taxed at the same rate.
Otherwise the good with the lower value of "ci0 , and hence more complementary
with leisure, should be taxed at the higher rate. This analysis is the basis for
claims that the good complementary to the untaxed good should be taxed more.
However, it should be noted that this conclusion is simply an artefact of the
homogeneity of the expenditure function rather than any fundamental result
about the optimal taxes trying to compensate for the missing tax on leisure.
The discussion of Section 6 has already shown that the non-taxation of labour
is simply a harmless normalisation and that any good could have been chosen as
the untaxed commodity. In other words, good 0 could be chosen to be one of the
consumption goods and good 1 labour. In that case, the direct link with leisure
is then lost from (4.93). Additionally, equation (4.90) presents the tax rule in
terms of own-price and cross-price elasticities of the two taxed goods without
any explicit mention of the untaxed good and provides an equally acceptable
point from which to seek interpretations.
124 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

This section has noted misunderstandings that have arisen in connection


with the interpretation of the position of the untaxed good. Although the tax
rule can be written so as to depend on the complementary with the untaxed
good, there is nothing fundamental in this observation. In addition, arguments
that an optimal system would tax all goods at the same rate are unfounded
since such a system would raise no revenue.

4.8 Uniform taxes


The numerical results reported in Section 5 have demonstrated that in general
the structure of optimal commodity taxes will be far from uniform. However,
uniform taxes are not without their supporters, see for example Hatta (1986),
and it is natural to consider whether there are any circumstances in which the
optimal structure should be uniform.
Conditions guaranteeing uniformity have been derived in papers by Deaton
(1979, 1981) and Besley and Jewitt (1990). These papers have used a variety
of representations of preferences in alternative formulations of the optimal tax
problem. To present the central result in the manner closest to the analysis
above, this section will present the problem in terms of ad valorem taxation
with an indirect utility function capturing preferences.
With ad valorem taxation the consumer price of good i is given by and the
optimal commodity tax problem becomes
n
X
max V (q1 ; :::; qn ; w; I) subject to R = tip ix i: (4.88)
ft1;: ::;tn g
i= 1

For the choice of tax rate on good k the maximisation in (4.94) has the …rst-order
condition
" n
#
@V X @x i
p k + ¸ pk xk + ti pi p k = 0; k = 1; :::; n: (4.89)
@pk i=1
@qk

Eliminating the common factor pk from (4.95) and using the Slutsky equation,
the Ramsey rule in this case takes the form
n
X
tip iSik = ¡µx k ; k = 1; :::; n; (4.90)
i=1
Pn
with µ = 1 ¡ ®¸ ¡ i=1 tip i @x
@I
i
.
Treating labour as good 0, the homogeneity of the expenditure function can
be used to write
X n
qiSik + wS0k = 0; (4.91)
i=1
where (4.97) is the generalisation of (4.91). Normalising w at 1 and using (4.97)
the optimal tax rule becomes
S0k = µx k ; k = 1; :::; n: (4.92)
4.8. UNIFORM TAXES 125

In this form of the Ramsey rule the tax rates are set so that the demand for
each good is proportional to the rate of substitution between that good and
labour. Using Shephard’s lemma and the relation of the substitution terms to
the expenditure function, (4.98) is equivalent to

C 0k (q1 ; :::; qn ; w; U ) = µC k (q1 ; :::; qn ; w; U ) ; (4.93)

with w = 1.
When a uniform system of taxation is optimal, so that ti = t all i, there
must be some t that solves

C 0k ([1 + t] p 1 ; :::; [1 + t] p n ; w; U) = µCk ([1 + t] p 1 ; :::; [1 + t] p n ; w; U) : (4.94)

Since the expenditure function is homogeneous of degree 1, its …rst derivative


is homogeneous of degree 0 and its second of degree -1. Therefore (4.100) is
equivalent to
µ ¶ µ ¶
1 w w
C0k p 1 ; :::; pn ; ; U = µCk p 1 ; :::; p n ; ;U ; (4.95)
1+ t 1+t 1+ t

or
C 0k (p1 ; :::; p n ; w 0 ; U) = µ 0C k (p1 ; :::; p n ; w 0 ; U) ; (4.96)

where µ 0 = µ [1 + t] and w 0 = 1+t


w
. For uniform taxation to be always optimal,
(4.102) must hold for all producer price vectors p 1 ; :::; p n and wage rates w 0 .
Condition (4.102) places restrictions upon the forms of cost function, and hence
preferences that they represent, that will always lead to uniform taxation.
From Deaton (1979, 1981), one form of cost function that satis…es (4.102) is

C (p1 ; :::; p n ; w; U) = C (c (p 1 ; :::; pn ) ; w; U) ; (4.97)

which is called the implicitly separable cost function. More generally, Besley
and Jewitt (1990) have shown that any preferences that can be de…ned in the
form
f (Á (x; x 0 ; U) ; x0 ; U ) = 1; (4.98)

where x0 is labour supply and Á (x; x 0 ; U ) is homogeneous of degree zero in


(x; x 0 ) will result in uniform commodity taxes. A simple example of (4.104) is
the utility function
µ µ ¶ ¶
x
U =U Á ; x0 : (4.99)
x0

The important conclusion to draw from this analysis is that the conditions
implying uniform taxation are restrictive and there is no reason why they should
be satis…ed in practice. Therefore there are no grounds for believing that the
optimal tax system should be uniform.
126 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

4.9 Production e¢ciency


Production e¢ciency occurs when an economy is maximising the output attain-
able from its given set of resources. This requires the economy to be on the
boundary of its production possibility set. When such a point is attained, real-
location of inputs amongst …rms cannot increase the output of one good without
reducing that of another. In the special case in which each …rm employs some
of all of the available inputs, a necessary condition for production e¢ciency is
that the marginal rate of substitution (MRS ) between any two inputs is the
same for all …rms. Such a position of equality is attained, in the absence of
taxation, by the pro…t maximisation of …rms in competitive markets. Each …rm
sets the marginal rate of substitution equal to the ratio of factor prices and,
since factor prices are the same for all …rms, this induces the necessary equality
in the MRS s. The same is true when there is taxation provided all …rms face
the same post-tax prices for inputs, that is, inputs taxes are not di¤erentiated
between …rms.
In the context of commodity taxation, Diamond and Mirrlees (1971) proved
the Production E¢ciency Lemma. Assuming the economy is competitive, the
lemma states that the equilibrium with optimal commodity taxation should be
on the frontier of the aggregate production set. This can only be achieved if
private and public producer face the same shadow prices and if input taxes are
not di¤erentiated between …rms. In addition, since the competitive assumption
implies that any set of chosen post-tax prices can be sustained by the use of
taxes on …nal goods alone, the latter statement also carries the implication that
intermediate goods should not be taxed.
This result was seen as surprising at its time of publication because it
was clearly in sharp contrast to the predictions of the Lipsey-Lancaster (1956)
Second-Best theory that was being widely applied. Application of Second-Best
theory, which typically suggests that one distortion should be o¤set by oth-
ers, would imply that the distortion induced by the commodity taxes should be
matched by a similar distortion in input prices. Commodity taxation is therefore
a special case for which the general reasoning requires careful application.
The e¢ciency lemma, and the structure of the optimal commodity tax prob-
lem, can easily be explained diagrammatically for a single household two-good
economy. In Figure 4.2 the horizontal axis measures input use and the verti-
cal axis output. The shaded area is the production set for the economy and
the horizontal distance of the production set from the origin represents the tax
revenue required in units of the input good. It is assumed that the household
supplies the input and consumes the output, so that the supply of more input
from the household permits the purchase of more output. The household’s bud-
get constraint is therefore upward sloping and, in the absence of lump-sum taxes
or income, must pass through the origin. Denoting the optimal set of post-tax
prices by q, the budget constraint corresponding to this price vector is illus-
trated. Since supplying the input causes the household disutility, an increase
in input supply must be compensated for by further consumption of output in
order to keep utility constant. The household’s indi¤erence curves are therefore
4.9. PRODUCTION EFFICIENCY 127

Figure 4.2: Production E¢ciency

downward sloping.
The optimal tax equilibrium is given by the highest point on the household’s
o¤er curve that is in the production set; in Figure 4.2 the optimum is indicated
by point e. At this point the household is on indi¤erence curve I0 ¡ I0 and
production is e¢cient. To ensure that …rms earn zero pro…ts when producing at
the equilibrium point, producer prices, p, are determined by the normal to the
production set. For both producer and consumer prices, the price of the input
is normalised at 1. The di¤erence between the two sets of prices, t = q ¡ p,
determines the optimal set of tax rates. It should also be noted that there are
points above the indi¤erence curve I0 ¡ I0 which are preferred to e and which
are productively feasible. These can only be reached by the use of lump-sum
taxes and their existence illustrates the second-best nature of the commodity
tax optimum. With the use of an optimal lump-sum tax, the household would
reach indi¤erence curve I1 ¡ I1 .
To see that the optimum must be on the frontier of the production set, con-
sider points f and g. If the equilibrium were at f , the household’s welfare could
be raised by reducing the use of the input whilst keeping output constant. Since
this is feasible, f cannot be an optimum. From g, output could be increased
without employing more input so that g cannot be an optimum. Since this
reasoning can be applied to any point that is interior to the production set, the
optimum must be on the boundary.
Although Figure 4.2 was motivated by considering the input to be labour, a
slight re-interpretation can introduce intermediate goods. Assume that there is
an industry that uses one unit of labour to produce one unit of an intermediate
good and that the intermediate good is then used to produce …nal output. Figure
128 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION

4.2 then depicts the intermediate good (the input) being used to produce the
output. Although the household actually has preferences over labour and …nal
output and acts only on the markets for these goo ds, the direct link between
units of labour and of intermediate good allows preferences and the budget
constraint to be depicted as if they were de…ned directly on those variables.
The production e¢ciency argument then follows directly as before and now
implies that intermediate go ods should not be taxed since this would violate
the equalisation of MRS s between …rms.
Moving now to a many-household competitive economy with constant re-
turns to scale, the formal statement of the Production E¢ciency Lemma can be
given.

Lemma 18 (Diamond and Mirrlees) Assume that social welfare is strictly in-
creasing in the utility level of all households. If either
b
(i) for some i, x hi 0 for all h and x hi < 0 for some b
h;
or
b
(ii) for some i, with qi > 0, xhi ¸ 0 for all h and xhi > 0 for some bh;
then if an optimum exists, the optimum has production on the frontier of the
production possibility set.

Proof. Assume the optimum is interior to the production set. In case (i),
increasing qi would not reduce the welfare of any household and would strictly
raise that of bh. Such a change is feasible since the optimum is assumed interior
and the aggregate demand function is continuous. The change would raise social
welfare, thus contradicting the assertion that the initial point was optimal. The
same argument can be applied in case (ii) for a reduction in qi .
When decreasing returns are permitted, Dasgupta and Stiglitz (1972) con-
clude that production e¢ciency is only desirable if the range of government
instruments is su¢ciently great, in e¤ect, only if pro…ts can be taxed at ap-
propriate rates. Mirrlees (1972) provides further clari…cation of the relation of
pro…ts and production e¢ciency. These …ndings show that the constant returns
to scale assumption can be relaxed. Whilst retaining the competitive assump-
tion, one partial exemption to the Diamond-Mirrlees rule has been identi…ed by
Munk (1980) and Newbery (1986). If there are restrictions on taxes on …nal
goods, then production e¢ciency is no longer necessarily desirable. In detail,
Newbery demonstrates that if there are some goods whose optimal tax would
be positive but the goods cannot be taxed, then input taxes should be used
as partial substitutes for the missing …nal taxes. Similar results to those of
Newbery are also given by Ebrill and Slutsky (1990), although their analysis is
phrased in terms of regulated industries.
The Diamond-Mirrlees lemma therefore provides an argument for the non-
taxation of intermediate goods and the non-di¤erentiation of input taxes be-
tween …rms. As noted, it has been extended from its original constant returns
to scale setting. However, except for some special cases, imperfect competition
invalidates the lemma and taxes on intermediate goods will raise welfare. This
result will be considered in Chapter 11.
4.10. SUMMARY 129

4.10 Summary
This chapter has reviewed the major contributions to the large literature on op-
timal commodity taxation in a competitive economy. The Ramsey rule, which
represents the starting point for the modern analysis of commodity taxation,
has been introduced and its standard interpretation has been given. Although
e¢cient, the tax system the tax system this describes would be inherently in-
equitable. To introduce equity considerations, the economy was then extended
to incorporate many households following the work of Diamond and Mirrlees.
This extension clari…ed the e¤ects of equity upon the optimal rates of tax and
demonstrated how the equity/e¢ciency trade-o¤ was resolved. The economy
was then generalised further and the Diamond-Mirrlees Production E¢ciency
Lemma was proved. Contrary to the expectations of Second-Best theory, this
lemma showed that production e¢ciency is desirable in conjunction with the
optimal set of commodity taxes.
The motivation behind the theory of commodity taxation is to provide prac-
tical policy recommendations. Although the analysis remains some way o¤ fully
achieving this aim, a number of interesting studies have applied these optimal
tax rules to data. This line of work is still in its infancy but gradual improve-
ments in generality have been achieved. The numerical results indicate that the
optimal set of taxes may be able to achieve signi…cant redistribution via the
subsidisation of necessities.
130 CHAPTER 4. COMMODITY TAXATION
Chapter 5

Income Taxation

5.1 Introduction
The taxation of income is a ma jor source of revenue in most developed coun-
tries. It is also one of the most contentious. From one point of view, an income
tax is seen as a direct means of e¤ecting redistribution in order to meet objec-
tives of equity. From another, the imposition of an income tax is viewed as a
major disincentive to e¤ort and enterprise particularly when the marginal rate
of tax increases with income. The theory of income taxation shows how these
competing views in‡uence the design of the optimal tax and how the competing
trade-o¤s are resolved.
The analysis of income taxation that is undertaken below follows from the
initial contribution of Mirrlees (1971). Prior to that, there had been no formal
analysis of the structure or determinants of an income tax schedule that fully
captured the e¢ciency/equity trade-o¤ involved in income taxation. In addition,
the Mirrlees analysis also embodied the fact that the truly relevant characteris-
tics for taxation, the unobservable ability levels of the households, can only be
inferred indirectly from observed behaviour. This implies that the structure of
the income tax must be compatible with the revelation of this information by
households.
The chapter begins by providing a general description of the Mirrlees’ econ-
omy which is the basis for the analysis. The major theoretical results that have
been derived both for the general case and for the restricted constant marginal
tax rate case are described. This is followed by a review of the results of a
number of numerical studies. A critical analysis of the assumptions on which
the simulations are based is then given and the implications of modifying these
is illustrated by a brief discussion of labour supply decisions and some attempts
at the direct assessment of labour supply e¤ects. The chapter is concluded by
reviewing extensions of the basic analysis, including the design of tax systems
with both linear and nonlinear taxes, and issues that it omits.

131
132 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

5.2 The Mirrlees economy


The value of the Mirrlees’ economy in the analysis of income taxation is due to
the manner in which it captures the most important features of the tax design
problem. These features are that the no-tax equilibrium of the economy must
have an unequal distribution of income in order to introduce equity motivations
for taxation. The income distribution must also be generated endogenously by
the model, with households di¤ering in the income they earn, and the income tax
must a¤ect the labour supply decisions of the households in order to introduce
e¢ciency considerations. The economy must also be su¢ciently ‡exible that no
prior restrictions are placed on the tax functions that may be solutions. The
Mirrlees’ speci…cation is the simplest that satis…es all these requirements.
To simplify and focus the analysis, it is assumed that the economy is com-
petitive and that households in the economy di¤er only in their levels of skill
in employment. A household’s level of skill determines their hourly wage and
hence their income. The skill level is private information and is not known to
the government. The only tax instrument of the state is an income tax. An
income tax is employed both because lump-sum taxes are infeasible and because
it is assumed that it is not possible for the state to observe separately hours
worked and income per hour. Therefore, since only total income is observed, it
has to be the basis for the tax system. The content of this restriction is best
understood by considering the consequences of its relaxation. If it were relaxed,
a tax could be levied that was based on income per hour; in many cases this
would be a better guide to a household’s potential earning power than actual
income. Indeed, in the economy employed below, income per hour is precisely
the ultimate target of taxation. Despite this, it does not seem unreasonable to
assume that, as in practice, only total income is observed.
The income tax function is chosen to maximise social welfare subject to
achieving the required level of revenue. The generality of the analysis, and the
source of many of the di¢culties involved in carrying it out, derives from the
fact that no restrictions are placed at the outset on permissible candidates for
the optimal tax function. It is intended by this that the economy determines
the structure of the tax function rather than important aspects of the function
being determined by a priori assumptions.

5.2.1 The optimisation


The optimal income tax function is chosen to maximise social welfare. This
maximisation is subject to two constraints. The …rst constraint is that the in-
come tax function must lead to an outcome that satis…es productive feasibility
or, equivalently, meets the governments revenue requirement. The second con-
straint that must be satis…ed is rather more complex and the way in which it is
handled is of central importance for the analysis. To best understand the nature
of this constraint, an alternative interpretation of the optimisation is helpful.
Rather than viewing the government as choosing an income tax function, it can
be seen as assigning to each household a pre-tax income - consumption pair.
5.2. THE MIRRLEES ECONOMY 133

The additional constraint is then that each household must …nd it in their own
interest to choose the pre-tax income - consumption pair that the government
intends for them rather than a pair assigned to a di¤erent household. In other
words, the intended pair be must utility-maximising for the household over the
set of available pairs. Due to its nature, this is termed the self-selection con-
straint. The nature of the self-selection constraint will be discussed in 2.4.
It is worthwhile noting at this point some of the di¢culties involved in the
analysis of the general problem. The tax function is not restricted in form so
that for most tax functions the budget constraints of the households will be
nonlinear. In those cases for which the budget set is non-convex, there may
be non-uniqueness in the solution to the individual households’ maximisations
and the solutions need not form a convex set. These facts prevent the behav-
iour of the individuals being expressible by demand functions, in contrast to
the commodity tax problem of Chapter 5, and therefore introduce considerable
mathematical complication. It is also the reason why the self-selection con-
straint must be made explicit in the analysis of income taxation but not in that
of commodity taxation. Mirrlees (1986) provides a thorough discussion of these
issues.

5.2.2 Basic structure


Turning now to further details of the economy, it is assumed that there are two
commodities: a consumption good and a single labour service. A household’s
supply of the labour service is denoted by ` and consumption of the good by x.
The supply of labour is limited by 0 ` 1 and x ¸ 0. When the distinction
becomes necessary, the demands of di¤erent households will be distinguished by
an additional index. Each household is characterised by their skill level s The
value of s gives the relative e¤ectiveness of the labour supplied per unit of time,
so a high s household is more e¤ective in production.
If a household of ability s supplies ` hours of labour, they provide a quantity
s` of e¤ective labour. The analysis is simpli…ed by assuming that the marginal
product of labour is constant and, for a worker of ability s, is given by s.
The total productivity of a worker during the ` hours at work is then equal
to s`. Denote the supply of e¤ective labour of a household with ability s by
z (s) ´ s` (s). Normalising the price of the consumption good at 1, z (s) is
also the household’s pre-tax income in units of consumption. Denoting the tax
function by T (z) and the consumption function by c (z), a household that earns
z(s) units of income can consume

x (s) c (z (s)) = z (s) ¡ T (z (s)) ; (5.1)

units of the consumption good.


The ability parameter, s, is continuously distributed throughout the popu-
lation with support S, which may be …nite with S = [S 1 ; S 2 ] or in…nite with
S = [0; 1]. Typically the …nite support will be used, with the in…nite sup-
port introduced where appropriate. The cumulative distribution of s is given
134 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

by ¡ (s), so there are ¡ (s) households with ability s or less. The corresponding
density function is denoted ° (s).
All households have the same strictly concave utility function, an assump-
tion that permits interpersonal comparability. This common utility function is
denoted
U = U (x; `) : (5.2)
Each household makes the choice of labour supply and consumption demand to
maximise utility subject to the budget constraint. Hence a household of ability
s chooses x(s); `(s) to

max U = U (x; `) subject to x (s) c (s` (s)) : (5.3)

De…ne u(s) = U (x(s); `(s)) as the maximised level of utility at the optimal
choices.
In the absence of income taxation, a household of ability s would face the
budget constraint
x s`: (5.4)
From (5.4) it can be seen that the budget constraint in (`; x)-space di¤ers with
ability.
For the purposes of tax analysis, it is the budget constraint after tax, or
equivalently the imposed consumption function, that is of interest. The analysis
is simpli…ed if all households face the same budget constraint and this can be
achieved by setting the analysis in (z; x)-space. In this space, the pre-tax budget
constraint is given by the 45 o line for households of all abilities. With income
taxation, the gradient of the consumption function (6.1) is equal to 1 minus the
marginal rate of tax, where the marginal rate of tax, T 0 , is de…ned as @T@z( z) ,
and the vertical distance between the consumption function and the 45o line
represents the total tax paid. This is illustrated in Figure 5.1 for the consumer
earning units of income.

5.2.3 The structure of utility


As already noted, the households have identical preferences over consumption
and leisure. The utility function is continuously di¤erentiable, strictly increasing
in consumption and strictly decreasing in leisure. In addition, it satis…es

Us > 0; U` < 0; Uxx < 0; (5.5)

and
U` (x; `) ! ¡1 as ` ! 1: (5.6)
Condition (5.6) implies that each household will endeavour to avoid corner so-
lutions with ` = 1. It should be noted that the quantity of labour supplied
is measured positively in order to conform with the literature. The indi¤er-
ence curves of the utility function are illustrated in Figure 5.2, in which utility
increases to the north west.
5.2. THE MIRRLEES ECONOMY 135

Figure 5.1: After-Tax Budget Constraint

Figure 5.2: Preferences


136 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

Figure 5.3: Translation of Indi¤erence Curves

To allow preferences and the budget constraint to be depicted on the same


diagram, the utility function can be written
³ z´
U = U (x; `) = U x; ´ u (x; z; s) : (5.7)
s
The indi¤erence curves of u (x; z; s), drawn in (z; x)-space are dependent upon
the ability level of the household since it takes a high-ability household less
labour time to achieve any given level of income. In fact, the indi¤erence curves
are constructed from those in (`; x)-space by multiplying by the relevant value
of s. This construction is shown in Figure 5.3 for the single indi¤erence curve
I0 and households of three di¤erent ability levels.
A number of the results below will require additional structure to be placed
upon preferences. This involves relating the gradient of the indi¤erence curves
through a given consumption-income point for households of di¤erent abilities
to the ability levels. The required assumption, termed agent monotonicity, was
introduced by Mirrlees (1976) and named by Seade (1982).
Agent Monotonicity
The utility function (5.7) satis…es agent monotonicity if is ¡ uuxz a decreasing
function of s.
It should be noted that © ´ ¡ uuzx is the marginal rate of substitution between
consumption and pre-tax income and that agent monotonicity requires © s ´

@s
< 0. An equivalent de…nition of agent monotonicity is that ¡` U `
Ux
is an
uz U` (x; zs )
increasing function of `. This can be seen by noting that ¡ ux = ¡ sU x; z .
x( s)
h i
U
@ ¡` U `
Calculating @`
x
and © s shows
h i
U`
1 @ ¡` Ux
©s = ¡ 2 : (5.8)
s @`
Agent monotonicity is equivalent to the condition that, in the absence of taxa-
tion, consumption will increase as the wage rate increases. This equivalence is
5.2. THE MIRRLEES ECONOMY 137

Figure 5.4: Agent Monotonicity

easily demonstrated by calculating the derivative in (5.8) and contrasting this


to the rate of change of consumption with respect to the wage rate derived from
the comparative statics of utility maximisation. A su¢cient condition for agent
monotonicity is that consumption is not inferior, i.e. it does not decrease as
lump-sum income increases. This result can also be derived from the contrast
between the comparative statics of utility maximisation and the derivative in
(5.8).
Since the marginal rate of substitution is the gradient of the indi¤erence
curve, agent monotonicity implies that at any point in (z; x)-space the indif-
ference curve of a household of ability s 1 passing through that point is steeper
than the curve of a household of ability s2 if s 2 > s1 . This is illustrated in
Figure 5.4. The name for the condition follows from this monotonicity property
that it imposes upon preferences. Agent monotonicity also implies that any two
indi¤erence curves of households of di¤erent abilities only cross once.
Theorem 5.1 shows that when the consumption function is a di¤erentiable
function of labour supply, agent monotonicity implies that gross income is an
increasing function of ability. It is important to stress that no other assumption
than di¤erentiability is placed on the consumption function to derive this result.

Theorem 19 (Mirrlees ) When ` > 0 and the su¢cient conditions for utility
maximisation are satis…ed, z(s) is an increasing function of s.

Proof. Writing the utility functions as U (c (s` (s)) ; ` (s)), the …rst-order
condition for utility maximisation, U` + Ux sc0 (s`) = 0, is equivalent to
¸
U` U`
s`c0 (s`) + ` = 0; (5.9)
s` Ux

U`
or, since s` < 0,
U`
zc0 (z) + ` = 0: (5.10)
Ux
138 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

The second-order condition then becomes


h i
@ zc0 (z) + ` UU`x
0: (5.11)
@z
The total di¤erential of the …rst-order condition (5.10) with respect to s is
given by h i h i
@ zc0 (z) + ` UUx` @ ` UU`x z
z 0 (s) ¡ = 0: (5.12)
@z @` s2
h i
U
@ ` U`
Since agent monotonicity implies @` x is negative, it follows from the second-
order condition (5.11) that z 0 (s) > 0.
This theorem can be reinterpreted as saying that if agent monotonicity holds
and the implemented tax function has pre-tax income increasing with ability,
then the second-order condition (5.11) for utility maximisation must hold. In
other words, with agent monotonicity, the second-order condition and the con-
dition that z 0 (s) ¸ 0 are equivalent. The importance of the condition z 0 (s) ¸ 0
will appear again in the discussion of self-selection.

5.2.4 Self-selection
In choosing the optimal tax function, it must be the case that each household
will …nd it in their interest to choose the income-consumption pair that the gov-
ernment intends them to select. This self-selection constraint is now introduced
formally and a convenient representation is derived.
Let x (s) and z (s) now represent the consumption and income levels that the
government intends a household of ability s to choose. The household of ability s
will choose (x (s) ; z (s)) provided that this pair generate at least as much utility
as any other choice. This condition must apply to all consumption-income pairs
and to all households. Written using (6.7) the self-selection constraint is as
follows.
Self-selection
The self-selection constraint is satis…ed if u (x (s) ; z (s) ; s) ¸ u (x (s0 ) ; z (s 0) ; s)
for all s; s0 .
It should be noted that the utility arising from the pair (x (s) ; z (s)) is com-
pared with that from all other possible combinations. It is this that leads to
some di¢culties in applying the self-selection constraint. Since the economy has
a continuum of ability levels, there is an uncountable in…nity of self-selection
constraints for each household when expressed in the form above. Clearly, such
a set of constraints cannot be easily incorporated as a restriction on a max-
imisation. An important aspect of the analysis is to construct an alternative
representation of the self-selection constraint that can be more easily accommo-
dated into a maximisation problem.
In the case of linear taxation, each household pays (or receives) a …xed
lump-sum and the marginal rate of tax on income is constant. The imposed
consumption function is linear and each household faces a convex budget set.
5.2. THE MIRRLEES ECONOMY 139

This structure eliminates the requirement to consider the self-selection con-


straints since the behaviour of the household can be determined as a function
of the two parameters that describe the tax function: the lump-sum payment
and the marginal rate of tax. The derivation of the optimal linear income tax
is therefore considerably simpler than that of the nonlinear tax and resembles
the analysis of commodity taxation.
When nonlinear taxation is considered, the self-selection constraints must
be included. This is achieved by noting that the satisfaction of the self-selection
constraint is equivalent to achieving the minimum of a certain minimisation
problem. If the su¢cient conditions for the minimisation are satis…ed by the
allocation resulting from the tax function, then the self-selection constraint is
satis…ed.
To derive the required minimisation problem, let u (s) ´ u (x (s) ; z (s) ; s)
represent the maximised level of utility for a consumer of ability s resulting
from (5.3). Now note that

0 = u (s) ¡ u (x (s) ; z (s) ; s) u (s0 ) ¡ u (x (s) ; z (s) ; s 0) ; (5.13)

so that s0 = s minimises u (s0 ) ¡ u (x (s) ; z (s) ; s0 ). Hence

u0 (s) = u s (x (s) ; z (s) ; s) : (5.14)

From the de…nition of u (s) it follows that

ux x 0 (s) + u z z 0 (s) = 0; (5.15)

is equivalent to (5.14). Condition (5.14), or equivalently (5.15), is the necessary


condition (or …rst-order condition) for the self-selection constraint to be satis…ed.
Its advantage over the direct formulation of self-selection is that it provides
a single condition for each value of s rather than an uncountable in…nity of
conditions.
The second-order condition for the self-selection constraint to be satis…ed is
found from the second derivative of u (s0 ) ¡ u (x (s) ; z (s) ; s0 ) with respect to s0
to be
u 00 (s) ¡ uss (x (s) ; z (s) ; s) ¸ 0: (5.16)
Again using the de…nition of u (s)

u 00 (s) = u sxx 0 (s) + usz z0 (s) + u ss; (5.17)

which gives, by using (5.16),

usx x 0 (s) + u sz z 0 (s) ¸ 0: (5.18)

Eliminating x 0 (s) using (5.15) provides the …nal condition


¸
uz 0 ©s
u sz ¡ u sx z (s) = ¡ z 0 (s) ¸ 0; (5.19)
ux ux
140 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

where © is the marginal rate of substitution introduced in the discussion of


agent monotonicity. With agent monotonicity ©s < 0, so that satisfaction of
the second-order condition for self-selection is equivalent to z 0 (s) ¸ 0. Any tax
function that leads to an outcome satisfying (5.15) and will therefore satisfy the
self-selection constraint.
It is also worth noting a further result that can be derived directly from
the conditions already stated. Since u x > 0 and u ` < 0, z 0 (s) ¸ 0 implies
from (5.15) that any tax function satisfying the self-selection constraint must
result in x0 (s) ¸ 0. The self-selection constraint therefore requires both pre-tax
income and consumption to be non-decreasing with s.

5.3 Characterisation of optimal tax function


The aim of the theoretical analysis is to provide a characterisation of the prop-
erties that the optimal tax function will have, given the speci…cation and as-
sumptions adopted. It will clearly not be possible to calculate the function
without precisely stating the functional forms of utility, production and skill
distribution. What will be achieved is the derivation of a set of restrictions that
the optimal function must satisfy. This is undertaken …rstly for the case where
the marginal rate of tax is assumed constant. As already noted, this implies
convexity of the individual budget set and allows behaviour to be expressible
via demand functions which considerably simpli…es the resulting analysis. The
general problem is then considered. Results are derived using both the nec-
essary conditions for the maximisation of social welfare and directly using a
diagrammatic framework.

5.3.1 The general problem


Using the individual demand and supply functions and integrating over the
population, it is possible to de…ne total e¤ective labour supply, Z, by
Z 1
Z= z (s) ° (s) ds; (5.20)
0

and aggregate demand, X, where


Z 1
X = x (s) ° (s) ds: (5.21)
0

The optimal tax function is then chosen to maximise social welfare, where wel-
fare is given by the Bergson-Samuelson function
Z 1
W = W (u (s)) ° (s) ds; (5.22)
0

with W 00 0.
5.3. CHARACTERISATION OF OPTIMAL TAX FUNCTION 141

There are two constraints placed upon the maximisation of (5.22). The …rst
is that the chosen allocation must be productively feasible. This requirement
can be denoted in terms of quantities by

X F (Z); (5.23)
where F (¢) is the production function for the economy. This de…nition of
productive feasibility can incorporate the government revenue requirement, ex-
pressed as a quantity of labour consumed by the government zG , by noting that
(5.23) can be written X Fb (Z ¡ z G ) = F (Z). Alternatively, the government
revenue constraint can be used in place of the production constraint to express
the restriction in value terms. Denoting the level of revenue required by R,
R ´ z G , the revenue constraint can be written
Z 1
R [z (s) ¡ x (s)] ° (s) ds: (5.24)
0

The second constraint upon the optimisation is that it must satisfy the self-
selection constraint. This has already been described in 2.4.

5.3.2 Linear taxation


The complexity of the general model of income taxation has lead to considerable
interest in the restricted case of linear taxation. With linear taxation the mar-
ginal rate of tax is constant and there is an identical lump-sum tax or subsidy
for all households. The advantages of this restriction is that it ensures that the
budget sets of all households are convex so that optimal choices will be unique
when preferences are strictly convex. In addition, the tax system is described
by just two parameters: the marginal tax rate and the lump-sum subsidy. The
choice of optimal policy therefore corresponds to a standard maximisation prob-
lem. In addition, the linear tax structure corresponds to proposals for negative
income tax schemes, in which all households below a given income level receive
a subsidy from the tax system, and to the tax reform proposals of a number of
countries that have reduced the number of tax rate bands.
Using the notation set out above, under a linear tax system a household
with ability s supplying ` units of labour will pay tax of amount

T (s`) = ¡¿ + ts`; (5.25)


where t is the marginal rate of tax and ¿ is a lump-sum subsidy if positive and a
tax if negative. Denoting [1 ¡ t] by ³ , the consumption function of the household
is
x = ¿ + ³ s`: (5.26)
Each household chooses consumption and labour supply to maximise utility
subject to (5.26), with utility represented by (5.2). Assuming the solution to
the individual maximisation is interior, the …rst-order conditions can be reduced
to
U`
¡ = ³ s: (5.27)
Ux
142 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

Combined with the consumption function (5.26), (5.27) implies labour supply
and consumption demand functions of the form
` = ` (³ ; ¿ ; s) ; x = ¿ + ³ s` (³ ; ¿ ; s) : (5.28)
Substituted into the utility function, these determine the indirect utility function
U = U (¿ + ³ s` (³ ; ¿ ; s) ; ` (³; ¿ ; s)) = V (³ ; ¿ ; s) ; (5.29)
with
@V @V
= Ux ; = Ux s`; (5.30)
@¿ @³
where @V
@¿
is equal to the marginal utility of income.
The government’s optimisation problem is to choose the parameters of the
tax system to maximise social welfare subject to raising the required revenue,
R. Using (5.26) and (5.29), the optimisation can be expressed as
Z 1
max W (V (³ ; ¿ ; s)) ° (s) ds; (5.31)
f¿ ;³g 0

subject to Z 1
[¡¿ + [1 ¡ ³] s` (³ ; ¿ ; s)] ° (s) ds ¸ R: (5.32)
0
Using (5.30) and de…ning the social marginal utility of income for a household
of ability s by
@V (³ ; ¿ ; s)
¯ (s) = W 0 (V (³ ; ¿ ; s)) ; (5.33)
@¿
the necessary conditions for the choice of ¿ and ³ respectively are
Z 1 Z 1 ¸
@z
¯° (s) ds = ¸ H ¡ [1 ¡ ³ ] ° (s) ds ; (5.34)
0 0 @¿
and Z 1 Z 1 ¸
@z
¯ z° (s) ds = ¸ z ¡ [1 ¡ ³ ] ° (s) ds; (5.35)
0 0 @³
where H is the population size, .
The …rst use of these necessary conditions is to derive a simple expression
for the optimal marginal tax rate, t, that is due to Tuomala (1985). To do this,
x
divide (5.35) by (5.34) and denote by a bar terms of the form H . This gives
R1 R1
¯z° (s) ds z ¡ 0 [1 ¡ ³ ] @z

° (s) ds
R0 1 = R1 : (5.36)
¯ ° (s) ds 1 ¡ 0 [1 ¡ ³ ] @z
0 @¿ ° (s) ds

The term on the left-hand side of (5.36) is now denoted by z(¯) and can be
interpreted as the welfare-weighted average labour supply. From totally di¤er-
entiating the government revenue constraint whilst holding R constant, it can
be found that R1
d¿ ¡z + 0 [1 ¡ ³] @z@³
° (s) ds
jR c on st = R1 : (5.37)
d³ 1¡ [1 ¡ ³ ] @z ° (s) ds
0 @¿
5.3. CHARACTERISATION OF OPTIMAL TAX FUNCTION 143

Hence from (5.36) and (5.37)


d¿
z(¯) = ¡ jR c on st : (5.38)

Since averaging over the population must give z = z (¿ ; ³ ), it follows from (5.38)
that, holding revenue constant,
dz dz dz d¿ dz dz
jR co n st = + jR co ns t = ¡ z(¯): (5.39)
d³ d³ d¿ d³ d³ d¿
Therefore, recalling that t = 1 ¡ ³, (5.36) can be written in the form
¸
dz dz dz
z(¯) ¡ z = [1 ¡ ³ ] z(¯) ¡ = ¡t jR c on s t ; (5.40)
d¿ d³ d³
or
z(¯) ¡ z
t= ; (5.41)
¡ dz j
dt R co ns t
where the derivative is taken with revenue constant.
Although the tax rule in (5.41) only provides an implicit expression for t, it
can be used to assess the e¤ects of various parametric changes. If it is assumed
that z(¯) ¡ z is positive and dz j
dt R c on st
negative, then an increase in the disin-
centive e¤ect of taxation (a rise in dz
dt j R c on s t ) would reduce the optimal tax rate.
A reduction in the optimal tax would also occur, with ¯ a decreasing function
of s and z an increasing function of s, if the welfare weights were increased on
the high-s households so that equity was given less weight. The e¤ect of other
variations can be addressed by similar reasoning.
From the …rst-order conditions it is also possible to provide general results
on the sign of the tax rates. The simplest result of this form is due to Romer
(1976) and Sheshinski (1972b) and is stated as Theorem 5.2.

Theorem 20 (Sheshinski/Romer) If (i) @z


@¿
< 0, (ii) @z

¸ 0 and R = 0, then
t > 0 and ¿ > 0.

Proof. It is clear form (5.34) and (5.33) that ¸ > 0 and that ³ > 0 (or else
x; ` = 0 for all s). Now assume that ³ > 1. Then (5.34) and (i) imply that
Z 1
[¯ ¡ ¸] ° (s) ds 0: (5.42)
0

Now since z is an increasing function of s in order that the second-order condi-


tion for utility maximisation is satis…ed and ¯ ¡ ¸ is a decreasing function
Z 1
[¯ ¡ ¸] z (s) ° (s) ds 0: (5.43)
0

From (5.35) and (ii) however, inequality (5.43) cannot be satis…ed if ³ ¸ 1.


Hence ³ < 1 which implies that the marginal tax rate t > 0. The positivity of t
then follows from the zero revenue condition.
144 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

The assumptions of this theorem have been weakened by Hellwig (1986) to


those of agent monotonicity and non-inferiority of leisure.
The linear model has also been used to …nd upper bounds upon the optimal
tax rate. Hellwig (1986) and Svensson and Weibull (1986) show that the optimal
rate is bounded above by the optimal tax under a maxi-min social welfare func-
tion and this rate is bounded by the revenue-maximising tax rate. Svensson and
Weibull (1986) also show that the upper bound given by the revenue-maximising
tax rate holds under a Pareto-ordering of states alone. Finally, Helpman and
Sadka (1978) consider some comparative statics e¤ects of changes in parame-
ters. An increase in the concavity of W (¢) is shown to raise the marginal rate
of tax (as suggested after (5.41)). In contrast, the e¤ect of a mean-preserving
increase in the spread of the skill distribution cannot be unambiguously signed.

5.3.3 Nonlinear taxation


With nonlinear taxation the self-selection constraint must be taken fully into
account. As shown in 2.4 this consists of (5.14) (the …rst-order condition) and
z 0 (s) ¸ 0 (the second-order condition). Most analyses of optimal income tax-
ation, such as Mirrlees (1971) and Seade (1977), have incorporated only the
…rst-order condition and adopt what has become known as the …rst-order ap-
proach. As shown in Mirrlees (1986) this may lead to incorrect results. In fact,
Ebert (1992) presents an example in which the solution with only the …rst-order
condition included leads to a consumption function with an interval over which
it is decreasing. In contrast Brito and Oakland (1977) and Ebert (1992) impose
both the …rst- and second-order conditions as constraints upon the maximisa-
tion and so avoid these di¢culties. Given these observations, the analysis below
will adopt the second-order approach and impose both the …rst-order condition
and the constraint z 0 (s) ¸ 0 upon the optimisation.

Formal optimisation
The maximisation problem has been analysed in two distinct ways. The analysis
of Seade (1977) formulated the maximisation in terms of the calculus of varia-
tions and employed as choice variables the functions x(s) and `(s). In contrast,
Mirrlees (1971) and Ebert (1992) employ a formulation based on Pontryagin’s
maximum principle. Naturally, there are slight di¤erences between the two, but
the …nal characterisation is the same. The optimal structure of income taxa-
tion is characterised here by applying Pontryagin’s maximum principle, a good
introduction to which is given in Intriligator (1971). In this framework, the
level of utility, u(s), pre-tax income z (s), and the tax payments of households
of ability s or less, given by
Z s
R (s) = [z (s0 ) ¡ x (s 0)] ° (s 0) ds0 ; (5.44)
s1

are taken as state variables and the derivative of gross income, ´ (s) ´ dz
ds , is
taken as the control variable. The level of consumption can then be found by
5.3. CHARACTERISATION OF OPTIMAL TAX FUNCTION 145

solving u (s) = u (x (s) ; z (s) ; s).


Adopting a utilitarian objective, the control variable is chosen to maximise
Z s2
u (s) ° (s) ds; (5.45)
s1

subject to
dR
= [z (s) ¡ x (s)] ° (s) ; (5.46)
ds
R (s 1 ) = R (s2 ) = 0; (5.47)
du
= u s (x (s) ; z (s) ; s) ; (5.48)
ds
dz
= ´ (s) ; (5.49)
ds
µ ¶
dz
µ = µ (´ (s)) ¸ 0: (5.50)
ds
The revenue constraint is captured by (5.46) and (5.47). To simplify, it is
assumed that zero revenue is to be collected and, from (5.44), this is re‡ected in
the upper end-point condition in (5.47). The rate of change in revenue, (5.46),
is derived directly from (5.44). The self-selection constraint is represented by
(5.48) - (5.50). The …rst-order condition (5.14) is written as (5.48) and the
second-order condition is included as (5.49) and (5.50). Condition (5.49) de…nes
the rate of change of the state variable . The interpretation of (5.50) is that the
straightforward inclusion of the second-order condition ´ (s) ¸ 0 would lead to
singularity when combined with (5.49). The second-order condition is therefore
transformed to (5.50) where the di¤erentiable function µ (´ (s)) satis…es µ (0) = 0
and µ 0 (´) > 0.
Introducing the adjoint variables ¸ (s), ¹ (s), º (s) and (s), the Hamiltonian
for the optimisation is

H = u (s) ° (s)+¸ (s) [z (s) ¡ x (s)] ° (s)+¹ (s) us (z (s) ; x (s) ; s)+º (s) ´ (s)+ (s) µ (s) ;
(5.51)
and the necessary conditions are

dH
= º + µ 0 (´) = 0; (5.52)

dH @ [[z (s) ¡ x (s)] ° (s)] @u s (z (s) ; x (s) ; s)


=¸ +¹ = ¡º 0; (5.53)
dz @z @z
dH @ [[z (s) ¡ x (s)] ° (s)] @u s (z (s) ; x (s) ; s)
= ° (s) + ¸ +¹ = ¡¹0 ; (5.54)
du @u @zu
dH
= ¡¸ 0 = 0; (5.55)
dR
dz
= 0; ¸ 0; (5.56)
ds
146 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

with transversality conditions


¹ (S1 ) = ¹ (S 2) = 0; º (S1 ) = º (S 2 ) = 0 (5.57)
To derive the form of these conditions that will be used below, note that
from the identity u (s) = u (z (s) ; x (s) ; s) it follows that
@x ux
=¡ = ©; (5.58)
@z uz
and
@x 1
= : (5.59)
@u ux
In addition,
@us (x (s) ; z (s) ; s) @x
= u sx + u z = ¡u x©; (5.60)
@z @z
and
@u s (x (s) ; z (s) ; s) @x u sx
= u sx = : (5.61)
@u @u ux
Now denoting Á (s) = (s) µ 0 (´ (s)), (5.52) - (5.57) can be given the alternative
formulation
¡¹ux © s + ¸ [1 ¡ ©] ° ¡ Á0 = 0; (5.62)
¸
0 u sx ¸
¹ +¹ + 1¡ ° = 0; (5.63)
ux ux
dz
Á = 0; Á ¸ 0; (5.64)
ds
¹ (S1 ) = ¹ (S2 ) = 0; Á (S1 ) = Á (S2 ) = 0; (5.65)
where the second part of (5.65) follows from (5.52).
The interpretation of these necessary conditions is best undertaken by con-
sidering separately the case in which Á is zero for all s and that in which it is
positive for some s. In the …rst case, since Á is zero the second-order condition
for the satisfaction of the self-selection constraint is not binding and pre-tax
income is a strictly increasing function of ability. When this is true, the re-
sults derived from the …rst-order approach of Mirrlees (1971) and Seade (1977)
are identical to those of the second-order approach. In particular, (5.64) and
the second part of (5.65) become irrelevant, and Á0 is eliminated from (5.62).
The two remaining equations are then the standard conditions of the …rst-order
approach describing the optimal tax function.
Now consider the case where there are some values of s for which Á is not
zero. For such s, z 0 = 0. Hence if Á is positive over the interval [s0 ; s1 ], all
households with abilities falling in that interval earn the same pre-tax income.
These households are therefore bunched at a single income level. Furthermore,
because of (5.15), they must also have the same level of consumption. A point
where bunching occurs can be identi…ed by a kink in the consumption function.
It is also interesting to note that although pre-tax income and consumption are
identical, utility is increasing with s over the bunched households since those
with higher s have to undertake less work to obtain the common income level.
5.3. CHARACTERISATION OF OPTIMAL TAX FUNCTION 147

Characterisation of optimal tax function


The …rst theorem on the structure of the optimal tax function is concerned with
demonstrating that if any households are unemployed at the optimum, then it
will be the lowest ability households.

Theorem 21 (Mirrlees) If there exists an ability level s 0 2 S such that ` (s 0 ) =


0, then ` (s) = 0 for any s < s 0 .

Proof. Assume ` (s0 ) = 0 and that there is some s, with s < s0 , such that
` (s) > 0. It follows that
µ µ ¶ ¶
s s
U (c (s` (s)) ; ` (s)) < U c s0 ` (s) ; ` (s) ; (5.66)
s0 s0

since ss0 < 1 and therefore the right-hand side of (5.66) represents the utility
derived with less labour supply but retaining the same level of consumption. In
addition,
µ µ ¶ ¶
s s
U c s0 ` (s) ; ` (s) < U (c (s0 ` (s 0)) ; ` (s0 )) ; (5.67)
s0 s0

since ` (s 0 ) is utility maximising for the household of ability s0 . Hence if ` (s) >
0, combining these inequalities gives

u (s) < u (s0 ) : (5.68)

However, if ` (s) = 0, it is clear that

u (s) = u (s0 ) : (5.69)

Therefore ` (s) > 0 is not utility maximising and ` (s) = 0 for s s0 .


Theorem 5.3 is an interesting result since it shows, even without specifying
the tax function, that the optimal tax system may generate unemployment in
the sense that it results in low ability households choosing to do no work. As
these households are productive whenever their ability level is non-zero, and
output would increase if they did work, this carries important implications for
the relation between optimal taxes and the achievement of maximum potential
output.
The second result demonstrates that a marginal tax rate in excess of 100%
will never be optimal.

Theorem 22 (Mirrlees ) The consumption function c(z) will be increasing in


z.

Proof. Self-selection requires that u xx 0 + u z z 0 = 0 and z0 ¸ 0, therefore


x ¸ 0. By de…nition, x (s) = c (z (s)) so that x 0 = c0 z 0 . Hence c0 ¸ 0. Since
0

c(z) = z ¡ T (z), the fact that c0 ¸ 0 implies that c0 = 1 ¡ T 0 ¸ 0 , T 0 1, so


the marginal tax rate is always less than or equal to 1.
148 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

Figure 5.5: A Tax Rate Greater than 100%

To illustrate the reasoning behind Theorem 5.4, consider a consumption


function that has a section with gradient less than zero, that is a marginal tax
rate greater than 100%. Such a consumption function is shown in Figure 5.5
with the decreasing section A ¡ B. Because the indi¤erence curves represent
convex preferences, no household will locate between A and C , although with
Leontief indi¤erence curves there may be some households indi¤erent between
A and C , and the consumption function with the ‡at section joining A and
C produces an identical …nal allocation. Therefore downward sloping sections
are redundant and there is no gain from a consumption function that has a
decreasing section.

The next theorem proves that the marginal rate of tax must always be
non-negative. The theorem was …rst proved for an additively separable util-
ity function by Mirrlees (1971) and for a linear tax system by Sadka (1976).
The generalisation of the theorem to nonlinear taxes and non-separable utility
was given in Seade (1982). The version of the theorem proved here relies upon
strong assumptions; in particular it is assumed that there is no bunching. An
extension of the theorem to take account of the possibility of bunching is con-
tained in Ebert (1992). The theorem can also be extended to prove that the
marginal tax rate must be strictly positive except for the households with the
highest and lowest abilities, again see Ebert (1992).
To develop the theorem it is …rst necessary to note that when there is no
bunching Á0 = 0 so that (5.62) can be written as

¹ux © s
1¡©= : (5.70)
¸°

Under the adopted normalisation, 1 ¡ © (s) is the marginal tax rate facing the
household of ability s: the pre-tax price of consumption relative to income is 1
and © (s), being the post-tax marginal rate of substitution, is equal to post-tax
relative prices. Given that ¸ will be proved to be positive below, the sign of
the marginal rate of tax is then the opposite of that of ¹. To establish that the
5.3. CHARACTERISATION OF OPTIMAL TAX FUNCTION 149

tax is non-negative, it is therefore necessary to establish that ¹ is non-positive.


This is the basis of the proof of the following theorem.

Theorem 23 (Seade) Assuming agent monotonicity, if leisure is not an infe-


rior good and u zx ¸ 0 then the marginal tax rate is positive.

Proof. It is …rst shown that non-inferiority of leisure and u zx ¸ 0 imply


that u x is a decreasing function of s. This follows since
¸
du x ux u xz
= uxx x 0 + uxz z 0 + u xs = x 0 uxx ¡ + uxs ; (5.71)
ds uz

where the second equality follows from the …rst-order condition (5.15). Non-
inferiority of leisure implies u xx ¡ u xuuzxz 0 and, since u xs = ¡ z usxz , the
assumption that uz x ¸ 0 (and u xx < 0) result in du
ds
x
0.
Solving the di¤erential equation (5.63) gives
Z ¸ "Z 0 #
S2 s
¸ 0 u sx 00
¹ (s) = 1¡ ° (s ) exp ds ds0 : (5.72)
s ux s u x

Since the transversality conditions require ¹ (S1 ) = ¹ (S2 ) = 0 and u x > 0, it


follows that ¸ > 0. In
h addition,
i (5.55) implies that ¸ is a constant. Combining
these observations, 1 ¡ u¸x cannot be always positive or always negative. In
fact, it must be negative for low values of s and positive for high values. This
implies that ¹ (s) is decreasing for s less than some s and increasing for s greater
than s. Since ¹ (0) = 0, ¹ (s) is then seen to be non-positive for all s, which
completes the proof when combined with (5.70).
The theorems stated to this point have been concerned with the general
structure of the tax function, rather than with particular properties. One par-
ticularly relevant property of an income tax function is progressivity. Although
there are several possible de…nitions of progressivity, see the discussion in Lam-
bert (1989), the one that is adopted here is to say the tax system is progressive if
it has a marginal rate that increases with income. This requirement is equivalent
to the condition
T 00 ¸ 0: (5.73)

Progressivity is a feature that almost all actual income tax systems pos-
sess, an observation that illustrates the importance of investigating whether
this property is always optimal.
The following theorem has obvious implications for the issue of progressivity
of the tax function. It is proved both by a direct argument and by appeal to
the necessary condition in (5.70).

Theorem 24 (Sadka/Seade) Let the upper bound on ability, S2 , be …nite. Then


the marginal rate of tax must be 0 for a household of ability S2 .
150 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

Figure 5.6: Zero Rate at the Top

Proof.
Let ABC in Figure 5.6 be the initial graph of c(z) = z ¡ T (z) and HBE be
an indi¤erence curve of a household with ability S2 . Since it is assumed that
T 0 > 0 for ABC , it follows c0 < 1, hence the gradient of HBE is < 1 at B. Now
de…ne a new tax T 1 as follows

T 1 (z) = T (z) for z z(S2 ; T ); (5.74)

and

T 1 (z) = T (z(S2 ; T )) all z ¸ z(S2 ; T ): (5.75)

Under the new tax T 1 , the tax payment is held constant above income level
z(S2 ; T ).
The graph of c1 (z) = z ¡ T 1 (z) is then ABD where the section BD has a
zero marginal rate. A household of ability S2 will move to K and is evidently
better o¤. Revenue has also not changed. Therefore this must represent an
improvement in welfare and T 0 (S2 ) > 0 cannot be optimal.
The alternative proof is to note that the upper bound on ability implies that
°(S2 ) > 0 and the transversality condition implies ¹(S2 ) = 0. Therefore, from
(5.62),
Á0
1¡©= : (5.76)
¸°
However, (5.64) and (5.65) imply Á0 is non-positive at S2 , giving 1 ¡ © 0 at
S2 . Combining this inequality with Theorem 5.5, it follows that 1 ¡ © (S2 ) = 0
and the theorem is proved.
For this argument to work in the case of the in…nite support, where it is
natural to assume lims!1 ° (s) = 0, further restrictions are necessary in order
to evaluate the limiting tax rate. Details of these can be found in Seade (1977).
Theorem 5.6 is purely local in the sense that it relates only to the household
of highest ability and, by continuity, to the households of similar ability. The
5.3. CHARACTERISATION OF OPTIMAL TAX FUNCTION 151

Figure 5.7: Initial Schedule

Figure 5.8: Pareto-Improving Schedule

next result of Seade’s is concerned with extending the improvement further down
the ability scale.

Theorem 25 (Seade) For a population with bounded ability, any income tax
schedule with a positive marginal rate at the top of the scale can be replaced by
one that leaves all households better o¤, inducing them to earn more income but
paying the same tax.

Proof. Start with the initial schedule µ in Figure 5.7 and the optimal
choices, illustrated for households of three di¤erent abilities, given by the tan-
gency points a, b and c.
It is …rst noted, as before, that any movement along a 45o line does not a¤ect
tax revenue since T 0 = 0 and no net payments are made out of the extra income.
Further, any relocation locally up the relevant line 45o for each household will
improve welfare. Hence the tax system bµ drawn in Figure 5.8 improves welfare.
The tax function bµ is constructed by …rst selecting ba for the household of
highest ability and then moving the tax function around their indi¤erence curve
and attempting to cross the 45o line through b (the location of the household
152 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

Figure 5.9: Final Schedule

with second highest ability) at the highest point, then continuing downwards.
This will obviously lead to a general improvement in welfare.
Such improvements can be continued until the schedule µ ¤ in the Figure 5.9
is reached.
Point a¤ obviously represents the maximum increase in utility possible with-
out altering the level of the tax payment. The resulting schedule is then con-
structed by working left from a¤ .
The previous two results have been concerned with the shape of the tax
schedule primarily at the top end of the ability scale. The next result of this
section is due to Seade (1977) and determines the tax rate facing the lowest abil-
ity household under the assumption that there is no bunching. This assumption
guarantees that the bottom of the tax function will only apply to the lowest
ability household and that they will be at an interior solution rather than at a
corner

Theorem 26 (Seade) If there is no bunching at the lowest income, the optimal


marginal rate for the household of lowest ability is zero.

Proof. From the no-bunching condition the lowest tax rate only applies to
the person of lowest ability. Applying the transversality condition (5.65) and
(5.70) then gives the result.
Combining Theorems 5.6 and 5.8 it is clear that, when there is no bunching
at the lowest income, the tax function cannot be progressive throughout since
it must begin with a zero rate and end with a zero rate. When bunching does
occur at the lowest income, the outcome is di¤erent. This is summarised in
Theorem 5.9.

Theorem 27 (Ebert) If there is bunching at the lowest income, the marginal


rate of tax is strictly positive at the end of the bunching interval.

Proof. From (5.62) and (5.65) at s = S1 ,

¸ [1 ¡ © (S1 )] ° (S1 ) = ¹ (S1 ) u x© s + Á0 (S1 ) = 0: (5.77)


5.4. NUMERICAL RESULTS 153

With bunching at the lowest income, x (s) and z (s) are constant over some
interval. Hence over this interval

d [1 ¡ © (s)]
= ¡© x x0 ¡ © z z 0 ¡ ©s > 0; (5.78)
ds

since x0 = z 0 = 0. Therefore 1 ¡ © (s) must be positive at the end of this


interval.
The same argument can be used to prove that there is no bunching at the
highest income level.

Theorem 28 (Ebert) There is no bunching at the highest income level.

Proof. Theorem 5.8 has already shown that the marginal tax rate on the
highest income is zero. Over the interval of bunching, 1 ¡ © (s) must increase as
s decreases and therefore becomes negative for some s < S2 . This contradicts
Theorem 5.6.

5.3.4 Summary
The major theoretical results for the analysis of the optimal nonlinear tax have
now been derived. These show that the optimal marginal rate of taxation must
lie between zero and one. At the highest and lowest abilities, the tax rate
must be zero. The latter …nding shows that the optimal tax function cannot be
progressive; a result that runs counter to observed income tax functions. It may
also be optimal to force some households to choose to undertake no labour. If
this is the case, it is the lowest ability households that will not work. Finally,
pre-tax income and consumption must both be increasing functions of ability.
To obtain further details of the structure of optimal taxes, it is necessary to
consider numerical analyses.

5.4 Numerical results


The standard analysis of optimal income taxation has been introduced above
and a number of results have been derived that provide some characterisation of
the shape of the tax schedule. It has been seen that the marginal rate is between
0 and 1 but as yet no idea has been developed, except for the endpoints, of
how close it should be to either. Similarly, although equity considerations are
expected to raise the marginal rate, this has not been demonstrated formally nor
has consideration been given to how e¢ciency criteria, particularly the e¤ect
of taxation upon labour supply, a¤ects the choice of tax schedule. Due to the
analytical complexity of the nonlinear model, these questions are best addressed
via numerical analysis.
154 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

5.4.1 Simulations
To generate numerical results, Mirrlees (1971) assumed that the social welfare
function took the form
R 1 1 ¡ºU
e ° (s) ds; º > 0;
W = 0R1 º (5.79)
0
U ° (s) ds; º = 0:

The form of (5.79) permits parametric variations of the form of the social welfare
function by changes in º . Higher values of º represent greater concern for equity,
with º = 0 representing the utilitarian case. The individual utility function was
assumed to be Cobb-Douglas

U = log x + log [1 ¡ `] ; (5.80)

and the skill distribution log-normal


" #
2
1 [log (s + 1)]
° (s) = exp ¡ ; (5.81)
s 2

with a standard deviation, ¾, of 0.39. This value of the standard deviation was
derived from data on the distribution of income given in Lydall (1968). There is
thus an implicit assumption that the skill distribution can be inferred directly
form an observed income distribution. Furthermore, this assumption implies
that the skill distribution is unbounded. A selection of the numerical results of
Mirrlees (1971) are given in Table 5.1.

Income Consumption Average Tax (%) Marginal Tax (%)


(a) zG = 0:013 º=0
0 0.03 - 23
0.055 0.07 -34 26
0.10 0.10 -5 24
0.20 0.18 9 21
0.30 0.26 13 19
0.40 0.34 14 18
0.50 0.43 15 16

(b) z G = 0:003 º=1


0 0.05 - 30
0.05 0.08 -66 34
0.10 0.12 -34 32
0.20 0.19 7 28
0.30 0.26 13 25
0.40 0.34 16 22
0.50 0.41 17 20
Table 5.1: Optimal tax schedule
5.4. NUMERICAL RESULTS 155

The most important feature of the results in Tables 5.1a and b are the
generally low marginal rates of tax, with the maximal rate being only 34%.
There is also limited deviation in these rates. Relating the results to Theorem
5.6, the marginal rates do become lower at high incomes but do not reach zero
because the skill distribution is unbounded. The average rate of tax is negative
for low incomes in both Tables 5.1a and b so that low income consumers are
receiving an income supplement from the government.
The set of results reported in Table 5.2, also from Mirrlees (1971), show the
e¤ecting of increasing the dispersion of skills. This raises the marginal tax rates
but these remain fairly constant across the income range. This occurs despite
the greater inequality of skills leads to a greater possible role for redistribution
via the income tax. Further results on the e¤ect of varying the dispersion of
skills are given in Kanbur and Tuomala (1994). These support the …nding that
an increased dispersion of skills raises the marginal tax rate at each income
level but show that if also has the e¤ect of moving the maximum tax rate up
the income range, so that the marginal tax rate is increasing over the majority
of households.

Income Consumption Average Tax (%) Marginal Tax (%)


0 0.10 - 50
0.10 0.15 -50 58
0.25 0.20 20 60
0.50 0.30 40 59
1.00 0.52 48 57
1.50 0.73 51 54
2.00 0.97 51 52
3.00 1.47 51 49
Table 5.2: Optimal tax schedule: increased dispersion of skills (z G = 0:013,
n = 1, ¾ = 1)

The nature of the tax rate at the upper end of the income scale and the
implications of the zero-endpoint result for nearby incomes has been investigated
by Tuomala (1990). Tuomala’s numerical results show that the marginal tax
rate may be far from zero on incomes close to the maximum. The zero-endpoint
result is therefore only a local conclusion and does not necessarily imply the
incomes near the maximum must also be subject to low marginal tax rates.
Although the numerical simulations of Mirrlees (1971) made a number of
variations in speci…cation, these were very restricted in comparison to the po-
tential range of formulations. In attempting to progress further, Atkinson (1972)
considered the e¤ect of changing the social welfare function to the extreme maxi-
min form
W = minfUg; (5.82)
which places the greatest possible emphasis on equity considerations. The rea-
soning for doing this follows from contrasting Tables 1a and b. From these it
can be seen that increased concern for equity, º going from 0 to 1, increased
the optimal marginal tax rates. The natural question would be: could strong
156 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

equity considerations lead to high marginal rates? The interest in this issue
can be appreciated by recalling that the top British tax rate in the 1970’s was
approximately 70% - 98%, dependent on the precise source of income. From
this perspective the rates derived by Mirrlees were relatively low.
The e¤ect of changing to a maxi-min social welfare function can be seen from
considering Table 5.3 which is based on Atkinson and Stiglitz (1980). From the
table it is possible to conclude that the maxi-min criterion leads to generally
higher rates. However they are again highest at low incomes and then decline.
In addition, they remain relatively low.

Utilitarian Maxi-min
Level of s Average rate Marginal rate Average Rate Marginal Rate
Median 6 21 10 53
Top decile 14 20 28 34
Top percentile 16 17 28 26
Table 5.3: Contrast of utilitarian and maxi-min

5.4.2 Choice of speci…cation


The numerical results discussed above have concentrated upon examples with
the same log-normal distribution of skill and Cobb-Douglas individual utility
function. Following the analysis of Stern (1976), which is devoted to considering
whether these assumptions are appropriate and the consequences of modifying
them, each of these assumptions is now discussed in turn.

Estimation of skill distribution


The …rst point to consider is the determination of the skill distribution. It is
natural to assume that this cannot be directly observed and must be inferred in
some way from observable data. The distribution employed by Mirrlees (1971)
was taken directly from an analysis of income data and therefore embodies the
assumption that skill and income have the same distribution. The question that
must be asked, considering the importance of the distribution demonstrated in
Table 5.3, is whether this assumption is justi…ed.
Stern (1976) makes the point that it is generally not possible to pass from
knowledge of the observed income distribution to knowledge of the underlying
skill distribution unless there is full knowledge of the utility function and the tax
function. This point is illustrated by the utility function U (x; `) = 1 ¡` if x ¸ x,
= ¡1 otherwise. If is unobserved, all that will be observed is that all consumers
achieve equal incomes and have consumption level x. However, consumers of
high ability use little labour time to obtain this consumption level but low
ability consumers require a considerable amount. From this example, it can be
seen that the income distribution need not directly re‡ect the skill distribution.
Whether the income distribution accurately re‡ects skills is dependent upon the
other components of the economy and is not an exogenous property.
5.4. NUMERICAL RESULTS 157

Labour supply
The choice of optimal income tax is concerned with maximising social welfare
by reaching an e¢cient trade-o¤ of equity against e¢ciency. The factor that is
most intimately linked with the e¢ciency cost of taxation is the wage elasticity of
labour supply or, alternatively, whether labour supply will be greatly a¤ected by
high marginal rates of taxation. This subsection brie‡y reviews some evidence
on the e¤ect of taxation on labour supply and then considers the implications
of alternative formulations of the labour supply function.
Empirical evidence on the e¤ect of income taxes can be found in both the
results of surveys and of econometric estimates of labour supply functions. Break
(1957) conducted a survey of the disincentive e¤ect of high tax rates upon
solicitors and accountants in the UK, 63% of whom where subject to marginal
tax rates above 50%. The survey concluded that as many respondents were
working harder because of the tax rates as were working less hard. A similar
conclusion was obtained by Brown and Levin (1974) in a survey of the e¤ect
of income taxation on the level of overtime worked by a sample of weekly paid
workers; little net e¤ect of taxation on working hours was found.
Econometric evidence has also produced comparable results. Burtless and
Hausman (1978) employ data from the Gary Negative Income Tax experiment
to estimate a labour supply function and …nd a wage elasticity of labour supply
of 0. These results, which relate primarily to the labour supply of males, suggest
that there are grounds for believing the disincentive e¤ect of income taxes for
males to not be great. In contrast, the elasticity of labour supply from married
females may be much higher and for this group the participation e¤ect is also
relevant. This suggests that the analysis should really treat the two groups
separately. Further discussion of the relation of labour supply to taxation is
given in Hausman (1985) and the evidence for the U.K. on female supply is
surveyed in Blundell (1992).
With respect to the response of labour supply to taxation, the speci…cation
adopted for the simulations generating Tables 5.1 - 5.3 was very restrictive due
to its imposed unit elasticity of substitution between leisure and consumption.
As will now be shown, alternative formulations can produce somewhat di¤erent
results.
First, consider the Cobb-Douglas utility as used by Mirrlees (1971) and
Atkinson (1972). The elasticity of substitution, ", between leisure, `, and con-
sumption, x, is de…ned as
@U
@x £ 1¡` ¤
@U
@ [1¡`] @ x
"= 1¡`
¸: (5.83)
@U
x @ @x
@U
@[1¡`]

This elasticity is a unit-free measure of the rate at which consumption can


be exchanged for leisure while keeping utility constant. For the Cobb-Douglas
function (5.80), " = 1. Hence the simulations of Atkinson (1972) and Mirrlees
(1971) were based on a constant elasticity of substitution equal to 1. Given the
158 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

restrictiveness of this formulation, it is natural to question its consequences and


whether it is justi…ed by data on labour supply.
Stern (1976) investigated the more general form of preferences described by
the constant elasticity of substitution (C.E.S.) utility function
h i¡ ¹1
U = ® [L ¡ `]¡ ¹ + [1 ¡ ®] x ¡¹ ; (5.84)

where L is full leisure time available. L was …xed at unity in (5.80). For (5.84)
the elasticity of substitution is given by
1
"= : (5.85)
¹+1
To understand the consequences that di¤erent values of " may have, con-
sider a consumer maximising the utility function (5.84) subject to the budget
constraint
x = A + s`; (5.86)
where s is the net wage and A is the level of lump-sum grant, which may be
negative. The …rst-order condition for utility maximisation is
¸¹+1
L¡` ®
= ; (5.87)
A + s` [1 ¡ ®] `

which gives an implicit expression for `. From di¤erentiating (5.87) it can be


found that
d` [A ¡ ¹s`] [L ¡ `]
= : (5.88)
ds s [¹ + 1] [A + s`]
Now from (5.85) it follows that ¹ = 1" ¡1 so, for ¹ positive, it is possible that A¡
d`
¹s`, and hence ds , may become negative and thus the labour supply curve bends
backwards. The importance of a backward bending labour supply function is
that tax increases at high incomes will actually increase labour supply; hence
the equity and e¢ciency factors are not directly competing. For low values of "
it is therefore to be expected that the optimal marginal rate of tax will be higher.
This possibility could not arise in the speci…cation based on the Cobb-Douglas
utility function model with ¹ = 0.
Applying the model based on (5.84) to the data of Ashenfelter and Heckman
(1973) from an analysis of 3,203 American males, Stern (1976) calculated the
elasticity of substitution and found that " = 0:408. This value of " is substan-
tially less than that used by Mirrlees in the numerical simulations.
Adopting (5.84) as the individual utility function and a social welfare func-
tion of the form Z
1 1 º
W = [U (x; `)] ° (s) ds; (5.89)
º 0
Stern (1976) presented estimates of the optimal linear income tax. Retaining
the log-normal distribution of ability with the standard deviation, the general
pattern of results is summarised by the Figure 5.10.
5.5. EXTENSIONS AND OMISSIONS 159

Figure 5.10: Optimal Tax Rate and Equity

From Figure 5.10 it can be seen that the Mirrlees speci…cation " = 1, º = 1
gives the lowest possible rates of taxation and that tax rates increase to 100% as
" tends to zero; a proof that this always occurs is given by Stern (1976). What
is important to note is that the tax rates are high for " = 0:0408 and º = ¡1.
Therefore high tax rates can be justi…ed without necessarily appealing to the
maxi-min criterion.

5.5 Extensions and omissions


The basic Mirrlees economy described above has been extended in a number of
directions and two of these are now considered. The …rst extension intro duces a
second form of labour service which allows the income tax to have indirect distri-
butional e¤ects via the changes in relative wages. Following this, the nonlinear
income tax is combined with linear taxes upon commodities and conditions are
found for which commodity taxes are unnecessary. The section is completed by
noting some relevant issues that are not addressed in the formal analysis.

Two forms of labour


The relevance of introducing a second form of labour service is that the economy
can be designed so that the population is partitioned with those of low skill
supplying a form of labour with a low wage and those of high skill supplying
labour with a higher return. To obtain such a partition it is only necessary to
assume that there are two distinct levels of skill: high and low. The new factor
introduced by the existence of two wage levels is that the income tax can alter
the relative values of these wages and, in doing so, alters the distribution of
income between the two skill groups. This second route for redistribution will
clearly be important in the determination of the optimal income tax.
In the …rst analysis of a model of this form Feldstein (1973) employed numer-
ical techniques to investigate the e¤ect of the relative wage variation upon the
value of the optimal linear income tax. With the two forms of labour entering
160 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

into a Cobb-Douglas production function, Feldstein concluded that there was


little di¤erence between the optimal tax with …xed wages and that with variable
wages.
The conclusion of Feldstein was reconsidered in Allen (1982) employing an
analytical, rather than a numerical, approach. The signi…cant extension made
by Allen was to use a more general form of production technology. This demon-
strated that in the Cobb-Douglas case the redistribution via the income tax
was reinforced by the adjustment of relative wages thus explaining the Feldstein
(1973) results. However, if the elasticity of substitution between the two forms
of labour is low and the labour service earning the higher wage has a negative
supply elasticity, then the relative wage e¤ect operates in the opposite direction
of the income tax e¤ect and may outweigh it. When the indirect e¤ect does out-
weigh the direct e¤ect, the optimal policy becomes a combination of lump-sum
tax and a negative marginal rate of income tax.
These results indicate that the analysis of income taxation becomes rather
more di¢cult and can generate surprising conclusions when more than one form
of labour service is introduced into the model. This assumption of the standard
economy may therefore be more restrictive than it at …rst appears.

5.5.1 Income and commodity taxes


The analysis of a combined tax system of linear commodity taxes and a nonlinear
income tax has been studied in a number of papers, most notably Atkinson and
Stiglitz (1976), Mirrlees (1976) and Revesz (1986). The major results of this
line of study are now brie‡y described.
It is assumed that there are n goods available with labour denoted as good
1 and the wage rate is w. As a normalisation rule the linear tax on good n is
set at zero. With these conventions, the budget constraint facing a consumer of
ability s takes the form
n
X
qi xi = swx 1 ¡ T (swx 1 ) : (5.90)
i=2

To simplify the derivation, the production technology is taken to be linear so


that production possibilities are constrained by the relation
n Z
X 1 Z 1
xi (s) ° (s) ds swx 1 (s) ° (s) ds ¡ zG : (5.91)
i= 2 0 0

With the linear technology, it is possible to take the producer price of each good
2; :::; n to be 1.
The optimal taxes can be found by treating U (s) as the state variable and
x i(s), i = 1; ::; n ¡ 1 as the control variables, with x n (s) determined from the
identity U(s) = U (x 1 (s); :::; x n (s)). The …rst-order condition for self-selection is
derived from (5.14) by using the fact that us = ¡ Us`2z = ¡ Us` ` or, in the present
5.5. EXTENSIONS AND OMISSIONS 161

U x
notation, u s = ¡ x1s 1 . Employing the …rst-order approach, the Hamiltonian
for the maximisation can be written using (5.91) as
" " n
##
X Ux x 1
H = U + ¸ swx 1 ¡ x i ° (s) ¡ ¹ 1 : (5.92)
i=2
s

For the choice of xk (s), k = 2; :::; n ¡ 1, using the fact that

@xn Ux
= ¡ k; (5.93)
@xk Ux n

the necessary condition for optimality is


¸ ¸
Ux k x1 Ux k
¡¸ 1 ¡ ° ¡¹ Ux 1 x k ¡ Ux 1 x n = 0; k = 2; :::; n: (5.94)
Ux n s Ux n

From the necessary conditions for household utility maximisation

U xk 1 + tk
= : (5.95)
Ux n 1

Substituting (5.95) into (5.94), the optimality condition (5.94) can be written
after some rearrangement as
2 h i3
Ux k
¹x 1 Uxk 4 d log Uxn
tk = 5 ; k = 2; :::; n ¡ 1: (5.96)
¸°s dx 1

h Ux
i
d log k
Uxn
The result in (5.96) reveals two facts. Firstly, if dx1 = 0, for all k =
2; :::; n¡1, which holds if the utility function is weakly separable between labour
and all other commodities, then tk = 0 for all k = 2; ::; n ¡ 1. This is the ma jor
result of Atkinson and Stiglitz (1976). In these circumstance the commodity
taxes are unnecessary and the income tax is su¢cient for achieving welfare aims.
This result derives from the tax system attempting to tax the innate ability of
the households but, when the separability holds, there is insu¢cient correlation
between consumption choice and ability for commodity taxation to have any
e¤ect. The second consequence of (5.96) is, holding all other variables constant,
that the tax rate on a good should be positively related to the rate of change
of the marginal rate of substitution between that good and labour as labour
supply increases. Therefore, those goods relatively preferred by the consumers
supplying most labour should be taxed more. Using a more general framework,
Mirrlees (1976) strengthens this conclusion to show that the commodity tax
rates should be highest on those goods for which the high ability households
have the relatively strongest preference.
An alternative perspective upon the combination of income and commodity
taxes has been provided by Christiansen (1984). Christiansen takes as the start-
ing point a situation in which the income tax has been optimised but with no
162 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION

commodity taxes and then determines the welfare e¤ect of introducing commod-
ity taxes whilst holding revenue constant. The analysis provides the conclusion
that goods for which demand increases if more leisure is obtained, but with
no change in income, should have positive commodity taxes introduced. If no
change in demand follows from the change in leisure, the tax should be zero and
it should be negative if demand falls.
The results noted have determined some relations between income and com-
modity taxes. However, the number of alternative perspectives from which the
model can be approached and the richness of the model prevent any simple and
summary statement being given.

5.5.2 Omissions
The economy that has been studied was, by necessity, highly stylised. Although
this brings undoubted analytical bene…ts, it does eliminate from consideration
many issues that are of practical interest. Some of these are now brie‡y dis-
cussed.
The economy involved only a single form of labour service but with di¤er-
ences in the ability of households to perform this service. In reality, there are
many di¤erent forms of labour in an economy which di¤er in the skills they re-
quire and in the working conditions they impose. The actual monetary payment
for the supply of labour may only be part of the package of remuneration, and
some of the return (or cost) may be entirely psychic in nature. A income tax
policy designed to maximise welfare would need to take account of the entire
package of characteristics that constitutes labour supply. The labour supply
decision also involves more than simply the determination of the number of
hours to work. As occupations di¤er in their characteristics, the choice between
occupations is important and this choice will be a¤ected by income taxation.
For instance, an increase in taxation will be detrimental to occupations where
the return is predominantly monetary. There are also intertemporal aspects to
the labour supply decision such as the timing of entry to the labour force and
the timing of retirement. As an income tax will introduce a distortion into such
decisions, this increases the potential e¢ciency loss. Some of these issues are
addressed in Christiansen (1988).
The preferences of the households have been taken as identical. This need
not be the case and di¤erences in preferences may arise as in Chapter 4. Fur-
thermore, the household has been viewed as supplying an homogeneous form
of labour but in practice the total labour supply is often the sum of male and
female components. The nature of these is often very di¤erent and empirical
evidence suggests that they have markedly di¤erent responses to taxation. This
observation implies that the analysis should be based upon greater detail of the
structure of households. Furthermore, it also raises issues concerning the tax
treatment of the individuals that constitute the household such as whether they
have the option or not of being tax as separate individuals or whether a joint
household return is compulsory.
5.6. SUMMARY 163

5.6 Summary
This chapter has reviewed the formal analysis of the optimal income tax prob-
lem. The problem has been treated as one of choosing the income tax function to
balance equity and e¢ciency considerations in an economy characterised by in-
equality in the distribution of income. The standard economy of Mirrlees (1971)
has been described and it has been noted that this is the simplest for which the
income tax problem has any real content. The ma jor theoretical results have
been derived and, although they do not provide a precise characterisation of the
optimal tax schedule, they do suggest its most important properties, some of
which are in con‡ict with the structure of observed tax schedules.
Numerical analyses have been used to further investigate the nature of the
tax schedule and its dependence upon the assumed structure of the problem.
Results from some of the most noteworthy of these analyses have been given
above. In particular they demonstrate that the marginal rates of tax may be
rather low but do increase with concern for equity. However, the conclusions
are sensitive to the assumptions invoked by the model. The implications of the
modi…cation of some of these assumptions was considered.
The chapter was concluded by a consideration of two extensions. The intro-
duction of a second form of labour service could lead to a marked change in the
form of the optimal tax function if the indirect e¤ect of taxation upon relative
wages outweighed the direct e¤ect. The optimal combination of income and
commodity taxes was then considered and it was shown that weak separability
of leisure would make commodity taxes redundant.
The methods of analysis can be adapted to treat other forms of nonlinear
taxation. It needs only a minor revision to turn the income tax into an expen-
diture tax with a suitable re-interpretation of the skill variable as a preference
parameter. Many of the theorems derived then apply directly to this new set-
ting. In fact, several of the studies cited, such as Mirrlees (1976) and Seade
(1977) are concerned with general nonlinear taxes rather than income tax per
se.
164 CHAPTER 5. INCOME TAXATION
Chapter 6

Policy Reform

6.1 Introduction
The previous two chapters have considered the determination of optimal com-
modity and income taxes. In practice, if the derived tax rules were to be imple-
mented it would be likely that a ma jor upheaval of the …scal structure would be
required. To be willing to enact such a major change would require the policy
maker to have considerable faith in the accuracy of the policy advice. Taking
this into account, many countries have opted in favour of gradual policy reforms
which involve slowly phasing in some taxes and removing others. The design of
such reforms will be the subject of this chapter.
The theoretical literature on policy reform has been concerned with char-
acterising when there exist feasible reforms that satisfy the policy maker’s ob-
jectives and with determining the optimal direction of reform. For the purpose
of formal analysis, reforms are always interpreted as di¤erential changes in the
vector of policy instruments. This is the limiting interpretation of the reforms
being small.
This chapter will review the standard analysis that has been developed for
determining the existence of worthwhile reforms in the vector of consumer prices.
The inverse optimum problem, which calculates the welfare weights of house-
holds implied by a given set of policy parameters, will be related to this analysis
and the concept of marginal social cost will be discussed. Several applications of
these methods, including empirical investigations, will be described. In consid-
ering the practical implications of these results, it should be noted that admin-
istration costs are not considered. If such costs are signi…cant they will reduce
the potential attractiveness of a series of small reforms.

6.2 The reform problem


The standard procedure is to take as given some initial vector of consumer
prices, supporting producer prices and implied tax rates. Given these values,

165
166 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

the equilibrium of the economy is calculated. It is clear that the values of the
policy variables will determine the welfare properties of the equilibrium. Small
changes in consumer prices are then considered and the question is asked: is
there a feasible change that raises welfare? This is the policy reform problem.
It is implicit in this description that as consumer prices change, producer prices
are adjusted to maintain equilibrium.
The welfare objective has typically been either the strict Pareto principle
under which an acceptable reform must raise all households’ welfare or a so-
cial welfare function in which case the policy reform must raise social welfare.
Both of these welfare criteria are considered below. An alternative ob jective,
a unanimous Wicksellian criteria, is studied in Weymark (1981). Feasibility is
de…ned in terms of the satisfaction of an aggregate production constraint or
alternatively, where permissible, a government revenue constraint. When the
production constraint is employed, a feasible change must result in a demand
vector that is in the production set. With the revenue constraint, a given level
of revenue must be collected before and after the change. Further discussion of
the structure of the reform problem can be found in Feldstein (1976a).

6.2.1 Productive feasibility


The analysis is set within a competitive economy that has H households and
n goods. The government policy variables are the n consumer prices denoted
by the vector qT = (q1 ; :::; qn ), with the superscript T denoting the transpose.
All vectors are written as columns and, for vectors, the notation x > y implies
x i > yi all i, x ¸ y implies x i = yi all i and x i > yi some i, and x = y implies
x i ¸ y i all i. Producer prices of the n goods are written pT = (p 1 ; :::; pn ).
To guarantee a separation between the production and consumption sectors, a
100% pro…ts tax is assumed as discussed in 4.6.
Formally, the reform problem is concerned with di¤erential changes in the
policy parameters from an initial position with policy vector qT = (q1 ; :::; qn ) to
a new position with policy q T + dqT = (q1 + dq1 ; :::; qn + dqn ). The direction of
change dq is restricted to be normal to q; hence qT dq = 0. The set of normals
to q is denoted T (q) and, until indicated otherwise, all consumer price changes
dq are assumed to belong to T (q). Since aggregate demand is homogeneous
of degree zero in consumer prices, this is simply a normalisation and does not
impose any real restriction on the set of reforms. Figure 6.1 illustrates this
procedure for a two-good economy. Given initial price vector q, T (q) is a line
through the origin orthogonal to q. The change in policy dq 2 T (q) is shown to
move the policy vector to q + dq. The homogeneity of aggregate demand implies
that it is only the direction of the price vector that is relevant, not its length.
It can be seen in Figure 6.1 that by moving along T (q), can be made to point
in any direction in the positive orthant.

Figure 6.1: The set of policy changes


The …rst step is to identify when a potential reform is productively feasible.
For the present, feasibility will be de…ned by satisfaction of an aggregate pro-
6.2. THE REFORM PROBLEM 167

Figure 6.1:

duction constraint. The production constraint is given in implicit form by the


strictly quasi-convex and di¤erentiable function

F (X (q)) 0; (6.1)

where
H
X
X (q) = x h (q) ; (6.2)
h =1

is the aggregate demand function. The assumption of strict quasi-convexity


ensures that at each point on the boundary of the production set there is a
unique (up to a scalar multiple) price vector that will make that point the pro…t-
maximising choice. Di¤erentiability then implies, as discussed in connection
with production e¢ciency in chapter 4 section 8, that this price vector will be
proportional to the gradient vector, rF , of F (¢). This assumption is relaxed
in Weymark (1979b) who considers non-di¤erentiable production constraints.
Given producer prices p, the supply vector is denoted by Y (p). An equilibrium
is termed tight if X (q) = Y (p) and non-tight if X (q) Y (p).
Feasibility of the policy reform requires that after the change in policy the
resulting demand vector remains within the aggregate production set. It is
assumed that the economy is initially on the boundary of the production set so
the policy change must satisfy

rF T Xq dq 0; (6.3)

where 2 3
@ X1 @ X1
@ q1 ¢ @q n
Xq = 4 ¢ ¢ ¢ 5; (6.4)
@X n @X n
@ q1
¢ @q n
168 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Figure 6.2:

is the Jacobian of the aggregate demand function. Employing the fact that
producer prices are proportional to rF , the feasibility constraint can be written
in the form
pT Xq dq 0: (6.5)
Hence, as noted by Guesnerie (1977), feasible reforms are those which cause a
change in aggregate demand that has a non-positive value at initial producer
prices. To simplify the expressions below, the expression ¡p T Xq will be denoted
rZ T .
After a change in the consumer price vector, producer prices will also adjust
in order to maintain equilibrium and it is assumed that such adjustment is
in a direction that is normal to p. The following result of Guesnerie (1977)
proves that, when the boundary of the production set is su¢ciently smooth,
the change in demand due to a di¤erential change in the consumer price vector
can be met by a supply change brought about by a di¤erential modi…cation of
producer prices. The proof is based on the observation that when the boundary
of the production set is smooth, its gradient changes continuously. In turn,
the normal to the production set changes continuously around its boundary.
This implies that the producer price vectors that support two nearby points,
which are proportional to the normals at those points, will be similar. Figure
6.2a shows a smooth production set for which a small change in demand can
be met by a di¤erential change in the producer price vector. In Figure 6.2b
the production set has a kink at y ¤ = (y ¤1 ; y ¤2 ) and to move production from
ye = (y ¤1 + "; y2¤ ¡ ") to yb = (y1¤ ¡ "; y ¤2 + ") requires a discrete change in producer
prices.

(a) Continuous change in normal (b) Discontinuity


Figure 6.2: Smooth and non-smooth production sets

As supply is homogeneous of degree 1 in producer prices, the Jacobian of the


supply function cannot have rank n. Smoothness of the production set therefore
6.2. THE REFORM PROBLEM 169

manifests itself in the supply function having rank n ¡ 1. Any lower rank indi-
cates that there are ‡at sections or ridges in the production set, either of which
will remove the property that the normal to the production set changes continu-
ously around the boundary of the production set. Following these preliminaries,
the formal statement of the lemma can now be given.

Lemma 29 (Guesnerie) If the Jacobian of the aggregate supply function has


rank n ¡ 1 then for any change in consumer prices such that rF T Xq dq 0,
there is at least one direction of change, dp, of producer prices such that (dq; dp)
is equilibrium preserving. If rF T Xq dq = 0 the change dp is unique and (dq; dp)
is tight equilibrium preserving.

Proof. Since aggregate supply is homogeneous of degree 0 in p, Y p p = 0 and


it follows from the symmetry of Y p , where Y p is the Jacobian of© aggregate supply,
ª
that Yp p = 0 , p T Yp = 0T . Now de…ne the set V by V = u : pT u = 0 . As
p T Yp u = 0, it follows that Yp u 2 V . Hence the linear mapping, Yp , maps from
V to V . To see that the linear mapping is also one-to-one, assume that it is
1 2 1 2 ¤
not so that
£ 1 there ¤ exist u 2 V and u 2 V such that Yp u = Y p u = u . From
this, Yp u ¡ u = 0. As the Jacobian of Y p is of dimension n ¡ 1, the set
2

W = fw : Y p w =£ 0g is of¤dimension 1 and, £ since¤Y p p = 0, if w 2 W , w = ¸p for


some ¸. Hence u1 ¡ u 2 = ¸p and pT u1 ¡ u 2 = ¸pT p 6= 0. However, as u 1
£ ¤
and u2 2 V , p T u 1 = p T u 2 = 0 ) pT u 1 ¡ u 2 = 0. This contradiction shows
the mapping must be one-to-one and onto. It then follows that on V , Y p has
an inverse Y p¡1 . Hence given a price change dp, Y p¡1 dp, where dY is a vector of
supply changes normal to dp: dp T dY = 0. Thus any vector of supply changes
normal to p can be obtained by a change in producer prices which is also normal
to p.
Now let dq be such that rF T Xq dq = 0. It follows that pT Xq dq ´ pT dX = 0.
Hence dx 2 V and there exists p = Y q¡1 dX. Then dY = Yp dp = Y p Y p¡1 dX =
dX; p is also unique since dX 2 V . Therefore, if the consumer price change leads
to a demand change, dX, on the boundary of the production set a producer price
change can be found that matches the change in demand with an equal change,
dY , in supply and is tight equilibrium preserving.
If dq satis…es rF T Xq dq < 0, then p T Xq dq ´ p T dX < 0 and the argument
can be repeated with U = dX + ±; ± > 0 and pT U = 0 to show dY = dU > dX
so the change preserves equilibrium but not tight equilibrium.
The value of Lemma 6.1 is that it allows the focus to be placed upon con-
sumer prices in the knowledge that any change satisfying (6.3) can be accom-
modated by adjustment of producer prices.

6.2.2 Improving reforms


Let V h (q1; :::; qn ) denote the indirect utility function of the hth household. The
level of social welfare is assumed to be determined by a Bergson-Samuelson
social welfare function
¡ ¢
W = W V 1 (q1 ; :::; qn ) ; :::; V H (q1 ; :::; qn ) : (6.6)
170 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Using (6.6), the e¤ect of the change in q upon welfare is given by

dW = rW T dq; (6.7)

where à !
H
X H
X
T @W @V h @W @V h
rW = ; :::; : (6.8)
@V h @q1 @V h @qn
h=1 h=1

The reform problem, in terms of …nding a reform that raises social welfare,
can now be introduced.
Welfare-Improving Reform (WI)
Does there exist a vector dq of reforms such that
(i) rW T dq > 0,
and
(ii) rZ T dq ¸ 0?
Condition (i) requires the reform to raise welfare and (ii) that it is produc-
tively feasible.
To formulate the Pareto-improving reform problem, de…ne the vectors
µ ¶
hT @V h @V h
rV = ; :::; ; h = 1; :::; H: (6.9)
@q1 @qn

It is assumed that rV h 6= 0 for all h. From these vectors the matrix P is formed
by using the vector rV hT as the hth row of P . This construction leads to the
following matrix 2 3
rV 1T
P =4 ¢ 5: (6.10)
rV H T

Using P , the strict Pareto-improving reform problem can be stated formally.


Strict Pareto-Improving Reform (PI)
Does there exist a vector dq of reforms such that
(i) P dq > 0,
and
(ii) rZ T dq ¸ 0?
Given the de…nition in (6.9), condition (i) is equivalent to rV hT dq > 0 for
all h, so that the reform must raise the welfare of all the households. The motive
for employing the strict Pareto reform, as opposed to a weak version where the
reform must bene…t at least one household while not harming any other, is that
it leads to a simpler statement of later results.
WI and PI represent the two standard policy reform problems and it should
be noted that both take the form of a system of linear inequalities. This has
important implications for the analysis of reforms. It is now possible to proceed
to a characterisation of when a solution, in terms of a non-zero vector that satis-
…es the relevant inequalities, exists to the problems and what can be concluded
when such a vector does not.
6.3. CHARACTERISING POSSIBILITIES 171

6.3 Characterising possibilities


The …rst approach to characterisation is to apply a Theorem of the Alternative.
This general class of theorems states that either a set of linear inequalities has
a solution or that there is a linear relationship between the component parts
of the inequalities. Applied to the reform problems, this implies that either
there is a solution to the reform problem or else there exists a set of weights
such that the initial point is optimal with respect to the ob jective function
determined by these weights. This section introduces the necessary Theorems
of the Alternative and then discusses the interpretation of these for the two
reform problems.

6.3.1 Solution via Theorems of the Alternative


The solution of the reform problem WI can be characterised by appeal to the
Tucker Theorem of the Alternative. This, and other similar theorems, are de-
scribed in detail in Mangasarian (1969).
Theorem 30 (Tucker) Given a matrix A and a vector B, with the number of
columns of A equal to the dimension of B, exactly one of the fol lowing holds
(a) there exists a vector x such that Ax ¸ 0, Bx = 0,
(b) there exist vectors y1 and y2 with AT y 1 + B T y 2 = 0, y1 > 0; y2 ¸ 0.
Proof. See Mangasarian (1969).
For WI, the matrices A and B represent rW T and rZ T respectively, both
are 1 by n. Condition (a) describes the case in which a feasible reform exists.
Since A ´ rW T , Ax is a scalar and the vector inequality Ax ¸ 0 implies that
this scalar is strictly positive. If no reform exists, so (a) cannot be satis…ed,
the theorem asserts the existence of a pair of vectors such that (b) is satis…ed.
The vectors y1 and y2 in (b) can be interpreted as the shadow variables in
the maximisation of welfare subject to the production constraint since, if no
reform exists, the initial point must be optimal. The maximisation problem
that generates (b) can be clearly seen in Theorem 1D9 in Takayama (1984) and
the solution leads to the optimal tax rules of Chapter 4. Employing (6.5) and
(6.8), the optimality condition (b) can be written as
H
X Xn
@W @V h @Xi
y1 ¡ y2 pi = 0; k = 1; :::; n: (6.11)
@V h @qk i=1
@qk
h=1

This is simply P
an alternative representation of (4.35) since the aggregate
Pn bud-
n @X i
get constraint q X
i= 1 i i and the relation q i = p i + t i imply ¡ i=1 i @q k =
p
Pn @X i
Xi +. i=1 ti @qk
The solution of PI requires the use of Motzkin’s Theorem of the Alternative.
Theorem 31 (Motzkin) For two matrices A and B with the same number of
columns, exactly one of the following holds
(a) there exists a vector x such that Ax > 0, Bx = 0, with A 6= 0,
(b) there exist vectors y1 and y2 with AT y 1 + B T y 2 = 0, y1 ¸ 0, y 2 ¸ 0.
172 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Proof. See Mangasarian (1969).


In terms of the reform problem PI, A represents the matrix P and is therefore
H by n and B is again rZ T which is 1 by n. If there is no solution then (b)
applies and the H-vector y1 =y 2 de…nes the implicit welfare weights attached
to the households if the initial state is optimal. This point is returned to in
the discussion of the inverse optimum problem below. Substituting into (b) of
Theorem 6.2,
H
X n
X @Xi
@V h
y 1h ¡ y2 pi = 0; k = 1; :::; n; (6.12)
@qk @qk
h= 1 i=1

@Vh
or, since @ qk = ¡®h x hk and ® h > 0,

H
X n
X @Xi
¸ h xhk + y2 pi = 0; k = 1; :::; n; (6.13)
@qk
h =1 i=1

where ¸ h = ® h y1h ¸ 0. This condition provides a characterisation of the Pareto


optimal allocation for the chosen weights upon the households.
In summary, application of a Theorem of the Alternative to the welfare-
improving and Pareto-improving reform problems demonstrates that either the
initial position is an optimum or else an improving reform can be found. When
a reform cannot be found, part (b) of the theorem provides a characterisation of
the optimum. For the welfare-improving reform problem, the characterisation
of the optimum has been discussed in Chapter 4.

6.3.2 Geometric analysis


An alternative perspective on the existence of a solution can be provided by geo-
metric considerations. The vector rZ T de…nes a half-space Q (p; q), or simply
Q, with x being in Q implying that

rZ T x ¸ 0: (6.14)

In terms
© of (6.5), theª set Q, its ©interior Int Q and
ª frontier Fr ©Q are de…ned by
ª
Q = x : p T Xq x 0 , Int Q = x : p T Xq x < 0 and Fr Q = x : p T Xq x = 0 .
Therefore any vector in Q leads to a change in consumption which has non-
positive value at initial producer prices and that satis…es the production con-
straint.

Welfare-improving reform

Taking the problem WI …rst, the vector rW T similarly de…nes a half-space S


in which all vectors, x, located in S are such that

rW T x ¸ 0: (6.15)
6.3. CHARACTERISING POSSIBILITIES 173

Figure 6.3: Welfare Improvement and Production Feasibility

That is, all the vectors in the half-space S satisfy the requirement that welfare
is not decreased by a change of prices in that direction. If there is a solution
to the© reform problemª it must be a vector that lies in the intersection of Int
S = x : rW T x > 0 and Q. A solution will therefore exist if Int S \Q is
non-empty. In fact, only if the boundaries of S and Q are coincident can there
be no solution. This discussion is summarised in Theorem 6.3.

Theorem 32 (Guesnerie/Weymark) If Int S \Q 6= Á then the solution set to


reform problem WI is non-empty. If the solution set is non-empty, a member
of the solution set, dq, will lead to a tight equilibrium if dq 2 Fr Q and to a
non-tight equilibrium if dq 2 Int Q.

Proof. Directly from the preceding discussion.


In the case that the boundaries of Q and S are coincident, so that there is
no solution, it follows that
rZ T = ¸rW T ; (6.16)
for some scalar ¸. Equation (6.16) again represents the necessary condition for
an optimum and is an alternative way of presenting (b) of the Tucker Theorem.
Figures 6.3 illustrates the vectorsrZ T and rW T and their implied half-
spaces for a three-good economy. With three goods, the set T (q) of price changes
normal to q is a plane and, to draw the diagram, this plane has been aligned
with the page. The vectors and are both shown as lying in T (q). For this follows
T h T
since
hPeach household
i is subject to the budget
h P constraint iq x = 0 and rW =
H h h H h T h
¡ h =1 ¯ x . From this q T rW = ¡ h=1 ¯ q x = 0 so rW 2 T (q).
£ ¤T T
Recalling (6.5), rZ T = ¡pT Xq so that q T rZ = ¡qT p T Xq = ¡ [Xq q] p.
The aggregate demand function is homogeneous of degree zero in q so Xq q = 0
and hence qT rZ = 0. is therefore in T (q). Hence, in a three-good economy,
rW and rZ are three-dimensional vectors that lie in the plane T (q) which is
coincident with the page.
Figure 6.4a depicts the existence of a welfare-improving reform. Here the
interior of the intersection of S and Q is non-empty. The solution set is shown
as a subset of T (q). In contrast, Figure 6.4b shows the arrangement of vectors
that result in the solution set being empty.
174 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Figure 6.4: Welfare-Improving Reform

Figure 6.5: Pareto-Improving Set

Pareto reform

The Pareto reform problem is analysed in two stages. In the …rst stage it is
determined whether there exist any policy changes that will increase the welfare
of all households. If such changes exist, the second stage is to check whether
any are productively feasible. Only when changes exist that satisfy both stages
does the Pareto reform problem have a solution.
Considering the …rst stage of the Pareto © reform problem,
ª each row of P
determines an open half-space, P h (q) = x : rV hT x > 0 , of reforms that
would bene…t the consumer whose preferences that row represents. As it is
required that the reform must increase the utility of all households, such a
reform will only exist if the intersection \H h
h=1 P (q) of these open half-spaces
h
is non-empty. A set of vectors rV , h = 1; 2; 3, that generate a non-empty
Pareto-improving set is shown in Figure 6.5a and the implied set of Pareto-
improving reforms in Figure 6.5b. Figure 6.5 is drawn by again aligning T (q)
with the plane of the page and utilising the fact that rV h 2 T (q) for all h,
which follows since rV h = ¡® hx h by Roy’s identity and q T xh = 0.
The intersection of the half-spaces corresponding to the vectors rV h will be
non-empty whenever the cone generated by taking all positive linear combina-
tions of these vectors (the rows of P ) is pointed, where a set K is a cone if k 2 K
implies ¹k 2 K for all ¹ ¸ 0 and a cone is pointed if K \ (¡K) = f0g. That
the vectors generate a pointed cone can be viewed as capturing the fact that
6.3. CHARACTERISING POSSIBILITIES 175

Figure 6.6: Cones

the preferences of the consumers are not be too dissimilar. The importance of
pointed cones in this context was …rst noted by Weymark (1979b). To illustrate
these points, the vectors in Figure 6.6a generate a pointed cone but those in
Figure 6.6b do not. n o
P
Denote by - (q) the cone generated by the rows of P , where - (q) = - : - = H h
h =1 ¸ h rV (q) ; ¸ h ¸ 0
© ª
and de…ne the positive polar cone to - (q) by £ (q) = ´ : - T ´ ¸ 0 for all - 2 - (q) .
If - (q) is pointed, £ (q) has a non-empty interior and the interior of £ (q), Int
£ (q) = \H h=1 P (q), is the set of strictly Pareto improving consumer price
h

changes. These sets are illustrated in Figure 6.5.


An alternative way of expressing this is to employ Roy’s identity to note that
rV hT dq > 0 is equivalent to x hT dq < 0. The reform is then a strict Pareto
improvement if it reduces the cost of the initial consumption choice for all house-
holds. Denotenby ¤ (q) the cone generated byothe household demand vectors,
PH
hence ¤ (q) = ¤ : ¤ = h=1 ¸h x h (q) ; ¸h ¸ 0 . Let P (q) be the negative po-
© ª
lar cone of ¤ (q), P (q) = ° : ¤T ° 0 for all ¤ 2 ¤ (q) . P (q) is the set of
price changes that reduces the cost of all households’ demands and the set of
strict Pareto improving reforms will be non-empty if P (q) has a non-empty in-
terior. This will be the case precisely when ¤ (q) is pointed. That ¤ (q) must be
pointed for the set of reforms to be non-empty again captures the idea that the
preferences, and hence demands, of the households must be similar. It should
be noted that - (q) = ¡¤ (q) ; £ (q) = P h (q) and Int P h (q) = \H h
h =1 P (q) :
These constructions are shown in Figure 6.7.
The second stage of the Pareto-improving reform problem is undertaken
by combining the Pareto-improving set with the half-space Q related to the
production constraint. It then follows that a feasible improving reform exists
if the cone generated by the rows of P , - (q), is pointed, so that the Pareto-
improving set is non-empty, and the intersection of Int £ (q) with the half-space
Q is non-empty. This reasoning is summarised as Theorem 6.4.

Theorem 33 (Guesnerie/Weymark) If - (q) is not pointed then Int £ (q) = Á


and the solution set is empty. If - (q) is pointed then Int £ (q) 6= Á and the
solution set to PI will be non-empty if Int £ (q) \ Q 6= Á. When the solution set
176 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Figure 6.7: Representation via Demands

is non-empty, a member of the set, dq, will lead to a tight equilibrium if dq 2 Fr


Q and to a non-tight equilibrium if dq 2 Int Q.

Proof. The theorem follows from the preceding discussion.


To determine whether the equilibrium leads to a tight or non-tight equilib-
rium it is su¢cient to consider the location of the vector p T Xq relative to ¤ (q),
the cone generated by the demand vectors. This is summarised in the following
theorem.

Theorem 34 (Guesnerie) Assume pT Xq 6= 0 then: (a) if p T Xq 2 ¡¤ (q) there


exist no Pareto improving changes; (b) if p T Xq 2 ¤ (q) there exist Pareto im-
C
proving changes but none is tight equilibrium preserving; (c) if p T Xq 2 (¤ (q) [ ¡¤ (q)) ,
where the superscript C denotes the complement, there exist Pareto improving
changes that are tight equilibrium preserving.

Proof. A formal proof can be found in Guesnerie (1977) but the theorem
follows directly from the de…nitions and is easily demonstrated by drawing the
implied diagrams, see Figure 6.8.
The proof of Theorem 6.5 is illustrated in Figure 6.8. In (a), it can be seen
that there is no improving reform. The improving reform in (b) leads to a non-
tight equilibrium because any point interior to ¡¤ (q) lies inside Q. Finally, in
C
(c) the shaded area is (¤ (q) [ ¡¤ (q)) and there are reforms, such as dq¤ , that
are tight equilibrium preserving.
The importance of Theorem 6.5 is that it demonstrates that a Pareto im-
proving reform may lead from an e¢cient point to a non-tight equilibrium with
the demand vector interior to the production set. Production ine¢ciency may
therefore be introduced as part of the reform process. This aspect of reform will
be considered further in Section 4.

6.3.3 Informational requirements


It is worth contrasting the information required to implement the Pareto im-
proving reform with that necessary for the welfare-improving reform and for
6.4. PRODUCTIVE EFFICIENCY AND MAXIMISING REFORMS 177

Figure 6.8: Explanation of Theorem

optimal taxation. The Pareto improving reform is based upon the gradient vec-
tors of the households but, to determine the Pareto improving set of reforms, it
is necessary only to possess knowledge of the direction of these vectors not the
length. From Roy’s identity, the direction can be determined by knowledge of
individual household demands; there is no requirement to observe the marginal
utility of income. Such information is, in principle, directly observable. To de-
termine whether a change satis…es productive feasibility it is su¢cient to know
initial producer prices and the derivatives, or elasticities, of aggregate demand.
Although this information cannot be directly observed, it can be easily inferred
from market data. The Pareto reform analysis can therefore be applied with-
out the need for specifying the social welfare function. An example of such an
application can be found in Ahmad and Stern (1984).
In contrast, the welfare-improving reform does require speci…cation of the
social welfare function and the individual marginal utilities so that the social
welfare weights can be derived. One methodology for achieving this has been
described in 4.5 but, as noted there, that involved imposing signi…cant restric-
tions upon the structure of the social marginal utilities of income. However, it is
worth emphasising that it is only the direction of the welfare vector that needs
to be known and not its length. The other informational requirements are as
for the Pareto reform.

6.4 Productive e¢ciency and maximising reforms


The analysis above has identi…ed when improving reforms exist but has left two
important questions unanswered. Firstly, if the solution set is non-empty, which
of the reforms in the solution set should be chosen? Secondly, can any insight
be obtained into when a reform will lead to an interior point of the production
set?
From the de…nitions of the previous section, it should be noted that a reform
will maintain e¢ciency if leads to a tight equilibrium. Producer prices are always
chosen to decentralise a point on the boundary of the production set so that at
178 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

a tight equilibrium, with X (q) = Y (p), consumption is also on the boundary


and e¢ciency occurs. When the equilibrium is non-tight, consumption is within
the production set and the equilibrium is ine¢cient. That ine¢cient equilibria
can arise due to the reform cannot therefore be ruled out and, in fact, appear
to be as likely as e¢cient outcomes.

6.4.1 The possibility of ine¢ciency


To proceed beyond these generalities the approach of Dixit (1979) will be fol-
lowed. The focus will be placed upon the welfare-improving reform problem
and the optimal reform will be derived as that from the solution set that max-
imises the increase in welfare. It is …rst necessary to restrict the set from which
solutions may be drawn since, in general, the solution set is a cone: if reform
x raises welfare by dW , then ¸x, ¸ > 0, which is also a solution, raises welfare
by ¸dW , hence no maximising reform exists. A procedure introduced by Dixit
(1979) is to restrict consideration to vectors dq that lie on the unit sphere. This
normalisation rule on the set of feasible reforms is now adopted in place of the
restriction used in the previous sections. The reforms must therefore satisfy
n
X
dqi2 = 1: (6.17)
i=1

To re‡ect the fact that the reforms in question are di¤erential, the interpretation
of this normalisation is that units are such that 1 is small.
The optimal reform is identi…ed as that reform on the surface of the unit
sphere which maximises the increase in welfare. Writing

F (q1 ; :::; qn ) 0; (6.18)

for the production constraint, where the function has been rede…ned to suppress
the dependence upon aggregate demand, the optimal choice of reform is the
solution to
max dW = rW T dq; (6.19)
fdq g

subject to the pair of constraints


n
X
dF = rF T dq 0; dqi2 = 1: (6.20)
i=1

The Lagrangean for this maximisation is


" n
#
X
T T
L = rW dq ¡ ¹rF dq + ¸ 1 ¡ dqi2 : (6.21)
i=1

From (6.21), the …rst-order condition for the choice of the ith element of the
reform vector is
rW i ¡ ¹rFi ¡ 2¸dqi = 0: (6.22)
6.4. PRODUCTIVE EFFICIENCY AND MAXIMISING REFORMS 179

Substituting (6.22) into the constraint on the size of the reforms provides the
restriction that ¸2
Xn
rW i ¡ ¹rFi
= 1: (6.23)
i=1

The focus of interest here is in the optimal reform, so it is assumed a non-zero


solution exists to (6.19)-(6.20) and hence that ¸ > 0. It follows that
rW i ¡ ¹rF i
dqi = h i 12 : (6.24)
Pn 2
j= 1 [rW j ¡ ¹rFj ]

As the denominator of (6.24) is positive, substitution from (6.24) into the pro-
duction constraint shows that productive feasibility will be satis…ed if

rF T rW ¡ ¹rF T rF 0: (6.25)

Solving (6.25) for m, the multiplier on the production constraint, gives

rF T rW
¹¸ : (6.26)
rF T rF
It is from (6.26) that production e¢ciency can be addressed. If rF T rW >
0 then ¹ > 0 and, from the complementary slackness conditions, production
e¢ciency is preserved. Conversely, rF T rW < 0 implies that ¹ = 0 so that the
reform will lead to a new equilibrium with productive ine¢ciency.
The importance of this result is the fact that for many situations, as captured
by the Diamond-Mirrlees Production E¢ciency lemma (Theorem 4.1) and its
extension by Hahn (1973), production e¢ciency will be desirable at the policy
optimum. It would then be expected that it would also be required along the
reform path. In contrast, these results show that this belief is not correct and
that reform may lead to ine¢ciency until the optimum is reached.
The geometric interpretation of the discussion of (6.26) is that rF T rW < 0
implies, in two dimensions, that the vectors rF and rW make an angle of more
than 90 o . The vector of reforms is chosen to make the narrowest feasible angle
with rW as this will maximise the increase in welfare. If rF T rW < 0, the
maximising reform lies along rW itself and can be de…ned by dq = ±rW , where
(±rW )T (±rW ) = 1. This situation is depicted in Figure 6.9 for a two-good
economy with the change in prices is restricted to be on the unit circle.
Production e¢ciency remains after the reform when rF T rW > 0. The
maximising reform is then the vector orthogonal to rF , thus satisfying the
production constraint, that makes the smallest angle with rW . This represents
a reform that moves the economy around the boundary of the production set.
This is illustrated in Figure 6.10.
To summarise the discussion, productive ine¢ciency may occur after the
reform has taken place. Whether it occurs is dependent upon the divergence
between the vector of derivatives of the welfare function and those of the pro-
duction constraint. When these are similar, production e¢ciency is retained.
180 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Figure 6.9: Production Ine¢ciency After Reform

Figure 6.10: Production E¢ciency

These results have been extended by Guesnerie (1977) and Fogelman, Quinzii
and Guesnerie (1978) who consider policy reform as a dynamic process. At each
moment in time the process is such that the reform must be Pareto-improving so
that individual utilities must be increasing along the reform path. In addition,
the changes in demand must be capable of being matched by supply changes
and consequent modi…cation of producer prices.
The major …nding of the analysis is, that to be successful, the reform process
must be allowed to pass through points interior to the production set. If it is not,
it may terminate at a point which is not a local Pareto optimum. Despite any
ine¢ciencies that may occur along the path, the process will always terminate
at an e¢cient point.

6.4.2 Interpretation
There are two interpretations of this result that are worth noting. The …rst
interpretation is that the production ine¢ciency arises because the reform is
seeking the maximum increase in welfare and there is no reason why this needs
to be along the frontier. Although the initial point for the reform process and
the …nal point are both on the frontier, the path of greatest increase in welfare
is more likely to go through the production set than to follow its boundary.
The alternative interpretation rests on the observation that the initial point
is not derived as the outcome of a social maximisation but is, in a sense, arbi-
trary. As a consequence, there is no reason to expect any relationship to hold
6.5. LUMP-SUM TAXES 181

between the gradient vectors Z and W , or between Z and the gradient vectors of
individual utilities. This should be contrasted to the position at the optimum,
shown in Figure 6.4b, where the gradient vectors Z and W point in opposite
directions. Given this arbitrary relation, it is only natural that production in-
e¢ciency may arise.

6.5 Lump-sum taxes


The analysis to this point has been concerned only with the e¤ects of changes in
the consumer price vector. It is reasonable to expect that other policy variables
will be available to the government such as income taxes or methods of e¤ecting
transfer payments and the e¤ect of these upon the reform problem needs to be
considered.
Although optimal lump-sum taxes can be ruled out for the reasons discussed
in Chapter 2 Section 4.1, a uniform lump-sum tax or subsidy cannot be dismissed
so easily. As shown by Smith (1983), the incorporation of a uniform lump-sum
subsidy has important implications for the reform problem. To understand the
nature of these implications, it is helpful to refer back to the discussion of 4.3.
Production ine¢ciency may arise because the gradient vectors of the indirect
utility functions of the individual households are essentially arbitrary. When
a lump-sum subsidy is introduced, the gradient vector of indirect utility with
respect to the set of policy instruments will have a positive entry for every con-
sumer for the e¤ect of the lump-sum subsidy. This observation ensures a degree
of similarity between the indirect utility functions of the separate households
and signi…cantly modi…es the conclusions.
Consider now the consequence of introducing a lump-sum subsidy, I, to all
households. From an initial point with I = 0, a reform in I and q will lead to a
Pareto improvement if
¸
hT dI
rV > 0; all h; (6.27)
dq

or, using Roy’s identity and eliminating the (positive) marginal utility of income,
if
dI ¡ xh T dq > 0: (6.28)

The change will be productively feasible if the change in demand has negative
value at initial producer prices which can be expressed as

H
X
p T x hI dI + pT Xq dq 0; (6.29)
h= 1

where x hI is the derivative of household h’s demand with respect to lump-sum


income. Since I is initially zero, the additional condition dI ¸ 0 must also be
satis…ed.
182 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Referring back to Theorem 6.5, a reform will lead to ine¢ciency if pT Xq 2


¤ (q). From the de…nition of ¤ (q), and the assumption that pT Xq 6= 0, this is
equivalent to the existence of ¸ h > 0, all h, and ¹ > 0 such that

H
X
¸h x h ¡ ¹p T Xq = 0: (6.30)
h=1

An improving reform that requires ine¢ciency will only exist if there exist ¸ h >
0, all h, ¹ ¸ 0 and ´ ¸ 0 such that (6.30) is satis…ed and

H
X H
X
¸h + ´ + ¹ pT xhI = 0: (6.31)
h=1 h=1

P
Since (6.30) requires ¹ > 0, (6.31) can only be satis…ed if H T h
h=1 p xI < 0. That
is, to obtain production ine¢ciency it is necessary
P that the aggregate income
e¤ect must be negative. If, as is more likely, H T h
h =1 p x I > 0 then production
ine¢ciency cannot arise. Hence, if all goods are normal, the use of a lump-sum
subsidy will eliminate production ine¢ciency along the reform path.
The reasoning behind this argument is simple. If the government budget is
balanced at the initial, e¢cient, point, it will be in surplus after moving to an
ine¢cient point. The lump-sum subsidy can be used to disburse this surplus. If
demand rises in response to the subsidy, which it will when goods are normal,
a tight equilibrium will be achieved and e¢ciency restored. This represents a
Pareto-imporvement
PH over the ine¢cient position. This process will not work
when h=1 p T x hI < 0 since the lump-sum subsidy will then reduce the value of
demand further and ine¢ciency will increase.
A …nal point worth noting is that the ability to use a lump-sum subsidy
ensures that the Pareto-improving set is non-empty. This follows because each
vector rV h T has a positive entry for the marginal e¤ect of an increase in lump-
sum subsidy so that the cone generated by the vectors must be pointed. With a
lump-sum subsidy only the second stage of the Pareto-improving reform problem
needs to be addressed.

6.6 The inverse optimum


The motivation for the inverse optimum is derived from noting that when no
feasible improving-reform exists it follows from the Tucker’s and Motzkin’s the-
orems that the initial position is optimal given the social welfare weights. This
result can have an alternative interpretation as follows. Given any initial po-
sition, it is possible to consider which set of welfare weights would make the
initial point an optimum. If these weights are calculated and they do not con-
form with those of the policy maker, this is equivalent to saying a reform exists.
The major work in this area is Ahmad and Stern (1984) who introduced the
inverse optimum and applied the methodology to Indian data.
6.6. THE INVERSE OPTIMUM 183

Figure 6.11: The Inverse Optimum

6.6.1 Theory
To formalise the inverse optimum, return to the welfare improving reform prob-
lem. It is convenient to adopt as a normalisation rule that the tax on good 1
is zero and that q1 = p 1 = 1; hence dq1 = 0. The vector rW T can then be
written as
ÃH H
! Ã H H
!
X @W @V h X @W @V h X h X h h
T h
rW = ; :::; = ¡ ¯ x 2 ; :::; ¡ ¯ xn ;
@V h @q2 @V h @qn
h=1 h=1 h= 1 h=1
(6.32)
where the second equality in (6.32) follows from (4.37). For the remainder of
this section, ¯ 1 ; :::; ¯ h are termed the social welfare weights of the households.
They remain, of course, a composition of social and private marginal utilities.
Employing (6.32), the …rst form of the inverse optimum problem can now
be stated.
Inverse Optimum ³ ´
What must the welfare weights ¯ 1 ; :::; ¯ h be in order that the equations

rW T dq > 0; (6.33)

and
rZ T dq ¸ 0; (6.34)

have only the zero vector as solution?


The interpretation of this formulation is that the ¯s are being treated as
variables and the aim is to discover the set of ¯s that justify the initial policy
as optimal. Given these values of the social weights they can be assessed in
terms of their suitable representation of social preferences. If they are obviously
unacceptable, the initial policy can be seen as non-optimal.
Recalling the discussion following (6.16), the diagrammatic explanation of
the inverse optimum is that ¯ is being adjusted until the vector rW is such
that the boundary of the halfspace, S, is coincident to the boundary of Q(p; q).
In Figure 6.11, the set of weights ¯ 00 would solve the inverse optimum.
184 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Figure 6.12: Solution of Inverse Optimum

Applying the same analysis to the Pareto-improving reform, part (b) of the
Motzkin theorem provides a set of non-negative weights under which no reform
can be found. These can also be interpreted as the implicit social welfare weights
of the households constituting the economy. Evidently, this can only be achieved
if the number of goods is equal to the number of households. With too many
households the ¯s will not be uniquely identi…ed and with too few the equations
need not have a solution. When the inverse optimum is solved it is possible that
some of the ¯ values may be negative. This indicates that a Pareto improvement
may be made.

6.6.2 Applications
In their application of the inverse optimum analysis, Ahmad and Stern (1984)
employ the same commodity groupings and Indian data set as in the work of
Murty and Ray reported in Chapter 4. Their …rst step is to take the revenue
requirement as given and to solve the inverse optimum problem. As their data
set has more households than goods, this is achieved by grouping the households
into 9 income bands to give the same number of households as goods. Table 6.1
describes the outcome of this procedure.
As can be seen from Table 6.1, there is considerable variance in the welfare
weights attached to the di¤erent income groups. There are also a number of
negative weights which indicate that Pareto-improving reforms are possible.
Having identi…ed the possibility of making Pareto-improving reforms, Ah-
6.6. THE INVERSE OPTIMUM 185

Figure 6.13: Tax Changes

mad and Stern proceed to calculate a vector of such reforms. This vector is
restricted by the assumption that the tax changes must not increase or decrease
the revenue raised by more than one rupee. This normalisation rule is an al-
ternative to (6.17). The resulting tax changes are shown in Table 6.2 and the
welfare e¤ects of these in Table 6.3.
The welfare change table shows clearly how welfare has increased for some
groups and decreased for none. Tax changes could obviously be undertaken
until the gains from reform were exhausted.
An alternative approach to the inverse optimum problem is taken by Chris-
tiansen and Jansen (1978). They approach the analysis from the perspective
that the welfare weights are determined by political considerations and the form
of the welfare function can be inferred from study of the political process. A
vector of income changes is de…ned as distibutively neutral if it leaves all relative
welfare weights unchanged and the political process is deemed to view an equal
relative increase of all incomes as neutral. Imposing an additive social welfare
function
XH
¡ ¢
W = W Mh ; (6.35)
h=1

and de…ning the welfare weight of h as a function of income by


¡ ¢
¡ h¢ @W M h
¯ M = ; (6.36)
@M h
the political view of distributional neutrality implies that
¡ ¢
¯ Mh
³ ´ ; h 6= b
h; (6.37)
b
¯ Mh
186 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Figure 6.14: Welfare Changes

b
is homogeneous of degree 1 in M h ; M h . From this it follows that the welfare
weight function must take the form

¯ (M ) = KM ¡º ; (6.38)

which is identical to the form in (4.51).


This analysis is then integrated within a study of the Norwegian commodity
tax system. In addition to the isues addressed in Chapter 4, the design of taxes
also takes into account the assumption that four of the …fteen commodities
groups may have signi…cant externality e¤ects. When the externality e¤ects are
ignored, a value of º = 1:706 rationalises the choice of observed tax rates. In
contrast, incorporating the externality e¤ects provides a value of º = 0:88. At
this value of the social welfare function (6.35) is approximately log-linear. The
di¤erence between the two values of show that the results of inverse optimum
calculations may be highly sensitive to the correct choice of framework.

6.7 Marginal social cost of taxation


The marginal social cost has been developed as a means of assessing the potential
optimality of a commodity tax system and, if the existing system is not optimal,
of indicating the direction in which it should be reformed. If carefully applied,
the technique is also useful for assessing other policy reforms. As above, the
existence of an improving reform follows from the non-optimality of the initial
position but the direction of reform is determined by assuming certain regularity
conditions for the economy, where the required regularity is clari…ed below.
6.7. MARGINAL SOCIAL COST OF TAXATION 187

6.7.1 Derivation
To introduce marginal social cost the Diamond-Mirrlees economy of Chapter
4 is employed. Recalling that analysis, the consumers are described by their
indirect utility functions
¡ ¢
U h = V h q1 ; :::; qn ; w; I h ; (6.39)

and the tax revenue that must be raised is given by


n X
X H
R= ti xhi : (6.40)
i=1 h=1

Social welfare is determined by a Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function


which is de…ned on the vector of indirect utilities
¡ ¢
W = W V 1 (¢) ; :::; V H (¢) : (6.41)

Starting from an initial vector of taxes (t1 ; :::; tn ), the e¤ect on social welfare
of a change dtk in the tax tk on good k is given by
" H #
X @W @V h
dtk : (6.42)
@V h @qk
h=1

The e¤ect of the same change in tk on tax revenue is


"H n X H
#
X X @xhi
h
xk + ti dtk : (6.43)
i=1
@qk
h =1 h= 1

Using these two terms, the marginal social cost of raising a unit of revenue by
increasing the tax on good k, ¸ k , is de…ned by (minus) their ratio
PH @ W @V h
h=1 @V h @q k
¸k = ¡ P Pn PH : (6.44)
H h @ xh
h=1 x k + h=1 ti @q k
i
i=1

It is clear from the …rst-order conditions for the optimal tax problem that at
an optimum all the marginal social costs for goods k = 1; :::; n should be equal.
If they are not equal, the existing tax system is not optimal. In the case that
the ¸s are not equal, those goods with the largest values of ¸ should have their
taxes reduced since collecting revenue via these goods leads to a larger loss in
social welfare for a unit of revenue than would taxes on low ¸ goods.
This procedure can be interpreted as being the …rst step in an iterative
algorithm to …nd the maximum. The speci…c requirement that the goods with
high values of ¸ k should have their taxes reduced is based on the assumption
that the problem has su¢cient regularity so that the direct e¤ect of tk on ¸ k
dominates the cross-e¤ects caused by the adjustment of other tax rates. If this
188 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

restrictions is satis…ed the variation in the ¸s indicates the correct direction of


reform. Typically, the non-concavity of the tax problem prevents the application
of standard theorems on the convergence of algorithms.
An interesting application of the social marginal cost is made in Newbery
(1986) where the issue of taxes on intermediate goods when there is not a com-
plete set of …nal goods taxes is addressed. The argument proceeds by evaluating
the marginal social costs of the existing set of taxes and contrasts these with
the marginal social costs of taxes on intermediate go ods. If the latter costs are
lower, and a condition is given by Newbery for when they will be, intermediate
goods taxes should be introduced. This result also indicates the importance of
a full set of commodity taxes in the proof of the Diamond-Mirrlees e¢ciency
lemma. The marginal social cost also forms the basis of the Murty-Ray algo-
rithm, described in hapter 4, for calculating optimal commodity taxes.

6.7.2 Empirical application


An empirical application of the use of the marginal social cost is given by De-
coster and Schokkaert (1989). The analysis is applied to Belgian data with a
twelve commodity breakdown. The welfare weights for the social welfare func-
tion are de…ned in the manner described in Chapter 4, thus
¸"
¹1
¯h = : (6.45)
¹h

The marginal social costs will evidently depend upon the chosen value of ". A
selection of the results is given in Table 6.4.
Table 6.3 illustrates that the Belgian tax system is not optimal for any value
of ". However, for all values tobacco has the highest marginal social cost and
services the lowest. The policy recommendation from this would be that the tax
on tobacco should be lowered and that on services raised. Furthermore, heating
also has a generally high marginal social cost. Decoster and Schokkaert also
present the social marginal costs for di¤erent income groupings from which can
be formed general views on the importance of various commodities to di¤erent
income groupings. For instance food appears important to the low income
groups with transport of no consequence. The ranking is exactly reversed for
the highest income group.

6.8 Political Constraints


The policy reform problem has been extended by Kanbur and Myles (1992) to
include political constraints upon directions of reform. These constraints are
intended to capture the fact that policy makers are invariably constrained in
their choice of policy by the need, for example, to win elections, avoid riots and
civil disorder and satisfy in‡uential citizens.
The general form of a political constraint consists of a set of S functions
T s (q) : <m ! <; s = 1; :::; S such that any policy change dq that satis…es the
6.8. POLITICAL CONSTRAINTS 189

Figure 6.15: Marginal Social Costs

political constraint has the property that

T dq ¸ 0; (6.46)

where 2 3
rT 1T
6 . 7
T = 4 .. 5; (6.47)
rT ST
is the matrix formed from the gradient vectors of the Ts functions. One simple
example arises in the case of a political elite whose welfare must not be reduced
by the reform. The functions Ts (q) are then the indirect utility functions of the
households comprising this elite and T is formed from the gradient vectors of
the indirect utility functions.
Incorporating the political constraints into the WI gives the following reform
problem
Constrained Welfare-Improving Reform (CWI).
Does there exist a vector dq of reforms such that

rW T dq > 0; rZ T dq ¸ 0; T dq ¸ 0? (6.48)

The structure of this problem can also be characterised by the use of a


theorem of the alternative. From Mangasarian (1969)
190 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

Theorem 35 Either there exists a vector x with


(a) Ax ¸ 0, Bx = 0, Cx = 0,
or there are three vectors such that
(b) AT y 1 + B T y 2 + C T y3 = 0, y 1 > 0, y2 ¸ 0, y3 ¸ 0.

Proof. See Mangasarian (1969).


Hence either a solution exists (case a) or there is some set of weights (case
b), with the vector y3 proportional to the Lagrange multiplier on the political
constraints, for which the initial state is optimal.
The size of the solution sets to PI, WI and CWI can be contrasted. Under
the normalisation rule in (6.17) that the reform vector must lie on the surface
of the unit sphere, the size of a solution set can be de…ned as the area it covers
on the surface of the sphere. Denote S P ; S C , S W to be the solution sets to PI,
CWI and WI respectively. The relative sizes of these solution sets are then as
given in Theorem 6.7.

Theorem 36 (Kanbur and Myles)


a) S C µ S W ; S P µ S W ,
and, when the constraint is the non-reduction of the utilities of a political
elite,
b) S P µ S C µ S W .
n P o
Proof. To show that S P µ S W de…ne KH = x : x = Hh =1 ¸ h rV hT ; ¸ ¸ 0
h

which is the cone generated by the vectors rV h , h = 1; :::; H. As @@W Vh


¸ 0,
all h, rW© 2 K H . Next,
ª take H rZ and ©H rW to be theª halfspaces de…ned by
HrZ = x : rV T x ¸ 0 and HrW = x : rW T x ¸ 0 . Using these de…ni-
© + ª
tions, S W = HrZ \Int HrW \ B1 and S P = HrZ \ K H =0 \ B1 where a
superscript “+“ indicates the positive
© + ª polar of a cone and B 1 denotes the unit
sphere. But, as rW 2 KH , KH =0 µInt HrW . Hence S P µ S W :
The proof that S C µ S W follows
© from using
ª the rows of the matrix T to
de…ne the halfspaces HrTs £= x : rT s¤T x ¸ 0 , s = 1; :::S. From this it can
be seen that S W = HrZ \ \Ss=1 HrTs \Int HrW \ B1 . It is then clear that
S C µ S W . This proves (a).
To prove (b), note that if the utility levels of a political elite constraint
policy then T is given by the gradient vectors of the indirect utilities of the
membersn of the Pelite. Index the members
o of the elite by c = 1; :::; C and let
C
K C = x : x = c=1 ¸c rV cT ; ¸c ¸ 0 be the cone generated by the political
constraints. Evidently, KC µ KH and S W = HrZ \ K C+\Int HrW \ B1 . Also,
+
as KC µ© KH it follows thatª KH µ KC+ and thus KH +
=0 µ K C+. From this
K H =0 µ K C \ Int HrW µInt HrW and S µ S µ S W .
+ + P C

The result in (a) arises because rW is a positive linear combination of the


rows of P and (b) is explained by the fact that in the case described the cone
generated by T is a subset of that generated by P . This theorem formalises
some of the comments in Ahmad and Stern (1984).
6.9. CONCLUSIONS 191

In the presence of the political elite, the optimal tax problem is


¡ ¢
max W = W V 1 (q1 ; :::; qn ) ; :::; V H (q1 ; :::; qn ) ; (6.49)
fq 1;:::; qn g

subject to the political constraint


c
V c (q1 ; :::; qn ) ¸ V ; all c 2 C; (6.50)

where C is the set of elite households, and the production constraint

F (X (q1 ; :::; qn )) 0: (6.51)

Solving (6.49) - (6.51), the optimal policy is characterised by


H
X C
@W @V h X c @V c @X i
h
+ ¹ ¡ ¸rF T = 0; i = 1; :::; n; (6.52)
@V @qi @qi @qi
h= 1 c=1

and
h i
c
¸F = 0; ¸ ¸ 0; ¹c V c ¡ V = 0; ¹c ¸ 0; c = 1; :::; C: (6.53)

From (6.52) and (6.53), it can be seen that the e¤ect of the constraint is
to raise the e¤ective welfare weight on the constraining households from @@ VWc
@W c
to @V c + ¹ , with the complementary slackness conditions, (6.53), guaranteeing
c
that ¹ is non-negative. From this it can be seen that the implicit e¤ect of the
constraint is to shift the optimal policy in favour of the constrained household
by e¤ectively giving greater concern in social welfare to them.
This result does have important implications for the analysis of the inverse
optimum problem. Working back from the solution to (6.52) would generate
@W c
the e¤ective weights @V c + ¹ which, whenever a constraint is e¤ective, will
@W
di¤er from the true weights @V c . Therefore whenever political constraints are
binding, it is not possible to recover the welfare function from observed policy.
The inverse optimum can only recover the combined values of the welfare weights
and the additional multipliers.

6.9 Conclusions
This chapter has reviewed the economic analysis of policy reform and has in-
troduced some of the important analytical tools and results. The importance
of Theorems of the Alternative have been stressed since these theorems show
that either an improving reform is possible or that the initial point is optimal.
An alternative insight into the existence of reforms was provided by a geometric
approach that relied on the properties of convex cones.
One of the most important conclusions to emerge from the analysis was that
temporary ine¢ciency may arise during a process of reform. This …nding should
be contrasted to the e¢ciency lemma of Chapter 4 which showed the desirability
192 CHAPTER 6. POLICY REFORM

of production e¢ciency at the optimum. It should also be stressed that although


the theory was developed in the context of price reform in a Diamond-Mirrlees
economy, the method of considering the e¤ects of di¤erential policy reform can
be usefully applied beyond this particular framework.
Chapter 7

Risk

7.1 Introduction
Risk is a factor that is evident throughout economic activity. Firms must choose
between investment plans for which both the cost and the return cannot be
known with certainty, households purchase goods whose value in use is deter-
mined by the state of nature and the government receives uncertain revenues
and allocate funds to projects with unknown outcomes. Although the Arrow-
Debreu economy is capable of incorporating risks of these kinds, so that they
can be viewed as having already been covered by previous analysis, the special
features involved with risk justify a separate chapter devoted to the subject.
The interpretation of the Arrow-Debreu economy in the presence of risk is
discussed …rst and the Pareto optimality of equilibrium is reconsidered with
particular focus placed upon the number of markets necessary to sustain op-
timality. This analysis is at the level of generality of previous chapters. The
reasons why there may be too few markets to sustain optimality and whether
this may justify government intervention are also considered. Individual atti-
tudes to risk, in terms of measures of risk-aversion are then contrasted to social
attitudes. Alternative perspectives on social attitudes, including the Arrow-
Lind theorem supporting risk-neutrality of government, are contrasted. A more
general framework is then presented which shows how social attitudes to risk
can be derived from the social insurance e¤ects of pro jects and the weighting of
households in the social welfare function.
A more speci…c interpretation of risk in terms of assets with random returns
is then adopted and household maximisation is analysed in further detail. Reac-
tions to taxation are determined under various assumptions about the loss-o¤set
provisions of the tax system, the return on the safe asset and the number of
risky assets available. Two alternative perspectives on the nature of risk and
the interaction with taxation are then described. The …rst is the standard util-
ity maximisation analysis of labour supply but extended to include uncertainty
about the wage. This is followed by a consideration of choice between occu-

193
194 CHAPTER 7. RISK

pations where one occupation has a known return and the other an uncertain
pay-o¤.
Several di¤erent approaches to the design of the income taxation with risk
are described. The …rst set of analyses consider risks which are purely individual:
some households may do well and others badly. The unifying feature of these
is shown to be the welfare gains that can be achieved by the use of a distorting
income tax due to the social insurance that the tax can provide. The social
insurance e¤ect is such that it preferable to raise revenue from a set of ex
ante identical households using the optimal income tax rather than a uniform
lump-sum tax. These results are contrasted to those that apply under purely
aggregate risk where the entire population either gains or loses. In the latter
case, taxation cannot provide social insurance.
Before proceeding, two points are worth noting. In common with most
recent literature, no distinction is made here between risk and uncertainty; the
two terms are employed interchangably. Secondly, the analysis of tax evasion is
reserved for later analysis in Chapter 12. Although tax evasion is an example
of choice with risk, it is somewhat special because of its illegality. In addition,
the substantial literature on tax evasion merits separate consideration.

7.2 General equilibrium with risk


Risk can be incorporated into the Arrow-Debreu economy with very few formal
modi…cations; e¤ectively all that needs to be done is to increase the number of
goods and prices in an appropriate manner. The results of the previous analysis
then follow as in Chapter 2. The classic presentations are given in Arrow (1963)
and Debreu (1959). Radner (1985) provides an extensive survey of the relevant
literature.
The major focus here will be placed on the simplest case in which all con-
tracts are formed in period 0 and the uncertainty is about the state of the world
that will occur in the only other period, period 1, in which contracts are ful…lled
and consumption takes place. In this setting it is not necessary to distinguish
commodities by their time of availability. The extension to many time periods
(though retaining a single period in which contracts are formed) will be brie‡y
discussed; none of the essential conclusions is modi…ed.

7.2.1 Risk in the Arrow-Debreu economy


To formalise the notion of risk, a set of alternative states of the world is in-
troduced. The set of states is intended to be an exhaustive list of all potential
states that di¤er in any economically relevant way. The relation of these states
to risk is that any realisation of random events will lead to one of the states, s,
where the states are indexed s = 1; :::; S, and that there are su¢cient states to
cover all possible di¤erent realisations.
Each good in the economy is di¤erentiated by its place and state of avail-
ability. Contracts are made prior to the realisation of the state and will cor-
7.2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM WITH RISK 195

respondingly specify the place of delivery and the state in which delivery will
be made. Since goods will only be delivered if the relevant state occurs, the
term contingent commodities is often used since delivery is contingent upon the
speci…ed state occurring.
The production set of each …rm is extended, in a manner compatible with the
extended list of commodities, to include all feasible input-output combinations
of contingent commodities. A production plan is then a list of inputs and
outputs of all goods in all states. Denoting the price vector of the n goods in
state s by p s = (p 1s ; :::; p ns ), the extended
³ list of prices becomes
´ p = (p 1 ; :::; p n ).
Firm j chooses a production plan y j = y j11 ; :::; y jn1 ; :::; ynS
j
to maximise pro…ts
¼ j = py j . With a known price vector this provides a clearly de…ned level of
pro…ts. The structure of this pro…t maximisation problem is formally identical
to that introduced in chapter 2 and, given strict convexity of the production set,
the outcome will be continuous supply and pro…t functions. It should be noted
that these are supplies of contingent commodities which will only be delivered
if the relevant state occurs.
The preferences of each household h are assumed to be representable by a
von Neumann-Morgernstern utility function
S
X ¡ ¢
Uh = ½hs Ush x hs ; (7.1)
s=1
¡ ¢
where xhs = x h1s ; :::; x hns is the vector of consumption of the n goods in state s
¡ h ¢
and ½1 ; :::; ½hn are the probabilities that household h assigns to the possibility
of states 1 to S occurring. The structure of (7.1) allows each of the within-period
utility functions to be state-dependent.
If the endowment vector of h in state s is ! hs, their budget constraint is
S
X S
X m
X
p sx hs p s! hs + µhj ¼ j : (7.2)
s=1 s=1 j=1

Once the price vector is known, the budget constraint in (7.2) is clearly de-
termined. The household will then choose their demand for each contingent
commodity to maximise utility subject to (7.2) and subject to the demand be-
ing in the consumption set of the household; the consumption set being de…ned
in terms of contingent commodities. As in Chapter 2, if (i) the utility function is
continuous and strictly quasi-concave, (ii) the consumption set is closed, convex
and has a lower bound and (iii) the endowment is interior to the consumption
set, this maximisation will generate continuous demand functions for all goods.
It should be noted that in this context quasi-concavity of the utility function
implies risk-aversion; see Arrow (1963) and Debreu (1959).
An equilibrium for the economy is a price vector such that demand is equal
to supply for all contingent commodities. Whichever state arises, it is then the
case that the demand for commodities in that state is equal to the supply. Since
the economy is only a reinterpretation of that without uncertainty, the method
196 CHAPTER 7. RISK

of establishing the existence of equilibrium remains the same. In particular, the


same set of assumptions applied to the extended de…nitions of the production
and consumption sets remain su¢cient for the existence of equilibrium.

7.2.2 E¢ciency
In considering the e¢ciency of the equilibrium that will result from trade, it is
necessary to distinguish between ex ante and ex post e¢ciency. An equilibrium
is ex ante e¢cient if no redistribution of contingent consumption levels can be
found that is Pareto-improving in terms of expected utilities. Conversely, ex
post e¢ciency would be achieved if no reallocation could take place of actual
consumption levels in the state that occurred that would be Pareto-improving
in terms of realised utilities.
The formal equivalence between the economy with certainty and that with
uncertainty implies immediately that the equilibrium will be Pareto e¢cient in
the ex ante sense; the proof of the First Theorem of Welfare economics is directly
applicable. Now let M fh ´ p sx h be the equilibrium value of the contingent
s s
commodities
³ demanded
´ by h in state s. Then, relative to the vector of income
levels M f1 ; :::; M
fh , the equilibrium allocation in any state s is also Pareto
s S
e¢cient in the ex post sense: once the state has been realised no reallocation
of consumption exists that is Pareto improving. This result ³ is explained ´ by
viewing households being endowed in state s with incomes M fs1 ; :::; M
fh and
S
then equilibrium being reached given these incomes. The outcome must be
Pareto-e¢cient.
A further observation merits attention. If no trade were to take place until
the state were realised, the income of household h in state s, M csh , would be
given by the value of the state-contingent endowment, M cs ´ pbs !hs , where pbs is
h

the equilibrium price vector that would be realised once state s had occurred. It
is also correct to observe that the equilibrium then reached in state s would be
Pareto e¢cient in ³ an ex post sense.
´ However, there is no³reason to expect
´ that
f 1 f h c 1 c h
the income vector M s ; :::; M S is a simple rescaling of M s ; :::; M S nor that
the equilibria reached with the two income distributions are identical. Both are
Pareto e¢cient but they will generally be based upon di¤erent income distrib-
utions. The di¤erence between the two income distributions arises because the
trade in contingent commodities allows households to reallocate their purchas-
ing power between states on the basis of their attitudes to risk and assessment
of the probabilities of the states occurring. Further discussion of this issue can
be found in Dreze (1970-1).
The equivalence between the economy with uncertainty and that with cer-
tainty also justi…es the direct application of the Second Theorem of Welfare
Economics. When the required convexity and continuity assumptions are sat-
is…ed, any allocation that is Pareto e¢cient in an ex ante sense can be decen-
tralised as a competitive equilibrium with appropriate lump-sum transfers. If
there are no restrictions upon policy instruments, the government can therefore
7.2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM WITH RISK 197

Figure 7.1: Time and Uncertainty

achieve a socially optimal outcome by lump-sum redistribution and operation


of competitive markets. It should be noted that the lump-sum transfers will be
in terms of contingent commodities and will generally be state-dependent.

7.2.3 Including time


The introduction of time in addition to uncertainty can be achieved following
the procedure due to Debreu (1959). Assume that there are T time periods,
indexed t = 1; :::; T , during which consumption can take place and a further
period, labelled 0, in which all trades are enacted. Period 0 occurs prior to
periods during which consumption can take place. At time T there is a set of
possible states of the world that may occur; these are indexed sT = 1 T ; :::; S T .
It is assumed that there is a unique series of states from period 0 through
to T by which state sT can be realised. Therefore, given a realisation of s T ,
the previous states of the economy are determined. These assumptions are
illustrated in …gure 7.1. The states of the economy at each time period can be
represented by the vertices of a tree. If T = 3, it can be seen that the realisation
of state 1 3 implies that states 12 ; 1 1 must also have occurred.
A commodity can now be de…ned by its place of availability and by the vertex
of the tree at which it is available. Specifying the vertex uniquely identi…es the
time and state in which the commodity is available. Since no delivery will
take place unless the relevant vertex occurs, these commodities again represent
contingent claims for delivery. Pro…t and utility maximisation can be de…ned
in terms of these contingent commodities and continuous supply and demand
functions derived.
It should be appreciated that this formulation of time and uncertainty does
not alter any of the essential structure of the economy. The previous reasoning
therefore continues to apply: under the standard assumptions an equilibrium
will exist, a competitive equilibrium will be Pareto e¢cient and any Pareto
e¢cient equilibrium can be decentralised. In an economy with this structure,
both time and uncertainty can be incorporated without the e¢ciency of the
competitive equilibrium being destroyed.
198 CHAPTER 7. RISK

7.2.4 Complete markets


When assessing the relevance of these results there are several issues that have to
be considered. In addition to the points raised in chapter 2 concerning the strict
applicability of the economy and the use of lump-sum taxation, it is now also
important to consider the number and arrangement of markets in the economy.
The economies described above have possessed a complete set of markets, that is,
when markets open at the start of the economy trades can be organised for every
good in any state and, in the extended economy, for any time. In short, the
economy is assumed to possess markets for all state-contingent commodities.
This requirement is naturally far too demanding for any actual economy to
satisfy; it is not even likely that the products that will be available in the future
will be known today. In reality there are well-organised futures markets in a
small number of …nancial, industrial and agricultural products but certainly not
for the majority of products. Furthermore, even when there are futures markets
there is no necessary implication that state-contingent contracts can be written
and enforced. Hart (1975a) demonstrates that if markets are incomplete the
outcome of competitive trade will not be Pareto e¢cient and may even fail
to be e¢cient relative to the set of markets that are open. In e¤ect, when
markets are incomplete the economy can become trapped in an equilibrium
which is Pareto-dominated. It is consequently unlikely that assumptions of this
economy can be satis…ed and hence its welfare properties cannot be appealed
to as descriptive of reality.
There is, however, an alternative form of the economy, due to Arrow (1963),
that is rather more tenable. This alternative interpretation reduces the number
of futures markets that have to be operational and brings the economy closer
to what is observed in practice. To formalise this idea it is simplest to return
to the economy with uncertainty but a single period of consumption. Assume
that there exists a set § of securities, with S members, such that security s 2 §
pays one unit of numeraire commodity if state s occurs and nothing otherwise.
Security s has price qs. Economic activity is then organised in two stages.
Firstly, households allocate their incomes to the purchase of securities. Hence
securities will be purchased by household h to satisfy the budget constraint

S
X
Mh = q¾ z¾h; (7.3)
¾=1

where M h is the income of h and z¾h is the quantity of security ¾ purchased by


h. Naturally, this procedure will determine the income of consumer h in state
s to be z¾h. The second stage of the economy occurs after the state has been
realised and involves the households using their income from security purchases
to buy the commodities that are available in that state.
The central feature of this reinterpretation is that it leads to precisely the
same equilibrium as the economy with a full set of futures markets. To see this,
¡assume that¢ in the original economy household h chose to purchase the vector
x h1s ; :::; xhns in state s. Given the equilibrium price vector, this choice will cost
7.2. GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM WITH RISK 199

the household an amount given by


n
X
p is x his : (7.4)
i=1

If securities are purchased so that


n
X
z¾h = p is x his ; all s = 1; :::; S; ¾ = s; (7.5)
i= 1

the household can guarantee the necessary income to purchase the optimal con-
sumption plan. They will, of course, also choose this level of income since it was
de…ned by the optimality of the consumption vector. The …nal step is to note
that since the total income to be allocated to securities is de…ned by the value
of the contingent endowments and the pro…ts of …rms, this remains the same
in both interpretations of the economy. The prices of the securities are then
determined on their market so that precisely the correct levels of income are
transferred forward. In summary, if for each state there exists a unique security
that has a unit return in that state and zero return in all others, the equilibrium
of the economy will be the same as that with a full set of futures markets. It
therefore has the same welfare properties and the Two Theorems can be proved
to hold.
Two further points are worth making about this economy. Firstly, the use
of securities has economised upon the number of markets that are required to
achieve optimality. The initial economy employed nS markets whereas the al-
ternative possessed S security markets and n goods markets since the goods
market was only opened after the state was realised. There is therefore greater
likelihood that the optimum will be attained in the latter case. Secondly, al-
though the economy was introduced in terms of the § elementary securities
that had returns in only a single state, it will also function when securities have
returns in several states provided the returns are such that the securities can be
combined so that any vector of returns across the states can be achieved; see the
discussion in Du¢e and Sonnenschein (1989). This property of the securities is
generally termed spanning in the literature. The applicability of this economy
is therefore broader than the initial description may have suggested.

7.2.5 Comments
The discussion above has demonstrated that the Arrow-Debreu economy may
be extended to accommodate uncertainty and, that when extended, it retains
the welfare properties of the economy with certainty. However, the extension
required either an expansion of the number of markets or the introduction of
security markets. The …rst interpretation probably has little to commend it
other than formal elegance since economies with complete sets of markets are
not observed in practice. The second is rather more applicable and does suggest
how economies actually attempt to cope with the existence of uncertainty but,
200 CHAPTER 7. RISK

although securities certainly exist, it is not clear that they actually satisfy the
spanning property. Furthermore, the structure of the economy also places very
strong informational requirements upon the participants. In order to determine
the optimal purchase of securities, it is necessary for the household to know the
prices that will rule in each possible state that may be realised; this is implicit
in the statement of (7.5). It must also be the case that all the agents agree upon
the prices that will be ruling in each state. This position is clearly untenable.
Although the interpretation of general equilibrium with risk shows that there
is no formal di¤erence between the economy with certainty and that with un-
certainty, the structure of the latter makes it apparent that even less emphasis
should be placed upon its welfare properties than was placed upon those of the
certainty economy. As before, the economy provides a benchmark case against
which other, more restricted, economies should be placed. As already noted, the
existence of a market failure is not a su¢cient condition for supporting govern-
ment intervention since the government may also be restricted by some of the
features of the economy that prevent the market being e¢cient. In every case
it must be veri…ed that the government can actually achieve a better outcome
than the market.

7.3 Private and social attitudes to risk


It is typically assumed that households prefer a certain outcome to a risky out-
come with the same expected payo¤. That such risk-aversion exists is supported
by the observation that the purchase of insurance policies is commonplace. The
holding of shares with limited liability and of money, which pays no interest,
can be similarly explained by the desire to avoid risk. Given that society is
the sum of its members, does it follow from this that the government, as the
representative of society, should also act in a risk-averse manner? The answer
to this question has important implications for policy choice since a risk-averse
government would undertake fewer risky projects than a risk-neutral one and
would structure policies to avoid uncertainty in revenues and expenditures.
This section will …rst recall some aspects of the theory of household attitudes
to risk and of the measurement of risk aversion. This is followed by a summary
of alternative views on social attitudes to risk including the Arrow-Lind theorem
that asserts the risk-neutrality of the government. The section is completed by
an analysis of the valuation of pro jects in a contingent-commodity framework
with, possibly, incomplete markets.

7.3.1 Private attitudes


Consider household h which derives utility level U h = U h (M ) ; U h0 (¢) > 0,
from certain income M . Assuming that the preferences of the household satisfy
the assumptions of von Neumann-Morgernstern expected utility theory, so that
the utility function is unique up to a¢ne transformations, the expected utility
of receiving income level Mf with probability ½ and M
c with probability 1 ¡ ½ is
7.3. PRIVATE AND SOCIAL ATTITUDES TO RISK 201

given by ³ ´ ³ ´
£ ¤
f + [1 ¡ ½] U h M
E U h = ½U h M c ; (7.6)

f + [1 ¡ ½] M
where E [¢] is the expectations operator. If ½M c = M then household
h is risk-averse if and only if
³ ´ ³ ´
U h (M ) > ½U h Mf + [1 ¡ ½] U h M c : (7.7)

The interpretation of (7.7) is that a risk-averse household would not take on an


actuarially fair bet. If the inequality was reversed the household would be a risk
lover. Equality in (7.7) would imply risk-neutrality.
For (7.7) to hold for all actuarially fair bets the marginal utility of income for
h must be decreasing, that is U h00 < 0. Equivalently, the utility function U h (M )
must be concave. A measure of the degree of risk-aversion of a household must
therefore involve the second derivative of utility. By itself, this cannot act as
a measure since it is not invariant of the particular transformation of utility
chosen. Two measures that are invariant to such transformations are given by
the Arrow-Pratt (Arrow (1965), Pratt (1964)) measures of absolute and relative
risk-aversion de…ned respectively by
h00
Absolute risk aversion, RA (M ) = ¡ UU h0 ,
and
h00
Relative risk aversion, RR (M ) = ¡ MUUh0 .
It is often hypothesised (for instance in Arrow (1965)) that RA (M ) is a de-
creasing function of M and that RR (M ) is an increasing function. The …rst of
these hypotheses implies that the willingness to take small bets of …xed size in-
creases with income, an observation that is not implausible. The second implies
that as the level of wealth and the size of bets increase in the same propor-
tion, the willingness to accept the bet should fall. This observation is not as
immediately appealing as the …rst.
Now consider a risk-averse household assessing whether to undertake a risky
investment project, for example the purchase of securities. The concavity of
the utility function that follows from the assumption of risk-aversion, implies
that the expected return to the household of the investment is less than the
expected value of the returns. This is simply a more general restatement of
(7.7). An alternative view is that the household discounts the returns for the
risk involved at a higher rate than is justi…ed by the probabilities of the outcomes
alone. In any case, a risk-averse household will not undertake a pro ject that has
an expected value of zero.
An alternative perspective can be obtained by using the concept of a risk
premiums. Consider a household facing a random income M and choose the
…xed income level M0 such that

U (M0 ) = E [U (M )] : (7.8)

Now set M0 = M ¡ where M = E [M ]. From (7.8) this implies that


¡ ¢
E [U (M )] = U (M 0 ) = U M 0 M ¡ : (7.9)
202 CHAPTER 7. RISK

The value is termed the risk premium and it can be interpreted as the amount
the household would be willing to pay to avoid the risk asso ciated with the
random income M . It should be clear that as risk-aversion increases, so will
the value of the risk premium that the household will pay. In fact, denoting
the variance of the random variable M by ¾ 2 , Pratt (1964) shows that the
risk premium and risk-aversion are related by = 12 ¾ 2 RA (M 0 ) + higher-order
terms.

7.3.2 Social attitudes


The implication of household risk- aversion for the social treatment of risk has
received considerable discussion and several alternative positions have been pro-
posed. These are based upon di¤ering views on the role of the government, its
relation to the agents that compose the society over which it governs and its
relative ability at dissipating risk.
A …rst view, propounded most forcefully by Hirshleifer (1964, 1966) and
Sandmo (1972) is that the government should really not be given any privileged
role with respect to risk bearing. In a perfect capital market, the decisions
and attitudes to risk of the agents that constitute those markets are re‡ected
in the equilibrium levels of discounting that are applied to risky projects since
the market functions to allocate risks e¢ciently. As the market captures the
views of agents, it is then argued that the government can do no better than
to adopt the market rate of discounting when making its own pro ject appraisal
decisions. A further development of this argument would be to suggest that if
the government did use a discount rate lower than the market rate, it would
adopt projects that were socially undesirable and which displaced private sector
projects with higher returns.
An alternative view, stated for example in Samuelson (1964) and Vickrey
(1964), is that the government is in an advantageous position with respect to
accepting risk relative to private sector agents. This advantage arises due to
the size of the public sector and the number and variety of pro jects that it
undertakes. If the returns from its various projects are not perfectly positively
correlated, it is possible for the government to pool the risks arising from the
projects and therefore lessen the overall uncertainty of its returns. The argument
is then completed by noting that an ability to pool risks allows a lower discount
factor to be applied to any single risky project than would be done if the project
were undertaken separately in the private sector.
There are several arguments that can be raised against this view. Firstly,
projects should be evaluated individually by the public sector and not as a pack-
age as implied by the risk pooling argument. Packaging projects may result in
some being adopted which are socially undesirable. Secondly, if the government
is able to reduce risk by pooling, it should confer the advantages of doing so on
the private sector rather then simply exploit them in the choice of public sector
project. One method of doing so is by direct subsidy of the private sector in
order to allow previously marginal projects to be adopted.
Rather than focus on the risk pooling ability of government, Arrow and Lind
7.3. PRIVATE AND SOCIAL ATTITUDES TO RISK 203

(1970) argue in favour of a lower discount factor for the public sector on the
grounds of the ability of the public sector to spread risk. A simple version of
this argument would go as follows. Although each taxpayer is risk-averse, the
total cost of a pro ject will be divided between taxpayers with each carrying only
a small amount of the cost and therefore only a fraction of the risk. Provided
that the number of taxpayers is su¢ciently great, that the project is not large
relative to the economy as a whole and that the (random) cost to any taxpayer
of the pro ject is not correlated with any existing uncertainty in their income
stream, then as the number of taxpayers increases the risk premium of each
taxpayer and the total risk premium to society tend to zero. Given this, the
public sector should act as if it were risk-neutral.
To prove this theorem, consider an economy with H identical households who
have identically distributed random incomes, M , and concave, bounded, strictly
increasing and di¤erentiable utility functions U (M ) which satisfy the axioms of
expected utility theory. The government carries all costs of investment in a
project and receives all returns. The payo¤, less costs, is denoted by ¦. Its
budget is to be balanced in the absence of the project so positive returns from
the project are given equally to the taxpayers (by reducing taxes) and costs are
carried by the taxpayers (by raising taxes).
The …rst step is to write the payo¤ to the project in the form ¦ = ¦ + X
where ¦ = E [¦] and E [X] = 0. Now consider an individual household and
let s, 0 s 1, be their share of the returns of the project. This household
would
h ³ pay a risk premium
´i ³(s) to avoid the´ risk where (s) is de…ned by
E U M + s¦ + sX = U M + s¦ ¡ (s) . The value of (s) is the cost
to the household of bearing the risk. With these de…nitions, Theorem 7.1 can
now be proved.

Theorem 37 (Arrow and Lind) Assume that ¡ 1 cov(M


¢ ; ¦) = 0 and that s = H1 .
The total cost of risk bearing, H (s) = H H = Hk (H), then tends to zero
as H tends to in…nity.

Proof. Di¤erentiating expected utility with respect to s gives

@ h ³ ´i h ³ ´h ii
E U M + s¦ + sX = E U 0 M + s¦ + sX ¦ + X : (7.10)
@s

Setting s = 0 and employing the fact that cov(M; ¦) = 0, which implies


cov(M; X) = 0, it follows that
h h ii
E U 0 (M ) ¦ + X = ¦E [U 0 (M )] : (7.11)

From the equality in (7.11), using the de…nition of a derivative shows that
h ³ ´ i
E U M + s¦ + sX ¡ U (M )
lim = ¦E [U 0 (M )] ; (7.12)
s!0 s
204 CHAPTER 7. RISK

or, equivalently under the assumption that s = H1 ,


" Ã ! #
¦+X
lim HE U M + ¡ U (M )
H !1 H
" Ã ! #
¦
= lim HE U M + ¡ k (H) ¡ U (M )
H !1 H

= ¦E [U 0 (M )] ; (7.13)

where the second equality follows from the de…nition of the risk premium.
¦
Noting that limH !1 H ¡ k (H) = 0, the de…nition of a derivative can be
used to write
h ³ ´ i
¦
E U M+H ¡ k (H) ¡ U (M )
lim = ¦E [U 0 (M )] : (7.14)
H !1 ¦
H ¡ k (H )

Using (7.14) to divide through (7.13) gives


h i
lim ¦ ¡ Hk (H) = ¦; (7.15)
H!1

or
lim Hk (H) = 0: (7.16)
H!1

The limit in (7.16) proves the theorem.


Although a formally attractive theorem, this result is not entirely persuasive.
The most obvious shortcoming is the assumed independence between private
and public risk. These risks may well be highly correlated, for instance in a
recession both public and private sector incomes will fall. More importantly, the
theorem overlooks existing private sector institutions for risk sharing. Foremost
amongst these are insurance and joint stock companies and the theorem does
not prove that the public sector can spread risk any more e¤ectively than these
institutions. Furthermore, if there is an element of self-selection in the adoption
of private sector risk, it may be the case that risk in the private sector is borne
by those who are risk-lovers and that the private sector is, in aggregate, less
than risk-neutral.
To provide further insight into these issues, consider the following analysis
due to Grinols (1985) which is based on the state-preference economy of Section
2 augmented by the existence of a stock market. The economy is assumed here
to last for two periods. There is no uncertainty in the …rst period, labelled 0, but
any one of S possible states, s = 1; :::; S, may arise in the second period. Trades
must be completed in the …rst period. It is possible to trade shareholdings in
…rms and to enact futures trades for some, or all, goo ds. A shareholding in a
…rm entitles the owner to a share in the production of the …rm proportional
to the shareholding and this is the only means by which households can obtain
consumption in period 1. To motivate a social role for government risk taking,
the analysis will focus on the case where there are incomplete futures markets.
7.3. PRIVATE AND SOCIAL ATTITUDES TO RISK 205

¡ ¢
A consumption plan for household h, h = 1; ::; H, is written x h = xh0 ; x h1 ; :::; x hS
¡ ¢
of which e h = eh0 ; eh1 ; :::; ehS is derived from the public sector and xh ¡ e h is
from the private sector; the consumption set is X h . Household h owns an initial
endowment ! h0 of the input; no endowments are held ³ of the state-contingent
´
commodities. The production plan for …rm j, y = x j0 ; xj1 ; :::; x jS , is chosen
j

from the production set Y j . The production set is de…ned so that y0h 0 is the
input and ysh ¸ 0 is the output if state s occurs. Government production is de-
noted e = (e0 ; e1 ; :::; eS ) with e 0 0, es ¸ 0, and is chosen from the production
set Y g .
The important feature of the economy is that ine¢cient risk bearing may
arise due to forward markets being incomplete. If the forward market does
not exist for good i, there will be no price quoted in period 0 for delivery of
good i in period 1. In order to determine its optimal production plan a …rm
must decide upon a value for the missing prices. This is assumed to be done
by weighting the valuations of the …rm’s shareholders of good i by the level
of …nal shareholding. This approach, and possible alternatives, are discussed
in Diamond (1967), Dreze (1974) and Grossman and Hart (1979).³ Formally, ´
denote the price vector that …rm j perceives to be facing by p j = p j0 ; :::; p jS
j
and normalise so that p 0 = 1, all³ j. The vector
´ of marginal rates of substitution
U0h h
US ¡ h ¢ h
for consumer h is written q = U h ; :::; U h = 1; q1 ; :::; qhn . Letting µ j be the
h
0 0

shareholding of h in …rm j before trade in shares and µ hj be the shareholding


after trade, the perceived prices for …rm j are given by
H
X
pj = µ hj qh : (7.17)
h =1

It should be noted that the economy with complete markets is a special case of
(7.17). With complete markets, trade results in the marginal rates of substitu-
tion being equalised across households and, since the shareholdings must sum
to 1, (7.17) then states the usual relation that price is equal to the (common)
marginal rate of substitution.
With the share price for …rm j represented by rj , an equilibrium of the
economy is de…ned as follows.
Equilibrium h © ª © ª © ª © ª n h oi
An equilibrium is an array pbj ; b rj ; byj ; bxh ; b µ 0 such that:
j
j j j j j
For all j = 1; :::; m, yb
³ maximises ´ y for y 2 Y ;¡
pb
h h ¢
For all h = 1; :::; H , xbh0 ; b
µ 1 ; :::; bµm maximises U h x h0 ; xh1 ; :::; x hS subject to
i) xh 2 X h ,
Pm Pm h h j
i
ii) x h0 + j=1 µ hj rj !h0 + j= 1 µj rj + y0 + eh0 ,
Pm
iii) x hs ¡ ehs ¡ j=1 µ hj ysj 0, s = 1; :::; S.
Conditions (ii) and (iii) capture the …rst- and second-period budget con-
straints. In (ii) the initial ownership of a share in a …rm implies that the
206 CHAPTER 7. RISK

household must provide a share of the input to the …rm proportional to the
shareholding.
It is now possible to consider the evaluation of public sector projects. The
comparison will be made between the valuation that a typical private …rm, say
j, would place on a project and that which the government would adopt. To
remove one reason for these to di¤er, it is assumed the returns to the public
sector project are distributed in precisely the same proportions as the returns
to the private …rm. Therefore, the proportion of the public sector pro ject that
is distributed to h, £ h , satis…es £ h = µ hj . To value public projects, the govern-
ment employs a social welfare function that is a weighted sum of the household
valuations
XH XS
W (x) = ah qsh xhs ; (7.18)
h=1 s= 0
PH
where ah ¸ 0, all h, and h=1 ¡ = H. A project
ah ¢ is interpreted as a di¤erential
change in consumption dx = dx10 ; :::; dx H
S . Such a project is valued by the
social welfare function at
H
X S
X H
X S
X
W (dx) = ah qsh dxhs = ah £h qsh dxs ; (7.19)
h= 1 s=0 h=1 s=0

using dxhs = £h dx s: Conversely, a change in production is valued by …rm j at


H X
X S
j
F (dx) = µ hs qsh dxs : (7.20)
h=1 s=0

Employing the restriction that £ h = µhj , the valuation in (7.19) and that in
(7.20) are related by

H
X S
X
£ h ¤
W (dx) = F j (dx) + a ¡ 1 £h µhs qshdx s : (7.21)
h=1 s=0

It is immediately apparent from (7.21) that if all households were weighted


equally in the social welfare function, so that ah = 1, private and social val-
uations would be equal. If (7.18) is viewed as a linear approximation of a
standard Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function, then there is no reason
why the weights should be equal. Consequently, there is no reason to expect
equality of private and social valuations.
To further investigate the di¤erence in valuations when are not weighted
equally requires a further distinction has to be drawn. A public project is
said to be contained within the private sector if the vector of returns dx can
be achieved by a portfolio of holdings in the existing private sector …rms. If
this is the case, then existing trading arrangements ensure that the valuations
of households and …rms are equalised for such a project. Conversely, a public
project is outside the private sector if its returns cannot be duplicated by the
7.3. PRIVATE AND SOCIAL ATTITUDES TO RISK 207

purchase of shareholding in …rms. A project outside the private sector has the
property that it extends the set of securities that are available and permits
further risk-spreading.
PS
For a project contained within the private sector it follows that s=0 qhs dx hs =
F j (dx), all h = 1; :::; H and j = 1; :::; m. Using this relation in (7.21) then gives
" H ¸#
X £ ¤ 1 £ ¡ ¢¤
W (dx) = F j (dx) 1 + ah ¡ 1 £ h ¡ = F j (dx) 1 + cov a h; £ h :
H
h= 1
(7.22)
The interpretation of (7.22) is that a project contained within the private sector
should be valued more highly by the public sector than by the private sector
when its returns accrue disproportionately to those households that have a high
weighting in the social welfare function. If the returns accrue to those with a low
weighting, the public sector should value the pro ject less than the private sector.
The major implication of (7.22) is therefore the demonstration that there is no
a priori reason for the public sector to employ a discount rate that is uniformly
higher
£ or lower
¡ than
¢¤ that of the private sector. As regards the choice of project,
if 1 + cov ah ; £h > 0, any project that satis…es F j (dx) > 0, and hence would
be undertaken by the private sector, also satis…es W (dx) > 0 so that it would
also be undertaken by the public sector. This result also emphasises the role
played by the assumption of the Arrow-Lind theorem that private and public
risks are uncorrelated. The argument of Hirshleifer (1966) that the government
should employ the same discount rate as private …rms follows from assumption
of complete futures markets which implies that all pro jects are within the pri-
vate sector. Similarly, Sandmo (1972) although assuming incomplete futures
markets, reaches the identical conclusion by considering only pro jects within
the private sector.
As already noted, a project that is outside the private sector introduces
a set of payo¤s that cannot be duplicated by shareholdings in …rms. If such a
project is undertaken, households a¤ected by the project will need to adjust their
portfolios of assets to achieve optimal risk-taking. If the portfolio adjustment
raises utility, then the pro ject can be viewed as providing social insurance and
this will raise the welfare valuation of that project. It is also possible that the
portfolio adjustment may reduce utility in which case the welfare valuation of
the project will be reduced.
To formalise these observations, the pro ject dx ´ (dx0 ; dx ¾ ), dx ¾ 2 <s , is
written in the form dx = de x + dbx, where dex is that part of the pro ject that
can be obtained by combining existing private sector returns and db x is the
uninsurable part. Expressed alternatively, de x´¡ (dx ; de
x
0 ¢ ¾ ) can be written as a
linear combination of basis vectors of the form dx 0 ; y¾j where y¾j are the future
returns of …rm j and is therefore the projection of dx onto the space spanned by
the future returns of the …rms. The uninsurable part of the project, representing
an addition to the existing set of risky assets, takes the form db x ´ (dx 0 ; dbx¾ )
and is orthogonal to the space of existing risks.
Substituting into (7.21) determines the relation between social and private
208 CHAPTER 7. RISK

valuations as
H
X H
X S
X
£ ¤ £ h ¤
W (dx) = F j (dx) + F j (de
x) ah ¡ 1 £ h + a ¡ 1 £h qhs de
xs
h =1 h=1 s=0
H
X S
X
£ ¡ ¢¤ £ ¤
= F j (db
x ) 1 + cov ah ; £h + F j (de
x) + ah ¡ 1 £h qh(7.23)
s de
x s:
h= 1 s=0

The evaluation of the project can therefore be divided into three components.
The …rst is the evaluation of the part of the pro ject that lies within the private
sector and can be interpreted in the manner following (7.22). The second and
third components are the …rm’s and the households’ evaluations of the compo-
nent of the project that is uninsurable. Since this part of the project is not
traded, these need not be equal. These can be positive or negative; hence the
social evaluation may be above or below the private valuation. There is there-
fore no a priori reason for believing the social valuation to be above or below
the private valuation. In the Arrow-Lind case for which the public project is
entirely uncorrelated with private returns, de
x would be zero and as the number
of households increased without limit the …nal term would tend to zero. This
leaves the government evaluation equal to the valuation of the risk-neutral …rms.

7.3.3 Summary
This section has considered alternative perspectives on the relation of social
attitudes to risk to private attitudes. There is, of course, some merit in each of
these proposals and it was shown how each could be generated as special cases
of a general state-preference economy. As a …nal approach to this issue, Glazer
(1989) has considered social attitudes to risk from a political perspective and
has argued that strategic voting behaviour may lead to pro jects being adopted
by the public sector that could only be rationalised by a discount rate below that
of the private sector. This emphasises that the political outcome may remain
distinct from that which is economically e¢cient.

7.4 Household choice and taxation


Although the contingent commodity framework used in the previous sections
has the appeal of generality, this is also its shortcoming as a vehicle for devel-
oping simple insights into the interaction between taxation and risk-taking. A
literature has therefore developed that focuses upon household portfolio choice
when there are only two assets available; one safe, one risky. If it is further
assumed that there are only two potential future states of the world, the house-
hold decision problem can be represented diagrammatically. This approach, and
its extensions, will be the subject matter of this section.
Consider a household with a given initial wealth, -, to divide between the
two available assets. One of the assets, termed the safe asset, yields a known
7.4. HOUSEHOLD CHOICE AND TAXATION 209

return r. The other, the risky asset, has a random return » which is distributed
with density ° (») and variance ¾ 2 . ° (» ) has support on (¡1; 1). The household
is concerned only with their …nal level of wealth, Y , and seeks to maximise
E [U (Y )] by choosing the amount, a, of their initial wealth invested in the risky
asset. The household is assumed to be risk-averse; hence U 00 (Y ) < 0. The
e¤ects of two taxes will be analysed: a wealth tax, denoted tw , and an income
tax, tm .
In order to specify the payo¤ to the household from a given portfolio, it is
…rst necessary to clarify the provisions in the tax system for o¤setting losses
(negative returns) against taxable income. If all losses can be o¤set, the tax
system is said to have full loss o¤set. The other extreme is termed no loss
o¤set. Between the extremes lie systems with partial loss o¤set. The relevance
of loss o¤set provisions is in their e¤ect upon the expected post-tax return from
the risky asset and the distribution of tax revenues. With full loss o¤sets, an
income tax reduces both the potential gains from holding the risky asset and the
potential losses. Conversely, with no loss o¤set only the gains are reduced. These
distinct e¤ects upon the structure of post-tax returns show why the e¤ects of
taxation will be dependent upon loss o¤set provisions. In addition, in all but the
no loss o¤set case, the government will incur some risk in the form of potentially
reduced tax revenues whenever the household holds some of the risky asset. The
extent of loss o¤set then determines the degree to which the government shares
the household’s risk.
Although full loss o¤set may seem at …rst sight a practically uninteresting
case, it should be noted that the investment behaviour under consideration may
only be a part of the broader economic activity of the household. When the
household earns income in addition to that derived from investment, then any
loss on investments can be set against other income in the determination of
taxable income. If all sources of income are taxed at the same rate, the tax
system would then appear as if it had full loss o¤set provisions.
Having clari…ed these distinctions, the analysis will …rst consider the e¤ect
of a wealth tax and then turn to the income tax. The formal results will be
developed for the general case described above but will be diagrammatically
illustrated for the special two-state case in which the risky asset either yields
a high return of a low return. The ma jority of the results are due to Mossin
(1968) and Stiglitz (1969a).

7.4.1 Wealth taxation


The wealth tax is levied upon the …nal wealth of the consumer that is determined
after the realisation of the return on the random asset. Provided that the …nal
wealth of the household is positive, the loss o¤set provisions are not relevant for
the determination of the e¤ect of the tax.
When the realised return on the random asset is », the …nal wealth of the
household with wealth tax tw < 1 is

Y = [[- ¡ a] [1 + r] + a [1 + » ]] [1 ¡ tw ] : (7.24)
210 CHAPTER 7. RISK

It then follows that the expected utility of the household can be calculated as
Z 1
E [U (Y )] = U ([[- ¡ a] [1 + r] + a [1 + » ]] [1 ¡ tw ]) ° (») d» : (7.25)
¡1

Di¤erentiating with respect to a and assuming that E [» ] > r, which is necessary


and su¢cient for an interior solution with a > 0 (see Arrow (1970)), the optimal
portfolio satis…es
[1 ¡ tw ] E [U 0 (Y ) [» ¡ r]] = 0; (7.26)
h 0 i
2
E U 0 (Y ) [» ¡ r] < 0: (7.27)

and
From (7.25) and (7.26) it can be seen that the e¤ect of the wealth tax is
equivalent to a reduction in initial wealth Y . An increase in the rate of tax
will decrease the proportion invested in the risky asset if the wealth elasticity
da -
of demand for the risky asset, d- a
, is greater than 1, will leave it unchanged if
da - da -
d- a = 1 and increase it if d- a < 1. The e¤ect of the taxation is this case is
straightforward.
To illustrate this result, assume that the risky asset provides a high return
» 1 with probability ½1 in state 1 and a low return »2 with probability ½2 in state
2; »1 > r > »2 . Investing all wealth in the risky asset will lead to …nal wealth
of - [1 + » 1 ] [1 ¡ tw ] in state 1 and - [1 + » 2 ] [1 ¡ tw ] in state 2. Alternatively,
if all income is invested in the safe asset, …nal wealth will be - [1 + r] [1 ¡ tw ]
in both states. The expected utility of the household is given by

E [U (Y )] = ½1 U ([[- ¡ a] [1 + r] + a [1 + »1 ]] [1 ¡ tw ])
+½2 U ([[- ¡ a] [1 + r] + a [1 + » 2 ]] [1 ¡ tw ]) : (7.28)

The indi¤erence curves of (7.28) and the budget opportunities facing the house-
hold are illustrated in Figure 7.2.
In Figure 7.2 the budget constraint is given by AB and the chosen portfolio
is at O. The proportion of wealth placed in the risky asset is AO AB
. The e¤ect
of an increase in the wealth tax or, equivalently, of a reduction in wealth is to
move points A and B towards the origin with the new budget line being parallel
to the old. Repeated for a series of changes in wealth, this will trace out the
wealth-portfolio locus of optimal portfolios. This is shown in Figure 7.3.
If the wealth-portfolio locus is a ray through the origin, as in Figure 7.3,
the proportion of wealth invested in the risky asset is constant as wealth or
the rate of wealth taxation change. This occurs when the wealth elasticity of
demand for the risky asset is equal to 1. When the wealth elasticity is greater
than 1 the wealth-portfolio locus will bend downwards away from the ray and
the proportion invested in the risky asset will fall as the rate of tax increases.
Conversely, a wealth elasticity less than 1 will lead to a wealth-portfolio locus
that rises more quickly than the ray and a consequent increase in the proportion
invested in the risky asset as the wealth tax increases.
7.4. HOUSEHOLD CHOICE AND TAXATION 211

Figure 7.2: Portfolio Choice

Figure 7.3: Wealth-Portfolio Locus


212 CHAPTER 7. RISK

7.4.2 Income tax


As already noted, it is necessary in the case of an income tax to specify the loss
o¤set provisions in the tax code. The analytically simpler case of full loss o¤set
will be treated …rst and then partial loss o¤set will be considered.

Full loss o¤set


To initially simplify the analysis, it will …rst be assumed that r = 0 so the safe
asset has a zero return. Under this assumption, when the realised return on the
random asset is », the …nal wealth of the household with income tax tm < 1 is

Y = - ¡ a + a [1 + » [1 ¡ tm ]] = - + a» [1 ¡ tm ] ; (7.29)

so that the expected utility of the household becomes


Z 1
E [U (Y )] = U (- + a» [1 ¡ tm ]) ° (») d» : (7.30)
¡1

Assuming that solution to the decision problem is interior, the optimal portfolio
satis…es
[1 ¡ tm ] E [U 0 (Y ) »] = 0: (7.31)
The e¤ect of a change in the tax rate upon the portfolio is found by di¤er-
entiating (7.31) with respect to tm . This gives
¸ ¸
@a
E U 00 (Y ) » [1 ¡ tm ] ¡ a» » [1 ¡ tm ] ¡ U 0 (Y ) » = 0: (7.32)
@tm

Employing the
h …rst-order
h condition (7.31)i implies that
i equation (7.32) can be
00 @a
reduced to E U (Y ) @tm » [1 ¡ tm ] ¡ a» » [1 ¡ tm ] = 0 or

@a a
= : (7.33)
@tm 1 ¡ tm

From (7.33) it can be seen that the holding of the risky asset is increased as the
rate of income tax increases. With full loss o¤set, an income tax encourages the
household to increase the holding of risky assets.
The surprising aspect of the result in (7.33) is that the response of the
household to the change in taxation is independent of the structure of prefer-
ences. It should be noted, however, that this is strongly dependent upon the
assumption that the safe asset has zero return. The reasoning lying behind
(7.33) is that the change in a described there is such that it keeps the mean
…nal wealth of the household, E [Y ] = - + aE [»] [1 ¡ tm ], the variance of …nal
2
wealth, var (Y ) = a2 ¾ 2 [1 ¡ tm ] , and all higher moments of the …nal wealth
distribution constant. Since the riskiness of the portfolio does not increase for
the household, social risk taking must have increased due to the government
holding part of an increased level of risky assets.
7.4. HOUSEHOLD CHOICE AND TAXATION 213

Figure 7.4: Income Tax with Zero Return on the Safe Asset

In terms of the two-state economy, the result is illustrated in Figure 7.4. The
assumption of zero return on the safe asset implies that point A is not a¤ected
by taxation. Point B moves inward to B 0 . Provided that the change in tax
rate is not so great as to push the household to a corner solution, the original
choice of returns, O, is still available but this now implies a greater holding of
the risky asset. The attainment of O requires the increase in investment in the
risky asset given by (7.33).
When the return to the risky asset is non-zero the result is less clear. The
level of expected utility is given by
Z 1
E [U (Y )] = U (- [1 + r [1 ¡ tm ]] + a [» ¡ r] [1 ¡ tm ]) ° (») d»: (7.34)
¡1

Maximising (7.34) by the choice of a and di¤erentiating the resulting …rst-order


condition with respect to tm gives

da E [U 00 (Y ) [» ¡ r]] -r a
= h i + : (7.35)
dtm E U 00 (Y ) [» ¡ r] 1 ¡ tm
2 1 ¡ tm

The …rst term of (7.35) can be viewed as a wealth, or income, e¤ect on asset
demand whilst the second term is in the nature of a substitution e¤ect. Since
these two con‡ict, no unequivocal conclusion can be given on the e¤ect of the
income tax on portfolio composition.
Further insight can
h be gained byi observing that the concavity of the utility
2
function implies E U 00 (Y ) [» ¡ r] . To evaluate the term E [U 0 0 (Y ) [» ¡ r]]
note that the wealth elasticity of demand for the risky asset is equal to

da - 1 + r [1 ¡ tm ] E [U 00 (Y ) [» ¡ r]] -
=¡ h i : (7.36)
d- a 1 ¡ tm E U 00 (Y ) [» ¡ r] a
2
214 CHAPTER 7. RISK

Figure 7.5: E¤ect of an Income Tax

Therefore the sign of is opposite to that of the wealth elasticity of demand.


Relating this to (7.35), if the wealth elasticity of demand for the risky asset is
negative, this further increases the level of demand for the risky asset caused
by the tax increase. When the elasticity is positive, the increase in demand is
reduced below 1¡atm . Substituting from (7.36) into (7.35) determines the e¤ect
of the tax as
da -r da a
= + : (7.37)
dtm 1 + r [1 ¡ tm ] d- 1 ¡ tm
Returning to the two-state case, the e¤ect of the income tax is illustrated in
Figure 7.5. The e¤ect of the income tax is to shift the budget constraint from
AB to A0 B 0 and the optimal choice from O to O 0. As drawn, the proportion of
wealth invested in the risky asset remains constant (the move down the dashed
line from O to O 0). An altered portfolio composition would be shown by a move
above or below the dashed line.

7.4.3 Imperfect loss o¤sets


When loss-o¤set provisions are imperfect, taxation has an asymmetric e¤ect
upon the post-tax returns to the household. The government takes a share of
positive returns but carries no responsibility, or at most a limited responsibility,
for any losses. It should therefore be expected that this will reduce the demand
for the risky asset relative to a system with full loss-o¤set. Due to the existence
of competing income and substitution e¤ects, the validity of such a claim de-
pends upon the basis for comparison adopted (for instance, at constant revenue
or at constant tax rate) and the method of specifying an imperfect loss-o¤set.
An analysis of imperfect loss-o¤sets can be found in both Mossin (1968)
and Stiglitz (1969a) but the approach taken here is based on the more general
analysis of Eeckhoudt and Hansen (1982). Let the income tax on positive returns
be …xed at tm and denote the tax on negative returns by tn with 0 tn tm .
7.4. HOUSEHOLD CHOICE AND TAXATION 215

If tn = tm the tax system has perfect loss-o¤set and if tn = 0 there are no o¤set
provisions. A move away from full loss-o¤set can be interpreted as a reduction
in tn .
The return to the household investing amount a in the risky asset is negative
[-¡a]r
if [- ¡ a] r + a» < 0. Hence for » < ¡ a the tax rate tn is applicable. For
other values of » returns are taxed at tm . The expected utility of the household
is therefore

E [U (Y )] =
Z ¡ [-¡a]r
a
U (- [1 + r [1 ¡ tn ]] + a [1 ¡ tn ] [» ¡ r]) ° (») d»
¡1
Z 1
+ U (- [1 + r [1 ¡ tm ]] + a [1 ¡ tm ] [» ¡ r]) ° (» ) d» : (7.38)
[-¡a]r
¡ a

The …rst-order condition for the choice of a to maximise (7.38) follows as

@E [U (Y )]
=
@a
Z ¡ [-¡a]r
a
U 0 (- [1 + r [1 ¡ tn ]] + a [1 ¡ tn ] [» ¡ r]) [1 ¡ tn ] [» ¡ r] ° (» ) d»
¡1
Z 1
+ U (- [1 + r [1 ¡ tn ]] + a [1 ¡ tm ] [» ¡ r]) [1 ¡ tm ] [» ¡ r] ° (») d»:
¡ [-¡a]r
a
(7.39)
n o
@a
The negativity of the second-order condition implies that sgn. @tn = sgn.
n 2 o
@ E [U (Y )]
@a@tn
. Calculating the latter derivative gives

Z ¡
[-¡a]r
@ 2 E [U (Y )] a
= [U 0 [» ¡ r] + U 00 [1 ¡ tn ] [» ¡ r] [- ¡ a] r + a»] ° (» ) d»:
@a@tn ¡1
(7.40)
Since the integration is conducted over values of » for which [» ¡ r] < 0 and
2
[- ¡ a] r + a» < 0, the concavity of the utility function implies that @ @E[U (Y )]
a@ tn
>
0. An increase the loss-o¤set provisions (tn increasing) therefore increases the
household’s investment in the risky asset. Phrased alternatively, the household’s
purchases of the risky asset will fall as the loss-o¤set provisions are reduced.
A similar analysis is conducted by Diamond and Stiglitz (1974) but with
the tax rate adjusted as loss-o¤set is changed in order to keep utility constant.
The same general result is also shown to hold in that case. With respect to the
e¤ect of changes in the tax rate on positive returns, Mossin (1968) shows that
the result is indeterminate due to the con‡ict between income and substitution
e¤ects even when the return on the safe asset is zero. Since these results are
straightforward to generate, they are not reproduced here.
216 CHAPTER 7. RISK

7.4.4 Generalisations
The results given above are based on a speci…cation that is restrictive in a
number of directions. The analysis has been entirely partial equilibrium and
the use to which tax revenues were put was not considered. It was assumed
that there was a safe asset; such an asset need not exist. The restriction to two
assets is unjusti…able. Some of the consequences of relaxing these restrictions
will now be considered.
With respect to the use of tax revenue, it can always be assumed that this is
used to purchase a public good and that all households’ preferences are separable
between …nal wealth and levels of the public good. Similar reasoning was used
in Chapters 4 and 5. It is possible to consider the implications of tax revenue
being distributed between households but, since no particular mechanism for
redistribution suggests itself as most appropriate and the results are mechanism-
dependent, few general insights can be gained from this. The partial equilibrium
nature of the results will be relaxed somewhat in Section 6 when the design of
the tax system will be addressed.
Although it may appear innocuous, the assumption that there exists a safe
asset is rather a strong one. An obvious candidate for this role is holding cash
which earns a known nominal return of zero. However, if there is in‡ation the
real return will be less than the nominal return and, if there is uncertainty about
future levels of in‡ation, the real return will be uncertain. The same comments
apply to any asset whose nominal return is …xed but whose real return may
vary. Fortunately, the analysis is not critically dependent upon the existence of
a safe asset and can be reworked to include two risky assets.
Introducing further risky assets leads to a number of complications. Firstly,
the extent of risk taking cannot be as easily measured as in the one safe-one
risky economy where the degree of risk taking is given by the proportion of
income invested in the risky asset. Secondly, basic comparative statics results
on the relation of the investment in the risky asset to wealth (with decreasing
absolute risk aversion and increasing relative risk aversion the amount invested
increases with wealth whilst the proportion falls, see Arrow (1965)) no longer
apply except in rather special cases, some of which are noted in Cass and Stiglitz
(1972). As shown by Hart (1975b) with more than one risky asset (plus one
safe) it is generally possible to construct the returns to the risky assets in such
a way that converse comparative statics results can be derived.
Despite these di¢culties, Sandmo (1977) demonstrates that some results still
apply. Consider a household faced with the choice between n risky assets and
a safe asset that pays return r. Let the return on risky asset k, k = 1; :::; n, be
given by »k and the amount that asset purchased be denoted ak so that …nal
wealth is
n
X
Y = - [1 + r [1 ¡ tm ]] + ak [»k ¡ r] [1 ¡ tm ] : (7.41)
k=1

The e¤ect of changes in the tax rate upon the demand for asset k is then given
7.5. LABOUR SUPPLY AND OCCUPATIONAL CHOICE 217

by
@a k -r @ak ak
=¡ + ; k = 1; :::; n: (7.42)
@tm 1 + r [1 ¡ tm ] @- 1 ¡ tm
This result has precisely the form of (7.37).

7.5 Labour supply and occupational choice


The choice of portfolio is not the only uncertain decision that a typical house-
hold will have to take. It may not be unusual for labour supply decisions to be
taken before the actual level of the wage is realised. This can occur in some
forms of self-employment (such as farming) where production takes place prior
to the return being realised and, even if the nominal wage is known, future price
variation can make the real wage random. An alternative source of uncertainty
can arise in the choice of occupation; in particular between entering paid em-
ployment with (possibly) known return and some form of entrepreneurship that
has a random return. In both these examples, the tax system interacts with the
uncertainty in determining household choice.

7.5.1 Labour supply


The analysis of labour supply under certainty is restricted in the number of clear
predictions that it provides about the e¤ects of taxation due to the inherent
con‡ict between income and substitution e¤ects. It does, however, provide two
clear conclusions. Firstly, if taxation is raised on exogenous non-labour income
then labour supply is increased provided that leisure is non-inferior. Secondly,
income-compensated increases in taxation upon earned income reduce labour
supply.
To see the implications of the introduction of uncertainty for these conclu-
sions, consider augmenting the standard analysis of labour supply by assuming,
as in Eaton and Rosen (1980), that the household does not know the wage
that they will receive but instead holds a probability distribution over possible
wages. Denoting labour supply by x 0 and consumption by x1 , the taxpayer
chooses labour supply to maximise expected utility, E [U (x0 ; x 1 )], given the
constraint that
x 1 = wx 0 [1 ¡ t] + I; (7.43)

where t is the tax rate and I is lump-sum income. Assuming an interior solution,
the necessary condition for maximisation is

E [U0 + U 1 [1 ¡ t] w] = 0: (7.44)

From (7.44), the e¤ect of an increase in lump-sum income can be found to be

dx0 E [U01 + U 11 [1 ¡ t] w]
=¡ ; (7.45)
dI S
218 CHAPTER 7. RISK

where S < 0 is the second-order condition for maximisation. If the utility


function is separable, so that U01 = 0, concavity with respect to consumption
implies that U11 < 0 and hence dx dI
0
< 0. An increase in lump-sum income,
which is received with certainty, therefore reduces labour supply. This result is
in agreement with that which would be derived with a certain wage.
Now consider the e¤ect of an increase in the tax rate that is compensated
for by an increase in lump-sum income. The e¤ect of this upon labour supply
is given by
dx0 dx 0 dx0
jcomp: = + wx0 ; (7.46)
dt dt dI
in which wx 0 dt, with w the expected wage, is the compensation required for the
tax change dt. Calculating (7.46) gives
dx0 E [U1 w + [U11 [1 ¡ t] + U01 ] wx0 [w ¡ w]]
jcomp: = : (7.47)
dt S
With certainty w = w so that the tax increase would unambiguously reduce
labour supply. In contrast, the e¤ect of uncertainty is to make the sign of
E [U1 w + [U11 [1 ¡ t] + U01 ] wx 0 [w ¡ w]] ambiguous and it is possible for a com-
pensated increase in the tax rate to raise labour supply.
Uncertainty can therefore have the e¤ect of reversing the direction of labour
supply responses to changes in taxation and the results of the certainty analysis
are not directly applicable. The results developed above will be employed in the
analysis of tax design in Section 6.

7.5.2 Occupational choice


The analysis of occupational choice involves a di¤erent decision framework to
that of the choice of labour supply. As emphasised by Kanbur (1980), occupa-
tion is not really a variable that can be continuously adjusted and it is more
reasonable to think of a discrete choice being taken between entering alternative
occupations that di¤ered in the certainty of their returns. The discreteness of
the choice prevents the household obtaining insurance against risk by combining
a portfolio of employment in several occupations. Analyses of the interaction
between taxation and occupational choice are given in Kihlstrom and La¤ont
(1983) and in Kanbur (1980). The presentation given below is based on the
latter.
Consider an economy in which each of the set of identical households has a
choice between either supplying 1 unit of labour and receiving the competitive
wage w with certainty or becoming an entrepreneur and accepting uncertainty
in earnings. Those households who choose to become entrepreneurs choose the
quantity of labour they employ in order to maximise

E [U (R (y; ») ¡ wy)] ; (7.48)

where U (¢) is the concave utility of income function common to all households, y
is the quantity of labour employed and R (y; ») is the revenue from entrepreneur-
ial activity when value » of the random variable is realised. It is the dependence
7.5. LABOUR SUPPLY AND OCCUPATIONAL CHOICE 219

of revenue on » and the randomness of » that is the source of uncertainty in


the return from entrepreneurship. It is assumed that each household holds a
common belief about the distribution of ». The maximisation of (7.48) leads
to a labour demand from each entrepreneur of y = y (w). If the proportion of
the population becoming entrepreneurs is denoted by ½, an equilibrium for the
economy, in the absence of taxation is given by a wage rate, w,
b and a proportion
½ such that
b

(i) b½y (w)


b = 1¡b
½;

and

(ii) E [U (R (y (w)
b ; ») ¡ wy
b (w))]
b = U (w)
b :

Condition (i) is the full employment condition that balances the labour demand
from entrepreneurs with the labour supply of those choosing the risk-free occu-
pation. The second condition equates the expected return from the occupations
so that here is no incentive at equilibrium to change occupation.
One course of action open to a government faced with this economy is the
di¤erential treatment of income from the risky and the safe activity. If such
di¤erentiation is feasible, it is natural to investigate which of the two forms of
income should carry the lowest rate of tax. To formalise this, let income from
entrepreneurship be taxed at rate t and that from risk-free labour supply be
subsidised at rate s. Post-tax incomes in the two occupations are then given by

Mne = [1 ¡ t] [R (y (w)
b ; ») ¡ wy b = [1 ¡ t] M e ;
b (w)] (7.49)

and
Mns = [1 + s] w
b = [1 + s] M s; (7.50)

in entrepreneurship and safe labour supply respectively. The analysis now de-
termines the direction that a balanced budget reform of the tax system should
take beginning in an initial position with t = s = 0. Assuming a utilitarian
social welfare function, the level of per-capita welfare is

W = ½E [U ([1 ¡ t] [R (y (w)
b ; ») ¡ wy
b (w)])]+[1
b ¡ ½] U ([1 + s] w)
b = U ([1 + s] w)
b ;
(7.51)
since, in equilibrium, E [U ([1 ¡ t] [R (y ( w)
b ; ») ¡ wy
b (w)])]
b b In
= U ([1 + s] w).
order that the budget remains balanced, the tax and subsidy must satisfy the
budget constraint

½tE [R (y (w) ; ») ¡ wy (w)] ¡ [1 ¡ ½] sw = 0: (7.52)

Hence " #
E[M e] ¸
E [M e] @ wy E [M e ]
ds = +t dt = dt; (7.53)
wy @t wy
220 CHAPTER 7. RISK

where the second equality follows from evaluating at the initial point with t = 0.
From (7.51) the e¤ect of a balanced budget reform upon social welfare is
¸
dW 0 dw ds
= U [1 + s] +w : (7.54)
dt dt dt
Di¤erentiating the equilibrium condition guaranteeing equivalence of utilities
and evaluating at t = s = 0 provides the relation
dw ds
[yE [U 0 ] + U 0 ] + E [M e U 0] + wU 0 = 0: (7.55)
dt dt
Combining (7.53), (7.54) and (7.55) and evaluating at t = s = 0 provides the
…nal expression
e 0 e 0
¸
dW 0 E [M ] E [U ] ¡ E [M U ]
=U : (7.56)
dt yE [U 0 ] + U 0
The concavity of the utility function implies that marginal utility and income
are negatively correlated; hence E [M e] E [U 0 ] > E [M e U 0 ]. Using this inequality
shows that (7.56) is positive. From this it can be concluded that starting from
the initial position with zero taxes the government can raise welfare by taxing
the risky occupation whilst subsidising the safe occupation. Furthermore, as
shown by Kanbur (1980), with non-increasing absolute risk aversion and non-
decreasing relative risk aversion such a tax reform will reduce the proportion of
the population that chooses the risky occupation. The analysis provides a clear
prediction that, given the use of di¤erentiated income taxes as available policy
tools, the government should attempt to reduce entry into the risky occupation.
A similar analysis can be conducted to characterise the structure of a linear
income tax that is common to earnings from both occupations. Denoting the
parameters of the income tax by ¿ and t, post-tax income is given by
M ni = [1 ¡ t] M i ¡ ¿ ; i = e; s: (7.57)
¿
Since the marginal rate of tax is t and the average rate + t, the tax is
Mi
progressive if ¿ < 0 and regressive if ¿ > 0. The direction of reform from an
initial position with no taxation can be found, as above, by di¤erentiating the
equilibrium conditions and the revenue constraint and evaluating at ¿ = 0; t = 1.
Noting that welfare is a monotonically increasing function of the post tax wage,
Mns, the direction of reform can be found by noting that
dM ns E [RU 0 ] ¡ E [R] E [U 0]
jt=0 = < 0; (7.58)
dt yE [U 0 ] + U 0
where the negative sign follows from observing that R and U 0 are negatively
correlated. Social welfare is therefore raised by the introduction of a progressive
linear income tax with ¿ < 0 and t > 0. This form of tax reduces the risk
carried by entrepreneurs since it raises their raises their income in the worst
state relative to that in the best state.
This analysis of occupational choice is applied to the taxation of pro…t in
Peck (1989) and is extended to include heterogeneous households in the analysis
of optimal linear income taxation in Boadway et al. (1991).
7.6. OPTIMAL TAXATION 221

7.6 Optimal taxation


In designing optimal taxation in the presence of uncertainty, it is necessary to
face several issues that did not arise in the analysis under certainty. There is
…rst the appropriate de…nition of a government budget constraint and whether
this should be satis…ed in an expected sense, which was implicitly what was
imposed in the previous section, or whether a separate budget constraint should
be enforced in each state of the world. The choice of policy instruments is also
broader since taxes may potentially be di¤erentiated across states in addition to
being di¤erentiated across goods. When risks in the economy are purely private
and uncorrelated across individuals, there is also a role for taxation in providing
social insurance in addition to raising revenue and e¤ecting redistribution.
Given this list of extensions beyond the analysis of certainty, it is clear that
the results given below cannot deal comprehensively with all of these. In fact,
the existing literature has made only initial investigations into each of them and
none is yet treated in an exhaustive fashion. The discussion in divided between
an analysis of tax design with private risk and that with aggregate risk.

7.6.1 Private risk


The majority of the literature on optimal income taxation under uncertainty
has focused upon the social insurance role played by taxation. This has been
achieved either by considering identical households who make a single-period
labour supply decision in the face of uncertainty about the wage they will receive
or by considering households with two-period lives, who may all be identical,
but face uncertainty about the second period of their lives. In both cases in-
come taxation, by providing the households with partial insurance against wage
variations, can increase welfare through a channel that does not exist without
uncertainty.
To develop the …rst result, the labour supply analysis described in (7.43)
to (7.47) is employed and the optimal linear income tax is characterised for
a population of identical households. With a linear income tax, the budget
constraint of a typical household becomes

x 1 = [1 ¡ t] wx0 ¡ ¿ + I; (7.59)

and the government budget constraint, which is required to hold in an expected


sense, expressed in per-capita terms is

R = tE [wx 0] ¡ ¿ : (7.60)

Assuming that the population is su¢ciently large and employing the fact that
the identical households all choose the same level of labour supply, over the
entire population (7.60) is equivalent to

R = tE [wx 0 ] ¡ ¿ = twx 0 ¡ ¿ ; (7.61)

where w is the expected wage.


222 CHAPTER 7. RISK

The optimal tax structure can be found by solving

max E [U (x0 ; x 1 )] = E [U (x0 ; [1 ¡ t] wx 0 + I + twx0 ¡ R)] ; (7.62)


ftg

where x0 = x0 (t; ¿ ) = x 0 (t; twx0 ¡ R). The …rst-order necessary condition for
(7.62) follows from di¤erentiation as
¸ ¸
@x0 @x0
E [U0 + U1 [[1 ¡ t] w + tw]] + wx0 + U1 [wx 0 ¡ wx0 ] = 0: (7.63)
@t @I

From (7.63), the optimal tax is characterised in the following proposition.

Theorem 38 (Eaton and Rosen) The optimal value of t 2 (0; 1) .

Proof. From (7.44) E [U0 + U1 [[1 ¡ t] w]] = 0. In addition, (7.46) shows


that @@t
x0
+ wx 0 @@xI0 is formed as an expectation on the distribution of w. Using
these, (7.63) reduces to
¸ ¸
@x 0 @x0
E [U 1tw] + wx0 + U1 [wx0 ¡ wx 0 ] = 0: (7.64)
@t @I

Evaluating at t = 0 gives

E [U1 [wx0 ¡ wx 0 ]] = ¡x 0 cov (U1 ; w) > 0; (7.65)

since dU
dw = U11 x 0 < 0. Therefore t = 0 is not optimal. When t ¸ 1, x 0 = 0
1

and the …rst-order condition reduces to


¸¸
@x 0 @x0
wE U1 + wx0 < 0; (7.66)
@t @I

where the inequality follows from noting that (7.47) implies @x @x0
@t + wx0 @I is
0

negative when x 0 = 0. Finally, any value of t < 0 can be shown by a revealed


preference argument to be dominated by t = 0 since a negative value of t
increases the variability of income.
The important aspects of Theorem 7.2 become clear when it is contrasted
with the case of certainty. Under certainty, the optimal way to raise revenue from
a set of identical households is to employ a lump-sum tax which will raise the
required revenue without introducing any distortions. This can be seen in the
derivations above by noting that certainty implies w = w and that t = 0 then
solves the …rst-order condition. Viewed this way, the proposition states that
lump-sum taxes are not the most e¢cient way to collect revenue in the presence
of uncertainty. This seemingly surprising result can be explained by repeating
the observation that income taxation provides partial insurance against the risk
due to the uncertain wage. That the optimal rate of tax is non-zero is then
simply a re‡ection of the fact that the gain from insurance initially outweighs
the loss of welfare arising from the ine¢ciency caused by the distorting nature
of the tax.
7.6. OPTIMAL TAXATION 223

An alternative perspective on the social insurance role of income taxation has


been provided by Varian (1980), who considers households that face a two-period
decision problem. In the …rst period the household works for a known wage and
divides income between consumption and saving. Uncertainty is introduced by
assuming that the level of consumption in the second period is equal to savings
plus a random component with zero mean. The interpretation of this framework
is that initially identical households di¤er in the luck they have in choosing the
correct form of deposit for their savings. For instance, if di¤erent portfolios of
stocks were chosen by di¤erent households, the …nal value of these would be
expected to di¤er.
Formalising this discussion, each of the identical households receives a …xed
income of w which is divided between savings, x, and consumption, w ¡ x.
Consumption in the second period in the absence of taxation is x + ", where
" is a random variable with zero mean that is independently and identically
distributed across the population. It is assumed that the government cannot
observe x and " separately but can only monitor their sum x + ". A tax system
can then be seen to take the form of the imposition of a budget constraint such
that second period consumption is given by c (x + ").
Under the assumption of identical households, the optimal tax system is
chosen to solve the following maximisation program

max U (w ¡ x) + E [U (c (x + "))] ; (7.67)


fc(¢)g

subject to
E [c (x + ")] = x; (7.68)
U 0 (w ¡ x) ¡ E [U 0 c (x + ") c0 (x + ")] = 0: (7.69)
The constraint (7.68) restricts the tax system to break even in expected terms
and (7.69) is the …rst-order condition for optimal savings choice by each of the
households.
In the case of a linear consumption function with gradient ° and intercept
¡, (7.68) can be solved to write ¡ = [1 ¡ °] x and (7.69) used to write x = x (°).
Together these allow the objective function, (7.67), to be written entirely in
terms of ° as

max U (w ¡ x (°)) + E [U (° [x (°) + "] + [1 ¡ °] x (°))] : (7.70)


f°g

Setting the derivative of (7.70) equal to zero and employing (7.69) the gradient
of the consumption function can be characterised implicitly by
U 0 (w ¡ x (°)) x 0 (°)
°= : (7.71)
U 0 (w ¡ x (°)) x 0 (°) ¡ E [U 0 (x (°) + °") "]

Since an increase in " reduces U 0 (x (°) + °"), E [U 0 (x (°) + °") "] < 0. From
(7.71) it is then clear that ° lies between 0 and 1. The reason for this …nding
is once again the social insurance role of the income tax. The numerical calcu-
lations presented in Varian (1980) also show that as the degree of risk-aversion
224 CHAPTER 7. RISK

rises so does the level of the marginal rate of tax, an observation which reinforces
the insurance interpretation of the tax system.
In the case of a general nonlinear consumption function, Varian establishes
that the marginal rate of tax must be less than 1, as in the standard income tax
analysis, but that the marginal rate of tax may be non-zero on the household
with the highest value of x + ". The latter result follows from the absence of
the disincentive e¤ect in this framework; high second period income is due to
luck rather than e¤ort.
Diamond, Helms and Mirrlees (1980) also consider an economy where in-
dividuals have a two-period horizon but introduce uncertainty by making the
introducing the possibility that a given individual will be unable to work in the
second period of their life (for instance through ill health). Since the govern-
ment cannot distinguish between those who are unable to work in the second
period and those who choose not to work, there is an additional moral hazard
problem in the creation of social insurance to cover the risk in the second pe-
riod. Numerical simulations for economies based on Cobb-Douglas preferences
show that linear taxation, although having some e¤ect, is of limited value in
providing social insurance.
The analyses of optimal income taxation descried above have fo cused on the
role of income taxation in providing social insurance in economies with uncer-
tainty. The same conclusion arises from each despite the somewhat di¤erent
formulations of the source of uncertainty: the social insurance value of income
taxation outweighs its disincentive e¤ects. Therefore, even when no revenue is
to be raised, social welfare can be increased by the introduction of an optimal
linear income tax. Even when revenue is to be raised, the linear income tax is
preferred to a uniform lump-sum tax for a population of identical households.

7.6.2 Aggregate risk


In the presence of aggregate risk taxation cannot have a social insurance role.
This being the case, the focus is now shifted to the design of a tax system that
is e¢cient in its collection of revenue. To make the situation precise, the single-
household economy of Christiansen (1993) is considered in which the household
allocates an exogenous income between a safe and a risky asset. The incomes
accruing from the two assets are tax at di¤erentiated rates and the aim of the
analysis is to characterise the form of the tax structure. Tax revenue is used to
provide a public good. The aggregate risk is captured in the variable return to
the risky asset. In this framework, taxation a¤ects the division of risk between
private and public consumption.
Denoting the exogenous wealth of the household by - and investment in the
risky asset by a, the consumption level of the household in state s is given by

xs = - + [1 ¡ tr ] r [- ¡ a] + [1 ¡ t» ] »s a (7.72)

where »s is the return to the risky asset in state s and tr ; t» are the tax rates
on the income from the safe and risky asset respectively. The tax rates are
7.6. OPTIMAL TAXATION 225

chosen subject to the constraint that expected government revenue is equal to


expenditure, g, or
E [tr r [- ¡ a] + t»» a] = g: (7.73)
The form of the government budget constraint is not inconsequential with un-
certainty. Expressing it in terms of expected revenue permits variations in the
level of revenue, and hence expenditure, across states of nature. This formula-
tion therefore leaves an element of risk in public consumption. An alternative
would be to …x the level of expenditure, and required revenue, in each state.
This would remove the uncertainty about the level of public consumption. Ex-
cept when utility is linear in public consumption or when there is a large number
of taxpayers with uncorrelated risks so that expected and actual tax revenue
are equal, the speci…cation of the budget constraint will a¤ect the optimal tax
system. Further discussion of this issue can be found in Christiansen (1993).
Assuming that the household’s derives utility from private consumption and
government spending and that the utility function is linear in g, social welfare
is given by

W = E [U (- + [1 ¡ tr ] r [- ¡ a] + [1 ¡ t» ] »s a)] + E [g] : (7.74)

The optimal tax rates are found by maximising (7.74) subject to (7.73).
To characterise the tax rates, …rst note from (7.73) that if expected revenue
is to remain constant, tr and t» are related by
@a
dtr aE [» ] + [t» E [»] ¡ tr r] @ t»
=¡ : (7.75)
dt» r [- ¡ a]

Di¤erentiating (7.75) with respect to t» whilst varying tr so as to keep revenue


constant gives ¸¸
dW 0 dt r
´ ¡E U r [- ¡ a] ¡ »a = 0: (7.76)
dt» dt»
Substituting (7.75) and the …rst-order condition for household portfolio choice

E [U 0 ] [1 ¡ tr ] r
E [U 0» ] = ¡ ; (7.77)
[1 ¡ t» ]

into (7.76) and rearranging, the optimal tax rates satisfy

t» E [»] ¡ tr r 1
= ; (7.78)
[1 ¡ t» ] E [»] ¡ [1 ¡ tr ] r b
a

where ba = [1¡a t»] @t


@a
»
is the elasticity of demand for the risk asset with respect
to [1 ¡ t» ]. The characterisation of optimal taxes in (7.78) is in the form of an
inverse elasticities rule in which the inverse of the elasticity is inversely related
to the ratio of the net tax on the risky asset and the net return on the risky
asset.
226 CHAPTER 7. RISK

7.7 Conclusions
In a competitive economy with complete markets, the presence of uncertainty
does not destroy the Pareto optimality of the equilibrium and suitably in-
terpreted versions of the Two Theorems still apply. Indeed, e¢ciency is still
achieved even if for each state there is only a single asset that has a positive
return in that state. Despite these results there may still be a role for the public
sector in an economy with complete markets if the public sector is able to bear
risk more e¢ciently than the private sector. Whether the public sector should
discount for risk at a lower rate than the private sector has been the subject of
some dispute and alternative perspectives on this issue were presented in Sec-
tion 3. In brief, the treatment of risk by the public sector is dependent upon
the form of the risk that is involved, in the terminology used above whether it
is inside or outside the private sector.
The e¤ects of income and wealth taxation upon portfolio choice were con-
sidered and can be viewed as an example of how taxation a¤ects risk taking.
They also illustrated the manner in which the use of taxation turns the govern-
ment into a partner in a household’s risk-taking activities. This also emphasised
the distinction between private and social risk taking, with social risk entering
through the variability of government revenue. Similar e¤ects were also noted
in the treatment of taxation and labour supply with an uncertain wage and in
the study of occupational choice.
The design of optimal taxes involves issues that do not arise in an economy
with certainty, in particular the speci…cation of the government budget con-
straint and the range of policy tools. Furthermore, in addition to the revenue-
raising and redistributional roles of taxation, there is now the possibility that
taxation can also provide social insurance by transferring from those who are
bene…ting from high random returns to those who are su¤ering low returns. This
e¤ect is su¢ciently strong that a distortionary income tax can raise welfare in
an economy of individuals who are identical except for random components in
their wealth. More interestingly, the optimal linear income tax is preferable to
a uniform lump-sum tax.
Chapter 8

Corporate Taxation

8.1 Introduction
The corporation is treated as a separate entity for tax purposes in all developed
countries. It has been subject to numerous tax instruments with a variety of dif-
ferent motivations. The transfers between the corporation and its stockholders
result in the behaviour of the corporation also being in‡uenced by the structure
of the personal tax system, most notably through the favourable tax treatment
of capital gains. The intention of this chapter is to describe the relevant tax
instruments and to determine their e¤ects. This will give an insight into the
many issues that arise in the analysis of corporate taxation.
This chapter is distinguished from those that proceed it by its focus upon the
e¤ects of taxation rather than upon optimisation exercises. There are several
reasons for this. Input taxes have often been employed in many countries and
the e¤ects of such taxes are important because of this, but it has already been
shown that they would not form part of an optimal tax system for a competi-
tive economy. Therefore there is no need for a further study of optimisation. In
simple settings where shareholders exercise direct control, the corporation can-
not be identi…ed as a entity distinct from its owners. A coherent tax structure
would then involve a comprehensive income tax on owners, covering all sources
of earnings, with no need for separate taxation of the corporation. Although
the e¤ects of corporation taxation are still of interest in such a framework since
they suggest issues that may arise in more complex settings, optimisation is
again of limited interest. When the setting becomes more complex, and the
existence of managers leads to a separation between ownership and control, the
task of clarifying the e¤ects of taxation is di¢cult enough, without considering
optimisation.
The next section will discuss the various taxes to which the corporation
has been subject and will consider the rationale for treating the corporation
as a distinct taxable entity. The incidence of a range of taxes will then be
considered in a two-sector general equilibrium economy. This form of economy

227
228 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

was popular in the 1970s following the work of Harberger (1962) and stills
remains instructive. The incidence results will be derived in the simplest setting
but a number of extensions will also be described. As a tool for studying taxation
of the corporation, the two-sector economy is restricted by its static nature and
its lack of integration with the personal tax system. These features prevent the
study of dividends and bonds and the consequences of preferential tax treatment
of some sources of income. Adopting an intertemporal framework, Section 4 will
consider the e¤ect of taxation upon the policy of the corporation under both
certainty and uncertainty.

8.2 Taxation of the …rm


As has already been noted, the corporation (and the …rm generally) has been
subject to a range of taxes. This section will describe a number of these but
with particular focus placed upon the corporate pro…ts tax. This mirrors the
emphasis upon this tax in the literature. A brief description will also be given
of how the corporate tax system interacts with the personal tax system.

8.2.1 Input and output taxes


The most prevalent form of input tax has been that levied upon the employment
of labour. In the US, the Social Security tax provides a notable example and
the economics of this are discussed further in Chapter 14. National Insurance
payments play a similar role in the UK. Both the Social Security tax and Na-
tional Insurance raise the cost of labour for the employer relative to the price of
capital and other inputs. Another example of a tax on labour is the Selective
Employment Tax which was levied in the UK between 1966 and 1973. The
rate of Selective Employment Tax was sector-speci…c: it taxed employment in
service industries and subsidised it in manufacturing. For further discussion of
the e¤ects of this tax see Reddaway (1970).
Factor subsidies have also been used to promote additional investment. Such
subsidies have the e¤ect of lowering the cost of additional units of capital rel-
ative to labour. These subsidies are often provided in the form of depreciation
allowances but cash subsidies to some forms of investment in de…ned geograph-
ical areas were available under the 1972 Industry Act in the UK. The corporate
pro…ts tax has often been interpreted as a tax on capital in the corporate sector.
This interpretation is explained further in 2.3.
Viewing the provision of …nance as an input to the corporation, there has
also been di¤erential treatment of payment to providers of …nance. Interest
payments to bondholders may be tax deductible for the …rm, in contrast to
dividends which are taxed. Provision of …nance by equity holders may lead to
capital gains which are taxed under the personal tax system at a di¤erent rate
to interest received from bondholdings or from dividends. How these various
provisions a¤ect the choice of …nancial policy for the …rm is investigated in
section 4.
8.2. TAXATION OF THE FIRM 229

The Value Added Tax (VAT) levied by the European Union is essentially a
tax on the output of the …rm. The tax is based on the value added in production.
Alternative taxes on output include production and turnover taxes. In contrast
to the VAT, these are based on the gross output of the …rm rather than its net
output.

8.2.2 Pro…t tax


A tax on corporate pro…ts is levied in all developed countries and is signi…cant
in the level of revenue it raises. Its economic e¤ects have also been extensively
analysed and this will be the focus of much of the analysis below. The discussion
here will simply set the scene and point-up some of the issues that are addressed
below.
With full allowance for capital expenditure, the …rm will optimise, by choice
of capital and labour, the level of after-tax pro…ts given by

¼ = [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [pF (K; L) ¡ wL ¡ rK] ; (8.1)

where ¿ c is the rate of pro…t taxation, p is the product price, r the rental rate on
capital, L the labour employed and K the level of capital. It is clear from (8.1)
that, provided the tax rate is not greater than 100%, the …rm’s optimal choice of
inputs will be una¤ected by the imposition of the tax. In this circumstance, the
pro…t tax will not cause any substitution e¤ects in the pattern of input use by
the …rm. This should not be taken as a claim that the tax is completely without
distortion. Since the …rm’s net of tax pro…t is reduced by the tax, its return
to its owners will fall and this may cause substitution in the asset holdings of
households and changes, for example, in their labour supply.
The results are modi…ed if payments to capital cannot be deducted before
tax. In this case the …rm seeks to maximise

¼ = [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [pF (K; L) ¡ wL] ¡ rK; (8.2)

or equivalently
¼ = [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [pF (K; L) ¡ wL ¡ r³K ] ; (8.3)
1
where ³ = 1¡¿ c
. If the tax rate is positive, the corporation tax raises the price of
capital relative to that of labour. Denoting total tax payments by ¡, assuming
constant returns to scale it follows that

pF (K; L) = wL + rK + ¡; (8.4)

which is the identity that total income must equal total disbursements. Substi-
tuting from (8.4) into (8.2) and using the zero pro…t identity gives

¼ = [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [rK + ¡] ¡ rK = 0; (8.5)

or
¡ = ¿ c rK: (8.6)
230 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

Given (8.6) it can be seen that with constant returns to scale and with the
non-deductibility of capital costs, the corporate pro…ts tax can be seen equally
as a tax on the value of capital use. Indeed, this is the interpretation that has
been adopted in much of the incidence literature that is discussed in section 3.

8.2.3 Personal taxes


The discussion of corporation tax given above provides a starting point for a
more detailed analysis but, because of the form of most tax codes, the corpora-
tion tax cannot be considered in isolation from other aspects of the tax system.
To brie‡y illustrate this consider a …rm about to …nance an extra unit of in-
vestment. This investment can be paid for either from retained earning, from
additional borrowing or from the issue of new equity. The fact that interest on
borrowing may be tax deductible leads to an obvious incentive to borrow rather
than issue equity. Also, the equity holders of the …rm may experience capital
gains and these will be taxed but at a lower rate than dividends. The response
of the …rm to corporation tax cannot then be seen in isolation from the capital
gains tax. Furthermore, dividends may be taxed twice: once as pro…t to the
…rm and then as income for a shareholder. The decision of the …rm in issuing
dividends must then be considered with the corporation tax. Finally, the sta-
tic nature of the analysis does not permit the discussion of investment. The
corporation tax, by a¤ecting …nancial policy, will a¤ect the cost of investment
and this needs to be addressed. Each of these points is addressed in turn in the
remaining sections of the chapter.

8.2.4 Why tax the corporation?


Having made these points about the structure and e¤ects of taxes, there remains
a further issue that must be addressed. This is the reason why the corporation is
taxed at all. If the corporation is seen merely as earning income and transmitting
this to its ultimate owners, then there is no reason why the corporation should
be taxed. Instead, the tax liability should be placed upon its owners alone. Kay
and King (1990) provide a forceful exposition of this viewpoint. This arguments
re‡ects the view that the corporation does not have a personality or existence
of its own other than that given to it in law.
The alternative perspective is that incorporation carries legal and economic
privileges and that the corporation tax is a tax upon the gains enjoyed from
the bene…t of these privileges. Foremost among these privileges is the limited
liability that the shareholders in the corporation enjoy in the event of bank-
ruptcy. Another possible view, and one re‡ected in US Tax Reform Act of 1986
which shifted the tax burden from the personal sector to the corporate sector,
is that corporations can a¤ord to pay taxes and should therefore carry their
share of the burden. There is also the argument, already explored above, that
corporation tax is taxing rent so is a distortion-free way of raising revenue. As
already noted, there are limits to how far this argument can be pushed since it
relies at the very least on the tax being levied on true economic pro…t.
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 231

Ultimately, the e¤ect of a tax depends upon how it a¤ects the individuals
in the economy and the correctness, or otherwise, of taxing the corporation
depends upon the …nal incidence of the tax. If the tax can achieve ob jectives,
and so raise social welfare, that other taxes cannot then there is a justi…cation
for its existence. In a sense, many of the arguments noted above simply direct
attention away from the main justi…cation for introducing any form of taxation,
which is to achieve speci…ed aims. As is always the case in Second-Best theory,
although a policy instrument may have no role in the First-Best, its use may
still be justi…ed in other circumstances.

8.3 Tax incidence


One aspect that has already been stressed in earlier chapters is that the economic
incidence of a tax is rarely the same as the legal incidence. Legal incidence
relates to who has to formally pay the tax to the tax collection agency whereas
economic incidence is identi…ed by the agents who su¤er reduced welfare due
to the imposition of the tax. Since there are general equilibrium repercussions
to any tax change, the identi…cation of economic incidence is not always a
straightforward exercise.
In terms of the corporation tax, Harberger (1962) was the …rst to present
a comprehensive analysis of incidence. The framework employed was that of a
two-sector economy with two factors of production: capital and labour. One
of the sectors of the economy was treated as incorporated and capital in that
sector bore the legal incidence of the corporation tax. This framework permitted
identi…cation of the real e¤ects of the corporation tax in terms of an output
e¤ect, capturing the change in the relative outputs of the two goods, and an
input substitution e¤ect, representing the adjustment of inputs within sectors.
In addition, Harberger also calculated the change in relative factors rewards in
order to determine the economic incidence of the tax in terms of whether the
tax burden fell on capital or labour.
In the period since its publication, the Harberger analysis has been subject to
many extensions and modi…cations, many of which are detailed in the surveys of
Mieszkowski (1969) and McLure (1975). The analysis of this section will describe
the Harberger economy and show how this can be employed to derive results on
the incidence of the corporation tax and a range of other tax instruments. Some
of the extensions will then be described. The analytical technique used to solve
the incidence question follows closely the original development of Harberger
(1962) and its description in Shoven and Whalley (1972).

8.3.1 Tax incidence in the Harberger economy


The Harberger economy is competitive with two goods, denoted 1 and 2, and
two factors of production, capital and labour. The factors of production are in
…xed supply. The initial equilibrium for the economy is de…ned in the absence
of taxation and the e¤ect of introducing in…nitesimal taxes is then considered.
232 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

This point must be stressed since it has not always been clari…ed in some of the
literature. The extension of the analysis to …nite taxes is described in 3.2.1.
To simplify the analysis by eliminating income e¤ects, it is assumed that the
government spends the tax revenue it receives in the same way that consumers
would have done in the absence of taxes. In conjunction with the fact that taxes
are in…nitesimal, this implies that income does not need to be considered as a
determinant of demand. The demand for good 1 is further assumed to depend
only upon the ratio of consumers prices or
µ ¶
q1
X1 = X1 : (8.7)
q2
Since demand is determined by the price ratio, the underlying utility function
must be homothetic; see Rapanos (1991). Denoting the compensated elasticity
of demand by ", total di¤erentiation of (8.7) gives
³ ´
q1
dX1 d q2
= " q1 : (8.8)
X1 q2

The elasticity appearing in (8.8) is compensated since the marginal propen-


sities to consume of households and government are assumed equal so that the
income e¤ect in government demand exactly o¤sets that in consumer demand.
This leaves only the substitution e¤ect. Units of measurement of the commodi-
ties are chosen so that the initial consumer prices are equal to unity. Equation
(8.8) can then be approximated by
dX1
= " [dq1 ¡ dq2 ] : (8.9)
X1
Production in sector i is determined by the di¤erentiable and homogeneous
of degree 1 production function

Xi = F i (Ki ; Li) : (8.10)

Total di¤erentiation of the production relation (8.10) gives

@F i @F i
dXi = dK i + dLi; (8.11)
@Ki @Li
which can be divided by Xi to read
dXi i
= fK dKi + fLi dLi; (8.12)
Xi
where
@Fi
i
K
@K i i
fK = (8.13)
Xi
is the relative share of capital in output (or the partial elasticity of output with
respect to capital) and f Li is de…ned similarly.
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 233

Let b
ri be the price paid by users of capital in sector i and wbi be the price paid
for labour. The de…nition of the elasticity of substitution, si, between inputs
then implies ³ ´ ³ ´
Ki ri
b
d Li d w
bi
Ki
= si ri
b
: (8.14)
Li w
bi
The set of input taxes that are to be considered include sector-speci…c taxes
and general taxes on capital and labour. Incorporating these taxes into factor
prices and taking an approximation linearises (8.14) to
dK i dLi
¡ = si [dr + dT K1 + dT K ¡ dw ¡ dT L1 ¡ dT L ] (8.15)
Ki Li
where r is the price received by owners of capital, T K1 the sector-speci…c tax on
capital and T K the general tax on capital. The notation is interpreted similarly
for the taxes T L1 and T L on labour. Units of measurement are also chosen for
inputs so that initial prices are unity. Given this, the tax rates can be interpreted
as being either be ad valorem or speci…c since, for example, the di¤erential of
r [1 + TK1 ] equals dr + dTK1 when r = 1 and T K1 = 0 which is equal to the
derivative of r + T K1 .
The assumptions of competitive behaviour and homogeneity of the produc-
tion functions imply that factor payments are equal to revenue in both sectors.
Hence
pi Xi = w
b i Li + b
riKi ; (8.16)
which when totally di¤erentiated gives
pi dXi + Xi dpi = w
bidLi + Li dwbi + b
ridKi + Ki db
ri : (8.17)

Pro…t-maximising input choice equates the marginal revenue product of the


input to its price so
@F i ri
b
= ; (8.18)
@Ki pi
and
@F i w
bi
= : (8.19)
@Li pi
Substituting (8.18) and (8.19) into (8.11) gives
w
bi rbi
dXi = dLi + dK i: (8.20)
pi pi
Given (8.20), (8.17) reduces to
Li Ki
dp i = dwbi + db
ri : (8.21)
Xi Xi
As initial input prices are unity, (8.13) and (8.18) imply that at the initial
i
equilibrium fK = K
Xi
i
and (8.20) that f Li = X
Li
i
. Hence (8.21) becomes

dp i = fLi dwbi + f K
i
db
ri : (8.22)
234 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

Incorporating taxes (8.22) can be written

dp i = fLi [dw + dT Li + dT L ] + fK
i
[dr + dT Ki + dTK ] + dT c i + dT c ; (8.23)

where Tc i is the sector-speci…c consumption tax and T c the general consumption


tax.
This completes the initial derivations. The solution for the e¤ect of the
introduction of the taxes into the economy is given by equations (8.9), (8.12),
(8.15) and (8.23). These equations will shortly be solved but …rst a preliminary
result is given that shows how various sets of taxes are equivalent in the sense
that they have the same e¤ect upon the equilibrium. This result is stated as
Theorem ??.

Theorem 39 When levied at the same rate the following equivalencies hold:
(i) T Ki and T Li to Tc i ; i = 1; 2;
(ii) T K and T L to T c ;
and
(iii) T c1 and T c2 to T c :

Proof. To prove (i) it is …rst noted that taxes only appear in (8.15) and
(8.23). When introduced at the same rate, dT Ki = dT Li , and the taxes cancel
from (8.15). From Euler’s theorem f Li + fK I
= 1 so that from (8.23) the increases
in dT Ki and dTL i are equivalent to an equal increase in dT c i. This establishes
that the e¤ect of raising dT Ki and dTL i is identical to that of raising dTc i :
The same argument applies to show the equivalence of T K and T L to Tc ,
where it must be noted that the change in rates a¤ects both sectors. Finally
(iii) is proved by noting that the tax changes involved only a¤ect (8.23).
The explanation lying behind (i) of Theorem 13.1 is that the pair of tax
changes T Ki and TL i together raise the price of factors equally for sector i, so
that no substitution between factors occurs. The consequent increase in costs
has the same e¤ect upon the equilibrium as a consumption tax T ci . In the case
of (ii), the pair of taxes raises the price of inputs equally in both sectors and so
is equivalent to a general consumption tax. The same general reasoning applies
to the pair of consumption taxes in (iii).
The equivalence demonstrated in Theorem 8.1 shows that only a restricted
set of taxes need be considered. To maintain the focus upon corporation tax-
ation, the taxes upon labour will now be set at zero. In addition, the general
consumption tax will not be considered. In the present context with no saving
and …xed labour supply, the general consumption tax is equivalent to an income
tax. A change in its value leads only to an income e¤ect and not a substitution
e¤ect so that it is of limited interest as a source of ine¢ciency. Due to the equiv-
alence result, it is also assumed that dT c 2 = 0. To understand the reason for the
…nal restriction, it is best to return to the original motivation for the analysis.
Harberger (1962) was concerned with the distortion that would arise through
the taxation of capital in the corporate sector while capital in the non-corporate
sector remained untaxed. Under this interpretation, only one of the two sectors
should bear a corporation tax. Correspondingly, it is assumed that sector 1 can
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 235

be treated as incorporated but sector 2 cannot. Hence the capital tax in sector
2, dT K2 ; is set at zero. Finally, the wage rate is chosen as numeraire so that
dw = 0 throughout.
Adopting these restrictions and substituting (13.23) for i = 1; 2 into (13.9)
provides

dX1 £ 1 2
¤
= " fK [dr + dT K1 + dT K ] + dT c1 ¡ f K dr : (8.24)
X1
Equating (8.24) to (8.12) and rearranging
£ 2 1
¤ 1 dK1 dL1 £ 1 ¤
" fK ¡ fK dr + f K + fL1 = " fK [dTK1 + dT K ] + dT c 1 : (8.25)
K1 L1
Since the supply of factors is …xed, it follows that dK 2 = ¡dK1 and dL2 = ¡dL1 .
Employing these facts, (8.15) for i = 2 can be transformed to
K 1 dK1 L1 dL1
s2 dr + ¡ = 0; (8.26)
K2 K1 L2 L1
and for i = 1 rearrangement of (8.15) gives
dK1 dL1
¡s 1 dr + ¡ = s1 dTK1 + s 1 dT K : (8.27)
K1 L1
Taken together, (8.25), (8.26) and (8.27) provide a three-equation system deter-
mining the dependence of the endogenous variables dr, dK 1 and dL1 upon the
tax changes dT K1 , dT K and dTc 1 .
Taking the sector-speci…c capital tax …rst, it follows from the solution of the
system that
¸ ¸¸
dr 1 K1 L1 1 L1 K1
= "fK ¡ + s1 f K + f L1 A; (8.28)
dTK1 K2 L2 L2 K2
where
¸ ¸¸¡1
£ 2 1
¤ K1 L1 1 L1 K1
A = " fK ¡ fK ¡ ¡ s2 ¡ s1 f K + f L1 : (8.29)
K2 L2 L2 K2
To interpret (8.28) it is …rst necessary to establish that A is positive. To
see this, note that ", s1 and s 2 are negative. Now if sector 2 is relatively
2 1
capital intensive then f K > fK and KK2
1
< L 1
L2
. The converse inequalities apply
if sector 1 is the most capital intensive. In either case the product of the two
terms is negative thus ensuring A is positive. The next point to note is that
since it has been assumed that dw = 0, a negative value of dr implies that
the imposition of the tax reduces the return to capital relative to that of labour
whilst a positive value indicates an increase in the relative return of capital. The
input substitution and output e¤ects of the tax can clearly be seen in (8.28).
The output e¤ect is determined by the elasticity of demand whilst the input
substitution e¤ect is dependent upon value of the elasticity of substitution.
Given these preliminaries, the next theorem follows from (8.28).
236 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

Theorem 40 (i) dTdrK can only be positive if sector 1 is more capital intensive
1
than sector 2;
(ii) If js1 j > j"j then dTdrK < 0;
1
dr
(iii) As js2 j increases without limit, dTK1 tends to zero;
K1 K2 ¡K 1
(iv) Assume L1 = L2 . Then if js 1 j = js2 j, it follows that dr
dTK1 = K1 +K 2
¡K 1
and capital bears the full burden of the tax. If js1 j > js2 j ; then dr
dTK1 > K1 +K 2
¡K 1
and if js1 j < js2 j ; then dr
dTK1< K 1+K 2 ;
(v) If js1 j = js2 j = 0, then the incidence of the tax depends only on factor
proportions.
h i
K1
Proof. (i) In (13.28), only the term "f K 1
K2
¡L 1
L2
can be positive. Hence
for dTdrK > 0 it is necessary that K K2
1
¡L 1
L2
< 0, which is the condition that sector
1
1 is more labour intensive.
1 L1 1 L1 dr
(ii) If js1 j > j"j then s1 f K L2 ¡ "f K L 2 < 0 so dTK1 < 0.
(iii) This follows from observing that s 2 only appears in the denominator of
(8.28) so, all else equal, an increase in s2 reduces the absolute value of dTdrK .
1
(iv) The expressions are obvious after substitution. Their interpretation
follows from noting that the total tax burden is K1 dT K1 so if the price of capital
net of tax falls by dr = ¡ K1K+K 1
2
dT K1 , then capital has borne the entire tax.
(v) From substitution.
It is the calculations of (iv) of Theorem 8.2 that describe the means of cal-
culating the economic incidence of the tax. Since a value of dr = ¡ K1K+K 1
2
dT K1
implies that capital bears the entire burden of the tax, incidence can be deter-
mined by contrasting this with the value of dTdrK given by (8.28). If the value in
1
(8.28) is higher then labour is also carrying some of the burden of the tax. What
(iv) achieves is to provide the answer to the incidence question under a speci…c
set of assumptions. Following the same line of enquiry, Harberger substituted
into (8.28) employing values from empirical studies in the US and reached the
conclusion that capital generally bears the entire tax burden. The value of this
conclusion is naturally restricted by the assumptions made about the economy
in which it is derived. Much of the work following Harberger was concerned
with testing the result under alternative assumptions. Some of this work will
be described in Section 3.2.
Returning to the analysis of the present economy, it can easily be calculated
that the introduction of the capital tax in sector 1 reduces employment of capital
in that sector. The e¤ect upon labour use in sector 1 is given by
¸ ¸
dL1 1 1 K1 £ 2 ¤ K1
= L1 s 1 s2 fK ¡ "f K s2 + s 1 ¡ s1 " f K ¡ f L1 A: (8.30)
dT K1 K2 K2
In general, the change in labour use cannot be signed because of the con‡icting
input substitution and output e¤ects but (8.30) permits the e¤ect of various
sets of restrictions on the elasticity of demand and elasticity of substitution
to be tested. As an example, when the elasticity of demand is zero, labour
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 237

demand in sector 1 increases as labour is substituted for capital. The e¤ect of


the sector-speci…c output tax upon the return to capital is
¸
dr K1 L1
=" ¡ A; (8.31)
dT c 1 K2 KL2

so that whenever the elasticity of demand is non-zero the change in the price of
capital depends entirely upon the relative capital intensity of sector 1.
These results are intended to be indicative of what can be achieved in the
context of the two-sector Harberger economy. Although only a limited number of
taxes have been considered here, the same methods can determine the incidence
e¤ect of a broad range of tax instruments. However, the assumptions of the
economy are rather restrictive and more is to be gained by relaxing these than
by extending the set of taxes.

8.3.2 Extensions
Since the publication of Harberger (1962), many extensions of the analysis have
been completed. Included among these are studies that have simply addressed
the same issues but under alternative assumptions and others that have applied
the analysis, often under very similar assumptions, to di¤erent issues. A survey
of the latter, which will not be covered here, can be found in McLure (1975).
In addition, Jones (1965, 1971) and McLure (1974) have developed alternative
analytical techniques for studying the Harberger economy. The extensions that
are now discussed are those that modify the structure of the Harberger economy
in order to relax the restrictiveness of its assumptions.

Income e¤ects

The discussion of the demand function (8.7) described how income e¤ects were
eliminated by the assumptions that in…nitesimal taxes were introduced from an
initial position with no taxation and that the government spent the tax revenue
in the same way as consumers. This assumption has been relaxed in two ways.
Mieszkowski (1967) considered demand to be derived from two distinct groups of
consumers whilst Ballentine and Eris (1975) retain the Harberger speci…cation
but incorporate income e¤ects for non-in…nitesimal tax changes.
The consumers in Mieszkowski (1967) are comprised of workers, who earn
income from the supply of labour, and capitalists, who receive the return from
capital. In such a framework, a number of anomalies may arise when compared
to the standard Harberger analysis. For instance, when these two groups have
very divergent spending propensities and the elasticities of substitution in pro-
duction are small, a tax on capital in the capital intensive sector may increase
demand for that sector’s commodity and increase the price of capital relative
to labour. Since the same general principals are involved, this analysis also
suggests the possibilities that would arise if the government did not spend its
revenue in the same way as consumers.
238 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

Ballentine and Eris (1975) write the underlying demand function as


X1 = X1 (q1 ; q2 ; rK + L + rtK1 K1 ) ; (8.32)
where rK + L is the income of consumers and rtK1 K1 the revenue of the gov-
ernment from the tax on capital in sector 1. The dependence of demand on
total income implies the assumption that government and consumer spending
patterns are identical. Taking the total derivative of (8.32) gives
¸
dX1 dq1 dq2 m
=" ¡ + [[K + tK1 K1 ] dr + rK1 dtK1 ¡ X1 dq1 ¡ X2 dq2 ] ;
X1 q1 q2 X1
(8.33)
where m is the marginal propensity to consume good 1. Solving the system
with (8.9) replaced by (8.33) gives the result

dr 1 + tK1 "£K1 A + s1 B ¡ mq1 C£ K1s 1 L1


L2
= h i; (8.34)
r dtK1 " [£ K2 ¡ £K1 ] A ¡ s1 B ¡ s2 + mq1 C £K1 s1 L1
+ s
L2 2

r[ 1+tKi ]K i K1
where £ Ki = q iXi , A= K2 ¡L K1 L1
L2 , B = £L1 K 2 + £K 1 L2 , £L1 =
1 wL1
q1X 1 and
tK1
C= 1+tK1 .
The value of (8.34) is that it permits the incorporation of …nite taxes into
the analysis. For zero initial taxes, it reduces to (8.28). It follows from (8.34)
that when sector 1 is capital intensive, capital will bear more of the burden of
any …nite tax than labour (i.e. dr < 0). This extends (i) of Theorem 8.2 to
…nite initial taxes. Similarly (iii) and (v) of Theorem 8.2 extend to …nite taxes
but (ii) and (iv) do not. In addition, (8.34) shows that if s1 = s2 = ¡1 and
the elasticity of substitution in consumption, ¾ , also equals - 1, then the fall in
payment to capital due to the tax exactly equals government revenue. To see
this, note that the homotheticity of demand implies
q1 X1
mq1 = ; (8.35)
q1 X1 + q2 X2
and
q2 X2
"= : (8.36)
[q1 X1 + q2 X2 ] ¾
With these restrictions, (8.34) reduces to
dr 1 + tK1 K1
=¡ ; (8.37)
r dtK1 K
so
dr dr 1 + tK1 r rK
K= =¡ : (8.38)
dtK1 r dtK1 1 + tK1 1 + tK1
The e¤ect of the tax change upon government revenue, R = rtK1 K1 , is
dR dr dK
= rK1 + tK1 K1 + t K 1r (8.39)
dtK1 dtK1 dtK1
¸
dr 1 + tK1 rtK1 K s2 L1 s1 rtK1 K L 1s 1
= rK1 + 1¡ ¡ ¡ (8.40)
:
r dtK1 1 + tK1 A L2 A 1 + tK1 L2 A
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 239

Substituting into (8.39) using (8.37) and the restriction that s1 = s2 = 1 gives
dR rK
=¡ ; (8.41)
dtK1 1 + tK1
thus demonstrating that the fall in income to capital is equal to government
revenue.

Imperfect competition
Monopoly was …rst intro duced into the analysis by Harberger in the original 1962
article. This was achieved by including a mark-up, representing the presence
of some monopoly element, in the pricing equation for sector 1. Doing this for
i = 1, (8.23) becomes
£ ¤
dqi = f Li [dw + dTL i + dTL ] + f K
i
[dr + dT Ki + dT K ] + dT ci + dT c [1 + ¹] ;
(8.42)
where ¹ is the monopoly mark-up. Although this is a straightforward method of
incorporating imperfect competition, it is not entirely persuasive since it omits
the optimisation of …rms in the determination of the mark-up. In addition,
it also changes the nature of the sector-speci…c tax on capital. It was argued
in Section 2 that this could be viewed as a corporation tax in a competitive
economy with constant returns to scale. The introduction of a mark-up in the
pricing equation now implies the existence of pure pro…ts which, in turn, prevent
this interpretation of the sector-speci…c capital tax.
With the monopoly mark-up included, the e¤ect of the capital tax upon the
return to capital is given by
¸ ¸¸
dr 1 K1 L1 1 L1 1 K1 b
= "f K [1 + ¹] ¡ + s1 f K + fL A; (8.43)
dT K1 K2 L2 L2 K2
where
¸ ¸¸¡ 1
£ 2 ¤ K1 L1 1 L1 K1
b = " fK
A 1
¡ fK [1 + ¹] ¡ ¡ s 2 ¡ s1 f K + f L1 (8.44)
K2 L2 L2 K2
Comparison of (8.42) - (8.43) with (8.28) - (8.29) shows that the inclusion of
the monopoly mark-up does not a¤ect in any fundamental way the content of
Theorem 8.2.
An alternative formulation of imperfect competition is given in Atkinson
and Stiglitz (1980) but this is based on a particular speci…cation of monopolis-
tic competition with a precise functional form for utility. Although instructive,
it is not able to address the full range of issues associated with imperfect com-
petition. A more general presentation of monopolistic competition is given and
Anderson and Ballentine (1976). They conclude that the existence of imperfect
competition does not much alter the incidence of taxation, concurring with the
…ndings of Harberger (1962), and that compared to the competitive case, im-
perfect competition ampli…es the welfare loss caused by the introduction of a
distortionary taxation.
240 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

In contrast to these static analyses, Davidson and Martin (1985) study a


dynamic economy in which collusion can arise in the repeated game played by
the imperfectly competitive …rms. The output level in the collusive equilibrium
is partly determined by the need to make deviation from the collusive level an
unpro…table strategy. Deviation is rewarded by increased pro…ts in the period
in which it takes place followed by reduced pro…ts in all future periods as the
…rms switch to punishment strategies. Full details of this form of equilibrium
can be found in Friedman (1977). Whether deviation is pro…table then depends
on the rate at which future pro…ts are discounted. In fact, as the discount rate
rises so must the collusive output level. The relation of this to the incidence
of capital taxation is due to the fact that the …rms will use the net return to
capital, r, as the discount rate. The corporation tax then a¤ects r in the manner
already analysed above and this e¤ect then leads, via changes in the collusive
output level, to changes in other factor and product prices. Consequently, even
though capital may be in …xed supply, a general tax on capital which applies
to all sectors is shifted rather than absorbed by capital because of the e¤ect of
the discount rate on the collusive equilibrium output level.

Intermediate goods

The main e¤ect of the introduction of intermediate goods into the Harberger
economy is to increase the possibilities for substitution between inputs. Unless
the technology is Leontief with …xed input coe¢cients, these substitution pos-
sibilities modify the conclusions on tax incidence. In a series of papers, Bhatia
(1981, 1982a, 1982b, 1986) has addressed these issues.
In an economy where there is a single intermediate good which is not used
for …nal consumption, Bhatia (1981) shows that (i), (iii) and (v) of Theorem
8.2 still apply to the extended economy but the (ii) cannot be proved in the
presence of intermediate goods. In addition to this, it is also proved that when
factor proportions in the …nal goods industries are the same, an increase in
the sector-speci…c capital tax will burden capital relatively more than labour
so long as capital and labour, and capital and the intermediate good, are not
complementary to each other in the taxed sector. Bhatia (1982b) considers
the contrast between a corporation tax and a VAT. It is shown that neither of
these tax instruments a¤ects relative prices if input coe¢cients are …xed and
the elasticity of demand is zero. When input coe¢cients are variable, only a
VAT applied at an equal rate to all industries is neutral.

8.3.3 Taxation and …nance


An important issue in the study of corporate taxation is the question of how
the tax system a¤ects the …nancing of a …rm and the investment plans of the
…rm. To …nance investment, a …rm has three sources of …nance. The …rm can
issue new equity, it can issue bonds or it can employ retained earnings. The
issue of new equity makes the …rm liable for future dividend payments, but does
not commit the …rm to any speci…c level of payment, whereas bonds involve a
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 241

…xed commitment to pay interest and, eventually, to redeem the bonds. A pro…t-
maximising …rm will naturally wish to choose the mix of these three instruments
that …nance the investment at minimum cost. Furthermore, the extent of future
investment will in turn be determined by the cost of …nance, usually referred to
as the cost of capital. The focus is therefore upon how the tax system in‡uences
the means of …nance and the cost of capital.
Most of the issues involved can be treated adequately under the assumption
of certainty with all agents in the economy fully informed of the future prospects
of the …rm. However, the assumption of certainty does imply some restrictions.
With certainty, there can be no possibility of any …rm becoming bankrupt since
such a …rm would simply not operate. In contrast, in an economy with uncer-
tainty there may be some states of nature in which a …rm is unable to meet its
obligations, essentially the contratual payments to bondholders, and therefore
has to go into bankruptcy. The consequences of this will be discussed further
below. A second issue that arises in the presence of uncertainty is that of the
objective of the …rm. In an economy with certainty, there will be unanimous
agreement of the shareholders that the …rm should maximise its pro…ts. This
need not be the case with uncertainty if there are incomplete markets. Gener-
ally, the problem facing the …rm is that of aggregating the diverse preferences of
its shareholders into a single objective. One possible resolution of this problem
has already been noted in Section 3 of Chapter 7. The issues that arise with
uncertainty have not been fully resolved and this limits what can be said about
the e¤ects of taxation.
The following section will discuss the essential aspects of the tax system that
will be analysed. The di¤erential tax treatment of di¤erent forms of transfer
from the corporate to the private sector imply that the analysis must involve
an integrated treatment of both corporate and personal taxation. The e¤ects of
taxation are then derived under the assumption of certainty with an emphasis
upon the …nancial decisions of the …rm. Uncertainty will then be introduced
and the Modigliani-Miller theorem proved. Some further aspects of taxation
will then be discussed.

8.3.4 Systems of corporate and personal taxation


The tax system that is now described is commonly termed the classical system
and is in use in the US and many other countries. This is to be distinguished
for the imputation system used in the UK and the two-rate system ; these are
described later.
The motivation behind the classical system is that the corporate tax is a tax
on the bene…ts that follow from incorporation. As such, the tax liability of the
corporation is treated as entirely distinct from that of the shareholders of the
company. Consequently, pro…ts are taxed at the rate set for corporation tax,
dividends are taxed at the personal income tax rate applicable to the sharehold-
ers who receive them, as is interest received by the bondholders of the …rm, and
a separate rate applies to capital gains which is levied on realisation of those
gains. Interest paid by the …rm is tax-deductible. Many of the consequences
242 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

of this tax system with respect to corporate …nance follow from the distortions
introduced by the di¤erential tax treatment of dividends and interest payments.
In what follows, the rate of corporation tax will be denoted ¿ c , dividends are
taxed at the personal rate ¿ p and capital gains at the rate ¿ g . To re‡ect the
reality of tax codes, it is assumed that ¿ g < ¿ p .
One of the perceived di¢culties of the classical system is the double taxation
of dividends: they are taxed once as corporate pro…t and then again as personal
income. The imputation system represents an attempt to avoid this double
taxation by integrating the corporate and personal tax systems. It does this by
giving each shareholder a credit for the tax paid by the company on the pro…t
out of which dividends are paid. In essence, any pro…ts distributed as dividends
are deemed to have already been subject to personal tax at what is known as the
rate of imputation. The shareholder receiving the dividend is then only liable
for the di¤erence between the rate of imputation and their personal tax rate. In
the UK the rate of imputation is equal to the standard rate of tax. A further
alternative system that has been employed in the UK and in West Germany
and Japan is the two-rate system. Under this system di¤erent tax rates apply
to distributed and undistributed pro…ts with the latter being taxed at a higher
rate. This is designed to partly o¤set the double taxation of dividends inherent
in the classical system. King (1977) provides further discussion of alternative
systems of corporation tax.

8.3.5 Finance and investment with certainty


The study of the e¤ect of taxation upon the corporation has gradually de-
veloped from the initial static analysis of Stiglitz (1973, 1976) and King (1975)
through to fully intertemporal presentations such as Auerbach (1979) and Brad-
ford (1981). Results derived in a static setting can be instructive but are unable
to capture many aspects of the problem. For example, one of the notable features
of the personal tax system is the favourable treatment of capital gains relative
to other sources of income but, since capital gains are essentially intertemporal
in nature, this aspect cannot be capture in a static framework. The same can
be said of the more general fact that the value of the …rm is determined by
the ‡ow of funds it provides to the household sector. The approach taken here
will be to fo cus entirely upon the intertemporal analysis originally developed in
Auerbach (1979) and extended in Auerbach and King (1983).
To motivate the approach taken to the analysis of corporation taxation, it is
worth …rst looking at the investment decision in a simple two-period economy.
Consider a …rm that is entirely owned by a single household. Assume that the
…rm can undertake an investment project which requires the input of 1 unit
of the economy’s single commodity. Under what conditions should the …rm
make the investment? If the household faces a price ratio of pp12 = 1 + r for
consumption in the present period (good 1) against consumption in the future
period (good 2) and can lend or borrow as it likes at interest rate r, then the …rm
should undertake the investment project if the return in units of consumption
in period 2 is greater than 1 + r. If this inequality is satis…ed then the …rm
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 243

is able to provide, via the investment pro ject, units of good 2 more cheaply
than the consumer can purchase them on the market. E¤ectively, undertaking
the investment expands the budget set of the …rm’s owner. Furthermore, since
the household will be maximising utility subject to the intertemporal budget
constraint, the rate of interest will also be equal to the household’s personal
rate of time preference.
In this context, the interest rate is termed the cost of capital and plays a
key role in determining the choice of investment projects. The conclusion of
the example illustrates a general truth about the investment decision: the …rm
should undertake any investment that gives a rate of return of at least the
rate of interest. In addition, the …rm should continue making investments until
the marginal investment just achieves the rate of interest. These observations
underline the role played by the cost of capital and are now applied to the
analysis of corporate and personal taxation. Further discussion of the cost of
capital from this perspective can be found in Auerbach (1983) who also considers
the e¤ect of imperfections in capital markets.

No personal taxes
The problem of …rm …nancial policy and investment strategy in the presence
of a corporation tax is …rst approached in the absence of personal taxes. The
analysis assumes that the …rm can …nance future investment through either
issuing new equity, by issuing bonds or through the use of retained earnings.
The timing of transactions is as follows. At the beginning of each period the
…rm distributes dividends to the shareholders of the previous period, it pays
interest on its debt and repays the principal (the bonds issued by the …rm are
assumed to have a term of 1 period) and sells new shares ex-dividend. Interest
payments are tax deductible for the …rm. The actions of the …rm in period t
are chosen so as to maximise the wealth of those who hold shares in the …rm at
the beginning of period t. The construction that follows determines the level of
wealth and its dependency upon the structure of the tax system.
At the beginning of period t the …rm chooses an investment policy, a debt
policy and an equity policy. Together these determine its dividend policy. An
investment policy is characterised by the set of cash ‡ows that arise as a result
of the investment rather than by looking directly at the investment itself. Such
an investment policy is denoted by a vector z = (zt; z t+1 ; zt+2 ; :::) where zt is the
…rm’s cash ‡ow at the beginning of period t net of corporation tax. Since bonds
have a term of 1 period, a bond policy, B = (Bt; Bt+1 ; Bt+ 2 ; :::), describes both
the number of bonds that will be issued in each period and the¡ total stock of debt¢
of the …rm in that period. An equity policy is denoted V n = V tn ; V t+1 n n
; V t+2 ; :::
n
with each V t being the value of new equity sold at the start of t. It follows that
these policies imply the dividend policy through the identity
n
Dt = zt+1 + Bt+1 + V t+1 ¡ [1 + it [1 ¡ ¿ c ]] Bt ; (8.45)

where Dt is the value of dividends paid at the beginning of period t + 1 to the


shareholders of period t and i t is the interest rate paid to bondholders.
244 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

After the payments of dividends in period t, the value of the …rm’s equity
is denoted V to . Following the sale of new equity the value of the total sto ck of
equity is
V t = V to + V tn : (8.46)

In period s ¸ t, some of the dividends paid will go to equity issued before the
beginning of t whilst the remainder will be received by holders of equity issued
from t onwards. The proportion of equity in period s that is in existence before
the beginning of t is
£ ¤
¹st = [1 ¡ ´ t] 1 ¡ ´ t+1 ::: [1 ¡ ´ s] ; (8.47)

Vn
with ´ t = Vtt . In an e¢cient market, the value of the …rm will equal the
discounted value of future dividends. Hence, letting ½t be the discount rate
applied by equity holders, the value of the equity at the beginning of t is
1
" s #
X Y ¡1
o
Vt = [1 + ½u ] ¹stDs : (8.48)
s= t u=t

Now noting that (8.46) and (8.47) can be used to write

1 ¡ ´t £ ¤
V to = o
Dt + Vt+ 1 ; (8.49)
1 + ½t

and from (8.45)


1 + ½t o
V = [1 + ½t] V t ; (8.50)
1 ¡ ´t t
it follows that
o
½t V t = Dt + V t+1 ¡ Vt : (8.51)

The …rm aims to maximise the wealth of existing shareholders and this
wealth is given by
W to = V to + Dt¡ 1 ; (8.52)

which after substituting from (8.44) and (8.45) is equal to

Wto = Vt + z t + B t ¡ [1 + i t¡1 [1 ¡ ¿ c ]] Bt¡1 : (8.53)

As the last term of (8.52) is pre-determined at t, maximising W to is equivalent


to maximising
c o = V t + zt + Bt :
W (8.54)
t

The …rm therefore acts to maximise the sum of security market value (equity
plus bonds) plus current cash ‡ow. From (8.50)

1
Vt = [V t+1 + At ] ; (8.55)
1 + ½t
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 245

where At = Dt ¡ V t+1
n , which on solving for V gives
t

1
" s #
X Y ¡1
Vt = [1 + ½u ] As : (8.56)
s=t u= t

The result in (8.55) shows that the value of the …rm is independent of the
level of dividends and new equity issues. From the de…nition of At it can be seen
that a one unit increase in dividends …nanced by a unit increase in the value of
new equity has no e¤ect on the value of the …rm, nor has an equal reduction in
both. In particular, the …rm has no reason to sell new equity in order to pay
increased dividends.
Assuming that no new equity is issued, so V t+1
n = 0; rearranging (8.54) and

adding to both sides gives

V t [1 + ½t] + Bt + it Bt [1 ¡ ¿ c ] = Vt+ 1 + Dt + Bt+ 1 ¡ Bt+1 + Bt + it Bt [1 ¡ ¿ c ] :


(8.57)
Using the de…nition of the dividend in (8.44) to replace Dt , (8.56) becomes

V t [1 + ½t ] + B t + i t Bt [1 ¡ ¿ c ] = V t+1 + B t+1 + zt ; (8.58)

or
Vt+ 1 + Bt+1 + zt
B t + Vt = ; (8.59)
1 + b ti t [1 ¡ ¿ c ] + [1 ¡ bt ] ½t
where b t = BtB+tVt is the leverage of the …rm. Combining (8.58) with (8.53)
relates the level of shareholder wealth in two consecutive periods by

cto = zt + [1 + rt ]¡ 1 c
W o
Wt+1 ; (8.60)

with rt = b t it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] + [1 ¡ b t ] ½t. The interpretation of rt is that this is now


the cost of capital for the …rm since it is the weighted average rate of return that
has to be paid for …nance. The weights are determined by the present …nancial
structure of the …rms in terms of its leverage. When the …rm can exercise choice
over its …nancial structure it will aim to minimise rt ; more will be said about
this shortly. Solving (8.59) under the assumption that there is convergence
1
" s¡1 #
X Y
c
W o = zt + [1 + ru ]
¡1
zs : (8.61)
t
s=t+1 u=t

From (8.60) it can be seen that the wealth of shareholders is equal to the present
value of future after tax cash ‡ows discounted using the cost of capital derived
above and it is this that the …rm’s policy should be chosen to maximise.
In considering the choice between bond …nanced investment and investment
via the sale of new equity, it should be noted that both these policies keep the
stream of cash ‡ows constant. Their only e¤ect is felt through the change in the
cost of capital and the …rm should choose b t to minimise rt . Assuming that the
…rm takes ½t and it as parametric, when the rates of return on bond and equity
246 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

di¤er there is no general presumption about the nature of the choice and the
outcome is dependent upon the corporation tax rate. However, in the central
case in which the rates of return are equal, bond …nancing is always preferred.
This reasoning is summarised as Theorem 8.3

Theorem 41 (i) If it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] > ½t then it is optimal to choose b t = 0 so …nance


is by equity alone;
(ii) If it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] = ½t then the …rm is indi¤erent about the value of b t ;
(iii) If it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] < ½t then it is optimal to choose bt = 1 so …nance is by
bonds alone.
In particular, if it = ½t then bond …nancing is preferred if ¿ c > 0 and the
…rm is indi¤erent about its …nancial policy if ¿ c = 0.

Proof. All these results follow from di¤erentiating the de…nition of rt . Doing
this gives
@rt
= i t [1 ¡ ¿ c ] ¡ ½t: (8.62)
@b t
When this is non-zero a corner solutions follows. If it is zero, indi¤erence arises.

The results in Theorem 8.3 encompass several of the most well known …nd-
ings in the study of corporation taxation and its e¤ects upon …nancing. The
conclusion that the …rm is indi¤erent about its …nancial policy in the absence
of taxation is the Modigliani-Miller theorem applied to the case of certainty. It
will be shown in Section 4.3 how this can be extended to the case of uncertainty.
The superiority of bond …nancing over equity …nancing when the discount rates
are equal is usually attributed to Stiglitz (1973). As the theorem shows, this
preference for bond …nancing is entirely due to the preferential treatment of
bonds under the corporation tax.

Integration with personal taxes

The analysis developed above can be easily modi…ed to incorporate the provi-
sions of the personal tax system provided that it is assumed that capital gains
are taxed on accrual in each period. This is counter to the usual practice under
which capital gains are taxed upon realisation but is a necessary assumption
since analysing taxation upon realisation would require a comprehensive study
of household choice over time in order to link taxation with timing of asset
sales. Undertaking this would remove the transparency of the analysis. What
the analysis will capture are the consequences of the basic fact that capital gains
are typically taxed at a lower rate than other sources of income.
When dividend income and capital gains are taxed, the net dividend received
by the shareholders is
£ o ¤
¢t = [1 ¡ ¿ p ] Dt ¡ ¿ g Vt+ 1 ¡ Vt ; (8.63)
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 247

and (8.47), giving the value of the …rm in period t, becomes


1
" s #
X Y ¡1
V to = [1 + ½u ] ¹st ¢t : (8.64)
s=t u =t

Following the same method of derivation as in (8.48) and (8.49)


o
½tV t = ¢t + V t+1 ¡ Vt : (8.65)

The wealth of shareholders is still given by (8.51) but after substitution can
be written as

W to = [1 ¡ ¿ g ] V t + [1 ¡ ¿ p ] [B t ¡ [1 + i t¡1 [1 ¡ ¿ c ]] Bt¡1 + zt]


¡ [¿ p ¡ ¿ g ] V tn + ¿ g V t¡1 : (8.66)

Since terms with subscripts t ¡ 1 are pre-determined at time t, maximisation of


W to is equivalent to maximising

c o = [1 ¡ ¿ g ] V t + [1 ¡ ¿ p ] [Bt + zt ] ¡ [¿ p ¡ ¿ g ] V n :
W (8.67)
t t

o
Substituting for ¢t and V t+1 in (8.64) and simplifying gives
¸ ¸
1 + ½t ¡ ¿ g 1 ¡¿p n
Vt = Dt ¡ V t+1 + Vt+ 1: (8.68)
1¡¿g 1 ¡¿g

Employing the de…nition of At and solving gives the value of the …rm as
" s #
X1 X 1 + ½ ¡ ¿ g ¸¡1 1 ¡ ¿p
¸
¿p ¡ ¿ g
¸ ¸
u n
Vt = At ¡ Vt+ 1 : (8.69)
s=t u=t
1 ¡ ¿g 1 ¡ ¿g 1 ¡ ¿g

The value given in (8.68) implies the following theorem which can be found in
Pye (1972) and King (1974).

Theorem 42 Given an investment policy, z, and a bond policy, B, if ¿ p > ¿ g


a decrease in V sn for any s > t increases V t .

Proof. Since At = Dt ¡ V t+1n = z


t+1 + Bt+1 ¡ [1 + i t [1 ¡ ¿ c ]] Bt, any change
in V s only has a direct e¤ect upon V t . Given ¿ p ¡ ¿ g > 0, a decrease in Vsn for
n

any s > t will increase V t .


The signi…cant implication of Theorem 8.4 is that the increases in value for
the …rm achieved by reducing new equity issues need not be exhausted when
V sn = 0. In fact, provided dividends remain positive, the …rm would wish to
repurchase its own equity (i.e. choose V sn to be negative) rather than increase
dividends. This result arises entirely from the preferential tax treatment given
to capital gains relative to dividends and emphasises how directly the structure
of the personal tax system can a¤ect the …nancial behaviour of the …rm. In
practice, …rms are restricted in their freedom to repurchase shares. To do so
248 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

in the UK requires a court order whilst in the US the Internal Revenue Code
prohibits …rms from repurchasing shares in lieu of distribution dividends.
As a consequence of Theorem 8.4 it becomes reasonable to assume that the
…rm will not issue new equity. Hence Vtn will now be taken as zero for all t.
Following the derivation in (8.56) to (8.60), the wealth of the shareholders is
given by " " s¡1 # #
1
X Y
c o
Wt = [1 ¡ ¿ p ] z t + [1 + ru] ¡1
zs ; (8.70)
s=t+1 u =t

where the cost of capital is

b ti t [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ p ] + [1 ¡ bt ] ½t
rt = : (8.71)
[1 ¡ ¿ g ] ¡ [¿ p ¡ ¿ g ] b t

The …nancial policy of the …rm can be inferred from (8.70) through the …rm
attempting to minimise the cost of capital. To do this, note that after tax a
bondholder receives [1 ¡ ¿ p ] it from each bond held. If households are to hold
both debt and equity simultaneously then their post-tax returns must be equal
so it follows that [1 ¡ ¿ p ] i t = ½t where ½t is the return on equity de…ned in
(8.64). This observation provides the basis for Theorem 8.5

Theorem 43 The …rm will employ only equity …nancing if [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] >


[1 ¡ ¿ p ] and will employ only debt …nancing if [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] < [1 ¡ ¿ p ].

Proof. Di¤erentiating (8.70) with respect to gives

drt [1 ¡ ¿ p ] [it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] ¡ ½t ]
= 2 ; (8.72)
dbt [[1 ¡ ¿ g ] ¡ [¿ p ¡ ¿ g ] b t]

so the …rm will choose only debt if it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] < ½t and only equity if the
inequality is reversed.
Now suppose that [1 ¡ ¿ p ] it = ½t so both debt and equity are held. If
[1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] > [1 ¡ ¿ p ] then it follows that it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] > ½t and the
…rm would switch to an equity-only policy. Conversely, if [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] <
[1 ¡ ¿ p ] then it [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] < ½t and the …rm will issue only debt.
The signi…cant content of Theorem 8.5 is its demonstration that the …nancial
policy of the …rm is determined solely by the structure of the corporate and
personal tax systems. As in Theorem 8.3, higher values of the corporate tax
work in the direction of favouring debt …nance as do increases in capital gains
tax. Conversely, an increase in the personal tax rate favours equity …nance. It is
also important to notice that the theorem predicts that a …rm will never use both
equity and debt …nancing except in the special case that i t [1 ¡ ¿ c ] [1 ¡ ¿ g ] = ½t .

Conclusions
The analysis of the …rm under certainty has made a number of strong predic-
tions concerning the e¤ect of the tax system upon the …nancing of the …rm.
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 249

Without taxation, the certainty version of the Modigliani-Miller theorem shows


that the …rm is indi¤erent about its choice of …nancial policy. The introduc-
tion of taxation directly alters this conclusion, with the corporation tax always
working in the direction of favouring bond …nance. The results also emphasise
how directly …nancial policy is a¤ected by the personal tax system.

8.3.6 Uncertainty
The analysis above has been restricted by the assumption that all actions by
the …rm lead to known future outcomes. Although a valuable assumption for
generating insights into …nancial policy, it is a poor re‡ection of reality especially
where long-term investments are considered. Uncertainty is now introduced
but it must be noted at the outset that the resulting analysis cannot be as
comprehensive as that conducted under certainty. Much of the reason for this
follows from the need to include the di¤ering risk characteristics of equity and
bonds in the portfolio choice problem of consumers. If the …rm does not become
bankrupt, bonds always pay a known return whereas the return to equity, in
both dividend and capital gain, will be dependent upon the state of nature. In
addition, if a …rm becomes bankrupt the equity of that …rm will be worthless
whereas bondholders will receive a share in the remaining value of the …rm.
The Modigliani-Miller theorem has already entered the earlier discussion and
this section begins with a formal demonstration of the theorem for the case of
uncertainty. This will provide a su¢cient set of assumptions under which the
value of the …rm is independent of the choice of …nancial policy. Following this,
the e¤ects of introducing taxation upon …nancial policy are discussed.

The Modigliani-Miller theorem


The Modigliani-Miller Theorem extends the observation in Theorem 8.3, that in
the absence of taxes the value of the …rm is independent of its …nancial policy, to
an economy with uncertainty. It was …rst published in Modigliani-Miller (1958)
and extended by Stiglitz (1969b). The limitation of both of these derivations
is that they were basically static and did not capture the intertemporal aspects
of the …rm’s decision. The theorem was extended to a multiperiod setting in
Stiglitz (1974) and it is upon this that the following is based.
Consider an economy with m …rms and H households. All …rms use one input
to produce an output of the same commodity. A plan for the …rm is a choice of
investment levels for each period t and, implicit in what follows, a production
technique contingent on the state of nature that arises at t. The investment
level of …rm j at time t in state of nature s (t) is denoted by Ij (t; s (t)) and the
level of gross pro…t by ¼ j (t; s (t)). These are taken as given. The …rm can use
two …nancial instruments: bonds and equity. Both of these are sold on perfect
markets. A bond represents a promise to pay 1 unit of output in period t. The
price of a bond with maturity at time ¿ in period in state s is p (t; s (t) ; ¿ ). It
is assumed that there is no bankruptcy so it must be the case that p (t; s; t) = 1
all s, t.
250 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

Now suppressing the state of nature, pro…ts can be written


1
X
Ij (t) = [p (t; ¿ ) [Bj (t; ¿ ) ¡ Bj (t ¡ 1; ¿ )]]+qj (t) [º j (t) ¡ º j (t ¡ 1)]+ª j (t) ;
¿ =t+1
(8.73)
where Bj (t; ¿ ) denotes the number of bonds at the end of period t with maturity
at ¿ , qj (t) the price of a share in the jth …rm at t, º j (t) the number of shares
outstanding at the end of period t and ª j (t) retained earnings. Hence the level
of investment must be equal to the change in value of outstanding bonds plus
the value of the change in the number of shares plus retained earnings. De…ne

V je (t) = qj (t) º j (t) ; (8.74)

to be the value of equity outstanding at the end of period t and

V jo (t) = qj (t) º j (t ¡ 1) ; (8.75)

to be the value outstanding at the beginning of the period. From these de…ni-
tions it follows that V je (t) ¡ V jo (t) is the value of the change in the number of
shares and V jo (t ¡ 1) ¡ V je (t) is the capital gain or loss between periods. Since
there are no taxes, the gross pro…ts of the …rm must be either held as retained
earnings or distributed as dividends or used to redeem bonds. Thus

¼ j (t) = Bj (t ¡ 1; t) + Dj (t) + ªj (t) ; (8.76)

where Dj (t) denotes dividend payments in period t.


The value of the jth …rm at the beginning of period t before the bonds ma-
turing in that period are redeemed is given by the present value of it outstanding
bonds plus the value of equity
1
X
Wjo (t) = V jo (t) + p (t; ¿ ) Bj (t ¡ 1; ¿ ) ; (8.77)
¿ =t

and the value at the end of period t is


1
X
W je (t) = V je (t) + p (t; ¿ ) B j (t; ¿ ) : (8.78)
¿ =t+ 1

Hence
Dj (t) = ¼ j (t) ¡ Ij (t) + Wje (t) ¡ W jo (t) : (8.79)
ho
Turning now to the household side of the economy, let w (t) be the wealth
of h at beginning of t, w h e (t) be wealth at end of t, º hej (t) be ownership of h
in j at the end of t and B h (t; ¿ ) be their ownership of bonds with maturity ¿ .
The assumption that there is no bankruptcy makes all …rms’ bonds identical so
they must have the same pricing structure. The wealth of h is therefore given
by
X m 1
X
w he (t) = º he
j (t) + p (t; ¿ ) Bh (t; ¿ ) ; (8.80)
j=1 ¿ =t+ 1
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 251

or
2 3
m
X 1
X m
X
w he (t) = µ hj (t) W je (t) + p (t; ¿ ) 4B h (t; ¿ ) ¡ µ hj (t) Bj (t; ¿ )5 ;
j= 1 ¿ =t+1 j=1
(8.81)
ºhe
j (t)
where µhj
(t) = ºe ( t) is the share of h in the equity of …rm j at the end of t.
j
Similarly,
m
X
ho
w (t + 1) = µ hj (t) W jo (t + 1)
j=1
2 3
1
X m
X
+ p (t + 1; ¿ ) 4B h (t; ¿ ) ¡ µ hj (t) Bj (t; ¿ ) 5 : (8.82)
¿ = t+1 j=1

Pm h
During period t household h receives dividends of j= 1 µj Dj and consumes
h
x (t) so the wealth levels at the beginning and end of t are related by
m
X
w he (t) = w ho (t) ¡ x h (t) + µhj (t ¡ 1) Dj (t) ; (8.83)
j=1

and the level of consumption is determined by


m
" 1
#
X X
h h e
x (t) = µj (t ¡ 1) ¼ j (t) ¡ Ij (t) + Wj (t) ¡ p (t; ¿ ) B j (t ¡ 1; ¿ )
j=1 ¿=1
1
X
+ p (t; ¿ ) B h (t ¡ 1; ¿ ) ¡ w he (t) ; all h; t: (8.84)
¿ =1

The description of the economy is completed by noting that equilibrium


requires the value of ownership claims on …rm j to equal the value of equity or
H
X H
X
V jhe (t) = µhj (t) V je (t) = V je (t) ; all j; t; (8.85)
h= 1 h=1

and for the supply of bonds to equal the demand


m
X H
X
Bj (t; ¿ ) = Bh (t; ¿ ) ; all t; ¿ : (8.86)
j=1 h=1

The following theorem can then be proved.

Theorem 44 (Modigliani-Miller/Stiglitz) Assume that there exists an equilib-


rium for the economy. Then there is another equilibrium in which any …rm (or
group of …rms) has changed its …nancial policy but in which the value of the
252 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

…rm and of all its bonds are unchanged. In addition, the portfolio changes of
investors are given by
m
X
¢B h (t; ¿ ) = µhj (t) ¢Bj (t; ¿ ) ; all t; ¿ ; j; (8.87)
j= 1

and
¢µ hj (t) = 0; all h; j; t: (8.88)

Proof. Assume that w h e (t), p (t; ¿ ) and W je (t) remain unchanged after the
change in …nancial policy. Under this assumption, it is clear from (8.81) that
the changes in portfolio described in (8.86) and (8.87) are feasible. From (8.83),
if these changes are undertaken then x j (t + 1) + w he (t + 1) remains constant.
Hence if x j (t + 1) is unchanged, so is w he (t + 1). In addition, for periods before
the change in …nancial policy, wealth levels will be unchanged. Consequently,
any consumption stream that was feasible before the change in …nancial policy
remains feasible after the change. Furthermore, the original consumption stream
must still be optimal since the opportunity set has not changed.
It remains to show that the markets for equity and bonds remain in equi-
librium. From (8.87) it is clear that the equity market must be una¤ected. For
the bond market, it follows from (8.86) that
m X
X H m
X
µhj (t) ¢Bj (t; ¿ ) = ¢Bj (t; ¿ ) : (8.89)
j=1 h=1 j=1

Since all markets are una¤ected, this justi…es the original assumption that
wealth, prices and values remained unchanged.
The basis of Theorem 8.6 is that any change in …nancial policy by …rms
can be neutralised by adjustment of household portfolio composition. In this
way, the equilibrium before the change can be maintained. The theorem does,
however, rely on some strong assumptions. Firstly, it requires that households
are unrestricted in their borrowing and lending and face the same rates on
loans as the …rms. Secondly, it was assumed that there was no bankruptcy.
The e¤ect of this assumption is to make all bonds maturing at some given date
perfect substitutes regardless of the …rm that issued them. This assumption is
clearly an inappropriate one. The role of the bankruptcy assumption is discussed
further in Hellwig (1981) who shows that the theorem can be extended to include
potential bankruptcy provided that, when only securities issued by …rms can
act as collateral on loans, short-selling of securities is permitted. However when
moral hazard is incorporated as a feature of loan contracts, even this theorem
does not apply.

Uncertainty and …nancial policy


In an economy with a full set of Arrow-Debreu contingent commodities, the
pro…t level of the …rm is certain, as described in Chapter 7, despite the under-
lying uncertainty. This follows from the contingent production plan having a
8.3. TAX INCIDENCE 253

certain value at the known prices for contingent commodities. Since an increase
in pro…ts of a …rm expands the budget set of all its shareholders, they will be
in unanimous agreement that the …rm should maximise pro…t. The implication
of these observations are that with a full set of markets the results on the in-
teraction of taxation and …nancial policy are the same under uncertainty as for
certainty. Additional content to the problem can therefore only be given in an
economy with incomplete markets.

With incomplete markets, there may no longer be unanimity between the


shareholders about the objective of the …rm. King (1977) presents an exam-
ple where households receive the same utility from consumption but di¤er in
the probabilities they assign to the occurrence of alternative states. As a con-
sequence, their von Neumann-Morgernstern expected utility functions di¤er.
Because of these di¤erences, there may be a con‡ict of interest between share-
holders arises since the expected utility of a policy is a product of the returns,
earned by the …rm in the various states, and the probabilities assigned to those
states. In addition to the lack of unanimity, the shareholders may prefer the
…rm not to choose the policy that maximises the value of the …rm. The explana-
tion for this is that shareholders are also concerned with the prices of the goods
they consume. If the actions of the …rm a¤ect both wealth and relative prices,
then wealth maximisation need not be optimal. This aspect is investigated
in Taggart (1980) who shows how the incompleteness of market prevents the
equalisation of shareholders marginal rates of substitution between current and
future consumption. This was also the reasoning behind the valuation adopted
in the analysis of incomplete markets in (7.17).

The requirement of including incomplete markets and analysing the …rm’s


decision problems when there is potentially no unanimity between shareholders
makes further progress di¢cult to obtain. One contribution that is worth noting
in this context is that of Auerbach and King (1983). Although this is restricted
by being developed within a framework in which households are concerned only
with the mean and variance of returns, so limiting the generality of preferences,
it does develop a number of important conclusions. It is shown that two forms
of equilibrium can arise. The …rst form of equilibrium arises when there is a …rm
whose returns are spanned by the returns of the other …rms. When this occurs,
value maximisation is optimal by …rms but households will be specialised in their
purchases. Because of taxes, some households will prefer to purchase only equity
whilst others will purchase only debt. The value of each …rm will be independent
of its …nancial policy. In the alternative equilibrium value maximisation is not
optimal and households will hold both debt and equity. However, for either
of the equilibria to exist, constraints upon the activities of households must
be imposed. There must be a limit upon the extent of borrowing that can
be undertaken and no households aggregate portfolio can be short-sold. The
force of these restrictions is to prevent in…nite trades to take advantage of tax
arbitrage.
254 CHAPTER 8. CORPORATE TAXATION

8.4 Conclusions
This chapter has considered the e¤ect of corporate taxation upon both the pro-
ductive activities of the …rm and its choice of …nancial policy. These represent
the two channels through which the corporation interacts with the other agents
in the economy. The structure of the chapter involved a process of moving from
the analysis of the productive decisions of the corporation in the Harberger
economy to the combination of …nancial and investment decisions in an uncer-
tain environment. The analysis of …nancial policy emphasised the importance
of both the corporate tax system and the personal tax system for the determi-
nation of …nancial policy. The e¤ect of taxation in determining …nancial policy
is emphasised most emphatically when contrasted with the conclusion of the
Modigliani-Miller theorem which asserts the irrelevance to the …rm’s value of
the choice between equity and debt.
Part III

Relaxing the Assumptions

255
Chapter 9

Public Goods

9.1 Introduction

When a public good is provided, it can be consumed collectively by all house-


holds. Such collective consumption violates the assumption of the private nature
of the goods in the Arrow-Debreu competitive economy. The existence of public
goods then leads to a failure of the competitive equilibrium to be e¢cient. Such
failure implies a potential role for the state in public good provision to overcome
the failure of the market.

The formal analysis of public goods began with Samuelson (1954) who de-
rived the rule characterising e¢cient levels of provision and, after de…ning some
necessary terms, this will also be the starting point of this chapter. E¢cient
provision will be considered for pure public goods and for public goods subject
to congestion. The theme of e¢ciency is continued into the study of Lindahl
equilibria with personalised prices. Following this, the analysis of private pro-
vision demonstrates the nature of the outcome when prices are uniform and
illustrates why a competitive market fails to attain e¢ciency.

If government provision is to be justi…ed, it must be shown that the gov-


ernment can improve upon the market outcome. Section 6 shows what can
be achieved when policy instruments are restricted to commodity taxation and
uniform lump-sum taxes. In seeking the attainment of an e¢cient outcome, the
government is faced with informational constraints of which the lack of knowl-
edge of household preferences is the most signi…cant. Section 8 on mechanism
design shows why households may choose to misrepresent their preferences and
how mechanisms can be designed to overcome this. Finally, the chapter is com-
pleted by a review of experimental evidence on private provision and preference
revelation, and the use of market data to elicit valuations..

257
258 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

9.2 De…nitions
A public good can be distinguished from a private good by the fact that it can
provide bene…ts to a number of users simultaneously whereas a private good can,
at any time, only bene…t a single user. If the public good can accommodate any
number of users then it is said to be pure. It is impure when congestion can
occur. This section de…nes a public good, clari…es the distinction between pure
and impure and develops its economic implications.

9.2.1 Pure public goods


The pure public good has been the subject of most of the economic analysis
of public goods. In some ways, the pure public good is an abstraction that
is adopted to provide a benchmark case against which other results can be
assessed. Before proceeding, it should be noted that public goods can take the
form of inputs into production in addition to their more commonly-presented
role as ob jects of consumption. A simple translation of the comments below can
be made in order to allow them to describe the public good as an input.
A pure public good has the following two properties.
Non-excludability
If the public good is supplied, no household can be excluded from consuming
it except, possibly, at in…nite cost.
Non-rivalry
Consumption of the public good by one household does not reduce the quan-
tity available for consumption by any other.
The implication of non-excludability is that consumption cannot be con-
trolled e¢ciently by a price system since no household can be prevented from
consuming the public good if it is provided. It is evident that a good satisfying
this condition does not …t into the framework of the competitive economy used
to derive the Two Theorems of Welfare Economics in Chapter 2. In the form
given, those theorems are inapplicable to an economy with public goods.
From the property of non-rivalry it can be deduced that all households can,
if they so desire, simultaneously consume a level of the public good equal to its
total supply. If it is possible for households not to consume the public good,
then some may consume less. In the latter case, the public good may satisfy
free-disposal, so that consumption can be reduced at no cost, or else disposal
can be costly. Further discussion of the modelling of free-disposal is given in
Milleron (1972) and of costly disposal in Oakland (1987). When all households
must consume, or want to consume, to the maximum, the welfare level of each
household is dependent on the total public good supply.
In reality, it is di¢cult to …nd any good that satis…es both the conditions of
non-excludability and non-rivalry precisely. For example, the transmission of a
television signal will satisfy non-rivalry but exclusion is possible at …nite cost.
Similar comments apply, for example, to defence spending which will eventually
be rivalrous and from which exclusion is possible.
9.3. OPTIMAL PROVISION 259

Figure 9.1: Consumption Possibilities for One Unit of Good

9.2.2 Impure public goods and congestion

In practice, public goods tend to eventually su¤er from congestion when usage
is su¢ciently great. Obvious examples include parks and roads. Congestion
results in a reduction in the return the public good gives to each user as the
use of a given supply by households increases. Such public goods are termed
impure. The utility derived by each household from an impure public good
is an increasing function of the level of supply and a decreasing function of
its use. There are a number of ways of representing the e¤ect of congestion
upon preferences and some of these will be described when optimal provision is
characterised.
To obtain further insight into these de…nitions it may be helpful to think of a
continuum of types of good running from purely private goods, for which there
is complete rivalry and exclusion at zero cost, to pure public goods. Figure 9.1
illustrates the possible division of the consumption of 1 unit of a good between
two households for the two extremes and for an impure public good. With a pure
public good it is possible for both to consume a maximum of 1 unit. In contrast,
the private good must be divided between the households. The consumption
possibilities for an impure public good lies between these limits.

9.3 Optimal provision


The characterisation of the e¢cient provision of a pure public good was …rst
published in Samuelson (1954) and was followed by a diagrammatic explanation
in Samuelson (1955). For this reason, the rule for e¢cient provision is typically
called the Samuelson rule. The following analysis will derive the Samuelson rule
for a pure public good, with and without free disposal, and for public inputs
and public goods with congestion.
260 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

9.3.1 Pure public good


To provide a reasonably simple derivation of the e¢ciency rule it will be assumed
that there is available a single public good and, initially, that disposal is not
possible. The latter assumption implies that all households must consume a
quantity of the public good equal to its supply. The extension to many public
goods is entirely straightforward.
The economy consists of H households, indexed h = 1; :::; H. Each household
has a utility function
¡ ¢
U h = U h xh ; G ; (9.1)
where xh is the consumption of household h of the vector of private goods and
G is the supply of the public good. The fact that total supply, G, appears in all
households’ utility functions indicates that the public good is pure.
It is assumed that the combinations of x h , h = 1; :::; H, and G that the
economy can produce are constrained by production possibilities. The implicit
representation of the production set is written

F (X; G) 0; (9.2)

where
H
X
X = xh : (9.3)
h= 1

To characterise the set of …rst-best, or Pareto e¢cient, allocations the gov-


ernment chooses x h , h = 1; :::; H, and G to maximise the utility level of the
…rst household, constrained by the requirement that households 2 to H obtain
given utility levels and by production possibilities. Varying the given utility
levels for households 2 to H traces out the set of Pareto e¢cient allocations.
The Lagrangean for this maximisation problem can be written

¡ ¢ H
X h ¡ ¢ i
h
L = U 1 x1 ; G + ¹h U h x h ; G ¡ U ¡ ¸F (X; G) ; (9.4)
h== 2

h
where U is the utility level that must be achieved by h = 2; :::; H. Assuming
that the speci…ed utility levels can be reached simultaneously, the necessary
condition describing the choice of a component xhi from x h is

@L @U h @F
h
´ ¹h h ¡ ¸ = 0; h = 1; :::; H; (9.5)
@xi @x i @Xi

with ¹h ´ 1 for h = 1. At an optimum (9.5) holds for all i = 1; :::; n. For the
choice of the level of public good, forming the Lagrangean and optimising with
respect to G gives
H
X
@L @U h @F
´ ¹h ¡¸ = 0: (9.6)
@G @G @G
h=1
9.3. OPTIMAL PROVISION 261

Solving (9.5) for ¹h , substituting into (9.6) and rearranging gives


H
X @U h @F
@G @G
@U h
= @F
; i = 1; :::; n: (9.7)
h =1 @xh
i
@X i

To interpret (9.7) note that each term in the summation on the left-hand side
is h
@U
@G
@ Uh
; (9.8)
@xhi

which is the marginal rate of substitution between the public good and the ith
private good for the hth household. The right-hand side of (9.7) is the marginal
rate of transformation between the public good and private good i. Equation
(9.7) can thus be written as
H
X
h
M RSG i = M RT Gi : (9.9)
h=1

Equation (9.9) is the Samuelson rule which states that Pareto e¢cient provision
of the public good occurs when the marginal rate of transformation between the
public good and each private good is equated to the sum, over all households,
of the marginal rates of substitution.
The result in (9.9) should be contrasted to the corresponding rule for e¢cient
provision of two private goods i and j
h
M RSji = M RT ji; all i; j; h: (9.10)

The di¤erence between (9.9) and (9.10) occurs due to the fact that an extra unit
of public good increases the utility of all households so that the social bene…t
of this extra unit is found by summing the marginal bene…t, measured by the
MRS, to individual households. At an optimum, this is equated to the marginal
cost given by the marginal rate of transformation. In contrast, an extra unit of
private good only increases the welfare of its single recipient and an optimum
o ccurs when marginal bene…ts are equalised across households and to marginal
cost.
Two points must be noted in the interpretation of this result. Firstly, al-
though non-excludability has been adopted as a de…ning characteristic of a pure
public good, it played no role in the derivation of the Samuelson rule. In fact,
the optimal level of provision is not dependent on the degree of excludability.
Instead, excludability is only relevant for determining feasible provision mecha-
nisms. Secondly, although the Samuelson rule is deceptively simple in form, care
should be taken before believing that it can be easily implemented. In order to
derive the rule it was assumed that the government had complete control over
the allocation of resources. Equivalently the government could employ lump-
sum taxation to redistribute income and to …nance the provision of the public
good, with decentralisation of the provision of private goods. It has already
262 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

been argued in Chapter 2 that optimal lump-sum taxes can rarely be employed
in practice and the same observation negates the implementation of the Samuel-
son rule. This conclusion has motivated the investigation of alternative forms of
…nance and the contrast of the resulting allocations to the …rst-best Samuelson
rule.

9.3.2 Free disposal


If free disposal of the public good is possible it is no longer necessary that each
household need consume the total quantity provided. If it is assumed that all
households wish to consume some¡ of the¢public good, the utility level of house-
hold h can be written U h = U h x h ; g h , where g h is the consumption of the
public good by h, and the constraint g h G, all h, added to the maximisation
in (9.4). The resulting Lagrangean is

¡ ¢ XH h ¡ ¢ h
i H
X £ ¤
L = U 1 x1 ; g 1 + ¹h U h xh ; g h ¡ U ¡ ¸F (X; G) + ½h G ¡ g h :
h=2 h=1
(9.11)
The version of the Samuelson Rule that applies in this case is given by
H
X @U h @F
@g h @G
@U h
= @F
; (9.12)
h =1 @xhi
@X i

h
with the condition @@gUh = 0 if g h < G. The interpretation of (9.12) is that
the marginal bene…t of increasing provision of the public good is set equal to
the marginal cost but allowing for the possibility that some households may be
satiated with the public good and receive no bene…t from additional provision.
This derivation can be extended to permit some households to consume a
zero quantity of the public good by introducing the constraint g h ¸ 0 into the
maximisation. It is also straightforward to remove the free disposal assumption
and replace it with a costly disposal. Oakland (1987) provides a derivation of
the relevant version of the Samuelson rule in these cases.

9.3.3 With congestion


For many public goods congestion is a very real phenomenon. Naturally, conges-
tion reduces the bene…t that all households receive from their use of the public
good and therefore modi…es the rule for e¢cient provision.
In the presence of congestion, the welfare of a household is typically written
as dependent upon the total supply of the public good and the usage of the
public good by all households. One approach to this (Oakland (1972)) is to
write ¡ ¢
U h = U h x h ; g1 ; :::; g H ; G ; (9.13)
h h h
with @U @U @U
@G > 0, @g h = 0 and for j 6= h, @gj < 0. It is the sign of the latter
term that captures the congestion e¤ect. If disposal of the public good is not
9.3. OPTIMAL PROVISION 263

possible then g h = G all h and (9.13) collapses to


¡ ¢
U h = U h xh ; G; H : (9.14)

A specialisation of (9.14) will be employed in Chapter 12. Alternative speci-


…cations which employ a household production approach have been suggested
by Sandmo (1973) and Muzondo (1978), who consider production processes us-
ing private and public goods, and Ebrill and Slutsky (1982) who focus on the
combination of public goods with scarce time.
If (9.13) is employed and the Lagrangean formed as in (9.11), the resulting
necessary conditions for the maximisation can be combined to give

H
X @U j
@ gh ½h
@U j
= @F
; i = 1; :::; n; h = 1; :::; H: (9.15)
j= 1 @xj
¸ @X i
i

and
H
X @U h H X
X H @ Uj @F
@g h @g h @G
@U h
+ @ Uj
= @F
i = 1; :::; n: (9.16)
h=1 @xhi h=1 j=1 @ xji @X i

If, at the optimum, g h < G for all h, then from the complementary slackness
conditions ½h = 0 and (9.15) states that each household’s use of the public good
should be expanded until the private return is exactly balanced by the sum
of negative externalities that this in‡icts on other households. Additionally,
the second term in (9.16) will be identically zero and (9.16) will describe the
standard Samuelson rule.
If some, or all, households are not satiated at the optimum, so that g h = G
for some households, then the second term in (9.16) is positive and the left-hand
side of the equation provides a measure of bene…t in excess of that used in the
standard Samuelson rule. This excess arises due to an increase in provision
of the public good a¤ecting utility both directly and through the reduction in
congestion that is brought about.

9.3.4 Public input


The characterisation of e¢ciency conditions for economies with pure public
inputs began with Kaizuka (1965). The subsequent literature, which has also
analysed congestible public inputs, is discussed in Feehan (1989).
To derive the e¢ciency conditions for the supply of a pure public input,
consider an economy with m …rms each using labour and the public good to
produce a single form of output. Denoting the labour use of …rm j by ` j , the
…rm’s production function is given by
¡ ¢
y j = f j `j ; G : (9.17)

The public good¡ is ¢produced by using labour alone according to the production
function G = Á `G . This is assumed to have an inverse `G = £ (G) ; £ (G) ´
264 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

Á¡1 (G). The equilibrium conditions, that supply must equal demand for goods
and labour, are given by
H
X m
X m
X ¡ ¢
xh = yj = f j `j; G ; (9.18)
h= 1 j=1 j=1

and
H
X m
X
h
` = `j + £ (G) : (9.19)
h =1 j=1

For this economy, an optimum allocation is found from the Lagrangean


2 3
¡ ¢ H
X h ¡ ¢ h
i H
X m
X ¡ ¢
L = U 1 x 1 ; `1 + ¹h U h xh ; ` h ¡ U + ¸ 4 xh ¡ fj `j; G 5
h=1 h=1 j= 1
2 3
H
X m
X
+½ 4 `h ¡ `j ¡ £ (G) 5 : (9.20)
h=1 j=1

Carrying out the maximisation in (9.20) provides the e¢ciency criteria


@ Uh
@` h @f j
@ Uh
=¡ ; h = 1; :::; H and j = 1; :::; m; (9.21)
@`j
@ xh

and
Xm
@f j @f j 0
= £ ; j = 1; :::; m: (9.22)
j=1
@G @`j

The …rst condition, (9.21), ensures that the marginal rate of substitution be-
tween labour and consumption is equated between households and this value
is set equal to (minus) the …rms’ common marginal product of labour. This is
a standard e¢ciency condition. Condition (9.22) is the form of the Samuelson
rule for the public input and requires the sum of marginal products of the public
inputs for the …rms to equal the private good foregone in producing marginally
more public good.
This completes the analysis of rules for e¢cient provision and from this point
the focus will be placed upon pure public goods. The Samuelson rule may char-
acterise the set of Pareto e¢cient outcomes but, as noted, it cannot in general
be implemented. This motivates the study of feasible allocation mechanisms
and the comparison of their outcomes to those that satisfy the Samuelson Rule.

9.4 Personalised prices and the Lindahl equilib-


rium
Now that the rule for Pareto e¢cient provision has been derived the natural
question is whether there is any form of economy in which competitive behaviour
9.4. PERSONALISED PRICES AND THE LINDAHL EQUILIBRIUM 265

will lead to an e¢cient outcome. The equilibrium in the standard model of


Chapter 2 will not be Pareto e¢cient in the presence of public goods. This
arises from the fact that consumers di¤er in the valuation they place upon a
given supply of the public good. Insisting that they all pay an identical price
for the supply cannot therefore be e¢cient.
Following this reasoning, it would appear likely that Pareto e¢ciency would
result if each consumer could pay an individual or personalised price for the
good. In this way, each will be paying a price that re‡ects their valuation.
Allowing such personalised prices represents an extension of the Arrow-Debreu
economy which assumed that each commodity had a single price. The equi-
librium with personalised prices is often called a Lindahl equilibrium after its
introduction by Lindahl (1919).
Two variants of the Lindahl equilibrium will be described in this section.
The …rst is for a simple economy with two households in which the price of the
public good is given by the share of the cost of the public good each household
must cover. Following this, it is shown how e¢ciency can be sustained in a
competitive economy with truly personalised prices. The section is completed
by analysing the relationship of the Lindahl equilibrium, and its extensions, to
the core.

9.4.1 Simple model


The …rst formal analysis of the Lindahl equilibrium can be traced to Johansen
(1963) who provided an analytical interpretation of Lindahl’s (1919) equilibrium
concept. With a single public good, the central aspect of this formulation is
that each household bases their consumption decision upon the share, ¿ h , of
the cost of provision of the public good that they must pay. Assuming that the
demand of household h for the public good increases¡ 1without ¢limit as ¿ ! 0, an
h
H
equilibrium can be de…ned as a set of cost shares, ¿ ; :::; ¿ , that sum to 1 and
are such that they lead all households to demand the same quantity of the public
good. The importance of this equilibrium is that it satis…es the Samuelson rule
and is therefore Pareto e¢cient despite the existence of the public good. If there
are many public goods, a cost share can be introduced for each public good and
optimality again achieved.
To illustrate these ideas in the simplest setting, consider an economy with
2 households who have an endowment of ! h units, h = 1; 2, of the numeraire
which they supply inelastically to the market. Each household therefore has
a …xed income of ! h . There is a single private good produced with constant
returns to scale using the numeraire alone and the units of measurement of this
good are chosen so that a unit of output requires one unit of numeraire input.
The price of the private good is therefore also equal to one. Production of the
public good is subject to constant returns to scale and each unit requires p G
units of labour. The marginal rate of transformation in production between the
public good and the private good is therefore constant at pG .
266 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

Assume that each household has a utility function such that


¡ ¢
U h = U h xh ; G ; h = 1; 2; (9.23)

where x h is the quantity consumed of the single private good and G is the
quantity of the public good. Utility is non-decreasing in x h and G. Now let
G h denote the quantity of the public good that household h would like to see
provided when faced with the budget constraint

x h + ¿ h p GG h = ! h : (9.24)

In (9.23) p G Gh is the total cost of providing the good and ¿ h the fraction of
this paid by h. From (9.22) and (9.23) household h chooses G h to maximise
¡ ¢
U h = U h ! h ¡ ¿ h p G Gh ; G : (9.25)

The necessary condition for this maximisation is


h
UG
= ¿ h pG : (9.26)
Uxh

Solving (9.25) for Gh generates the Lindahl reaction function


¡ ¢
Gh = Lh ¿ h ; ! h ; (9.27)

which describes the household’s demand for the public good as a function of the
cost share it faces and its initial endowment. If the second-order condition for
maximising (9.24) is satis…ed and the utility function is strictly concave, then
Lh (¢) is a decreasing function of ¿ h . n o
A Lindahl equilibrium is a pair of cost shares ¿b 1 ; b
¿2 such that
1 2
(i) b
¿ +b ¿ = 1,
and ³ ´
(ii) Lh b¿ h ; ! h = G¤ ¸ 0; h = 1; 2:
The …rst condition guarantees that su¢cient revenue will be obtained to
…nance the equilibrium public good provision and the second-condition that the
households will both be satis…ed with the supply. It follows from the fact that
utility is non-decreasing in G that the cost shares will be non-negative.
The nature of the Lindahl equilibrium is illustrated in Figure 9.2. The
Lindahl reaction functions are formed as the loci of the vertical points on the
indi¤erence curves of the utility function in (9.24) and the equilibrium is given
by the intersection of the functions. At this point, the indi¤erence curves for the
two households are tangential and the equilibrium is therefore Pareto e¢cient.
To demonstrate the latter point, note that (9.25) must hold for both households
at the equilibrium. Summing for the two households then gives
2
X 2
X 2
X
UGh h
= M RS Gx = ¿ h pG = p G = M RT Gx : (9.28)
Uxh
h=1 h =1 h=1
9.4. PERSONALISED PRICES AND THE LINDAHL EQUILIBRIUM 267

Figure 9.2: The Lindahl Equilibrium

Since (9.27) is the Samuelson rule for this economy, it demonstrates that the
Lindahl equilibrium is Pareto e¢cient. This establishes a form of the First
Theorem of Welfare Economics for the Lindahl equilibrium. The relation of
the Lindahl equilibrium to the Second Theorem will be investigated formally
below. For the present, it is su¢cient to note that by redistributing the initial
endowment it is possible to generate a new Lindahl equilibrium which represents
another point in the set of Pareto e¢cient outcomes.

9.4.2 A general treatment


The analysis of the Lindahl equilibrium in terms of cost shares clearly indicates
how the reasoning can be generalised. In the budget constraint (9.24) the price of
a unit of public good for household h is given by ¿ h p G . Whenever the cost shares
di¤er, the households face di¤erent prices for the public good. It is the existence
of these personalised prices that leads to the attainment of e¢ciency. The
asymmetry between private and public goods should also be noted: with private
goods all households face the same prices but demand di¤erent quantities; with
public goods the households face di¤erent prices but, at the equilibrium, demand
the same quantity.
The presentation of the Lindahl equilibrium via cost shares and reaction
functions has the bene…t of simplicity but, as careful study of the previous
section shows, it does not make it obvious how general theorems on the existence
of equilibrium or the welfare properties of the equilibrium can be obtained. To
develop these it is preferable to exploit the fact that the use of personalised
prices allows the Lindahl equilibrium to be expressed as the equilibrium of a
suitably de…ned competitive economy. Since standard existence and welfare
theorems apply to the competitive economy, they naturally apply to the Lindahl
equilibrium. This approach to the Lindahl equilibrium was developed by Foley
(1970), Milleron (1972) and Roberts (1973, 1974).
To formalise this idea consider an economy in which there are s non-disposable
public goods available with these public goods used only for …nal consumption.
268 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

The aggregate production set of the economy is denoted Y and, with n private
goods available, Y ½ <n+s . It is assumed that Y is a closed, convex cone that
contains the origin and thus that the technology satis…es constant returns to
scale. A production plan is written in the form (g; y) where the …rst s ele-
ments represent public goods and the …nal n private goods. It is assumed that
no public good is required as an input: if (g; y) 2 Y then (b g ; y) 2 Y where
g i = g i if g i > 0 and b
b gi = 0 if gi < 0. Each household, h, from the set of H
h n+s
households possesses a consumption
¡ h h ¢ set X ½ < with a consumption choice
for the household denoted g ; x . Household ¡ h has
¢ continuous preferences
over X h represented by the utility function U h g h ; xh , where U h (¢) is strictly
¡ ¢
monotonic and quasi-concave. The endowment of h is denoted by ! h = 0; ! h .
There are no endowments of public goods. © ª
A state of this economy is an array g; x 1 ; :::; x H of public and private good
vectors. A feasible state is now de…ned.
Feasibility
¡ ¢
(i) gh ; x h 2 X h for all h = 1; :::; H,
³ P £ ¤´
H
(ii) g; h=1 x h ¡ !h 2 Y .
Condition (i) ensures the consumption allocation is in the consumption set
for each household and (ii) that it is productively feasible.
The relevance of personalised prices has already been discussed and they are
now employed to de…ne the Lindahl equilibrium. Let p hG be the price vector for
public goods faced by h and p be the common vector of private goods prices.
The formal de…nition of a Lindahl equilibrium can now be given.
Lindahl equilibrium © ª
A Lindahl equilibrium with respect to the endowment ! 1 ; :::; !H is a fea-
© ª © ª
sible allocation b x1 ; :::; xbH and a price system pb1G ; :::; pbH
g; b ; pb ¸ 0 such that
hP i h P £ ¤i hP i G
H H H
(i) h=1 p bhG ; pb ¢ gb; h= 1 xbh ¡ ! h ¸ bhG ; pb ¢ [g; y] for all [g; y] 2
h =1 p
Y,
(ii) pbhG b
g ¡+ pbbxh¢ pb!h¡; ¢ ¡ ¢
h
(iii) U b g; xbh ¸ U h g; x h for all g; x h 2 X h such that pbhG g+ b px h b p! h .
This de…nition is a direct extension of that in 4.1.
The …rst issue concerning this economy is the existence, or otherwise, of an
equilibrium. Although this is not of direct relevance here, it is worth making
some comments. To develop an existence proof, both Foley (1970) and Milleron
(1972) construct a quasi-economy in which the commodity space is expanded
to allow each public good for each household to be treated as a separate good.
Consumption sets, preferences and the production set are rede…ned to be com-
patible with this. Equilibrium is then proved to exist, under assumptions closely
related to those in Section 9 of Chapter 2, for the quasi-economy and this equi-
librium is shown to be an equilibrium for the original economy. The alternative
approach adopted by Roberts (1973) is to work directly with the Lindahl econ-
omy and to construct a mapping from the price space for private goods and the
quantity space for public goods into the same two spaces. A …xed point of this
mapping is shown to exist and to be the equilibrium for the economy. Further
9.4. PERSONALISED PRICES AND THE LINDAHL EQUILIBRIUM 269

discussion of these proofs can be found in Roberts (1974) and an extension to


non-convex productions sets in Bonnisseau (1991). From these results, it can
be concluded that under relatively weak conditions a Lindahl equilibrium exists
and it is justi…able to proceed to an analysis of its welfare properties.
Given the existence of a Lindahl equilibrium and the obvious parallel of this
to the competitive equilibrium, it follows that a version of the First Theorem
must hold. The proof of this exactly mirrors that for the standard competitive
economy: assume the equilibrium is not Pareto e¢cient and that there exists
a preferred allocation; the preferred allocation can then be shown not to be
feasible.
Theorem 9.1 The First Theorem for Lindahl Economies (Foley)
The Lindahl equilibrium is Pareto e¢cient.
Proof
See Foley (1970). jj
Since the Samuelson rule describes the set of Pareto e¢cient allocations, it
follows that the Lindahl equilibrium also satis…es the Samuelson rule.
To prove the equivalent of the Second Theorem, that any Pareto optimum
can be decentralised as a Lindahl equilibrium, requires the application of a
separation theorem as in the proof of Theorem 2.4. The proof proceeds by
constructing two convex sets which have no interior points in common and can
therefore be separated. The normal to the separating hyperplane is then taken
as a set of equilibrium prices which are such that the Pareto e¢cient output is
pro…t maximising and each consumption plan is cost minimising over choices
yielding at least as much utility.
The proof given is based on Foley (1970)©and requiresªthe following additional
assumption:
© ª given the feasible allocation g; x1 ; :::; x h there exists, for all h,
h
g; e
x such that xeh < x h and e xh 2 X h . When the price vector is positive
this assumption states that, given any consumption plan, there is always an
alternative plan with lower value. Using this assumption, the Second Theorem
for Lindahl economies can now be proved.
Theorem 9.2 The Second © Theorem for
ª Lindahl Economies (Foley)
1 H
If a feasible
© allocation ª b g; xb ; :::; b
x is Pareto e¢cient, there exists a price
vector p = p1G ; :::; p H ; p ¸ 0 such that
hP iG h P £ h ¤i hPH i
H h H h h
(a) h=1 G p ; p ¢ g
b ; h= 1 x
b ¡ ! ¸ p
h =1 G ; p ¢ [g; y] for all [b
g ; y] 2
Y, ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
(b) if U h g; x h > U h b xh then p hG g + px h phG b
g; b g + pb x h.
Proof ©¡ ¢ ª
De…ne the set F = g 1 ; :::; gH : g 1 = ::: = g H = g and (g; y) 2 Y . Since
Y is a convex cone, F isnalso a convex cone. It is also non-empty since 0 2 F .
¡ ¢ PH ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢o
Next, de…ne the set D = g 1 ; :::; gH ; y : y = h =1 y h with U h g h ; y h + ! h > U h b xh .
g; b
D is convex and nonempty due to the quasi-concavity and monotonicity of util-
ity. © ª
As b xH is Pareto e¢cient, D and F have no points in common.
g; xb1 ; :::; b
¡ ¢
Therefore there exists a separating hyperplane with normal p 1G ; :::; pH G ; p 6= 0
270 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

and a scalar r such that


¡ ¢ PH
(i) for all g 1 ; :::; g H ; y 2 F , h h
h= 1 pG g + py r;
and ¡ ¢ PH
(ii) for all g 1 ; :::; g H ; y 2 D; D the closure of D; h h
h =1 p G g + py ¸ r.
© 1 H
ª
Since the allocation b g; b
x ; :::; xb is Pareto e¢cient, monotonicity of pref-
erences implies (b g ; yb) 2 D and the feasibility of the allocation implies that
g ; :::; b
P P
(b
g ; :::; b y ) 2 F . Hence H
g; b h=1 p G b
h g + pb y=r¸ H h= 1 pG g + py for all (g; y) 2 Y .
h h

This proves (a).


Since F is a convex cone containing zero, r ¸ 0 However, if r > 0 then it
could be increased without limit by expanding any plan that gave positive pro…t.
Hence r = 0. Since preferences are monotonic, p ¸ 0 or (ii) would be violated
by increasing the consumption on any good with a negative price. Similarly,
p = 0, phG ¸ 0 cannot arise since public goods with positive price could then
be produced using costless inputs (public goods are not needed as inputs) and
pro…t would be positive. Hence p ¸ 0. ³
¡ ¢ ¡ k k¢ PH £ ¤´
Suppose U k g k ; x k > U k b g ;b x . Then g 1 ; :::; g H ; h=1 xh ¡ !h where
PH PH £ h ¤
xh = b xh , g h = b g h all h 6= k, is in D so h h
h=1 p G g + p h=1 x ¡ !
h
¸
PH h
P H £ h h
¤
h= 1 Gp g
b + p h=1 x
b ¡ ! . But, as only the terms relating to k in the in-
equality di¤er, this reduces to p kG g k + px k ¸ pkG b g + pb xk . Suppose this was an
equality. Then the assumption that for any feasible allocation there is a point
in the consumption set of k¡ with lower ¢ value implies that along the line joining
k k
the point
¡ of lower
¢ value to g ;
¡ x there
¢ is, by continuity, a point of lower value
than g k ; xk and preferred to b xk . This would imply the existence of a point
g; b
in D contradicting (ii). Therefore the inequality is strict and (b) is established.
jj
Theorems 9.1 and 9.2 demonstrate how the Lindahl equilibrium replicates
the properties of the competitive equilibrium for economies with public goods.
Implicit in the Second Theorem is the fact that the distribution of resources
is chosen so that the Pareto e¢cient allocation satis…es the budget constraint
of each household. To achieve this objective, starting from an arbitrary initial
allocation, requires the use of lump-sum transfers or taxation. This makes the
Second Theorem for Lindahl economies subject to the criticisms discussed in
connection with Theorem 3.2.

9.4.3 Core equivalence


One of the observations supporting the use of the competitive equilibrium no-
tion is, that for economies with large numbers of consumers, the set of core
allocations shrinks to the set of competitive equilibrium. This was stated below
as Theorem 2.2. In this way, identical equilibrium allocations are isolated using
two very di¤erent concepts of equilibrium. If it were also true that the core of
an economy with public goods shrank to the set of Lindahl equilibrium as the
number of consumers increased, this would provide similar support for the use
of the Lindahl equilibrium concept.
9.4. PERSONALISED PRICES AND THE LINDAHL EQUILIBRIUM 271

Unfortunately, this is not the case. It is true that the Lindahl equilibrium is
in the core, and this will be proved below, but Muench (1972) presents an exam-
ple for which the set of core allocations is larger than the set of Lindahl equilibria
despite the economy possessing a continuum of consumers. The relevance of the
continuum is that Aumann (1964) demonstrated the core and competitive equi-
librium are equivalent in this case. Therefore, although the Lindahl equilibrium
has many of the properties of the competitive equilibrium, it does not satisfy
the same core equivalence so that its relation to the core cannot be appealed
to in support of the equilibrium concept. The failure of core equivalence can
be traced to the fact that when a coalition, say S, attempts to improve upon a
given allocation it must be able to provide, from its own resources, quantities
of the public goods. Since there are returns to coalition size in the provision of
public goods, it is di¢cult for coalitions to improve upon existing allocations.
The result that the Lindahl equilibrium is in the core is given in the following
theorem.
Theorem 9.3 (Foley)
© ª
If ©bg; bx1 ; :::; xbHª; b
p1G ; :::; pbH
G;pb is a Lindahl equilibrium
© 1 for the
ª endowment
1 H H
vector ! ; :::; ! , it is in the core with respect to ! ; :::; ! .
Proof
© ª
Suppose the© coalition S ª can improve upon the allocation b x1 ; :::; b
g; b x H with
the allocation g; x 1 ; :::; xH . Since the new allocation is preferred by all mem-
bers of S, it follows from the de…nition of a Lindahl equilibrium that
P P P P P
i2S p biG g + pb i2S xi > i2S pbiG b xi = pb i2S ! i.
g + pb i2S b
i
PH i P i
PH
Since£ pbiG ¸ 0i¤ for all i, i=1 pbG ¸ i2S pbG so that b g ¸ 0 implies h=1 pbhG g+
P
pb i2S x ¡ ! > 0. The latter condition contradicts pro…t maximisation in
the Lindahl equilibrium and proves the theorem. jj

9.4.4 Cost-share equilibria


At the heart of the Lindahl equilibrium is the concept of personalised pricing. In
the economy described in 4.2 the cost that household h faces for the public good
provision, p hG g, is a linear function of the quantity of provision. In a natural
generalisation of this framework Mas-Colell (1980b), Mas-Colell and Silvestre
(1989) and Weber and Wiesmeth (1991) have investigated the implications of
permitting monotonic cost functions Áh (G) which are not necessarily linear for
economies with a single public good.
The main result of this literature is the equivalence theorem of Weber and
Wiesmeth which proves the that the set of cost-share equilibria is identical to the
set of core allocations. The additional ‡exibility o¤ered by the nonlinear cost-
shares is therefore su¢cient to provide the equivalence that is absent in the linear
Lindahl equilibrium. However, since it is already di¢cult to envisage linear
personalised pricing being applied in practice, nonlinear personalised pricing
would seem devoid of practical interest.
272 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

9.4.5 Comments
The Lindahl equilibrium demonstrates how e¢ciency can be attained in an
economy with public goods by the use of personalised prices. The personalised
prices succeed in equating the individual valuations of the supply of public
goods to the cost of production in a way that uniform pricing cannot. These are
important observations that support the relevance of the Lindahl equilibrium
concept.
Unfortunately, the Lindahl equilibrium is not without fault. It is central to
the equilibrium that each household should face a price system that is designed
to capture that household’s evaluation of the public good supply. When it par-
ticipates in the public goods market each household is the only purchaser at its
particular price ratio and is not in the position it would be in a competitive
market of being one purchaser among many. In a competitive equilibrium there
is no incentive for the household to act in any other way than just to purchase
its most preferred consumption plan. In contrast, the fact that the household
is in a stronger position in the Lindahl equilibrium raises the very clear possi-
bility that it can gain by false revelation of preferences in an attempt to adjust
equilibrium prices to its advantage. Such strategic behaviour on the part of
households undermines the foundation of the Lindahl equilibrium. If it does
occur, the Lindahl equilibrium with strategic behaviour no longer possesses the
e¢ciency properties set out above. The consequences of strategic behaviour,
and responses to it, will be discussed further in Section 8.

9.5 Private provision of public good


The characterisation of optimal provision in Section 3 was concerned with an
economy in which the government provided the public good and was unrestricted
in its policy instruments. This …rst-best outcome is now contrasted to the
equilibrium of an economy in which the public good is funded entirely by the
voluntary contributions of individual households. Economies with government
provision alone and those with only private provision should be seen as the two
extreme cases since in practice, as charitable donations indicate, public goods are
usually provided by a combination of both methods. The focus of the analysis
will be upon the welfare properties of the private provision equilibrium and the
level of public good supply relative to e¢cient levels. In addition, the e¤ect of
the number of households on supply and changes in the income distribution will
also be considered.
In order to analyse private provision, it is necessary to make an assumption
about how each household expects their contribution to the provision of public
goods to a¤ect the contributions of others. The assumption that was made in
the initial literature on private provision (for example Bergstrom, Blume and
Varian (1986), Chamberlin (1974, 1976), Cornes and Sandler (1985), McGuire
(1974) and Young (1982)) was the standard Nash assumption: in planning their
contribution, each household takes the contribution of the others as given. This
9.5. PRIVATE PROVISION OF PUBLIC GOOD 273

is not the only assumption and alternatives have been investigated; some of
these will be discussed brie‡y in 5.6.

9.5.1 Equilibrium
The equilibrium with private provision will be derived in the economy used to
introduce the Lindahl equilibrium. The economy therefore has H households
who each have an endowment of !h units of the numeraire which they supply
inelastically. The income of each household is …xed at !h . The single private
good is produced with constant returns to scale using the numeraire alone and
a unit of output requires one unit of numeraire input. The price of the private
good is equal to one. Production of the public good is subject to constant
returns to scale and each unit requires pG units of labour. The price of the
public good is constant at p G .
Each household has a utility function
¡ ¢
U h = U h x h ; G ; h = 1; :::; H; (9.29)
P H
where xh is the quantity of private good consumed, G = h=1 g h and gh is the
contribution of h. The contribution towards the public good by all households
other than h, Gh , is de…ned by
G h = G ¡ g h: (9.30)
h h h
Using the budget constraint x + p G g = ! , utility can be written in terms of
G h and g h as follows
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U h x h ; G = U h ! h ¡ p G g h ; gh + G h = V h g h ; G h; p G : (9.31)
h h
i
Household h chooses g h to maximise (9.30) given G h and subject to gh 2 0; !pG .
¡ ¢
Indi¤erence curves of V h (¢) can be drawn in g h ; Gh space. Increasing G h
will always lead to a higher attainable level of V for given g h , g h is limited by
the budget constraint and preferred sets are convex.
Since the household takes the provision of others as given when maximising,
the optimal choice of g h for a given value of G h occurs at the tangency of the
¤
indi¤erence curve and the horizontal line at Gh . This is shown in Figure 9.3 and
the solid locus, the Nash reaction function, traces out the optimal choices of g h
as G h varies. The gradient of the reaction function, when the chosen value of
g h is interior, can be derived by noting that for all g h on the reaction function
¡ ¢
g h = arg max U h ! h ¡ pG g h ; g h + Gh : (9.32)
Di¤erentiating this, g h solves
¡Uxh pG + UGh = 0: (9.33)
Now considering variations in g h and Gh that satisfy the …rst-order condition
(9.32),
dg h U h pG ¡ U h
= h 2 xG h G G h ; (9.34)
dGh Uxx p G ¡ 2Ux Gp G + UG G
274 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

Figure 9.3: Indirect Preferences over Private Provision

which is always negative when UxG h > 0.

Alternatively, taking incomes as …xed, (9.32) can be solved to express gh as


a function of G h . The reaction function can then be written as
¸
h h
¡ ¢ h
¡ ¢ !h
g = ½ G h ; ½ Gh 2 0; : (9.35)
pG

This function traces out the optimal response of the household to the supply
G h of the other households.
The equilibrium of the private provision economy occurs at a set of choices for
the households such that all the reaction functions are simultaneously satis…ed.
Private provision equilibrium © hª h
h Ah iprivate provision equilibrium
¡ ¢
is an array of contributions b
PH
g , b g 2
! h h
0; pG , such that bg = ½ Gh for all h = 1; :::; H, with Gh = j=1; j6=h b gj.
If gbh > 0 household h is termed a contributor and is a non-contributor if
h
g = 0. The set of contributors is denoted C.
b
The proof that such an equilibrium exists employs the standard argument for
demonstrating the existence of a Nash equilibrium. ¡ Assuming
¢ ¡ that preferences
¢
are strictly convex, the composite function R g1 ; :::; g H ´ ½1 ; :::; ½H de…nes
h i
!h
a continuous function from the compact, convex set £H h= 1 0; p G to itself. From
¡ ¢
Brouwer’s
¡ 1 theorem¢ R g1 ; :::; g H has at least one …xed point and a …xed point
of R g ; :::; g H is clearly a private provision equilibrium.
It has also been shown that under weak conditions the private provision
equilibrium is also unique. Given ¡ G ¢ h , (9.31) determines the contribution of h as
a function of income, g h = f h ! h . Bergstrom, Blume and Varian (1986, 1992)
@f h(! h)
show that the restriction 0 < @! h
< 1 is su¢cient to prove uniqueness.
This restriction is simply the requirement that both private and public goods
are normal.
For a two-household economy the private provision equilibrium can be pre-
sented diagrammatically. The households solve the following maximisations
9.5. PRIVATE PROVISION OF PUBLIC GOOD 275

Figure 9.4: Private Provision Equilibrium

¡ ¢
Household 1: maxfg1g U 1 ! 1 ¡ p G g 1 ; g 1 + g 2 ; with g2 …xed.
¡ ¢
Household 2: maxfg2g U 2 ! 2 ¡ p G g 2 ; g 1 + g 2 ; with g1 …xed.
The ¡solution
¢ to these¡ maximisations
¢ are given by the reaction functions
g 1 = ½1 g 2 and g 2 = ½2 g 1 . The equilibrium is then a pair b g1, bg 2 such that
¡ ¢ ¡ 1¢
gb1 = ½1 gb2 ; gb2 = ½2 b
g : (9.36)

This equilibrium is illustrated in Figure 9.4 in which the reaction functions are
simultaneously satis…ed at their intersection.

9.5.2 Pareto improvements


It is a property of Nash equilibria that they are not, in general, Pareto e¢cient
and, although no agent can improve their welfare when acting independently,
a simultaneous change in actions can bene…t all agents. This observation ap-
plies to the private provision equilibrium in which a simultaneous increase in
contributions will raise all households’ welfare.
To demonstrate this it is …rst observed, as is always the case, that the set
of Pareto e¢cient allocations are the points of tangency of the households’
indi¤erence curves. In contrast, it follows from the construction of the reaction
function in Figure 9.3 and the structure of equilibrium in Figure 9.4 that for
the two household economy the private provision equilibrium occurs at a point
where two households’ indi¤erence curves are at right-angles. The set of Pareto
e¢cient allocations and the private provision equilibrium are shown in Figure
9.5. Since the private provision equilibrium is not Pareto e¢cient, there exist
Pareto improvements and these are given by the shaded area.
In is also apparent in Figure 9.5 how an increase in both the households’
contributions can lead to a Pareto improvement. Therefore, local improvements
in welfare can be achieved by an increase in the provision of public goods.
Compared to Pareto preferred allocations, the private provision equilibrium
leads to an undersupply of public goods.
276 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

Figure 9.5: Non-Optimality of Private Provision

Figure 9.6: Oversupply

9.5.3 Quantity of provision


The result described above, that the private provision equilibrium is Pareto-
dominated by allocations with a higher level of public good, has often been
interpreted as demonstrating that private provision leads to undersupply relative
to the socially optimal level. However, a global optimum of a Paretian social
welfare function may lie anywhere on the locus of Pareto e¢cient allocations
and not necessarily on that part of the locus that Pareto-dominates the private
provision equilibrium.
Buchanan and Kafoglis (1963) demonstrated that it was possible for coun-
terexamples to be constructed in which the quantity of a public good is decreased
as the economy moves towards the optimum from the private provision equilib-
rium. The possibility of such anomalies arising is illustrated in Figure 9.6. The
private provision equilibrium occurs at point N and the set of Pareto e¢cient
allocations are given by the locus of tangencies of the indi¤erence curves.
The line CC represents an aggregate level of public good supply equal to
that in the private provision equilibrium. For the optimum to have less of the
public good simply requires the locus of Pareto optima to cut the line CC and
9.5. PRIVATE PROVISION OF PUBLIC GOOD 277

for social welfare to be maximised at some point below C C. If the optimal point
is P a reduction in the total supply of the public good is required in the move
from the private provision equilibrium to the optimum. It should also be noted
that if the locus does cross C C, a social welfare function can always be found
that places the optimum below C C.
As shown by Diamond and Mirrlees (1973), such anomalies can only be ruled
out by placing restrictions upon the second derivatives of the households’ util-
ity functions. There are no fundamental reasons why restrictions upon second
derivatives should be satis…ed and hence anomalous cases may well occur even
in the two-household model. Therefore, although local results can be estab-
lished without too much di¢culty, it is not straightforward to provide global
comparisons.

9.5.4 The number of households


It has already been established that the private provision equilibrium is not
Pareto e¢cient. A further issue that has been addressed (Chamberlin (1974,
1976), McGuire (1974)) is how the deviation from e¢ciency depends upon the
number of households that may potentially contribute. The natural expectation
would be that an increase in the number of households would lead to greater
divergence as each household expected all others to contribute. However, as
is often the case, the actual result di¤ers somewhat from this expectation. In
addition, the limiting properties of equilibrium, as the number of households
increases without limit, will be analysed following the approach of Andreoni
(1988a).
To consider the consequence of variations in the number of households, as-
sume that all the households are identical in terms of both preferences and
endowments. Assuming both goods are normal, the uniqueness result then jus-
ti…es the study of symmetric equilibria. For an economy with H households, it
follows that at the symmetric equilibrium

G
g= ; (9.37)
H ¡1
¡ ¢
where g is the households’ common contribution. In terms of g; G space,
an allocation satisfying (9.36) must lie somewhere on a ray through the origin
with gradient H ¡ 1 and, for each level of H, the equilibrium is given by the
intersection of the appropriate ray with the reaction function. The welfare
optima, if all households are treated equally, are the locus of tangencies between
the rays and the indi¤erence curves. This is shown in Figure 9.7.
Whether the quantity of public good at the private provision equilibrium
increases as
¡ H ¢ increases is dependent upon the gradient of the reaction func-
tion. If ½0 G < ¡1, then provision, given by Hg, is an increasing function of
¡ ¢
H . When ½0 G = ¡1, provision is independent of H and it is a decreasing
¡ ¢
function of H if ½0 G > ¡1. These conditions can be related to the structure
278 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

Figure 9.7: Equilibria and Optima for Various H

of preferences via (9.33). For instance, with the utility function

U (x; G) = x + K (G) ; (9.38)


h h
the reaction curve has a gradient of - 1 since Uxx = UxG = 0 and the total level
of provision is independent of the number of households.
The e¤ect of increasing the number of households upon the divergence be-
tween the private provision equilibrium and the equal-treatment welfare optima
is not so easily determined. It can be seen in Figure 9.7 that this is dependent
upon the curvature of the indi¤erence curves between the two equilibria and,
as shown by Cornes and Sandler (1984a), both income and substitution e¤ects
are involved. What can be said is that examples can be constructed, such as
the case shown in Figure 9.7, in which the divergence decreases as H increases.
The opposite result can also be shown to be possible.
The natural extension of the above analysis is to consider the equilibrium
level of provision as the number of households tends to in…nity. An idea of what
will occur with identical households can be seen by considering the consequence
of the ray in Figure 9.7 becoming vertical: provision will tend to the level at
which the reaction function crosses the vertical axis and the provision of each
household will tend to zero. This result is due to Chamberlin (1974). Now
consider an economy where all households have the same preferences but di¤er
in their endowments. The following theorem is due to Andreoni (1988).
Theorem 9.4(Andreoni)
For an economy of H households with identical preferences and endowments
distributed according to a continuous density function f (!) with support (0; -),
then as H increases to in…nity:
(i) The proportion of the population contributing decreases to zero;
(ii) Only the households with the highest endowment contribute;
(iii) Total contributions increase to a …nite value;
(iv) The average contribution decreases to zero.
Proof
9.5. PRIVATE PROVISION OF PUBLIC GOOD 279

¡ ¢
The maximisation of household h can be written maxfxh;Gg U xh ; G sub-
h h h h
ject to the constraints
n ³x + G = G and G ¸ G . This yields the demand
´! +h o
h h
function G = max ³ ! + G ; G . It is assumed that private and public
h
goods are normal so 0 < ³ 0 < 1. If G > G , the demand function can be inverted
to give g h = ! h ¡ Á (G) where Á (G) = ³ ¡1 (G) ¡ G and 0 < Á0 (G) < 1. De…ne
by ! ¤ the level of endowment above which the household becomes a contributor
and note ! ¤ = Á (G). Then

!h ¡ ! if ! h > !¤ ;
gh =
0 if ! h !¤ :
PH P ¤ £
Hence G = h= 1 gh = !h ¡ ! ¤ = Á¡ 1 (! ¤ ).
! h> ! ¤
¡1 P £ h ¤
Now consider the function MH (s) ´ Á H(s) = H1 ! h >s ! ¡ s which, for
given endowments for the H households, has solution s = ! ¤H . Now add to the
vector of endowments by making random draws from the density f (w). By the
R-
law of large numbers, MH (s) tends to M (s) = s [! ¡ s] f (w) d! as H tends
to in…nity. Denote the solution to this equation ! ¤¤ , then limH !1 ! ¤H = ! ¤¤ .
Á¡1(! ¤ )
Since ! ¤H is bounded and Á¡ 1 is …nite, limH!1 M H = limH!1 H
H
= 0.
¤¤
R - ¤¤ ¤¤
It then follows that M (! ) = s [! ¡ ! ] f (w) d! = 0. From this, ! = -
and limH!1 ! ¤H = -.
From this result, (i), (ii) and (iv) follow immediately. (iii) follows from noting
that G = Á¡ 1 (-). jj
This theorem has been generalised by Andreoni (1988) to economies with
heterogeneous preferences. In that case, the same conclusions hold with the
addition that the set of contributors will converge to a set of individuals of a
single type.

9.5.5 Invariance results


The private provision equilibrium is characterised by some surprising invariance
properties. Changes in the endowment distribution that satisfy certain condi-
tions will not a¤ect the total level of provision. An increase in exogeneous public
good supply, for instance through the government providing some public good
in addition to the private sector, will not a¤ect total supply in the limit. Public
provision therefore crowds out private provision on a one-for-one basis. These
results are now demonstrated.
In most economic situations a change in the endowment, or income, distri-
bution will a¤ect the equilibrium except when households have identical a¢ne
Engel curves. For the private provision equilibrium, Warr (1982) proved the
much stronger result that, provided all households contribute, the total level
of public good is independent of the endowment distribution. This result was
extended by Bergstrom, Blume and Varian (1986) to allow for the possibility of
non-contributors. This result is given in the following theorem.
Theorem 9.5 (Bergstrom, Blume and Varian)
280 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

The total provision of the public good is una¤ected by any income redistri-
bution that leaves the set, C , of contributors unchanged.
Proof
PH h
P It was
£ h shown¤
¤ in the proof of the previous theorem that G =
¤
h=1 g =
h2 C ! ¡ ! and that ! is independent of the income distribution. From
this equality it follows trivially that any redistribution of income that does not
change the set of contributors will leave G unchanged. jj
To consider the e¤ect of an exogeneous increase ¡ in ¢public good supply,
notice that if h chooses G > Gh ; then G = ³ ! h + G h implies that g h =
¡ ¢
³ ! h + G h ¡ G h. Now let the exogeneous increase in supply be denoted by
d¡. The response of household h to this change is given by
£ ¤
dgh = ³ 0 dG h + d¡ ¡ dGh ¡ d¡; (9.39)

where dG h is the total response of households other than h. Rearranging and


summing across all households gives
PH 1¡³ 0
h =1 ³ 0
dG = ¡ PH 1¡ ³0 d¡; (9.40)
1+ h=1 ³ 0

from which the total change in supply can be calculated as

1
dG + d¡ = PH 1¡³ 0
d¡ ¸ 0; (9.41)
1+ h= 1 ³0

assuming normality, so that ³ 0 is strictly less than 1. There exists ¯ such that
PH 1¡³0
H¯ h =1 ³ 0 . Substituting into (9.40) this implies

1
dG + d¡ = d¡ (9.42)
1 + H¯

From (9.41) the invariance result of Andreoni (1988) follows as a consequence


of noting that the total change in supply tends to zero as H tends to in…nity.
For large populations, an exogeneous increase in public good supply is exactly
met by a reduction in private provision. Expressed di¤erently, any government
provision will crowd out an exactly equal amount of private provision.

9.5.6 Alternative formulations


The properties of the private provision equilibrium that have been derived have
been taken as indicative of the failure of the equilibrium concept to accurately
capture reality. The conclusion that only the richest household in a large popula-
tion will contribute is not an accurate representation of, for example, charitable
contributions in the United States. Nor does the average level of contribution
appear to be close to zero. Crowding out has been estimated to be of the order
of a 5 to 28 cent reduction for each dollar of government spending (Abrams and
9.5. PRIVATE PROVISION OF PUBLIC GOOD 281

Schmitz (1984)), not the one-for-one predicted by the analysis. At the private
provision equilibrium an increase in contribution by one household will lead to
a reduction by all others. This feature has also been criticised as an inaccurate
representation of reality. These observations have lead a number of authors to
investigate alternative maximisation procedures for the households and di¤erent
preference structures with the view to generating equilibria whose properties are
more in accord with empirical observations.
The simplest modi…cation to the private provision equilibrium is to consider
conjectural variations that di¤er from the Nash conjecture. In the maximisation
in (9.31) each household takes the contributions of others as given when making
their decision. The alternative to this is to assume that the household views the
choices of others as being dependent upon their decision and takes this variation
into account when maximising. Including this variation, the …rst-order condition
(9.32) would becomes
2 3
H
X @g j
¡Uxh p G + UGh 41 + 5 = 0; (9.43)
j=1; j6=h
@gh

j
@g
where the terms @g h are the conjectural variations. Cornes and Sandler (1984b)

investigate the e¤ects of alternative values for the conjectural variation and show
that if they are positive the equilibrium will have greater total public good
supply than the Nash equilibrium. Despite this modi…cation, Dasgupta and
Itaya (1992) demonstrate that the invariance to the distribution of endowment
still holds for any constant conjectures.
Consistent conjectures are those which agree with the actual responses of the
j
households involved, that is @@ggh must be equal to the change in contribution
that j would make if h were to change theirs. Sugden (1985) argues that the
j
only consistent conjectures are for all the terms @@ggh to be negative. If this is
the case, equilibrium provision of the public good will be zero under reasonable
assumptions.
Moving to non-Nash conjectures can therefore alter the equilibrium level
of the public good but does not necessarily eliminate the invariance properties.
Overall, this approach must be judged as somewhat arbitrary. There are sensible
game-theoretic motives for focusing upon the Nash equilibrium and these are
not matched by any other set of conjectures. If the Nash equilibrium of the
private provision economy does not agree with observations, it would seem that
the objectives of the households and the social rules they observe should be
reconsidered, not the conjectures they hold when maximising.
One approach to modi…ed preferences has been taken by Andreoni (1989,
1990) who¡ considers¢ the case of impure altruism given by the utility function
U h = U h x h ; G; g h . Here the contribution of h provides both a public and
a private return. This representation of utility leads to equilibria that are not
invariant and produce predictions closer to observed behaviour. There remains
the problem of why a pure public good should provide the private bene…t.
282 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

A …nal modi…cation that has been considered is to remove the individualism


by modifying the rules of so cial behaviour. Sugden (1984) considers the principle
of reciprocity by which each household considers the contributions of others and
contrasts them to what they feel they should make. If the contributions of others
match, or exceed, what is expected then household h is assumed to feel under
an obligation to make a similar contribution. Formalising this notion, Sugden
(1984) proves that the outcome will be Pareto e¢cient if all households agree
upon the expected contributions. In all other cases Pareto improvements can
be made by increasing supply. Bordignon (1990) has provided a formalisation
of Kantian behaviour that leads to similar conclusions.

9.5.7 Summary
In the absence of government intervention, public good provision will be left to
the private contributions of households. The basic model of private provision is
built upon the assumption of Nash behaviour and it has been shown that this
leads to an ine¢cient outcome. In addition, the equilibrium level of provision is
invariant to changes in the income distribution and exogeneous changes in public
good supply. These properties, and the limiting behaviour of the equilibrium,
are at variance with empirical observations. Alternative conjectures have been
analysed but these are entirely arbitrary and do not provide a better explanation
of reality. Altering the structure of preferences and the social rules do provide
improved predictions but no alternative has yet received convincing arguments
in its favour.

9.6 Finance by taxation


The rules for e¢cient provision derived in Section 3 require for their imple-
mentation that there are no restrictions upon the tax instruments that can be
employed by the government or, equivalently, that the government has complete
control over resource allocation. When optimal lump-sum taxes are not an avail-
able policy instrument the rule for provision, and the resulting level of provision,
must take account of the method of …nance. In particular, the gain in welfare
enjoyed due to the provision of the public good has to be o¤set against any
distortions caused by the method of …nance. This section considers the implica-
tions of methods of …nancing in an economy with a set of identical consumers,
which e¤ectively behaves as a single-consumer economy with no distributional
aspects, and in a Diamond-Mirrlees economy with many consumers.

9.6.1 Identical consumers


In an economy with many identical consumers, if a lump-sum tax can be em-
ployed at all it must feasible to choose the optimal lump-sum tax. To provide
content to the analysis it is therefore assumed that the only tax instruments
available to the government to …nance the public good are commodity taxes.
9.6. FINANCE BY TAXATION 283

This will be relaxed when di¤erentiated consumers are considered and restricted
lump-sum taxes become meaningful. The aim of the analysis is to determine
how the distortions caused by the commodities taxes a¤ect the Samuelson Rule
and the level of provision. This is undertaken by following the work of Atkinson
and Stern (1974).
Each of the identical consumers maximises their utility U (x; G) subject to
the budget constraint qx = 0 where q is the vector of post-tax prices and x the
vector of net demands. There is one change from the standard commodity tax
model: revenue must now equal expenditure, G, on the public good
n
X
H tix i = G: (9.44)
i=1

Market clearing implies that the revenue constraint and the production con-
straint may be used interchangeably as argued in Chapter 2 above. The pro-
duction constraint is used and is written in the form F (X; G) = F (Hx; G) = 0.
It is assumed that
@F
F1 = ; (9.45)
@X1
and good 1 is taken to be the numeraire with q1 = p 1 = 1. Pre-tax prices are
chosen so that F k = p k .
For the choice of optimal tax rates, t, and quantity of public good, the
appropriate Lagrangean is
L = HV (q; G) ¡ ¸F (X (q; G) ; G) : (9.46)
From this, the …rst-order condition for the choice of G is
" n #
@L @V X @Xi
´H ¡¸ Fi + FG = 0; (9.47)
@G @G i=1
@G

which, using the de…nition of pre-tax prices, can be written


n
@V
@G pk ¸ F G ¸ X @Xi
H = + pi ; (9.48)
®qk qk ® Fk ®qk @G
i=1

where ® is the marginal utility of income for each consumer. From each con-
@U
sumer’s …rst-order condition for the utility maximising choice of go od k, @x k
=
®qk . Therefore the term
@V @U
@G @G
H =H @U
; (9.49)
®qk @xk

is the sum of marginal rates of substitution between the public good and private
good k.
Evaluating the …rst-order condition (9.47) for k = 1, so that q1 = 1, it can
be rearranged to give
@U n
X
FG ® @G @Xi
= H @U
¡ [qi ¡ ti ] ; (9.50)
F1 ¸ @xk i= 1
@G
284 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

P
but since the consumers’ budget constraints imply ni=1 qi @@G
Xi
= 0, (9.49) can
be written Pn
FG ® @U @ i= 1 tiXi
= H @@ G ¡ : (9.51)
F1 ¸ @xU @G
k

The expression in (9.50) represents the Samuelson rule for optimal provision
with distorting commodity taxation. It di¤ers from the …rst-best rule (9.9) in
two ways: the sum of marginal rates of substitution is multiplied by the term ® ¸
which may not be equal to one and there is an additional term on the right-hand
side. This additional term measures the e¤ect of public good provision upon
tax revenue due to substitutability or complementarity in demand between the
public good and the private goods.
The revenue e¤ect implies that if provision of the public good increases tax
revenue, which will be the case for example if it is a complement to highly taxed
goods, this reduces the cost , measured by the M RT , of providing the public
good. This factor tends to increase provision above the level determined by the
Samuelson rule. The converse holds if provision
Pn reduces tax revenue.
@ i=1 ti Xi
To isolate the …rst e¤ect assume that @G = 0 so that the public good
is revenue neutral. In this case the departure from the …rst-best is determined
by ®¸ alone. To proceed further, consider the choice of tax rate for good k. From
the Lagrangean
n Pn
@V X @Xi @ i=1 p iXi
H =¸ Fi =¸ : (9.52)
@qk @qk @tk
i=1

Using Roy’s identity and the fact that


P P P
@ ni= 1 p iXi @ ni=1 tiXi @ ni=1 qi Xi
+ = ; (9.53)
@tk @tk @tk
(9.51) can be written Pn
@ i=1 ti X i
® @tk
= : (9.54)
¸ Xk
Finally, using the Slutsky equation,
n
X @Xi X S ik n
®
=1¡ ti + ti : (9.55)
¸ @I Xk
i=1 i=1

From (9.54) it can be seen that the divergence of ®¸


from 1 can be separated
Pn
into two components: (i) a revenue e¤ect given by i=1 ti @@IXi
; and (ii) a dis-
Pn S ik
tortionary e¤ect i=1 ti X k . From the negative semi-de…niteness of the Slutsky
matrix it follows that n
X S ik
ti 0: (9.56)
Xk
i=1

The negativity in (9.55) has the e¤ect of tending to reduce ® belowP ¸. This
would imply that the true bene…t of the public good is less than the M RS:
9.6. FINANCE BY TAXATION 285

P
In contrast, the second e¤ect ni=1 ti @@I Xi
cannot be unambiguously signed. If it
were positive then ® would be less than ¸. This would be the case if all taxed
goods were normal, but this may not be the case.
In summary, when the public good has P to be …nanced by distortionary taxa-
tion there is a divergence of M RT from M RS. This divergence can be broken
down into the e¤ect of provision on tax revenue and two further components:
one of which always P reduces the bene…t measure so that the bene…t becomes
something less than M RS, the other is also likely to reduce it though this
cannot be guaranteed. An alternative perspective upon this issue can be found
in Christiansen (1981) who derives su¢cient conditions P for the standard cost-
bene…t calculation of comparing the M RT to the M RS to be valid even
when there are distributional objectives. Adopting the Mirrlees’ formulation of
labour supply described in Chapter 5 but with a public good and a second pri-
vate good incorporated in utility, Christiansen shows that weak separability of
utility between work e¤ort and all other goods combined with the optimal taxa-
tion of income is su¢cient to eliminate the distributional factors and leave only
the basic cost-bene…t calculation. Outside of these special cases, the additional
e¤ects described above must be included in the optimality calculation.
The analysis above has been addressed to …nding the appropriate bene…t
measure in the presence of distortion and has not directly answered the question
of whether more or less public good should be provided when its provision is
…nanced by distortionary taxation. Unfortunately no complete answer can be
given to this.
Consider an economy where …nance is possible either through a lump-sum
tax T or a tax t is levied upon the single factor of production L . The Lagrangean
is
HV (t; T ; G) + ¸ [HT + tHL ¡ G] ; (9.57)
with …rst-order necessary conditions
¸
@L
Vt + ¸ L + t = 0; (9.58)
@t

HV G ¡ ¸ = 0; (9.59)
HT + HtL ¡ G = 0: (9.60)
T is treated as a parameter that can vary from 0 to G.
To provide an answer on the level of provision it would be necessary to
demonstrate that (9.57) for T = 0 and T = G could be drawn as, for example,
in Figure 9.8. In the case shown provision is lower when distortionary taxes are
employed. However, to actually show that GC T < GLS , where subscripts refer
to “commodity taxes“ or “lump sum“, it is necessary to contrast ¸ CT and ¸ LS .
The analysis has only been able to determine ® ¸
which is not su¢cient for this
purpose. The question of output levels therefore remains unanswered.
In terms of examples, Atkinson and Stern (1974) show that the for the utility
function
U (X; L; G) = a log X + [1 ¡ a] log (1 ¡ L) + f (G) ; (9.61)
286 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

Figure 9.8: Comparison of Lump-Sum and Commodity Tax Finance

the level of provision of public good is lower with commodity taxation than for
the …rst-best. Wilson (1991a) has extended this conclusion to the function

U (X; L; G) = U (! (X; 1 ¡ L) ; G) ; (9.62)

where ! (X; 1 ¡ L) is of the CES form and G is assumed to be a normal good. No


example has been published that has higher provision with commodity taxation
than at the …rst-best. This lends a degree of support for the conclusion that the
…rst-best level will exceed the second-best.

9.6.2 Di¤erentiated households


Allowing the households to di¤er in their income and preferences provides mo-
tivation for considering restricted forms of lump-sum taxation. Even though an
optimal set of lump-sum taxes may not be feasible, it may well remain possible
to levy a uniform lump-sum tax. At the margin, such taxes have the property
of providing a non-distortionary source of …nance.
Now consider an economy with an arbitrary, but non-zero, set of commodity
tax rates and implied consumer prices which are taken as …xed. Since the
private sector of the economy is distorted by the existence of the commodity
taxes, the non-distortionary uniform lump-sum tax provides a means by which
resources can be moved from the distorted sector into provision of the public
good. It does not then seem unreasonable that if the private sector is su¢ciently
distorted, more resources would be moved to the public sector than at the …rst-
best optimum. This will result in the second-best provision of the public good
being above the …rst-best.
This reasoning has been formalised by Wilson (1991b) who derives a con-
dition that determines the relative levels of public good provision and provides
examples to con…rm that second-best provision may be greater than …rst-best.
9.6. FINANCE BY TAXATION 287

Figure 9.9: Manipulating the Lindahl Equilibrium

9.6.3 Summary
The results have shown how distortionary …nancing a¤ects the form of the
Samuelson rule. Although there is a presumption that when …nance is entirely
by commodity taxation the second-best level of provision will fall below the
…rst-best, this has not been formally established and the form of (9.50) suggests
that it cannot be. In contrast, when some …nancing can be undertaken by lump-
sum taxation their non-distortionary nature provides a reason for second-best
provision to rise above …rst-best and examples have been constructed to con…rm
this.Mechanism design
That a household will choose the action that leads to the maximisation of
their welfare is one of the basic assumptions of economic theory. If applied
consistently, this assumption implies that a household will behave dishonestly
if it is in their interests to do so. This simple observation has surprisingly
important implications for the theory of public goods.
The analysis of the Lindahl equilibrium assumed that households were hon-
est in revealing their reactions to the announcement of cost shares. However,
there will be a gain to households who attempt to cheat, or manipulate, the
allocation mechanism. By announcing preferences that do not coincide with
their true preferences, it is possible for a household to modify the outcome in
their favour provided that others do not do likewise. To see this, consider a two-
household economy in which household 1 acts honestly and household 2 knows
the preferences of 1. In Figure 9.9, honesty on the part of household 2 would
lead to the equilibrium EL . However, by claiming their preferences to be given
by the Lindahl reaction function L20 (¿ 2 ), rather than the true function L(¿ 2 ),
the equilibrium can be driven to point M which represents the maximisation of
2’s utility given the Lindahl reaction function L1 (¿ 1 ) of 1.
Due to this problem, attention has focused upon the design of allocation
mechanisms that overcome attempted manipulation. As will be shown, the
design of some of these mechanisms leads households to reveal their true pref-
erences. From this property is derived the description of these mechanisms as
288 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

preference revelation mechanisms.


The general form of allocation mechanism can be described as a game in
which each household has a strategy set and chooses a strategy from this set
in order to maximise their pay-o¤. The aim of the analysis is to determine
when a game can be constructed such that the equilibrium strategies lead to
the allocation that the policy maker wishes to see implemented. The game
will be one of incomplete information since it is natural to assume that each
household has knowledge only of its own payo¤ function. For such games a
number of equilibrium concepts may be employed. Of these, most attention in
the early literature was upon the dominant strategy equilibrium, where each
household has a dominant strategy regardless of the choices of others, and the
Nash equilibrium in which the chosen strategy must be optimal given that other
households play their equilibrium strategy. In the setting of incomplete informa-
tion the dominant strategy equilibrium has the appealing property that, since
a dominant strategy is the best response to any choice by opponents, a house-
hold does not need to form any expectations about how others will play the
game. Consequently, the di¢culties caused by the incomplete information are
overcome. More recent work has also considered Bayesian equilibria in which
the information problem is explicitly modelled.

9.6.4 De…nitions
The set of potential public projects from which the choice is to be made is
denoted by G, where G is a compact set, and a typical element of G is denoted
G. There are H households who have preferences over the public projects and
over monetary transfers, th , where the monetary transfers arise as part of the
game that is played by the households. For the present, each household is
assumed to have additively separable preferences given by

U h (G; th ) = º h (G) + th : (9.63)

The representation of preferences in (9.62) is interpreted as being net of the


costs of the project imputed to household h. It is then possible to term º h (G)
the valuation of project G by household h. Q
The strategy space of household h is given by S h and S = H h= 1 S . A
h

strategy choice for household h is denoted ¡ by s ¢ 2 S with a set of strategy


h h

choices for the households denoted s = s1 ; :::; s H . A game form, ¡, consists of


a strategy space and a payo¤ function, ° h (s), for each household. If the outcome
of the game is determined by a decision function d : S ! G, which determines
the project chosen given the announced strategies, and a transfer rule t : S !
< h , t (s) = (t1 (s) ; :::; tH (s)), determining the transfer to each household, it is
termed ©a mechanism.
ª A mechanism is therefore composed of a set of strategy
spaces, S h , and a function f : S ! G £ < h , f ´ [d (s) ; t1 (s) ; :::; tH (s)] where
the accepted project is d (s) and th (s) is the transfer received by household h.
Once determined, the decision d (s) and the transfers th (s) are enacted by the
government or centre.
9.6. FINANCE BY TAXATION 289

A revelation mechanism is a mechanism for which the strategy space of


each household is the set of possible valuation functions and a strategy is the
announcement of a valuation function. The set of possible valuation func-
tions for h is denoted V h . In the case that the strategy space is the set of
possible valuations, let the reported valuation of h be given by w h (¢). A di-
rect revelation
¡ mechanism is¢ thenn de…ned as a revelation mechanism
PH suchothat
d (w) = d w 1 (¢) ; :::; w H (¢) 2 G ¤ : G¤ = arg maxfG ¤2Gg h=1 w h (G) . A
direct revelation mechanism therefore has the property that the chosen pro ject
maximises the sum of reported valuations and is therefore optimal given those
valuations. To ensure that the maximum exists, it is assumed the each º h (G)
is upper semi-continuous. The reported valuations must then also be restricted
to be upper semi-continuous.

9.6.5 Dominant strategies


If a dominant strategy exists for each participant of a game, a strong argument
can be made that the participants will play those strategies. In addition, the
existence of dominant strategies removes any need to consider how the par-
ticipants form expectations about the strategy choice of their opponents and
di¢culties introduced by the existence of incomplete information are overcome.
If the preference revelation problem can be solved by a mechanism involving
dominant strategies, there are persuasive reasons for recommending its use.
These observations provide the motivation for the study of dominant strategy
mechanisms.
A direct revelation mechanism with decision function d (w) and associated
transfers fth (w)g is termed strongly individual ly incentive compatible (s.i.i.c.)
if truth-telling is a dominant strategy. Announcement of the truth will be a
dominant strategy for all agents if and only if
¡ ¡ ¢¢ ¡ ¢
º h 2 arg max º h d w h ; w ¡ h + th w h ; w¡ h ; 8w ¡h ; h = 1; :::; H;
fw h2 V hg

¡ ¢ (9.64)
where w ¡h = w 1 ; :::; w h¡1 ; w h+1 ; :::; w H , so that the true valuation maximises
the payo¤. To demonstrate the existence of a mechanism that satis…es (9.63),
…rst note that from the de…nition of a direct revelation mechanism it follows
that d (w) has the property that
H
X
¡ ¡ ¢¢ ¡ ¡ ¢¢
º h 2 arg max º h d w h ; w ¡h + w j d w h ; w ¡h ; h = 1; :::; H:
fw h2V hg
j= 1;j6=h
(9.65)
Hence truthful revelation by h maximises the sum of the payo¤ to h and the
payo¤s, in terms of announced valuations, to the other households. Now write
the transfers in the form
H
X
th (w) = w j (d (w)) + rh (w) ; h = 1; :::; H; (9.66)
j=1;j6= h
290 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

which can always be done by suitable choice of the functions r h (w). Using
(9.65), the dominant strategy condition (9.63) can be written

H
X
¡ ¡ h ¡h ¢¢ ¡ ¡ ¢¢ ¡ ¢
º h 2 arg max
h h
º h
d w ; w + w j d w h ; w ¡ h +rh wh ; w ¡h ; h = 1; :::; H:
fw 2V g
j=1;j6=h
(9.67)
Contrasting (9.66) and (9.64) it¡ can be seen
¢ that social and individual objec-
tives will coincide whenever rh w h ; w ¡h is independent of w h . Following its
introduction in Groves (1973), a Groves scheme is de…ned by a set of transfers
such that
H
X ¡ ¢
th (w) = w j (d (w)) + rh w ¡h ; h = 1; :::; H; (9.68)
j=1;j6=h

and a Groves mechanism is a direct revelation mechanism with the transfer rule
given by (9.67). The reasoning above can then be summarised in the following
theorem which was originally proved in Groves and Loeb (1975).

Theorem 45 (Groves and Loeb) A Groves mechanism is strongly individually


incentive compatible.

Proof. Directly from comparing (9.64) and (9.66) after substitution of


(9.67).
The interpretation of the Groves mechanism is that the transfers are designed
so that the only e¤ect the strategy choice of a household can have upon the
size of the transfer is via the e¤ect that the decision on the public pro ject,
based upon that strategy, has upon other households’ welfare. There is no
direct e¤ect on the transfer. This mechanism can be viewed as internalising
the external consequences of the strategy choice of each household, since the
external consequences are given by the welfare e¤ects on other households of
the public decision. In a¡ Clarke
¢ mechanism, which was introduced by Clarke
(1971), the functions r h w ¡h are given by

H
X
¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ ¢¢
r h w ¡h = ¡ w j dh w ¡h ; h = 1; :::; H; (9.69)
j=1;j6=h

¡ ¢ P
where dh w ¡h is the maximiser of H j
j=1; j6=h w (G). In this case the transfer is
exactly the change in welfare of other households due to in‡uence of household
h on the public project decision. This is a special case of the Groves mechanism.
Having demonstrated the existence of an s.i.i.c. mechanism it is natural to
consider whether there are any alternative mechanisms that will also serve the
same purpose. The following analysis will show that there are not: the Groves
mechanism is the only s.i.i.c. direct revelation mechanism. To demonstrate this
result, which is due to Green and La¤ont (1977), it is …rst necessary to provide
the following de…nition.
9.6. FINANCE BY TAXATION 291

Direct revelation mechanism


A direct revelation mechanism satis…es
(i) the transfer independence¡ ¡property
¢ if th¤ (w)
¡ ¡his independent
¢ G ¤ i.e.,
¡of ¡h ¢ if
¡h h h0 ¤ h h h0
for w ; w ; w such that G w ; w = G w ; w then th w ; w h =
¡ ¢
th w ¡ h ; w h 0 ;
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ PH
(ii) the compensation property if th w¡ h ; wh ¡th w ¡h ; wh 0 = j=1;j6=h w j (G¤ )¡
PH j ¤0 ¤
j= 1;j6=h w (G ) where G maximises the sum of announced valuations given
w and G is the maximising project given announcement wh 0.
h ¤0

It is immediately clear from this de…nition that the transfer independence


and compensation properties uniquely characterise the Groves mechanism. A
direct revelation mechanism is therefore a Groves mechanism if and only if it
satis…es transfer independence and compensation.
The proof that the Groves mechanism is the only s.i.i.c. direct revelation
mechanism can now be undertaken by demonstrating that if transfer indepen-
dence and compensation are not satis…ed by a direct revelation mechanism, it
cannot be s.i.i.c. Therefore it follows from the equivalence of these conditions to
the Groves mechanism that the Groves mechanism is the unique s.i.i.c. direct
revelation mechanism. The relevant theorem is as follows.

Theorem 46 (Green and La¤ont) An s.i.i.c. direct revelation mechanism must


satisfy the transfer independence and compensation properties.

Proof. First assume that there exists an s.i.i.c. direct revelation mechanism
¡h h h0
for which transfer independence is not ¡ satis…ed. ¢ Then¡ ¡ there are
¢ w ; w ; hw
¤ ¡h h h h0
with the same optimal G but with th w ; w > th w ; w . Now let º =
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
w h 0 and note that th w¡ h ; wh + º h (G ¤ ) > th w¡ h ; º h + º h (G¤ ). The choice
of º h is then not a dominant strategy. An s.i.i.c. direct revelation mechanism
must therefore satisfy transfer independence.
Now assume that the mechanism does not satisfy the compensation
P property.
There then exist w ¡h ; w h ; w h0 such that G ¤ maximises H j=1;j6=h w j + w h over
PH ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
G, G¤0 maximises j=1;j6=h w j + w h0 over G and th w ¡h ; w h ¡ th w ¡h ; w h0 =
PH j ¤
PH j ¤0
j= 1;j6=h w (G ) = j= 1;j6=h w (G ) + " for some " > 0.
0 0 P 0 P
Let w e h (G¤ ) = ¡ H
e h be de…ned by w j ¤
e h (G¤0) = ¡ H
j=1;j6=h w (G ) ; w
j ¤0
j=1;j6=h w (G )+
0 P
"
2
and w e h (G) = ¡c for G 6= G¤ or G ¤0 with c > maxfG 2Gg H j
j=1;j6=h w (G) +
0 0
weh (G). Since weh is upper semi-continuous, it is a permissible valuation an-
nouncement.
P 0
Now note that G ¤0 = arg maxfG 2Gg H j e h (G), since it has
j=1; j6=h w (G) + w ³ 0
´
been shown that the mechanism must satisfy transfer independence, th w ¡ h ; w h =
292 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS
³ 0
´
e h . Hence
th w ¡h ; w
¡ ¢ ³ 0
´ ¡ ¢ ³ 0
´
th w ¡h ; w h ¡ th w ¡h ; w h = th w ¡h ; w h ¡ th w ¡h ; w
eh
H
X H
X
= w j (G¤ ) ¡ w j (G¤0) + "
j=1;j6=h j=1;j6=h
h0 ¤ "
h0
w =
e (G ) + w e (G ¤0 ) + :
2
¡ ¡h h¢ 0
³ 0
´ 0
Rearranging gives th w ; w + weh (G¤ ) > th w ¡h ; weh + weh (G ¤0 ). Letting
0
ºh ´ w e h then contradicts the assumption that the mechanism was s.i.i.c since
truth is not the dominant strategy. A s.i.i.c. direct revelation mechanism must
therefore satisfy the compensation property.
In the form given, Theorem 9.7 only restricts the valuation functions to be in
the class of semi-continuous functions. However, restricting the set from which
valuation functions may be drawn does not extend the set of direct revelation
mechanisms. As proved by Holmstrom (1979), provided the domain of valuation
functions is smoothly connected (that is, there exists a di¤erentiable deformation
of one valuation function in the domain into any other), the Groves scheme will
be unique.
These results permit the study of s.i.i.c. direct revelation mechanisms to be
undertaken by studying only the properties of Groves mechanisms. Although it
has been shown that a Groves mechanism can implement the correct choice of
project, it should not be presumed that it will necessarily lead to a fully-e¢cient
equilibrium. To be e¢cient the mechanism must also have the property that the
sum of transfers must be identically zero, in which case the mechanism is termed
balanced. If it is negative some resources are being taken from the households
and not used to produce welfare elsewhere. It may be felt that these resources
could be redistributed to the households but if this were done the incentives
would be introduced for the households to choose their announced valuation
taking into the e¤ect it would have upon the redistribution. The s.i.i.c. aspect
of the mechanism would then fail. Conversely, if the sum of transfers is positive,
some resources are being transferred from the centre to the households and the
centre is bearing the cost of implementing the mechanism.
To investigate the possibilities, assume that the valuation functions are dif-
ferentiable and can be given a one-dimensional parametrisation. Let household
h be described by the preference parameter µ³h 2 £ h´where £h is an open interval
of < and assume the valuation function º h G; µ h is smooth. Finally, assume
³ ´
there for any array of household preferences µ = µ 1 ; :::; µH , there exists a dif-
PH ³ ´
ferentiable function G ¤ (µ) > 0 such that G¤ (µ) = arg maxfG >0g h=1 º h G; µ h .
The following theorem describes the conditions necessary for the existence of a
balanced mechanism.

Theorem 47 (Green and La¤ont) There exists a balanced mechanism if and


9.6. FINANCE BY TAXATION 293

only if
H
X ¸
@ H ¡1 @º h @G¤
´ 0:
h=1
@µ1 ; :::; @µ h¡1 ; @µh +1 ; :::; ; @µ H @G @µ h

Proof. In the case described the transfer functions will depend only on the
h
parameter vector µ . Denoting the true preference parameter e
h ³ of h byh ´µ , truth
will be the dominant strategy if µe = arg maxf µh2£ hg º h G¤ (µ) ; e µ + th (µ)
h ¤ h
for all µ ¡h . This will only apply if @º @G @th
@G @ µh + @ µh ´ ³ 0 when evaluated at eµ for all
´ R h
@G ¤
µ ¡h . Integrating with respect to µ h then gives th µh ; µ ¡h = ¡ @º @G @ µh
dµ +
³ ´ ³ ´
rh µ¡h , where rh µ¡ h is arbitrary.
PH hR @º h @ G¤ ³ ´i
The mechanism is therefore balanced if h=1 ¡ @G @ µh dµ + rh µ¡ h ´
0. Di¤erentiating this condition for a balanced h h mechanism
i with respect to
1 H PH @ H¡1 @º @G¤
µ ; :::; µ gives h=1 @µ 1;:::; @µh¡1;@µ h+1;: ::;;@µ H @G @µh
´ 0 which establishes
necessity. Su¢ciency is proved by integrating the stated condition successively
to obtain the condition for a balanced mechanism.
Since the condition required for the Groves mechanism to be balanced even in
the simple environment of parametrised preferences is restrictive, this theorem
demonstrates that it will not be possible to always …nd a balanced mechanism.
This result is established formally by Green and La¤ont (1979) who prove that
there exists no Groves mechanism that is balanced for all possible valuations.
It is therefore unlikely that a Groves mechanism will achieve full e¢ciency. The
lack of e¢ciency is, of course, the price that has to be paid for the revelation of
information.
These negative conclusions are somewhat diminished as the size of the pop-
ulation of households increases. As shown by Green and La¤ont (1979) and
Rob (1982), the likelihood that any household receives a negative transfer (i.e.
pays a tax) tends to zero as the population increases without bound and the
expected total transfer also tends to zero. These results imply that the limiting
outcome is approximately e¢cient.
A important assumption that has been employed up to this point has been
the additively separability of preferences described in (9.62). Given the restric-
tiveness of this assumption, it would be hoped that this was simply a convenient
assumption that could be dropped when necessary. Unfortunately this is not
the case. Bergstrom and Cornes (1983) have shown that the Groves mechanism
will still function successfully if preferences are given by
¡ ¢
U h x h ; G = A (G) x h + B h (G) ; h = 1; :::; H; (9.70)

where A (G), which is assumed to be known, is common to all individuals and


x h is the quantity of private good consumed by h. This, however, is only a
minor extension.
The possibility of proving a general result on the existence of an s.i.i.c. is
ruled out by the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem. To describe the content of this
294 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

theorem, consider a set ¥ of social states and a set of economic agents. Each
of the H economic agents has a preference order, P h , de…ned over ¥. Let ¦ be
the set of possible preference orders. A social choice function (SCF) is de…ned
as a function from £H H
h=1 ¦ into ¥ which assigns to any P 2 £ h=1 ¦ a social
state » 2 ¥. An SCF, W ¡ , is manipulable ¢at the preference pro…le P if there
exists P h0 such that W P 1 ; :::; P h0 ; :::; P H is preferred by h, with preference
¡ ¢
P h, to W P 1 ; :::; P h; :::; P H . Manipulability means that h can alter the social
decision to one they prefer by announcing a set of preferences, P h0 , which di¤er
from their true preferences. The SCF is s.i.i.c. if there is no set of preferences,
P , at which it is manipulable. Now let the range of the SCF, W , be ¥0 µ ¥.
The SCF is dictatorial when for any » 2 ¥0, » 6= W (P ), W (P ) is preferred by
h to ». Agent h is then said to be the dictator.
Given these preliminaries, the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem can now be
stated.

Theorem 48 (Gibbard-Satterthwaite) If ¥0 has at least three alternatives, an


SCF with range ¥0 satisfying s.i.i.c. and having an unrestricted domain (so no
restrictions on preferences are permitted) is dictatorial.

Proof. See La¤ont (1987).


The implication of the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem is that the search for
a mechanism that will e¢ciently implement social decisions in all circumstances
is a futile one. As has been shown, the Groves mechanism illustrates that
implementation can occur in some restricted circumstances but there is little
hope for proceeding very far beyond this. This negative conclusion provides the
motivation for studying equilibrium concepts that are weaker than dominant
strategies.

9.6.6 Nash equilibrium


The simplest alternative equilibrium concept is that of Nash equilibrium, so that
each household’s strategy has to be optimal only against the optimal choices of
other households. This weakening of the equilibrium concept does open up new
possibilities and the work of Groves and Ledyard (1977) demonstrates that Nash
equilibrium can lead to optimality. However, there remain di¢culties with the
interpretation of the Nash equilibrium concept in the context of games with
incomplete information. These will be discussed further below after the results
that can be obtained are described.
Consider a set ¥ of social states and an SCF, W , W : £H h= 1 ¦ ! ¥. The
game form ¡ implements W if, for every P 2 £H h= 1 ¦, the set of equilibrium
strategies for ¡, denoted
¡ E ¡ (P ¢), is non-empty and ¡ (E ¡ (P )) µ W (P ). A set
of strategy choices s1¤ ; :::; sH¤ are a Nash equilibrium for the game form ¡ if
and only if for all h
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
° h sh ¤ ; s¡h¤ > ° h sh ; s¡ h¤ ; 8s h 2 S h : (9.71)
9.6. FINANCE BY TAXATION 295

The …rst result of this subsection, due to Dasgupta et al. (1979), concerns
the relationship between truthful implementation in Nash equilibrium and in
dominant strategies.

Theorem 49 (Dasgupta, Hammond and Maskin) The social choice function W


can be truthfully implemented in Nash strategies if and only if it can be truthfully
implemented in dominant strategies.

Proof. If W can be implemented in dominant strategies, it can be im-


plemented in Nash since a dominant strategy equilibrium is a Nash equilib-
rium. Now assume that the game form ¡ truthfully implements W in Nash
strategies. For all P 2 £H h=1 ¦, truthful revelation is then a Nash equilib-
rium.¡ This ¢implies¡ that for ¢all h, for all P 2 £H h=1 ¦, and for all P
h0
2 ¦,
h h ¡h h h0 ¡h
° P ;P > ° P ;P . Truth is therefore the dominant strategy.
The implication of this theorem is that there is nothing to be gained by
considering Nash equilibria in direct mechanisms since the same result could be
obtained by considering only dominant strategies. If the Nash equilibrium is to
be of value in extending the set of circumstances in which implementation can
take place it will be necessary to consider mechanisms in which individuals do
not announce their true preferences at the equilibrium.
The major contribution of Groves and Ledyard (1977) was to provide a
mechanism that was balanced and which lead to a Pareto optimal allocation.
Assume that there are available K public goods and denote the price vector (to
the public sector) of these public goods by pG . The Groves-Ledyard mechanism
then restricts strategy space of each household to be <K . This can be given the
interpretation that each household announces the incremental adjustment they
would like to be made to the sum of public goods supplies requested by other
households. With this restricted strategy space, the mechanism clearly does not
¡elicit the valuation
¢ functions from the households. For PaH set of strategy choices
s1 ; :::; sH the decision function is given by d (s) ´ h =1 sh and the transfer
functions by
2 3
XH ¸
¯ H ¡ 1 £ ¡ ¢¤ 2 ¡ ¢ 2
th (s) ´ ¡ 4® hp G sj + s h ¡ ¹ s¡ h ¡ ¾ s¡h 5 ; h = 1; :::; H;
2 H
j=1
(9.72)
PH h
¡ ¡h
¢ PH j
¡ ¢
¡h 2 1
PH h
£
¡ ¡h ¢¤ 2
where h =1 ® = 1, ¯ > 0, ¹ s ´ j=1;j6=h s and ¾ s ´ j= 1;j6=h s ¡ ¹ s
H¡2 .
Under this transfer rule the transfer from household h increases as their request
deviates further from the average of other requests and is reduced as the squared
standard error of the others’ requests increases.
Although the Groves-Ledyard mechanism is balanced and achieves Pareto
optimality, di¢culties still remain. In the context of the private ownership
economy with government in which they embedded the mechanism, there is no
reason to believe that the mechanism is individually rational. That is, after
participating in the mechanism a household may be left with a utility level
lower than that given by their initial endowment. In these circumstances the
296 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

rational act for the household would be not to engage in trade but to simply
consume their endowment. Imposing individual rationality, Hurwicz (1979a,
1979b) demonstrates, under mild continuity and convexity restrictions, that the
set of Lindahl allocations is a subset of the Nash equilibria and all interior Nash
equilibria are Lindahl allocations.
These results would seem to suggest that implementation in Nash strategies
provides an attractive means of overcoming the failings of the dominant strategy
mechanisms. Unfortunately, Nash mechanisms are not without their failings.
The ma jor di¢culty is the level of knowledge implied by the equilibrium concept.
Interpreted literally, it requires each household to know the preferences of the
others and to be able to solve the game for the set of equilibrium strategies.
Such common knowledge amongst the households is in sharp contrast to the
lack of knowledge of the centre. Although it has been argued that there may
be situations when this is appropriate (see Moore and Repullo 1988), the public
goods problem is almost certainly not amongst them. Alternatively, the Nash
equilibrium could be seen as being achieved as the outcome of some iterative
process but, again, this falls outside the scenario envisaged.

9.6.7 Bayesian equilibria

Bayesian equilibria, in which each household holds a probability distribution


over the distribution of preferences in the population and maximise expected
utility subject to this, have also been considered most notably by d’Aspremont
and Gérard-Varet (1979) and La¤ont and Maskin (1982). Although Bayesian
equilibria can generate fully e¢cient outcomes, in common with Nash equilibria
they su¤er from informational di¢culties. In order that a household can cal-
culate an equilibrium strategy the probability distributions held by the house-
holds must be common knowledge. In addition, Bayesian mechanisms su¤er
from multiplicity of equilibria. These points alone are su¢cient to cast serious
doubt upon the relevance of Bayesian equilibria.

9.6.8 Conclusions

This review of mechanism design has included some positive results and some
negative ones. It has been shown possible to achieve e¢cient, though not al-
ways fully-e¢cient, outcomes when preferences are separable using dominant
strategies. Unfortunately, the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem shows that this
result cannot be extended to apply to all possible forms of preferences. E¢-
ciency is attainable using Nash equilibrium but the informational requirements
of the equilibrium concept appear unsustainable in the public goods context.
The same is also true of Bayesian equilibrium. The mechanism design problem
is therefore far from fully solved.
9.7. EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE AND MARKET DATA 297

9.7 Experimental evidence and market data


The previous section has considered the design of mechanisms to elicit house-
holds’ valuations of public goods. The presumption that such a mechanism is
required is based on the view that households act always to maximise welfare
even when this involves dishonesty. Whether this view is justi…ed has been
tested in numerous experiments and the results of a number of these are de-
scribed in section 9.1. Although households may have an incentive to not reveal
their true preferences in markets involving public goods, this does not apply
in markets for private goods. This suggests the possibility that behaviour in
markets for private goods may reveal information about preferences for public
goods.

9.7.1 Experimental evidence


The analysis of private provision demonstrated that the equilibrium will not be
Pareto e¢cient and that, compared to Pareto-improving allocations, too little of
the public good will be supplied. A simple explanation of this result can be given
in terms of each household relying on others to contribute and hence deciding to
contribute little themselves. In a sense, each household is free-riding on others’
contributions and, since all attempt to free-ride, the total contribution fails
to reach an e¢cient level. The similar, but distinct, concept of misrevelation
of preferences was analysed in the previous section. If asked to reveal their
valuation of a public good, each household will typically have strategic motives
for revealing a false valuation in order to manipulate the allocation mechanism
in their favour.
The experimental literature on public goods has attempted to test the pre-
dictions of these theories and to evaluate methods of overcoming misrevelation.
Unfortunately, some of the literature has not been su¢ciently careful in the dis-
tinction between free-riding and misrevelation with the result that some papers
discuss examples of misrevelation and then conduct an experiment that tests
the free-riding hypothesis. With this in mind, the results of a number of these
experiments are now discussed.
Marwell and Ames (1981) report the …ndings of a series of experiments. The
basic structure of the experiments, which was maintained in many later exper-
iments, was to give participants a number of tokens that could be invested in
either an individual exchange or a group exchange. The individual exchange had
a set repayment per token that was independent of the total investment by the
individual and of the total investment by the group. This should be interpreted
as the purchase of a private good. In contrast, the return from the group ex-
change was dependent upon the investment into the group exchange of the other
participants and an investment in the group exchange by any participant lead to
a payment to all participants. The group exchange therefore has the properties
of a pure public good. The rates of return were made known to the participants
and the total return from investment was paid to the participant. It was there-
fore in the interests of each participant to maximise their payo¤. The structure
298 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

of payo¤s were such that the private provision equilibrium would result in no
investments in the public good although the e¢cient outcome would involve
only investment in the public good. Each participant made a single investment
decision.
Although the structure of payo¤s, the distribution of tokens and the nature
of the public good (divisible or lumpy) changed between experiments, the results
were remarkable consistent. In the …rst 11 experiments, the average investment
in the public good lay between 28% and 87% of tokens with most observations
falling in the 40%-50% range. In the 12th experiment, with a group of …rst-year
graduates in Economics, the investment in the public good fell to 20%. These
results clearly do not support the predictions of the private provision model.
Isaac, Walker and Thomas (1984) modi…ed the experiment by repeating the
investment decision over ten rounds with the view that this should allow time for
the participants to learn about free-riding and develop the optimal strategy. The
results from this experiment are not as clear as in Marwell and Ames (1981) and
a wider range of investments occurs. Free-riding is not completely supported but
some instances are reported in which it does occur. However, this …nding should
be treated with caution since having ten rounds of the game introduces aspects of
repeated game theory. While it remains true that the only credible equilibrium
of the repeated game is the private provision equilibrium of the corresponding
single-period game, it is possible that in the experiments some participants may
have been attempting to establish cooperative equilibria by playing in a fashion
that invited cooperation. Additionally, those not trained in game theory may
have been unable to derive the optimal strategy even though they could solve
the single-period game. Similar comments apply to Kim and Walker (1984) who
also employ a repeated game framework. In their experiments free-riding was
found to occur but some odd responses involving occasional large investments
in the public good also arose.
The repeated game framework was also applied by Isaac, McCue and Plott
(1985) who conducted nine experiments with undergraduate economists. It was
found that the contributions to the public good fell short of the Lindahl level
but remained above the zero level that would occur in the private provision
equilibrium. It is interesting to note that in experiments in which the Lindahl
level was announced after 5 or 6 rounds, the contributions then increased. Al-
lowing communication also raised contributions but less noticeably. Overall, the
experiments show some evidence of free-riding but do not conform exactly to
the predictions of the private provision equilibrium. Isaac and Walker (1988)
use the same format to examine the e¤ect of group size upon free-riding. The
results show that increasing group size leads to increased divergence from the
e¢cient outcome when accompanied by a decrease in marginal return from the
public good but the results do not support a pure numbers-in-group e¤ect. This
…nding is compatible with the theoretical …nding that the e¤ect of group size
on the divergence from optimality was in general indeterminate.
The results above indicate that there is little evidence of free-riding in single-
period, or one-shot, games but in the repeated games the contributions fall to-
wards the private provision level as the game is repeated. Andreoni (1988b)
9.7. EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE AND MARKET DATA 299

suggests two reasons for these …ndings and attempts to choose between them.
The …rst possibility is that the decay could be due to learning as the partici-
pants are initially unable to solve the game and only learn the optimal strategy
by repeated play. Alternatively, the pattern of contributions observed may be a
strategic choice where some cooperation in the early stages is part of that strat-
egy. To distinguish between the two explanations, one set of participants in the
experiment were placed in di¤erent groups after each round of investment. Since
the groups were randomly chosen, this prevented any bene…t existing from play-
ing a long-term strategy. Alongside these varying groups were 3 groups which
remained …xed throughout the 10 rounds of the experiment. If the strategic
explanation is correct, the …xed groups should have higher contribution levels
in the early stages of the game. In addition to the groups playing a …xed num-
ber of 10 rounds, an identical number of participants again split into …xed and
varying groups were subject to 10 rounds of the game and then told the game
was to be restarted for another 10 rounds. If learning is the correct explanation,
restarting should not a¤ect the level of contributions.
The results do not con…rm either hypothesis. Contributions by the members
of …xed groups were always less than those made by members of the variable
groups and in both cases remained above the level that would be achieved in
the private provision equilibrium After the restart the level of contributions was
temporarily higher for the variable groups. For the …xed groups there was a
lasting increase in contribution after the restart.
Taken together, these experiments do not provide great support for the equi-
librium based on the private provision economy with Nash behaviour. In the
single-period games free-riding is unambiguously rejected. Although it appears
after several rounds in repeated games, the explanation for the strategies in-
volved is not entirely apparent. Neither a strategic nor a learning hypothesis
is con…rmed. What seems to be occurring is that the participants are initially
guided more by a sense of fairness than by Nash behaviour. When this fairness is
not rewarded, the tendency is then to move towards the Nash equilibrium. The
failure of experimentation to support free-riding lends some encouragement to
the views of Johansen (1977) that although such behaviour may be individually
optimal, it is not actually observed in practice.
In a series of papers Bohm (1971, 1972 1984) has suggested a procedure for
dealing with misrevelation, provided experimental results and has described the
outcome of the procedure in practice. To provide a practical method for deter-
mining the valuation of a public good, Bohm suggests running two preference
revelation mechanisms simultaneously. The …rst mechanism should be designed
to lead to an under-reporting of the true valuation of the pro ject and the second
to the over-reporting. The direction of misrevelation can easily be controlled by
the link between reported valuation and the charge levied for use of the public
good. For instance, if the charge is credibly announced to be zero then over-
reporting will always take place if provision of the public good is dependent
upon reported valuations being greater than its cost. If those whose valuations
are sought are randomly allocated between the …rst and second mechanism then
an upper and lower bound are obtained on the valuation of the public good with
300 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS

the true valuation lying somewhere in the interval. The decision to provide the
public good is then taken if all points in the interval are greater than the cost
and it is not provided if all points are less than the cost. A level of cost lying in
the interval indicates potential indi¤erence between provision and non-provision
of the public good at the given level of cost.
Bohm (1972) conducted an experimental implementation of this procedure
on 200 people from Stockholm who had to evaluate the bene…t of seeing a pre-
viously unshown TV program. The participants were divided into four groups
which faced the following payment mechanisms: (i) pay stated valuation; (ii)
pay a fraction of stated valuation such that costs are covered from all payments;
(iii) pay a low ‡at fee and (iv) no payment. Although the …rst two provide an in-
centive to under-report and the latter two to over-report, the experiment found
that there was no signi…cant di¤erence in the stated valuations, suggesting that
misrevelation may not be as important as suggested by the theory. In the prac-
tical application, Bohm (1984) describes how the choice on whether to collect
statistics on housing is determined by obtaining the local government valua-
tions of these. Two alternative contracts were o¤ered, the …rst had payment
as a proportion of valuation with the proportion chosen to cover costs and the
second had a …xed payment for any valuation over a given …gure. A valuation
below this …gure resulted in exclusion from the use of the statistics. The results
indicated that valuations were on average lower (SEK 827) for the o¤ered the
…rst contract than for those o¤ered the second (SEK 889) with the valuation
interval being small. This work suggests that the misrevelation problem is not
as great as the theory predicts and that simple procedures may well exist that
overcome the actual degree of misrevelation.
In assessing these results, it must be borne in mind that the experimental
procedures are always sub ject to the criticism that the participants do not treat
them in the way they would act in real situations. The rewards involved are
usually small and the experiment is always somewhat arti…cial. Furthermore,
the participants may not be a representative sample of the population.

9.7.2 Market data


When acting in a competitive market, a household has no incentive to reveal
false information about their preferences. At the parametric price they face,
their only decision is the quantity to buy and if they do not buy the quantity
that is optimal for them the only e¤ect is to reduce their welfare. This simple
observation can sometimes provide the basis for constructing valuation schedules
for public goods.
To focus the following discussion, consider the case of housing. Viewed in a
characteristics framework (see Lancaster (1966) or Gorman and Myles (1987)),
a house is treated as a collection of attributes and the value to a purchaser of
a house is determined by their assessment of the set of attributes. Equally, the
cost of supplying a house is also dependent upon the attributes supplied. As
shown by Rosen (1974), willingness-to-pay and willingness-to-supply schedules
determine the equilibrium price as a function of characteristics. Now consider
9.8. CONCLUSIONS 301

that part of the attraction of any house is the environmental quality of its
locality, for example whether there is a nearby park. There is obviously no
market for environmental quality as such, but if the prices of a variety of houses
are observed that di¤er in their environmental quality then a valuation of this
can be derived by obtained by observing the prices at which they trade. The
di¤erence in price of two houses that are identical in all respects except for
environmental quality captures the value of the environmental di¤erence.
These observations lead into the theory of hedonic analysis of price which
is the statistical formalisation of the method just described. Examples of the
application of hedonics can be found in Griliches (1971), Ball (1973) and Brook-
shire et al. (1982). It must be noted that the method do es have shortcomings,
particular in that many public goods may have no private good market associ-
ated with them.

9.8 Conclusions
This chapter has reviewed the standard analysis of the e¢cient level of provision
of a public good leading to the Samuelson rule and its generalisations. These
e¢ciency rules generate allocations that can only be achieved if the government
is unrestricted in its policy tools or, as the Lindahl equilibrium demonstrated,
personalised pricing can be employed. If a uniform price must be charged, it was
shown that private provision would not generate a Pareto e¢cient outcome and
that it would be Pareto-improving for each household to increase their contribu-
tion towards provision of the public good. Such results provide a natural role for
the government to participate in …nancing and provision and the consequences
of …nancing public goods by distortionary taxation were analysed.
One aspect of public goods that prevents the government making e¢cient
decisions is the government’s lack of knowledge of households’ preferences and
willingness to pay for public goods. Mechanisms were shown to exist that could
overcome the incentives for households to misreveal their preferences but for
the most relevant equilibrium concept, that of dominant strategies, these were
restricted in the forms of preferences to which they applied. Despite these
rather negative theoretical conclusions, experimental evidence indicates that
household behaviour when confronted with decision problems involving public
goods does not conform with the theoretical prediction and that the private
provision equilibrium may not be as ine¢cient as theory suggests. Furthermore,
misrevelation has not been con…rmed as the inevitable outcome.
302 CHAPTER 9. PUBLIC GOODS
Chapter 10

Externalities

10.1 Introduction
An externality represents a connection between economic agents which lies out-
side the price system of the economy. As the level of externality generated is not
controlled directly by price, the standard e¢ciency theorems on market equi-
librium cannot be applied. The market failure that can result raises a potential
role for correction through policy intervention.
Externalities and their control are a sub ject of increasing practical impor-
tance. The greenhouse e¤ect is one of the most signi…cant examples of the
consequences of an externality but there are any number of others, from purely
local environmental issues to similarly global ones. Although these may not
appear at …rst sight to be economic problems, many of the policy responses to
their existence have been based on the economic theory of externalities. The
purpose of this chapter is to demonstrate the consequences of the existence of
externalities and to the review policy responses that have been suggested. In
particular, it will be shown how the unregulated economy generally fails to reach
an e¢cient outcome and to what degree this can be corrected using standard
tax instruments.
The chapter begins with a discussion of alternative de…nitions of an exter-
nality which di¤er in whether they focus on e¤ects or consequences. Adopting
an e¤ect-based de…nition, it is then shown how the market generally fails to
achieve e¢ciency. This lack of e¢ciency is contrasted to the claim of the Coase
theorem that e¢ciency will be eliminated by trade. An emphasis is placed on
the role of missing markets and ine¢ciency in bargaining with incomplete in-
formation. The design of the optimal set of corrective, or Pigouvian, taxes is
then addressed under alternative assumptions about the feasible degree of dif-
ferentiation between di¤erent households and …rms. The chapter is completed
by contrasting the use of taxes with direct control through tradable licences and
value of internalisation.

303
304 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

10.2 Externalities
Although the nature of an externality as an e¤ect in‡icted by one agent upon
another may seem very clear at an intuitive level, once a formalisation is at-
tempted a number of issues arise that need to be resolved. Of most importance
is the question of whether the existence of an externality should be judged by
its e¤ects or by its consequences. Since both approaches have some merit, but
can lead to di¤erent classi…cations, there is no universally agreed de…nition of
an externality. This section discusses two alternative de…nitions and describes
the representation of externalities adopted in the following analysis.

10.2.1 De…nitions
In the literature there have been a number of alternative de…nitions of an ex-
ternality and several attempts at providing classi…cations of various types of
externality; a survey is presented in Baumol and Oates (1988). There are two
ma jor categories of de…nition, the …rst of which de…nes an externality by its
e¤ects and the second by the reason for its existence and its consequences.
The …rst de…nition of an externality is the most commonly adopted and is
based on the e¤ects of externalities.
Externality (1)
An externality is present whenever some economic agent’s welfare (utility
or pro…t) includes real variables whose values are chosen are chosen by others
without particular attention to the e¤ect upon the welfare of the other agents
they a¤ect.
This is a very broad de…nition but does have the advantage of allowing an
externality to be recognised from its e¤ects. The de…nition also implicitly dis-
tinguishes between two broad categories of externality. A production externality
is said to exist when the e¤ect of the externality is upon a pro…t relationship and
a consumption externality is present whenever a utility level is a¤ected. Clearly,
an externality can be both a consumption and a production externality simul-
taneously. For a household, an externality can a¤ect either the consumption set
or the utility function. In either case, …nal welfare will be a¤ected. Similarly,
for a …rm, an externality may determine the structure of the production set or
it may enter the pro…t function directly.
The di¢culty with this de…nition is its dependence upon the institutional
context in which it is placed. The following example of Heller and Starret (1976)
illustrates this point. In a barter economy with two households, the utility of
each household is dependent upon the quantity that the other household is
willing to give up in exchange. From the de…nition above, this must clearly
count as an externality although such a classi…cation seems inappropriate. If
the institutional setting is altered by the introduction of competitive markets
then the externality is removed. Furthermore, it is precisely the nonexistence
of functioning markets for external e¤ects that leads them to be classi…ed as
externalities. Based on this reasoning, Heller and Starret (1976) provide an
10.2. EXTERNALITIES 305

alternative de…nition of externalities that relates to existence, or otherwise, of


markets and the consequences of the externality.
Externality (2)
An externality is present whenever there is an insu¢cient incentive for a
potential market to be created for some good and the nonexistence of this market
leads to a non-Pareto optimal equilibrium.
Although the conditions of the second de…nition are stronger than those of
the …rst so that, for a given institutional framework, the externalities it identi…es
will be a subset of those identi…ed by the …rst, in most cases the two de…nitions
will delineate precisely the same set of e¤ects as externalities. Moreover, since
the focus below will be placed upon externalities in a competitive economy, the
e¤ects of varying the market institution upon the set of externalities will be of
limited interest. On this basis, the …rst de…nition is adopted as the determinant
of what constitutes an externality. The second de…nition is still important,
however, due to it directing attention to the question of why some markets exist
and some do not.

10.2.2 Representation
Having de…ned an externality, it is possible to move on to the formal©representa- ª
tion. Denote, as in Chapter 3, the array of consumption vectors x = x 1; :::; x H
© ª
and the array of production vectors y = y 1 ; :::; y m . It is assumed that con-
sumption externalities enter the utility functions of the households and that
production externalities enter the production sets of the …rms. At the most
general level, this assumption implies that the utility functions take the form

U h = U h (x; y) ; h = 1; :::; H; (10.1)

and the production set is described by

Y j = Y j (x; y) ; j = 1; :::; m: (10.2)

In this formulation the utility functions and the production sets are dependent
upon the entire arrays of consumption and production vectors. The expressions
in (10.1) and (10.2) represent the general form of the externality problem and in
some of the discussion below a number of further restrictions will be employed.
In particular, the case where the total externality e¤ect is due to the sum of
contributions will be used on a number of occasions.
It is immediately apparent from (10.1) and (10.2) that the actions of the
agents in the economy will no longer be independent or determined solely by
prices. The linkages via the externality result in the optimal choice of each agent
being dependent upon the actions of others. Viewed in this light, it becomes
apparent why the e¢cient functioning of the competitive economy will generally
not be observed in an economy with externalities.
Before proceeding to analyse potential ine¢ciency of the market outcome, it
is worth noting that an economy based on the utility and production functions
de…ned in (10.1) and (10.2) may still possess a competitive equilibrium even
306 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

though this equilibrium may not be Pareto optimal. Provided demand and sup-
plies remain continuous functions of their arguments, the proof of the existence
of equilibrium can proceed along the lines sketched in chapter 2. Further de-
tails can be found in Arrow and Hahn (1971) and McKenzie (1955). There are
two additional di¢culties that arise in the proof of equilibrium in an economy
subject to externalities which concern the boundedness of the economy and the
convexity of production sets. Boundedness is a technical point that is not of
great importance here, a detailed discussion can be found in Osana (1973). The
possible non-convexity of production sets is of rather more importance and will
be considered in Section 4.2.2.

10.3 Market ine¢ciency


It has been implicit throughout the discussion above that the presence of exter-
nalities will result in the competitive equilibrium failing to be Pareto optimal.
The immediate implication of this fact is that incorrect quantities of goods, and
hence externalities, will be produced. It is also clear that a non-Pareto optimal
outcome will never maximise welfare. This provides scope for economic policy
to raise welfare. The purpose of this section is to demonstrate how ine¢ciency
can arise in a competitive economy. Cases where externalities do not lead to
ine¢ciency will also be described. The results are developed in the context of
a simple two-consumer model since this is su¢cient for the purpose and also
makes the relevant points as clear as possible.

10.3.1 Equilibrium and ine¢ciency


Consider a two-household economy where the households have utility functions
¡ ¢
U 1 = U 1 x11 ; x 12 ; x21 ; (10.3)

and ¡ ¢
U 2 = U 2 x21 ; x 22 ; x11 : (10.4)
The externality e¤ect in (10.3) and (10.4) is generated by consumption of good
1 by the other household. The externality will be positive if U h is increasing in
x j1 , h 6= j, and negative if decreasing.
To complete the description of the economy, it is assumed that the supply of
good 2 comes from an endowment to the households whereas good 1 is produced
from good 2 by a competitive industry that uses one unit of good 2 to produce
one unit of good 1. Normalising the price of good 1 at one, the structure of
production ensures that the equilibrium price of good 2 must also be one. Given
this, all that needs to be determined for this economy is the division of the initial
endowment into quantities of the two goods.
In specifying demand it is necessary to make an assumption concerning the
treatment of the externality e¤ect by the households in their maximisation de-
cisions. The standard assumption is that both households take the level of
10.3. MARKET INEFFICIENCY 307

externality as given when they maximise. Although this may seem inappropri-
ate for a two-household economy, two points should be stressed. Firstly, this
analysis is illustrative and, in the more relevant case of many households, the ef-
fect of each on external e¤ects would be negligible and the assumption is rather
more tenable. Secondly, it is also possible that the households may be aware of
the externality but not of its cause. They therefore take the quantity as given
when maximising.
Incorporating this assumption into the maximisation decision of the house-
holds, the competitive equilibrium of the economy is described by the equations

@U h
@xh
1
@U h
= 1; h = 1; 2; (10.5)
@xh
2

xh1 + xh2 = ! h2 ; h = 1; 2; (10.6)


and
x11 + x 21 + x 12 + x 22 = ! 12 + ! 22 : (10.7)
It is equations (10.5) that are of primary importance at this point. For household
h these state that the ratio of private bene…ts from each good, determined by
the marginal utilities, is equated to the ratio of private costs. The external e¤ect
does not appear directly in the determination of the equilibrium.
To characterise the set of Pareto optimal allocations, the technique employed
is to maximise the utility of household 1 subject to holding household 2 at a
…xed level of utility and subject to the production possibilities. Varying the
…xed level of households 2’s utility will then trace out the set of Pareto optimal
allocations. The resulting equations will then be contrasted to (10.5). In detail,
the Pareto optima are the solution to
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ 2
max U 1 x11 ; x 12 ; x21 subject to U 2 x 21 ; x22 ; x 11 ¸ U ;
f xhig
and ! 12 + ! 22 ¡ x11 ¡ x21 ¡ x 12 ¡ x 22 ¸ 0: (10.8)

Denoting the Lagrange multiplier on the …rst constraint by ¹, the solution is


characterised by the conditions

@U 1 @U 2
@x1 @x1
1
@U 1
+¹ 1
@U 1
= 1; (10.9)
@x1
2 @x1
2

and
@U 2 @U 1
@x2 2
¡1 @x1
1
@U 2
+ ¹ @U 2 = 1: (10.10)
@x2
2 @x2
2

In (10.9) and (10.10) the externality e¤ect can be seen to a¤ect the optimal
allocation between the two goods via the derivatives of utility with respect to
308 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

the externality. If a positive externality, these will raise the value of the left-
hand terms. They will decrease them if a negative externality. The value of
¹ can be interpreted as the relative social welfare weight given to the second
2
household and it will change as U changes. For example, if the optimum had
been derived by maximising a utilitarian social welfare function, then ¹ would
be identically 1. It can then be seen that at the optimum with a positive
externality the marginal rate of substitution of both households is below its
value in the market outcome. The converse is true with a negative externality.
Since the marginal rates of substitution can be interpreted as valuations, it can
be seen that the externality leads to a divergence between the private valuations
of consumption given by (10.5) and the corresponding social valuations in (10.9)
and (10.10). This observation has the implication that the market outcome is
not Pareto optimal. It is also tempting to conclude that if the externality is
positive then more of good 1 will be consumed at the optimum than under the
market outcome. However this is not always the case, a point that is discussed
in Section 5.
There is one further point worth noting. When a richer production structure
is added to the model, the question of whether it is always optimal for …rms
to produce on the frontier of their production sets arises. The answer to this
is given by Murakami and Negishi (1964) who provide an example that has an
optimum with ine¢ciency. However, if it is optimal for at least one …rm to be
ine¢cient then the outputs of that …rm must cause a negative externality on
other, e¢cient, …rms and the inputs must cause a positive externality. This is
a fairly restrictive condition so that productive ine¢ciency is probably not of
great consequence.

10.3.2 Pareto irrelevant externalities


Although it conveys the message that externalities generally lead to a failure
of the competitive economy to achieve Pareto optimality, the simplicity of the
preceding analysis is somewhat misleading. As shown by Osana (1972), Rader
(1972) and Parks (1991) there are certain classes of preferences for which the
competitive equilibrium is Pareto optimal.
To see how this may arise, assume that the preferences of household h can
be represented by a utility function of the form

h i½ h
j j
U h = x h1 xh2 x1 x 2 ; (10.11)

h i½h
j j
where the term x 1 x 2 captures the externality e¤ect on h arising from the
consumption of j . With these preferences, the competitive equilibrium is then
characterised by
x h1
= 1; h = 1; 2: (10.12)
x h2
10.4. THE COASE THEOREM 309

The necessary conditions determining a Pareto optimum can be written


£ ¤½ 1 £ ¤½ 2¡1 1
x 1k x21 x 22 + ¹½2 x21 x 22 x11 x 12 xk = ¸; k = 1; 2; (10.13)

and
£ ¤½ 1¡1 2 £ ¤½ 2
x 11x 21 ½1 x21 x 22 x k + ¹x2k x11 x 12 = ¸; k = 1; 2: (10.14)
Dividing the equation for k = 1 in (10.13) by that for k = 2 gives (10.12).
Repeating this for (10.14) also gives (10.12). The existence of the externality
therefore does not a¤ect the e¢ciency of the competitive equilibrium.
Parks (1991) shows that the Pareto irrelevant externalities arise when the
preferences of the households have the general form
¡ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢¢
U h = U h f 1 x1 ; f 2 x2 ; :::; f H xH : (10.15)
¡ ¢
In (10.15) the functions f h xh can be interpreted as the private utility that
h derives form their consumption x h . The total utility of each household is
then given as a Bergson-Samuelson function of the vector of private utilities.
Although for each household this Bergson-Samuelson function must be de…ned
on the true private utilities, it can di¤er between households as it would in the
example of (10.11) if ½1 6= ½2 . It is straightforward to show
¡ that
¢ the competitive
equilibrium derived from the private maximisation of f h x h is described by the
same necessary conditions as a Pareto optimum obtained from the maximisation
of (10.15).
The form of (10.15) clearly demonstrates that it is interdependent utili-
ties that give rise to Pareto irrelevant externalities. The result arises because
the externality e¤ects exactly o¤set each other when the optimal allocation is
determined. Other forms of externality, such as Meade’s (1952) atmosphere ex-
ternality which is a function of the sum of consumption of one of the goods,
cannot satisfy this condition and will be Pareto relevant.

10.4 The Coase theorem


The Coase theorem is central to understanding the policy implications of exter-
nalities. It does this through indicating those situations in which market activ-
ities will eliminate the e¤ects of externalities and suggests new perspectives on
why market solutions to externalities may fail and appropriate policy responses.
This section states the Coase theorem and then explores its interpretations and
implications.

10.4.1 The Theorem


As Coase (1960) never formally stated the theorem but merely described it via
examples, a number of alternative interpretations of the theorem have resulted.
In very general terms, the theorem asserts that if allowed to function freely
the market will achieve an e¢cient allocation of resources. A generally agreed
version of the Coase theorem is as follows.
310 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

The Coase Theorem


In a competitive economy with complete information and zero transaction
costs, the allocation of resources will be e¢cient and invariant with respect to
legal rules of entitlement.
Stated in this form, the theorem makes two distinct claims. Following Regan
(1972), these are termed the e¢ciency thesis and the invariance thesis. In a
given situation it is possible for one of these to be valid whilst the other is false.
No attempt will be made to prove the theorem in the conventional sense. As the
discussion will make clear, it is close to being tautological in some circumstances
and false in others.
The legal rules of entitlement, or property rights, are of central importance
to the Coase theorem. These rules determine the rights of the agents in the
economy, for example the right to unpolluted air or the right to enjoy silence,
and determine the direction in which compensation payments will be made if
the right is violated. If valid, the implication of the Coase theorem is that there
is no need for policy intervention with regard to externalities except to ensure
that property rights are clearly de…ned. When they are, private agreements over
compensation will generate a Pareto optimal outcome. This conclusion naturally
runs counter to the standard assessment of the consequences of externalities and
explains why the Coase theorem has been of considerable interest.
A natural expectation would be that the assignment of rights will determine
the equilibrium level of an externality, for example that the level of pollution
under a polluter pays system will be less than that under a pollutee pays. The
invariance thesis of the Coase theorem states that this is incorrect and that the
equilibrium level of externality is independent of the assignment of property
rights. To show how this may work, consider the example of a factory that is
polluting the atmosphere of a neighbouring house. When the …rm has the right
to pollute the householder can only reduce the pollution by paying the …rm a
su¢cient amount of compensation to make it worthwhile to stop production or
to …nd an alternative means of production. Let the amount of compensation the
…rm requires be C . Then the cost to the householder of the pollution, ¡, will
either be greater than C , in which case they will be willing to compensate the
…rm and the externality will cease, or it will be less than C and the externality
will be left to continue. Now consider the outcome with the polluter pays
principle. The cost to the …rm stopping the externality now becomes C and
the compensation required by the household is ¡. If C is greater than ¡ the
…rm will be willing to compensate the household and continue producing the
externality, if it is less than ¡ it stops the externality. Considering the two cases,
it can be seen the outcome is determined only by ¡ relative to C and not by
the assignment of property rights’ which is essentially the content of the Coase
theorem.
That the invariance thesis of the Coase theorem is usually false is easily
seen from the example. The change in property rights between the two cases
will cause di¤erences in the …nal distribution of income due to the direction of
compensation payments. The invariance thesis can only be correct if there are
no income e¤ects. Since income e¤ects will generally exist, the invariance thesis
10.4. THE COASE THEOREM 311

is false. Attention is now paid only to the e¢ciency thesis.

10.4.2 Markets for externalities


In the study of externalities considerable emphasis has been placed on the value
of markets for externalities. This arises because if the externalities were actu-
ally traded, the market outcome would be Pareto optimal. The failure of the
competitive equilibrium to achieve optimality can then be seen as arising from
the necessary markets being missing from the economy. The idea that exter-
nalities could be overcome by the introduction of markets for external e¤ects
was …rst introduced by Arrow (1969) and employed by Meyer (1971). Starret
(1972) provided the formal development of the idea and the proofs of the central
results; the analysis now described is based closely on Starret (1972).
To demonstrate the role of markets, consider an economy with three …rms,
labelled j = 1; 2; 3, and two goods. An externality is introduced by assuming
that the production set for each …rm depends upon the production plans of
the other …rms. The production set, Y 1 , of¡ …rm 1 is therefore¢ de…ned on six-
dimensional space with a typical element y11; y 12 ; y 21 ; y 22 ; y13 ; y23 . Clearly, …rm
1 only has direct choice upon the …rst two elements of this set. The same
comments apply to the production sets of …rms 2 and 3, where these …rms have
direct control over the second and third pairs of entries respectively.
Now let y j be the output vector of …rm j . The economy’s production set is
8 9
< X 3 =
Y = y :y = y j ; y j 2 Y j ; j = 1; 2; 3 : (10.16)
: ;
j=1

Provided there is no point interior to the production set which is Pareto optimal,
the e¢cient production plan will be a point, by , on the boundary of Y and, if Y is
convex, this will imply a price vector q under which b y maximises qy over all y in
Y . Under this interpretation the price system q captures the true social rates of
transformation between the goods. The optimality question can now be phrased
formally as determining whether there exists any arrangement of trade in this
economy such that the equilibrium is Pareto optimal, so demonstrating the First
Theorem of Welfare Economics, and whether there exists a price system which
will lead, by pro…t maximisation of the individual …rms, to the production plan
yb and hence demonstrating that the Second Theorem of Welfare Economics
applies.
Before proceeding, it may be worth recalling how the Two Theorems of
Welfare Economics were demonstrated in Chapter 2. For the First Theorem, it
is su¢cient for it to hold that all agents are maximising subject to parametric
prices with no external e¤ects. The proof of the Second Theorem required
that the …rms’ production sets were independent and that the price vector that
ensured the optimal allocation was pro…t maximising for the economy as a whole
also had the property that it was pro…t maximising for individual …rms to choose
the quantities that lead to the optimal output. These observations indicate that
312 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

for the Theorems to apply the important point is to de…ne the production sets
so that they are independent between …rms.
The required independence can be obtained by delineating goods both by
the …rm that produces them and by the …rm upon which they have an exter-
nality e¤ect. Thus de…ne good yikj to be the net output of good i by …rm j as
observed
¡ k1 k1 byk2…rm k. The production
¢ set of …rm k is now de…ned on the variables
y 1 ; y 2 ; y1 ; y k2 k3 k3
2 ; y 1 ; y2 , k = 1; 2; 3. A count of the commodities shows that
this leads to there being 18 di¤erent goods. In addition, the production sets of
the …rms are formally independent since the goods over which any …rm exercises
choice do not appear in the production set of any other …rm. To complete the
argument, a set of prices are introduced that correspond to the number of goods
in
¡ k1the arti…cial markets. ¢The price vector faced by …rm k is therefore written
p 1 ; pk1 k2 k2 k3 k3
2 ; p 1 ; p2 ; p 1 ; p 2 . Since none of the agents now face an external ef-
fect, it follows that if agents act competitively and an equilibrium exists for the
economy including the markets for external e¤ects, then the equilibrium must
be Pareto optimal. It is also possible to appreciate that there are now su¢cient
prices to allow the control of …rms’ decisions that is necessary for decentrali-
sation. In particular, it is possible to choose the prices such that the identity
k0 j
y kj
i = y i , all k; j; k ; i is satis…ed.
0

Starret (1972) proves the following result which extends the Second Theorem
to the economy with markets for externalities.
¡ ¢
Theorem 50 (Starret) The price vector p 11 nm
1 ; :::; p n can be chosen such that
the pro…t maximising production plans of the …rms have the property that they
sum to the optimal aggregate output yb and the prices satisfy .

Proof. See Starret (1972).


Theorem 10.1 shows that the prices can be chosen so that individual pro…t
maximisation generates the chosen level of output and that the prices on the
arti…cial markets are equal to the true social costs. In other words, the equality
states that the total cost of a unit of good i for …rm j, including all the ex-
ternality e¤ects it has upon other …rms, sums to the social cost. In this way,
the externality e¤ects are brought into the price system. The motivation for
this result is that each good can be seen as a bundle of commodities traded on
the arti…cial markets and the price of the bundle is the sum of the prices of its
components. An alternative way of viewing it is to note that the direct price of
ij
a unit of good i for …rm j is pi . Taking qi to be the consumer price of good, it
follows from the identity
m
X
qi = p jj
i + p kj
i ; (10.17)
k=1;k6=j

Pm
that the sum k=1;k6=j pkji can be seen as total tax payments per unit of good
i by …rm j to cover the externality e¤ects. Equation (10.17) therefore captures
the basic duality between prices on arti…cial markets and corrective taxes. To
summarise, if arti…cial markets are created for the externalities, so that they are
10.4. THE COASE THEOREM 313

treated as distinct goods according to the …rm that produces them and the …rm
that they a¤ect, then a price system de…ned over these constructed commodities
can support the optimal allocation. In addition, this price system can also be
interpreted as de…ning a set of optimal taxes to counter the externalities.
This analysis can be given two alternative interpretations. Firstly, it can be
taken as prescriptive of what should be done to overcome ine¢ciency due to
the existence of externalities in the sense that if there is an externality problem
then this can be overcome by the introduction of markets for external e¤ects.
Secondly, it can be treated as a proof of the e¢ciency thesis of the Coase the-
orem as it shows that if externalities can be traded on competitive markets
then the equilibrium must be e¢cient. In this context, the Coase theorem be-
comes almost tautological. If the markets exist then, as in the second de…nition
of an externality, there must actually be no externalities. As regards policy
prescriptions, since trading in the arti…cial commodities is equivalent to trad-
ing property rights, the analysis can also be interpreted as showing that policy
should be directed to facilitating the exchange of property rights.

10.4.3 Non-existence of markets


The discussion of the previous section has shown that if the economy has su¢-
cient markets and if these markets function competitively, then the equilibrium
will be Pareto optimal even in the presence of externalities. From the construc-
tion, it is clear that this argument presumes that each externality will have
its own market. The question that is now addressed is, given their obvious
desirability, why a complete set of such markets are not observed in practice.

Property rights
The …rst di¢culty in proposing the results above as a solution to the problem
of externalities lies with the assignment of property rights in the market. When
considering trade for commodities de…ned in the usual sense it is clear who is
the purchaser and who is the supplier and, therefore, the direction in which
payment should be transferred. However, when externalities are interpreted as
commodities, this is no longer the case.
If property rights are not clearly speci…ed, it may not be obvious who should
be seen as the recipient of payment. For example, consider the case of air
pollution. It may be that it is acknowledged that the polluter should pay with
the implicit recognition of the right to clean air. On the other hand, the tradition
may have established a right to pollute, with clean air something that should
have to be paid for. When neither tradition is generally accepted, the direction
in which payment should go remains unclear. As a consequence, without clearly
speci…ed property rights, the markets may not function since none of the parties
involved would be willing to accept the responsibility for payment and costly
litigation would diminish the gain due to the existence of the market. These
observations suggest that the clari…cation of property rights should constitute
that …rst step in the construction of a policy towards externalities.
314 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

Figure 10.1: Non-Convexity

Non-convexities

It has been implicit in the discussion up to this point that the standard as-
sumptions on convexity, particularly of production sets, will still be applicable
to the economy despite the existence of externalities. Without convexity, max-
imising choices may not be continuous functions of underlying variables and no
equilibrium may exist. When there is no equilibrium, policy proposals based
on its assumed existence, with or without the arti…cial markets, will be of little
value. Furthermore, even if an equilibrium exists it may not be decentralisable.
Although convexity is not too contentious without externalities, this is not the
case with externalities. As noted by Starret (1972) there are strong reasons for
doubting its applicability.
As an example of the …rst reason for the possible failure of the convexity
assumption, consider the case of a negative production externality. For a …rm
that is a¤ected, if this has the e¤ect of driving its output to zero regardless of
the level of other inputs then the production set will not be convex. Two ways
in which this may occur are illustrated in Figure 10.1 where the output, y, of
the …rm is drawn as a function of the level, z, of some externality for a given
level of inputs.
In the left-hand diagram, output becomes identically zero after some level
of the externality is reached. The right-hand diagram does not have the zero
output level but shows output driven to asymptotically to zero. In both these
case the production set of the …rm is not convex.
In such cases the economy based on arti…cial markets will fail to have an
equilibrium. Suppose the …rm were to receive a positive price for accepting
externalities. The optimal behaviour for the …rm would then be to produce zero
output and o¤er to accept an arbitrarily large quantity of externalities. Since
its output is already zero the externalities can do it no further harm, so that
this plan will lead to an unbounded level of pro…ts. If the price for accepting
externalities were zero, the same …rm would not accept any. The demand for
externalities is therefore discontinuous and an equilibrium need not exist. If
10.4. THE COASE THEOREM 315

the externality were positive, the …rm would choose a production plan involving
an arbitrarily large negative quantity of the externality which again leads to
unbounded pro…t.
The second reason for non-convexity is due to Meade (1952). It is often
assumed that once all inputs are properly accounted for, all …rms will have
constant returns to scale since they can always replicate their behaviour. That
is, if a …xed set of inputs (i.e. a factory and sta¤ ) produce output y, doubling all
those inputs must produce 2y since they can be split into two identical sub-units
(e:g. two factories and sta¤ ) producing an amount y each. Now consider a …rm
subject to a negative externality and assume that it has constant returns to
all inputs including the externality. From this view, there are constant returns
from the perspective of society. Now consider the …rm doubling all its inputs but
with the externality held at a constant level. Since the externality is a negative
one, it becomes diluted by the increase in other inputs and output must more
than double. The …rm therefore faces private increasing returns to scale. With
such increasing returns, the …rm’s pro…t maximising decision may not have a
well-de…ned …nite solution and market equilibrium may again fail to exist.
Further analysis of these issues is given in Otani and Sicilian (1977). Their
theorem demonstrates that convexity is inconsistent with a set of reasonable
assumptions describing the consequences of external e¤ects. This simply for-
malises the arguments above. However they also note that by not permitting
…rms to demand negative quantities of inputs or supply negative a quantity
of output the problem does not occur with positive externalities. Therefore
non-convexity appears more of an issue for negative externalities.
These comments have been of a fairly negative nature since non-convexities
are the source of severe di¢culties for conclusions based on competitive behav-
iour. Although they may not be of critical importance in practice, they do act
as a warning that decentralised solutions may not be appropriate for dealing
with externalities.

Transaction costs
If the exchange of commodities would lead to mutually bene…cial gains for two
parties, the commodities will be exchanged unless the cost of doing so outweighs
the bene…ts. Such transactions costs may arise from the need for the parties
to travel to a point of exchange or from the legal costs involved in formalising
the transactions. They may also arise due to search required to …nd a trading
partner. Whenever they arise, transactions cost represent a hindrance to trade
and, if su¢ciently great, will lead to no trade at all taking place. The latter
results in the economy having a missing market.
The existence of transaction costs is often seen as the most signi…cant reason
for the nonexistence of markets in externalities. To see how they can arise,
consider the problem of pollution caused by car emissions. If the economy above
is applied literally, then any driver of a car must purchase pollution rights from
all of the agents that are a¤ected by the car emissions each time, and every
time, that the car is used. Obviously, this would take an absurd amount of
316 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

organisation and, since considerable time and resources would be used in the
process, would certainly not correspond to the frictionless market envisaged in
the Arrow-Debreu economy. In many cases it seems likely that the welfare loss
due to waste of resources in organising the market would outweigh any gains
from having the market.
Despite these negative conclusions, the transactions cost perspective upon
the Coase theorem still has policy value. The prescription arising from it is that
the cost of transferring legal entitlements between agents should be reduced as
far as possible to permit trade.

Missing markets and side-payments


If markets for external e¤ects are missing, it may be possible for direct transfers,
or side-payments, between agents to overcome this and achieve e¢ciency. One
way to formalise this idea has been considered by Bigelow (1993). Assume that
two agents are initially faced with playing a bimatrix nonconstant sum one-shot
game. Denote the payo¤ of this game to 1, if agent 1 chooses strategy i and
agent 2 strategy j, by ¡1 (i; j) and for 2 by ¡ 2 (i; j ). Without side-payments,
there is no reason why the Nash equilibrium of the game should be e¢cient.
Side-payments can be introduced by allowing agent h, h = 1; 2, to o¤er agent
k an outcome contingent payment of if strategies i; j are chosen for the original
game. Incorporating these side-payments, the payo¤ for 1 if i, j is chosen is
¡ 1 (i; j ) + ¤1 (i; j) ¡ ¤2 (i; j) and for 2 is ¡ 2 (i; j) + ¤2 (i; j) ¡ ¤1 (i; j). An
equilibrium for the game with side-payments is then a set of side-payments
which are chosen optimally given that the resulting strategies form a Nash
equilibrium for the game where the payo¤s include side-payments.
A missing market is then represented by an original matrix game in which
the payo¤ of one agent is not a¤ected by the action of the other. Bigelow (1993)
then proves that the existence of side-payments is su¢cient to ensure that an
e¢cient equilibrium is achieved. In contrast when two markets are missing,
so any form of payo¤s may arise in the original matrix game, an equilibrium
may not exist in the game with side-payments and when it does, it need not be
e¢cient. Although they are rather stylised, these results do show the limitations
of side-payments in achieving e¢ciency when there are missing markets.

10.4.4 Bargaining
When external e¤ects are traded, there will generally only be one agent on each
side of the market. This thinness of the market undermines the assumption
of competitive behaviour that can support the e¢ciency hypothesis. In such
circumstances, the Coase theorem has been interpreted as implying that bar-
gaining between the two agents will take place over compensation for external
e¤ects and that this bargaining will lead to an e¢cient outcome. Such a claim
requires substantiation.
Bargaining can be interpreted as taking the form of either a cooperative game
between agents or as a non-cooperative game. When it is viewed as coopera-
10.4. THE COASE THEOREM 317

tive, the tradition since Nash (1950) has been to adopt a set of axioms which
the bargain must satisfy and to derive the outcomes that satisfy these axioms.
The requirement of Pareto optimality is always adopted as one of the axioms
so that the bargained agreement is necessarily e¢cient. If all bargains over
compensation payments were placed in front of an external arbitrator, then the
Nash bargaining solution would have some force as descriptive of what such an
arbitrator should try and achieve. However, this is not what is envisaged in the
Coase theorem which focuses on the actions of markets free of any regulation.
Although appealing as a method for achieving an outcome agreeable to both
parties, the fact that Nash bargaining solution is e¢cient does not demonstrate
the correctness of the Coase theorem.
The literature on bargaining in a non-cooperative context is best divided
between games with complete information and those with incomplete informa-
tion, since this distinction is of crucial importance for the outcome. One of the
central results of non-cooperative bargaining with complete information is due
to Rubinstein (1982) who considers the division of a single object between two
players. The players take it in turns to announce a division of the object and
each period an o¤er and an acceptance or rejection are made. Both players
discount the future so are impatient to arrive at an agreed division. Rubinstein
shows that the game has a unique subgame perfect equilibrium with agreement
reached in the …rst period. The outcome is Pareto optimal.
The important point is the complete information assumed to prevail in this
representation of bargaining. The importance of information for the nature of
outcomes has been already been emphasised on several occasions and its conse-
quences are equally important for bargaining. In the simple bargaining problem
of Rubinstein (1982) the information that must be known are the preferences of
the two agents, captured by their rates of time discount. When these discount
rates are private information the attractive properties of the complete infor-
mation bargain are lost and, as shown by Rubinstein (1985), there many be
many potential equilibria with the equilibria being dependent upon the precise
speci…cation of the structure of bargaining.
In the context of externalities it seems reasonable to assume that information
will be incomplete since there is no reason why the agents involved in bargaining
an agreement over compensation for an external e¤ect should be aware of the
other’s valuation of the externality. The formalisation of this situation given
by Myerson and Satterthwaite (1983) considers the sale of an object (which
would be the property right) from one agent to another. Each agent knows
their own valuation at the time of bargaining but is uncertain about that of the
other agent. The characterisation of bargaining is then undertaken by determin-
ing the form of Bayesian incentive-compatible and individually rational direct
mechanisms for reaching agreement (see the de…nitions in Chapter 9 Section
8). Application of the revelation principle, which asserts that for any Bayesian
equilibrium there is an equivalent mechanism that involves truthful revelation,
justi…es the restriction to incentive compatible direct mechanisms.
Agent 1 initially owns the object and agent 2 wishes to purchase. The
valuation of the ob ject by 1 is denoted º 1 and that of 2 by º 2 . Household j,
318 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

¡ ¢
j = 1; 2, believes , i 6= j, to be distributed with density function fi º i which
¡ ¢
has strictly positive support on [ai; b i] and
¡ 1 cumulative
¢ distribution F i º i . The
outcome is determined by a function p º ; º 2 ¡which¢represents the probability
that the object is transferred and a function q º 1 ; º 2 that is the payment that
must be made. Given a pair of such functions, the expected payment as viewed
by 1 is given by
Z b2
¡ 1¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
q1 º = q º 1 ; w2 f2 w 2 dw 2 ; (10.18)
a2

and the cost expected by 2 is


Z b1
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
q2 º 2 = q w 1 ; º 2 f1 w 1 dw 1 : (10.19)
a1

Similarly, the probability of transfer expected by 1 is


Z b2
¡ 1
¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
p1 º = p º 1 ; w 2 f2 w 2 dw 2 ; (10.20)
a2

and by 2
Z b1
¡ 2
¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
p2 º = p w1 ; º 2 f1 w 1 dw 1 : (10.21)
a1

Employing (10.18) and (10.20), the expected payo¤ of 1 can be written


¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 1 º 1 = q 1 º1 ¡ º1 p1 º1 ; (10.22)

and that of 2 ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 2 º 2 = q 2 º2 ¡ º2 p2 º2 : (10.23)
The characterisation of the mechanism begins by noting that incentive com-
patibility implies for agent 1 that
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 1 º 1 = q1 º 1 ¡ º 1 p 1 º 1 ¸ q 1 w 1 ¡ º 1 p1 w1 ; (10.24)

and ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 1 w 1 = q 1 w 1 ¡ w 1 p 1 w 1 ¸ q1 º 1 ¡ w 1 p 1 º 1 ; (10.25)
1 1
for any º and w . Taken together, (10.24) and (10.25) give
£ 1 ¤ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ £ ¤ ¡ ¢
w ¡ º 1 p 1 º 1 ¸ U 1 º 1 ¡ U 1 w1 ¸ w 1 ¡ º 1 p 1 w 1 : (10.26)
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
Choosing w 1 > º 1 shows that p 1 º 1 ¸ p 1 w 1 so that the probability is
1
decreasing in valuation. ¡Di¤erentiating
¢ ¡ 1 ¢(10.26) with respect to º and letting
1 1 10 1
w ! º shows that U º = ¡p1 º . Integrating gives
Z b1
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 1 º 1 = U 1 (b 1 ) + p 1 w 1 dw 1 : (10.27)
º1
10.4. THE COASE THEOREM 319

Repeating the argument for agent 2 shows that p 2 (¢) is increasing and

Z º2
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 2 º 2 = U 2 (a2 ) + p2 w2 dw2 : (10.28)
a2

The central result of Myerson and Satterthwaite (1983) can now be stated.

Theorem 51 (Myerson and Satterthwaite) If the intervals [a1 ; ; b i], i = 1; 2,


have an intersection with non-empty interior (so there is a positive probability
of gains from trade) and neither is a subset of the other then there is no e¢cient
mechanism that satis…es incentive compatibility.

¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
Proof. Substituting for U 1 º 1 and U 2 º 2 in (10.27) and (10.28) using
(10.22) and (10.23) and summing the resulting equations gives

¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
q 1 º 1 ¡ q2 º 2 = º 1 p 1 º 1 ¡ º 2 p 2 º 2 + U 1 (b1 ) + U 2 (a2 )
Z b1 Z º2
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
+ p 1 w 1 dw 1 + p2 w2 dw 2: (10.29)
º1 a2

As there is no outside agency involved,


£ ¡ ¢¤the expected
£ ¡ ¢¤income of 1 is equal to
the expected payment of 2 or E q1 º 1 = E q2 º 2 . The expectation of
the right-hand side of (10.29) is therefore zero. Taking the expectation and
integrating by parts gives

Z " ¡ ¢#
b1
1 2 F1 º 1
1
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U (b 1 ) + U (a2 ) = ¡ º + 1
p 1 º 1 f1 º 1 dº 1
a1 f 1 (º )
Z b2 " ¡ ¢#
2 1 ¡ F2 º 2 ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ 2
+ º ¡ 2
p 2 º 2 f2 º 2 dº(10.30)
:
a2 f2 (º )

¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
Replacing p1 º 1 and p 2 º 2 using (10.18) and (10.20) and noting that indi-
vidual rationality requires U 1 (b 1 ) ¸ 0, U 2 (a2 ) ¸ 0, (10.30) implies

Z Z "" ¡ ¢# " ¡ ¢ ##
b2 b1
1 ¡ F2 º 2
2 1 F1 º1 ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
0 º ¡ 2
¡ º + 1
p º 1 ; º 2 f1 º 1 f 2 º 2 dº 1 dº 2 :
a2 a1 f2 (º ) f 1 (º )
(10.31)
Condition (10.31) must be satis…ed by any incentive compatible and individually
rational mechanism.
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
An e¢cient outcome requires p º 1 ; º 2 = 1 if º 1 < º 2 and p º 1 ; º 2 = 0 if
320 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

º 1 > º 2 . Substituting these restrictions into the right-hand side of (10.31) gives
Z b2 Z min f º 2;b 1g £ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¤ ¡ ¢
º 2 f 2 º 2 + F2 º 2 ¡ 1 f1 º 1 dº 1 dº 2
a2 a1
Z b2 Z min fº 2;b 1g £ 1 ¡ 1¢ ¡ ¢¤ ¡ ¢
¡ º f1 º + F 1 º 1 f 2 º 2 dº 1 dº 2
a2 a1
Z b2 £ Z b2
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¤ ¡ ¢ © ¡ ¢ ª ¡ ¢
= º 2 f 2 º 2 + F 2 º 2 ¡ 1 F 1 º 2 dº 2 ¡ min º 2 F1 º 2 ; b 1 f2 º 2 dº 2
a2 a2
Z b2 Z b2
£ ¡ ¢¤ ¡ ¢ £ ¤ ¡ ¢
= ¡ 1 ¡ F 2 º 2 F 1 º 2 dº 2 + º 2 ¡ b 1 f2 º 2 dº 2
a2 b1
Z b2 Z b2
£ ¡ ¢¤ ¡ ¢ £ ¡ ¢ ¤
= ¡ 1 ¡ F 2 º 2 F 1 º 2 dº 2 ¡ F2 º 2 ¡ 1 dº 2
a2 b1
Z b1
= ¡ [1 ¡ F 2 (w)] F 1 (w) dw < 0: (10.32)
a2

Contrasting (10.32) and (10.31) shows that an e¢cient outcome contradicts


individually rationality.
Theorem 10.2 shows how asymmetric leads to ine¢ciency in the outcome
of bargaining. The incentive for each agent to attempt to exploit their private
information prevents all the gains from trade being exhausted. Rob (1989) and
Mailath and Postlewaite (1990) extend this ine¢ciency result to economies in
which the externality caused by one agent a¤ects many agents. As the number of
agents increases the e¤ect of each upon the externality becomes negligible. The
degree of ine¢ciency can therefore increase as the number of agents increases.
The e¢ciency thesis of the Coase theorem relies on agreements being reached
on the compensation required for external e¤ects. The results above suggest that
when information is incomplete, bargaining between agents will not lead to an
e¢cient outcome.

10.4.5 Conclusions
In summary, the Coase Theorem suggests that externalities can be overcome
by decentralised trading between a¤ected parties. In practice it is di¢cult to
imagine that its conditions are actually satis…ed so that it cannot be given too
much weight as a foundation for the formulation of policy. The arguments above
provide some fairly powerful reasons why the full set of markets required for
optimality may not exist. Furthermore they also show why bargaining between
a¤ected parties is also unlikely to achieve e¢ciency.

10.5 Welfare-improving changes


A natural expectation would be that if the production of a good generated a
negative externality, then too much of that good would be produced at the
10.5. WELFARE-IMPROVING CHANGES 321

competitive equilibrium and that welfare could be raised by reducing output.


The same point would apply to consumption externalities. If this reasoning was
always correct, it would provide a simple rule of thumb for policy to follow.
This section investigates the truth of this statement for a model with a single
externality. The claim is shown to be true for marginal changes but, as will be
discussed, must be treated with care when non-marginal changes are involved.

10.5.1 Local results


Consider an economy that has a single externality that is generated by the …rms
in the economy at a level that is related to their output of good 1. The quantity
of externality generated by …rm j , z j , is determined by
³ ´
z j = z j y1j : (10.33)

The total quantity of externality then amounts to


m
X m
X ³ ´
z= zj = z j y j1 : (10.34)
j=1 j=1

It is assumed that the externality a¤ects both the consumers, via their utility
functions, and the …rms, via their production sets. The utility of household h
is therefore denoted ¡ ¢
U h = U h xh1 ; :::; x hn ; z : (10.35)
From (10.35) it can be seen that utility is a function only of the total quantity of
the externality and is not related to its distribution across …rms. The production
set of each …rm is written in implicit form as
n ³ ´ o
y1j ; :::; y jn : f j y1j ; :::; y jn ; z 0 ; j = 1; :::; m: (10.36)

The analytical procedure is now to start at a competitive equilibrium and


to calculate the e¤ect of a di¤erential increase in the output of good 1 by all
…rms, with an o¤setting changes in the consumption and production of all other
goods. This e¤ect is then converted into a social valuation via a utilitarian
aggregation procedure. If the social valuation of the increase has a negative
value, then welfare will be raised by reducing the output of good 1 by all …rms.
The competitive equilibrium allocation must satisfy both the de…nition,
(10.34), of the level of externality and it must be productively feasible for the
…rms, that is (10.36) must be met for all j. In addition, an equilibrium allocation
has to meet the market clearance condition
H
X m
X j
xhi !i + yi ; i = 1; :::; n; (10.37)
h=1 j=1

where ! i is the total endowment of good i.


322 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

It is now assumed that the constraints (10.34), (10.36) and (10.37) are met
with equality so that the e¤ect of the increase in the output of good 1 can be
calculated by total di¤erentiation. Carrying out the di¤erentiation gives
m
X @z j
dz = dy1j ; (10.38)
j=1
@y1j

H
X m
X j
dx hi = dyi ; i = 1; :::; n; (10.39)
h =1 j=1

and
n
X j j
df j = fi dy i + f zj dz = 0; j = 1; :::; m: (10.40)
i=1

Equation (10.40) can be rearranged to give the equivalent form


n
X
f ij dy ji ¡ f zj dz; j = 1; :::; m: (10.41)
i= 1

To derive an expression for the social value of this change in the production
plan, it is …rst noted that utility maximisation of household h leads to the
equalities
Uih = ¸p i; Unh = ¸p n ; (10.42)
where ¸ is the Lagrange multiplier on the household’s budget constraint. If pn
is normalised at 1, then
Uih
= pi; (10.43)
Unh
is a measure of the value of good i to household h relative to the other goods.
To generate a measure of change in social welfare, the e¤ect of rearrangement
in production is de…ned as

Xn XH ¸ H
X ¸
Uih h Uzh
dW = dx i + dz: (10.44)
i=1
Unh Unh
h =1 h=1

If dW is positive, the modi…cation of production is assumed to be of positive


value for society.
The aim now is to express dW in terms of the output of goo d 1 so that it
can be ascertained whether a reduction in the externality producing good will
raise welfare. The …rst step is to note from the resource balance equation that
any change in consumption must be met with an equal change in production.
Hence
H
X m
X j
dx hi = dyi ; i = 1; :::; n: (10.45)
h =1 j=1

In addition, the fact that the initial point is assumed to be a competitive equilib-
rium implies that the …rms must be equating the marginal rate of transformation
10.5. WELFARE-IMPROVING CHANGES 323

between any two goods to the ratio of their prices. In particular, taking all other
goods relative to good n this gives

f ij
M RT i;j n = = p i; i = 1; :::; n; all j: (10.46)
f nj

Using (10.45) and (10.46), dW can be written


n X m
" # H ¸
X fi
j
j
X Uzh
dW = j
dyi + dz: (10.47)
i=1 j=1 fn h=1
Unh

j
From (10.41) the terms in fi can be eliminated to provide
2 3
Xm j
¸ XH h
¸
f U
dW = 4¡ z
j +
z 5
h
dz: (10.48)
j= 1 f n U n
h=1

Finally, using the externality generation process de…ned in (10.38) gives


2 3
Xm j
¸ X H h
¸ X m
4 f z U z 5 j j
dW = ¡ j + h
z1 dy 1 : (10.49)
j=1 f n
U n j=1
h=1

The expression in (10.31) captures the welfare e¤ect of a feasible change in


the production of good 1 by all …rms. To interpret this condition, note that
j
f zj > 0; fnj > 0; z1 > 0 all j; and Uzh < 0; Unh > 0; all h: (10.50)
j
Therefore, if dy1 is positive for all …rms, dW is negative. Hence a reduction in
the output of good 1 by all …rms, that is dy j1 < 0 all j; would raise welfare.
In conclusion, a reduction in the output of an externality-producing good
from its level determined at the competitive equilibrium will raise welfare. This
is the intuitively plausible result that agrees with the presumption that it should
always be the intention of policy to reduce the level of a negative externality.
By reversing the signs of fzj , all j, and Uzh, all h, it is also clear that (10.31)
implies that the quantity of a good producing a positive externality should be
increased from its competitive equilibrium level. The methodology employed to
derive this result is clearly analogous to the more general policy reform analysis
of Chapter 6. The metho ds of that chapter could be employed to extend the
model to several externalities and corresponding changes in several outputs.

10.5.2 Global results


In addition to the usual caveats that must be applied to any result, such as
the appropriateness of the model within which it was derived, the claim of
the previous section is restricted by a further consideration. Since the formal
analysis considered only the consequence of a di¤erential change in the output
324 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

of good 1, the result is purely local in that it refers to the correct course of
action only in the locality of the competitive equilibrium. It must therefore not
be read as suggesting that the output of good 1 should be reduced regardless of
the starting point or that the optimal level of the output of good 1 is less than
that at the competitive equilibrium. Both the latter statements are examples
of global results and could only be supported by stronger arguments.
A global result would relate the production and consumption arrays fx c g ;
fy g at the competitive equilibrium to the optimal arrays fx o g ; fy o g. In fact, as
c

shown in Baumol and Oates (1988), a comparison between these arrays can only
be made under stronger assumptions than have so far been adopted. In partic-
ular, even with a single externality, convexity of the production sets becomes
essential.
Buchanan and Kafoglis (1963) demonstrate that it also possible for coun-
terexamples to be constructed in which, for example, the quantity of a positive
externality is decreased as the economy moves towards the optimum. Consider
a two-consumer, two-good, economy with a single positive consumption exter-
nality. For each consumer, the externality arises from the other’s consumption
of good 2. Under these assumptions the utility functions are of the form
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 1 = U 1 x11 ; x 21 ; x12 ; U 2 = U 2 x 11 ; x21 ; x 22 : (10.51)

As each consumer maximises their utility taking the other consumer’s contribu-
tion to the externality as …xed, the equilibrium occurs at a point at which the
indi¤erence curves cross at right-angles. This is precisely the same argument as
for the private provision of public goods in Chapter 9. Therefore, as shown in
Chapter 9 Section 5.3, it is possible for there to be too much consumption of
goods causing positive externalities at the market outcome relative to the social
optimum and too little of goods causing negative externalities.
The conclusion of this section is that although local results can be estab-
lished without too much di¢culty it is not straightforward to provide global
comparisons. However, since many policy recommendations are only concerned
with marginal changes, this is not of too great a consequence for the formulation
of practical policies.

10.6 Corrective taxation


In response to the non-optimality of the market equilibrium in the presence of
externalities, a natural policy to adopt is the imposition of a set of taxes to
correct for the distortions. Such taxes, often termed Pigouvian taxes following
the work of Pigou (1920), will be the subject of this section. Before proceeding
to characterise optimal taxes, it is …rst necessary to clarify several important
issues regarding the extent to which the taxes may be di¤erentiated.
Taxation has already been implicit in much of the discussion of arti…cial
markets and was made explicit in (10.17). The content of the …rst sub-section
will be to derive a set of taxes of the form of those described in (10.17) for a
model of consumption externalities. The perspective chosen emphasises the fact
10.6. CORRECTIVE TAXATION 325

that the rates of tax need to be di¤erentiated between commodities and between
consumers. This is a far stronger requirement than that normally imposed upon
models of commodity taxation and, arguably, is not administratively feasible.
When the requirement that the taxes must be uniform across consumers is
imposed, the …rst-best allocation cannot, in general, be sustained except for
some special cases. This leads to the choice of taxes that will generate the
optimal second-best outcome. Uniform taxes are considered in the second sub-
section.

10.6.1 Non-uniform taxation


It has already been argued in the analysis of arti…cial markets that the …rst-best
can be sustained by a system of personalised prices and that the components of
these prices can be given the interpretation of taxes as in (10.17). The analysis
involved asserting the existence of such prices by exploiting the convexity of the
model but did not discuss the means by which such prices could be calculated.
To remedy this, optimal taxes are now reconsidered for a model of consumption
externalities.
Let the utility of household h be given by
¡ ¢
U h = U h xh1 hH h1 hH
1 ; :::; x 1 ; x 2 ; :::; xn ;

where the externality e¤ects have been included as arti…cial commodities with
e
x hi h denoting the consumption of good i by e
h as viewed by h. The aggregate
quantity, Xi , of good i is de…ned by
H
X
Xi = x hh
i ; (10.52)
h=1

and the production feasibility constraint is expressed as

F (X1 ; :::; Xn ) 0: (10.53)

Following Meyer (1971), the optimal taxes can be characterised by calculat-


ing a Pareto optimum for the economy set out above. Such an optimum appears
as the solution to the maximisation problem
H
X ¡ ¢
max ¯ h U h x h1 hH
1 ; :::; x n ; (10.54)
f x11 HH ;X ;::: ;X
1 ;:::;xn 1 n g h=1

subject to
H
X e
Xi ¸ x hh hh hh e e
i ; 0 ¸ F (X1 ; :::; Xn ) ; x i = xi ; i = 1; :::; n; h; h = 1; :::; H; h 6= h:
h =1
(10.55)
The …nal set of constraints capture the consistency condition that the con-
sumption of h as viewed by eh must equal the actual consumption of h. Let
326 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

¸ i, i = 1; :::; n; denote the Lagrange multipliers on the …rst n constraints, ¸ 0


e
be the multiplier on the production feasibility constraint and »hhi , i = 1; :::; n,
h = 1; :::; H be the multipliers on the remaining H(H ¡ 1)n constraints.
For the choice of good x hh
i , the …rst-order condition is

H
X
h@U h e
¯ ¡ ¸i ¡ » hh
i = 0; (10.56)
@xhh
i e
h =1;e
h 6=h

e
and for good xhi h ,
e
e @U h e
¯h e
+ » hh
i = 0: (10.57)
@xhh
i
e
It can be seen in (10.58) that the multipliers »hh
i are proportional to the exter-
nality e¤ect. In addition, dividing two of the …rst-order conditions (10.57) for
goods i and j for a consumer, h, gives
@U h PH e
@ xhh ¸i + e
h=1;eh6=h
» hh
i
i
@U h
= PH e
; (10.58)
hh
@ xhh
j
¸j + e h6= h » j
h =1;e

which would be the …rst-order condition for choice of the consumer if they faced
P e
prices given by ¸ i + He » hh for good i, a fact …rst noted by Davis and
h=1;eh6=h i
e
Whinston (1965). Therefore the multipliers »hhi can be treated as the per-unit
ehh
tax rate on consumer h for each unit of good x i they generate. The total tax
paid on a unit of consumption, that is for each unit of good xhh i , is then the
sum of these individual taxes. This is the same interpretation as given after
(10.17). Note that from (10.58), if the externality is negative, the individual
tax component will be positive.
From the above it can be concluded that for the Pareto optimum to be
achieved the taxes must have the potential to be di¤erentiated between con-
sumers so that each consumer e¤ectively faces a personalised price for each
good. As will be noted below, there are some case where the e¤ects are sym-
metric across consumer so that they actually face the same optimal prices but
these are the exception rather than the rule. These results have precisely the
same interpretation as the demonstration in Chapter 9 that the Lindahl equilib-
rium with personalised prices can decentralise the optimum level of public good
provision. Indeed, public goods can be treated entirely as a special case of the
more general externality framework.
The remaining …rst-order conditions take the form

@F
¸i ¡ ¸0 = 0: (10.59)
@Xi

These equations imply that the marginal rates of transformation between each
pair of goods is equated to the ratio of the ¸s. Since the ¸s can be interpreted
10.6. CORRECTIVE TAXATION 327

as pre-tax prices this has the implication that there is production e¢ciency and
hence the optimal tax system distorts only the consumption side of the economy
in response to a consumption externality.
This discussion has demonstrated that a set of taxes can be derived that
will support a Pareto optimum in the presence of externalities. However, these
taxes will in general need to be di¤erentiated both across goods and across
consumers. If the model was extended to include production externalities, the
taxes would also need to be di¤erentiated across …rms. Theorem 2.5 investigated
some of the consequences of attempting to implement a tax system with this
degree of di¤erentiation and showed that such attempts were most likely to fail.
Since they are based on private information of a similar nature, this general
conclusion also applies to the di¤erentiated Pigouvian taxes that support the
…rst-best. Consequently, although a …rst-best outcome can be achieved if the
necessary information were available, the implied tax scheme is unlikely to be
implementable.

10.6.2 Uniform taxation


Uniform taxation refers to the situation in which the taxes can be di¤erentiated
across goods but not across consumers. As already noted, such taxes will not in
general be su¢cient to sustain the …rst-best outcome. This sub-section begins,
however, with a discussion of circumstances in which uniform taxes will sustain
the …rst-best. Following this, the determinants of the level of taxes are consid-
ered and the important distinction between direct and indirect tax instruments
is introduced.

Attainment of …rst-best

Considering the problem set out in (10.55) and (10.56), uniform taxation will
e
be the solution to this problem when, for a given good i, all the multipliers » hh
i
have the same value for all h and e h. The …rst case in which this will occur
is the relatively uninteresting one of identical consumers with each given the
same weight in social welfare. Under these conditions the derivatives of utility
in (10.58) will be the same for all h and the claim then follows.
Rather more interesting is the example of Meade’s (1952) additive atmosphere
externality. The level, °, of such an externality is determined by the relation
à H
!
X
°=° xhi ; °0 ¸ 0: (10.60)
h=1

From (10.60) the level of the externality is determined as an increasing function


of the sum of individual consumption of good i. What is important about the
form of this externality generating process is that the marginal contribution of
each individual to the total is identical. As will now be shown, for this form of
externality uniform taxation generates the …rst best.
328 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

To simplify the notation, assume a two-consumer, two-good economy; nei-


ther of these restrictions is of any consequence. With the atmospheric external-
ity the utility function are written
¡ ¢
U h = U h x h1 ; x h2 ; ° ; h = 1; 2; (10.61)

and, assuming that the externality is generated by the consumption of good 1,


° is determined by ¡ ¢
° = ° x 11 + x 21 : (10.62)
The optimum is then characterised as arising from the solution to
2
X
max ¯h U h ; (10.63)
fx1 2
1 ;:::;x2 ;X1 ;X 2 ;° g h=1

subject to
2
X ¡ ¢
Xi ¸ xhi ; 0 ¸ F (X1 ; X2 ) ; ° = ° x11 + x 21 : (10.64)
h=1

This problem generates the …rst-order conditions

@U h @°
¯h h
¡ ¸ 1 + »1 h = 0; h = 1; 2; (10.65)
@x 1 @x1

@U h
¯h ¡ ¸ 2 = 0; h = 1; 2; (10.66)
@x h2
@F
¸i ¡ ¸0 = 0; i = 1; 2; (10.67)
@Xi
and
@U 1 @U 2
¯1 + ¯2 + »1 = 0: (10.68)
@° @°
As @@°
x1

= @x 2 , (10.66) and (10.69) have the implication that the consumers
1 1
should face the same shadow prices for the two goods or, equivalently, that the
tax rate on good 1 should not be di¤erentiated across the consumers. Therefore
uniform taxes can sustain the …rst-best in the presence of the atmosphere exter-
nality. Alternative derivations of this result, for external economies of scale in
production, can be found in Aoki (1971) and Chipman (1970). A more detailed
characterisation of optimal taxes with the atmospheric externality can be found
in Sandmo (1975).

Direct and indirect taxes


When uniform taxation cannot generate the …rst-best, the range of tax instru-
ments that are available is of great importance. To aid the discussion, it is …rst
necessary to distinguish between direct taxes, which are levied on the activity
that causes the externality, and indirect taxes that are levied on some activity
10.6. CORRECTIVE TAXATION 329

that is related, via demand or supply functions, to the externality generating


activity. For example, if the use of a car causes air pollution then a tax on
motoring would be a direct tax and a tax on petrol an indirect tax. Although
only direct taxes have been su¢cient in the example considered above, it is
clear that when direct taxes are restricted to be uniform the extra instrument
of an indirect tax may raise welfare further, a point made clearly by Green and
Sheshinski (1976).
The analysis that is now developed will consist of two parts. The …rst will
consider only direct taxes and will aim to characterise the factors that determine
their level. This will be followed by the introduction of indirect taxes and the
factors that determine the optimal mix of direct and indirect taxes will then be
of primary importance.
To provide clear conclusions, the …rst step will be to restrict the individual
utility functions to be linear in all commodities except that causing the exter-
nality. Aggregating the non-externality commodities into a single commodity
and labelling this good 2, the utility functions are assumed to take the form
¡ ¢
U h = U h x11 ; :::; x H
1 + x h2 : (10.69)
In addition, the utility functions are assumed to have the concavity and sepa-
rability properties as below
@2Uh @2Uh
h h
< 0; e
= 0; h 6= e
h: (10.70)
@x 1 @x1 @x h1 @xh1
The zero cross derivative implies that there are no connections between the
e¤ect on utility of di¤erent households contributions to the externality.
For consumer h with income M h , solving the utility maximisation problem
¡ ¢
max U h x11 ; :::; x H
1 + x h2 s.t. [p 1 + t1 ] x h1 + xh2 = M h ; (10.71)
h h
fx 1 ;x2 g
where the price of good 2 is normalised at 1, generates the demand function
x h1 = x h1 (p 1 + t1 ) : (10.72)

Now assuming, as in Diamond (1973a), that any tax revenue is returned to


the consumers via lump-sum taxes, the social welfare function can be written
in the form
H
X H
X H
X
¡ ¢
W = U h x11 (p1 + t1 ) ; :::; xH
1 (p1 + t1 ) ¡ p1 xh
1 (p 1 + t 1 ) + M h:
h= 1 h=1 h =1
(10.73)
Di¤erentiating (10.74) with respect to t1 , setting the expression equal to zero
for a maximum, and using the …rst-order condition from (10.72), the optimal
tax can be written implicitly as
PH PH e
h @ xh
¡ h= 1 eh=1;eh6=h @U@xh @t1
1

t1 = PH @xh1
1
: (10.74)
h=1 @t1
330 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

From (10.75) it can be seen that the optimal tax is given by the sum of exter-
nality e¤ects weighted by the demand derivatives.
The simple characterisation in (10.75) was derived on the basis of a num-
ber of strong assumptions. In particular, the separability between the e¤ects
of di¤erent households’ contributions to the externality is almost indefensible.
When this is removed however, the possibility is opened for rather more sur-
prising results to emerge. For example, Diamond (1973a) is able to construct
a two-consumer example which has t1 = 0 as the optimal solution despite the
presence of a negative externality. This line of reasoning is developed further
by Green and Sheshinski (1976) who introduce a third good that enters into
the non-linear part of the utility function. With this formulation they permit
indirect taxation of the third commodity and demonstrate that an optimum
may involve a zero direct tax but a non-zero indirect tax.
These results are placed into a common framework by Balcer (1980) whose
analysis is now described. The previous model is extended by assuming a utility
function of the form
¡ ¢ h¡ ¢
U h x h1 ; x h3 + U x 11 ; :::; x h¡
1
1
; x h+1
1 ; :::; x H
1 + x h2 : (10.75)

In (10.76), the externality e¤ect remains separable from the direct level of con-
sumption of good 1 but it is distinguished form (10.72) by the inclusion of good
3 in the …rst component of the utility function. The focus of the analysis is on
the e¤ect of the substitutability/complementarity relation between good 1 and
3 and the structure of the optimal taxes.
Retaining the assumption that all tax revenues are returned to the consumers
via lump-sum transfers, the welfare function can be written

H
X H
¡ ¢ X h ¡ ¢
W = U h xh1 ; x h3 + U x11 ; :::; x h¡1
1 ; x h+1
1 ; :::; xH
1
h= 1 h=1
H
X H
X H
X
¡p1 x h1 ¡ p3 xh3 + M h: (10.76)
h =1 h=1 h =1

By di¤erentiating the welfare function with respect to these tax rates and de…n-
ing

H H e
h H
X @x hN e X @U X h
£N e N´ eh @xN ; N = 1; 3; i = 1; 3;
i ´ ; Uh ´ e
; U£ i U
@ti @x h1 @ti
h=1 e
h=1;eh6=h e
h =1
(10.77)
the optimal taxes can be implicitly expressed as
2 he i3
U £1
e 16
¡ U£ £22 ¡ £ 21 2
e £1
1 U 7
t1 = 4 1
5; (10.78)
£11 £ 22 ¡
£1
£21 £21
1
10.7. TRADEABLE LICENSES 331

and 2 he i3
U £1
e 11
U£ £12 ¡ £ 11 2
6 e £1
U 7
t2 = 4 1
5: (10.79)
£11 £ 22 ¡
£1
£21 £21
1

The …rst result that can be derived form these expressions is that if

e 1
U£ e £1
U
2 1
1
= ; (10.80)
£2 £ 11

then t2 = 0 and t1 is given by (10.75). This will occur if the either the externality
is of the atmospheric kind so that Ueh is the same for all h or if the consumers are
identical. As has been noted above, these are the situations for which a uniform
tax can sustain the …rst-best so the present conclusion is simply an application
of that result.
In other situations the values of the tax rates are determined by two factors:
the degree of aggregate complementarity (£21 < 0) or substitutability (£21 > 0)
and how those individuals that cause a greater amount of externality at the
margin view the good. When the larger o¤enders view the goods as complements
and the goods are aggregate complements then t2 < 0 and t1 is less than the
value determined by the Diamond formula. Moving to aggregate substitutability
makes t1 greater than the Diamond value whilst the signs are all reversed when
larger o¤enders view the goods as substitutes.

10.6.3 Summary
These results conclude the analysis of the determination of tax rates. Although
the economies have been restricted in comparison to some of those in previous
sections, they have illustrated some of the most important determinants of the
tax rates. In particular, it has been shown that uniform taxation cannot sustain
the …rst-best except in restricted circumstances and that optimality will often
require the use of taxes on related goods. However, even when taxes on related
goods are included the …rst-best will generally not be achievable. Indirect taxes
can also be motivated in situations where direct taxes cannot be employed, such
as when emissions cannot be monitored directly but the level of production that
generates them can be. Finally, the e¤ect of the related goods depends on their
substitutability or complementarity to the externality producing good and upon
how the larger contributors to the externality view the goods.

10.7 Tradeable licenses


The motivation underlying the use of corrective pricing is that the unregulated
market will produce incorrect quantities of externalities but, by altering the rel-
ative cost of generating an externality, taxation can lead to the optimal quantity
of externality. When phrased in this way, it may then actually appear simpler to
directly limit the quantity of externalities rather than to attempt to in‡uence it
332 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

via the price system. An obvious way to do this, …rst suggested by Dales (1968),
is to introduce licences that permit the generation of an externality and to al-
low agents to produce externalities only to the extent of the licences they hold.
Allowing the licences to be traded should see them held by the agents who value
them most highly resulting in e¢cient generation of externalities. Set against
these observations has to be the fact that the markets on which permits are
traded may be thin so that the competitive outcome will not be achieved.
Administratively, the use of licences has much to recommend it. The calcu-
lation of tax rates requires considerable information to correctly forecast their
relationship to externalities generated. In addition, changes in other prices
will a¤ect the optimal tax rates and in a dynamic setting the taxes will need
continuous adjustment. These problems are avoided entirely by licences. In
a spatial economy, the control of the spatial distribution of externalities will
only be achieved through taxation if the tax rates are spatially di¤erentiated
which raises the information necessary for their design. In contrast, licences can
restrict the right to emit externalities to a given area and control the spatial
allocation directly. Despite these points, when the properties of licences and
taxes are considered in detail, the choice between the two is not as clear-cut as
these administrative advantages may suggest.

10.7.1 Certain costs and bene…ts


The basis of the argument in favour of licences, which is given in more detail in
Parish (1972), is that a market in pollution quotas would see them purchased by
those who value them most highly and that such purchasers would give the best
return to society for the given level of pollution. The quantity of licences would
determine the level of externality that would be generated, which it is presumed
would be set at the optimal level, whilst the bidding for them would see this
quantity allocated e¢ciently between alternative sources. The tradeable licence
system therefore attains an e¢cient outcome.
When all costs and bene…ts are known with certainty by both the govern-
ment and individual agents, tradeable permits and taxation are equivalent in
their e¤ects up to a redistribution of income. This result is demonstrated for a
very rich spatial economy in Montgomery (1972), for an exchange economy in
Bergstrom (1976) and for a competitive market with entry and exit by Pezzey
(1992). The distribution of income resulting from licences is dependent upon the
method of distribution of licences. If each externality generating agent is sold a
quantity of licences equal to their optimal quantity at the market clearing price
then no further trading will take place and the distribution of income will be
identical to that with taxation. Alternatively, the licences may be distributed
free, possibly in proportion to agents existing level of generation of external-
ity, which will lead to a redistribution of income from the government to the
externality generators relative to the tax solution. Other then these income
di¤erences, the choice between the two systems under certainty will primarily
depend on administrative convenience.
10.7. TRADEABLE LICENSES 333

10.7.2 Prices versus quantities


When costs and bene…ts are uncertain, the equivalence argument does not apply.
To see how this can arise, assume that the level of externality generation can be
reduced at some cost but that this cost is uncertain. If a quantity constraint is
chosen based on expected costs, this will lead to the level of externalities being
too high relative to the optimum when a low value of cost is realised. Conversely,
if a tax, or charge, is introduced this will result in excessive reduction when the
cost of reduction is revealed to be low. The consequences of this observation
were …rst formalised by Weitzman (1974) who derived a condition determining
which of quantity control or pricing would be preferable.
Consider the regulation of a single agent producing an externality and let ½
denote a reduction in the level of the externality from some initial baseline. The
emission of this externality can be controlled either by announcing a Pigouvian
tax of t per unit of externality or by directly announcing the reduction that must
be achieved. Although the assumption of a single agent prevents any trading
in the licences, the argument can be extended to many agents with the licences
traded between then. The cost of reducing the externality is given by C (½; µ)
where µ is a random variable whose distribution is known to the regulator but
whose realisation is not observed at the time the policy must be announced. The
bene…ts are represented by B (½; ´) where ´ is also random with the distribution
known but the realisation not observed until after the policy is announced. It
is assumed that E [µ] = E [´] = 0 and E [µ´] = 0.
When the regulation policy takes the form of an announcement of the reduc-
tion in externality that must be achieved, the optimal reduction, b½, is de…ned
by
b½ = arg max E [B (½; ´) ¡ C (½; µ)] ; (10.81)
f½g

so that it satis…es
E [B1 (b½; ´)] = E [C 1 (b
½; µ)] : (10.82)
When a charge per unit of externality is employed, a maximising agent will
reduce the externality up to the point where the charge is equal to the marginal
cost of reductions after the realisation of the random variable µ. This gives the
equality
t = C 1 (½; µ) : (10.83)
When C 11 6= 0, (10.84) can be solved to write

½ = h (t; µ) : (10.84)

The optimal value of t, denoted e


t, is then de…ned by

e
t = arg max E [B (h (t; µ) ; ´) ¡ C (h (t; µ) ; µ)] ; (10.85)
ftg

so that
£ ¡ ¡ ¢ ¢ ¡ ¢¤ £ ¡ ¡ ¢ ¢ ¡ ¢¤
E B1 h e
t; µ ; ´ h 1 e
t; µ = E C1 h e
t; µ ; µ h 1 e
t; µ : (10.86)
334 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

Using (10.84) in (10.87) gives


£ ¡ ¡ ¢ ¢ ¡ ¢¤
E B1 h e
t; µ ; ´ h 1 e
t; µ
e
t= £ ¡ ¢¤ ; (10.87)
E h1 e t; µ
¡ ¢
and a level of externality reduction e e µ . This level of externality reduc-
½ = h t;
tion is known only after µ is realised.
To permit a comparison of the two methods of regulation, the costs and
bene…ts are approximated around b½ by the quadratic expansions

£ ¤ C3 2
C (½; µ) = C 1 + C 2 + µ [½ ¡ b
½] + [½ ¡ b
½] ; (10.88)
2
and
£ ¤ B3 2
B (½; ´) = B 1 + B2 + ´ [½ ¡ b½] + [½ ¡ b
½] : (10.89)
2
£ 2 ¤
From (10.89), di¤erentiation
£ 2 ¤ gives C1 (½; µ) = C + µ + C 3 [½ ¡ b½] and from
3
(10.90) B1 (½; ´) = B + ´ + B [½ ¡ b ½]. The equality in (10.83) then implies
that C 2 = B 2 . Solving (10.84) using (10.89) gives the reaction of the agent as

t ¡ C2 ¡ µ
½ = h (t; µ) = b
½+ ; (10.90)
C3
hence
1
h 1 (t; µ) = : (10.91)
C3
Substituting (10.92) into (10.88), cancelling the terms in C 3 and taking the
expectation of B1 (½; ´) gives

e B3 B3
t = B2 ¡ 3 C 2 + 3 t: (10.92)
C C

From the equality of B 2 and C 2 , it follows that e


t = C 2 . Using this result in
(10.91) yields
µ
½=b
e ½ ¡ 3: (10.93)
C
To determine which of fee and quantity regulation is superior, de…ne the
additional gain from using taxation relative to quantity control by

¡ = E [[B (e
½; ´) ¡ C (e
½; µ)] ¡ [B (b½; ´) ¡ C (b½; µ)]] : (10.94)

Substituting into (10.94) using the derived terms


£ ¤
¾2 B 3 + C3
¡= 2 ; (10.95)
2 [C 3 ]
£ ¤
where ¾ 2 = E µ2 . The result in (10.95) is easily interpreted. From the approx-
imations in (10.89) and (10.90) it can be seen that a natural assumption would
10.8. INTERNALISATION 335

be B 3 < 0 < C 3 . Therefore taxation will be preferable if the gradient of the


marginal bene…t function is less (in absolute value) than that of marginal cost.
When the opposite holds, quantity restrictions are preferred.
This analysis has been extended to a number of other regulatory schemes by
La¤ont (1977), Ireland (1977), Yohe (1978), Dasgupta, Hammond and Maskin
(1980) and Chen (1990) (not all of which are directly applicable to the control
of externalities). However, all these analyses are restricted by the employment
of quadratic approximations. Therefore, beyond the observation that charges
and quantities are not equivalent under uncertainty, no general principles have
been derived from this line of analysis.

10.7.3 Nonlinear pricing


The di¤ering e¤ects of fees and licences suggests that, rather than relying on
either one alone, it would be best to combine the instruments. Roberts and
Spence (1976) prove that such a combined system reduces expected social costs
below the level achievable by either fees or licences alone. This, though, does
not exhaust the possibilities.
Spence (1977) observes that control by licences can be interpreted as a non-
linear pricing system in which the price of the right to emit an externality is
zero (or the cost of the licence) until the quantity permitted by the licence is
reached. For any quantity above this level, the price becomes in…nite. In con-
trast, fees represent a linear price system for the externalities. It follows from
these observations that if the set of permissible pricing systems is extended to
the set of continuous functions, both fees and licences, or any combination of
the two, will be dominated by a suitably chosen nonlinear pricing system from
this set. In such a system, the price for emitting externalities is dependent
upon the quantity emitted. These results show that the choice between price
and quantity is therefore irrelevant and all that really matters is the selection
of the optimal nonlinear pricing system. Although the optimal nonlinear price
system can be characterised using methods similar to those of Chapter 5, its
value is limited by the considerable administrative di¢culties involved with the
implementation of such a system.

10.8 Internalisation
A further method of externality control, as …rst discussed by Davis and Whin-
ston (1962), is to encourage the internalisation of the externality so that private
and social costs become the same. The essence of the internalisation is that if
…rm A causes a negative externality only upon …rm B, then the …rm formed by
merging both A and B will take account of the externality when choosing its
optimal behaviour. Hence, no ine¢ciency will arise. Such arguments have also
been proposed as providing part of the rationale concerning the existence of the
…rm.
336 CHAPTER 10. EXTERNALITIES

Internalisation though is not without its di¢culties. To highlight the …rst


of these, consider an industry in which the productive activity of each …rm in
the industry causes an externality for the other …rms in the industry. In this
situation the internalisation argument would suggest that the …rms become a
single monopolist. If this were to occur, welfare loss would then arise due to
the monopolistic behaviour and this may actually be greater than the initial
loss due to the externality. Although this is obviously an extreme example,
the internalisation argument always implies the construction of larger economic
agents and a consequent increase in market power. The welfare loss due to
market power then has to be o¤set against the gain from eliminating the e¤ect
of the externality.
The second di¢culty is that the economic agents involved may simply not
wish to be amalgamated into a single unit. This objection is particularly true
when applied to consumption externalities since if a household generates an
externality for their neighbour it is not clear that they would wish to form a
single household unit, particularly if the externality is a negative one.
In summary, internalisation will eliminate the consequences of an externality
in very direct manner by ensuring that private and social costs are equated.
However it is unlikely to be a practical solution when many distinct economic
agents contribute separately to the total externality and has the disadvantage
of leading to increased market power.

10.9 Conclusions
Externalities are a prevalent feature of economic life and their existence can
lead to ine¢ciency in an unregulated competitive economy. Although the Coase
theorem suggests that such ine¢ciencies will be eliminated by private trading
in competitive markets, number ob jections can be raised to this conclusion.
Amongst these are the lack of well-de…ned property rights, the thinness of mar-
kets and the incomplete information of market participants. Each of these
impediments to e¢cient trading undermines the practical value of the Coase
theorem.
The obvious policy response to the externality problem is the introduction
of a system of corrective Pigouvian taxes with the tax rates being proportional
to the marginal damage in‡icted by externality generation. When su¢cient
di¤erentiation of these taxes is possible between di¤erent agents, the …rst-best
outcome can be sustained but such a system is not practical due to its informa-
tional requirements. Restricting the taxes to be uniform across agents allows
the …rst-best to be achieved in some special cases but, generally, leads to a
second-best outcome. An alternative system of control is to employ marketable
licences. These have administrative advantages over taxes and lead to an iden-
tical outcome in conditions of certainty. With uncertainty, licences and taxes
have di¤erent e¤ects and combining the two can lead to a superior outcome.
Chapter 11

Imperfect Competition

11.1 Introduction
In the previous chapters, the assumption of competitive behaviour has been
maintained throughout. It is often best to view this as a useful restriction
for developing initial ideas and eliminating unnecessary complication. As a
representation of reality it is clearly ‡awed, an observation easily supported
by casual empiricism. This chapter relaxes the competitive assumption and
reviews some of the major results that have been derived within the framework
of imperfect competition.
The …rst point to note is that there are numerous forms of imperfect compe-
tition which vary with respect to the nature of products, the strategic variables
of the …rms, the objectives of the …rms and the possibility of entry. Products
may be homogeneous or di¤erentiated and the strategic variables of the …rms
can either be prices or quantities with, possibly, additional instruments such as
investment or advertising. The …rms’ objectives may be individual pro…t max-
imisation or, alternatively, joint pro…t maximisation. Entry may be impossible,
so that an industry is composed of a …xed number of …rms, it may be unhin-
dered or incumbent …rms may be following a policy of entry deterrence. To
avoid some of this complexity, this chapter will focus primarily upon economies
with quantity setting oligopoly and homogeneous products although at some
points conjectures are introduced to permit ‡exibility. For a suitable choice
of conjecture, this form of oligopoly has the advantage of being equivalent to
monopoly when the industry has a single …rm and, under most circumstances,
to competition as the number of …rms increases without limit. This makes the
economy both straightforward and ‡exible.
A second point of some relevance is that tax incidence is more complex
with imperfect competition. Under the competitive assumption any taxes are
simply passed forward by the …rms since price is always set at marginal cost.
In contrast, prices on imperfectly competitive markets are set at a level above
marginal cost and an increase in cost due to taxation need not be re‡ected in

337
338 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

an identical increase in price. To determine the actual change it is necessary to


work through the comparative statics of the industry in question. In addition
to the price e¤ects, imperfectly competitive …rms may also earn non-zero pro…ts
and the e¤ect of taxation on these must also be determined.
The initial sections of this chapter focus on issues related to the construc-
tion and analysis of a general equilibrium economy with imperfect competition.
After introducing the economy that forms the basis of the chapter, it is shown
why the equilibrium is not Pareto optimal and measures of the welfare loss due
to imperfect competition are described. This is followed by an analysis of com-
modity tax incidence and optimal tax rules. The chapter is completed by a
reconsideration of the necessity for production e¢ciency.

11.2 Imperfect competition and general equilib-


rium
The …rst formal general equilibrium economy with imperfect competition can be
attributed to Negishi (1961). Also of signi…cance are Arrow and Hahn (1971),
Gabszewicz and Vial (1972), Roberts and Sonnenschein (1977), Cornwall (1977)
and the survey by Hart (1985). Unlike the Arrow-Debreu formulation of the
competitive economy there is not a single, generally accepted framework but a
number of alternative speci…cations. The economies are di¤erentiated by the
assumptions made about the form of demand function known by the …rms and
on the relation of demand to pro…t.

11.2.1 Objective and subjective demand


The …rst distinction to note is between economies that employ objective demands
and those using subjective demands. This distinction arises from the information
that the …rms comprising an imperfectly competitive industry must possess in
order to know their pro…t function. In a competitive economy, a …rm need only
observe the set of market prices to determine its pro…t maximising strategy. In
contrast an imperfectly competitive …rm requires the knowledge of the demand
function for its product. Naturally this is a far greater informational requirement
than just the knowledge of prices and, when literally interpreted, implies that
the …rms need to be able to solve the economy to generate the excess demands.
Faced with this informational problem, Negishi (1961) assumed that the
…rms actually knew only a linear approximation to their true demand functions,
with the restriction that the linear approximation was equal to the true demand
at equilibrium prices. The latter condition ensures that the …rms generate
the pro…t levels that they were expecting. Such demands have been labelled
subjective since they exist only as beliefs held by …rms. This approach has been
extended by Gary-Bobo (1989) to consider …rms that perceive knowledge of a
kth order Taylor expansion of their true demand. When k = 1 the equilibria
coincide with the equilibrium arising from the true demands.
11.2. IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM 339

In an economy with objective demand, such as Gabszewicz and Vial (1972),


it is assumed that the …rms actually know their demand functions. Despite
the informational burden this imposes, it does overcome the problems of the
subjective approach in that it does not require speci…cation of how the …rms form
the subjective demands or of how they may seek to revise them. In the analysis
of this chapter only the objective approach is followed. This can be supported
on the grounds of simplicity and the fact that since subjective demands are
typically chosen equal to objective demands at equilibrium, the equilibrium of
the economy should not be a¤ected by the choice.
The assumptions concerning the distribution of pro…ts and their e¤ect upon
demand is another area in which alternative economies di¤er. If returned to con-
sumers as dividends, whenever income e¤ects are non-zero a …rm’s pro…ts must
appear as an argument of its demand function. This causes some di¢culties
for the speci…cation of the …rm’s maximisation problem since the quantity to
be maximised (pro…t) appears as an argument in the objective function. When
this occurs, standard results on maximisation are not applicable.
There have been three responses to this. The …rst is to assume the structure
of the economy is such that there are no income e¤ects. This approach is exem-
pli…ed by the work of Hart (1982) in which the economy is divided into separate
sectors and the …rms distribute pro…t generated in one sector to consumers who
purchase in a di¤erent sector. In this way, although aggregate demand depends
on pro…t, the demand for each …rm is independent of its own pro…t level. How-
ever, assumptions such as this have the disadvantage of being highly arti…cial.
The second response is more direct and simply involves assuming that all pro…ts
are taxed at a rate of 100% so that pro…t income accrues to the government
alone. This assumption has the disadvantage of eliminating the motive for the
choice of pro…t maximising strategy for the …rms. The …nal approach is to meet
the problem directly and to extend the analysis to suit. This has the drawback
of leading to greater complication in the results. The approach taken below will
be to adopt a combination of the latter two possibilities, with the choice made
to suit the purpose.
To complete this discussion of the choice of structure, it should be noted that
intermediate goods are almost never included in general equilibrium economies
with imperfect competition. This exclusion is due to the di¢culty of formulating
the derived demand for such goods when a number of …rms have market power.
For a discussion of this point, see Hart (1985). Although they are similarly
excluded from most of the discussion below, they do occur at two points: in the
discussion of the extent of welfare loss due to imperfect competition and in the
treatment of production e¢ciency.

11.2.2 Price normalisations


Prior to setting out the details of the economy, it is necessary to describe the
method of price normalisation that is to be employed. For competitive gen-
eral equilibrium economies, the permissible price normalisations are well known
and have been described in Chapter 2: the price vector may be transformed
340 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

in any way provided the ratios of prices remain una¤ected. The same claim
cannot be made for economies with imperfect competition and the general class
of permissible normalisation rules is more restricted than for the competitive
economy.
Since the work of Gabszewicz and Vial (1972) it has been recognised that
normalisation rules that would not a¤ect a competitive equilibrium will have
real e¤ects upon equilibrium with imperfect competition as the following ex-
ample demonstrates. Consider an economy with one single-product monopo-
list producing at zero cost and whose pro…t maximising output is …nite. Now
imagine a representation of this economy which, for analytical simplicity, uses a
normalisation rule that selects the monopolist’s good as the numeraire. The mo-
nopolist’s pro…t maximising output in the representation of the economy then
becomes unbounded and so the normalisation rule has altered the real equilib-
rium. Since this normalisation rule is known not to a¤ect competitive equilibria,
this example demonstrates that the class of normalisation rules that do not af-
fect equilibrium is smaller for imperfect competition than for the competitive
model. The actual rules employed by Gabszewicz and Vial are essentially arbi-
trary and were no doubt used for computational convenience. The same general
comment applies to Dierker and Grodal (1986). In contrast, both Negishi (1961)
and Cornwall (1977) restrict prices to the unit simplex in order to exploit the
resulting compactness properties of this set. Cornwall notes that this choice
will a¤ect the equilibrium except in the special case of the Negishi model with
linear subjective demand. Roberts (1980d) employs leisure as the numeraire
and notes that the equilibrium is generally not numeraire free. It is not clear
whether the market for the numeraire is competitive or not. Neither Gues-
nerie and La¤ont (1978) nor Roberts and Sonnenschein (1977) use or discuss a
price normalisation. Finally, each economy in the survey paper of Hart (1985)
employs a di¤erent method of price normalisation.
As the variety of price normalisations noted above illustrates, there is no
common approach but there is general agreement that some price normalisations
will a¤ect the real equilibrium. In Cripps and Myles (1989), it is shown that the
equilibrium is invariant to any normalisation rule that is de…ned as a function
of competitive goods prices but is independent of the prices of goods traded on
imperfectly competitive markets. For the economies described below, a simple
version of this rule is adopted: labour is assumed to be traded on a competitive
market and the wage rate is taken as numeraire.

11.2.3 The economy


The general equilibrium economy with imperfect competition that will form the
basis for the analysis of commodity taxation and production e¢ciency is now
introduced. The economy is based upon that used for the analysis of commodity
taxation by Myles (1989a). It will be assumed that there is a …xed number of
…rms in each industry but the economy can easily be extended to allow for entry.
Consider an economy with n + 1 goods, indexed i = 0; 1; :::; n, where good 0
is chosen to be labour. It is assumed that the labour market is competitive and
11.2. IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM 341

that consumers’ endowments are of labour alone. The n goods are partitioned
into two subsets. The …rst subset consists of goods i = 1; :::; K and these are
assumed to be produced by competitive industries, each employing a constant
returns to scale technology that has labour as the only input. The assumptions
of constant returns and a single input imply that for each good there is a constant
ci that describes the labour input per unit of output. With a wage rate p0 , the
competitive assumption implies marginal cost pricing so that

p i = cip 0 ; i = 1; :::; K: (11.1)

Since pro…ts are zero under constant returns to scale, equation (11.1) is a com-
plete description of the competitive sector.
The remaining n ¡ K goods are produced by imperfectly competitive indus-
tries. In the industry producing good i, there are m i …rms, indexed j = 1; :::; m i.
The demand function for good i is denoted by

Xi = Xi (p 0 ; :::; p n ; ¼) ; (11.2)

where the aggregate level of pro…t, ¼, is equal to the sum of pro…ts of all …rms
n
X mi
X
¼= ¼ ji : (11.3)
i=K +1 j=1

The demand function in (11.2) is taken to be the true demand for the economy
so it is one of objective demand. Assuming that (11.2) is strictly monotonic in
p i , it can be solved to give the inverse demand function for good i

p i = Ái (p 0 ; :::; pi¡1 ; Xi ; p i+1 ; :::; p n ; ¼) : (11.4)

To analyse the …rms’ decisions, it is assumed that quantities are the strategic
variable. Hence each …rm in industry i chooses its output level to maximise
pro…ts. Denoting a typical …rm by j, the …rm chooses x ji to maximise
³ ´
j j j j
¼ i = Ái (p0 ; :::; p i¡1 ; Xi; p i+1 ; :::; pn ; ¼ ) x i ¡ C i xi ; (11.5)
³ ´
j j
where C i xi is the cost function of the …rm. The Cournot assumption is
j j0
adopted so that when choosing x i …rm j takes as …xed the outputs, x i , j 0 =
1; :::; m i; j 0 6= j; of all other …rms in its industry. In addition, the Cournot
assumption is extended to the other arguments of (11.4) so the …rm also takes
as given the prices on all other markets and the pro…t levels of all …rms other
than itself.
Totally di¤erentiating (11.5) under these assumptions gives
¸ " #
j
j j @Ái j j @Ái @C i
d¼ i 1 ¡ x i = dxi pi + x i ¡ j : (11.6)
@¼ @Xi @xi
342 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

Assuming that the income e¤ect in demand is su¢ciently weak that the left-
hand side satis…es

1 ¡ xji i > 0; (11.7)

then the …rst-order condition that the …rms decision must satisfy is given by
j
j @Ái @Ci
p i + xi ¡ j = 0: (11.8)
@Xi @x i

In addition to satisfying this condition, at an equilibrium any choice for the …rm
must also have the property that it is consistent with the assumptions made on
the pro…t levels and outputs of other …rms. That is, the chosen level of output
must also satisfy the pro…t identity
³ ´
¼ ji ¡ Ái (p0 ; :::; p i¡1 ; Xi; p i+1 ; :::; pn ; ¼) xji + C ij x ji = 0: (11.9)

Simultaneously solving (11.8) and (11.9) for the mi …rms comprising industry i,
the output and pro…t of …rm j can be expressed in terms of the prices charged
on other markets and the pro…ts levels of …rms in other industries. This gives
the following two equations
0 1
n m i0
j j
X X j 0
¼ i = °i @ p 0 ; :::; p i¡1 ; p i+ 1 ; :::; p n ; ¼ i0 A ; (11.10)
i 0 =K+ 1;i 06=i j=1

0 1
n m i0
X X 0
xji = ¾ ji @ p 0 ; :::; p i¡1 ; p i+ 1 ; :::; p n ; ¼ ji0 A : (11.11)
i 0 =K+ 1;i 06=i j=1

Equation (11.11) can now be used to replace aggregate output, Xi, in (11.4)
by the sum of individual …rms’ outputs and (11.10) to substitute for the pro…ts
levels of …rms in industry i. This determines an equilibrium price on market i
as 0 1
n mi0
X X 0
p i = © i @ p 0 ; :::; pi¡1 ; p i+1 ; :::; pn ; ¼ ji0 A : (11.12)
i 0 =K +1;i 06= i j=1

Using equations (11.10) and (11.12), a general equilibrium can now be de-
…ned formally.
Imperfectly Competitive Equilibrium n n oo
An imperfectly competitive equilibrium is an array fp ig ; ¼ ji such that
(i) pi = ci p0³, i = 1; :::; K,
Pn Pmi0 j 0 ´
(ii) p i = ©i p0 ; :::; p i¡1 ; p i+ 1; :::; p n ; i0 =K+1;i06=i j=1 ¼ i0 , i = K+1; :::; n,
and ³ Pn Pm 0
´
(iii) ¼ ji = °ji p 0 ; :::; pi¡1 ; p i+1 ; :::; pn ; i0 =K +1;i0 6=i j=i01 ¼ ji0 , i = K+1; :::; n,
j = 1; :::; mi .
11.3. IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND WELFARE 343

This de…nition of the equilibrium incorporates both the pro…t maximisation


of the …rms and the existence of positive levels of pro…t. It should be noted that
the economy takes as given the demand functions of the households, rather than
using their preference relation, and restricts demand to depend only upon total
pro…ts. It is therefore being implicitly assumed in the above statement that
there is some array of shareholdings that determine the allocation of pro…ts to
households and that the households are maximising utility given their income
levels and consumption sets. Since the emphasis here is upon the consequences
of the non-competitive behaviour of the …rms, it does not seem necessary to
provide the details of the consumption sector since these remain as for the
competitive economy.
It is considerably more problematic to prove the existence of an equilibrium
for the imperfectly competitive economy than for the competitive case. The
…rst di¢culty arises from the maximisation de…ned in (11.5). If this is to have
a unique solution that is continuous in the variables parametric to the indi-
vidual …rm, then the pro…t function of the …rm must be strictly convex as a
function of its own output. Unfortunately, strict convexity is a strong require-
ment since it imposes severe restrictions upon the demand function facing the
…rm. As shown by Roberts and Sonnenschein (1977) it is possible to construct
economies in which the convexity fails. Moving from the single …rm to the econ-
omy, the equilibrium requires that the output and pro…t functions given in the
de…nition should all be satis…ed simultaneously. Although similar in nature to
simultaneously solving the excess demand functions for a competitive economy,
there is less structure in the imperfectly competitive economy and stronger as-
sumptions are necessary to ensure the existence of a solution. Despite these
di¢culties, given that it is assumed an equilibrium exists, the characterisation
of equilibrium above is straightforward and can be employed in further analysis.

11.3 Imperfect competition and welfare


Imperfect competition is one of the standard examples of market failure which
lead to the non-achievement of Pareto optimality. It is on this basis that eco-
nomic policy is usually suggested as necessary in the presence of imperfect com-
petition in order to reduce ine¢ciency.

11.3.1 Failure of Pareto optimality


To demonstrate that imperfect competition does not generate a Pareto opti-
mum, it is necessary to provide a suitable characterisation of Pareto optimality.
There are several ways in which this can be done. Firstly, by consideration of
the competitive equilibrium it can be appreciated that competitive …rms price
at marginal cost and that this is one of the conditions for Pareto optimality.
Contrasting this to the pricing policy implicit in (11.8), it can be seen that

whenever @Xii is non-zero, price will not be equal to marginal cost in the im-
perfectly competitive industry. Further investigation of the relation of prices to
344 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

costs, or the mark-up over costs, with imperfect competition can be found in
Cowling and Waterson (1977).
A second method of comparison is to return to the economy summarised in
(9.1) and (9.2) but without the inclusion of the externality e¤ects. Repeating
the analysis given there, the conclusion that follows is that at a Pareto optimum
the ratio of shadow prices for any pair of goods, given by the ¸s, should be should
be equal to the ratio of rates of transformation. In addition, at a competitive
equilibrium the ratio of shadow prices is equal to the ratio of market prices
@F
pi ¸i @X i
= = @F : (11.13)
pk ¸k @X k

For the economy with imperfect competition, assuming that there is a single
…rm in each imperfectly competitive industry in order to simplify the construc-
tion, the production possibilities are constrained by the relation that the sum
of labour demand from the competitive and imperfectly competitive sectors
satis…es
XK Xn
Ci (Xi)
ai X i + ¡ ! 0 0; (11.14)
i=1 i=K +1
p0

where Ci (Xi) is the cost function of the single …rm in industry i and ! 0 is the
initial endowment of labour. For two goods i and k produced by imperfectly
competitive …rms, it follows from (11.14) that

@F @C i
@X i @xi
@F
= @C k
: (11.15)
@ Xk @xk

Hence using (11.8),



pi + x i @Xii
@Á k
: (11.16)
pk + x k @X k

Equation (11.16) captures the notion of market failure due to the lack of price
taking behaviour. The prices should be proportional to the marginal rates of
transformation which capture the social cost of producing each good. However,
the fact that the imperfectly competitive …rms take the e¤ect of their actions
upon prices into account eliminates the direct proportionality.

11.3.2 Measures of welfare loss


It has been shown that the imperfectly competitive equilibrium is not Pareto
optimal. Following from this, the equilibrium cannot maximise the value of any
social welfare function that satis…es the Pareto criterion de…ned in Chapter 2.
This observation then makes it natural to consider what the degree of welfare
loss may actually be, either for a real economy or for simulated examples. The
assessment of monopoly welfare loss has been a sub ject of some dispute in which
11.3. IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND WELFARE 345

calculations have provided a range of estimates from the e¤ectively insigni…cant


to considerable percentages of potential welfare.

Contributions to the literature on monopoly welfare loss can be characterised


according to three criteria: the welfare measure used; whether data or simula-
tions are employed and whether the underlying model is of general or partial
equilibrium. The choice between welfare measures can e¤ectively be reduced
to either calculating welfare loss triangles (in terms of National Income in Har-
berger (1954) and Gross Corporate Product in Cowling and Mueller (1978)) or
specifying an explicit welfare function and using this to evaluate welfare loss,
a methodology whose case has been argued most forcefully by Bergson (1973).
The earlier contributions were primarily concerned with the use of data to cal-
culate losses for actual economies (Harberger for the USA, Cowling and Mueller
for the UK and USA) but more recent work has concentrated on the use of
simulations to calculate potential losses (Bergson (1973), Kay (1983)). Dickson
and Yu (1989) employs a mix of both data and simulation. With respect to the
form of model, the vast majority of contributions have adopted a partial equi-
librium framework. There are some exceptions to this, most notably Ireland
(1978), Kay (1983) and Myles (1994a).

The initial study of monopoly welfare loss is usually attributed to Harberger


(1954) who considered the e¤ect of monopolisation in United States manufac-
turing industry for the period 1924 to 1928. From the data it is concluded that
welfare loss is equal to 0.08% of national income. Clearly if this …gure is accurate,
then monopoly welfare loss was insigni…cant in the United States. In contrast
to Harberger, Cowling and Mueller (1978) include the cost of advertising in the
measure of welfare loss on the interpretation that advertising is undertaken with
the intention of maintaining a monopoly position. This naturally raises their
estimates. Their analysis of welfare loss in the United States is based on data
for 734 …rms between 1963 and 1966 and concludes that welfare loss is between
4% and 13% of Gross Corporate Product. For the United Kingdom, Cowling
and Mueller conclude that the top 103 …rms in 1968 to 1969, accounting for
a third of GNP, generated a welfare loss of between 3.9% and 7.2% of Gross
Corporate Product. This contrasts with the loss of 0.2% to 3% using the Har-
berger measure for the same data set. These two sets of …gures clearly provide
con‡icting evidence, as do the numerous other contributions that are surveyed
in Sawyer (1981). The actual extent of welfare loss therefore remains an open
question.

Turning now to measures of welfare loss in simulation models, these have


generated far higher …gures than analyses of data. Using a constant elasticity
of substitution utility function, Bergson (1973) produces a range of estimates
from 0.06% of national income to 39.03% The drawback to these …gures is that
they are calculated on the basis of hypothesised price-cost mark-ups rather than
having the mark-up determined as the equilibrium of a speci…ed economy. Kay
(1983) employs a model with one consumption good that is produced by a
346 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

monopolist using a single form of labour service. With the utility function

x 1¡"
1
U = ¡ x0 ; (11.17)
"

a range of estimates were calculated ranging from 3% of GNP when " = 0:1
to 134% when " = 0:9. In addition, the loss was above 10% for all values of
" > 0:3.
The analyses described above have considered monopoly power to be present
only in the markets for …nal goods and have implicitly taken intermediate goods
markets to be competitive. When the outputs of imperfectly competitive indus-
tries are used both as intermediate inputs and for …nal consumption, welfare loss
can only be increased by the additional distortion of input prices. In a general
equilibrium economy with intermediate goods, Myles (1994a) …nds welfare loss
…gures ranging from 11% of the attainable utility level to 79%.
It can be appreciated from this discussion that there have been a broad range
of estimates of monopoly welfare loss. The …gures generated by simulation
studies are generally greater than those arising from data and indicate that,
theoretically, monopoly may be very damaging in terms of reduced welfare.

11.4 Commodity taxation


The use of commodity taxation when there is imperfect competition has the
additional motivation, beyond those of raising revenue and redistributing welfare
present in the analysis of commodity taxation in Chapter 4, of attempting to
reduce the welfare loss due to non-competitive behaviour. There is consequently
a counter-distortionary role for commodity taxation even in a single consumer
model with zero revenue requirement.
Compared to the competitive model there are several factors that complicate
tax analysis when imperfect competition is introduced. Firstly, the analysis of
tax incidence is more complex in the imperfectly competitive case. With com-
petition, commodity taxes are simply passed forward by the …rms since they
always price at marginal cost. In contrast, prices on imperfectly competitive
markets are set at a level above marginal cost and an increase in cost due to
taxation need not be passed directly to consumers. The actual change in price
can only be determined by working through the comparative statics of the indus-
try in question. The analysis of taxation therefore begins with a consideration
of tax incidence. Secondly, in addition to the price e¤ects, imperfectly compet-
itive …rms may also earn non-zero pro…ts and the e¤ect of taxation upon these
must also be determined. As with the incidence of taxes upon prices, the pro…t
e¤ects have to be calculated from the comparative statics of each industry.
With imperfect competition it is also necessary to note that ad valorem and
speci…c taxation do not have identical e¤ects. That is, for a given level of post-
tax price, the two methods of taxation may lead to di¤erent levels of revenue.
To reduce the level of complexity below, the major part of the analysis of this
11.4. COMMODITY TAXATION 347

chapter will the conducted in terms of speci…c taxes. The interaction of speci…c
and ad valorem taxes is considered in Section 5.
After a review of tax incidence, two economies will be analysed. The …rst
economy is has a single consumer and three goods. This is employed to in-
vestigate the factors that determine the levels of taxation when the taxes are
used solely to counter the distortions due to non-competitive behaviour. The
second economy characterises optimal taxes using the imperfectly competitive
economy introduced in Section 2.3 and provides a non-competitive variant of
the Diamond-Mirrlees optimal commodity tax rule.

11.4.1 Tax incidence


Tax incidence is concerned with the e¤ect of taxation upon prices and pro…t
levels. Although tax incidence was of considerable importance in the determi-
nation of the optimal tax rules of Chapter 4, the structure of the competitive
economy that was used to derive the Ramsey rule simpli…es tax incidence to
such an extent that a formal discussion of incidence was not required. In addi-
tion, in the more general economy of Section 6 of Chapter 4, the separation of
producer and consumer sectors again obviates the need for an analysis of tax
incidence. With imperfect competition, an analysis of tax incidence is essential.
To emphasise the points made above, it is worth looking again at the e¤ects
of commodity taxation in the competitive model. Retaining the assumption
that labour is the only input implies that with the wage rate as the untaxed
numeraire that there is a set of …xed producer prices p0 ; :::; p K in the competitive
sector. It then follows immediately that

qi = p i + ti; i = 1; :::; K; (11.18)

and from this that


@qi
= 1; (11.19)
@ti
and
@qi
= 0; i 6= k: (11.20)
@tk
Equation (11.19) states that the commodity tax is forward-shifted at the rate
of 100%, that is, the entire tax is shifted by the …rm onto the consumer. Equa-
tion (11.20) illustrates that there is no interaction between the price of a good
produced by a competitive industry and the tax on any other good. It is these
results that give the competitive tax rules their precise structure.
To illustrate the important features of tax incidence with imperfect compe-
tition a simple, but ‡exible, example will now be considered. Consider a single
industry and assume that this industry is composed of m i …rms, each with the
same cost function and beliefs about the other …rms’ reactions. These assump-
tions ensure that there will be a symmetric equilibrium, will all …rms producing
the same output level. The inverse demand function facing the industry is
348 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

denoted 0 1
Xmi
qi = Ái @ xji ; qk A ; (11.21)
j=1

where xji is the output of …rm j and qk is some representative other price. The
second price is introduced in order to allow consideration of the consequences
of its variation. Note that the prices are represented by qs to denote that they
are post-tax consumer prices. Each of the m i …rms aims to maximise
0 1
mi
X 0
³ ´
¼ ji = xji Ái @ xji + x ji ; qk A ¡ tix ji ¡ Ci x ji ; (11.22)
j 0 =1;j 0 6=j

³ ´
j
where C i x i is the cost function that is the same for all …rms in industry i
and ti is the speci…c tax levied on the output of the ith industry.
The ‡exibility in the example is introduced by assuming that each …rm holds
a conjecture about how the other …rms will respond to changes in its output
level. By suitable choice of the conjecture, it is possible for the model to generate
all outcomes from competitive pricing to monopoly pricing. The conjecture, ¸,
can be de…ned formally as
³ Pmi ´
j0
@ x ji + j 0=1;j 06= j x i
¸= : (11.23)
@xji

As will be made clear after inspection of the …rst-order condition (11.24) below,
if ¸ = m i monopoly pricing arises, ¸ = 1 represents Cournot behaviour and ¸ =
0 generates the Bertrand equilibrium with competitive marginal cost pricing.
Employing the de…nition of the conjecture, the …rst-order condition for pro…t
maximisation for …rm j is
j
@¼ i j @Ái @C i
j ´ qi ¡ t i + x i ¸ ¡ j = 0: (11.24)
@xi @Xi @xi
The …rst question concerning tax incidence is the calculation of the e¤ect
of changing ti upon the equilibrium values of ¼ ji , j = 1; :::; mi , and qi . These
e¤ects are derived by …rst noting that the symmetry assumption implies that
x ji = x i, all j and hence that
0 1
mi
X j
qi = Ái @ x i ; qk A = Ái (mi xi ; qk ) : (11.25)
j=1

Totally di¤erentiating the …rst-order condition (11.24) by varying all outputs


and the tax rate gives
¸
@Á @Á @ 2 Ái @2 C i
dx i mi i + ¸ i + xi mi ¸ ¡ = dti : (11.26)
@Xi @Xi @Xi2 @x2i
11.4. COMMODITY TAXATION 349

From the inverse demand function


@Ái
dqi = mi dx i: (11.27)
@Xi
Using (11.27) to eliminate dx i from (11.26) determines the e¤ect of the tax
change upon the equilibrium price as

dqi mi @ Xii
= @Á @ 2Á
; (11.28)
dti [m i + ¸] @ Xii + x im i ¸ @ X 2i
i

where it has been assumed for simplicity that marginal cost is constant. The
expression dqdti is termed the degree of forward shifting of the tax and, except
i

when the equilibrium is in the sense of Bertrand with ¸ = 0, it can be seen from
(11.28) that dqdti is not necessarily equal to 1.
i

It is standard practice to distinguish between overshifting, in which case the


price rises by more than the increase in tax, and undershifting, for when it rises
by less. This distinction will be seen to be important in the determination of
relative tax rates. To proceed further, it is assumed that the equilibrium is
stable in the sense of Seade (1980), for which a su¢cient restriction is that the
denominator of (11.28) is negative. Using the stability restriction, it follows from
(11.28) that overshifting, which is equivalent to dq i
dti
> 1, occurs for non-zero ¸
when
@Á @Ái @ 2 Ái
m i i < [m i + ¸] + x im i ¸ : (11.29)
@Xi @Xi @Xi2
Since both the left- and right-hand sides of (11.29) are negative, it can be
rearranged to give the equivalent condition for overshifting
@Ái @ 2 Ái
> ¡x im i ¸ : (11.30)
@Xi @Xi2
Condition (11.30) above can be viewed in two ways. Firstly, it represents a
restriction on the convexity of the inverse demand function since, if overshifting
2
is to occur, it is necessary that @@ XÁ2i is positive. Secondly, it can be phrased in
i
terms of Seade’s (1985) E by de…ning
2
¡Xi @@ XÁ2i
E´ @Ái
i
; (11.31)
@ Xi

where E measures the elasticity of the slope of the inverse demand function.
In terms of E, when ¸ = 1; condition (11.30) states that overshifting occurs
when E > 1, that taxes are shifted at a rate of 100% when E = 1 and under-
shifted when E < 1. For other values of ¸; the critical values of E are adjusted
accordingly.
Turning now to pro…ts, the pro…t level of …rm j can be written as a function
of the tax rate
j
¼ i (ti ) = xi (ti) [qi (ti) ¡ ti ] ¡ Ci (x i (ti )) : (11.32)
350 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

Di¤erentiating pro…ts with respect to ti gives


j ¸ ¸
d¼ i @qi @xi @C i
= xi ¡1 + qi ¡ t i ¡ : (11.33)
dti @ti @ti @x i

Now using (11.24), (11.26) and (11.28) provides the expression


h 2
i
@Á i 2m ¸ @ Ái
j
d¼ i ¡ 2x i @X i
+ xi i 2
@ Xi
= 2 : (11.34)
dti [m i + ¸] @Á i
+ xi m i¸ @ Á2i
@X i @X i

The result in (11.34) provides the interesting conclusion that the …rm’s pro…t
level may actually increase as the tax rate increases, a result …rst shown by
Seade (1986). The su¢cient condition for this to occur, when ¸ = 1; can be
found from (11.34) to be E > 2. This possibility arises due to the tax change
moving the oligopolistic equilibrium closer to the monopoly outcome. Further
results along these lines can be found in de Meza (1982), Dierickx, Matutes and
Neven (1988), Myles (1987) and Stern (1987).
The tax incidence analysis above comprises what have been termed the direct
e¤ects of taxation, where direct refers to the fact they relate to the e¤ect of
the tax levied on the industry under consideration. In addition to the direct
e¤ects there may also arise indirect or induced changes in prices and pro…ts in
imperfectly competitive industry i due to changes in the tax rates on industries
other than i. From (11.20) and the fact that pro…ts are zero for the competitive
industries, these induced e¤ects do not arise in the competitive model.
To evaluate the induced e¤ects upon price, (11.24) can be di¤erentiated with
respect to qk to give
h h i i
@Ái @ Ái @ 2Á i @Ái @ 2Á i
dqi ¸ @q k @X i
+ x i m i @ Xi2 ¡ x i m i @X i @X i@q k
= @Á i @ 2Ái
: (11.35)
dqk [m i + ¸] @X i + x im i¸ @X 2
i

Provided the inverse demand for good i is not independent of qk , the induced
price e¤ect is almost always non-zero. Inspection of (11.35) shows that the
change in qi may be of either sign. That is, the induced e¤ect may increase or
decrease the price of good i.
To illustrate the importance of this factor assume that good k is produced
by a competitive industry so that the inverse demand function can be written
as 0 1
mi
X j
qi = Ái @ x i ; pk + tk A : (11.36)
j= 1

dq i dq i
Hence dq k
calculated above is equal to dt k
so, in optimising over tk , these
induced e¤ects must be taken into account. Similar reasoning also holds when
industry k is imperfectly competitive but the additional, nonlinear, relation of
qk to tk must be included. To complete this analysis, it should also be noted
11.4. COMMODITY TAXATION 351

that there will be an induced e¤ect of changes in qk upon the pro…t levels in
industry i.
To summarise this section, it has been noted that with imperfect compe-
tition taxes may be undershifted or overshifted. Overshifting implies that the
…nal price rises by more than any increase in tax, undershifting the converse.
The rate of shifting is determined by the degree of concavity or convexity of
the demand function facing the industry and the cost functions of the …rms
that compose that industry. Concavity of demand leads to undershifting and
su¢cient convexity to overshifting. When marginal cost is constant, the rele-
vant factor is Seade’s E , the elasticity of the gradient of the demand function.
The dependence of the market price upon the demand function introduces a
further factor. If a price of another good alters, due perhaps to a tax levied on
it, then this will a¤ect the demand function and hence the market price of the
imperfectly competitive industry in question. These induced price changes are
considered in detail in Myles (1987, 1989a). To the above e¤ects must also be
added the e¤ects of taxation upon the pro…t levels of the …rms which are not
always as straightforward as may be expected.

11.4.2 Optimal taxes


It is now possible to move beyond the study of tax incidence to a consideration
of the factors that determine optimal rates of commodity taxation in imperfectly
competitive economies. The analysis will …rst focus on tax reform in a two-good
and labour economy in order to highlight the importance of the tax incidence
results. This will then be extended to a construction of optimal tax rules in the
general equilibrium economy detailed at the start of this chapter.

An illustration
To begin the analysis of tax design, consider the following simple economy
taken from Myles (1987) in which the tax analysis consists of characterising
the welfare-improving tax reform starting from an initial position with no com-
modity taxation. The economy has a single consumer and a zero revenue re-
quirement so the taxes are used merely to correct for the distortion introduced
by the imperfect competition. There are two consumption goods, each pro-
duced using labour alone. Good 1 is produced with constant returns to scale by
a competitive industry. It has post-tax price q1 = p 1 + t1 . The second good is
produced by an imperfectly competitive industry that faces inverse demand
0 1
Xm2
j
q2 = Á2 @ x2 ; q1 A : (11.37)
j= 1

It is assumed that the preferences of society can be represented by an indirect


utility function
V = V (p 0 ; q1 ; q2 ) ; (11.38)
352 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

where p0 is the price of labour. Pro…ts are assumed to be taxed at a rate of


100% and the revenue used to purchase labour.
Rather than repeat the tax incidence analysis, the direct and induced e¤ects
of taxation are understood to have been constructed as above. They are then
denoted
dq2
h1 ´ ; (11.39)
dt1
and
dq2
h2 ´ : (11.40)
dt2
The expression of these e¤ects at a general level has the advantage that it is
unnecessary to specify the particular model of imperfect competition in order
to derive results. A speci…c formulation is only needed when the results require
evaluation.
The tax reform problem now involves …nding a pair of tax changes dt1, dt2
that raise welfare whilst collecting zero revenue. If the initial position is taken
to be one with zero commodity taxes, the problem can be phrased succinctly
as …nding dt1 , dt2 , from an initial position with t1 = t2 = 0 such that dV > 0,
dR = 0, where tax revenue, R, is de…ned by

R = t1 X1 + t2 X2 : (11.41)

This framework ensures that one of the taxes will be negative, the other positive
and the aim is to provide a simple characterisation of the determination of the
relative rates. It should be noted that if both industries were competitive the
solution would be dt1 = dt2 = 0 so that non-zero tax rates emerge due to the
distortion caused by the imperfect competition.
From di¤erentiating the indirect utility function, it follows that the e¤ect of
the tax change upon welfare is

@V @q1 @V @q2 @V @q2


dV = dt1 + dt1 + dt2 : (11.42)
@q1 @t1 @q2 @tq1 @q2 @t2

Since q1 = p 1 + t1 , (11.19) implies @q


@t1 = 1. Using this fact and the de…nition of
1

the tax incidence terms h 1 and h2


¸ ¸
@V @V @V
dV = + h 1 dt1 + h2 dt2 : (11.43)
@q1 @q2 @q2

From the revenue constraint

dR = 0 = X1 dt1 + X2 dt2 ; (11.44)

where the fact that t1 = t2 = 0 initially has been used. Solving (11.44) for dt1

X2
dt1 = ¡ dt2 : (11.45)
X1
11.4. COMMODITY TAXATION 353

Substituting (11.45) into the welfare expression determines the welfare change
as dependent upon dt2 alone
¸
@V X2 @V X2 @V
dV = h2 ¡ ¡ h 1 dt2 : (11.46)
@q2 X1 @q1 X1 @q2

Finally, using Roy’s identity


¸
X2
dV = ¡®X2 h 2 + ®X2 + ®X2 h 1 dt2 : (11.47)
X1

It then follows that if


X1 [1 ¡ h 2 ] + X2 h 1 < 0; (11.48)
then dt2 < 0. From (11.48), the output of the imperfectly competitive industry
should be subsidised and the competitive industry taxed when h 2 is large, so
that overshifting is occurring, and h 1 is negative. These are, of course, su¢cient
conditions. In general, the greater the degree of tax shifting the more likely is
subsidisation. The explanation for this result is that if …rms overshift taxes, they
will also do the same for any subsidy. Hence a negative dt2 will be re‡ected by an
even greater reduction in price. If h1 is also negative, the tax on the competitive
industry secures a further reduction in the price of good 2.
The conclusion of this analysis is that the rate of tax shifting is important
in the determination of relative rates of taxation. Although the economy is
simpli…ed by abstracting away from pro…t e¤ects, it does demonstrate that
with imperfect competition commodity taxation can be motivated on e¢ciency
grounds alone.

Optimal taxes
The insights of the example are now employed to provide a characterisation
of optimal commodity taxes when there is also a positive revenue requirement.
This analysis is therefore a development of the commodity tax theory of Chap-
ter 4 to incorporate imperfect competition. The economy to be used is based
on Myles (1989a) and involves introducing commodity taxes into the general
equilibrium economy described at the start of this chapter. To simplify no-
tation, only a single-consumer tax rule will be constructed. The extension to
many-consumers is straightforward.
Treating labour as an untaxed numeraire with a wage rate p0 , the post-tax
price of good i from the competitive sector when the commodity tax is set at ti
is given by
qi = ci p 0 + ti; i = 1; :::; K: (11.49)
Pro…ts remain zero for all …rms in the competitive sector.
Introducing taxes into the de…nition of pro…t for the imperfectly competitive
…rms, each …rm in industry i chooses its output level to maximise
³ ´
j j j j
¼ i = [Ái (q0 ; :::; qi¡1 ; Xi; qi+1 ; :::; qn ; ¼) ¡ ti ] xi ¡ Ci x i ; (11.50)
354 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

where inverse demand, Ái (¢), is now dependent on post-tax prices. Simultane-


ously solving the …rst-order condition that results from maximising (11.50) and
the pro…t identities for the m i …rms comprising industry i, the output and pro…t
of …rm j in industry i can be expressed by the following two equations:
0 1
n mi0
j j
X X j 0
¼ i = ° i @q0 ; :::; qi¡1 ; ti; qi+1 ; :::; qn ; ¼ i0 A ; (11.51)
i 0=K +1; i0 6=i j 0 =1
0 1
n m i0
X X 0
x ji = ¾ ji @q0 ; :::; qi¡1 ; ti; qi+1 ; :::; qn ; ¼ ji0 A : (11.52)
i 0=K +1; i0 6=i j 0 =1

It should be noted that the arguments of (11.51) and (11.52) are the prices
and pro…ts of other industries and the tax rate on industry i. Aggregating
output and using the inverse demand function determines an equilibrium price
on market i
0 1
n m i0
X X 0
qi = f i @q0 ; :::; qi¡1 ; ti; qi+1 ; :::; qn ; ¼ j0 A : (11.53) i
i 0=K +1; i0 6=i j 0 =1

j
The derivatives of f i and ° i are precisely the tax incidence terms calculated
in the previous section for which it was assumed that all other variables are
constant.
The general equilibrium of the economy with taxation is then the simulta-
neous solution to
qi = ci p0 + ti ; i = 1; :::; K; (11.54)
0 1
n m 0
X X i
j0
qi = f i @q0 ; :::; qi¡1 ; ti; qi+1 ; :::; qn ; ¼ i0 A ; i = K + 1; :::; n;
i 0=K +1; i0 6=i j 0 =1
(11.55)
and
0 1
n mi0
X X 0
¼ ji = °ji @ q0 ; :::; qi¡1 ; ti; qi+1 ; :::; qn ; ¼ ji0 A ; i = K+1; :::; n; j = 1; :::; m i:
i 0= K+1;i 06=i j 0 =1
(11.56)
Solving equations (11.55) and (11.56) simultaneously for all imperfectly com-
petitive goods prices and …rms’ pro…ts determines the equilibrium level of prices
and pro…ts in the imperfectly competitive industries as functions of the tax rates
and the competitive prices
qK+1 = © K+1 (q0 ; :::; qK ; tK +1 ; :::; tn ) ;
..
.
qn = © n (q0 ; :::; qK ; tK+ 1 ; :::; tn ) ;
(11.57)
¼ 1K +1 = -1;K +1 (q0 ; :::; qK ; tK+1 ; :::; tn ) ;
..
.
¼m
n
n
= - 1;K +1 (q0 ; :::; qK ; tK +1 ; :::; tn ) :
11.4. COMMODITY TAXATION 355

These equations can be used to determine the e¤ects of changes in the govern-
ment control variables.
Before proceeding to a derivation of the optimal tax rules, it is helpful to
understand the relation between equations (11.57) and (11.51)-(11.53). To do
this it is necessary to realise that the derivatives of (11.57) capture the e¤ect
of the tax changes taking into account general equilibrium adjustment of all
other prices and pro…ts whilst those of (11.51)-(11.53) capture only the partial
equilibrium e¤ects holding other prices and pro…ts constant.
The choice of optimal commodity taxes are the solution the to maximisation
" n
#
X
max L ´ V (q0 ; :::; qn ; ¼) + ¸ t i Xi ¡ R ; (11.58)
ft1;::: ;tng
i=1

subject to
qi = pi + ti; i = 1; :::; K; (11.59)

qK+1 = © i (q0 ; :::; qK ; tK +1 ; :::; tn ) ; i = K + 1; :::; n; (11.60)

and
j
¼ i = - j; i (q0 ; :::; qK ; tK +1 ; :::; tn ) ; i = K + 1; :::; n; j = 1; :::; mi : (11.61)

From this system, di¤erentiation with respect to the tax rate of a typical
good, k, from the competitive sector provides the …rst-order condition

Xn n mi
@V @V s @V X X
+ ©k + -j;
k
s
@qk @qs @¼
s= K+1 s=K+ 1 j= 1
2 3
n
X @Xi X X n n n n mi
@Xi s X X X @Xi j;s
+ ¸ 4 Xk + ti + ti © + ti - 5 = 0:
i=1
@qk i=1 s=K+1
@qs k i=1 s= K+1 j=1 @¼ k

In (11.62) the subscripts on ©s and - j;s denote the argument with respect to
which the function is di¤erentiated.
This …rst-order condition is distinguished from its equivalent for the compet-
itive model, (4.7), by the inclusion of the e¤ects of the induced price and pro…t
changes, given respectively by the terms © sk , and - j;s
k . Using Roy’s identity and
the Slutsky equation, (11.62) can be written

n ¸
X 1
tiS ki = ¡µXk + ¡k ; k = 1; :::; K; (11.62)
¸
i=1

where
n
® X @Xi
µ=1¡ ¡ ti ; (11.63)
¸ i=1 @¼
356 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

and
n
X n
X ms
X n
X n
X @Xi s
¡k = ® Xs© sk ¡ ® - j;s
k +¸ ti ©
s=K +1 s=K+1 j=1 i=1 s=K+ 1
@qs k
n
X n
X mi
X @Xi j;s
+¸ ti - : (11.64)
i=1 s=K +1 j=1
@¼ k
£ ¤
If the term ¸1 ¡k were not included, (11.65) would be identical to the standard
Ramsey rule so this additional term can be interpreted as the modi…cation
required to incorporate the imperfect competition. As can be seen from its
de…nition, ¡k is determined by the induced price and pro…t e¤ects which would
not be present in a competitive model. Retaining the standard interpretation
of the Ramsey rule given in Chapter 4, an analysis of the constituents of ¡k
shows that the reduction in compensated demand for good k is smaller when a
tax on this good increases the prices of imperfectly competitive goods (© sk > 0),
reduces pro…ts (- j;s
k < 0) and the induced tax changes lower tax revenue.
Repeating the derivation for a typical good k from the imperfectly compet-
itive sector gives the …rst-order condition for the choice of tax rate

n
X n
X mi
X
@V k @V s @V j;s
© + © + -k
@qk k @qs k @¼ s=K +1 j=1
s=K +1;s6=k
2 3
n
X n
X n n mi
@Xi s X X X @Xi j; s5
+ ¸ 4 Xk + ti © + ti - = 0:
@qs k @¼ k
i=1 s=K +1 i= 1 s=K +1 j=1

After employing Roy’s identity and the Slutsky equation, (11.66) becomes
n
X ¸
1
tiS ki = ¡µ k Xk + ¡k ; k = K + 1; :::; n; (11.65)
¸
i=1

where
n
1 ® X @Xi
µk = k
¡ ¡ ti ; (11.66)
©k ¸ @¼
i=1

and
" Pn Pn Pms j;s #
k 1 ® s=K+ 1 Xs© sk ¡ ® s=K+1 j=1 -k
¡ = k Pn Pn Pn Pn Pm i @ Xi j;s :
©k +¸ i=1;i6=k s=K +1 ti @X i
©s + ¸ i=1 s=K +1 j=1
@ qs k
ti @¼ - k
£ ¤ (11.67)
In (11.67) the term 1¸ ¡k again represents a correction to the competitive Ram-
sey rule for the existence of the induced price and pro…t e¤ects. The interaction
of its constituent parts with the reduction in compensated demand can be bro-
ken down precisely as for (11.65). The distinction between (11.65) and (11.69)
is that for the latter µk is dependent upon the good k under good consideration
11.5. AD VALOREM AND SPECIFIC TAXES 357

due to the appearance of the tax-shifting term in (11.69). Since µ k is inversely


related to ©kk , the greater the degree of overshifting the smaller will be the re-
duction in compensated demand. This result is the natural generalisation of
that derived for the two-good example.
To summarise this discussion, for a good produced by a competitive industry
the standard Ramsey tax rule is adjusted by the incorporation of an additional
term that captures the induced e¤ects of the tax on that good. For goods from
imperfectly competitive industries, the tax rule incorporated the correction term
for the induced e¤ects and the reduction in compensated demand was inversely
related to the degree of tax shifting. The tax incidence results in (11.28), (11.34)
and (11.35) capture the fact that the direct and induced e¤ects are dependent
upon industrial conduct via the value of the conjecture, ¸. Consequently the
tax rules (11.63) and (11.67) show that industrial conduct is as important as
tastes in determining relative rates of taxation.

11.5 Ad valorem and speci…c taxes


In the competitive model there is no distinction between the e¤ects of speci…c
taxes, which are an addition to the unit costs of production, and ad valorem
taxes, which represent a proportional reduction in the received price. That
is, for a given increase in consumer price, the two forms of taxation will raise
an identical level of revenue. Although discussions of commodity taxation are
generally phrased in terms of speci…c taxes, as was Chapter 4, a similar analysis
can be conducted for ad valorem taxes and, as shown by Hatta (1986), the
form of the optimal tax rules are not a¤ected by the choice. When imperfect
competition is under consideration, the equivalence between the two forms of
taxation no longer applies. This distinction has been emphasised by Kay and
Keen (1983) and Delipalla and Keen (1992). Myles (1994b) shows the potential
gains that can be obtained by combining the two forms of taxation. The purpose
of this section is to review these results.

11.5.1 Tax incidence


Returning to the economy used to derive the tax incidence results above and
denoting the speci…c and ad valorem taxes levied on industry i by tsi and tºi
respectively, the pro…t of …rm j is
³ ´
¼ ji = x ji qi [1 ¡ tºi ] ¡ tsi x ji ¡ Ci xji : (11.68)

The …rst-order condition for pro…t maximisation at a symmetric equilibrium is


then
¸
º @Ái @Ci
[1 ¡ ti ] qi + ° Xi ¡ tsi = j; (11.69)
@Xi @x i
358 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

¸
where ° = mi
. Now de…ning A by

@ 2C i
@xj2
A= ¡ i
@Á i
; (11.70)
¸ [1 ¡ tºi ] @X i

the procedure used in (11.26) to (11.28) can be repeated to give the e¤ects of
the taxes upon price as

dqi 1
s = º ; (11.71)
dti [1 ¡ ti ] [1 + ° [1 + A ¡ E ]]

where Eis as de…ned in (11.31), and


@ Ci
dqi dqi @xji
+ tsi
= £ s; £ = : (11.72)
dtºi dti 1 ¡ tºi
P i j
With respect to aggregate pro…ts, ¼ = mj=1 ¼ i ; the e¤ects of the taxes are

d¼ °Xi [2 + A ¡ E]
=¡ ; (11.73)
dtsi [1 + ° [1 + A ¡ E ]]

and
d¼ d¼ °qi Xi [1 ¡ °]
º = qi s ¡ d (11.74)
dti dti "q [1 + ° [1 + A ¡ E ]]
with " dq the price elasticity of demand.
These equations indicate that the incidence e¤ects of speci…c and ad valorem
taxes are not identical. It can therefore be expected that they have di¤erent
welfare implications. The …rst step to understanding the welfare e¤ects is to
consider starting from a position with both taxes zero and then varying the
taxes whilst holding revenue at zero. Such a reform satis…es the equation

0 = qi dtºi + dtsi : (11.75)

The e¤ect of the reform on the price level is determined by


@qi º @qi
dqi = dt + s dtsi : (11.76)
@tºi i @ti

Using (11.77), this reduces to

@qi s
dqi = [£ ¡ qi] dt : (11.77)
@tsi i

Since (11.71) implies £ < qi and @q i


@ts > 0, it can be seen from (11.79) that
i
consumer price will be lower if the reform is chosen to satisfy dtsi > 0. Therefore
a positive ad valorem tax and a negative speci…c tax can generate budget-neutral
reductions in consumer price.
11.6. OPTIMAL COMBINATIONS 359

Strengthening this …nding, Delipalla and Keen (1992) prove that if the spe-
ci…c tax is restricted to be non-negative, then the solution of the problem

max V (qi) + ¼ subject to [tºi qi + tsi ] Xi = R; tsi ¸ 0; (11.78)


f tsi;tºi g

will have zero as the optimal value of tsi . The reason for this result is described
in Venables (1986): raising the ad valorem tax reduces the perceived e¤ect of
changes in output upon prices and leads, in the limit, to the competitive state
in which a change in output has no e¤ect on price. Therefore, the ad valorem
tax is lessening the consequence of the imperfect competition.

11.6 Optimal combinations


Relaxing the restriction that the speci…c tax be non-negative, the optimal com-
bination of ad valorem and speci…c taxation can eliminate the welfare loss due
to imperfect competition. In particular, the use of the pair of tax instruments
can lead to the set of prices that maximise welfare given the budget constraint.
Such prices are often termed Ramsey prices and arise as the solution to both the
problem of choosing optimal public sector prices subject to budget constraint
and from analysis of the design of commodity taxation; the latter having already
been discussed in Chapter 4. Bös (1986) clearly elucidates the major principles
of Ramsey pricing and provides a number of alternative characterisations of the
relevant optimality conditions.
To show that Ramsey prices can be generated despite the imperfect com-
petition, consider an economy that has one consumer, a government and an
industry that produces the single consumption good using labour as the only
input. The government levies taxes and uses the revenue to purchase labour.
The labour required by the …rms and government is supplied by the consumer
through a competitive market with the wage rate as numeraire. All pro…t in-
come is paid as a dividend to the consumer. The single industry is oligopolistic
with m …rms indexed by j = 1; :::; m. The inverse demand function facing the
industry is given by p = p(X), with …rst derivative p X < 0. Each …rm has
the cost function C = C (xj ) where F ´ C (0) ¸ 0 and Cx > 0. The common
dX
conjecture of the …rms on the value of dx i
is denoted by ¸, with 0 < ¸ m. If
government receives all pro…ts or production is under state control, the Ramsey
price,p ¤ , is the solution to
m
X
max V (p; I) sub ject to R + C (xj ) = pX (p) ; I = 0; (11.79)
fpg
j=1

so that it maximises welfare given the budget constraint and the restriction that
lump-sum income be zero. In the single sector economy, the solution to (11.81)
will also satisfy the budget constraint
¡ ¢
p¤ X (p ¤ ) = R + mC m ¡1 X (p¤ ) ; (11.80)
360 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

where the assumption of symmetry between …rms has been imposed. The Ram-
sey price p ¤ is optimal given that the existing number of …rms is maintained;
changes in the number of …rms are not considered.
The …rst-order condition for pro…t maximisation of a typical oligopolistic
…rm is
[1 ¡ tº ] p ¡ C x ¡ ts + [1 ¡ tº ] °pX X = 0; (11.81)
¸
where ° = m . Since the symmetry implies that x j = x = X m
, all j = 1; :::; m,
(11.83) can be solved to express the equilibrium level of output as a function of
the tax rates. This solution is denoted

X = » (tº ; ts ) : (11.82)

Substituting (11.84) into the inverse demand function then determines the equi-
librium price conditional on the taxes. Hence

p = p (» (tº ; ts )) = ½ (tº ; ts ) : (11.83)

Finally, using (11.83) and the pro…t identity determines the equilibrium pro…t
level as
¼ j = ¼ = & (tº ; ts ) ; all j = 1; :::; m: (11.84)
Employing (11.84) - (11.86), a combination of ad valorem and speci…c tax-
ation can generate Ramsey pricing if it is possible to …nd a pair such that the
following three conditions are satis…ed simultaneously

(i)½ (tº¤ ; ts¤ ) = p ¤ ; (ii)& (tº¤ ; ts¤ ) = 0; (iii) [tº¤ ½ (tº¤ ; ts¤ ) + ts¤ ] » (tº¤ ; ts¤ ) = R:
h (11.85)
i
»
If (11.87i) and (11.87iii) are satis…ed, then ¼ = [[1 ¡ tº ] p ¡ ts ] X
m
¡C = ½ ¡ R» m ¡
h i
C , using (11.87iii), ½ ¡ R 1
» m [½» ¡ R ¡ mC] = 0 using (11.87i) and (11.81).
Therefore the satisfaction of (11.87i) and (11.87iii) implies (11.87ii) and the op-
timal tax scheme need solve only two of the three equations. In the analysis
below, the focus is placed upon (11.87i) and (11.87iii).
To give the problem content, it is assumed that the revenue requirement is
su¢ciently small that it can be achieved by use of either of the tax instruments
alone. This ensures that the use of both instruments occurs through choice.
De…ning à 1 = ftº ; ts : ½ (tº ; ts ) = p ¤ g and à 2 = ftº ; ts : [tº ½ (tº ; ts ) + ts ] » (tº ; ts) = Rg,
the …rst lemma relates the relative positions of these curves to the pro…t levels
of the …rms.
s
¡ º s ¢ 52 If, ¡ º fors ¢a given value of t , denoted
º
Lemma tbº , t and tes are de…ned
º
by
b C x +ts
t ; t 2 Ã 1, b t ; et 2 Ã 2 , and for all pairs ft ; t g that solve (11.87i), t 1¡
º s
tº <
s ¡ º s¢ s ¡ º s¢
¡ [1 ¡ °] p X X, then t < e s
t if & bt ; e s
t > 0, and t > et if & b t ;et < 0.
¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ º s ¢¢ ¡ º s ¢ ¡ ¡ º s ¢¢
Proof. Using (11.81), de…ne G tbº ; ts ´ p » b
t ;t » b t ; t ¡R¡mC m ¡1 » b t ;t .
¡ º s¢
b @G @»
The derivative of G t ; t is given by @ts = [p ¡ C x + Xp X ] @ts . Given that
11.6. OPTIMAL COMBINATIONS 361

@» @G
@t s < 0, @ts is positive if p ¡ Cx + Xp X < 0. From (11.82) p ¡ Cx + Xp X =
tº C x +ts
1¡tº ¡ °] pX X which is negative by assumption.
+ [1
¡ º s¢ ¡ º s¢
> 0 it is clear that if G b
Since @@tGs t ; t evaluated at b t ;e
t is positive then
¡ º s¢ s
the solution to G bt ; t = 0 is reached by reducing t and hence t < e
s
ts: The
¡ º s¢ ¡ º s¢ £º ¤
converse holds if G bt ; t is negative at b t ;e
t . Now note that if b t p+e ts X =
º s º s
R, then G = pX ¡ R ¡ ¡ mC ¢= pX ¡ mC ¡ X [t ¡p º+ ts ¢] = [[1 ¡ t ] p ¡¡ºt ]sX
¢ ¡ mC
= m¼. Therefore G t ; t > 0 if m¼ = m& t ; t > 0 and G t ; e
bº es b e b t < 0 if
¡ º s¢
m¼ = m& b t ; et < 0.
º
C x +ts
The assumption that t 1¡ tº
< ¡ [1 ¡ °] pX X is clearly very weak. The
right-hand side is always positive but, since only values of tº satisfying tº 1
need be considered and ts < ¡Cx for most points in à 1, the left-hand side is
generally negative.
The next result determines the change in pro…t on the à 1 curve as tº in-
creases.

Lemma 53 Pro…t is monotonically decreasing along the à 1 curve as tº in-


creases.

Proof. The lemma is directly proved by total di¤erentiation along and à 1 .


See Myles (1995a).
The implication of Lemma 11.1 is that the à 1 curve lies outside the à 2
curve whenever the …rms earn positive pro…ts on the à 2 curve. Hence if there
are points on the à 2 curve such that the …rms earn negative pro…ts then the
continuity implies that the two curves must cross at some point prior to this.
From this observation follows Theorem 11.1.

Theorem 54 If there exist tºn ; tsn such that tsn < 1, [tºn ½ (tºn ; tsn )] » (tºn ; tsn ) = R
and & (tºn ; tsn ) < 0, then there exists a unique pair (tº¤ ; ts¤ ) with tº¤ < 1 that
generates Ramsey pricing.

Proof. The statements in the proposition imply, by Lemma 11.1, that à 1


must lie to the right of à 2 at tºn ; tsn . Therefore,¡since¢ assumption 1 implies ¼ ¸ 0
when evaluated at bts , where b ts is de…ned by b ts; 0 2 Ã 2 , there must be some
point at which à 1 and à 2 cross and at this point tº < 1. The crossing point
therefore determines the taxes that generate Ramsey pricing. The crossing point
is also unique since if the curves intersected more than once Lemma 11.2 would
be violated.
Theorem 11.1 has demonstrated that Ramsey pricing can be generated when
the …rms become unpro…table at some combinations of taxes that satisfy the
revenue requirement. This provides the …rst possible form of optimal tax policy.
The economic reasoning lying behind this result is that the use of an ad valorem
tax reduces the perceived market power of the imperfectly competitive …rms by
lowering marginal revenue whilst the speci…c tax can be targeted as a subsidy
towards covering …xed costs.
For the case of constant marginal cost, the positivity of F is a necessary
condition that pro…t become negative at some point on the à 2 curve. This can
362 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

be seen by solving (11.87i) to (11.87iii). Doing this shows that the levels of tº
and ts are characterised implicitly by
" ¡ ¢ #
º Fm s C m¡ 1X F
[1 ¡ t ] = ¡ ; t = ¡m + ; (11.86)
°p X X 2 X °pX X 2

where X and pX are evaluated at the Ramsey price and quantity. From (11.88),
tº can only be less than 1 when F is positive.
The optimal policy when there is no pair of tax rates on the à 2 curve that
lead to negative pro…ts can be found by applying the following lemma.
Lemma 55 Tax revenue is monotonically increasing along the à 1 curve as tº
increases.
Proof. See Myles (1995a).

Theorem 56 If there does not exist tºn ; tsn such that tsn < 1, [tºn ½ (tºn ; tsn )] » (tºn ; tsn ) =
R and & (tºn ; tsn ) < 0, then the optimal policy is to let tº ! 1 with ts determined
by the à 2 curve. If lim ¼ = 0 as tº ! 1 along à 2 then Ramsey pricing is
generated in the limit.

Proof. Lemma 11.1 shows tax revenue is less on à 1 than à 2 for given tº :
From Lemma 11.3, the two curves must then converge as tº increases. Hence
the optimal policy is always to let tº tend to 1 to move as close to à 1 as possible
since this takes the price closer to the Ramsey price. The second part of the
theorem follows from Lemma 11.1.
It is therefore possible for the combination of speci…c and ad valorem taxa-
tion to support Ramsey pricing in imperfectly competitive economies and such
an optimal tax system has the e¤ect of eliminating the welfare loss due to
monopoly power. The use of both tax instruments is able to achieve rather
more than the use of a single instrument.

11.7 Production e¢ciency and the taxation of


labour
The important Diamond-Mirrlees production e¢ciency lemma was discussed in
Chapter 4. Since this implied that all producers should face the same shadow
prices, there was no need for taxes upon intermediate goods in an optimal tax
structure. The result was based on several assumptions, amongst them being
those of competition and of constant returns to scale. Although the latter can
be relaxed without harming the essence of the conclusion, the former cannot.
This purpose of this section is investigate why production e¢ciency fails when
there is imperfect competition and to consider the consequences for the taxation
of intermediate goods. It was also assumed in Chapter 4 that labour could act
as an untaxed numeraire. Although valid in a competitive economy, the non-
taxation of labour is an additional restriction with imperfect competition. The
consequences of relaxing this are also explored.
11.7. PRODUCTION EFFICIENCY AND THE TAXATION OF LABOUR363

11.7.1 Production e¢ciency


If taxes upon intermediate goods are introduced these will a¤ect the vector of
input prices faced by producers. With competition, a change in input costs is
re‡ected in …nal prices only to the extent to which it a¤ects marginal cost. In
contrast, this simple relationship is lost when imperfect competition is intro-
duced. A change in input costs operates through the cost function and then
through the optimisation of the …rm. As with commodity taxation, a change
in production costs may be overshifted or undershifted in …nal price. By ma-
nipulating input prices through taxation, tax design can exploit these shifting
e¤ects, and the pro…t e¤ects, in order to gain welfare increases.
These issues have been analysed by Myles (1989b) and Konishi (1990). Myles
(1989b) considers economies with …xed numbers of …rms whereas Konishi (1990)
analyses free-entry Cournot oligopoly in which a number of competitive indus-
tries produced goods that were used as inputs by the oligopoly and as …nal
consumption goods. Both focus only upon the e¢ciency aspects of taxation
and …nd that, in general, welfare can be raised by the taxation of intermedi-
ate goods. The relative rates of tax between di¤erent industries are dependent
upon returns to scale. Konishi shows that taxation should encourage the use of
intermediate goods that are demanded elastically and reduce the use of those
with inelastic demand. This has been termed the production side Ramsey rule.
To demonstrate the nature of these results, consider an economy in which a
competitive industry’s entire output is sold as an intermediate good to a monop-
olist whose output constitutes the economy’s …nal good. Attention is focused
upon e¢ciency arguments by assuming the existence of a single consumer who
consumes the …nal goods, receives the monopolies’ pro…ts and supplies labour.
Each …rm in the competitive industry is assumed to have a …xed coe¢cient
production function and units are normalised so that each unit of output re-
quires one unit of labour. Writing p 0 for the wage rate, the post-tax price of
the competitive industry’s good, which is labelled 1, is

q1 = p 0 + & 1 ; (11.87)

where & 1 is the tax levied upon the intermediate good. Directly from (11.89)
@q1
= 1: (11.88)
@&1
The monopoly produces with costs given by

C (q1 ; p 0 ; X2 ) + X2 t2 ; (11.89)

where X2 is the …rm’s output level and t2 the level of commodity tax. The
monopolist chooses its price, q2 , to maximise pro…t, ¼, where

¼ = [q2 ¡ t2 ] X2 (q2 ; p0 ; ¼) ¡ C (q1 ; p 0 ; X2 ) ; (11.90)

X2 (¢) being the demand function. The presence of ¼ on both sides of (11.92)
captures the income e¤ects that occur in a general equilibrium model. Assuming
364 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

the condition in (11.7) is satis…ed, the pro…t maximising choice is characterised


by ¸
@C @X2
X2 + q2 ¡ t 2 ¡ = 0; (11.91)
@X2 @q2
and the second-order condition is
¸ ¸2 2
@X2 @C @ 2 X2 @X2 @ C
2 + q2 ¡ t 2 ¡ 2
¡ < 0: (11.92)
@q2 @X2 @q2 @q2 @X22

In addition, the equilibrium must also satisfy the pro…t identity (11.92).
Treating (11.92) and (11.93) as a two-equation system, they can be di¤er-
entiated and solved to give the tax incidence terms
@C

=¡ h @q1 i; (11.93)
@& 1 1¡ @X 2
q2 ¡ t 2 ¡ @C
@¼ @X 2

@¼ X
=¡ h 2 i; (11.94)
@t2 1¡ @X 2
q2 ¡ t2 ¡ @C
@¼ @X 2

@X 2 @ 2C
@q2 @q 2 @ q 1@X 2
= ¡ h i h i2
@& 1 @ 2X 2
2 @X 2
@q 2
+ q2 ¡ t2 ¡ @C
@X 2
¡ @X
@ q22
2
@q 2
@ 2C
@X 22
h 2
h i i
@C @X 2 @ X2 @C @X 2 @X 2 @ 2 C
@q 1 @¼ + @¼ @q 2 q 2 ¡ t 2 ¡ @X 2 ¡ @¼ @q 2 @X2 2
+h h ii h i 2 h i2(11.95)¸;
@X 2 @C @ X2 @C @ X2 @X 2 @ 2C
1¡ @¼
q2 ¡ t2 ¡ @X 2
2 @q 2
+ q 2 ¡ t2 ¡ @ X2 @q 2 ¡ @q 2 @X 2
2 2

and
@X 2
@q2 @q 2
= ¡ h i h i2
@t2 @ 2X 2 @ 2C
2 @X 2
@q 2
+ q 2 ¡ t2 ¡ @C
@X 2 2
@ q2
¡ @X 2
@q 2 @X 22
h h i i
@ 2X 2 2
X2 @¼ + @¼ @q2 q2 ¡ t2 ¡ @X 2 ¡ @X
@ X2 @C 2 @X 2 @ C
@ ¼ @q 2 @ X22
+h h ii h i h i2(11.96)
¸:
@ 2 X2 @ 2C
1 ¡ @X@¼
2
q 2 ¡ t 2 ¡ @C
@X 2
2 @ X2
@q 2
+ q 2 ¡ t2 ¡ @C
@ X2 @ q2
¡ @X 2
@q 2 @X 2
2 2

The …rst term of (11.98) is the direct e¤ect of the change in tax upon price
2
and, as shown above, it may be greater than 1. Assuming @@¼@q X2
2
> 0, the second
term will certainly be negative if marginal cost decreases with output. This
negativity captures the fact that the tax lowers pro…ts, which then leads to a
reduction in demand. The same interpretation applies to (11.97).
To demonstrate that the intermediate good should be taxed, it is worth …rst
considering the tax reform problem of …nding the direction of change in tax-
ation, from an initial position with both taxes zero, that raise welfare whilst
11.7. PRODUCTION EFFICIENCY AND THE TAXATION OF LABOUR365

maintaining a balanced budget. Formally stated, starting from an initial posi-


tion with & 1 = t2 = 0, the sign of d& 1 , dt2 such that dV > 0 and dR = 0 will
be determined where V = V (p 0 ; q2 ; ¼ ) is the single consumer’s indirect utility
function, which acts as the measure of social welfare, and R = & 1 X1 + t2X2 .
To characterise the solution, …rst di¤erentiate the utility function and the
revenue constraint to give
¸ ¸
@V @q2 @V @¼ @V @q2 @V @¼
dV = + d& 1 + + dt2 ; (11.97)
@q2 @& 1 @¼ @& 1 @q2 @t2 @¼ @t2

and
dR = X1 d&1 + X2 dt2 = 0: (11.98)
@C
From Shephard’s lemma, X1 = @q 1
so (11.100) gives

@C
dt2 = ¡ @q1 d&1 : (11.99)
X2
Substituting (11.101) and (11.95) - (11.98) into (11.99)
@C @X2
@X 2 @ 2C @ q1 @ q2
@V @q 2 @q 1@X 2 ¡ X2
dV = h i h i2 d&1 : (11.100)
@q2
2 @X 2
@q 2 + q2 ¡ t 2 ¡ @C
@X 2
@ 2X 2
@q 22
¡ @X 2
@q 2
@2 C
@X 2
2

Using (11.102), the direction of reform can be summarised in Theorem 11.3.


2
Theorem 57 d& 1 6= 0 if X2 @q@1@CX2 ¡ @C
@q 1 6= 0. In particular, d& 1 > 0 if
2 2
X2 @q@1@CX2 ¡ @C
@q 1
< 0 and d&1 < 0 if X2 @q@1@CX2 ¡ @q
@C
1
> 0.

@V @ X2
Proof. Since @q 2
; @ q2 and the denominator of the bracketed term in (11.102)
are negative, the resultnfollows from inspection.
o n o
2
@ 2C
Assuming that sgn. X2 @q@1@CX2 ¡ @q @C
1
= sgn. X 2 @p0 @X2
¡ @C
@p 0
, so the pro-
duction function is well-behaved, Theorem 11.3 can be stated in terms of returns
to scale.

Theorem 58 If the monopolist produces with constant returns to scale, d&1 = 0.


Increasing returns imply d& 1 > 0 and decreasing returns that d& 1 < 0.

Proof. If the monopolist produces with constant returns to scale, C (q2 ; p0 ; X2 ) =


2
c (q2 ; p 0 ) X2 . From this, X2 @q@1@XC
2
@C
¡ @q 1
= 0 and hence d& 1 = 0. The rest follows
2
from noting that increasing returns imply X2 @q@1@CX2 ¡ @C
@ q1 < 0 and decreasing
2
returns that X2 @q@1@X
¡ C
2
> 0. @C
@q 1
Theorem 11.3 demonstrates clearly that with imperfect competition there
will typically be a case for the taxation of intermediate goods providing the
monopolist does not produce with constant returns to scale. The basis for these
taxes are the di¤erent rates at which the intermediate tax and the …nal tax
366 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

a¤ect the consumer price. In terms of Theorem 11.4, when the monopolist
has decreasing returns the input should be subsidised in an attempt to induce
a larger level of output by cost reductions. Although the precise structure of
these statements is due to the simple model used, the same features would also
be of importance in any larger model.
As discussed in Chapter 4, the analysis of perfect competition with decreas-
ing returns has demonstrated that production e¢ciency is desirable when pro…ts
are correctly taxed. This can be investigated for imperfect competition by in-
troducing a pro…ts tax into the analysis above. Writing ´ (< 1) for the rate of
pro…t taxation, the demand function now becomes

X2 = X2 (q2 ; p 0 ; [1 ¡ ´] ¼) : (11.101)

Including the revenue from the pro…ts tax, the new revenue constraint is

´¼ + & 1X1 + t2 X2 = 0; (11.102)

and, for a given value of ´, the di¤erential of this is


¸ ¸
@¼ @¼
´ + X2 dt2 + ´ + X1 d&1 = 0: (11.103)
@t2 @& 1

Repeating the tax incidence analysis, di¤erentiating the utility function and
substituting from (11.105) again generates (11.102). Consequently, the char-
acterisation of policy given in Theorem 11.3 is still valid independently of the
value of the pro…t tax. This is in contrast to the Dasgupta and Stiglitz (1972)
result for competitive economies.
These results demonstrate clearly that non-taxation of intermediate goods
is not theoretically justi…ed in economies with imperfect competition. Although
they do not match the generality of the competitive economy of Diamond and
Mirrlees, they are su¢ciently rich in possibilities to highlight the major factors.
Furthermore, the conclusion that intermediate goods should be taxed is merely
strengthened by increasing the complexity of the economies.

11.7.2 Taxation of labour


Turning now to the taxation of labour, it should …rst be noted that in analyses
of commodity taxation labour is treated as an untaxed numeraire in economies
with constant returns and as taxed at a uniform rate when there are decreasing
returns. The arguments of Munk (1980) justify these choices of normalisation
in competitive economies and their optimality is assured via the Production
E¢ciency lemma. With imperfect competition however, treating labour as an
untaxed numeraire places an additional restriction upon the tax system.
The taxation of labour in the presence of imperfect competition is addressed
in Myles (1995). As in the case of the taxation of intermediate goods, it is the
nonlinear relation of …nal price to labour cost that is the key factor. Providing
the response of …nal price to the wage rate di¤ers across industries, then it will
11.8. OTHER FORMS OF REGULATION 367

be justi…able on welfare grounds to use a labour tax that is di¤erentiated across


industries. By subsidising labour in industries where price is very responsive
to labour cost and taxing those were it is not, a welfare-improving reduction in
the price level can be achieved. The rate of response of price to tax is again
determined by demand conditions, summarised by Seade’s E, and returns to
scale in the production process. The determinants of relative tax rates are the
returns to scale of each industry and industrial conduct within the industry.
Optimal taxes relate the reduction in supply from each industry due to the tax
system to the returns to scale of the industry, the e¤ect of the tax upon price
and the interaction of the industry with the economy.

11.8 Other forms of regulation


The focus of this chapter has been upon the e¤ects of commodity taxation in
imperfectly economies and the optimisation of such taxes. In practice, a number
of forms of regulation have been employed to reduce the welfare loss arising
from the existence of imperfect competition. The most important distinction
between these is whether the …rm is taken into public ownership or remains in
the private sector. The forms of regulation used in these cases may di¤er but
the aim remains the same: to encourage the …rm to act in a socially e¢cient
manner.
When faced with imperfect competition, the most obvious policy response
would be the encouragement of competition. This could be done by removing
any barriers to entry and by providing initial inducements for competitors to
become active. The limits to the operation of this policy are confronted when
natural monopoly arises. The essence of natural monopoly is that the production
technology has the property that output can always be produced more cheaply
by one …rm than it can by two or more. This property, termed sub-additivity
by Baumol et al. (1977), is a necessary condition for natural monopoly to arise.
Stated formally, a sub-additive cost function satis…es

k
X k
X
C (y) < C (y k ) ; y = y k ; k ¸ 2: (11.104)
j= 1 j=1

With natural monopoly, the market will not sustain more than one …rm nor can
it be socially optimal to have more than one …rm otherwise costs will not be
minimised. It is therefore necessary to devise some policy other than introducing
competition.
The two policy options that have been most widely employed are public
ownership and private ownership with a regulatory body controlling behaviour.
The most signi…cant di¤erence between these is that under public control the
government is as informed as the …rm about demand and cost conditions. It
can therefore determine the behaviour of the …rm using the best available in-
formation. Although this information may not be complete, so policy can only
maximise the objective function in an expected sense, the best that is possible
368 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION

will be achieved. In contrast, when the …rm is in private ownership, the govern-
ment, via the regulatory body, may well be far less informed about information
pertinent to the operating conditions of the …rm than the …rm itself. Informa-
tion about cost structures and market conditions are likely to remain private
and the …rm may have strategic reasons for not revealing this accurately.
When the …rm is run under public ownership, the level of price should be
chosen to maximise social welfare sub ject to the budget constraint placed upon
the …rm. The …rm may be required to break-even or to generate income above
its cost. Alternatively, it may be allowed to run a de…cit which is …nanced from
other tax revenues. In any case, as already noted in Chapter 4, the structure
of the decision problem for the government mirrors that in determining optimal
commodity taxes and will generate the Ramsey price for the …rm.
Assume all other markets in the economy are competitive. The Ramsey
price for public …rm subject to a break-even constraint will then be equal to
marginal cost if this satis…es the constraint. If losses arise at marginal cost,
then the Ramsey price will be equal to average cost. The literature on public
sector pricing has extended this reasoning to situations in which marginal cost
and demand vary over time such as in the supply of electricity. Doing this leads
into the theory of peak-load pricing (see Brown and Sibley (1986) and Dreze
(1964)). When other markets are not competitive, the Ramsey prices will re‡ect
the distortions elsewhere (see Bös (1986)). The principles involved are the same
in all cases.
As an alternative to public ownership, a …rm may remain under private own-
ership but be made subject to the control of a regulatory body. This introduces
possible asymmetries in information between the …rm and the regulator. Faced
with limited information, one approach considered in the theoretical literature
is for the regulator to design an incentive mechanism that achieves a desirable
outcome. An example of such a regulatory scheme is the two-part tari¤ studied
in Baron (1989) and Lockwood (1995) in which the payment for the commod-
ity involves a …xed fee to permit consumption followed by a price per unit for
consumption, with these values being set by the regulator. Alternatively, the
regulator may impose a constraint on some observable measure of the …rm’s ac-
tivities. Adopting the framework characteristic of regulation in the US, Averch
and Johnson (1962) study the optimisation of the …rm under the constraint that
it must not exceed a given rate of return upon the capital employed. Even more
simple are the regulatory schemes in the UK which involve restricting prices to
rise at a slower rate than an index of the general price level.

11.9 Conclusions
This chapter has shown how imperfect competition leads to a failure to attain
Pareto optimality. As with all such failures, this opens a potential role for
government intervention to promote e¢ciency. Estimates of the welfare loss
due to imperfect competition have been constructed from both observed data
and from numerical simulations. These vary widely from the almost insigni…cant
11.9. CONCLUSIONS 369

to considerable proportions of attained welfare. On balance, it is likely, however,


that imperfect competition is of signi…cance.
There are numerous ways in which imperfect competition can be represented.
The subjective and ob jective demand approaches were discussed and a num-
ber of unresolved issues were highlighted. An economy incorporating quantity-
setting oligopoly using objective demand, and conjectural variations when in-
teresting, was then adopted and it was shown how this could be employed to
determine the structure of optimal commodity taxation. The tax rules derived
were direct generalisations of those for the competitive economy and their im-
plementation would require information additional to the competitive rules.
In contrast to the competitive case, speci…c and ad valorem taxation are not
equivalent with imperfect competition. In a choice between the instruments, ad
valorem taxation is more e¤ective since it has the e¤ect of reducing perceived
monopoly power. Combining the instruments can lead to further gains and, if
correctly chosen, the welfare loss due to the monopoly power can be eliminated
entirely Finally, imperfect competition was also shown to invalidate the general
argument for production e¢ciency, so that taxes on intermediate goods could
be justi…ed.
370 CHAPTER 11. IMPERFECT COMPETITION
Chapter 12

Tax Evasion

12.1 Introduction
An implicit assumption that supported the analysis of taxation in the previous
chapters was that …rms and consumers honestly report their taxable activities.
Although acceptable for providing simpli…ed insights into the underlying issues,
this assumption is patently unacceptable when confronted with reality. The
purpose of this chapter can therefore be seen as the introduction of practical
constraints upon the free choice of tax policy. Tax evasion, the intentional
failure to declare taxable economic activity, is pervasive in many economies as
the evidence given in the following section makes clear and is therefore a subject
of practical as well as theoretical interest.
After reviewing evidence on the extent of tax evasion, the chapter considers
the tax evasion decision of consumers. This decision is represented as a choice
under uncertainty and naturally employs the techniques of Chapter 7. Within
this framework, the optimal degree of auditing and of punishment is considered.
This is then extended to include decisions over labour supply, since the choice of
o ccupation can determine opportunities for evasion, and the role of public goods
and social norms. The analysis predicts the relationship between the level of
evasion, tax rates and punishments. The results of experiments that investigate
these are discussed. A more developed analysis of the optimal choice of audit
is then given. The analysis of tax evasion is then completed by consideration of
evasion by …rms.

12.2 The extent of tax evasion


The importance of developing a theoretical understanding of tax evasion can
only be assessed by estimating the actual extent of evasion. If such evasion
constitutes a signi…cant activity within the economy, then a theory of evasion is
of potential use in designing structures that minimise evasion at least cost and
ensuring that policies are optimal given that evasion occurs.

371
372 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

Due to its very nature, the measurement of tax evasion and unreported
economic activity is fraught with di¢culty and uncertainty. Tax evasion should
be distinguished from tax avoidance, which is the reorganisation of economic
activity, possibly at some cost, to lower tax payment. Tax avoidance is legal,
tax evasion is not. This illegality makes surveys prone to error if the fear of
prosecution remains and, by de…nition, tax evasion is not measured in o¢cial
statistics. The estimates reported below therefore rely on a number of methods
of inference which naturally leaves them open to error. They should be regarded
primarily as rough approximations. In addition to measurement errors, there is
also the issue of what should be included. Illegal activities, such as the supply
of drugs or smuggling generally, would not be included in measured GDP even
if they were known. It is open to debate as to whether they should be included
in measures of the hidden economy.
One of the earliest published studies of tax evasion is the analysis by Rey
(1965) of the Italian General Sales Tax. This tax is levied on all exchanges
of goods and services, with some exceptions, and in 1961 raised revenue equal
to approximately 4% of GNP. The tax had several methods of collection and
of the largest of these, which raised two thirds of revenue, Rey estimated that
evasion was equal to 52.46% of actual yield. This is clearly a signi…cant degree
of evasion.
In an article that proved the starting point for many studies, Gutmann
(1977) attempted to measure the extent of unobserved economic activity, or the
hidden economy, in the USA. Based on the observation that transactions in the
hidden economy are invariably …nanced by cash rather than cheque or credit,
Gutmann used the growth of currency in circulation relative to demand deposits
as an indirect measure of unobserved activity. This procedure resulted in an
estimate of $176 bn. for illegal GNP in 1976 which was approximately 10% of
legal, measured activity. This …gure is in accordance with that reported by the
Internal Revenue Service in 1979 which estimated unreported income in 1976
to be between $75 bn. and $100 bn. or 7% to 9% of reported income.
Feige (1979) attempted to measure the same activity as Gutmann but em-
ploying a di¤erent methodology. The method of Feige was to work from the
observation that total economic activity, including both measured and unmea-
sured sectors, is equal to the price level times transactions. An estimate of the
unmeasured sector is then provided by the ratio of the value of measured income
to that of transactions. The major di¢culty with this approach is determining
the number of transactions that actually occur. Feige achieved this by using
data on the life-span in months of bank notes in circulation relative to the num-
ber of times it is expected each note can be used. This analysis provides an
estimate of the unmeasured sector in 1976 of $369 bn., which is 22% of GNP,
and $704 bn., 33%, in 1978. Given the size of these estimates, Feige concludes
that o¢cial statistics must be very misleading.
Applying the same methodology to the UK, Feige (1981) calculates that the
unobserved sector produced a GNP of £28 bn. in 1979 which was equal to 15%
of measured GNP. This estimate must be set against the reported comments of
an ex-Chairman of the Inland Revenue that undeclared income could amount to
12.3. EVASION AS A DECISION WITH RISK 373

7.5% of GNP. An alternative approach to measurement of the UK unobserved


sector has been taken by Pissarides and Weber (1989) who employ data from the
1982 Family Expenditure Survey. By assuming that income and expenditure
are reported accurately by employees whose employer …led their income report,
an estimate of the expenditure function for these households then gives the true
relation between income and expenditure. Observing the expenditure of other
households then permits an estimate to be made of their income and, conse-
quently, their tax evasion. The …nal estimate is that the unobserved economy
is 5.5% of GDP. Finally, Feige and McGee (1983) report an estimate of 10%
for unobserved activity in Sweden and Smith (1981) presents a useful summary
table of results.
Even when the possible degrees of error are taken into account, the impres-
sion that these estimates give is that undeclared economic activity, and hence
tax evasion, is a signi…cant part of total economic activity in many western
economies. Although the methods employed are imperfect, they cannot be dis-
missed entirely. Such an observation clearly justi…es further study of the causes
and consequences of tax evasion.
To close this section, it is worth noting that implicit in many discussions
is the assumption that tax evasion reduces tax revenue. However, as shown
by Peacock and Shaw (1982), if unreported activity has a multiplier e¤ect and
would take place at a lower level if it were subject to taxation, then estimates
of revenue loss will be overstated, even to the extent that evasion may lead to
no revenue loss at all. This e¤ect is enhanced by the possibility that evasion
may encourage participation in taxed activities. As the analysis of Peacock and
Shaw is based on a simple Keynesian model, this is a point that could bear
further investigation.

12.3 Evasion as a decision with risk


The decision to evade taxation …ts naturally into the framework of choice under
risk. Since not all tax evaders are caught by the tax authorities, risk arises since
an individual who evades tax stands a chance of succeeding with the evasion, and
hence having increased wealth, or a chance of being caught and punished. As an
initial approximation, the individual can be viewed as choosing the extent of tax
to evade, subject to the probability of being caught and punished, to maximise
expected utility. The earliest formal analyses of this decision were given by
Allingham and Sandmo (1972), Srinivasan (1973) and Yitzhaki (1974). These
di¤er only in the structure of the punishments and that Srinivasan imposes
risk neutrality by assuming the individual’s objection is the maximisation of
expected income. The derivation given below will be based primarily upon
Yitzhaki. A diagrammatic presentation can be found in Cowell (1985a).
The tax-payer receives an exogeneous income M which is known to the tax-
payer but not to the tax collector. The analysis is simpli…ed by assuming that
declared income, X, is taxed at a constant rate t. If the taxpayer is caught
evading, which occurs with probability p, a …ne F > 1 is placed upon evaded
374 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

tax. The taxpayer’s aim is to choose X so as to maximise a von Neumann-


Morgernstern utility function. This decision problem can be written as

max E [U (X)] = [1 ¡ p] U (M ¡ tX) + pU (M ¡ tX ¡ F t [M ¡ X]) ; (12.1)


fXg

where E is the expectation operator and F t [M ¡ X] is the total …ne paid when
caught evading. De…ning Y = M ¡ tX and Z = M ¡ tX ¡ F t [M ¡ X], the
…rst- and second-order conditions for maximising (12.1) are

p [F ¡ 1] U 0 (Z) ¡ [1 ¡ p] U 0 (Y ) = 0; (12.2)

and h i
S ´ t [1 ¡ p] U 00 (Y ) + [F ¡ 1]2 pU 0 0 (Z) 0: (12.3)

It is assumed that U 0 > 0 and U 00 < 0.


For tax evasion to take place, the solution to (12.2) must have X < M . When
@E[U ]
(12.3) holds for all X, this will occur when the derivative @X is negative when
evaluated at X = M implying that X must be reduced to arrive at the optimum.
Calculating the derivative at X = M , tax evasion will occur whenever pF < 1.
It is assumed from this point that this condition is satis…ed.
The aim of the analysis is to determine how the level of tax evasion is a¤ected
by changes in the model’s variables. There are four such variables that are of
interest: the income level M , the tax rate t, the probability of detection p and
the …ne rate F . The computation of these e¤ects is a straightforward exercise in
comparative statics using (12.2) and (12.3). Totally di¤erentiating (12.2) with
respect to X and p and rearranging gives

dX [F ¡ 1] U 0 (Z) + U 0 (Y )
=¡ > 0; (12.4)
dp S

so that an increase in the probability of detection raises the level of income


declared and reduces evasion. This is a clearly expected result since an increase
in the likelihood of detection lowers the payo¤ from evading and makes evasion
a less attractive proposition. Repeating the procedure for a change in the …ne
rate upon evaded tax provides the expression

dX pU 0 (Z) ¡ p [F ¡ 1] U 00 (Z) t [M ¡ X]
=¡ > 0: (12.5)
dF S
As expected, an increase in the …ne leads to a reduction in the level of tax
evasion. There is therefore no ambiguity about the e¤ects of the two punishment
variables upon the level of evasion.
The next variable to consider is the tax rate upon declared income. Di¤er-
entiating (12.2) with respect to X and t gives

[S] dX+[[1 ¡ p] U 00 (Y ) X ¡ p [F ¡ 1] U 00 (Z) X ¡ p [F ¡ 1] U 00 (Z) [M ¡ X]] dt = 0:


(12.6)
12.3. EVASION AS A DECISION WITH RISK 375

The …rst-order condition (12.2) implies that p [F ¡ 1] U 0 (Z) = [1 ¡ p] U 0 (Y )


and this can be used to write the second-bracketed term in (12.6) as

[[1 ¡ p] U 00 (Y ) X ¡ p [F ¡ 1] U 00 (Z) X ¡ p [F ¡ 1] U 00 (Z) [M ¡ X]] =


¸
0 [1 ¡ p] U 00 (Y ) X p [F ¡ 1] U 00 (Z) X p [F ¡ 1] U 00 (Z) [M ¡ X]
[1 ¡ p] U (Y ) ¡ ¡ :
[1 ¡ p] U 0 (Y ) p [F ¡ 1] U 0 (Z) p [F ¡ 1] U 0 (Z)
(12.7)

U 00(I )
Using the Arrow-Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion RA (I) = ¡ U 0 (I) to
simplify (12.7), the e¤ect of the tax rate upon tax evasion is given by

dX [1 ¡ p] U 0 (Y ) [X [RA (Z) ¡ RA (Y )] + F [M ¡ X] RA (Z)]


=¡ : (12.8)
dt S
Since RA is positive, for an increase in the tax rate to increase the level of income
declared it is su¢cient that RA (Z) ¡ RA (Y ) > 0. Thus if absolute risk aver-
sion decreases as income increases, higher tax rates will lead to greater income
declarations and a reduction in evasion. This result has provoked considerable
discussion since it runs counter to the intuitive expectation that an increase in
tax rates should provide a greater incentive to evade. Such a relationship is
supported by the observation that estimates of the uno¢cial economy suggest
that it has grown in periods when the average tax burden has increased.
Di¤erentiating (12.2) with respect to X and M and repeating the substitu-
tion used in (12.7) determines the e¤ect of an increase in income upon evasion
as
dX F tRA (Z) ¡ [R A (Z) ¡ RA (Y )]
= : (12.9)
dM F tRA (Z) ¡ t [RA (Z) ¡ RA (Y )]
dX
The condition RA (Z) ¡ R A (Y ) > 0 then implies, since t < 1, that dM < 1
and hence declared income rises less fast than actual income implying that tax
evasion rises with income.
In assessing the latter two results it should be stressed that the restriction
that absolute risk aversion decreases with income cannot be regarded as univer-
sally acceptable so there remains some degree of uncertainty as to the validity
of the presumption that higher tax rates and higher income lead to greater tax
evasion. In addition, these results are also sensitive to the precise form of the
punishment for evasion. If the …ne is determined as in Allingham and Sandmo
(1972) by f [M ¡ X], f > t, rather than F t[M ¡ X], then neither the e¤ect of
the tax rate or of income can be unambiguously signed even with decreasing
absolute risk aversion.
Before proceeding to a discussion of the choice problem of the tax authori-
ties, it is worth noting two directions in which the analysis has been extended.
Cross and Shaw (1982) have conducted a joint determination of evasion and
avoidance activities, where avoidance refers to legal but costly means of alter-
ing activity in order to reduce total tax payments. They highlight the possible
complementarities between the two activities so that an increase in the level of
one of the activities leads to a reduction in the cost of the other. For instance,
376 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

if tax can be avoided by claiming expenses, there is little additional cost in-
volved in in‡ating an expenses claim and therefore evading taxation. A second
direction taken has been to embed the evasion decision within a more general
choice problem by introducing additional assets with risky returns. This then
makes tax evasion only one of a portfolio of activities that have risky returns.
As shown by Landskroner, Paroush and Swary (1990) even in this generalised
setting the comparative statics results remain much as given above with de-
creasing absolute risk aversion still being the critical factor. A further extension
of the analysis, the choice of labour supply, will be discussed in more detail in
Section 5.

12.4 Optimal auditing and punishment


In developing the comparative statics properties of the tax evasion decision,
it has been assumed that the probability of detection, or of auditing, and the
…ne levied when detected are constant. This is correct from the viewpoint of
the tax evader but from the perspective of the tax collector they are variables
which can be chosen to attain speci…ed objectives. The present section will con-
sider the choice of these variables within the simplest framework; an alternative
perspective is given in Section 9.
From (12.4) and (12.5) it can be seen that both an increase in the probability
of detection and of the …ne will reduce evasion. Therefore, as noted by Allingham
and Sandmo (1972), the two instruments are substitutes with respect to reducing
evasion since a reduction in one can be compensated for by an increase in the
other. For this to be strictly true it must also be the case that increases in the
instruments also raise additional revenue, a property that is now demonstrated
to be satis…ed.
Following Kolm (1973), if it is assumed that the taxpayer of previous the
section is a representative of a large population of identical taxpayers, then the
average tax revenue from a taxpayer is equal to the expected revenue from each.
The level of average revenue is then given by

R = tX + pF t [M ¡ X] : (12.10)

Di¤erentiating with respect to p determines the e¤ect of an increase in the


probability of detection upon revenue as
@R @X
= F t [M ¡ X] + t [1 ¡ pF ] > 0; (12.11)
@p @p
where the positivity follows from (12.4) and the interior-solution assumption
pF < 1. Repeating for the …ne rate gives
@R @X
= pt [M ¡ X] + t [1 ¡ pF ] > 0; (12.12)
@F @F
which is positive by (12.5). These results con…rm that the two instruments are
indeed substitutes.
12.5. TAX EVASION AND LABOUR SUPPLY 377

It is now possible to consider the determination of the optimal values of p and


F . A natural assumption is that detection is costly in the sense that resources
are used in the auditing procedure. Thus increases in p require additional ex-
penditure. In contrast, there are no di¤erences in the cost of alternative levels
of F and, e¤ectively, increases in F are costless to produce. Given this, it is
clear what the optimal, revenue-maximising combination of p and F should be:
p should be set to zero and F increased without limit. This structure provides
maximum deterrence at zero cost. In the words of Kolm (1973), the optimal
policy should be to hang tax evaders with probability zero. This result is also
supported by the analysis of Christiansen (1980) which shows, with a slightly
di¤erent speci…cation, that when the detection probability and the …ne are ad-
justed to keep the expected gain from tax evasion constant, tax evasion will be
reduced by an increase in the …ne so that the …ne is the more e¢cient deterrent.
Further development of this result, introducing non-proportional taxes, can be
found in Koskela (1983).
There are several comments that can be made in respect of this result.
Firstly, it has been assumed that the aim of the tax collector was to choose
the probability and the …ne in order to maximise tax revenue. This runs in con-
trast to the position of previous chapters in which social welfare is maximised
subject to a revenue constraint. If this latter viewpoint is accepted in the present
context and the set of choice variables extended to also include the tax rate,
then an interior solution may exist. This will be considered when public good
are introduced in section 6. Secondly, the level of the …ne may not be under the
direct control of the tax collector but may be determined by the courts relative
to punishments for other crimes. In this case, the only choice variable is the
probability of detection and if detection is costly an interior solution is again
likely to exist. Finally, if a majority of the population are evading taxation,
there is little public support for strong enforcement since each consumer may
perceive the threat of punishment to outweigh any gains that may accrue from
additional tax revenue.
This section has considered the determination of the optimal values of detec-
tion probability and …ne within a tax-revenue maximisation context and in this
particular case the optimum involved zero detection and maximal punishment.
This result should be contrasted to those of later sections in which the structure
is somewhat modi…ed.

12.5 Tax evasion and labour supply


The labour supply decision with evasion has two important components. Firstly,
there is the question of how the possibility for evasion and non-declaration of
income a¤ects the labour supply decision in terms of the comparative statics of
labour supply. Secondly, there is also the issue of occupational choice. If some
forms of employment have greater possibilities for evasion than others, then each
household must reach a decision on the quantity of each form of employment
to be undertaken. The tax system and the punishments for evasion will clearly
378 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

have an in‡uence upon this decision.

12.5.1 Labour supply


Allowing labour supply to be variable introduces a additional degree of ‡exibil-
ity. However, this is not without cost. As shown by Pencavel (1979) virtually
none of the comparative statics e¤ects of parameter changes can be unambigu-
ously signed when labour supply is variable. The only exception to this is that
an increase in lump-sum income reduces declared income when the marginal
rate of tax is non-decreasing. This failure to provide de…nite results arises from
the con‡ict between income and substitution e¤ects. If the substitution e¤ects
alone are considered, then it is possible to derive speci…c results.
If hours of labour supply are denoted by x 1 and utility is additively separable
with the form
U = R (x 1 ) + S (wx1 ) ; (12.13)
where wx 1 is the income level achieved, then Andersen (1977) shows that

@x1 @ [wx 1 ¡ X]
jU c on st. < 0; jU co ns t. > 0; (12.14)
@t @t
where wx1 ¡ X is the level of evaded income. Therefore an increase in the tax
rate, holding utility constant, reduces labour supply but increases the level of
evaded income. If evaded income is taxed at a penalty rate f when discovered,
then the e¤ects of increases in f are

@x1 @ [wx 1 ¡ X]
jU c on st. < 0; jU co ns t. > 0; (12.15)
@f @f

so that an increase in the penalty rate, with utility constant, reduces labour
supply and evaded income. Finally, if relative risk aversion increases with income
and is greater than 1, then an increase in the probability of detection reduces
evaded income.
These results do indicate that some conclusions can be derived when the
labour supply decision is introduced. However, these are almost entirely re-
stricted to substitution e¤ects for a separable utility function. Once such re-
strictions are invoked, it is not surprising that the conclusions do not di¤er
greatly from those with exogeneous income.

12.5.2 Allocation of hours


It has been assumed above that tax evasion takes the form of a simple failure
to declare some of the income earned. In practice tax evasion is also linked to
occupational choice, with some occupations providing greater opportunities for
evasion than others. Furthermore, within an occupation it may also possible to
divide labour time between an o¢cial market, the income from which must be
declared, and an uno¢cial market from which the income earned is not declared.
It is upon this latter aspect that the focus will now be placed.
12.5. TAX EVASION AND LABOUR SUPPLY 379

Two wages are now de…ned: w r , the wage in the registered or o¢cial market
and w u , the uno¢cial market wage. Since the recipient of the wages does not
pay tax when working on the uno¢cial market, it is assumed that w u < w r .
This has the implication that the gain from evading tax is split between the
supplier and employer of uno¢cial labour. Compatible with these wage rates
are the hours of labour x r1 ; x u1 . The income level when evasion is not detected
is given by
wu x u1 + w r x r1 [1 ¡ t] ; (12.16)
and when detected
w u x u1 [1 ¡ f] + w r x r1 [1 ¡ t] : (12.17)
The consumer chooses x r1 ; x u1
to maximise expected utility subject to the con-
straints (12.16) and (12.17).
The aim is to determine how the allocation of labour between the two mar-
kets is a¤ected by changes in the tax and punishment parameters. However, it
has already been noted that, in general, few of these e¤ects are actually signed.
In order to derive concrete results, it is necessary to place restrictions upon the
utility function. As shown by Cowell (1981), with a utility function of the form

U = U (M; 1 ¡ x r1 ¡ x u1 ) ; (12.18)

where M is total income and the time endowment is normalised at 1, the im-
portant restriction is that h i
@ U 1
U2
= 0; (12.19)
@M
where U1 ´ @@U @U
M ; U2 ´ @ L , with L, the leisure consumed, de…ned by L =
r u
1 ¡ x1 ¡ x 1 . The consequence of this restriction is that it determines the total
labour supply, x r1 + x u1 , as a function of the post-tax wage on the o¢cial market
and any lump-sum income.
To pro duce easily interpretable results, a precise functional form that satis-
…es (12.19) is now employed. Following Isachen and Strom (1980), the utility
function is de…ned by
U = log (M ) + log (L) : (12.20)
The maximisation facing the consumer can then be written

max [1 ¡ p] [log (wu x u1 + w r x r1 [1 ¡ t]) + log (L)]


f xr1;xu1 g
+ p [log (w u xu1 [1 ¡ f ] + w r xr1 [1 ¡ t]) + log (L)] : (12.21)

To guarantee an interior maximum, the assumption

w u [1 ¡ p] > w r [1 ¡ t] (12.22)

is adopted. Solving the …rst-order conditions for a maximum of (12.21) it can


be found that
x r1 w u [[1 ¡ p] [1 ¡ f ] w r [1 ¡ t] + pw r [1 ¡ t] ¡ [1 ¡ f ] w u ]
u = : (12.23)
x1 w r [1 ¡ t] [[1 ¡ p] w u + p [1 ¡ f ] wu ¡ wr [1 ¡ t]]
380 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

Di¤erentiating (12.23) and using (12.22) shows that


h ri h ri
@ xxu1 @ xxu1
1
> 0; 1
> 0; (12.24)
@f @p
so that an increase in either the …ne rate on undeclared income or the probability
of detection reduces the proportion of time spent in the uno¢cial labour market.
In addition h ri
x
@ xu1
1
< 0; (12.25)
@t
so an increase in the tax rate reduces the proportion of time spent in the o¢cial
labour market and increases tax evasion. It should be noted that this result is
in contrast to that for the exogeneous income model.
It is the last of these results that is probably the most important since it
supports the general presumption that the growth in uno¢cial economic activity
is due to increases in taxation. However, it should be recalled that it was derived
on the basis of a particular form of utility function and does not constitute a
general …nding.
This section has studied two particular assumptions about the method of
reporting income and the ‡exibility of labour supply. The …rst involved the
household having complete freedom in choice of hours and reporting whatever
level of income they felt to be optimal. In the second, labour supply was still
variable but evasion was only possible on uno¢cial income. These are not the
only possible sets of assumptions, for instance it is likely that hours of work are
…xed in the o¢cial market and that changes in supply can only be made in the
uno¢cial market. Cowell (1985b) presents a summary of results to be obtained
from the di¤erent sets of assumptions; the results di¤er only in minor details.

12.6 Public goods


When the objective of the policy maker is revenue maximisation, it was shown
above that the optimal choice of detection probability and …ne was to have
in…nite punishment with zero probability of detection. The reason for the op-
timality of this extreme strategy was that the objective function did not take
account of the welfare of the taxpayers nor the use to which the revenue would
be put. Once these are incorporated, the choice problem has more content.
The simplest means by which to close the system is to assume that tax
revenue is used to supply a public good from which all households derive welfare.
This provides the motivation for the existence of taxation. In addition to this, it
is also necessary to include a cost function for the detection probability, re‡ecting
the fact that catching tax evaders requires the input of resources. Combining
these features with a suitable welfare function then provides a well-speci…ed
maximisation problem.
The speci…cation of the welfare function raises some interesting issues in
this context. Since the government, whose preferences are captured by the social
12.6. PUBLIC GOODS 381

welfare function, would prefer all taxpayers to act honestly and does not hesitate
to punish those who do not, should it take account of the welfare of evaders when
formulating policy? Since tax evasion is only a minor crime it may seem that
tax evaders should not be excluded from consideration by society. However,
this cannot be claimed to constitute a general proposition about all crimes since
there probably reaches a point where a crime is so heinous that its perpetrator
does not merit attention in the formulation of society’s preferences. Although
there is no clear set of guidelines to answer this question, the tradition in the
literature, for instance Kolm (1973) and Sandmo (1981), has been to adopt
a utilitarian framework in which the utilities of evaders are included in social
welfare. This is probably for analytical simplicity rather than for philosophical
reasons.

12.6.1 The valuation of public funds


Following Kolm (1973), let there be a population of n identical consumers,
where n is intended to be a large number. If p is the true probability of being
detected when evading tax and all the population evade tax, then np consumers
are caught evading and [1 ¡ p] n are not. With a cost function C(p), C (0) = 0,
C 0 > 0, representing the cost of achieving the probability p of detection and tax
revenue R = tX + pf [m ¡ X], where f is the …ne rate, the level of public good
supply is given by
G = R ¡ C = tX + pf [m ¡ X] ¡ C (p): (12.26)
The expected welfare of a typical consumer is then de…ned by a utility function
that is additively separable in private consumption and public good consumption
E [U ] = [1 ¡ p] U (Y ) + pU (Z) + V (G) ; (12.27)
where Y = M ¡ tX and Z = M ¡ tX ¡ f [M ¡ X]. The level of G is certain for
the individual consumer due to the assumption that n is large. Given that G
is parametric for the individual, the analysis of (12.1) is appropriate here and
the action of each consumer is to choose the optimal value of X. Due to the
separability assumption, the optimal X depends only upon p, t and f , hence
X = X (t; p; f ) ; (12.28)
with partial derivatives denoted Xt ; Xp and Xf .
Invoking the large number assumption again, social welfare is given by
W = n [[1 ¡ p] U (Y ) + pU (Z) + V (G)] ; (12.29)
since exactly np of the population are caught evading. De…ning the per-capita
variables g = Gn
, r = R
n
and c(p) = C(p)
n
, maximising (12.29) is equivalent to
maximising
µ ¶
G
W = [1 ¡ p] U (Y ) + pU (Z) + V
n
= [1 ¡ p] U (Y ) + pU (Z) + v (g) ; (12.30)
382 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

with
g = r ¡ c (p) = tX + pf [M ¡ X] ¡ c (p) : (12.31)
Di¤erentiating (12.30) with respect to the choice variables t, p and f and
noting that the optimality of X implies that [1 ¡ p] U 0 (Y ) t +pU 0 (Z) [f ¡ t] = 0,
the …rst-order conditions are
dW
= X [v 0 ¡ E [U 0]] + v 0 [t ¡ pf ] Xt = 0; (12.32)
dt

dW
= p [M ¡ X] [v 0 ¡ U 0 (Z)] + v 0 [t ¡ pf ] Xf = 0; (12.33)
df
and

dW
= U 0 (Z) ¡ U 0 (Y ) + v 0p [M ¡ X] ¡ v 0c0 + v 0 [t ¡ pf ] Xp = 0; (12.34)
dp
where
E [U 0 ] = [1 ¡ p] U 0 (Y ) + pU 0 (Z) : (12.35)
It has already been demonstrated in (12.4) and (12.5) that Xp and Xf are both
positive. In addition, if it is assumed that Xt < 0, then the …rst-order conditions
imply that the marginal utilities can be ranked as U 0 (Y ) < E [U 0 ] < U 0 (Z). The
central inequality is reversed if Xt > 0. In particular it follows that

v0 1
= h i ; (12.36)
E [U 0 ] 1 ¡ 1 ¡ pf t @X
t X @t

so that the ratio of the marginal utility of public income to the consumer, v 0 , to
the marginal utility of private income, E [U 0 ], is a¤ected by the e¤ect of changes
in the tax rate upon the declared level income. Since this valuation of public
funds would be employed in any cost-bene…t calculations, it can be seen that
tax evasion should be taken into account when determining all public decisions.
The main conclusion to be drawn from endogenising the use of revenue and
formulating the objective function in terms of social welfare is that it is possible
to generate an interior solution for the detection probability and the level of
the …ne for evasion. As such, these variables are subject to the same basic
considerations as other instruments of public policy.

12.6.2 Congestible public goods


The second e¤ect that public goods may have is to modify the response of the
household to changes in tax rates. It has been noted that the standard prediction
is that an increase in the tax rate will lower evasion; a result that runs counter
to expectations. If households feel that public goods are over-provided then an
increase in the tax rate will lead to even greater over-provision. As the greater
provision exacerbates the initial feeling of over-provision, the households may
well alter the extent of their tax evasion; in particular circumstances, decreasing
12.6. PUBLIC GOODS 383

absolute risk aversion will lead to increased evasion. This aspect could not arise
in the previous model where the additive separability of the utility function
ensured that the evasion decision was independent of the level of public goods
provided. This intuitive argument has been formalised by Cowell and Gordon
(1988).
De…ne the level of evaded income by E ´ M ¡ X so that the gain from
evasion is tE is evasion in undetected and ¡tEf if detected. The household can
then be viewed as cho osing a quantity tE of a random asset which has return
r = 1 with probability 1 ¡ p and return r = ¡f with probability p. Hence
consumption can be de…ned as the random quantity

x = [1 ¡ t] M + rtE: (12.37)

The revenue raised from taxation is

R = n [tM + rtE ] ¡ nc (p) ; (12.38)

where the large-population has been used to replace the random variable r by
its mean r = 1 ¡ p ¡ pf. In contrast to Section 6.1 the quantity of public good
available to each individual is also dependent upon the size of the population;
an assumption that is intended to capture congestion e¤ects. In detail,
R 1 n 1
G= ; lim = 0; lim = > 0: (12.39)
à (n) n!1 à (n) n!1 à (n) Ã

If the n ¡ 1 other households each evade an amount E , then the evasion E of


the nth household determines the level of public good as
n [tM ¡ c (p)] ¡ [n ¡ 1] rtE rtE rtE
G= ¡ = G (n; t) ¡ : (12.40)
à (n) à (n) à (n)

In determining their consumption, it is assumed that the household takes G (n; t)


as …xed. This is the Nash assumption as employed in the analysis of the private
provision of public goods in Chapter 9. It is important to note that in writing
(12.40) it is assumed that the household takes account of how their choice of
evasion a¤ects the level of public good provision. E¤ectively, the population is
su¢ciently large that the mean can be substituted into (12.38) but not so large
that the e¤ect of each household is negligible. Without this assumption, the
essential link between evasion and provision is lost. The best interpretation to
give this is that a small number economy is considered and the limit assumption
is imposed in (12.42) and (12.47) to provide a simpli…cation.
By choosing their level of evasion, E, each household seeks to maximise the
von Neumann-Morgernstern utility function

U = E [U (x; G)] ; (12.41)

with G de…ned by (12.40). The …rst-order condition for this maximisation is


¸
UG
E Ux r ¡ r = 0: (12.42)
à (n)
384 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

Imposing the limit assumption in (12.39), the …rst-order condition reduces to

E [U xr] = 0: (12.43)

As noted, the aim of the analysis is to determine the e¤ect of changes in the
tax rate, t, upon the level of tax evasion. To do this, the …rst-order condition
(12.43) is di¤erentiated with respect to t and tE to give
@G
d (tE ) E [Uxx r] M ¡ E [UxG r] @t
= : (12.44)
dt E [Uxxr 2 ]

At the symmetric Nash equilibrium, the level of the public good is given by

n [tM ¡ c (p)] ¡ nrtE


G= : (12.45)
à (n)
Hence di¤erentiating this
@G nM nr @tE
= ¡ : (12.46)
@t à à @t
Substituting (12.46) into (12.44) provides the …nal characterisation

d (tE ) E [Uxx r] M ¡ E [U xG r] M
Ã
= ; (12.47)
dt E [Uxx r2 ] ¡ E [UxG r] Ãr

where the limit assumption has again be used on the terms nà .


To determine the sign of (12.47), it is …rst noted that stability of the Nash
equilibrium implies that the denominator is negative. Therefore the sign is the
opposite of the denominator. In general, the sign of the numerator cannot be
restricted so the model can therefore generate a positive relationship between
evaded tax and the tax rate, in contrast to the model without public goods. In
order to be more precise, consider the special case where UUGx is independent of
x. This assumption implies that

U xUxG ¡ U xxUG = 0; (12.48)

and hence E [UxG r] = E [Uxxr] m, where m = UUGx . Using this restriction, (12.47)
can be written h i
m
d (tE) E [U xG r] M 1 ¡ Ã
= : (12.49)
dt E [Uxx r ] ¡ E [U xGr] mr
2
Ã

To complete the analysis, note that the e¤ect on utility of an increase in t is


given by ¸ ¸
dE [U ] E [UG ] m
=M ¡ E [Ux] = M ¡1 : (12.50)
dt à Ã
If this expression is positive, it suggests public goods are underprovided since
the consumer would welcome an expansion of the public sector. Returning to
12.7. EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE 385

(12.49),
h i since the denominator is negative, tax evasion will increase whenever
m
1¡ is positive. Therefore an increase in tax rate will increase evasion when
Ã
public goods are over-provided.
The introduction of public goods represents one way of closing the system
so that tax revenue raised has some bene…cial e¤ect. It has been demonstrated
how such closure can lead to an interior solution for the punishment variables
and thus places these within the standard framework of public economics. In
addition, it was also demonstrated that tax evasion alters the cost of raising
public funds and that this should be taken into account in any cost-bene…t
calculations. Finally, the introduction of public goods may lead to the degree
of tax evasion increasing as the tax rate increases, a result more in conformity
with a priori expectations.

12.7 Empirical evidence


The theoretical analysis of tax evasion has predicted the e¤ect that changes in
various parameters will have upon the level of tax evasion. In some cases, such as
the e¤ect of the probability of detection and the …ne, these are unambiguous. In
others, particularly the e¤ect of changes in the tax rate, the e¤ects depend upon
the precise speci…cation of the tax system and upon assumptions concerning
attitudes towards risk. Given these uncertainties, it is valuable to investigate
empirical evidence in order to see how the ambiguities are resolved in practice.
Furthermore, analysis of empirical evidence also allows the investigation of the
relevance of other parameters, such as source of income, and other hypotheses
on tax evasion, for example the importance of social norms.
There have been three basic approaches taken in studying tax evasion. The
…rst has been to collect survey or interview data and from this to infer the
extent of evasion and some qualitative aspects of its relationship to various pa-
rameters. Secondly, econometric analysis has been applied to both survey data
and to standard economic statistics. Such analysis provides a more quantitative
determination of the relationships. Finally, tax evasion experiments have been
conducted which provide an opportunity of designing the environment to permit
the investigation of particular hypotheses.
An early example of the use of interview data can be found in the study
of Norwegian taxpayers by Mork (1975). The methodology was to interview
individuals in order to ascertain their actual income levels. This information
was then contrasted to that given on the tax returns of the same individuals
and indicated a steady decline of declared income as a proportion of reported
income as income rose. This result is in agreement with that of the comparative
statics analysis.
Combining econometrics and survey methods, Spicer and Lundstedt (1976)
sought to investigate the importance of attitudes and social norms in the evasion
decision; the data were taken from a 1974 survey in the United States. Econo-
metric analysis revealed that the propensity to evade taxation was reduced by
an increased probability of detection and an increase in age. Surprisingly, an
386 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

increase in income reduced the propensity to evade. With respect to the atti-
tude and social variables, an increase in the perceived inequity of taxation and
of the number of other tax evaders known to individual both made evasion more
likely. The extent of tax evasion was also increased by the attitude and social
variables but was also increased by the experience of the tax payer with previous
tax audits. This study clearly demonstrated the importance of social variables
in addition to the economic variables.
Clot‡eter (1983) estimated tax evasion equations using data from the In-
ternal Revenue Services Taxpayer Compliance Measurement Program survey of
1969. These indicated that tax evasion did, in fact, increase as marginal tax
rates increased and was decreased when wages where a signi…cant proportion of
income. This result was supported by Crane and Nourzad (1986) employing the
di¤erence between income and expenditure …gures in National Accounts from
the United States for the period 1947 - 1981. Although their major focus was
the fact that in‡ation raised evasion, the results also showed that increased mar-
ginal tax rates also raised evasion. In contrast to this, the study of Geeroms and
Wilmots (1985) of Belgian data found precisely the converse conclusion with tax
increases leading to lower evasion. Therefore these econometric studies do not
resolve the ambiguity about the relation between marginal tax rates and tax
evasion.
Turning now to experimental studies, Friedland, Maital and Rutenberg (1978)
employed a tax evasion game in which participants were given a monthly in-
come and a set of tax and punishment parameters. Given these, they were
requested to make tax declarations. The major …ndings of this study were that
evasion increased with the tax rate and, that keeping the net gain from evasion
constant, evasion fell as the …ne was increased and the detection probability re-
duced. This result is in agreement with the theoretical analysis of Christiansen
(1980). Further results showed that women evaded more often than men but
evaded lower amounts and that purchasers of lottery tickets, presumed to be
less risk averse, were no more likely to evade than non-purchasers but evaded
greater amounts when they did evade. A similar experiment was conducted
by Becker, Büchner and Sleeking (1987) but with the inclusion of endogenous
transfers of tax revenue back to the taxpayers and with income being earned
by the participants. With respect to the propensity to evade, a high transfer
had a negative e¤ect as did the probability of detection and, surprisingly, the
perceived level of tax. Income level had a positive e¤ect and hence raised the
propensity to evade. Only the audit probability had a signi…cant e¤ect on the
level of evasion.
Finally, Baldry (1986) contrasted the …ndings of two sets of experiments.
The …rst was framed as a tax evasion decision and this determined that some
participants never evaded tax and that the decision to evade was in‡uenced by
the tax schedule. This experiment was then repeated as a simple gamble with
the same payo¤s. The …nding was then that all participants betted and each
made the maximum bet. From these contrasting …ndings, it can be concluded
that there is more to tax evasion than gambling and that the moral and social
dimensions are of importance.
12.8. HONESTY AND SOCIAL NORMS 387

The important lessons to be drawn from these results are that the theoretical
predictions are generally supported, with the exception of the e¤ect of the tax
rate which remains uncertain, and that tax evasion is rather more than a simple
gamble; there are attitudinal and social aspects to the evasion decision. This
latter observation naturally carries implications for further theoretical analysis
of the evasion decision. In particular, the fact that some taxpayers never evade
requires explanation.

12.8 Honesty and social norms


The feature that distinguishes tax evasion from a simple gamble is that tax-
payers submitting incorrect returns feel varying degrees of anxiety and regret.
To some, being caught would represent a traumatic experience which would do
immense damage to their self-image. To others, it would be only a slight incon-
venience. The innate belief in honesty of some taxpayers is not captured by the
representation of tax evasion as a gamble nor are the non-monetary costs of de-
tection and punishment captured by preferences de…ned on income alone. The
…rst intention of this section is to incorporate these features into the analysis
and to study their consequences.
The empirical results show a positive connection between the number of tax
evaders known to a taxpayer and the level of that taxpayer’s own evasion. This
observation suggests that the evasion decision is not made in isolation by each
taxpayer but is made with reference to the norms and behaviour of the general
society of the taxpayer. Given the empirical signi…cance of such norms, the
second part of this section focuses on their implications.
To introduce the concept of a preference for honesty into the utility function,
the simplest approach is to adopt a function of the form
U = U (x) ¡ ÂE ; (12.51)

where  is the measure of the taxpayers honesty and, with E the extent of
evasion, ÂE is the utility cost of deviating from complete honesty. It is assumed
that taxpayers are characterised by their value of  but are identical in all other
respects.
Combining (12.51) with the budget constraint (12.37), individual maximisa-
tion leads to the …rst-order condition for choice of E
E [U 0 (x) rt] ¡ Â = 0: (12.52)

E will only be positive when the marginal utility of evasion is greater than
zero at a zero level of evasion. Formally, evasion will occur when V0 ¡ Â > 0,
where V 0 ´ [1 ¡ p ¡ pf ] tU 0 (M [1 ¡ t]). Hence those taxpayers characterised by
values of  that satisfy V 0 ¡  > 0 will evade and those with higher values of
 will not. The population is therefore separated into two parts with honest
taxpayers not evading whilst dishonest will evade. The term honest does not
have its standard meaning in this context since all taxpayers with …nite  will
evade if the expected gain is su¢ciently great.
388 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

The comparative statics with respect to the punishment and income para-
meters are not too di¤erent from those of the model described by (12.1). The
ma jor di¤erence is that the aggregate e¤ect is composed of the changes in the
level of evasion by existing evaders and the marginal changes as either more or
less taxpayers evade. Since these e¤ects work in the same direction, there is no
change in the predicted e¤ects on aggregate or individual evasion.
The e¤ect of an increase in the tax rate is given in the following theorem
from Gordon (1989).

Theorem 59 (Gordon) With decreasing absolute risk aversion, there exists


some ¤ < V 0 such that @E
@t
< 0 if  < ¤ and @@tE > 0 if V0 >  > ¤ .

Proof. By di¤erentiation of (12.52), the e¤ect of the tax change can be


found to be
@E E [U 00 (x) rt [M ¡ rE ]] ¡ Ât
= : (12.53)
@t E [U 00 (x) rt [M ¡ rE ]]
For  = 0, (12.53) reduces to (12.8) which has already been shown to be nega-
tive. In the limit as  tends to V0 (12.53) is clearly positive since E is tending
to 0 from a positive value. As the decreasing absolute risk aversion implies the
numerator is monotonic in Â, the sign of @@Et must change once as stated in the
theorem.
This analysis predicts that there will be some evaders who increase the extent
of their evasion as the tax rate increases. In addition to this e¤ect, an increase
in t also raises V 0 so that previously honest taxpayers will begin to evade. It
is therefore possible, though not unambiguous, that the introduction of utility
cost of evasion can generate a positive relation between the tax rate and the
extent of evasion.
Social norms have been incorporated into the evasion decision in two distinct
ways. Gordon (1989) introduces the social norm as an additional element of
the utility cost to evasion. The additional utility cost is assumed to be an
increasing function of the proportion of taxpayers who do not evade. This
formulation is intended to capture the fact that more utility will be lost, in
terms of reputation, the more out of step the taxpayer is with the remainder of
society. The consequence of this modi…cation is to reinforce the separation of
the population into evaders and non-evaders. This approach has been developed
further by Myles and Naylor (1995a) who show that reputation e¤ects can lead
to multiple equilibria and epidemics of evasion.
An alternative approach has been taken by Bordignon (1993) who explicitly
imposes a social norm upon behaviour. The social norm is based on the con-
cept of Kantian morality and, e¤ectively, has each individual assessing their fair
contribution in tax payments towards the provision of public goods. This calcu-
lation then provides an upper bound on the extent of tax evasion. To calculate
the actual degree of tax evasion each taxpayer then performs the expected utility
maximisation calculation, as in (12.1), and evades whichever is the smaller out
of this quantity and the previously determined upper bound. This formulation
is also able to provide a positive relation between the tax rate and evaded tax
12.9. OPTIMAL AUDITING WITH AN INDEPENDENT REVENUE SERVICE389

for some range of taxes and to divide the population into those who evade tax
and those who do not.
The introduction of psychic costs and of social norms is capable of explaining
some of the empirically observed features of tax evasion which are not explained
by the standard expected utility maximisation hypothesis. It does this modify-
ing the form of preferences but the basic nature of the approach is unchanged.
The obvious di¢culty with these changes is that there is little to suggest pre-
cisely how social norms and utility costs of dishonesty should be formalised.

12.9 Optimal auditing with an independent rev-


enue service
In the analysis of the optimal …ne and detection probability conducted in Section
4, it was assumed that both instruments were under the control of the authority
that also determined the rate of tax. In practice it is more likely that there is a
distinction between the agencies that determine each of these variables. Taxes
are set by the exchequer, punishments by the courts in relation to those for other
o¤ences, and detection rates by a revenue service. If this view is adopted, it is
more appropriate to analyse the determination of the optimal rate of detection
in isolation taking as given the rate of tax and the …nes that will be levied.
Having identi…ed the revenue service as an agency in its own right, it follows
that its objective can be identi…ed as the maximisation of revenue collected less
the cost of enforcing its veri…cation policy.
As noted by Reinganum and Wilde (1985), tax evasion is distinguished from
many other forms of crime in that the tax evader is required to make a report of
their income to the revenue service and it is on the basis of this report that the
revenue service founds the decision whether to investigate or not. Consequently
the reports can be viewed as a signal from the tax payer about their true income
and the revenue service can attempt to extract information from this signal.
Formalising this, given their observed income, which is private information,
each taxpayer …les an income report and the revenue service decides to audit,
or not, on the basis of this report. The reported income is chosen to maximise
the welfare of the taxpayer and the audit probabilities are chosen to maximise
the net revenue of the revenue service.
To complete the description, the distinction must also be drawn between an
equilibrium with pre-commitment and that without. With pre-commitment the
revenue service is bound by a pre-announced audit policy which it cannot alter in
the light of taxpayers responses even if the audit policy is then non-optimal. The
assumption of pre-commitment reduces the model to a principal-agent problem
in which the revenue service (the principal) designs the contract for the taxpayer
(the agent). Without pre-commitment the audit policy must remain optimal
given the choices of the taxpayers. There is hence a degree of simultaneity in
the choices and the Nash equilibrium concept becomes appropriate.
Taking the no commitment model …rst, Reinganum and Wilde (1986) con-
390 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

sider a veri…cation policy as a function ½ = p(X), where X is the taxpayers


reported income. Given a report of income X, the function p(X) determines
the probability ½ with which evasion will be detected. Given a true income level
of M the taxpayer chooses X to maximise

E [U (X)] = p (X) [M [1 ¡ t] ¡ tf [M ¡ X]] + [1 ¡ p (X)] [M ¡ tX] : (12.54)

The speci…cation in (12.54) embodies the assumption of risk neutrality so the


consumer is attempting to maximise expected income. Given p(X ), the max-
imisation in (12.54) determines a report as a function of true income. This
function is denoted r(M ), hence the report is given by X = r(M ).
When it receives an income report the revenue service must form an expecta-
tion of the true income level of the person …ling that report. Let these beliefs be
captured by a function ¿ (X), that is if income X is reported the revenue service
believes the taxpayer to be of true income ¿ (X). De…ning the cost of achieving a
probability ½ of detection as c(½), the expected revenue from a taxpayer making
report X is given by

R (X; ½; ¿ ) = ½ [t¿ (X) + f t [¿ (X) ¡ X]] + [1 ¡ ½] tX ¡ c(½): (12.55)

Given its beliefs, the revenue service chooses ½ to maximise R (X; ½; ¿ ).


The equilibrium that is to be de…ned is assumed to be a separating equilib-
rium in which each income type …les a di¤erent report. This implies that the
report function r(M ) is monotonic in M ; in particular it is natural to assume
that r(M ) is monotonically increasing in M . A separating equilibrium can then
be de…ned.
Separating equilibrium
A set of functions f¿ (X); p(X); r(M )g is a separating equilibrium if r(M ) is
monotonically increasing and
(i) Given ¿ (X), p(X) maximises R (X; ½; ¿ );
(ii) Given p(X), r(M ) maximises E [U (X)];
and
(iii) ¿ (r(M )X ) = M .
Condition (iii) is the consistency condition for the beliefs of the revenue
service and simple asserts that they cannot be consistently wrong in their as-
sessment of the income levels from the reports that they are given.
For each value of X the optimal audit probability can be found by di¤eren-
tiating (12.55). This provides the necessary condition

t [1 + f ] [¿ (X) ¡ X] ¡ c0 (½) = 0: (12.56)

Assuming that c00 is positive, this is also a su¢cient condition for the choice of
audit probability. From (12.54), the taxpayer’s optimal report must satisfy

p (r (M )) tf ¡ p 0 (r (M )) t [1 + f ] [M ¡ r (M )] ¡ t [1 ¡ p (r (M ))] = 0: (12.57)

The second-order condition is

2p 0 (r (M )) t [1 + f ] ¡ p 00 (r (M )) t [1 + f ] [M ¡ r (M )] 0: (12.58)
12.9. OPTIMAL AUDITING WITH AN INDEPENDENT REVENUE SERVICE391

The consistency condition ¿ (r(M )X) = M can be given the alternative formu-
lation ¿ (r(M )) = r¡ 1 (X), where r¡ 1 (X) is the inverse of the function r(M ).
Using this identity (12.56) - (12.58) can rewritten
£ ¤
t [1 + f ] r¡ 1 (X) ¡ X ¡ c0 (½) = 0; (12.59)
£ ¤
p (X) tf ¡ p0 (X ) t [1 + f ] r¡1 (X) ¡ X ¡ t [1 ¡ p (X)] = 0; (12.60)
and £ ¤
2p 0 (X) t [1 + f ] ¡ p 00 (X) t [1 + f ] r ¡1 (X) ¡ X 0: (12.61)
The advantage of these transformed equations is that they are now in terms of
X and can be used to characterise the reporting and auditing strategies.
Since (12.59) and (12.60) must hold for all X they can be di¤erentiated to
give £ ¤
t [1 + f ] r¡ 10 (X) ¡ 1 ¡ c00 (p (X)) p 0 (X) = 0; (12.62)
£ ¤ £ ¤
p 0 (X) t [1 + f ] 2 ¡ r¡ 10 (X) ¡ p00 (X) t [1 + f ] r¡ 1 (X) ¡ X = 0: (12.63)
The form of the optimal audit function is then given in the following theorem.

Theorem 60 (Reinganum/Wilde) p 0 (X) < 0 and r ¡10 (X) 2 (0; 1).

Proof. For (12.62) to hold either p 0 > 0 and r ¡10 > 1 or p 0 < 0 and r¡ 10 < 1.
Similarly, for (12.63) to hold either p 0 > 0 and r ¡10 < 0 or p 0 < 0 and r¡ 10 > 0.
These requirements can only be consistent when p 0 < 0 and 0 < r ¡10 < 1. This
proves the theorem.
Theorem 12.2 has the implication that the equilibrium e¤ort at veri…cation
diminishes the higher is the level of reported income. In addition the identity
r ¡10 = r10 and the result 0 < r¡ 10 < 1 imply that r 0 (M ) > 1 and hence that tax
evasion declines with income since M ¡ r(M ) is decreasing in M . The second of
these two conclusions may seem surprising but if evasion increased with income
the revenue service would have an incentive to raise the audit probability on
high incomes.
This analysis has been extended to a social custom model of tax evasion in
Myles and Naylor (1995b). The existence of the social custom results in the
equilibrium being characterised by some taxpayers evading whilst others pay
their taxes honestly. This leads to there being pooling of honest and dishonest
taxpayers at some income report levels. The optimal audit schedule is still
decreasing over the reports by evaders, with the probability of audit reaching
zero at the highest income report of a tax evader. An increase in the …ne rate
raises the audit probability (where positive), in direct contrast to the analysis
of Section 4 where the two instruments are substitutes.
Turning now to the analysis with pre-commitment, somewhat di¤erent re-
sults are obtained. Allowing pre-commitment permits the adoption of strategies
by the revenue service which involve a zero probability of auditing some income
levels. In fact, as shown by Scotchmer (1987), the optimal policy takes the form
of a cut-o¤ rule in which income reports above a certain level are not audited at
392 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

all. Since this leads all taxpayers with an income above the cut-o¤ level to …le
a report at the cut-o¤, this can only be an equilibrium when pre-commitment
is allowed because if there were no commitment the revenue service would gain
by reneging on the zero audit probability and catching all the evaders at the
cut-o¤ point. This optimal strategy is clearly an exaggeration of the decreasing
audit probability shown to be optimal without commitment.
The consequence of the cut-o¤ rule is that the o¢cial tax which is pro-
portional at rate t becomes regressive since actual tax payment is constant on
incomes above the cut-o¤ point and the e¤ective tax function is regressive. This
observation illustrates the general point that with tax evasion the properties of
the e¤ective tax function may well be very di¤erent from those of the o¢cial tax
function. This is a point pursued further by Cramer, Marchand and Pestieau
(1990) who also note the di¢culties in determining optimal taxes due to the
nonconvexity of the social welfare function.

12.10 Tax evasion by …rms


The analysis of the previous sections has been concerned with the tax evasion
decisions of households. To complement this, and to provide the results needed
for considering optimal taxation with evasion, it is also necessary to consider
tax evasion by …rms. Firms can evade taxation either by misreporting sales or
pro…t or by making false declarations about input use. It is possible that all three
methods may be required simultaneously to disguise evasion if the information
gathering process of the revenue service is su¢ciently thorough. The analysis
given below is simpli…ed however by considering only the under-reporting of
sales. Tax evasion will be analysed in both competitive and imperfectly com-
petitive markets.

12.10.1 Competitive …rms


The tax evasion decision for competitive …rms has been analysed by Virmani
(1989), Yamada (1990) and Cremer and Gahvari (1993), with each employing a
slightly di¤erent structure; the analysis given here follows Cremer and Gahvari.
Consider a competitive industry producing with a constant marginal cost c
whose output is subject to a speci…c tax t. Each …rm in the industry can choose
to reveal only a fraction Á of its sales to the revenue service. However, to
conceal output requires the use of resources by the …rms. The resource cost of
concealing each unit of output is determined by a convex function G(1 ¡ Á) of
the proportion of sales concealed. The probability that evasion is detected is
given by ½. The penalty rate on evaded tax is given by ¿ ¡ 1.
Denoting the market price of output as q, a typical …rm in the industry
maximises expected pro…t given by

¼ e = [q ¡ c ¡ [1 ¡ Á] G(1 ¡ Á) ¡ [1 ¡ ½] Át ¡ ½ [t + [¿ ¡ 1] [1 ¡ Á] t]] y; (12.64)


12.10. TAX EVASION BY FIRMS 393

where y is its output. Given that y is positive, Á is chosen to maximise

q ¡ c ¡ [1 ¡ Á] G(1 ¡ Á) ¡ [1 ¡ ½] Át ¡ ½ [t + [¿ ¡ 1] [1 ¡ Á] t] : (12.65)

De…ning g(1 ¡ Á) ´ [1 ¡ Á] G(1 ¡ Á), the necessary condition for choice of Á is

g 0 (1 ¡ Á) = [1 ¡ ½¿ ] t: (12.66)

The second-order condition is naturally satis…ed by the assumption that G(1¡Á)


is a convex function. Equation (12.66) therefore characterises the optimal Á.
De…ning the expected tax rate, te, by

te = [Á + [1 ¡ Á] ½¿ ] t; (12.67)

the competitive assumption implies that market price must be equal to expected
marginal cost or
q = c + g + te ; (12.68)
where g and te are evaluated at the optimal value of Á.
These equations allow the comparative statics e¤ects of changes in the un-
derlying parameters to be calculated. Taking changes in the tax rate …rst,
di¤erentiation of (12.66) gives

dÁ [1 ¡ ½t]
=¡ < 0; (12.69)
dt g 00

so that reported sales decrease as the tax rate increases. The e¤ect upon the
expected tax rate follows from (12.67) as
2
dte [1 ¡ ½t] t
= [Á + [1 ¡ Á] ½¿ ] ¡ : (12.70)
dt g 00

This e¤ect may be positive or negative since an increase in t directly raises the
expected tax but causes an indirect decrease as evasion rises. Finally, using
(12.69) and (12.70), the e¤ect upon price is

dq dq
= [Á + [1 ¡ Á] ½¿ ] ; 0 < < 1: (12.71)
dt dt
The post-tax prices rises but by less than the amount of the tax since some of
the tax increase is absorbed in increased evasion.
The e¤ect of changes in the probability of detection are also derived from
(12.66) to (12.68). The results are given by

dÁ t¿
= 0 0 > 0; (12.72)
d½ g

dte [1 ¡ ½t] t2 ¿
= [1 ¡ Á] t¿ + >0 (12.73)
d½ g 00
394 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

and
dq
= [1 ¡ Á] t¿ > 0: (12.74)
dt
Hence an increased probability of evasion raises the proportion of sales declared,
the expected tax and the market price. It can be seen from the last result that
an increase in the probability has an ambiguous e¤ect upon welfare since it
raises the price level to the detriment of consumers.
These results are generally without surprises but they indicate that tax eva-
sion can be incorporated onto the analysis of the competitive …rm. They will
also be employed in the characterisation of optimal taxes below. Before con-
sidering imperfect competition, it should be noted that Virmani (1989) studies
…rms with U-shaped average costs and establishes the result that with tax eva-
sion production will not take place at minimum average cost. This raises a
channel through which tax evasion can lead to production ine¢ciency.

12.10.2 Imperfect competition


Tax evasion by monopolistic …rms has been studied by Marrelli (1984) and
evasion by oligopolisitc …rms by Marrelli and Martina (1988). Both authors
assumed that the …rms were risk averse. Since this is not standard practice
the analysis below will assume risk neutrality. The case of monopoly will be
reviewed here; the extension to oligopoly is straightforward.
The structure remains as that for the competitive …rm but with the addi-
tion that the price is chosen by a pro…t maximising monopolist. Denoting the
demand function by X(q), the price and level of evasion are chosen to maximise

¼ e = X (q) [q ¡ c ¡ g(1 ¡ Á) ¡ [1 ¡ ½] Át ¡ ½ [t + [¿ ¡ 1] [1 ¡ Á] t]] : (12.75)

For the choice of Á, the …rst-order condition is

X (q) [g 0 (1 ¡ Á) ¡ [1 ¡ ½¿ ] t] = 0: (12.76)

Assuming that X(q) is positive, this is simply the condition given in (12.66)
again. In addition, since X(q) can be cancelled from (12.76), q does not appear
in the condition determining Á. Hence the evasion decision is independent of the
pricing decision. The converse is not true since the evasion decision determines
the expected level of costs, inclusive of tax, and therefore the level of price. To
see this formally, note that the …rst-order condition for the choice of q is given
by

X 0 (q) [q ¡ c ¡ g(1 ¡ Á) ¡ [1 ¡ ½] Át ¡ ½ [t + [¿ ¡ 1] [1 ¡ Á] t]] + X (q) = 0;


(12.77)
where (12.77) is evaluated at the optimal Á.
The qualitative nature of the comparative statics are su¢ciently similar to
those of the competitive model not to require close study. However, it is worth
noting that tax overshifting will occur when

E > 2 ¡ [Á + [1 ¡ Á] ½¿ ] : (12.78)
12.11. OPTIMAL TAXATION WITH EVASION 395

Contrasting this to (11.31), tax evasion reduces the possibility of overshifting


whenever ½¿ < 1 and increases it if ½¿ > 1. Therefore, the higher the rate of
punishment, the more likely is overshifting of taxation.

12.11 Optimal taxation with evasion


The existence of tax evasion clearly has implications for the determination of
optimal taxes. It has been noted above that optimal auditing policies will not
generally result in complete elimination of evasion. Therefore the design of taxes
should take this into explicit account. With respect to commodity taxation, the
evasion of …rms implies that the relationship between tax and price will be
modi…ed by the existence of evasion. For income taxation, tax evasion has the
e¤ect of altering the elasticity of labour supply due to the possibility of working
in the shadow economy. These factors are now incorporated into the relevant
optimal tax problems.

12.11.1 Commodity taxation


Consider a single consumer competitive economy with n industries as described
in Section 4 of Chapter 4. Normalising the wage rate to unity, industry i will
have a constant marginal cost of ci. Given a tax tk on good k, the result in
(12.68) shows that the post-tax price will be

qk = ck + gk + tek ; (12.79)

where tek = [Ák + [1 ¡ Ák ] ½k ¿ ] tk is the expected tax payment per unit of output
of a …rm in industry k and the tax evasion cost, gk, the evasion choice, f k, and
the detection rate, ½k , are all industry-speci…c. Employing the argument that
each industry is composed of a large number of …rms permits the claim that
actual and expected tax revenue are equal so that
n
X
R= tei Xi: (12.80)
i=1

In the optimal tax problem, the choice variables of the government are the
set of tax rates (t1 ; ::; tn ) and the detection probabilities (½1 ; ::; ½n ). The problem
can be written
n
X
max V (q1 ; :::; qn ) sub ject to teiXi ¡ C (½1 ; ::; ½n ) = R; (12.81)
ft1;::;tn ;½ 1;::;½ ng
i=1

where C(½1 ; ::; ½n ) is the cost of implementing the chosen set of detection prob-
abilities. This problem has the associated Lagrangean
" n #
X
L = V (q1 ; :::; qn ) + ¸ tei Xi ¡ C(½1 ; ::; ½n ) ¡ R : (12.82)
i=1
396 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION

Di¤erentiating with respect to tk gives the …rst-order condition


h ®i Xn
@Xi
Ak ¡ Xk + tei = 0; (12.83)
¸ i= 1
@qk

where
@tek
@tk
Ak ´ @q k
: (12.84)
@tk

For the optimal choice of audit probability, the …rst-order condition is


h ®i Xn
@Xi Ck
Bk ¡ Xk + tei = ; (12.85)
¸ i= 1
@qk [1 ¡ Ák ] tk ¿

where the right-hand side follows from (12.74) and


@tek
@½ k
Bk ´ @q k
: (12.86)
@½ k

The fundamental result of Cremer and Gahvari (1993) is now found by sub-
tracting (12.85) from (12.83). Replacing [1 ¡ Ák ] tk ¿ by @@½qk and then solving
k
provides the conditions
@q k @te
k
@ tk @tk
@q k
= @te
; k = 1; :::; n: (12.87)
Ck
@½k
k
@½ k
¡ Xk

The interpretation of these equations are that the taxes and detection probabili-
ties should be adjusted until the rate of substitution between tax and probability
holding the price of good k constant, and hence welfare constant, given by the
term on the left equals the rate of substitution holding tax revenue constant
which is the right-hand term. This equality of rates of substitution provides the
obvious balance between the e¤ects of the alternative instruments.
To provide a direct contrast between the tax rule in (12.83) and its counter-
part with no evasion given by (5.16), the Slutsky equation can be used to write
(12.83) as " n #
Xn X @Xi
e e ®
ti Ski = ti + ¡ Ak Xk : (12.88)
@I ¸
i=1 i=1

This di¤ers from the standard Ramsey rule in two ways. Firstly, it is in terms
of the expected rather than the actual taxes. Secondly, the term Ak enters and
hence the right-hand side is raised or lowered depending on whether Ak is less
than or greater than zero. Ak measures the rate at which the expected tax rate
increases relative to price as the nominal tax is raised. It is therefore preferable
to tax those goods where Ak is relatively high. This is re‡ected in (12.88) where
a high value of Ak leads to a greater reduction in compensated demand.
12.12. SUMMARY 397

12.11.2 Income taxation


Sandmo (1981) considers the determination of an optimal linear income tax
in the presence of tax evasion. Taxpayers are divided into two groups. The
…rst group consists of taxpayers who have a choice of allocating some, or all,
of their labour to an unobserved sector and hence avoiding income tax. The
second group of taxpayers do not have this option open to them and must pay
tax upon all their earned income. An optimal income tax is then derived by
maximising a utilitarian social welfare function. This resulting tax rule provides
an implicit characterisation of the optimal marginal tax and can be partitioned
into two parts: the …rst being the standard formula for the optimal marginal
tax and the second being a correction term for the existence of tax evasion. If
a higher tax rate leads to substitution towards labour in the unobserved sector
then this makes the correction term positive and implies a tendency for the
marginal rate of tax to be increased. This result is in marked contrast to the
view that tax evasion should be o¤set by lower marginal rates of tax.

12.12 Summary
Tax evasion is an important and signi…cant phenomenon that a¤ects both de-
veloped and developing economies. Although there is residual uncertainty sur-
rounding the accuracy of measurements, even the most conservative estimates
suggest the hidden economy in the UK and US to be at least ten per cent of
the measured economy. The substantial size of the hidden economy, and the
tax evasion that accompanies it, requires understanding so that the e¤ects of
policies that interact with it can be correctly forecast.
The predictions of the standard Allingham-Sandmo representation of tax
evasion as a choice with risk were derived and contrasted with empirical and
experimental evidence. This showed that although it is valuable as a starting
point for a theory of evasion, the Allingham-Sandmo representation some key
aspects of the evasion decision, most notably the e¤ects of morals and the social
interactions between taxpayers. In addition, tax evasion also impinges upon the
broader issues of labour supply and the allocation of hours between markets and
o ccupations. It was shown how each of these issues could be incorporated into
the evasion decision.
398 CHAPTER 12. TAX EVASION
Part IV

Introducing Real Time

399
Chapter 13

Overlapping Generations
Economies

13.1 Introduction
The overlapping generations economy, so called because of its assumed demo-
graphic structure, was introduced by Samuelson (1958). It has since proved
useful in many areas of economics including macro economic growth theory, pub-
lic economics and monetary economics. One of the economy’s major points of
interest is the welfare properties of its equilibrium. Even when the standard
competitive assumption are imposed, the equilibrium of the overlapping gener-
ations economy may not be Pareto optimal. This is in marked contrast to the
Arrow-Debreu competitive economy.
Despite its value in many areas, as demonstrated by the previous chapters,
there are several shortcomings of the Arrow-Debreu economy when applied to
intertemporal issues. The …rst is that it is essentially static and, although it can
be interpreted as intertemporal, this is not completely satisfactory as noted in
Chapter 2. It would seem to be stretching the interpretation too far to accept
trading in a single period for all go ods into the inde…nite future. Trades in the
economy are carried out by barter and there is simply no role for money. This is
a consequence of the assumptions that agents are assumed to know universally
the terms of trade between commodities and that any sequence of transactions
can be completed without cost or hindrance. The equilibrium of the economy
is also Pareto optimal, so there can be no ine¢ciency in investment or in the
choice of production techniques. Finally, the economy implicitly assumes the
lives of each agent to be at least as long as the length of the economy itself. In
many ways, the economy is simply too rich: it can cover all possibilities but can
never describe anything in detail.
These observations provide the motivation for the study of overlapping gen-
erations economies. By structuring the evolution of the population and intro-
ducing time in a very real sense, the overlapping generations economy is able

401
402 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

to address many issues of interest in public economics. The potential failure


of its competitive equilibrium to be Pareto optimal provides an e¢ciency-based
justi…cation for assessing the bene…ts of government intervention. In addition
to possessing ine¢cient equilibria, overlapping generations economies can also
generate cyclical equilibria without any requirement for exogenous shocks. Fur-
thermore it is possible for …at money to be valuable and for a continuum of
equilibria to exist. All these features will be discussed below.
This chapter sets out the structure of both the pure exchange overlapping
generations economies and an aggregate economy with production due to Dia-
mond (1965). A version of the economy proposed by Samuelson is introduced
…rst, and the failure of e¢ciency demonstrated. The economy is then gener-
alised and placed in an Arrow-Debreu format in order to make the comparison
with the …nite economy as sharp as possible. This generalised economy is em-
ployed to characterise e¢cient equilibria. Money, dynamics and indeterminacy
are then considered. For the aggregate production economy, the focus is placed
on characterising its steady state and the welfare properties of the steady state
equilibrium.

13.2 Overlapping generation exchange economies


The features of the overlapping generations economy that have been noted above
are most clearly identi…ed in economies without production and it is these that
have been most extensively analysed. For exchange economies it is straight-
forward to reinterpret an overlapping generations economy as a special case
of the Arrow-Debreu economy described in Chapter 2 in which the lifetime of
each household is …nite but, over the lifetime of the economy, there are an in-
…nite number of households and goods. It is this double in…nity that gives an
overlapping generations economy its unique structure.
Following a general description of a typical overlapping generations econ-
omy, this section will demonstrate the failure of Pareto optimality in the simple
economy …rst described by Samuelson (1958). Although instructive in itself,
this style of presentation of the economy does not make clear the link between
overlapping generations economies and the Arrow-Debreu economy. A more
general economy is therefore introduced which is cast in a form that emphasises
the parallels between it and the Arrow-Debreu economy. This general form
of overlapping generations economy is then employed to demonstrate the most
important features of the equilibria of such economies.
An overlapping generations economy is explicitly intertemporal. Time is
divided into discrete periods with the basic interval of time being equal to the
length of time that elapses between the birth of one generation and that of the
following generation. There is no …nal period for the economy. The population
of households alive at any point in time in a typical overlapping generations
economy consists of a set of …nitely-lived consumers. At each date is born a
cohort of young consumers and, if the rate of growth is positive, each cohort is
larger than the previous. In this and the following chapters, the term household
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 403

Figure 13.1: Structure of Generations

is reserved for a sequence of consumers linked by family ties. The lifespan of


each consumer is assumed to be two periods; it will be shown below that this
is not a signi…cant restriction. The structure of the population is illustrated in
Figure 13.1 where the solid lines represent the lifespan of the generations. Each
generation is identi…ed with the period in which its members are born. The
…gure shows the motivation for the name applied to these economies.
An equilibrium for the economy is a sequence of prices that equate demand
to supply in each time period. In this section it is assumed that there is no
production and no storage of commodities. Since the absence of storage possi-
bilities prevents any of the endowment of one period being carried over to the
next period, the supply in each period is equal to the …xed endowment. The
existence of the in…nite population makes the de…nition of a Pareto optimum
non-trivial; alternative concepts will be de…ned later.

13.2.1 The Samuelson economy


The Samuelson economy is de…ned as one in which all consumers are identical,
except for their date of birth, and in which there is a single good available. Each
consumer receives their endowment of this good entirely in the …rst perio d of
their life. Since there is no storage, the only means by which a consumer can
enjoy consumption in the second period of their life is by organising a series
of trades in which they deliver some quantity of the good in the …rst period
of their life and receive a delivery in the second period. It is the possibility,
or otherwise, of organising such trades that will determine the e¢ciency of the
competitive equilibrium.
s
The consumption in period s of a consumer ¡ tborn in
¢ period t is denoted xt
t+1
so that their utility level is given as U = U x t; x t . Such a consumer will
be referred to as belonging to generation t. It is assumed that the utility func-
tion satis…es limxtt!0 @@ xUt = limxt+1!0 @ t+1
U
= 1 so that the consumer strictly
t t @xt
desires consumption in both periods of their life. The consumer’s endowment,
which for a consumer of generation t is received entirely in period t, comprises
! tt units of the good. If prices p t and p t+1 hold in periods t and t + 1, the budget
404 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

constraint of the consumer is

p tx tt + p t+1 xt+
t
1
= p t !tt : (13.1)
pt
De…ning 1 + rt+1 = pt+1
, the budget constraint can be written in the alternative
form £ ¤
[1 + rt+1 ] !tt ¡ x tt ¡ x t+1
t = 0; (13.2)
which can be interpreted as saying that any savings out of the endowment earn
interest at rate rt+ 1 .
Generation t is de…ned as the set of consumers who are born in period
t. The population grows at rate n, so that if generation t is of size Ht then
Ht+1 = [1 + n] Ht . An allocation is feasible for the economy if consumption
by the two generations alive at each point in time is no greater than the total
endowment. At time t the consumption levels of the generations must satisfy

Ht¡ 1 xtt¡ 1 + Ht xtt = Ht! tt ; (13.3)

where equal treatment of the identical households in each generation has been
assumed. Using the assumed growth path of the population, (13.3) can be
written as £ ¤
[1 + n] !tt ¡ x tt ¡ x t+1
t = 0: (13.4)
From (13.4) a steady state equilibrium for the economy, in which the endowment
and the consumption levels are independent of t, is restricted to satisfy
£ ¤
[1 + n] ! 1 ¡ x 1 ¡ x2 = 0; (13.5)

where x 1 and x2 denote the steady state consumption levels in …rst and second
period of life and ! 1 is the constant …rst period endowment. From these equal-
ities can be proved the following theorem due to Samuelson (1958) and Gale
(1973).

Theorem 61 (Gale, Samuelson) There are at most two possible steady state
equilibria. Either (i) rt+1 = n all t or (ii) x1 = ! 1 all t.
£ ¤
Proof. In the steady state (13.2) reduces to [1 + r] ! 1 ¡ x 1 ¡ x2 = 0.
Contrasting with (13.5) proves the theorem.
It is interesting to note that there is actually no economic behaviour behind
Theorem 13.1 and that it is simply a consequence of the accounting constraints.
The economic implications follow from studying the welfare properties of the
two steady state equilibria.
Consider case (i) …rst. Assume that the steady state consumption levels
x 1 ; x2 chosen by the consumers when rt+1 = n all t yield less utility than an
alternative pair of stationary consumption levels x 1 ; x 2 . Revealed preference
implies that since x 1 ; x2 were chosen, x1 ; x 2 must be more costly so that, from
the budget constraint (13.2),
£ ¤
[1 + n] ! 1 ¡ x 1 ¡ x2 < 0: (13.6)
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 405

However, (13.6) implies that the pair x1 ; x 2 cannot satisfy (13.5) and hence must
be infeasible. It follows that rt+1 = n and the associated choices x 1 ; x 2 represent
a Pareto optimal outcome for the economy. The optimality of this equilibrium
has lead to it being termed the Golden rule path for the economy. Conversely,
the equilibrium in case (ii) with x1 = ! 1 is clearly not Pareto optimal. Given the
assumptions made about the form of the utility function, each consumer would
be willing to trade consumption in the …rst period of their life for consumption
in the second period at any …nite price.
Since there are two steady state equilibria with one strictly dominating the
other, it is now necessary to identify which will arise as an equilibrium of a com-
petitive economy. To sustain a market equilibrium with rt+1 = n it is necessary
that consumers are able to trade some of their endowment for consumption in
the second period of their life since rt+1 = n implies that the price of second
period consumption in terms of …rst period consumption is …nite. Such a trade
would require the household to form a contract which involved transferring con-
sumption in period t to a second party and receiving, from the same second
party, consumption in t + 1. Unfortunately, the only economic agents alive in
both period t and t + 1 are all members of the same generation and they are
all trying to enact the same trade. This absence of trading partners therefore
prevents the equilibrium rt+1 = n being sustained as a competitive outcome.
In contrast, the autarkic outcome x1 = ! 1 can be sustained as a competitive
equilibrium since, by default, it involves no trade. Implicitly, this equilibrium
requires the price of consumption in the second period of life relative to that in
the …rst period being in…nite or, equivalently, rt+1 = ¡1.
The Samuelson economy therefore leads to an outcome in which there exists
a single steady state equilibrium that can be supported by competitive behav-
iour and this equilibrium is not Pareto optimal. The existence of a competitive
equilibrium that is not Pareto optimal, in contradiction to the First Theorem of
Welfare Economics, is just one of a number of surprising features that overlap-
ping generations economies possess. Although the Samuelson economy forces
this equilibrium by preventing any possibility of all consumers simultaneously
transferring consumption from the …rst to the second period of their lives, the
same possibility will be shown to hold in more general economies below. In addi-
tion, only the steady state equilibria have so far been described. More attention
will be paid to non-steady state equilibria below.

13.2.2 Overlapping generations as Arrow-Debreu economies


It would not be unreasonable to suspect that the source of the failure of Pareto
optimality lay in the fact that the Samuelson economy in particular, and overlap-
ping generations economies in general, were of an entirely di¤erent nature to the
competitive Arrow-Debreu economy described in Chapter 2. Such di¤erences
could possibly stem from trades being enacted sequentially in the overlapping
generations in contrast to the completion of trades prior to economic activity
in the Arrow-Debreu economy. Alternatively, the restriction that consumers
conduct trades only during their own life-span may be felt to account for the
406 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

failure of optimality so that if consumers could trade in any period the inef-
…ciency would perhaps be removed. Two …nal possibilities may be that the
endowment pattern was responsible for the ine¢ciency or that the assumption
of identical consumers was responsible.
It will now be shown that none of these claims is justi…ed. This will be
achieved by setting out the structure of a general form of overlapping gener-
ations economy in an Arrow-Debreu format as in Balasko and Shell (1980).
Several features will be made more precise including specifying the time periods
over which the economy operates. Once this is done, it will be seen that the
overlapping generations economy is simply a special case of the Arrow-Debreu
economy in which there are an in…nite number of consumers and goods. Hence,
although the structure of the Samuelson economy was certainly responsible for
producing such stark …ndings, none of the assumptions was strictly necessary
for producing the ine¢ciency result.

The economy

In each time period t = 1; 2; 3; ::: of the economy there is a …nite number n of


goods, none of which can be stored. The consumers are indexed by their date
of birth. Each consumer lives for two periods so those born in period t are alive
during periods t and t + 1. At the start of the economy in period 1 there is a
generation, labelled generation 0, whose lives …nish at the end of period 1. To
provide some simpli…cation, each generation consists of a single consumer.
The consumption of commodity i by the consumer born in t during period s
s;i
is denoted by xt . The lifespans of the consumers are re‡ected in their prefer-
ences by assuming that the consumers only derive utility from consuming during
the periods they are alive. The utility of the³consumer born ´ at t is thus given
1;1 1;n
by Ut = Ut (x t), t = 0; 1; ::: with x0 = x10 = x 0 ; :::; x 0 for t = 0 and xt =
¡ t t+1 ¢ ³ t;1 ´
xt ; xt = x t ; :::; xt;n
t ; xt
t+1; 1
; :::; x t+1;n
t for t = 1; 2; :::. The utility function
is assumed to be strictly quasiconcave, di¤erentiable and all its …rst-order partial
derivatives are strictly positive. The indi¤erence curves are also assumed not to
cross any of the coordinate axes. Each consumer receives an endowment ³ in each ´
period they are alive. These endowments are denoted ! 0 = ! 10 = ! 1;1 0 ; :::; ! 1;n
0
¡ ¢ ³ ´
t;1 t; n t+ 1;1 t+1;n
for t = 0 and ! t = ! tt ; !t+ t
1
= ! t ; :::; !t ; !t ; :::; ! t for t =
1;
¡ 2; :::. The ¢ notation x0 is used to refer¡ tot both ¢the vector
¡ x 10 and the sequence ¢
1 t+1
x 0 ; 0; 0; ::: . Similarly, x t represents x t ; xt and 0; :::; 0; xtt ; x t+1
t ; 0; 0; ::: .
The same convention also applies to the endowments and to the demands de-
…ned below. ¡ ¢
The price
¡ 1 of2 good by p t;i so that p t = pt;1 ; :::; p t;n
¢ i in period t is represented 1;1
and p = p ; p ; ::: . The price normalisation p = 1 is employed. Using these
de…nitions of the prices, the demands of the consumer comprising generation 0
solve
¡ ¢
max U0 x 10 subject to p 1 x10 p 1 !10 = M 0 ; (13.7)
f x0 g
1
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 407

while those of generation t = 1; 2; ::: solve


¡ ¢
max Ut xtt ; xt+
t
1
subject to pt x tt + pt+1 x t+1
t p t! tt + p t+1 !t+
t
1
= Mt :
t+1
x t
f t t g
;x

¡ 1 ¢ (13.8)
These
¡ maximisations
¢ result in demand functions x 0 = x 0 p ; M 0 and xt =
x t p t; p t+1 ; Mt or, alternatively, x 0 = x0 (p; M 0 ) and x t = x t (p; Mt ). These
demand functions can be treated equally as mapping into either a vector or
a sequence. For instance, for t = 0 the demand maps either to x 10 or into
a sequence x 10; x 20 ; ::: with a positive entry for x10 alone. Given these demand
functions, a competitive equilibrium for the overlapping generations economy
can be de…ned.
Competitive equilibrium
A competitive
P equilibrium
P is a sequence p ; p ; ::: of strictly positive prices
1 2

such that t x t (p; Mt ) = t !t .


The proof of the existence of an equilibrium is sketched in the next section.

13.2.3 Existence of equilibrium


The proof of the existence of an equilibrium is of interest both in its own right
but also because of the insight it gives into the non-uniqueness of equilibrium.
A formal proof of existence will not be given here but instead a fairly detailed
description of the steps involved is provided.
The …rst step in the proof is to truncate the economy at period t and to
consider the existence of a solution to the equations

x 10 (¢) + x 11 (¢) = !10 + !11 ; (13.9)

x 21 (¢) + x 22 (¢) = !21 + !22 ; (13.10)


..
. (13.11)
xtt¡1 (¢) + xtt (¢) = ! tt¡1 + ! tt1 ; (13.12)
It should be clear that the solutions of (13.9) to (13.11), which is termed
the truncated economy E t, will determine a set of prices Pb with typical member
pt+1 . The equations must have a solution since adding the additional
pb1 ; pb2 ; :::; b
equation to (13.9) - (13.11) gives a set of equilibrium conditions for a t +1 period
Arrow-Debreu economy. As this extended set of equations must have a solution,
the reduced set certainly does. Thus any sequence of prices p = p 1 ; p 2 ; ::: can be
treated as an equilibrium for the t-period truncated economy provided it agrees
with some pb1 ; pb2 ; :::; b pt+1 from Pb in its …rst t + 1 elements. Alternatively, the
truncated economy determines the …rst t + 1 elements of a price sequence with
the remaining elements being indeterminate.
The next step is to provide upper and lower limits for possible equilibrium
prices. Assume that the endowment of each consumer is strictly positive. In
equilibrium each consumer must reach a level of utility at least equal to that of
their endowment and their maximum consumption level is limited by the total
408 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

endowment of the economy. The set of possible equilibrium consumptions for a


consumer is therefore given by the intersection of the set above the indi¤erence
curve through the endowment and below the total endowment. Since the indif-
ference curves of each consumer’s utility function do not cross the coordinate
axes, this set is compact and the set of possible gradients of the indi¤erence
curves through points in this set is also compact. Measuring the gradient rel-
ative to that of good 1, the desirability assumption implies that the gradients
are bounded above zero but are also …nite. Hence for each time period t there
is an lower bound ® t and an upper bound ¯ t on the gradient of the indi¤erence
curves and hence on the possible equilibrium prices.
The above reasoning shows that the equilibrium prices for the t-period trun-
cated economy E t belong to a compact set which is a subset of the possible
equilibrium prices for E t¡1 . As t tends to in…nity, a sequence of nonempty
compact sets is generated with each being a subset of the previous. Such an
in…nite sequence of sets has a nonempty intersection. An element of the in…nite
intersection is an equilibrium price system for the economy. This proves the
existence of an equilibrium.

Welfare properties
It has already been shown that the equilibrium of an overlapping generations
economy need not be Pareto optimal, even though it is characterised by compet-
itive behaviour and an absence of externalities or any other standard source of
market failure. The purpose of the present section is to formalise de…nitions of
Pareto optimality that are appropriate for in…nite economies and to characterise
Pareto optimal equilibria via the structure of the supporting price sequences.
Pareto optimality is usually tested by considering whether there exists any
reallocation of resources that can raise the welfare of one consumer without
reducing that of any other. In a …nite economy this is a su¢cient descrip-
tion. However, in an in…nite economy it is necessary to consider the number of
consumers that can be involved in any reallocation of resources. Searching for
improving allocations where only a …nite number of consumers can have their
allocation altered will clearly provide di¤erent results than allowing allocations
to be altered for an in…nite number of consumers. Accordingly, the distinction
is made between weak Pareto optimality and Pareto optimality as follows.
Pareto optimality
0 0
TheP allocation P fx 0 ; x 1 ; :::g is Pareto optimal if there is no allocation fx 0; x 1 ; :::g
with t x t = t x t , Ut (xt ) ¸ Ut (x t) all t and Ut0 (x t0 ) > Ut0 (xt0 ) for some t0 .
0 0 0

Weak Pareto optimality


The allocation Pfx0 ; x 1P ; :::g is weakly Pareto optimal if there is no allocation
fx00 ; x 01 ; :::g with t x t = t x 0t , xt = x0t for all but a …nite number of t, Ut (x 0t) ¸
Ut (x t ) all t and Ut0 (x 0t0 ) > Ut0 (xt0 ) for some t0.
To understand the distinction between these forms of optimality, consider
the following example from Shell (1971). Each consumer has a linear utility
function, so that utility is the sum of consumption levels in the two periods,
and each consumer is endowed with 1 unit of the single available good in each
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 409

period of life. The competitive equilibrium in this case must have consump-
tion equal to the endowment. Now consider a series of transfers in which the
consumer who is born in period 1 transfers their …rst period endowment to
the consumer who was born in period 0 and, in each successive period, the
consumer born in that period transfers their endowment to the consumer born
in the previous period. Compared to the competitive outcome, all consumers
born from period 1 onwards still attain a utility level of 2 but the consumer
born in period 0 has their utility raised from 1 to 2. The transfer has there-
fore achieved a Pareto improvement and the competitive equilibrium was not
Pareto optimal. In making this Pareto improvement, the allocation of an in…-
nite number of consumers has been changed. More importantly, it can easily
be seen that a Pareto improvement could not be made if only a …nite number
of consumers were involved in the reallocation. The competitive equilibrium is
therefore weakly Pareto optimal but not Pareto optimal.
The conclusions of this example will now be shown to be generally applicable.
That is, competitive equilibria will be shown to be weakly Pareto optimal but
not necessarily Pareto optimal. The …rst of these statements is proved in the
following theorem.

Theorem 62 (Balasko and Shell) Every competitive equilibrium is weakly Pareto


optimal and every weakly Pareto optimal allocation is a competitive equilibrium
allocation for a suitable assignment of endowments.
¡ ¢
Proof. Given an allocation x = fx 0 ; x1 ; :::g, the price sequence p = p 1 ; p 2 ; :::
is said to support the allocation x if and only if for all t = 0; 1; 2; ::: x t maximises
U t (¢) subject to px t Mt for some sequence of incomes M t .
It is easy to see that every competitive equilibrium allo cation x, with its
associated equilibrium price sequence p, is supported by p when the income
sequence is given by fMtg = fp! t g. Conversely, if an allocation x is supported
by a price sequence p, there exists a sequence of endowments f!t g such that x
is a competitive equilibrium and the equilibrium prices are given by p. To see
this, note that if p supports x then, from utility maximisation x t = xt (p; pxt ),
for t = 0; 1; 2; ::: . If the endowment sequence is chosen so that ! t = x t the
claim follows. Given these observations connecting competitive equilibria and
supporting price sequences, the proof is completed by showing that an allocation
is weakly Pareto optimal if and only if there exists a price sequence which
supports it.
To show that any allocation supported by a price sequence is weakly Pareto
optimal, let x be supported by p and assume that x is not weakly Pareto optimal.
Therefore, since weak Pareto optimality is concerned with allocations that di¤er
in only a …nite number of components, the assumption that x P is not weakly
P
Pareto optimal implies that there exists x0 with x 0t = x t for t ¸ t0 , t x0t = t xt
and Ut (x0t ) ¸ Ut (x t) with at least one strict inequality for t < t0 . From revealed
preference px0t = px t with strict inequality for at least one t < t0 . Hence
P t0¡1 0 Pt0 ¡1 P 0 P 0 0
t=0 px t = t=0 x t , contradicting t xt = t x t and xt = xt for t ¸ t .
410 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

Finally, it is necessary to show that an allocation x is weakly Pareto opti-


mal only if there exists a price sequence that supports it. It is obvious that an
allocation is weakly Pareto optimal if and only if the …rst t elements of the allo-
cation sequence are Pareto optimal for any truncated economy E t , t = 0; 1; 2; :::
. The allocation x 0 is uniquely supported in E 0 by p 1 = µrU0 (x 0 ) with µ
chosen so that p1;1 = 1. The argument is now completed by induction by show-
ing that, given unique supporting prices p1 ; p 2 ; :::; pt for x 0 ; :::; xt¡ 1 in E t¡1 ;
there exists a unique p t+1 such that p 1 ; p2 ; :::; p t+1 supports x 0 ; :::; xt in E t. As-
sume that p0t ; p 0t+1 support x t so that p0t ; p 0t+1 = ÁrU t (x¡t ) for some ¢ Á > 0.
Now since x0 ; :::; x t is Pareto optimal in E t , p 0t = °rUt ¢; xt+1 t with xt+
t
1

0t
¡ t¡ 1 ¢ t¡1
…xed and p = 'rUt¡1 xt¡ 1 ; ¢ with x t¡1 …xed. ¡ But,¢ by the assumption that
' t
p 1 ; p2 ; :::; p t supports x0 ; :::; x t¡1 , p t = rUt¡1 xt¡1t¡1 ; ¢ . Hence p 0t
= p . Now
de…ne p t+1 = ' p0t+ 1 . p 1; p 2 ; :::; p t+1 clearly supports x0 ; :::; x t in E t and the
proof is completed.
The characterisation of Pareto optimal allocations is somewhat more com-
plex than that of weakly Pareto optimal. To provide necessary and su¢cient
conditions requires considerable work. As a consequence, the theorem that is
proved below describes only su¢cient conditions. An informal description of
the necessary and su¢cient conditions is also given. To permit proof of the
theorem, a description of Pareto-improving sequences of feasible transfers is re-
quired. Let x be a given feasible allocation. The sequence h = (h 0 ; h 1 ; :::) is
aPfeasible sequence of commodity transfers if x + h is a feasible allocation and
t h t = 0. Since commodities can only be transferred between consumers who
are alive
¡ at the ¢ same
¡ t time, it follows
¢ that h0 = h10 = ¡h 11 and, for t 6= 0,
h t = htt ; ht+ t
1
= ¡h t¡1 ; ¡h t+1
t+1 . A sequence of transfers is Pareto improving
on the allocation x if Ut (x t + ht ) ¸ Ut (xt ) for all t and with strict inequality for
at least one t. The following theorem gives su¢cient conditions for an allocation
to be Pareto optimal.

Theorem 63 (Balasko and Shell) A weakly Pareto optimal allocation x sup-


ported by prices p is Pareto optimal if the sequence (x0 ; x 1 ; :::) is bounded from
above and lim inf t!1 kpt k = 0.

Proof. The …rst step in the proof is to show that if an element of a sequence
of Pareto improving transfers, from an initial weakly Pareto optimal position, is
positive at t = t0, it is positive for all t ¸ t0. To show this, assume P the converse.
Hence there exists t1 > t0 such that ht 1 = 0. Now, since t h t = 0, the
P t1 P
structure of transfers implies that t=t0 h t = 0 and t>t1 h t = 0. Therefore the
sequence ht = (0; :::; 0; ht0 ; :::; h t1 ; 0; :::; 0) would be feasible and U t (xt + h t) ¸
Ut (x t ) for all t = 0; 1; ::: . Due to strict quasiconcavity of utility, the sequence
(0; :::; 0; ¸h t0 ; :::; ¸h t1 ; 0; :::; 0), 0 < ¸ < 1, would be Pareto improving. This
sequence has only a …nite number of non-zero elements; a contradiction to the
supposition that the initial state was weakly Pareto optimal which establishes
the claim.
The second step is to show that the transfers involved in a Pareto improve-
ment can be ranked in terms of their values. In particular, it is now shown
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 411

that
p t+1 ht+ 1
t+ 1 p t htt ::: p 1 h 11 = ¡p1 h 11 = ¡p 1 h10 0;
with strict inequality for t ¸ t0 , t0 as de…ned above. To prove this, …rst note
that for generation £ 0, U
¤ 0 (x 0 + h 0 ) ¸ U 0 (x0 ) which, by revealed preference,
implies that p 1 x10 + h 10 ¸ p 1 x10 or p 1 h10 ¸ 0. For generation 1, p 1 h11 + p 2 h21 ¸ 0
so that p 2 h21 ¸ p1 h 11 . From the structure of transfers, h 11 = ¡h10 and h21 = ¡h 22
hence p 2 h22 p 1 h 11 = ¡p 1 h 10 0. This construction can be continued for all t
with strict inequality holding for t ¸ t0 .
The proof is completed by noting that (x0 x 1 ; :::) is bounded from above
and that lim inf t!1 kp t k = 0. Assume that there exists a Pareto improving
sequence of transfers. For such a set of transfers, it follows that for t ¸ t0 ,
p t h tt < p t0+1 h tt00+1 t0 t0
+1 < p h t0 . The assumed boundedness of (x 0 x1 ; :::) implies that
h t is also bounded and the assumption that lim inf t!1 kp tk = 0 implies that
t

lim inf t!1 kp th tt k = 0. This contradicts the preceding inequality and establishes
that under the conditions of the theorem the allocation x is Pareto optimal.
It should be noted how this result provides a characterisation of Pareto
optimality in terms of the price sequence that supports an allocation rather than
in terms of the allocation itself. The restriction that the sequence of allocations
is bounded above prevents the economy enjoying unlimited growth.
The result described in Theorem 13.3 is not the most general that is avail-
able. Since lim inf t!1 kp t htt k = 0 is a su¢cient condition for Pareto optimality,
it leaves open the possibility that there may be important cases in which this is
not satis…ed but which are Pareto optimal. After placing further regularity as-
sumptions upon the curvature and gradient of indi¤erence curves and bounding
feasible allocation sequences above and below, Balasko and Shell (1980) prove
the following.

Theorem 64 (Balasko P and Shell) A weakly Pareto optimal allocation x is Pareto


optimal if and only if t kp1tk = +1, where p is the price sequence that supports
x.

Proof. See Balasko and Shell (1980). P 1


It should be noted that lim inf t!1 kp t htt k = 0 implies t kpt k = +1 but
not the converse. For instance, in the Samuelson economy with no population
growth, so that n = 0, if trades could be organised the Pareto optimal equi-
librium
P 1 would be supported by the price sequence p = (1; 1; ::::) which satis…es
t t
t
t kp k = +1 but not lim inf t!1 kp ht = 0. This characterisation of Pareto
k
optimality will be employed further in the discussion of dynamics for overlapping
generations economies.

General demographic structure


The demographic structure of two-period lifetimes may seem unduly restrictive
and potentially responsible for some of the more surprising conclusions. How-
ever, this is not the case and, as shown by Balasko, Cass and Shell (1980), it
is possible to transform economies with more general demographic structures
412 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

into two-period economies by suitable relabelling. The restriction to two period


lives therefore involves no loss of generality.
The basis for this procedure is to distinguish between real calendar time
and (arti…cial) time used for labelling lifespans. Let calendar time be labelled
s = 0; 1; 2; ::: . At s = 0, out of the set of consumers alive at that time, the
consumer with the greatest future longevity is identi…ed. It is then assumed
that s = 0 represents the end of the …rst half of their life. The second half of
their life ends at their date of death, say s1 . Economic time is then constructed
so that t = 1 is associated with s1 . The same process is repeated at s 1: the
consumer with the greatest longevity is identi…ed and viewed as being at the
end of their …rst period of life. Their date of death, s2 , is then associated with
t = 2.
Proceeding in this way, the economic periods are constructed so the con-
sumers live at most two periods. It is possible that some may be born, for
instance, at a date s > 0 and die at s < s1 . Such consumers are regarded as
having single-period lifespans. The construction is completed by treating all
commodities available between s = 0 and s = s 1 as being traded at t = 1. This
is repeated for t = 2; ::: . Preferences are then de…ned over vectors of goods at
t and t + 1.

13.2.4 Money, dynamics and indeterminacy


As noted in the introduction, overlapping generations economies di¤er from
…nite economies in more ways than simply that their competitive equilibria
may be ine¢cient. Three of these further di¤erences are now brie‡y discussed.

Money
In a standard competitive economy that exists over a …nite number of periods,
…at money whose only use is as a store of value would be worthless. This
conclusion can be established by a simple backward induction argument. Money
is clearly worthless in the …nal period since it has no further use as a store of
value. Seeing that it is worthless in the last period, no consumer would wish to
purchase money in the second to last period so that it is also worthless in that
period. This argument can be continued backward until the beginning of the
economy. Money is therefore worthless unless it is arbitrarily assumed that it
must be used as a means of exchange.
This backward induction argument cannot be applied to the in…nite overlap-
ping generations economy and the possibility then arises that …at money may
have value. This can be shown most clearly by returning to the Samuelson
economy. The ine¢ciency in that economy arose because consumers have no
opportunity for turning their …rst-period endowment into second-period con-
sumption. Money provides such a possibility. As …rst shown by Samuelson
(1958), the introduction of money can permit the attainment of Pareto op-
timality provided that all generations believe money to be valuable and are
willing to accept money in exchange for goods.
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 413

Figure 13.2: E¢cient Allocation

This argument can be illustrated simply as follows. Assume that each con-
sumer is endowed with one unit of the single consumption good when young
and none when old and that if generation t has Ht identical members then
H t+1 = [1 + n] Ht . In each period the feasible allocations are given by

Ht x tt + Ht¡1 x tt¡1 = H t; (13.13)

or, in per capita terms,


x tt¡1
xtt + = 1: (13.14)
[1 + n]
From (13.13) the structure of the population ensures that the feasible allocation
to any individual must be constrained by

x t+1
xtt + t
= 1: (13.15)
[1 + n]

This constraint is shown in Figure 13.2. As already argued, the only competitive
equilibrium
¡ for
¢ this economy is the autarkic outcome with consumption alloca-
tion x tt; x t+1
t = (1; 0) whereas the e¢cient outcome is shown as the tangency
between indi¤erence curve and constraint (13.14) at point o.
Introducing money increases the set of potential trades consumers may make.
Suppose at time 0 a quantity of M units of money is divided equally between
those already alive (the generation who will be old in period 1) and that they
and all following generations believe this money to have value. In period t a
consumer then solves the maximisation
¡ ¢
max U xtt ; xt+1 t subject to pt = M td + p t xtt ; p t+1 x t+1
t = Mtd ; (13.16)
t+1
fx tt;xt g

where Mtd is money demand. This maximisation


³ ´ implies a demand function for
Mtd pt
real balances of the form pt = M pt+1 so that equilibrium on the money
414 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

market in period t requires


µ ¶
pt
Ht M pt = M : (13.17)
pt +1

Equating this to money demand in period t + 1, which must equal the same
stock, provides the equilibrium condition
µ ¶ µ ¶
pt pt pt+1
M = [1 + n] M : (13.18)
p t+1 p t+1 pt+2
p
At a steady state solution with p pt+1
t
= p t+1
t+2
´ 1 + ½, this equation is solved
when 1 + ½ = 1 + n. Combining the budget constraints in (13.15) and employing
the solution to (13.17) shows that at the steady state with 1 + ½ = 1 + n, each
consumer faces the budget constraint

x t+1 x t+1
x tt + t
= xtt + t = 1: (13.19)
[1 + ½] [1 + n]

The constraint in (13.18) is identical to (13.14). Faced with this budget con-
straint, each consumer will choose the e¢cient consumption point o. This ob-
servation demonstrates how the introduction of money that is valued allows
the decentralisation of the Pareto e¢cient outcome by extending the range of
allocations that can be sustained through competitive behaviour. It should be
noted that the discussion has been restricted to the steady state.
The fact that money can have value in an overlapping generations economy
is another surprising aspect of these economies. Equally surprising are the
potential e¢ciency gains from the introduction of a commodity with no actual
consumption value. Although money will not receive further analysis in the
chapters that follow, these observations provide an insight into the results that
can emerge. Further properties of monetary equilibria are discussed in Balasko
and Shell (1981) and Hahn (1982).

Dynamics
The analysis to this point has characterised the steady state solutions of the
Samuelson economy and investigated the existence and welfare properties of
equilibria for the generalised economy. The intention now is to consider the
possible dynamics of non-steady state solutions. The dynamics of overlapping
generations economies were …rst investigated by Gale (1973), who provided an
example of an economy with two period cycles, and then in detail by Grand-
mont (1985). The work of Grandmont revealed the potential complexity of the
dynamics that can arise.
The structure of dynamics can most easily be seen by considering a slightly
modi…ed version of the Samuelson economy. It is now assumed that there is a
single consumer in each generation and that an endowment is received in both
periods of life. In addition, the preferences of all consumers are identical and
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 415

can be represented by a utility function that is separable between consumption


in the …rst and second perio ds of life.
The budget constraint for each consumer is given by
£ ¤
[1 + rt+1 ] ! tt ¡ x tt + ! t+1
t ¡ x t+1
t = 0; (13.20)
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
so that maximisation of the utility function U xtt ; x t+1 t = U 1 (x tt ) + U 2 x t+1
t
results in the necessary condition
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 10 x tt ¡ [1 + rt+1 ] U 20 x t+1
t = 0: (13.21)

Eliminating [1 + rt+1 ] by using the budget constraint (13.19) reduces (13.20) to


£ t ¤ ¡ ¢ £ ¤ 20 ¡ t+1 ¢
! t ¡ x tt U 10 x tt + ! t+1
t ¡ x t+1
t U xt = 0: (13.22)

The aggregate feasibility condition for the economy requires that total consump-
tion does not exceed the total endowment or

! tt ¡ xtt + ! tt¡1 ¡ x tt¡1 = 0: (13.23)

Taken together, (13.21) and (13.22) fully describe the dynamic evolution
of the economy from any feasible initial starting value of x10 . Given x 10 , (13.22)
determines x11 and then, using the value of x11 , (13.21) determines x 21 . Returning
to (13.22), x22 can then be found. Repeating this process, whilst taking account
of nonnegativity constraints, provides the entire sequence of consumption levels
for the economy. Although some of the consumption patterns that will arise in
this dynamic process appear not to be feasible trades given what has been said
above, two modi…cations can overcome this objection. As noted by Gale (1973),
a …ctitious central clearing house could be introduced that can organise trades
that would not otherwise be possible. Alternatively, money could be introduced
with only minor modi…cation to the analysis.
The above argument provides a simple constructive approach to the dynam-
ics but it provides limited insight into the dynamic processes that may emerge;
for example it neither con…rms or refutes the possible existence of periodic cy-
cles. To proceed further in this direction, (13.22) can be used to substitute for
x tt in (13.21) giving
£ t ¤ ¡ ¢ £ ¤ 20 ¡ t+1 ¢
x t¡1 ¡ ! tt¡1 U 10 ! tt + !tt¡ 1 ¡ x tt¡1 + !t+
t
1
¡ xt+
t
1
U xt = 0: (13.24)

The structure of (13.23) is (implicitly) that of a nonlinear …rst-order di¤erence


equation relating xt+ t
1
to x tt¡1 . Hence given the consumption in the second
period of life for members of generation t ¡ 1, (13.23) determines the second
period consumption of generation t. First period consumption levels can then
be read from (13.22). If it is further assumed that all generations receive an
identical pattern of endowments, so that ! tt = ! 1 , ! t+1t = ! 2 all t, (13.23)
reduces to
£ t ¤ ¡ ¢ £ ¤ 20 ¡ t+1 ¢
x t¡1 ¡ ! 2 U 10 ! 1 + ! 2 ¡ x tt¡1 + ! 2 ¡ x t+1
t U xt = 0: (13.25)
416 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

The relevance of this assumption is that if xs+ 1 = xt+ 1 then xs = xt so that


s t s t
if the consumer of generation s has the same second period consumption as
that of t, they also have identical …rst period consumption. The structure
of the economy then ensures that generations s and t face identical nominal
variables and choose identical real variables. If such equivalence occurs every k
generations, the economy can be said to possess a cycle of period k.
The next step is to show that such cycles can actually¡occur. Gale ¢ (1973)
demonstrated that if the utility function has the form U x tt; x t+1 t = 10x t
t ¡
t+1 t+12
¡ t+1
¢
4xt2
t + 4xt ¡ x t and the endowment !t; !
t t = (0; 2) then there exists a
p p
5¡ 5 5+ 5
cycle of period 2 with consumption levels x tt = 6 = x t+2 t+1
t+2 , x t+1 = 6 =
t+3
x t+3 . One of the interesting features of such a cycle is that it is driven entirely
by equilibrium behaviour under certainty and is not the consequence of random
shocks hitting the economy or of false expectations.
Now return to (13.24). Theorem 13.1 shows that (13.24) has two steady state
solutions, that is there are two values of x tt¡1 such that xtt¡ 1 = x t+1 . Hence,
¡ t t+1
¢ ¡t t ¢
if the locus of pairs of x t¡1 ; x t that solve (13.24) are drawn in x t¡1 ; xt+1 t
space, the locus must cross the 45 o line twice. The gradient of the locus can be
calculated as £ £ ¤¤
dxt+
t
1
U 10 1 ¡ A1 ! 2 ¡ x tt¡1
= 20 £ £ ¤¤ ; (13.26)
dxtt¡ 1 U 1 ¡ A2 x t+1 t ¡ !1
i00
where Ai = ¡ UU i0 is the coe¢cient of absolute risk aversion in period i of life.
At the autarkic steady state with consumption equal to the endowment the
10
gradient is equal to UU 20
> 0. The locus therefore cuts the 45 o line from below
at the autarkic steady state and hence must cut it from above at the Pareto
e¢cient steady state.
If the second period endowment is su¢ciently low that the e¢cient steady
state level of second period consumption is greater than the endowment, then
the locus of solutions to (13.24) will appear as in Figure 13.3. Point a denotes
the autarkic equilibrium and b the e¢cient steady state. In particular, if the
second period endowment is 0 then the autarkic steady state will be the origin.
Starting with a value of x10 on the horizontal axis, x 21 can be found on the
vertical axis by reading o¤ the graph of the curve. Translating this value through
the 45 o line back onto the horizontal axis then allows x32 to be plotted on
the vertical. In this way, the dynamics of consumption in second-period of
life for each generation of consumers can be traced on the diagram. There
is a signi…cant mathematical literature on systems that have the form shown
in Figure 13.3 and only a sketch of the most important will be given here.
Further details of the mathematics can be found in Collet and Eckmann (1980)
and simple surveys are given in Baumol and Benhabib (1989) and Boldrin and
Woodford (1990).
The possible forms of dynamic behaviour that the system may display can
be placed into four general categories. These are:
1. Convergence
The system may converge to a steady state.
13.2. OVERLAPPING GENERATION EXCHANGE ECONOMIES 417

Figure 13.3: Dynamic Solution

2. Convergence to a cycle
After an initial period the system settles down to a cycle in which the same
points are visited after speci…c intervals. An example of an economy with a
cycle of period 2 has already been described.
3. Non-cyclical
Here the system never returns to the same point twice. The system may
simply be erratic or it may be drawn to a strange attractor in which case it
becomes arbitrarily close to some cycle.
4. Chaotic
In the case of chaos the system never returns to the same point and has
sensitive dependence on initial conditions. That is, two solution paths that start
at two initial points an " apart will, after a …nite time, be a signi…cant distant
apart. This has the implication that such a system cannot be investigated by
numerical simulation since rounding errors will be su¢cient to invalidate the
analysis.
To delineate conditions under which each of these would arise requires con-
siderable further formalisation which is not worth undertaking here. However,
two further points are worth noting. Firstly, if for some starting point the sys-
tem has a cycle of period 3, then starting points can be found that will give a
cycle of any desired order. This is an implication of Sarkovskii’s Theorem : if a
system has a cycle of period 3, it has cycles of all orders. Grandmont (1985)
actually provides conditions under which such a cycle exists in an overlapping
generations economy. Secondly, it is di¢cult to determine if an observed chaotic
times series is generated by a deterministic system or is actually random.
There are two important conclusions that follow from this discussion. The
…rst is economies may be constructed whose dynamics that reproduce the prop-
erties of observed economic time series. Observed series generate cyclical behav-
iour of fairly stable periodicity. Such cycles can be generated by few economies
other than the overlapping generations economy, except for exceptional sets of
parameter values. This gives the overlapping generations economy an important
role in the analysis of business cycles. Secondly, the fact that the economy can
418 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

generate endogenous cycles provides a natural motivation for counter-cyclical


policy. The policy implications of these dynamics have been investigated in
detail by Grandmont (1985).
In the context of policy reactions to cycles it may seem surprising to note
that the cycles, with the exception of the autarkic 1-cycle, are actually Pareto
optimal. The argument behind this conclusion is the observation that if the
economy is cyclical equilibrium prices must also be cyclical. During the time
span of the economy the samePprices must therefore be repeated an in…nite
number of times. This implies t kp1t k = +1, hence the cycle must be Pareto
optimal.

Indeterminacy
A theorem of Debreu (1970) shows that almost all competitive economies of the
form described in Chapter 2 have a …nite number of isolated equilibria so that
each equilibrium is locally unique. That a similar conclusion does not apply to
overlapping generations economies has been shown by Gale (1973), Geanakop-
los and Polemarchakis (1984) and Kehoe and Levine (1985). For overlapping
generations economies robust examples can be constructed that have a contin-
uum of equilibria so that both …niteness and local uniqueness do not apply.
Such indeterminacy imposes considerable problems for analysis. Comparative
statics exercises are not possible and the concept of perfect foresight along such
indeterminate paths is implausible. The introduction of money compounds the
problem by introducing a further dimension to the indeterminacy.
The problem of indeterminacy is inherent in all applications of overlapping
generations economies. It is sidestepped in the chapters that follow, as well as
in much of the literature, by focusing only upon steady states. As has already
been shown, there are just two steady states for the Samuelson economy and in
the aggregate production economy discussed next it is possible for there to be
a unique steady state.

13.2.5 Summary
This section has described the overlapping generations economy and has illus-
trated a number of the important properties that such economies possess. In
contrast to standard competitive economies, the equilibria of an overlapping
generations economy need not be Pareto optimal, though all are weakly Pareto
optimal, and there may be an uncountable in…nity of equilibria. Furthermore,
…at money can play a socially useful role in leading to the attainment of a Pareto
optimum and, consequently, may be valued.
These features of overlapping generations economies undermine many of the
presumptions developed from analysis of standard competitive economies. Due
to this, it has proved an important tool in the study of public economics. The
version of the overlapping generations economy that will be employed in the
following chapters is less general than that described in this section but the
results here provide the foundation of the analysis.
13.3. AN AGGREGATE PRODUCTION ECONOMY 419

13.3 An aggregate production economy


The overlapping generations economies described above involved no production
but only exchange of commodities. Each generations of consumers received
their endowment and then traded. In contrast, the overlapping generations
economy described in Diamond (1965) introduced a production process that
involved both capital and labour. This extension permits the analysis of many
interesting topics, including the assessment of the e¢ciency of choice of capital-
labour ratio.
In the Diamond economy each consumer again lives for just two periods.
They work only during the …rst period of their life and inelastically supply
one unit of labour. This unit of labour is their entire endowment. In their
second period of life they are retired and supply no labour. Income earned by
a consumer during the …rst period of their life is divided between consumption
and savings. Second period consumption is equal to savings plus accumulated
interest. With the exception of their date of birth, all consumers are identical.
At each date is born a cohort of consumers and the population grows at a
constant rate.
The economy has a single consumption good which is produced using capital
and labour. Available capital consists of a stock of the single good and is gener-
ated by the savings of the previous period. Capital does not depreciate during
the production process. The production function exhibits constant returns to
scale. The level of production is chosen so as to maximise pro…ts. Finally, all
markets are competitive. The existence of capital as a store of value allows
consumers to carry purchasing power from one period to the next.

13.3.1 Consumers
All consumers have identical preferences which, for the consumer born in period
t , are represented by the utility function
¡ ¢
U = U x tt; x t+1
t ; (13.27)

where x tt is the consumption level of the single good when the consumer is young
and x t+1
t consumption when old. There is no disutility from labour supply.
To construct the budget constraint of a typical consumer, note that labour
income must be divided between consumption and savings and that each con-
sumer supplies one unit of labour. With the price of the consumption good in
period t denoted p t , consumption and savings, s t, must satisfy

W t = p t xtt + p ts t; (13.28)

where W t is the wage received for the single unit of labour. The value of second
period consumption must be equal to the value of savings, hence

p t+1 x t+1
t + p ts t: (13.29)
420 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

Combining (13.27) and (13.28) and de…ning the interest rate by

p t ¡ p t+1
rt+1 = ; (13.30)
p t+1

the budget constraint becomes

Wt x t+1
´ w t = x tt + t
; (13.31)
pt 1 + rt+1

where w t is the real wage. Employing the de…nition of the interest rate also gives
x t+1
t = [1 + rt+1 ] st . Note that the relevant interest rate is rt+ 1 since interest is
notionally paid in period t + 1.
From (13.26) and (13.29) the utility-maximising consumption plan satis…es
the …rst-order condition
¡ ¢
U1 x tt; x t+1
t
¡ ¢ = [1 + rt+1 ] : (13.32)
U2 x tt; x t+1
t

Equation (13.30) relates the intertemporal marginal rate of substitution to the


rate of transformation and is a simple extension of the standard condition for op-
timal choice. The simultaneous solution of (13.30) and (13.29) provides demand
functions of the form

x t+i
t = x t+i
t (wt ; rt+1 ) ; i = 0; 1: (13.33)

13.3.2 Production
The productive sector of the economy is described by an aggregate production
function
Y t = F (Kt ; Lt ) ; (13.34)
where K t is the capital stock in period t and Lt aggregate labour supply. Since
each young consumer inelastically supplies one unit of labour, Lt = Ht. The
production function can either be interpreted literally as representing the tech-
nology of a single …rm or as the aggregate production function of a set of identi-
cal …rms. A formal demonstration of such an aggregation argument is given in
Sargent (1979). As capital does not depreciate, consumption and saving must
satisfy
F (Kt ; Lt ) + Kt = Htx tt + Ht¡1 x tt¡1 + Ht st : (13.35)
The production function therefore gives net output not including the non-
depreciating capital.
It is assumed that F (K t; Lt ) satis…es constant returns to scale and is there-
fore homogeneous of degree 1 so that F (º Kt ; ºLt ) = ºF (Kt ; Lt) for all positive
º . As the size of the population is growing at rate n, what matters as a measure
of the output of the economy is not total output but output per head. The ho-
mogeneity of production permits the analysis to be phrased in these terms. To
13.3. AN AGGREGATE PRODUCTION ECONOMY 421

Lt
see this, set º = Lt
in (13.33) and use the homogeneity to extract the numerator
of º. This gives
µ ¶ µ ¶ µ ¶
1 1 Kt Kt
Y t = Lt F Kt ; Lt = Lt F ;1 = Lt f : (13.36)
Lt Lt Lt Lt

Now de…ne
Yt Kt
yt = ; kt = : (13.37)
Lt Lt
Then output per unit of labour is determined by a function that has the capital-
labour ratio as its sole argument

y t = f (kt ) : (13.38)

As the labour market is competitive, pro…t maximisation in the choice of


labour by …rms implies that the marginal product of labour must be equated to
the real wage. The marginal product of labour is derived by noting that
µ ¶
Kt
Y t = Lt f ; (13.39)
Lt

so that
µ ¶ µ ¶
@yt Kt Kt Kt
=f ¡ L tf 0 = f (kt ) ¡ kt f 0 (kt ) : (13.40)
@L t Lt Lt L2t

The optimum choice of labour therefore satis…es

wt = f (kt ) ¡ kt f 0 (kt) : (13.41)

Similarly, the optimum choice of capital equates the rate of interest to the
marginal product
rt = f 0 (kt ) : (13.42)

13.3.3 Equilibrium
At the equilibrium it is necessary that consumers maximise utility, …rms max-
imise pro…t and all markets clear. For capital market equilibrium, the relevant
condition is that capital used must be equal to the level of savings, since capital
is the only store of wealth. To derive the capital market equilibrium condition,
…rst note that the population of young consumers is of size Ht in period t, so
the equality of total savings with capital available in period t + 1 implies that
£ ¤
Ht wt ¡ x tt = Kt+1 : (13.43)

Dividing through (13.41) by Ht , recalling that Ht+1 = Ht [1 + n] and Ht = Lt ,


gives
wt ¡ x tt = kt+1 [1 + n] : (13.44)
422 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

When equation (13.42) is satis…ed, there is equilibrium in the capital market.


Collecting equations, the equilibrium evolution through time of the economy
is determined as the simultaneous solution to
¡ ¢
U1 x tt; x t+1
t
¡ ¢ = [1 + rt+1 ] ; (13.45)
U2 x tt; x t+1
t

xt+ 1
w t = x tt + t
; (13.46)
1 + rt+1

wt = f (kt) ¡ ktf 0 (kt ) ; (13.47)

rt = f 0 (kt) ; (13.48)

and
w t ¡ xtt = kt+1 [1 + n] : (13.49)

These equilibrium equations can be used to provide a simple description


of the evolution of the capital stock through time which can then be used to
generate the time paths of the other endogenous variables. To do this recall that
the simultaneous solution of (13.43) and (13.44) provides demand functions of
the form
x t+i
t = x t+i
t (wt ; rt+1 ) ; i = 0; 1: (13.50)

From the determination of w t described in (13.45), and from stepping (13.46)


one period forward, it follows from substitution into the demand function that

x tt = x tt (f (kt ) ¡ kt f 0 (kt) ; f 0 (kt)) : (13.51)

Now substituting (13.49) into the capital market equilibrium equation (13.47)
gives the …nal expression

f (kt ) ¡ kt f 0 (kt ) ¡ xtt (f (kt ) ¡ kt f 0 (kt ) ; f 0 (kt+1 )) = kt+1 [1 + n] : (13.52)

Equation (13.50) has as its only arguments the capital-labour ratio in periods
t and t + 1 and it represents the basis for studying the dynamic equilibrium of
the economy. Assuming that (13.50) can be solved for kt+1 in terms of kt , the
relation can be written
kt+1 = º (kt) : (13.53)

The intertemporal evolution of the capital-labour ratio is summarised in (13.51)


in the sense that it determines kt+ 1 for given kt . As with (13.23), (13.51) is a
nonlinear …rst-order di¤erence equation and the potential dynamics that were
discussed in connection with that equation are again relevant here.
To analyse (13.51) …rst assume that, for all kt ,
¯ ¯
¯ @kt+1 ¯
¯ ¯ (13.54)
¯ @k ¯ < 1;
t
13.3. AN AGGREGATE PRODUCTION ECONOMY 423

Figure 13.4: Stable Convergence to the Steady State

which, after implicitly di¤erentiating (13.50), will hold if


¯ h @xt i ¯
¯ t
¡ 1 kt f 00 ¯¯
¯ @w t
¯ ¯ < 1: (13.55)
¯ t ¯
¯ 1 + n + @@rxt+1
t
f 00 ¯

In this case, if the system given by (13.50) has a stationary solution with kt =
kt+ 1 = k all t, it will be globally stable. That is, if there is a …xed point such
that

f (k) ¡ kf 0 (k) ¡ xtt (f (k) ¡ kf 0 (k) ; f 0 (k)) = k [1 + n] ; (13.56)

then the system will always converge to k regardless of the initial level of the
capital stock. A stable system of this form is illustrated Figure 13.4.
The system in Figure 13.4 also has the property that the º (kt) function is
monotonically increasing. This may be a reasonable restriction and it certainly
rules out many forms of badly-behaved solution. Su¢cient conditions for the
function º (kt ) to be increasing in kt are that
@x t @ xt+1
a ) @ wtt > 0; @ twt > 0,
and t
@xt
b) @rt+1 < 0.
Condition (a ) is the requirement that both goods are normal. The impor-
@xt
tance of (a) is that it implies @wtt < 1. Together conditions (a ) and (b) guarantee
that the numerator and denominator of (13.53) are positive. Of course further
restrictions are needed to ensure that the derivative is less than 1.
Alternatively assume that for some values of kt
¯ ¯
¯ @kt+1 ¯
¯ ¯ (13.57)
¯ @k ¯ > 1;
t

and that º (kt ) is …rst increasing and then decreasing with a unique maximum
which can occur if second period consumption is inferior. This provides the
424 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

hump-shaped relationship of Figure 13.3 and permits the possibility of the com-
plex dynamics discussed following that …gure. The Diamond economy can there-
fore potentially generate convergent, cyclical, non-cyclical and chaotic behaviour
in the capital-labour ratio and hence in output per head.

13.3.4 Steady State Solution


Although the dynamic solution is of much potential interest, the focus of most
analyses of overlapping generations economies in public economics has been
placed upon steady state equilibria. A steady state is the situation in which the
economy repeats itself period after period in the sense that the capital-labour
ratio, the output-labour ratio and the interest rate are constant over time. The
steady state is typically interpreted as constituting the long-run equilibrium
for the economy. The typical policy analysis characterises the steady state
and performs comparative statics exercises as the policy variables are modi…ed.
Such exercises will be the subject matter of Chapters 14 and 15. The present
concern is the characterisation of the steady state and the analysis of its welfare
properties.
Since all nominal variables and per capita variables are constant in the steady
state, the time subscripts are now dropped. Denoting the steady state value of
the capital-labour ratio by k and the interest rate by r, the budget constraint
can be written
x2
x1 + = w; (13.58)
1+r
where x1 and x 2 are …rst- and second-period consumption levels. Using the facts
that w = f (k) ¡ kf 0(k) and r = f 0 (k), the budget constraint can be written

x2
x1 + = f (k) ¡ kf 0 (k): (13.59)
1 + f 0 (k)

From capital market equilibrium

w ¡ x 1 = [1 + n] k; (13.60)

or
f (k) ¡ kf 0(k) ¡ x 1 = [1 + n] k: (13.61)
The points to be made about the properties of the steady state can be derived
from using (13.59) to eliminate x 1 from (13.57). Di¤erentiating the equation
obtained gives
dk 1
= > 0; (13.62)
dx 2 [1 + n] [1 + f 0 + kf 00 ]
under the assumption that 1 + f 0 + kf 00 > 0: It is therefore
¡ ¢ possible to solve for
k as a function of x 2 . This solution is denoted k = k x 2 . The next step is to
substitute the solution for k into (13.59) to give
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
f(k x 2 ) ¡ k x 2 f 0(k x 2 ) ¡ x 1 = [1 + n] k x2 : (13.63)
13.3. AN AGGREGATE PRODUCTION ECONOMY 425

Figure 13.5: Consumption Possibility Locus

¡ 1 2¢
The solutions to equation (13.61) generates a locus of¡ pairs ¢ x ; x termed
the consumption possibility frontier and, using k = k x 2 , an implied value
of k. Each point on this frontier is potentially a steady state with the actual
steady state that arises as the competitive equilibrium being determined by
consumer preferences. There are basic economic reasons for expecting the locus
to describe a non-monotonic relationship between x1 and x2 . For low values of
x 2 the capital-labour ratio is also low so that total production, and hence x1 ,
must also be small. As x 2 increases the capital-labour ratio grows and permits
x 1 to rise. Eventually, the capital-labour ratio will become too large and x1 will
again fall. As an example, for the Cobb-Douglas production function

f (k) = k ®; 0 < ® < 1; (13.64)


the locus has the shape shown in Figure 13.5.
The importance of this construction is the following interpretation. The
long-run steady state will generate some ¡ value¢ of k as the equilibrium of the
economy. This value of k implies a pair x 1 ; x2 on the consumption possibility
locus. The question then arises as to whether
¡ the
¢ k determined in this manner,
or equivalently the consumption pair x 1 ; x2 , has any e¢ciency properties.
That is, are some values of k preferable to others and, if so, will the economy
have an optimal value of k as its equilibrium? The answers to these questions
are considered next.

13.3.5 Golden rules


It is possible to de…ne the optimal value of k in a number of ways. The simplest
is to view the optimum as the level of the capital-labour ratio that maximises
per capita consumption in the steady state. The relation that this level of
capital satis…es is termed the Golden rule and the resulting capital-labour ratio
is the Golden rule level. The analysis of the Golden rule is undertaken in 3.5.1.
Alternatively, optimality can be de…ned in terms of the maximisation of a social
426 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

welfare function. When the social welfare function is chosen as a discounted


sum of utilities, the modi…ed Golden rule is obtained. This is derived in 3.5.2.
Such rules are important throughout the economic theory of economic growth.

The Golden rule


This section considers the maximisation of consumption per period or, equiva-
lently, consumption per capita, a procedure that leads to the Golden rule level
of the capital-labour ratio. The following section will relate the Golden rule to
Pareto optimality and dynamic e¢ciency.
The objective of the central planner is

max x tt Ht + xtt¡1 Ht¡ 1 ; (13.65)

Ht
which, since Ht¡ 1 = 1+ n
, can be expressed in per capita terms as

x tt¡1
max xtt + :
1+ n
Since the maximisation will be restricted to the choice between steady states,
(13.64) reduces to
x2
max x 1 + : (13.66)
1+n
The constraint facing the central planner is that consumption in any period
must be equal to total output less additions to the capital stock. Hence

xtt Ht + xtt¡ 1 Ht¡1 = Htf (kt) ¡ Ht [kt+1 [1 + n] ¡ kt ] :

At a steady state equilibrium (13.66) reduces to

x2
x1 + = f (k) ¡ nk: (13.67)
1+n
The optimisation in (13.65) is therefore equivalent to maxfkg f (k) ¡ nk. From
this maximisation the …rst-order condition

f 0 (k) ¡ n = 0: (13.68)

is obtained. Hence the optimal k, k¤ , should be chosen such that

f 0 (k¤ ) = n: (13.69)

The capital-labour ratio k¤ is termed the Golden rule capital-labour ratio and
it is the optimal ratio in the sense that it maximises consumption per head.
Returning to the competitive economy, since f 0 = r, if the competitive
economy reaches a steady state equilibrium with r = n, this equilibrium will
satisfy the Golden rule. Since no other equilibrium will, this identi…es r = n
as the Golden rule rate of interest. To understand the structure of the Golden
13.3. AN AGGREGATE PRODUCTION ECONOMY 427

Figure 13.6: Golden Rule Competitive Equilibrium

rule competitive equilibrium, (13.57) and (13.59) can be used to show that the
gradient of the consumption possibility locus is given by

dx1 kf 00 + 1 + n
2
= : (13.70)
dx [1 + n] [1 + f 0 + kf 00 ]

dx1
When f 0 = n, (13.70) reduces to dx2 = 1
1+n . When facing a rate of interest
U1(x1 ;x2)
r = n consumer maximisation implies that U2(x1 ;x2) = 1 + n. Therefore at the
Golden Rule the consumers’ budget constraints, maximal indi¤erence curves and
the consumption possibility locus have identical gradients. This is illustrated in
Figure 13.6.

The modi…ed Golden rule

The modi…ed Golden rule is derived by choosing the growth path of the economy
to maximise a social welfare function de…ned as the discounted sum of future
utilities. This social welfare function is denoted by
1
X ¡ ¢
°t U x tt; x t+1
t : (13.71)
t=0

Although the size of population in each generation does not enter explicitly into
(13.71), it can be incorporated via the de…nition of the discount factor °.
The objective of the social planner is to maximise (13.71) subject to the pro-
duction constraint upon the economy which is summarised in (13.66). Dividing
through by Ht , (13.66) becomes

xtt¡ 1
kt + f (kt ) = [1 + n] kt+1 + x tt + : (13.72)
1+n

Substituting into (13.71) for xs¡ 1 s


s¡ 1 and xs using (13.72), social welfare can be
428 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

written
1
X s¡2
X
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
°t U xtt ; x t+1
t = ° tU x tt ; x t+1
t
t=0 t=0
à !
s¡1
x
+° s¡1 U ks¡1 + f (ks¡1 ) ¡ [1 + n] ks ¡ s¡2 ; xss¡ 1
1+n
µ ¶
xs
+° sU ks + f (ks ) ¡ [1 + n] ks+ 1 ¡ s¡1 ; xs+1
1+n s
X1
¡ ¢
+ ° tU x tt ; x t+1
t : (13.73)
t=s+ 1

From (13.73) the optimal choice of x ss¡1 and ks is determined by


¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
s¡1
@U x s¡1 s
s¡1 ; x s¡1 ° s @U x ss; x s+1
s
° ¡ = 0; (13.74)
@x ss¡1 1+n @x ss

and
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
s¡1
@U x s¡1 s
s¡1 ; x s¡1 @U xss ; xs+
s s
1
¡° [1 + n] + ° [1 + f 0 ] = 0: (13.75)
@x s¡1
s¡1
@xss

Along the optimal growth path, (13.74) and (13.75) must hold for all values of
s.
Moving to the steady state, (13.74) and (13.75) become
°
U2 ¡ U 1 = 0; (13.76)
1+n
and
1 + n = ° [1 + f 0 ] : (13.77)
Equation (15.77) is the modi…ed Golden rule which relates the optimal
capital-labour ratio to the rate of population growth and the discount factor.
Since social welfare de…ned by (13.71) is only properly de…ned if ° < 1, the
modi…ed Golden rule results in a lower capital-labour ratio than the standard
Golden rule. This is due to the impatience implied by the discounting leading
to higher consumption in the present and less accumulation. The interpretation
of (13.76) is that the steady state must involve optimal intertemporal alloca-
tion of consumption for each consumer when faced with an implied interest rate
°
satisfying 1 + r = 1+n .

13.3.6 Pareto optimality


Having now characterised the Golden rule capital-labour ratio and correspond-
ing rate of interest, it is possible to relate this to the question of Pareto op-
timality. To do this, …rst note that if k > k¤ then r < n. The converse is
13.4. CONCLUSIONS 429

true if k < k¤ . This is a simple consequence of the concavity of the production


function. These two cases will now be discussed in turn, beginning with k > k¤ .
A capital-labour ratio above k¤ represents an economy that has over-accumulated
along the growth path. In such an economy it would be feasible for the con-
sumers alive in any period with k > k ¤ to consume some of the existing capital
stock so as to reduce the stock to the level k ¤ . Such consumption would have
two consequences. It would raise the welfare of the existing generations because
it increases their present consumption at no cost. Secondly, it would raise the
welfare of all following generations because it would place the economy on the
Golden rule path and would consequently maximise their consumption. Thus,
such consumption of the excess of the capital stock above the Golden rule level
would lead to a Pareto improvement. Therefore, any steady state with k > k ¤
and r < n is not Pareto optimal. Such states are called dynamically ine¢cient.
When k k¤ no such Pareto improvements can be found. Any act of invest-
ment that raises the welfare of the following generations must be undertaken at
a cost to the existing generations in foregone consumption. Therefore all such
states, including the Golden rule and modi…ed Golden rule states, are Pareto
optimal and are termed dynamically e¢cient.
The importance of this discussion is that when r < n the equilibrium is
not Pareto optimal despite the economy satisfying all the standard competitive
assumptions. To illustrate that the failure of Pareto optimality does not require
an unusual structure to be placed on the economy, consider the following exam-
ple from Diamond (1965). The utility function of the single consumer in each
generation is given by
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U x tt; x t+1
t = ¯ log xtt + [1 ¡ ¯] log x t+1
t ; (13.78)

and the production function is y = Ak® . The steady state interest then can be
calculated to be
® [1 + n]
r= : (13.79)
[1 ¡ ¯] [1 ¡ ®]
This will only be equal to the Golden rule rate when
®
n= : (13.80)
[1 ¡ ¯] [1 ¡ ®] ¡ ®

If preferences and production do not satisfy this condition, and there is no


reason why they should, the economy will not grow on the Golden rule growth
path. This example illustrates that a Golden rule economy will be the exception
rather than the norm.

13.4 Conclusions
Overlapping generations economies have a number of interesting features that
are not shared with standard Arrow-Debreu economies. The competitive equi-
libria can be ine¢cient, complex endogenous dynamics can be generated, …at
430 CHAPTER 13. OVERLAPPING GENERATIONS ECONOMIES

money may be valuable as a store of value and its existence can raise the level
of welfare and indeterminacy in equilibria may exist. In the context of public
economics, it is the …rst of these that is arguably the most important since it
provides a role for corrective policies in the absence of any additional market
failure.
More importantly, the structure of the economy permits the analysis of the
e¤ects of policies that are essentially intertemporal in nature. This will be
utilised in the analysis of social security in Chapter 14 and debt and taxation in
Chapter 15. In both cases, the nature of ine¢ciency in overlapping generations
economies and the structure of Golden rules will be central in explaining the
results of policy analysis.
Chapter 14

Social Security

14.1 Introduction
The provision of social security to provide cover against disability and the inabil-
ity to work due to old age is a feature of all developed economies. Such programs
are large, both in terms of the proportion of population receiving bene…ts and in
terms of the total payments as a proportion of national income. The programs
are not without their di¢culties. Thompson (1983) describes the adjustments
made to the US program following overly optimistic forecasts of real earnings
growth. The expected increase in the ratio of retired to employed due to greater
life expectancy will also place the system under pressure. There is also evidence,
see Kotliko¤ (1989), that social security programs are required due to the inad-
equate savings and insurance purchases of the elderly which would not support
them through retirement. These observations show that the analysis of social
security and its economic impact is a subject of practical importance.
The …rst issue in the analysis of social security is its e¤ect upon the equi-
librium of the economy and, particularly, upon the level of the capital stock.
If a social security program has the form of a forced saving program, so that
consumers are provided with greater second period earnings than they would
naturally choose, then the program may raise the capital stock. This outcome
will be bene…cial in an undercapitalised economy. Conversely, if the program
simply transfers earnings from those who are working to those who are retired,
savings and hence the level of capital may fall. It can be judged from the di¤er-
ence in outcomes of these simple scenarios that the consequence of the existence
of social security is closely dependent upon the program’s structure. In addi-
tion to its e¤ects on savings, the interaction between social security and the
retirement decision may also be signi…cant.
A second major issue that arises is the e¤ect of demographic change upon
the social security program. Present trends are for the proportion of retired
consumers to increase and for the retired to live longer. At a practical level,
this raises the question of whether the working population can continue to fund

431
432 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

social security. A related, but more theoretical issue, is the question of whether
there exists an optimal rate of population growth. This issue arises from the ob-
servation that if the rate of population growth increases, there are more workers
to support each retired consumer but the level of capital per worker is reduced.
This trade-o¤ suggests there may be an optimal growth rate.
The introduction of a social security program results in a transfer of re-
sources towards the generation that bene…ts on the introduction of the program
and away from later generations. This raises the question of how such a program
receives the support that is required for it to be introduced at all. The mech-
anism by which the level of bene…ts in the program are selected also needs to
be addressed. Furthermore, the reasons why the private sector cannot provide
insurance cover on terms at least as attractive as those o¤ered by social security
must also be addressed.
This chapter begins by setting out the important distinction between fully
funded and pay-as-you-go social security. The economic e¤ects of these two polar
forms of program are markedly di¤erent. An optimal social security program is
then characterised under the strong assumptions of certainty and …xed labour
supply. A number of extensions of the basic result are considered including
an analysis of optimal population growth. Determination of the level of social
security by majority voting and various justi…cations for social security are
then considered including altruism, myopia and aggregate uncertainty. The
…nal section analyses the e¤ect of introducing individual uncertainty about the
length of life.

14.2 Fully funded and pay-as-you-go


The …nancing of social security can have important implications for the eco-
nomic e¤ects of the program and for its sustainability in the face of demo-
graphic change. The purpose of this section is to de…ne alternative structures
of …nancing and to broadly sketch their di¤ering e¤ects.
To make the de…nitions as precise as possible, assume that the economy
is one with overlapping generations and that each consumer lives for just two
periods. Each consumer supplies labour during their …rst period of life and
is retired in the second period. Finally, there is one capital good available,
purchases of which provide a repository for savings.
In a fully-funded system each consumer when young make contributions
towards social security via a social security tax and the contributions are used
to purchase capital by the social security program. Total capital in the economy
is then given by the sum of private capital and the publicly owned capital of the
social security program. Total pension bene…ts received by a consumer when
retired are then equal to their contribution to the program plus interest received.
Such a program satis…es the equalities
pensions = social security tax plus interest = capital plus return.
A fully-funded social security system e¤ectively forces each consumer to save
an amount at least equal to the tax they pay. Consumers may, of course, choose
14.3. AN OPTIMAL PROGRAM 433

to save more. If, in the absence of social security, all consumers chose to save an
amount in excess of the taxed levied by the program then, holding all else con-
stant, a fully-funded system will simply replace private saving by an equivalent
amount of public saving. If these conditions are met, a fully-funded system will
have no e¤ect upon the equilibrium outcome. In more general settings with a
variety of investment opportunities, the possibility must be considered that the
rate of return on private savings may di¤er from that on public savings. When
it does, a fully-funded system may a¤ect the equilibrium.
In contrast to the fully-funded system, a pay-as-you-go social security pro-
gram does not own any capital. Instead, a pay-as-you-go system relies on the
contributions of the young of each generation to provide the pensions of the old
of the previous generation. Such a program therefore satis…es the equality
total bene…ts received by generation t ¡ 1 = contributions of generation t.
The system presently in operation in the US is of this form since the capital
it owns would only fund approximately two months of bene…t payments (see
Thompson (1983)).
A pay-as-you-go system leads to an intergenerational reallocation of re-
sources whereas a fully-funded system can at most cause an intertemporal real-
location for each generation. From this observation it can be seen immediately
that the two systems will have rather di¤erent welfare implications, some of
which will be investigated in the following sections.
Systems that fall between these two extremes will be termed non-fully-
funded. Such systems own some of the capital stock but the payments made in
a period may be greater than or less than the revenue, composed of tax pay-
ments and interest, received in that period. The di¤erence between the two will
comprise investment, or disinvestment, in capital.

14.3 An optimal program


The analysis of this section presents Samuelson’s (1975a) characterisation of
an optimal social security program. The assumptions under which this will
be undertaken are strong. In particular, it is assumed that labour supply is
completely inelastic and that the date of retirement cannot be varied. The
relaxation of these restrictions, and others, in later sections will place the results
of this section in context.
Given that the competitive equilibrium may be non-optimal in an overlap-
ping generations economy, there is potentially a role for a social security to
enhance e¢ciency. In fact, in the discussion of Pareto optimality in chapter
13, a simple form of social security program was shown to be Pareto-improving
over the competitive outcome. That example involved each young consumer
transferring a unit of the good to the old consumer of the previous generation.
This series of transfers, which is essentially a pay-as-you-go social security pro-
gram, raised the welfare of the generation that were old when the program was
introduced and left that of all later generations una¤ected. This argument is
further formalised in Aaron (1966).
434 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

To proceed beyond this result, consider a Diamond economy in which there


exists a social security program. The program taxes each worker an amount ¿
and pays each retired person a pension ¯. The programme also owns a quantity
Ks
K st of capital. Equivalently, it can be said to own kst , kst = L tt , of capital per
unit of labour. A social security program will be optimal if the combination of
¿ , ¯ and kst is feasible for the program and leads the economy to the Golden
rule.
A feasible social security program must satisfy the budget identity
£ ¤
¯Lt¡ 1 = ¿ Lt + rtktsLt ¡ kst+1 Lt+1 ¡ ktsLt ; (14.1)

which states that pension payments must be equal to tax revenue plus return
on capital holdings less investment in capital. Since the population grows at
Lt
rate n, in a steady state the identities Lt¡ 1 = 1+n , Lt+ 1 = [1 + n] Lt and
s s s
kt+1 = kt ´ k can be used in (14.1) to generate the steady state budget
identity
¯
= ¿ + [1 + r] k s ¡ [1 + n] ks : (14.2)
1+ n
Employing the equilibrium conditions r = f 0 (k), where k denotes the total
capital stock, the budget constraint of a consumer under the programme can be
written
x2 ¯
x1 + = f (k) ¡ rk ¡ ¿ + : (14.3)
1+r 1+ r
Note that the pension, ¯, which is received in the second period, is discounted
2
since x1 +s = w ¡ ¿ and [1 + r] s+ ¯ = x 2 ; hence s = x1+r¡¯
. The budget identity
of the program can be used to eliminate ¯ in the individuals budget constraint
to give
x2 1+n
x1 + = f (k) ¡ rk ¡ ¿ + [¿ + [r ¡ n] ks ] : (14.4)
1+ r 1+r
Equilibrium in the capital market requires that private savings be equal to
total capital less capital owned by the social security program. This condition
can be expressed as
w ¡ x1 ¡ ¿ = [1 + n] [k ¡ k s] : (14.5)
Substitution for x1 from the individuals budget constraint (14.4) gives

x2 1+n
¡ [¿ + [r ¡ n] ks ] = [1 + n] [k ¡ k s] : (14.6)
1+r 1+r
The equilibrium of the economy is then the simultaneous solution to

x2 1+n
x1 + = f (k) ¡ rk ¡ ¿ + [¿ + [r ¡ n] ks ] ; (14.7)
1+ r 1+r

f 0 (k) = r; (14.8)
U1
= 1 + r; (14.9)
U2
14.3. AN OPTIMAL PROGRAM 435

and
x2 1+n
¡ [¿ + [r ¡ n] k s] = [1 + n] [k ¡ ks ] : (14.10)
1+ r 1+r
These equations represent the private budget constraint, the choice of produc-
tion technique, individual choice and the capital market equilibrium respectively.
The aim now is to investigate the e¤ect that the social security policy can
have upon the equilibrium. In particular, is it possible to design a policy that
will generate the Golden rule? To see why this may be possible it should be
noted that the failure of the competitive equilibrium without intervention to
be e¢cient results from the savings behaviour of individuals which may lead to
over- or under-accumulation of capital. With the correct choice of social security
program the government can e¤ectively force-save for individuals. This alters
the steady state level of the capital stock and hence the growth path of output.
Equations (14.7) to (14.10) determine the endogenous variables k; x 1 ; x2 ; w
and r conditionally upon the exogenous variables ¿ and ks describing the social
security programme. The solution of (14.7) to (14.10) provides the following
system

k = k (¿ ; ks ) ; x1 = x 1 (¿ ; k s) ; x2 = x2 (¿ ; ks ) ; r = r (¿ ; k s) ; w = w (¿ ; ks ) :
(14.11)
For a social security program to achieves the Golden rule, there must exist a
pair f¿ ; ks g that satis…es the equality

r (¿ ; k s) = n: (14.12)

To see the values that should be chosen, set r (¿ ; ks ) in the capital market
equilibrium condition (14.10) and employ the functional relationships (14.11) to
give
x 2 (¿ ; k s)
= ¿ + [1 + n] [k (¿ ; ks ) ¡ ks ] : (14.13)
1+n
From (14.13) can be determined the set of pairs of f¿ ; k sg that will give the
Golden rule rate of growth. Since this is one equation in two variables, there
will in general be a continuum of solutions rather than a single unique solution.
If there exists a solution for ¿ when k s = 0, then the optimum can be sustained
by a pay-as-you-go system.
The structure of this so cial security program is that the young in each gener-
ation give up some consumption, in the form of tax payments, to the old on the
understanding that they will receive a similar a gift when old. There is conse-
quently an element of trust involved in the transactions that support the social
security policy. This should be contrasted to the failure of Pareto optimality in
the Samuelson economy due to the lack of intergenerational trades.
To show that the optimal program will not be fully-funded, note that a
fully-funded program must satisfy the identity

¯Lt¡1 = ¿ Lt¡ 1 [1 + r] = ks Lt [1 + r] : (14.14)


436 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

The substitution of (14.14) into the equilibrium conditions (14.7) - (14.10) shows
that they reduce to the original market equilibrium conditions described in
(13.43) - (13.47). The fully-funded system therefore replaces private capital
by public capital and does not a¤ect the consumption choices of individual
consumers. It can therefore have no real e¤ect on the equilibrium and, if the
initial steady state were not at the Golden rule, a fully-funded social security
program cannot restore e¢ciency.
This analysis has demonstrated how a correctly designed social security pro-
gram can generate the Golden rule equilibrium, provided that it is not of the
fully-funded kind. A fully-funded system simply replaces private savings by
public savings and does not a¤ect the growth path. In contrast a non-fully
funded system can a¤ect the aggregate levels of savings and hence the steady
state capital-labour ratio. The results have been concerned only with the com-
parison between steady states. Burbidge (1983a) discusses the stability of the
steady states and presents some simulations of the adjustment paths that are
followed. The optimality result can also be extended, as in Gigliotti (1984),
to show that a social security program can be designed such that the implied
steady state maximises the discounted sum of future utilities and achieves the
modi…ed Golden rule.

14.4 Some extensions


The optimality result of the previous section was derived under strong assump-
tions. Foremost amongst these was the inelastic supply of labour. One obvious
consequence of the provision of a pension is to encourage retirement and through
this mechanism to reduce labour supply. An induced increase in retirement
raises the proportion of retired to working consumers and reduces the welfare
gains obtained from the implementation of social security. The provision of a
pension will also a¤ect the savings decision. There will be an incentive to reduce
saving since a pension is simply a substitute for private saving. Conversely, ear-
lier retirement suggests the need to raise savings to cover the longer retirement
period. The resolution of these e¤ects will have important implications for the
level of the capital stock. Variable labour supply, and other extensions to the
basic analysis, are now considered.

14.4.1 Labour supply and retirement


The interaction between social security provision and the retirement decision
has been analysed from both partial equilibrium and general equilibrium per-
spectives. Although the important results of the former will be noted, it is the
latter that is of primary interest here.
Under the assumptions of perfect capital markets, actuarial fairness and
known lifespan, Kotliko¤ (1979) shows that the provision of social security will
not a¤ect the retirement decision. This is simply a result of pensions being
equivalent to private savings in that the provision of pensions does not alter the
14.4. SOME EXTENSIONS 437

opportunity set of a consumer. An increase in pension simply replaces private


savings on a one-for-one basis. Relaxing each assumption in turn, Crawford
and Lilien (1981) show that the e¤ect on the date of retirement is in general
ambiguous but a progressive system tends to advance retirement for low-income
workers. Diamond and Mirrlees (1986) focus on the problems raised by the
government’s inability to distinguish those unable to work and those who choose
not to work. When consumers are forced to retire due to an inability to work,
but with no prior warning of this, it is shown that the optimal social security
program will have bene…ts rising with the age of retirement.
Although suggestive, these analyses do not address the interaction between
the retirement decision and the equilibrium of the economy. There are clearly
important connections between these since early retirement reduces labour sup-
ply while reduced savings lower the equilibrium capital stock. A simple ex-
tension of the Samuelson analysis by Hu (1979) that incorporates endogenous
retirement is now discussed.
The production side of the economy and the structure of the population re-
mains as in Section 3. What distinguishes the present economy is that although
all consumers must supply one unit of labour in the …rst period of their life, they
can choose what proportion of the second period of life they spend working. To
provide a motive for retirement, utility is increasing in the length of the period
of retirement.
Expressed formally, the utility function is assumed to take the form
¡ ¢
U = U xtt ; xt+
t
1
; ®t ; (14.15)

where ®t , 0 ® t 1 is the proportion of the second period of life that is spent


in retirement. Again denoting the tax paid toward the social security program
whilst working by ¿ and the pension by ¯, the consumers budget constraint is

x t+1 [1 ¡ ®t ] [wt+1 ¡ ¿ ] ®t ¯
x tt + t
= wt ¡ ¿ + + ; (14.16)
1 + rt+ 1 1 + rt+1 1 + rt+1

or, in the steady state,

x1 + ½x 2 = w ¡ ¿ + ½ [1 ¡ ®] [w ¡ ¿ ] + ½®¯: (14.17)

Maximising utility leads to the necessary conditions

@U @U
= ½ 1; (14.18)
@x 2 @x
and
@U @U
= ½ [w ¡ ¿ ¡ ¯] 1 : (14.19)
@® @x
From (14.18) and (14.19) can be derived consumption demands and a retirement
decision that are dependent upon w; ½; ¿ and ¯. It is assumed that the optimal
® satis…es 0 < ® < 1. If the upper bound were attained the model would be
identical to that already analysed.
438 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

The total population at time t is denoted by Pt . With growth rate n, the


proportion of the total population that is in the second period of life, µ, is given
by
Ht¡1 Ht¡ 1 1
µ= = = : (14.20)
Ht + Ht¡1 [1 + n] Ht¡1 + Ht¡ 1 2+n
The social security program is assumed to operate on the pay-as-you-go basis.
Noting that bene…ts are only paid once a consumer has retired, the program
satis…es the budget identity

Pt µ®¯ = Lt ¿ = Pt l¿ ; (14.21)

where L is total labour supply and l is average labour supply given by [1 ¡ µ + µ [1 ¡ ®]]
= [1 ¡ µ®] since proportion 1¡µ of the population work full-time and proportion
µ work for fraction 1 ¡ ® of the time. Equation (14.21) reduces to

®µ¯ = [1 ¡ µ®] ¿ : (14.22)

The decision problem of …rms is una¤ected by the existence of the social


security program. In the steady state capital and labour demands satisfy r =
f 0 (k) and w = f (k) ¡ kf 0 (k), where the capital-labour ratio k = K L
. These
equations can be solved to express the interest rate as a function of the wage
rate or w = Á (r). This relationship is termed the factor price frontier and is
the locus of pairs of w, r that are consistent with equilibrium for …rms. Since
dr = f 00 dk and dw = ¡kf 00dk; dw
dr = ¡k.
The optimal social security program can be derived by maximising (14.15)
with respect to the level of the pension, ¯, taking into account the dependence
of the choice variables on ¯ and the budget constraint of the program. Di¤er-
entiating (14.15) and using (14.18) and (14.19) gives
¸
dU dU dx 1 dx2 d®
= + ½ + ½ [w ¡ ¿ ¡ ¯] ; (14.23)
d¯ dx 1 d¯ d¯ d¯
i
where the total derivatives dx d¯
, i = 1; 2 and d® d¯
take account of the induced
change in ¿ via (14.22). The derivative of the budget constraint (14.17) can
then be substituted into (14.23) to give
¸
dU dU d [w ¡ ¿ ] £ 2
¤ d½
= [1 + ½ ¡ ®½] + w ¡ ¿ ¡ x ¡ ® [w ¡ ¿ ¡ ¯ ] + ®½ :
d¯ dx1 d¯ d¯
(14.24)
Using the second-period budget constraint w ¡ ¿ + [1 + r] s = x 2 + ® [w ¡ ¿ ¡ ¯],
where s is …rst-period saving, (14.24) becomes
¸
dU dU d [w ¡ ¿ ] d½
= [1 + ½ ¡ ®½] ¡ [1 + r] s + ®½ : (14.25)
d¯ dx 1 d¯ d¯

By de…nition, d½ 2 dr 1
dr = ¡½ and, from the factor price frontier dw = ¡ k . Since
the level of capital is given by K = P µs and total labour supply L = P l =
14.4. SOME EXTENSIONS 439

µs d½
P [1 ¡ ®µ], k = [1¡®µ ]
. Substituting these de…nitions into (14.24), using d¯
=
d½ dr dw
dr dw d¯
and collecting terms
¸
dU dU h ½ i dw d¿
= 1 + ½ ¡ ¡ [1 + ½ ¡ ®½] + ®½ : (14.26)
d¯ dx 1 µ d¯ d¯
£ ¤
1
Finally, since µ = 2+n and ½ = 1+r 1
, 1 + ½ ¡ ½µ = [r ¡ n] ½, the optimal pension
solves
¸
dU dU dw d¿
= [r ¡ n] ½ ¡ [1 + ½ ¡ ®½] + ®½ = 0: (14.27)
d¯ dx 1 d¯ d¯
The contrast between this result and the conclusion drawn from the economy
in which no labour can be supplied in the second period of life can be seen by
setting ® = 1 in (14.27). From (14.22), when ® = 1, d¿ d¯
= 1¡µ µ . Substituting
into (14.27) then gives
¸ ¸¸
dU dU dw µ r¡n
j®=1 = [r ¡ n] ½ ¡ = 0: (14.28)
d¯ dx 1 d¯ 1¡ µ 1+r
dU
Since dx 1 > 0, the solution to (14.28) must have r = n so that the program

achieves the Golden rule.


When 0 < ® < 1, it then follows that r = n will not be achieved at the
d¿
solution to (14.27). Assuming that d¯ > 0, if dw

< 0 then the program will
lead to a rate of interest less than the growth rate of population. The converse
holds if dw

> 0.
The conclusion to be drawn from this analysis is that the decentralisation
of the Golden rule by the use of a social security program will not be desirable
when the retirement decision is endogenous. This is because the tax used to pay
for pensions introduces a distortion into the choice problem of each consumer.
Although the program can aid the dynamic e¢ciency of the economy by a¤ecting
the level of the capital stock, this has to set against the ine¢ciency caused by
the tax. Continuous-time versions of this analysis are presented in Hu (1978)
and Sheshinski (1978).
In addition to a¤ecting the retirement decision, social security will also have
an impact upon the labour supply decision itself. This impact will be partic-
ularly pronounced when a household framework is adopted and the distinction
is made between male and female labour supply. Since female labour supply is
typically more elastic than male supply, it will be female labour supply that is
proportionately more a¤ected by the social security program. Simulation evi-
dence on the strength of these e¤ects is presented by Craig and Batina (1991).
They consider an economy in which each generation is composed of an equal
number of males and females. Pairs of males and females then form house-
holds and jointly choose their labour supplies to maximise a household utility
function. Except for the fact that they now supply two forms of labour, male
and female, these households are equivalent to the consumers of the economies
above. It is assumed that the two forms of labour are close, but not perfect,
440 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

substitutes in a CES production function. Since they are not perfect substitutes,
the equilibrium wage rates may di¤er.
The social security program considered by Craig and Batina contains pro-
visions other than a simple retirement bene…t. The retirement bene…t is deter-
mined by the value of earnings prior to retirement and may be di¤erent between
males and females. Furthermore, each female has the option of choosing either
a pension based on their own earnings history or one based on their spouse’s
earnings. The social security program is …nanced by a tax on labour earnings, a
lump-sum tax and an additional tax upon labour earnings when, in the second
period of life, these rise above a cut-o¤ level. Incorporating these provisions, the
budget constraint of a household whose members are born in period t is given
by
¸
x t+1 wt+ 1 Lt+1 + w 0t+1 L0t+1
x tt + t
= [1 ¡ t] w tLt + w 0tL0t+ ¡T
1 + rt+1 1 + rt+1
" £ ¤ #
¯ [wt Lt + wt+ 1 Lt+1 ] + ¯ 0 [1 ¡ ±] w 0tL0t + w 0t+1 L0t+1 + B
+
1 + rt+1
¸ " £ ¤#
¾± [[w tLt + w t+1 Lt+1 ]] ¿ wt+1 Lt+1 + w0t+1 L0t+1 ¡ a
+ ¡ (14.29):
1 + rt+1 1 + rt+1

In (14.29) the primes denote variables relating to the female, ¯ is the bene…t
rate on own earnings, ± = 0 if the wife chooses a pension based on her earnings
and ± = 1 if they choose that based on their spouses. ¾ is the bene…t rate on
spouse’s earnings. B is the lump-sum bene…t, T the lump-sum tax, t the tax
rate on earnings and t the tax on second-period earnings above the level a.
For a program with t = 0.15, ¯ = ¯ 0 = 0.2, s = 0.1 and ¿ = 0.5, the results
obtained are summarised in Table 14.1. The primary e¤ects of the program
are to shift labour supply toward the beginning of the life-cycle for both males
and females and to increase the level of household consumption in the second
period of life relative to that in the …rst period. Lifetime labour supply of both
male and female falls. The program also causes a slight shift in relative wages
in favour of males.

w xtt
w0
Lt Lt+1 L0t L0t+1 xtt+1
Without programme 1.790 0.478 0.232 0.434 0.084 0.561
With programme 1.804 0.503 0.095 0.462 0 0.470
Table 14.1 E¤ect of Social Security

These results demonstrate how the introduction of a social security program


a¤ects the allocation of labour and consumption over the lifecycle. In particular,
it acts as a disincentive to supply labour in the later stages of life. The reduction
of total labour supply that is caused will also have consequences for the level of
output that is produced and the capital-labour ratio.
14.4. SOME EXTENSIONS 441

14.4.2 E¤ect on savings and capital


With a pay-as-you-go social security program in operation, any e¤ect that the
existence of the program has upon private savings is re‡ected directly in the
level of the capital stock since, by de…nition, the program owns no capital. So-
cial security has two con‡icting e¤ects upon the level of private saving. The
…rst e¤ect is the substitution of social security for private savings which nat-
urally reduces the level of saving. O¤setting this e¤ect is the likelihood that
social security will bring forward retirement. If this does occur, private saving
should rise in order to cover the increased length of retirement. At this level of
generality, the net e¤ect is indeterminate.
In contrast to the earlier evidence of Cagan (1965) and Katona (1964) which
showed that consumers covered by private pensions did not save less than those
not covered, Feldstein (1974) estimated that the existence of the US social se-
curity program reduced private savings by 30-50%. This evidence was based on
the estimation of a consumption function that included social security wealth as
one of the explanatory variables. The central estimate suggested that, during
the 1960’s, the capital stock was 38% lower with the social security program
than it would have been without. Although widely cited, these results have not
always been replicated in later studies. Danziger, Haveman and Plotnick (1981)
suggest that the true …gure should be somewhere in the range of 0-20% whilst
Aaron (1982) concludes that there is simply a lack of agreement amongst the
studies. As an example of con‡icting …ndings, work by Lee and Chao (1988)
estimates labour force participation and personal savings simultaneously tak-
ing into account private pensions. Although social security wealth is found to
encourage retirement, the payment of contributions to social security has an
insigni…cant e¤ect on private savings.
Whether it is possible for a theoretical economy to exhibit a similar respon-
siveness to the introduction of social security as that suggested by Feldstein has
been investigated by Kotliko¤ (1979) in an analysis involving a continuous-time
formulation of endogenous retirement. Consider an economy of identical individ-
uals with has a population growth rate of n and endogenous labour-augmenting
technical progress at rate g. The latter assumption implies that the wage rate
is also growing at rate g. At each point in time, the fraction of the existing
population that have lived out their lifespan of D years will be replaced by
new consumers. Each consumer cho oses their consumption stream and date of
retirement to maximise discounted utility.
Denoting instantaneous utility by U (xt (t)), discounted utility is given by
Z D
U = U (xt (t)) e¡½tdt; (14.30)
0

where ½ is the rate of time preference. Utility (14.31) is maximised subject to


the budget constraint
Z D Z R Z D
x t (t) e¡ rtdt = W [1 ¡ ¿ ] e ¡[r¡g ]t dt + ¯e¡[r ¡g ]tdt: (14.31)
0 0 R
442 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

In writing (14.32), it is assumed that both the wage, W , and the pension, ¯, are
growing at rate g. The pay-as-you-go identity for the social security program is
given by
¿ W [1 ¡ µ]
¯= ; (14.32)
µ
1¡ µ
with µ the ratio of those working to those retired de…ned by
R R ¡nt
1¡µ e dt
= R 0D (14.33)
µ e¡ nt dt
R

At each point in time, additions to the capital stock are equal to the savings of
those working plus the savings of those who are retired. For a working consumer
born at date t, their savings are
dKt (t)
= W [1 ¡ ¿ ] eg t ¡ xt (t) + rKt (t) ; (14.34)
dt
whilst for a retired consumer
dKt (t)
= ¯eg t ¡ xt (t) + rKt (t) : (14.35)
dt
Solving (14.35) provides the capital owned by a consumer born in t and solving
(14.36) determines the capital of a retired consumer. Total capital can then be
found be integrating over the population. The total savings provided by con-
sumers can then be equated with the capital demand by …rms and equilibrium
computed.
x (t) 1¡®
Adopting an instantaneous utility function of the form U = t1¡ ® and a
Cobb-Douglas production function, the simulation results of Kotliko¤ for the
e¤ect of the introduction of a social security program with a value of ¿ of 0.1
are summarised in Table 14.2. Inspection of Table 14.2 demonstrates that a
social security program can have e¤ects with the order of magnitude identi…ed
by Feldstein. The reductions in the capital stock range from 10% to 21% which,
although somewhat less than 38%, are still signi…cant. Even in very simple
economies it is therefore possible for the introduction of pay-as-you-go social
security to substantially reduce the capital stock and with it the output of the
economy.

Net rate of interestAge of retirement Rate of time preference Reduction in capital stock
42 0.0160 -0.213
0.05 45 0.0120 -0.190
50 0.0058 -0.104
42 0.0232 -0.212
0.06 45 0.0196 -0.189
50 0.0148 -0.102
Parameters: ® = 1, D = 55, r = 0.05, ¿ = 0.1, r = n + g, n = g
Table 14.2: E¤ect on Capital Stock
14.4. SOME EXTENSIONS 443

14.4.3 Ricardian equivalence


Ricardian equivalence originally referred to the proposition that the method of
…nancing government expenditure, whether through taxes or borrowing, was
irrelevant. To illustrate this, consider the following example. To reduce the
level of taxation by D in period t, the government sells quantity D of bonds. To
repay the bonds the following period, the government must levy additional taxes
in t + 1 of [1 + r] D. Since the discounted value of this increase in taxation is
exactly equal to the value of the original tax cut, the net wealth of the economy
is unchanged when viewed from period t. The bond-…nanced plan is therefore
equivalent to keeping the initial level of taxation unchanged, illustrating the
principle of Ricardian equivalence.
Ricardian equivalence will be discussed in detail in Chapter 15 but a further
point needs to be made here in order to relate the argument to the analysis of
social security. Returning to the example above, it would seem that if some of
the households alive at time t were no longer alive at t + 1 then the equivalence
would fail since they would bene…t from the reduced tax payment but would
avoid the increased tax. To make this point stronger, assume the bonds ma-
ture N periods after issue. The argument of the example would still apply if
the population remained unchanged over the N period but it now seems less
reasonable to expect this.
There is, as …rst noted by Barro (1974), a mechanism that will maintain
equivalence even if the population changes between issue and redemption of
bonds. Suppose that each consumer has a single identi…ed descendent and that
they care about their own level of consumption and about the utility level of their
descendent. Such intergenerational altruism then links …nitely-lived consumers
into a household whose lifespan is as long as that of the economy. The altruism
will manifest itself in consumers choosing to leave bequests to their descendants
and it is via the bequest motive that Ricardian equivalence arises. To see this
point, assume that the bonds are purchased by generation t but the tax liability
is borne by generation t + 1. If generation t raises its bequest to t + 1 by exactly
the amount necessary for t + 1 to meet their increased tax liability then the
consumption plans of both generations will remain una¤ected by the switch
from tax-…nance to bonds thus maintaining the equivalence result. Although
there are, of course, limitations to this result which are described in Chapter
15, it does have implications for the analysis of social security.
One implication of Ricardian equivalence has, in fact already been described.
The discussion of a fully-funded social security program in Section 2 noted that
such a program would leave the equilibrium of the economy una¤ected. The
fully-funded system requires that the pensions received by each generation are
equal to the taxes that they paid. In this case an increase in tax when young
is accompanied by the receipt of a pension when old which is equal in value
to the tax plus interest. This is simply the opposite of the initial example of
equivalence and a slight modi…cation of that argument shows why it has no
net e¤ect. The households reduce their private savings by the amount of the
tax, maintain their consumption levels and replace private saving by saving in
444 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

the pension plan. Since private and public savings have the same return, they
are indi¤erent to this rearrangement. It is worth noting that this argument
presumes that private savings are initially greater than the tax used to …nance
the pension. If they are not, then equivalence will not apply.
Introducing intergenerational altruism allows the equivalence argument to
be extended to pay-as-you-go social security. A pay-as-you-go system can be
interpreted as a forced transfer from the young generation to the old. If all
members of the old generation were making a positive bequest to their descen-
dants prior to the introduction of the program, the e¤ects of the program can
be entirely neutralised by the old simply increasing their bequest by exactly
the pension they receive. By the de…nition of a pay-as-you-go system, this in-
creased bequest will exactly match the taxes paid by the young. Therefore,
with intergenerational altruism, pay-as-you-go social security will have no e¤ect
upon the equilibrium provided the bequest motive is operational prior to the
commencement of the program.
In this context, it should be stressed that intergenerational altruism must
manifest itself through each member of generation t having a utility function of
the form introduced by Barro (1974)
¡ ¢
U t = U x tt; x t+1
t ; U t+1 ; (14.36)

where U t+1 is the utility level of their descendent. The dependence of U t upon
U t+1 provides the linkage that e¤ectively turns the separate generations of the
family into a single household. Furthermore, although there may be a bequest
motive, bequests may still be zero if the consumer¡ ¢ is 2at t+1
a corner solution. For
the separable utility function U (x tt ) + ¾ 1 U x t+1
t + ¾ U , Weil (1987) shows
that the bequest will only be positive if ¾ 2 > 1+n 1+re where r
e is the rate of interest
in the absence of bequests. If the no-bequest economy is dynamically ine¢cient
then re < n and with discount rate ¾ 2 < 1 bequests will never occur.
An alternative speci…cation (used, for example, in Hu (1979)) is to assume
that each consumer cares about the size of the bequest, b t, that they leave to
their descendent, rather than their descendants welfare, so that utility takes the
form ¡ ¢
U t = U x tt ; x t+1
t ; b t: (14.37)
With the speci…cation of utility in (14.38), the equivalence result no longer
applies. This follows from observing that the introduction of a social secu-
rity program that has an initial transfer to generation t will result in standard
changes in x tt; xt+
t
1
; b t via an income e¤ect rather than an increase in b t exactly
equal to the level of the pension. If it is a normal good, the level of the bequest
will increase but not to the point that maintains the welfare of generation t + 1.
In the presence of intergenerational altruism it is therefore possible for social
security programs to have no e¤ect upon the equilibrium of the economy. Indeed,
the discussion above may suggest that this is the typical outcome. However,
there are many circumstances it which the Ricardian equivalence result does
not apply and, although this pre-empts some of the material of Chapter 15, it
is worth noting some of these. As already stated. the utility function must take
14.4. SOME EXTENSIONS 445

the form of (14.37) and the bequest motive must be active for all consumers
prior to the introduction of the program. The existence of bequests in itself is
not su¢cient; these may simply be left due to uncertainty about the time of
death or poor planning. Taxes and bene…ts must be equal for each household
so that if there is a redistributive element to the program then equivalence will
not apply. In addition the empirical evidence already discussed suggests that it
does not apply in practice.
Although equivalence may apply in the simple economies used so far if altru-
istic preferences are introduced, the limits to the result are soon reached when
obvious extensions to these economies are made. With respect to the analysis of
social security, Ricardian equivalence should therefore be viewed as a theoretical
curiosity rather than a result of practical relevance.

14.4.4 Demographics
The growth rate of population is an important determinant of the success of
a social security program. A rapidly increasing population will make it easier
for the young to provide pensions for the (relatively) smaller number of old. It
will also lead to a dilution of the capital stock which makes it more di¢cult
for the pensions commitments to be met. This trade-o¤ suggests that there
may be a rate of population growth which will maximise the welfare of the
representative consumer. Indeed, Samuelson (1975b) claimed to have provided a
characterisation of this optimal rate. However, it was shown by Deardor¤ (1976)
that in many reasonable cases Samuelson’s conditions actually described the
growth rate that minimised welfare. This fact is further clari…ed in Samuelson
(1976).
The connection between the rate of population growth and the optimal level
of social security can be investigated by optimising the choice of program for
given n and then varying n; this is the method adopted by Lopez-Garcia (1991).
Assuming that each consumer can choose the amount of labour they supply in
each period. Denoting this level of labour supply by ` tt, a consumer born in t
maximises ¡ ¢
U t = U x tt; x t+1
t ; 1 ¡ `tt : (14.38)
The social security tax is levied proportionately upon labour income at rate ¿
so, in the steady state with identical consumers, the budget constraint for the
program is given by
¯ = [1 + n] ¿ w`: (14.39)
The pension ¯ is assumed to be a constant proportion, ½, of the net wage so that
¯ = ½ [1 ¡ ¿ ] w`. As a function of the replacement rate ½, the tax supporting
the program is equal to
½
¿ = : (14.40)
1+n+½
The individual budget constraint is
x2 [1 + n] [1 + r + ½]
x1 + = w` = w`;
b (14.41)
1+r [1 + r] [1 + n + ½]
446 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

so that maximisation of (14.39) gives consumption demands x i = x i ( w; b r),


i = 1; 2, and labour supply ` = ` ( w;b r). Employing the factor price frontier,
w = ' (r), the equilibrium interest rate is the solution to
0h i 1
µ 1
¶ 1+n
b r) ¡ x1 ( w;
' (r) ` (w; b r)
[1 ¡ ¿ ] w` ¡ x 1+n+½
r = f0 = f0@ A : (14.42)
[1 + n] ` [1 + n] ` (w;
b r)

The solution to (14.43) is denoted r = r (½; n).


Substituting into (14.39), the attainable level of utility can be written U =
V (½; n). Di¤erentiating utility with respect to ½ for …xed n gives
¸ ¸
@V @U 1+ n @r ' (r) `
= [n ¡ r (½; n)] k` + ; (14.43)
@½ @x 2 1 + n + ½ @½ 1 + n + ½

where use has been made of the conditions describing consumer choice. The
sign of (14.44) is the same as that of n ¡ r since it can be shown, employing
the su¢cient condition for stability, that @r @½ > 0. Hence only if r (0; n) < n will
there be an interior, positive solution for ½. In that case, since the second-order
condition can be shown to be negative at r = n, the maximising value of ½
satis…es r (½; n) = n.
Assuming now that an interior solution exists for ½, with ½ > 0, the fact that
optimal social security program can be employed to maintain the equality of r
with n allows (14.43) to be written as
0h i 1
1+n
1+n+½ ' (n) ` (' (n) ; n) ¡ x1 (' (n) ; n)
n = f0 @ A: (14.44)
[1 + n] ` (' (n) ; n)

Solving (14.45) for ½, the solution is written ½ = ½ (n). This allows utility to be
expressed as U = V (½ (n) ; n) and hence

@U @V (½ (n) ; n) @½ @V (½ (n) ; n)
= + : (14.45)
@n @½ @n @n

However, since ½ is chosen optimally, (14.46) reduces to

@U @V (½ (n) ; n) @U ½'`
= = 2
: (14.46)
@n @n @x 1 + n + ½

Since it has been assumed that ½ > 0, (14.47) is always positive so that increasing
the rate of population growth will increase welfare. In this case, there is no
optimal rate of population growth. The ability of an increasing population to
provide a larger pension dominates in this case.
Alternatively, if the optimal replacement rate is negative, utility is always
decreasing in the rate of population growth. Finally, if a replacement rate of
0 is optimal, so that no social security program is required for the Golden rule
to be obtained, then (14.47) is always zero. It can easily be shown, however,
14.5. DETERMINATION AND JUSTIFICATION 447

that this may either be minimum, as in Deardor¤ (1976), or a maximum. The


competitive outcome that achieves the Golden rule may therefore be sustained
by a rate of population growth that can either maximise or minimise utility,
thus being either the best or worst of all worlds.
In conclusion, the relation between the growth rate of population, the choice
of social security program and the level of utility may take many forms. If
there is an optimal social security program that has a positive pension, then an
increase in population growth always raises welfare. The converse holds if the
optimal pension is negative. More surprisingly, when it is optimal to have no
pension system the rate of population growth that supports such an equilibrium
will either maximise or minimise the level of utility. From a policy perspective,
there may be bene…ts to be obtained from rapid population growth as the in-
creasing population can support a more generous social security program.

14.5 Determination and justi…cation


There are several justi…cations for the existence of social security programs.
The optimal program of Section 3 would raise the welfare of all generations that
bene…ted from the attainment of the Golden rule steady state although there
may be some losers along the adjustment path (see Flemming (1977)). This
need not be true of pay-as-you-go systems with their implied intergenerational
transfers nor of fully-funded systems which may simply replace private saving
by public saving. Given these observations, the purpose of this section is to look
at various methods of determining the structure of social security programs and
of justifying their existence.

14.5.1 Voting equilibria


The most obvious mechanism by which the level of social security can be deter-
mined is through a system of voting. Although systems of voting di¤er widely,
the literature focuses only upon simple majority voting and the median voter
outcome. The rationale for this position is that these are the most tractable
analytically and capture the essence of more sophisticated alternatives.
The earliest analysis of these issues is given in Aaron (1966) who shows
that since a social security program with positive bene…ts always provides a
transfer to the old, a median-age voter may …nd it in their favour to vote for
the continued existence of a program despite its total e¤ect being to reduce the
welfare of all households. Browning (1975) considers an economy in which there
is no capital market so that the only method of saving is via social security. In
such circumstances, majority voting leads to a level of social security in excess
of that which maximises lifetime welfare.
A simple result on the outcome of majority voting in an economy with capital
markets is obtained by Hu (1979) for the economy of Subsection 4.1. Since
population growth is positive, at any point in time the young generation is
larger then the old. Combining this observation with the assumption that all
448 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

consumers are identical, it follows that the program chosen by majority voting
will be that which maximises the lifetime utility of a young consumer. The
program therefore solves
¡ ¢
max U x 1 ; x2 ; ® ; (14.47)
fx 1;x2;®;¯ g

subject to the consumers budget constraint (14.17) and the budget identity of
the social security program (14.22). Assuming that the consumer treats the
wage as independent of ¯ when performing the optimisation, the social security
program chosen by ma jority voting will satisfy
@¿
[1 + ½ ¡ ®½] ¡ ®½ = 0: (14.48)

In general, there is no reason to expect that the program determined by (14.49)


will be anymore, or any less, generous than the program arising from (14.27).
However, in the special case of labour supply only in the …rst period of life, so
® = 1, (14.49) reduces to
µ r ¡n
= 0; (14.49)
1¡ µ 1 +r
so that ma jority voting will attain the Golden rule.
This analysis is extended by Hu (1982) who considers an economy in which
consumers live for three periods. They work in the …rst two and are retired in
the third. The important distinction is that with population growth satisfying
the restriction
2
2 + n > [1 + n] ; (14.50)
so that, at any given time, the number of consumers in either the second or
third period of their life is greater than the number in their …rst period, ma-
jority voting will always lead to an outcome that is supported by two of the
three generations. Furthermore, if there is a possibility that the social security
program determined by voting at time t may be overturned by a re-vote at t + 1
or later, the possibility of strategic voting arises. That is, a consumer in the
early stages of their life may vote for a program with a low level of tax with the
intention later in life of voting for one with higher provision.
Employing this framework Hu (1982) shows that the equilibrium arising
from majority voting when consumers are uncertain about the impact of present
voting intentions on later outcomes may have an interest rate either above or
below that of the Golden rule. This …nding indicates that although majority
voting need not be e¢cient, the possibility arises that it may be possible to
design a mechanism that implements the Golden rule. The weakness of this
framework is that the uncertainty is necessary for a consumer to have an interior
solution to their choice of preferred social security tax rate. In the certain case,
when no re-voting can occur, they will always choose a tax rate of 1 when the net
gain from the program is positive and zero when it is negative. The uncertainty,
however, is introduced in a fairly arbitrary fashion: it is simply assumed that
future provision, though uncertain, is increasing in the present level.
14.5. DETERMINATION AND JUSTIFICATION 449

An alternative approach to this issue is provided by Boadway and Wildasin


(1989) who employ the continuous time framework described in (14.31) - (14.34)
but with g = 0. The majority voting assumption results in the equilibrium
level of social security being determined by the median voter. To overcome the
problem that in the absence of uncertainty this choice would either be a tax
rate of 0 or 1, the capital market is assumed imperfect so that consumers face
constraints upon borrowing. In addition, it is assumed that voting is infrequent
so that when determining their voting intentions each consumer expects the
level of social security adopted to remain constant for the remainder of their
lifespan. The major …ndings are that, given an existing level of social security
bene…ts, preferences are single-peaked over alternative levels so that the median
voter outcome applies and that when consumers cannot borrow against future
bene…ts, if the existing level of bene…ts are below the optimal level for the
median-age voter, the median-age voter will also be the median voter.

14.5.2 Altruism
Voluntary intergenerational transfers can arise when consumers have altruistic
feelings about other generations. These feelings can extend both to previous
generations and to following generations. Some of the consequences of bequests
have been discussed in Subsection 4.3; the focus here is primarily upon voluntary
gifts from young to old since this is the essence of a pay-as-you-go program.
Altruism has been represented as a consumption externality by Veall (1986)
with the utility of generation t being of the form
¡ ¢
U t = U xtt ; xt+
t
1
; x tt¡1 : (14.51)

In the formulation of (14.52) the consumption of generation t ¡ 1 in the second


period of life a¤ects the utility of generation t. When the externality e¤ect is
positive, it can be interpreted as a form of altruism. The alternative represen-
tation of Hansson and Stuart (1989) develops the Buiter (1980) and Carmichael
(1982) formulation of altruism and assumes that each consumer alive at time t
has the utility function
" ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢#
U 1 x t¡1 + U 2 x t ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
t¡1 t¡1
Ut = + U 1 xtt + U 2 x t+1
t
[1 + n] [1 + °]
X1 ¸
£ 1 z 2
¡ z+ 1 ¢¤ 1 + n z¡t
+ U (xz ) + U x z ; (14.52)
1+¾
z=t+ 1

where the …rst term captures concern for the older generation, with ¾ the rel-
evant discount rate, and the third term that for following generations with
discount rate ¾. Although analytical details are rather di¤erent, the two for-
mulations provide an essentially identical motive for the introduction of a pay-
as-you-go social security program that, on its introduction, involves an initial
transfer to the older generation. Here the approach of Hansson and Stuart will
be followed.
450 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

Assume that production is subject to a constant coe¢cient production func-


tion so that the wage rate, normalised at 1, and the interest rate, r, are both
constant. Two restrictions upon the utility function are adopted. Firstly, ¾ > n
so that the in…nite sum in (14.53) converges and ¾ > r so that, as noted in 4.3,
no consumer desires to leave a bequest. Denoting the gift given by generation t
to generation t ¡ 1 by at , the budget constraints in the …rst- and second-periods
of life are
x tt = 1 ¡ st ¡ at ; xt+
t
1
= [1 + r] st + [1 + n] at+1 : (14.53)

The gift a t satis…es the necessary condition


¡ ¢
U 20 x tt¡1 ¡ ¢
¡ U 10 x tt 0; = 0 if at > 0; (14.54)
1+°

where ° is the rate of discounting applied to the older generations utility in


(14.53).
Hansson and Stuart (1989) note that this economy has two steady state
equilibria. The …rst arises when the …rst part of (14.55) is satis…ed with equality
and positive gifts are passed between generations. ¡ ¢ In such a steady state the fact
that ° > 0 implies, from (14.55), that U 20 x tt¡1 > U 10 (xtt ) so that the marginal
utility of consumption when old is greater than ¡when¢young. This is in contrast
to the outcome without altruism in which U 20 xtt¡1 = ½U 10 (xtt ), with ½ < 1,
see (14.18). This equilibrium is therefore not Pareto optimal since ¡ a¢ marginal
increase in st would raise the utility of generation t by U 20 x tt¡1 [1 + r] ¡
U 10 (x tt) > 0. The second steady state equilibrium occurs when (14.55) is an
equality and gifts are zero. If n ¸ r, then the outcome is not Pareto optimal
since an introduction of gifts can raise welfare of all generations. This is not
possible if n < r.
The structure of a social security program that is acceptable to the two
generations alive at the time of its introduction, say time 0, is constructed by
…rst deriving the optimal program for the old, generation -1, and the then for the
young, generation 0, where the program takes the form of gifts from young to
old fa0 ; a1 ; :::g and savings fs 0; s 1 ; :::g. For generation -1 the optimal program
solves ¡ ¢
20
¡ 0 ¢ U 10 x 00
U x¡1 ¡ 0; = 0 if a0 > 0; (14.55)
1+ ¾
¡ ¢ U 10 (xtt )
U 20 x tt¡1 ¡ 0; = 0 if at > 0; t > 0; (14.56)
1+ ¾
and
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
¡U 10 xtt + U 20 x t+1
t [1 + r] 0; = 0 if st > 0; t > 0: (14.57)
The optimal program for generation 0 also satis…es (14.57) and (14.58) but
replaces (14.56) by
¡ ¢
U 20 x 0¡1 ¡ ¢
¡ U 10 x00 0; = 0 if a0 > 0: (14.58)
1+°
14.5. DETERMINATION AND JUSTIFICATION 451

The …rst point to note is that savings must tend to zero. Assume otherwise.
Then (14.57) and (14.58) imply that
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
10
¡ t+ 1¢ U 20 xt+1
t U 10 (x tt ) [1 + ¾] U 20 x tt¡1 [1 + ¾]2
U xt+ 1 = = = : (14.59)
1+¾ 1+r 1+ r
From the¡ assumption
¢ that ¾ > r, (14.60) implies that as t ! 1, U 10 (x tt ) ! 1
and U x t¡1 ! 1 or x tt ! 0 and xt+
20 t
t
1
! 0. The budget constraints (14.53)
and (14.54) can then be combined to give

x tt¡1 1+r
s t = 1 ¡ xtt ¡ + st¡1 : (14.60)
1+n 1+ n

Hence xtt ! 0 and xt+1 t ! 0 imply st ! 1 contradicting st 1. Thus for some


t; st = 0. Now let b t be the …rst period with zero savings. Because savings are
positive for all earlier periods, (14.57) and (14.58) imply that x t+1 t
t+1 < xt and
t+1
x t < x tt¡1 . From (14.61) it then follows that
¸
1+r
s t¡1 ¡ st > [s t ¡ s t+1 ] ; for 0 t < bt: (14.61)
1+n

As bt is the …rst period with st = 0, s bt¡1 > sbt which implies from (14.62) that
s t > st+ 1 for all 0 t < b
t. If there were any period after b t with st > 0 then the
same backward induction argument would contradict sbt = 0.
Contrasting (14.56) and (14.59), it can be seen that generation -1 would
prefer that a0 be larger than the level that would be chosen by generation
0. More importantly, since (14.57) are common to the characterisation of the
optimal program for both generations, given a value of a 0 both generations
would agree upon the values of fa1 ; a2 ; :::g and fs0 ; s 1 ; :::g that should constitute
the remainder of the program. Furthermore, (14.57) and (14.58) also capture
optimal choices for the older generation in every future time period so that they
would always support the continuation of the program.
That the program raises the welfare of the introducing generations can be
seen by setting a0 at the level, say a0 , determined in the equilibrium without
social security with further transfers set optimally. Comparison of (14.55) and
(14.57) then shows that the equilibrium set of transfers without social security is
not optimal for generations -1 and 0 so that they must gain by the introduction
of the program. Their welfare could potentially be raised further by choosing
a value of a0 6= a0 . If the solutions of (14.56) and (14.59) both determine a
value of a0 lower than a0 then the maximum of the two would from part of an
equilibrium program. The converse holds when a0 is less then the solutions to
(14.56) and (14.59). In other cases, the level a0 will lie in the acceptable range.
The move to such an equilibrium social security program moves the economy to
a Pareto optimum. Although the program raises the welfare of the generations
that introduce it, this need not apply to any of the later generations although,
as already noted, no generation will seek to change the program. In particular,
if the initial steady state was one without transfers, the introduction of the
452 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

program reduces the utility o¤ all generations after a given date. To see this,
note that without social security, total lifetime consumption ¡ would
¢ be 1 + rst
with consumption levels chosen to maximise U 1 (x tt) + U 2 x t+1 t . With social
security savings fall to zero by date b t so, if n = 0, total lifetime consumption
after b must equal 1 and, from (14.58), this is not chosen to maximise U 1 (xtt ) +
2
¡ tt+1 ¢
U xt . Generations after b
t must clearly be worse o¤.

14.5.3 Myopia
An obvious motivation for the introduction of social security is that consumers
do not make appropriate provision for their retirement. This may be because
they are myopic and fail to appreciate their later needs, either discounting the
future completely or placing a lower weight upon than would capture their true
preferences. Alternatively, consumers may make mistakes in their planning, lack
information or simply be irrational. Whatever the reason, empirical evidence
(Diamond (1977), Kotliko¤, Spivak and Summers (1982)) does suggest that
consumers accrue insu¢cient savings to cover retirement.
Although the behavioural foundations of myopia di¤er signi…cantly from
those of consistent utility maximisation, the formulation of myopic behaviour
of Feldstein (1985) can be incorporated into the analysis developed above by
making only minor adjustments. Assume that the preferences of each consumer
can be represented by the utility function
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U t = U 1 xtt + U 2 x t+1
t ; (14.62)

but, due to myopia, chooses their saving decision to maximise


¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U t = U 1 xtt + ¸U 2 x t+1
t ; (14.63)

where 0 ¸ 1 captures the degree of myopia. Complete myopia is given by


¸ = 0. Each consumer works only during the …rst period of life and divides post-
tax wages between consumption and savings sub ject to the budget constraint

x tt = [1 ¡ ¿ ] wt ¡ st : (14.64)

A second aspect of consumers’ myopia is that they underestimate the level of


bene…ts received from the social security program in their retirement. The
perceived budget constraint is therefore

x t+1
t = [1 + r] st + ®¯ t+1 ; (14.65)

with ® < 1. It should be clear that the two aspects of myopia have con‡icting
e¤ects upon
¡ t+1 ¢ the level of savings. Adopting the assumption that U 1 (xtt ) and
2
U xt are logarithmic, the optimal level of saving is

¸ ®¯ t+1
st = [1 ¡ ¿ ] wt ¡ ; (14.66)
1+¸ [1 + ¸] [1 + r]
14.5. DETERMINATION AND JUSTIFICATION 453

where it should be noted that low values of ¸ reduce saving while low values
of ® increase it. Using the budget constraint for the social security program,
¯ t = ¿ wt [1 + n], and assuming that the wage grows at rate g, so that w t+1 =
w t [1 + g], (14.67) can be written

¸ ®¿ [1 + °] w t
st = [1 ¡ ¿ ] wt ¡ ; (14.67)
1+¸ [1 + ¸] [1 + r]

where [1 + °] = [1 + n] [1 + g].
In contrast to the myopia in consumer behaviour, the social security program
is chosen to maximise the social welfare on the basis of true preference. In year
t the total utility of those alive is
t t
W t = [1 + n] ln ([1 ¡ ¿ ] wt ¡ st ) + [1 + n] ln ([1 + r] st¡1 + ¯ t) : (14.68)

The optimal social security program is de…ned as that which maximises the
steady-state value of (14.69). When ® = 0, so that the future pension is entirely
discounted, the optimal tax rate is

[1 + ¸] [1 + °] ¡ ¸ [1 + r] [2 + n]
¿ = : (14.69)
[1 + ¸] [1 + °] [2 + n] ¡ ¸ [1 + r] [2 + n]

With complete myopia, ¸h = 0i and (14.70) reduces to ¿ = [2 + n]¡1 with cor-


responding pension ¯ = 1+n
2+n
w. If population growth is zero, the pension is
exactly half the wage. It rises above half the wage when population growth is
positive. More generally, it can be seen from (14.70) that the tax rate falls, and
with it the pension, as ¸ rises. Hence the less myopic the consumers, the lower
is the pension. If the pension is restricted to be non-zero, then ¯ = 0 if

[1 + °]
¸¸ : (14.70)
[1 + r] [2 + n] ¡ [1 + °]

Therefore, even though myopia may in some cases justify social security, even
in this simple framework there is a range of partial myopia described in (14.71)
for which social security is not justi…ed. If ® 6= 0 broadly similar conclusions
apply and there remains a signi…cant range of parameter values for which social
security is not justi…ed. In addition, it can be shown that the optimal level of
pension is decreasing in ®.
The main message of this analysis is that myopia is not in itself justi…cation
for the introduction of social security. Although myopic consumers will not
make su¢cient provision for their retirement this is not a su¢cient reason for
providing a state pension.
This myopia formulation is also used by Feldstein (1987) to assess the means
testing of social security. In an economy with a mixture of myopic consumers
and fully-rational consumers, the there is a natural trade-o¤ between providing
protection for the myopic who fail to make adequate provision for retirement
and reducing the incentive to save of the rational. The argument in favour of
454 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

means-testing is that it allows an overall reduction in the size of the program


and therefore of the distortion it causes. The reduction in distortion is especially
relevant in this situation since those who would not receive bene…ts after means-
testing would not have their savings behaviour a¤ected at all by the existence
of the program.
In an economy that is composed of a mixture of completely myopic (¸ = 0)
consumers and fully-rational (¸ = 1) who, except of the value of ¸, have identical
preferences and earnings, Feldstein (1987) shows that there is a strong case for
means-testing but it is not always superior to a program of universal bene…ts.
The reason why the universal system may be superior is that means-testing
may result in a low level of bene…ts since, if the bene…t is not to be universal by
default, it is necessary to provide an incentive for some consumers to continue
saving. An upper bound is therefore placed upon means-tested bene…ts which
may be below the level attainable in a universal program.

14.5.4 Uncertainty
The motivation for social security in the presence of uncertainty has already
been addressed for static economies in Chapter 7. It was shown there how social
insurance could raise welfare by enabling intragenerational transfers of income.
Essentially, the insurance contract reallocated income from the fortunate to the
unfortunate. In a dynamic setting a social security program can also provide
intergenerational income transfers as insurance against unfavourable outcomes.
This intergenerational insurance aspect of social security clearly has important
implications for the design of programs.
Two forms of uncertainty will be considered in this section. The economies
considered up to this point have been characterised by populations that have
grown at a steady rate so that the size of each generation has been known
with certainty. The …rst source of uncertainty to be considered arises from
randomness in the size of the generation that is born at each date. In this case,
social security can play a role in insuring against the risk of being born in a large
generation. The second source of uncertainty is introduced via randomness in
the production technology. That is, given known inputs, output is determined by
a random process. Social security can then act so as to insure those generations
faced with unfavourable realisations of the productive shock.
Random population growth and random output both represent forms of
aggregate uncertainty that cannot be a¤ected by the actions of individual con-
sumers. In contrast, Section 6 will consider individual uncertainty about the
length of life. Since the length of life may potentially be a¤ected by decisions
taken by consumers, lifetime uncertainty is of a di¤erent nature to aggregate
uncertainty and requires a separate treatment.

Population uncertainty
To be born into a generation that is large relative to its predecessor and its
successor has two disadvantages. When working, the wage received will be low
14.5. DETERMINATION AND JUSTIFICATION 455

since the labour-capital ratio is high and when retired the return on savings
will be low since the capital-labour ratio will be high in the next period. In the
absence of social security, large generations will therefore have a relatively lower
level of welfare than small generations. These observations are incorporated
into the analysis of social security by Smith (1982).
Population uncertainty can be introduced by taking the economy of Section
3 but treating the growth rate of population as a random variable. The size of
the generation born at t is given by Ht = [1 + nt ] Ht ¡1 where nt is drawn from
some known distribution. To simplify the analysis, it is assumed that consumers
born at t ¡ 1 know the value of nt when making their savings assumption.
Two alternative structures for the pay-as-you-go social security program are
considered. In the …xed tax system, the level of tax remains constant for all
generations but the level of pension received is dependent upon generation size.
Alternatively, in a …xed pension system it is the level of the tax that is variable.
Under the …xed tax system, a tax rate of ¿ in period t is equal to a pension
of [1 + nt ] ¿ for each member of generation t ¡ 1. The budget constraint of a
consumer born in t is therefore

xt+1 rt+1 ¡ nt+1


xtt + t
= wt ¡ ¿: (14.71)
1 + rt+1 1 + rt+1

Hence, in a dynamically e¢cient equilibrium with rt+1 ¸ nt+1 if the interest rate
and the wage are una¤ected by the introduction of social security, no generation
(with the exception of the generation that bene…ts when the system is …rst
introduced) can be made better-o¤ by the introduction of the …xed tax program.
The same result can also be shown to apply if the wage rate and interest rate
do adjust provided consumption is never an inferior good. The reason for this
conclusion is simple. With the …xed tax large generations will receive smaller
pensions than small generations despite being the poorest.
Under a …xed pension system with the pension is …xed at ¯ , a member of
¯
generation t will pay a tax of 1+n t
so that their budget constraint is

xt+1 ¯ ¯
xtt + t
= wt ¡ + : (14.72)
1 + rt+1 1 + nt 1 + rt+1

If the economy is dynamically e¢cient with rt+1 ¸ nt+1 , this does not rule
out the possibility that rt+ 1 < nt which, when the interest rate and the wage
rate are constant, will occur when generation t is large. For large generations
(14.73) therefore shows that the introduction of a social security program with
a …xed pension may bene…t large generations although it will reduce the welfare
of small generations. When the wage rate and interest rate are not …xed, the
o¤setting e¤ects of the reduction in wage rate due to reduced saving and the
receipt of the pension leave the outcome ambiguous. However Smith (1982) does
provide an example for which expected utility, where the expectation is taken
with respect to the distribution of generation size, increases if risk aversion is
su¢ciently great.
456 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

An alternative approach to the insurance role of social security with an


uncertain population is discussed by Brandts and de Bartolome (1992). As
already noted, if the generation born at t is large, the wage will be low and
the return on capital high. Retired consumers therefore gain by the birth of a
large generation whilst the large generation loses. The converse occurs when the
generation is small. Since, at any time t, the incomes of the young and the old
are negatively correlated, there are potentially gains to be obtained from the
provision of insurance. To fully exploit these, it must be necessary for transfers
to be made from young to old or vice versa.
The analysis of Brandts and de Bartolome determines whether the introduc-
tion of a small program can be Pareto-improving for the existing members of the
generation born at 0 and potential members of generation 1. The existence and
structure of a Pareto-improving contract is then dependent upon the process
by which potential consumers become actual consumers. The interpretation is
that there exists a pool of potential consumers who may become members of
generation 1 with some probability and the size of generation 1 is determined
according to a known distribution function.
Three cases are examined. In the …rst, the welfare of an unborn worker
is taken to be the expected utility in …rst period of life if they were born. A
Pareto-improving contract will almost always exist in this case although the
structure of payments may run in the opposite direction to those that would
provide insurance. The second case corresponds to that of Green (1988) and
assumes that unborn workers are arranged in a queue with those are the front
certain to be born and others further down the line only born if the generation is
large. Since those who will only be born if the generation is large care only about
the payment they will receive in that state, no contract exists that is Pareto-
improving. In the …nal case, each potential consumer in the pool of unborn
consumers is treated symmetrically and has the same probability of being born.
In this case, a social insurance contract is always Pareto-improving.

Output uncertainty
The interaction between output uncertainty and social security has been analysed
Enders and Lapan (1982) in an economy in which labour is the sole input into
production and production is subject to a multiplicative disturbance. Since the
form of technology leads to an absence of capital as a store of value, …at money
is introduced to serve this purpose. In consequence, the underlying structure of
the economy is distinct from those studied in previous sections.
Given labour supply of ` t from a consumer of generation t, the output of
that consumer is given by
y t = Â t` t ; (14.73)
where
¡ Ât is ¢the random disturbance. It is assumed that E (Â t) = 1, that
cov Ât ; Ât+i = 0 all i and that the same value of  t is realised by all con-
sumers in generation t. With product price p t, the budget constraint in the …rst
period of life is
pt x tt + Mt = pt Ât ` t [1 ¡ ¿ ] ; (14.74)
14.5. DETERMINATION AND JUSTIFICATION 457

and in the second period


£ ¤
p t+1 x t+1
t = Mt + ¯ t+ 1 = p t  t` t [1 ¡ ¿ ] ¡ xtt + ¯ t+1 : (14.75)

It is assumed that the pension is determined according to the relation


¸
`t
¯ t+ 1 = ¿ pt+1 Â t+1 Lt+1 ; (14.76)
Lt

where Lt denotes aggregate labour supply. This formulation relates the level
of pension to work-e¤ort in period t. Alternative speci…cations could equally
well be adopted. If each generation is of identical size, the market for the
consumption good will clear in period t if

M
+ x tt = Â tLt [1 ¡ ¿ ] ; (14.77)
pt

with M total money supply. From (14.78) it can be seen that given x tt the
market clearing price level is dependent upon the realisation of Ât .
If there were no uncertainty in the economy, so that  t = 1, all t, the
stationarity of the economy implies that the price level would be constant over
time, and the identical consumers of each generation would each supply the
same quantity of labour. Eliminating M t between (14.75) and (14.76), and
using (14.77), it can be seen that the resulting lifetime budget constraint is
independent of the parameters of the social security system so that the social
security system described has no e¤ect in a certain environment. This conclusion
arises because under the assumption of a constant population, the return on
social insurance taxes is equal to the return of private saving.
When uncertainty is present, each consumer chooses their labour supply
prior to the realisation of  t but chooses consumption and savings after Ât
has been realised. Their preferences are represented by the utility function
¡ ¢ xt
U x tt ; x t+1
t ; ` t . Denoting the propensity to consumer out of gross income, Â t`t ,
t
by » , a stationary rational expectations equilibrium for this economy is now
de…ned.
Stationary rational expectations equilibrium
A stationary rational expectations equilibrium is a pair of functions p (Â),
» (Â) and a level of labour supply ` that satisfy

M
(i) [1 ¡ » (Â)] ÂH` = + ¿ ÂH`;
p (Â)
µ µ ¶ ¶
p (Â) Â` [1 ¡ ¿ ¡ s] +1
(ii) » (Â) = arg max U Â`s; E Â +1 + ¿Â ` ; ` ;
fsg p (Â+ 1 )
and

µ µ ¶¶
p (Â) Âs [1 ¡ ¿ ¡ » (Â)] +1
(iii) ` = arg max EÂ;Â+1 U Â`» (Â) ; + ¿ Â s; s ;
fsg p (Â+1 )
458 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

where  is the productivity level in the …rst period of a consumers life, Â+ 1


the level in the second period and Ex denotes the expectation taken over the
random variable x. Condition (i) captures market clearing, (ii) the choice of
consumption to maximise utility taken after  is realised and (iii) the choice of
labour supply made before  is realised.
To permit an explicit solution a utility function of the CES form
¸
1 h£ t ¤½ £ t+ 1 ¤½ i1
½ ½
U= x t + ¸xt + [1 ¡ ` t] ; ½ < 1; ½ 6= 0; (14.78)
½

is adopted where ¸ 1 is the rate of time preference. For ½ = 0 this collapses


to a log-linear function. The following theorem can then be proved.

Theorem 65 (Enders and Lapan) Two equilibrium solutions to (ii) exist: (a)
£ ¤1¡½
» 1 (Â) = 1 ¡ ¿ , (b) »2 (Â) < 1 ¡ ¿ . If ¸ 1¡¿
¿ < 1, (a) is the unique solution.
Furthermore, for equilibria characterised by (b) there is a level of the tax rate
1
¸ 1¡½
¿¤ = 1 , such that a social security program with tax rate ¿ ¤ maximises
1+ ¸ 1¡½
the expected utility of each consumer.

Proof. The solution of the maximisation in (ii) is characterised by


0 " ¡ ¢ # ½¡ 1 1
½¡1 p (Â) p (Â) Â` [1 ¡ ¿ ¡ »] + ¿ p Â+1  +1 `
[Â`» ] = ¸EÂ+1 @ A;
p (Â +1 ) p (Â+1 )
(14.79)
which can be reduced to
³£ ¤½ £ ¡ ¢¤ £ ¡ ¢¤ ½¡1 ´
½¡1
 ½ » (Â) [1 ¡ ¿ ¡ » (Â)] = ¸EÂ+1 Â+1 1 ¡ ¿ ¡ » Â+1 1 ¡ » Â+1 ;
(14.80)
by employing (i) and the assumption that all consumers are identical. Solutions
(a) and (b) can then be seen by inspection.
Noting that  and Â+1 have the same distribution, for solution (b) (14.81)
can be further reduced to
à ¸½¡1 !
1 ¡ » (Â)
¸E = 1: (14.81)
» (Â)
µh i½¡1 ¶
2 1¡» (Â) £ 1¡¿ ¤1¡½
Since » (Â) < 1 ¡ ¿ , the inequality ¸E »(Â) <¸ ¿ must hold
£ 1¡¿ ¤1¡ ½
in such an equilibrium. Hence for tax rates such that ¸ ¿ < 1, (b) cannot
be an equilibrium.
h i
¤ 1¡½
Now let ¿ ¤ satisfy ¸ 1¡¿
¿¤ = 1. Then as ¿ ! ¿ ¤ from below, » ! 1 ¡ ¿ ¤
h i ¡1 h i¡1 ¸¡1
1 1 1
with 1 ¡ ¿ ¤ = 1 + ¸ 1¡½ and ` (¿ ¤ ) = 1 + ¸ 1¡½ [E (½ )] ½¡1 + 1 .
14.6. LIFETIME UNCERTAINTY 459

Again employing the observation that  and Â+1 have the same distribution,
expected utility can be written
¸
1 1
E (U ) = [[1 ¡ `]½ + `½ E (½ [» (Â)½ + ¸ [1 ¡ » (Â)]½ ])] ½ (14.82)
½

It is clear that this is maximised by » (¿ ¤ ) and ` (¿ ¤ ).


This analysis demonstrates how the existence of a social security program can
raise the level of welfare when the economy is faced by production uncertainty.
Since no social security was required in the equivalent economy with certainty,
production uncertainty provides an argument for the provision of social security
that does not depend on any form of economic irrationality, such as myopia, or
market failure.

14.6 Lifetime uncertainty


The distinguishing feature of uncertainty about the length of life is that it con-
stitutes individual, rather than aggregate, risk. Since the risk is individual,
information about the nature of the risk may be held by the individual and
be unobservable to the government. Furthermore, individuals may take unob-
servable actions that a¤ect the nature of the risk. Each of these aspects of
individual risk leads to a position of asymmetric information between agents in
the economy which can result in the failure of markets to achieve a Pareto e¢-
cient outcome. Such failure provides a further motivation for the introduction
of social security.
Consider an economy in which each consumer lives with certainty for one
period but with some positive probability less than 1 may die before they enter
their second period of life. The payment of tax towards a social security program
can then be viewed as the purchase of an annuity which has a return equal to
the pension if the consumer survives into the second period and a return of zero
if they do not. The analysis of Sheshinski and Weiss (1981), which is described
in more detail below, introduced this perspective of social security and showed
how the introduction of such annuities with an actuarially fair return, where
none previously existed, could raise welfare.
If all information were public, there is clearly no reason why such annuities
could not be provided privately at actuarially fair rates of return. If they were,
the introduction of a social security program with the same structure of returns
would have no e¤ect on welfare. To avoid this conclusion, Sheshinski and Weiss
(1981) rule out such private annuities while Karni and Zilcha (1986) allow pri-
vate annuities but assume that they can only be provided at actuarially unfair
rates for reasons of resource cost in provision. The individual nature of lifetime
uncertainty however provides su¢cient reasons for not expecting actuarially fair
private annuities to be available. If the probability of not surviving into the sec-
ond period of life di¤ers between consumers and is private information, then
the problem of adverse selection may arise. That is, an annuity designed for
those who have a low probability of survival will also appeal to those with a
460 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

high probability. Hence any actuarially fair annuity will entail a loss for its
supplier. If individuals can take actions that a¤ect the probability of survival
which cannot be observed by the suppliers of annuities then moral hazard will
lead to no actuarially fair annuities being o¤ered.
The basic model of uncertain lifetime and the annuity approach to social
security are now described. This is followed by an analysis of the consequences
of adverse selection and moral hazard for economies with both private annuities
and social security.

14.6.1 Symmetric information


Uncertainty in the length of lifetime is captured by assuming that each consumer
lives with certainty for one period of life during which they work and that they
then live for a fraction µ, 0 µ 1, of the second period during which they are
retired. The retirement period µ is distributed randomly across each generation
and the distribution is the same for all generations. The value of µ is known
neither to a consumer or to the government but its distribution is known to
both.
In addition to the standard form of saving that pays a return of r, a fully-
funded so cial security program is represented as an annuity that pays a return
throughout a consumers retirement. The social security program is assumed to
be actuarially fair so that its return is given by 1+r µ
where µ = E (µ). For later
comparison with a pay-as-you-go program, the optimum social security program
is interpreted as the level of annuity that is chosen by one of the (ex ante)
identical consumers. Denoting the purchase of annuities by a representative
consumer born in t by at , a consumer solves the maximisation
¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ ¢ ¢
max U = U 1 x tt + E U 1 xt+
t
1
; µ + V (b t ) ; (14.83)
f xt;xt ;a t ;stg
t t+1

subject to the budget constraints

x tt = w + b t¡1 ¡ at ¡ st ; (14.84)

and ¸
1+ r t+1
b t = [1 + r] st + at ¡ x t µ; (14.85)
µ
where b t¡1 is the bequest received, b t the bequest left and V (b t ) the utility
derived from the bequest. The …rst-order conditions for this maximisation with
respect to st , at and xtt +1 are respectively

¡U 10 + [1 + r] E (V 0) = 0; (14.86)
¸
10 1+ r
¡U + E (µV 0) = 0; (14.87)
µ
and ¡ ¢
E Ux2 ¡ µV 0 = 0: (14.88)
14.6. LIFETIME UNCERTAINTY 461

From (14.87) and (14.88) it follows that E (µV 0 )¡µE (V 0 ), so that cov (µ; V 0 ) =
0 and hence, when V 00 < 0, bt is constant for all µ. From the budget constraints
(14.85) and (14.86) it then follows that xt+t
1
= 1+ r at and bt = [1 + r] st . Since
µ
the consumer chooses the purchase of annuities to maximise welfare, a fully-
funded system with tax rate ¿ equal to the value of at that arises from the
solution to conditions (14.87) to (14.89) will be optimal.
Turning now to a pay-as-you-go system, let the tax paid by generation t be
denoted by ¿ t so that the bene…t received by a member of generation t ¡ 1 is
µ¿ t
µ
. With this notation, the budget constraints facing a consumer are

x tt = w + b t¡1 ¡ ¿ t ¡ st; (14.89)

and
¸
¿ t+1 t+1
b t = [1 + r] st + ¡ xt µ: (14.90)
µ

To characterise the optimal policy, it is …rst noted that level of welfare of gen-
eration t is now determined by the net bequest, bt ¡ ¿ t+1 , left to the following
generation. The optimal program then solves
¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ ¢ ¢
max U = U 1 x tt + E U 1 x t+1
t ; µ + V (b t ¡ ¿ t+1 ) ; (14.91)
f xtt ;xt+1
t ;¿ t;st g

subject to (14.90) and (14.91). The …rst-order conditions for this maximisation
with respect to s t, ¿ t and xt+1
t are respectively

¡U 10 + [1 + r] E (V 0 (bt ¡ ¿ t+1 )) = 0; (14.92)

¡ £ ¤¢
E V 0 (bt ¡ ¿ t+1 ) µ ¡ µ = 0; (14.93)

and
¡ ¢
E Ux2 ¡ µV 0 (bt ¡ ¿ t+1 ) = 0: (14.94)

The solution to (14.93) to (14.95) satis…es ¿ t+1 = x t+1


t µ and bt = [1 + r] st .
More importantly, it is clear from inspection of (14.87) to (14.89) and (14.93) to
(14.95) that the outcomes under the two social security programs will involve the
same levels of consumption and the bequests will di¤er by an amount equal to
the social security tax. The optimal levels of the two program therefore achieve
the same real equilibrium and the method of …nancing, being it fully-funded or
pay-as-you-go, is irrelevant. In addition, it is clear that the introduction of the
social security system raises expected utility.
Sheshinski and Weiss (1981) extend this analysis to show that a decrease
in the birth rate increases the optimal level of social security whilst reducing
bequests and savings. As to be expected, an increase in life expectancy also
increases the optimal level of social security.
462 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

14.6.2 Adverse selection


In the economy described in section 6.1 the optimal allocation achieved by the
fully-funded social security program could also be achieved by an actuarially
fair privately provided annuity. If such a private annuity were provided, no fur-
ther welfare improvements could be achieved by the provision of social security.
However, the existence of private annuities is not, in itself, su¢cient to make
the provision of social security redundant. Myopia on the part of consumers,
which was discussed in 5.3 and in this context by Feldstein (1990), will result
in an ine¢cient equilibrium as consumers will not purchase su¢cient annuities.
Enforced purchases through social security could then raise welfare. The same
would apply to mistaken assessments of survival probabilities.
A social security program may also be justi…ed if private annuities are not
actuarially fair. The lack of actuarial fairness may arise simply as a result of
the resources that are employed in operating the annuities and in the provision
of risk premia to underwriters. This aspect of private annuities provides the
motivation for the analysis of Karni and Zilcha (1986) which shows that the
introduction of social security will improve welfare provided that it o¤ers better
terms than private annuities. There is no reason though why the costs of running
a public annuity system should be any less than those of a private system so
that this motivation for social security is not entirely persuasive.
A second reason why private annuities should not be actuarially fair arises
from private information about survival probabilities and the adverse selection
problem that arises. Unlike a statutory social security program, the suppliers
of private annuities are subject to competition in the market. As …rst shown
by Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) in the context of insurance markets, with
adverse selection it is possible for the competitive equilibrium to be Pareto
ine¢cient with the equilibrium contract not o¤ering full insurance. The same
reasoning was shown by Eckstein, Eichenbaum and Peled (1985) to apply to
private annuity markets.
It is now assumed that each generation can be divided into two groups, A
and B, with ° type B consumers for each type A. All consumers are endowed
with ! units of the single, non-produced consumption good and live for a least
one period. Consumers in group i have a probability ½i of surviving into the
second period of life with 0 < ½A < ½B < 1. Assuming that each generation
is large, these probabilities are also the proportions of each type that live for a
second period. Focusing attention on steady-state equilibria only, the utility of
a type i consumer is given by
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U i = U x i1 + ½i U x i2 ; (14.95)

where the survival probability is used to discount second-period utility.


Pareto e¢cient allocations for this economy are characterised by solving the
optimisation
X X
max ¹iU i; ¹i ¸ 0; ¹i = 1; (14.96)
x i i
f 1 2
;x ; i= A;B g i=A;B
14.6. LIFETIME UNCERTAINTY 463

subject to
xA A B B
1 + ½ A x2 + °x1 + °½ B x 2 = ! [1 + °] : (14.97)
When both ¹i > 0, the solution to the optimisation is characterised by
¡ ¢ ¡ ¢
U 0 xA
1 U 0 xB
¡ ¢= ¡ 1 ¢: (14.98)
U 0 xA
2 U 0 xB
2

For later comparison, it should be noted that this optimum can be sustained by
the provision of two private annuities that have returns of ½1 and ½1 . The …rst
A B
will be purchased by type A consumers and the second by type B. This results
in a separating equilibrium with both types of consumers purchasing annuities
that are actuarially fair for their group.
Asymmetric information is introduced by assuming that each consumer knows
their probability of survival and the population proportions. The government
knows the probabilities of survival and the population proportion but cannot
infer the survival probability of an individual consumer. An annuity contract is
de…ned as a pair fav ; ³ v g where av is the number of units of the annuity that
must be purchased and ³ v the return. A consumer purchasing contract will
achieve utility level

V i (a; ³ ) = U (! ¡ a) + ½iU (³ a) : (14.99)

From (14.100) the gradient of an indi¤erence curve is

dxi1 U 0 (³a)
i
= ¡½i 0 ; (14.100)
dx2 U (! ¡ a)

so that at any level of consumption the gradient of a type B consumers in-


di¤erence curve will be steeper than that of a type A. The equilibrium of a
competitive market in annuity supply is now determined and shown to be in-
e¢cient. The possibility for a social security program to raise welfare is then
discussed.
An equilibrium in the supply of contracts is de…ned as follows.
Contract equilibrium
An equilibrium is a set of contracts such that:
(i) no contract in the equilibrium set makes a negative pro…t;
(ii) no contract outside the equilibrium set would make a positive pro…t if
o¤ered.
The properties of the equilibrium are given in Theorem 14.2.

Theorem 66 (Eckstein, Eichenbaum and Peled)


(i) There can be no pooling equilibrium.
(ii) If an equilibrium exists it is a separating
n equilibrium
o in which consumers
of type A purchase a contract of the form a1 ; ½1 and the contract purchased
n o A
½
by type B consumers is 1+½B ! B ; ½1 .
B B
(iii) For su¢ciently small values of ¸ > 0, there is no equilibrium.
464 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

Figure 14.1: Non-Existence of Pooling Equilibrium

Proof. (i) If a pooling equilibrium


£ were to
¤ exist it must satisfy the zero-
pro…t condition aA + °aB = ³ ½AaA + ½B °aB for the pooling rate of return ³
and aA ; aB are the purchases of annuities by As and Bs. Since pooling implies
aA = aB = a, ³ = ½ 1+° , ½1 < ³ < ½1 . In Figure 14.1 a potential pooling
A+½ B ° B A
equilibrium contract is shown by P . All other contracts with return must also lie
on the line joining ! and !³ . The relative slopes of the indi¤erence curves then
implies that a contract such as ¡ that is preferred to P by group A consumers
and -makes®positive pro…t always exists regardless of the location of P on the
line !; !³ .
(ii) It is a condition of equilibrium that each contract o¤ered must make non-
negative pro…ts. The contract purchased by type B consumers cannot therefore
be more favourable than that which gives full insurance and consumption levels
xB B !
1 = x2 = 1+½ B nor can the contract o¤ered to type As be preferred by the Bs
to the full insurance contract. Hence if a separating equilibrium exists it must
have full insurance for the Bs and the type As being supplied with the contract
de…ned as the solution to
µ ¶
a1
max U (! ¡ a1 ) + ½A U ; (14.101)
fa 1g ½A

subject to the restriction that type Bs prefer their full insurance contract
µ ¶ µ ¶
! a1
[1 + ½B ] U ¸ U (! ¡ a1 ) + ½B U : (14.102)
1 + ½B ½A

This proves (ii).


(iii) The potential separating equilibrium of (ii) with type A’s contract at
SA and B’s at S B is shown in Figure 14.2. This equilibrium will not exists of
14.6. LIFETIME UNCERTAINTY 465

Figure 14.2: Separating Equilibrium

the line describing actuarially fair contracts is as shown in (a). In that case a
contract such as P 00 will be preferred by both types and make positive pro…ts.
This will always be possible for small °. The separating equilibrium does exist
in (b) since no pooling contract can make positive pro…t. This proves (iii).
Having now characterised the competitive equilibrium, it is possible to con-
sider the e¤ect of introducing social security. The distinction between contracts
that can be o¤ered by private …rms and social security is that a social security
program can cross-subsidise the provision of annuities to one group with the
proceeds from another. If a competitive …rm attempted to do this, it would
be undercut by another …rm that o¤ered a slightly more attractive version of
the pro…t-making contract. To show that circumstances exist in which social
security can raise welfare, consider each consumer having to participate in a
mandatory program which involved the purchase of a units of annuity with an
actuarially fair return ½ = ½ 1+° based on the population survival probabil-
A+ °½B
ities. Figure 14.3 shows how the social security program raises welfare. The
forced purchase of annuities with value a at the actuarially fair rate leaves at
most ! ¡ a to consume in period 1. Beginning at this point on the popula-
tion fair rate line, the two groups can then purchase annuities along their own
fair-return lines. This modi…es the budget constraints from their initial position
in (a) to the new position in (b) with a consequent change in the separating
equilibrium. The new separating equilibrium is determined by the intersection
of the indi¤erence curve of type Bs through the full insurance point with the
fair-return line of type As. In (b) this intersection is shown above the initial
indi¤erence curve of type As. Therefore in this case social security leads to a
Pareto improvement. However, study of the Figure will show that this need not
be the case.
The outcome of this analysis is that social security may not always be able to
466 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY

Figure 14.3: Social Security

improve upon the equilibrium of the competitive market but, even when it can,
it will not lead to a Pareto e¢cient outcome. The government is constrained
by the same informational limitations as the competitive market and has only
the advantage of being able to cross-subsidise between contracts. This is not
su¢cient to achieve the Pareto e¢cient outcome of full insurance for both types.
It should also be noted that when the social security program does lead to a
Pareto improvement, the type As would prefer to exchange private annuities for
social security whereas the type Bs would prefer the opposite.
An alternative analysis of the e¤ect of adverse selection is given in Abel
(1986a). That analysis is generalised by the inclusion of a bequest motive and
private savings. However, only a pooling equilibrium in the provision of private
annuities is considered. It is shown that the rate of return on private annuities
is below the population (fair) rate and falls when social security, which is fair,
is introduced. The e¤ect of social security on the capital stock is ambiguous.

14.6.3 Moral hazard


Moral hazard can be introduced into the analysis of social security by assum-
ing that consumers can take action which a¤ect their longevity but cannot be
observed by …rms providing annuities or by the government. This can be in-
corporated into the framework used above by assuming that the probability of
survival is dependent upon the level of consumption of some health-related ac-
tivity so that ½ = ½ (e). If the consumption raises longevity then ½0 (e) > 0 and
if it reduces it ½0 (e) < 0.
The central reason why the competitive supply of annuities in such an econ-
omy is ine¢cient is that consumers, when choosing their consumption level of
e, take account only of the direct cost of the activity. Since the price of a fair
14.7. CONCLUSIONS 467

annuity is based upon ½ (e), the health-related activity also has an indirect cost
via the e¤ect it has upon the price of annuities. A consumer maximising subject
to …xed prices does not take this into account. This externality generates an
ine¢cient equilibrium as discussed in Chapter 10.
These ideas have been formalised by Davies and Kuhn (1992). They show
that the nature of the externality leads to an over-investment in the health
related activity in the sense that a reduction in investment accompanied by a
actuarially fair reduction in the price of annuities would raise welfare. Further-
more, since the government is constrained by the same informational de…ciency
as private …rms, provision of social security at fair returns cannot raise welfare
and will reduce it if mandatory purchases are above private purchases. Unlike
adverse selection where the government could pool risks when the …rms could
not, the government has no advantage over …rms in the case of moral hazard.

14.7 Conclusions
Many aspects of social security have been addressed in this chapter from the
design of an optimal program in the Diamond economy to the interaction of so-
cial security and asymmetric information. In terms of broad policy conclusions,
the most compelling must be that there are many circumstances in which the
introduction of a social security program can raise welfare and, of those consid-
ered above, only myopia involved any irrationality on the part of the agents in
the economy.
Without uncertainty, social security could be justi…ed by dynamic ine¢-
ciency in the economy even when the retirement decision was made endogenous.
More surprisingly, the con‡icting e¤ects of an increase in the rate of population
growth lead to there being several possible relations between it and the level of
welfare and, consequently, between the rate of population growth and the struc-
ture of social security. With aggregate uncertainty, social security could play a
limited redistributive role between fortunate and unfortunate generations. Indi-
vidual uncertainty introduced asymmetric information and, as the government
need have no informational advantage over other agents, it was not always pos-
sible for social security to raise welfare. Finally, it should also be noted that
voting mechanisms were shown to be an ine¢cient means of determining the
level of social security to be provided since there was no obvious connection
between the level they determined and the optimal level.
468 CHAPTER 14. SOCIAL SECURITY
Chapter 15

Debt and Taxes

15.1 Introduction
In the policy analyses of previous chapters it was invariably assumed that the
government revenue requirement was pre-determined and the policy instruments
were chosen to maximise welfare given this …xed requirement. The satisfaction of
the revenue constraint implicitly prevented the government issuing any debt. In
a static setting there is some sense in this procedure since, by its very nature, the
static setting prevents a comprehensive analysis of the e¤ects of the borrowing
and repayment process. Introducing time and considering the intertemporal
maximisation of welfare permits the endogenisation of government debt and
allows the determination of its optimal level to become part of the overall policy
formulation process. It also allows the interaction between debt and taxation
to be explored. The employment of both debt and taxation as instruments of
government policy will a¤ect the capital market of the economy and, through
this, the dynamic evolution of the economy and the eventual steady state.
The content of this chapter will re‡ect these intertemporal issues. Section 2
is concerned with the e¤ects of the maintenance of a constant stock of debt upon
the long-run equilibrium of the economy. Section 3 then analyses the relation
between lump-sum taxation and debt and characterises the optimal combination
of the two instruments. The focus of Section 4 is upon debt neutrality and the
circumstances in which this does, and does not, hold. Section 5 of the chapter
is more concerned with tax policy than debt and it studies the optimisation
of income and interest taxation in an economy with an heterogeneous popula-
tion. In this case, both intragenerational and intergenerational redistribution
are important.
It should be noted that the policy optimisation problems studied in this
chapter are complicated by the in…nite timespan of the economy. This leads to
the maximisation being subject to the in…nite set of constraints which describe
the evolution of the economy. Two ways of characterising the solutions to such
problems are illustrated. The …rst is based upon the methodology of dynamic

469
470 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

programming; in particular the principle of optimality. The second approach


reduces the dimensionality of the problem by assuming that the chosen alloca-
tions achieve Pareto optimality between generations. This provides a shadow
interest rate with which future variables can be discounted.

15.2 The e¤ect of debt


The e¤ect of national debt has long been a contentious issue, with the debate
stretching back to at least Ricardo (1817). It is also a subject at the heart
of policy analysis since the issuing of debt is an important practical policy
tool. The conservative perspective upon debt is that it can only be harmful to
welfare and that governments should do all they can to minimise borrowing.
Alternatively, the philosophy of Keynsianism is that debt is simply another
tool of policy and should be employed whenever advantageous. To assess these
competing viewpoints, it is clear that a dynamic economy must be analysed as
its e¤ects are felt through its issuing, servicing and redemption.
The existence of debt instruments as an alternative to investment in physical
capital as a means of saving for consumers alters the relationship between the
level of savings and available capital for the following period. In fact, capital
accumulation must be less for any given level of private saving. The taxes
required to service debt also have an e¤ect upon the behaviour of consumers and
the equilibrium of the economy. Given these observations, the question remains
as to whether debt is always harmful to welfare. This section will determine
both the positive e¤ects of debt on the long-run equilibrium of the economy
and its welfare e¤ects. This is undertaken for both internal and external debt.
The analysis is set in the Diamond economy, with a …xed labour supply, and a
diagrammatic framework is employed that simpli…es the derivation of results.

15.2.1 External and internal debt


The starting point of the analysis is to distinguish between internal and external
debt. This is necessary since they have distinctly di¤erent e¤ects upon the
stationary equilibrium and the welfare level of consumers.
External debt is debt owed to agents located abroad, that is the holders of the
debt are not resident in the economy that issued the debt. On such debt there
is an interest charge that must be paid each period and this must be …nanced
by either further borrowing or by taxation. The important features of such debt
are that it is not in competition with physical capital as a savings instrument
for the consumers of the issuing economy but its servicing and repayment lead
to a ‡ow of resources out of the economy.
In contrast, internal debt is held by residents of the economy in which it
is issued. With internal debt the government borrows o¤ its own citizens by
providing bonds which compete with private capital. Private savings are divided
between the two investment instruments. When there is no uncertainty bonds
and capital will be perfect substitutes, so in equilibrium they must pay the same
15.2. THE EFFECT OF DEBT 471

rate of return. The cost of …nancing internal debt is again met by either further
borrowing or by taxation. In contrast to external debt, internal debt does not
lead to any resources being transferred away from the economy that issues the
debt.

15.2.2 E¤ects of debt


The analysis now considers the real e¤ect upon the steady state equilibrium,
and the utility level of each consumer, of internal and external debt, starting
with external debt. The analytical technique employed, as in Diamond (1965),
is to characterise the steady state of the economy as the simultaneous solution
to a pair of equations for a …xed stock of debt. The consequence of a change in
the level of debt can then be found by determining its e¤ect upon the graphs of
these equations.

External Debt
It has already been noted that the analysis is conducted for a …xed stock of
debt. Before it can be undertaken, it is …rst necessary to clarify the sense in
which the level of debt is …xed since alternative interpretations are possible.
If the stock of debt were …xed in absolute terms, it would eventually have no
e¤ect upon the economy as population growth took place and the level of debt
per capita became asymptotically zero. Therefore, rather than …x the absolute
stock of debt, it is assumed that the level of debt per young consumer remains
constant and the e¤ect of changes in this ratio are analysed.
Denote the quantity of external debt by in period t by D1t and the debt per
D1
young consumer ratio, Htt , by d1t . If the ratio is to remain constant, then the
growth of the absolute stock of debt is governed by
1 1
Dt+ 1 = [1 + n] Dt ; (15.1)

where n is the growth rate of the population. The payment of interest upon the
debt is …nanced either by new borrowing or through taxation. With interest
rate rt, the payment of interest upon the debt in period t is

rtDt1 ; (15.2)

and new borrowing is


nD1t : (15.3)
The di¤erence between (15.2) and (15.3) given by

[rt ¡ n] Dt1 ; (15.4)

represents that part of the interest payments that must be …nanced by taxation.
The tax employed to generate the required revenue is assumed to take the
form of a lump-sum tax on the young generation. Given (15.4), the level of this
472 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

tax for each consumer when young is

D1t
T t = [rt ¡ n] = [rt ¡ n] d1t : (15.5)
Ht
With this tax payment included, the budget constraint of a consumer born in
period t becomes
x t+1
t
x tt + = wt ¡ [rt ¡ n] d1t ; (15.6)
1 + rt+ 1
ct , is given by
so that full income, M

ct = w t ¡ [rt ¡ n] d1 :
M (15.7)
t
¡ ¢
From the maximisation of the utility function U = U x tt; x t+1 t , subject to
(15.6), the savings function for a member of generation t is
³ ´ ³ ´
st = st Mct; rt+1 = wt ¡ [rt ¡ n] d1 ¡ xt M ct ; rt+1 : (15.8)
t t

Capital market equilibrium requires that the capital-labour ratio is related


to the level of savings by
³ ´
[1 + n] kt+1 = st Mct; rt+1 ; (15.9)

so that the interest rate satis…es


0 ³ ´1 0 ³ ´1
st Mct ; rt+1 wt ¡ [rt ¡ n] d1t ¡ xtt Mct ; rt+ 1
rt+1 = f 0 @ A = f0 @ A:
1+ n 1+n
(15.10)
Given rt, (15.10) implicitly determines a relationship between wt and rt+1 . This
relation describes the locus of pairs of wage rate and interest ¡ rate for¢ which
capital demand is equal to supply and is denoted by rt+1 = Ã w t ; rt; d1t and is
dependent upon the level of internal debt via the determination of the level of
savings.
Pro…t maximisation by …rms occurs when the wage rate satis…es the equality
w t = f (kt ) ¡ kt f 0 (kt ) and the interest rate rt = f 0 (kt), where kt is the capital-
labour ratio. Together these imply the factor price frontier (see 14.4.1) wt =
Á (rt) with Á0 (rt ) = ¡kt < 0 and Á00 (rt ) = ¡ f100 > 0. It should be noted that
Á (rt) is independent of the level of debt.
The long-run steady-state
¡ ¢ equilibrium of the economy, with rt = r all t,
occurs when r = Ã w; r; d1 and w = Á (r) are satis…ed simultaneously, where
d1 is the constant stock of debt. If an equilibrium exists, the steady state will
be stable if the à curve is steeper (in absolute value) than the Á curve. It
is assumed that the à curve is downward sloping, that an equilibrium exists
(so the curves intersect) and that the equilibrium is stable and unique. These
assumptions give the con…guration of Figure 15.1 which also shows part of the
15.2. THE EFFECT OF DEBT 473

Figure 15.1: Equilibrium and Stability

Figure 15.2: E¤ect of Increase in External Debt

path of the economy starting from an initial point r0 . It can be seen that, given
the assumptions placed on the gradients of the curves, the adjustment process
is convergent to the equilibrium at the intersection of the two curves.
To discover the e¤ect of changes in the level of external debt it is only
necessary to determine how the change a¤ects the à curve. From (15.10) it is
evident that the e¤ect will depend upon sgn.frt ¡ ng. If rt = n, so that the
Golden rule is achieved, there will be no e¤ect. From di¤erentiating (15.10),
holding rt constant, it can be found that
@st
@rt+1 f 00 [n ¡ rt] @w
= t
: (15.11)
@d1 1 + n ¡ f 00 @r@ t+1
st

The assumption that the à curve is downward sloping restricts that denominator
of (15.11) to be positive. The numerator is positive if rt > n and negative for
rt < n. Hence, for given rt , the à curve pivots around the point r = n as the
level of external debt increases. This is illustrated in Figure 15.2 below.
It is now straight forward to exhibit the e¤ect of an increase in debt upon
474 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

Figure 15.3:

Figure 15.4:

the long-run equilibrium. In the steady state


à ¡ ¢! à ¡ ¢!
1 1
s w ¡ [r ¡ n] d ; r s Á (r) ¡ [r ¡ n] d ; r
r = f0 = f0 : (15.12)
1+n 1+n

From di¤erentiating (15.12) the e¤ect of an increase in external debt upon the
steady state interest rate is

@r f 00 [n ¡ r] @w
@s
= : (15.13)
@d1 1 + n ¡ f 0 0 @s
@r
+ f 00 d1 @@sw

The three possible outcomes, which depend upon the sign of n ¡ r, are shown
in Figure 15.3.
In both cases (a) and (c) where n ¡ r is non-zero, the increase in external
debt moves the steady state interest rate, determined by the intersection of the
curves, further from the Golden rule interest rate. If r < n, then the steady
state wage rate w rises and if r > n, then w falls. When the economy is already
15.2. THE EFFECT OF DEBT 475

Figure 15.5: Steady State E¤ect

at the Golden rule interest rate then the di¤erential increase in debt has no
e¤ect.
The e¤ect upon the welfare level of a consumer via changes in the steady
state levels of r and w is found by di¤erentiating the utility function, de…ned
following (15.7), taking account of the demand function and using the factor
price frontier to eliminate the wage rate. Doing this gives
¸
dU 1 dr k dr
= ¡U 1 [r ¡ n] + d + [r ¡ n] : (15.14)
dd1 dd1 1+ r dd1

The three terms in the bracket on the right-hand side of (15.14) are related to
the taxes required to …nance the debt, the change in the tax burden due to
interest rate changes and the change in factor payments respectively.
Theorem 15.1 summarises the e¤ects of external debt.

Theorem 67 (Diamond)
(i) If r > n, a di¤erential increase in external debt raises r, reduces w and
reduces utility;
(ii) If r < n, an di¤erential increase in external debt reduces r, raises w and
may increase utility;
(iii) If r = n, an di¤erential increase in external debt has no e¤ect.

Proof. (i) When r > n the …rst and second bracketed terms of (15.14) are
dr
positive. As dd 1 has the sign of [r ¡ n], the third term is also positive. It is

then clear that utility will fall as the level of debt increases.
(ii)When r < n the …rst two terms of (15.14) are negative and the third
positive. Hence there are o¤setting e¤ects which arise due to r falling, but w
rising.
(iii) Obvious from (15.13) and (15.14).
The reasoning behind the conclusions of this theorem are that when r > n,
the capital stock is too small and the levying of a tax to service the debt has
the e¤ect of taking the economy further from the optimal level of capital. The
476 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

opposite applies when r < n and e¢ciency is increased by the reduction in the
capital stock. This gain has to be o¤set against the direct loss in welfare due to
the imposition of the tax and the net e¤ect may still be a reduction in welfare.

Internal Debt

In the case of internal debt, the issue of debt results in the government borrowing
from its own citizens. This leads to competition between government debt
and physical capital for consumer savings. Internal debt therefore a¤ects the
economy through both the taxes required to service the debt and through its
e¤ect on the capital market.
Denoting the ratio of internal debt to the number of young consumers in
period t by d2t , the savings function of a consumer of generation t is now given
by
¡ ¢
st = st w t ¡ [rt ¡ n] d2t ; rt+1 : (15.15)

In (15.15), the term [rt ¡ n] d2t captures the tax payment required to service the
debt. On the supply side of the capital market, there is now both private capital
and government bonds. Equilibrium requires that the aggregate level of saving
must be equal to the total stock of capital and debt, or
2
St ´ Ht st = Kt+1 + Dt+1 : (15.16)

Expressing (15.16) in terms of quantities per member of generation t + 1 gives


the alternative equilibrium condition
st
= kt+1 + d2t : (15.17)
1+n

The à curve for the case of internal debt is found by substituting from (15.17)
into rt+1 = f 0 (kt+1 ) to give
à ¡ ¢ !
st w t ¡ [rt ¡ n] d2t ; rt+1
rt+ 1 = f 0 ¡ d2t : (15.18)
1+n

It follows from (15.18) that for constant rt


h i
@ st
@rt+ 1 ¡f 00 [rt ¡ n] @w t
+ 1 + n
= : (15.19)
@d2t 1 + n ¡ f 00 @ @s t
rt+1

@st
Assuming that consumption is a normal good, so 0 < @w t
< 1, it follows that
@rt+1
@d 2
> 0. An increase in internal debt, holding rt constant, therefore causes
t
the à curve to move out to the right. The e¤ect of this upon the steady state is
to lower the wage rate but to increase the interest rate, regardless of the initial
position. This is shown in Figure 15.4.
15.3. OPTIMISATION OF DEBT AND LUMP-SUM TAXES 477

Figure 15.6: E¤ect of an Increase in Internal Debt

The change in steady state utility brought about by the increase in debt can
be found by di¤erentiating the utility function to be
¸
dU k + d2 dr
= ¡U 1 [r ¡ n] 1 + : (15.20)
dd2 1 + r dd2

The e¤ects of internal debt are summarised in the following theorem.

Theorem 68 (Diamond)
(i) If r > n, utility is decreased by a di¤erential increase in internal debt.
(ii) If r < n, utility is increased by extra debt.
(iii) If r = n there is no e¤ect.
dr
Proof. As dd 2 > 0, the second bracketed term in (15.20) is positive. The

conclusions then follow immediately.


The explanation behind this theorem is that when r > n the increase in
debt raises the interest rate and moves the equilibrium further from the optimal
point of r = n. This must reduce welfare. When r < n the increase in debt
causes r to move closer to n. This e¤ect is su¢cient to raise welfare despite the
competition for savings between government debt and physical capital.

15.3 Optimisation of debt and lump-sum taxes


In a static economy with identical consumers, the only role that lump-sum taxa-
tion can have is to collect revenue (and, of course, it is the most e¢cient method
of revenue collection). Other than this, there is no role for it to play in raising
e¢ciency or welfare. The same cannot be said in an overlapping generations
context since the potential ine¢ciency of the competitive equilibrium opens up
additional avenues by which lump-sum taxation can a¤ect welfare. By varying
the timing of taxation over the life-cycle it is possible for lump-sum taxes to af-
fect the savings decisions of consumers and, through this mechanism, the level of
the capital stock. This a¤ects the intertemporal evolution of the economy. The
478 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

employment of lump-sum taxation also makes it possible for the government


to achieve intergenerational transfers of income. These observations makes the
study of the design of lump-sum taxes a worthwhile exercise.
The purpose of this section is to characterise an optimal lump-sum tax policy
for an economy with an homogeneous population of consumers. The homogene-
ity assumption removes the need to consider intragenerational transfers and
focuses attention upon the intergenerational consequences of taxation. It also
overcomes some of the objections to the use of lump-sum taxes expressed in
Chapter 2. Before undertaking this, it is …rst necessary to determine the rela-
tionship between lump-sum taxes and internal debt since there are important
interconnections between the two policy instruments.

15.3.1 Lump-sum taxation and debt


The provision of government debt and the use of lump-sum taxation are both
methods of a¤ecting the life-cycle behaviour of consumers. When viewed as
such, it is not surprising that there is a signi…cant degree of substitutability
between the two instruments. To investigate this substitutability formally, it
is assumed that each household in generation t, in a Diamond economy with
variable labour supply, is subject to a lump-sum tax of Ttt in the …rst period of
their life and one of T tt+1 in the second period. Either, or both, of these may
be negative. With these taxes, the lifetime budget constraint of a consumer is

x t+1 T tt+1
xtt + t
= w t` t ¡ Ttt ¡ : (15.21)
1 + rt+1 1 + rt+1

Using R to denote the level of government revenue to be collected, the govern-


ment budget constraint is

Ht T tt + Ht¡ 1 Tt¡
t
1 = R + [1 + t t ] Dt¡1 ¡ Dt ; (15.22)

where Dt is the quantity of debt issued in period t. In per-capita terms the


government budget constraint becomes
t
T t¡1 e + [1 + rt ] dt¡1 ¡ dt ;
Ttt + =R (15.23)
1+n 1+n
D e ´ R . Since the lump-sum tax in the
with dt¡ 1 ´ H t¡1
t¡1
, dt ´ D Ht
t
and R Ht
…rst period of life, Ttt , a¤ects consumers’ savings decisions, the capital market
equilibrium condition becomes

[1 + n] e
kt+1 = w t `t ¡ T tt ¡ xtt ¡ dt ; (15.24)

where e
K t+1
kt+1 ´ H t+1
is the level of capital per young consumer. It is important
K t+1
to distinguish this from the capital labour ratio kt+ 1 ´ H t+1`t+1
since the two
are not equal when labour supply is variable.
15.3. OPTIMISATION OF DEBT AND LUMP-SUM TAXES 479

© ª
A tax policy is a sequence of lump-sum taxes :::; T t¡1 t¡1 t ; T t ; T t+1 ; T t+1 ; :::
; T t¡1 t t t+1
and a debt policy is a sequence of government debt issues f:::; dt¡1 ; dt ; dt+ 1; :::g.
Together with the factor price frontier, (15.21), (15.22) and (15.24) describe the
equilibrium of the economy for any given tax policy and debt policy.
The following theorem, originally due to Bierwag et al. (1969), relates tax
policies and debt policies.
© t¡1
ª
Theorem 69 (Bierwag, Grove, Khang) The combined tax policy :::; T t¡1 t
; T t¡1 ; T tt; T tt+1 ; T t+1
t+ 1
; :::
and debt policy f:::;ndt¡1 ; dt; dt+1 ; :::g lead to the same o real equilibria as:
t¡1 t t t+1 t+1
(i) a tax policy :::; Tbt¡ 1 ; Tbt¡1 ; Tbt ; Tbt ; Tbt+1 ; ::: and no debt, where Tbtt =
T tt + dt and Tbtt+1 =nTtt+1 ¡ [1 + rt+1 ] dt ; o n o
(ii) a tax policy :::; Tet¡1
t¡1
; 0; Tett ; 0; Tet+1
t+1
; ::: and a debt policy :::; det¡ 1 ; det ; det+1 ; ::: ,
T tt+1 T tt+1
where Tett = T tt + 1+n rt+1
and det = dt ¡ 1+ rt+1
;
o n o
(iii) a tax policy t t+1 t+2
:::; 0; Tbt¡ 1 ; 0; Tbt ; 0; Tbt+1 ; ::: and a debt policy :::; dbt¡1 ; dbt; dbt+1 ; ::: ,
where Tbtt+1 = [1 + rt+1 ] T tt + Ttt+1 and dbt = dt + T tt;
and n o
(iv) a tax policy f:::; Tt¡ 1 ; Tt ; T t+1 ; :::g and a debt policy :::; d¸t¡ 1 ; ḑt ; ḑt+1 ; ::: ,
h ih t+1 i t+1
Ttt
where T t = 1+r t+1
2+rt+1
Ttt + 1+rTt
t+1
and d¸t = dt ¡ 2+r t+1
Tt
¡ 2+r t+1
.

Proof. (i) With the tax policy alone the equilibrium conditions become

xt+1 Tbtt+1
x tt + t
= w t `t ¡ Tbtt ¡ ; (15.25)
1 + rt+1 1 + rt+1

Tbt¡1
t
Tbtt + e
= R; (15.26)
1+ n
and
[1 + n] e
kt+1 = wt `t ¡ Tbtt ¡ xtt : (15.27)
Contrasting (15.24) and (15.27) shows that the capital market will be una¤ected
by the change in policy if Tbtt = T tt + dt . Substituting into (15.26) and equating
to (15.23) gives Tbtt+1 = T tt+ 1 ¡ [1 + rt+1 ] dt . It can also be seen that these
changes leave the consumer’s budget constraint una¤ected. Parts (ii) to (iv) are
proved in an identical manner.
The relevance of Theorem 15.3 is that it shows that a restricted lump-sum
tax policy, either one employing uniform taxes (case iv) or one with taxes levied
in only one period of life (cases ii and iii), and an appropriate debt policy is
as e¤ective as lump-sum taxes di¤erentiated across the lifecycle. It is arguable
that the uniform lump-sum tax policy requires less information than the di¤er-
entiated policy so that employing a uniform tax can economise on information
with no loss in potential welfare. The theorem also shows that in characterising
the optimal lump-sum tax policy, any one of the …ve combinations of tax and
debt policies will lead to the same real equilibrium.
480 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

15.3.2 Optimal lump-sum taxation and debt


Theorem 15.3 shows that in order to demonstrate the e¤ect of an optimal lump-
sum tax policy it is su¢cient to consider only one of the …ve alternative com-
binations of lump-sum taxes and debt. The representation chosen here will be
to adopt (i) and to set government debt equal to zero in all periods. Once the
results are derived, the translation can easily be made to one of the other forms
of policy. The technique used to characterise the choice of policy is the principle
of optimality of dynamic programming which has been employed in this context
by Diamond (1973), Atkinson and Sandmo (1980) and Park (1991).
The aim of the government is assumed to be the maximisation of the dis-
counted sum of utility from perio d s, in which the maximisation takes place,
onwards. With discount rate , the social welfare function is that used in Chapter
13 Section 3.5.2 and is given by
X1 µ ¶
T tt+1
° t V T tt + ; (15.28)
t=s
1 + rt+ 1
³ ´
Ttt+1
where V T tt + 1+r t+1
is the indirect utility function of the generation born in
t. It is clear from the budget constraint in (15.21) that it is the discounted sum
of lump-sum taxes that determines welfare rather than the individual taxes.
The maximisation is constrained by the behaviour of the household and by
production possibilities. The maximisation of utility by each consumer sub-
ject to (15.21)
³ determines
´ commodity³ demands and ´ labour supply ³ of the form´
T t+1 T t+1 T t+1
x tt = x tt T tt + 1+rt t+1 , xt+1
t = x t+1
t T tt + 1+r
t
t+1
and `t = `t T tt + 1+trt+1 .
With a working population of Ht each choosing to undertake hours `t of em-
ployment, output with a capital stock of Kt is given by F (Kt ; Ht; ` t). Assuming
that the production function is homogeneous of degree one, ³ ´output is given in
e
e
terms of capital per young consumer, kt = H t , as Ht `t f k` tt . Output is allo-
Kt

cated between consumption, government purchases, R, and savings. With no


depreciation, the demand for output equals its supply when

F (K t; Ht ; `t ) + K t = Ht xtt + Ht¡ 1 xtt¡ 1 + R + Ht st : (15.29)


Expressing this equality in terms quantities of per worker (15.29) becomes
à !
e
kt xtt¡ 1
`t f = x tt + e + [1 + n] kt+1 ¡ kt :
+R (15.30)
`t 1+n

The equality of savings in period t to capital in t + 1 requires that


[1 + n] e
kt+1 = w t `t ¡ T tt ¡ xtt ;

which can be used in (15.30) to give the alternative representation of production


possibilities " Ã ! #
e
k xt
e
kt + ` t f
t
¡ wt ¡ t¡1 ¡ R e + T t = 0: (15.31)
t
`t 1+ n
15.3. OPTIMISATION OF DEBT AND LUMP-SUM TAXES 481

Equation (15.30) can also be solved to express the capital stock of period t + 1
as a function of variables at t. Doing this gives
¸" Ã !
e t
#
e 1 k t x t¡1 e +e
kt+ 1 = `t f ¡ xtt ¡ ¡R kt : (15.32)
1+ n `t 1+ n

The optimal choice of lump-sum taxation is now characterised by the use


of the maximum principle of dynamic programming. The government enters
period s with the capital stock already determined by the savings decision of
period s ¡ 1. In addition, the lump-sum taxes a¤ecting generation s ¡ 1 are
also pre-determined. The maximum welfare that can be achieved from period
s
Ts¡1
s onwards is therefore a function of e s¡ 1
ks and T s¡1 + 1+r . This maximum value
³ s ´ s
T s¡1
e
function is denoted ª ks ; T s¡1
+ ; s or just ª (s) when the meaning is
s¡ 1 1+rs
clear. From the basic recursive relation of dynamic programming (see Stokey
and Lucas with Prescott (1989)), the maximum value at s must be equal to
the maximised value of period s’s indirect utility, constrained by productive
feasibility, plus the maximum value attainable in s + 1 discounted. That is
( " " Ã ! # # )
eks x ss¡1
ª (s) = max e
V (Zs) + ¸ s ks + ` s f ¡ ws ¡ e s
¡ R + T s + °ª (s + 1) ;
f Tss;Tss+1g `s 1+n
³ ´ (15.33)
s Tss+1 e s Tss+1
where Zs = T +s 1+rs+1 and ª (s + 1) = ª ks+1 ; T +
s 1+rs+1 ;s+1 .
The necessary conditions for the maximisation in (15.34) with respect to T ss
and T ss+1 are
" " # #
@V @` s e
0 ks @w s @ª (s + 1)
+ ¸s f ¡ ws ¡ f ¡ `s + ¸s + °
@Zs @Zs `s @Zs @Zs
¸" "
e
# #
@ª (s + 1) 1 @`s ks @xss
+° f ¡ f0 ¡ =0 (15.34)
@eks+ 1 1+n @Zs `s @Zs
and
" " # #
@V 1 @` s e
ks @w s 1 @ª (s + 1) 1
0
+ ¸s f ¡ ws ¡ f ¡ `s +°
@Zs 1 + rs+1 @Zs `s @Zs 1 + rs+1 @Zs 1 + rs+1
¸" "
e
# #
@ª (s + 1) 1 @` s 0 ks @x ss 1
+° f¡f ¡ = 0: (15.35)
e
@ ks+1 1+n @Zs `s @Z s 1 + rs+1

Comparison of (15.35) and (15.36) shows immediately that ¸ s = 0. The reason


for this is that the ‡exibility in the lump-sum taxes allows T ss to be varied
whilst keeping Zs constant. This renders the production constraint ine¤ective.
Conditions (15.35) and (15.36) therefore both reduce to
¸" "
e
# #
@V @ª (s + 1) @ª (s + 1) 1 @` s 0 ks @x ss
+° +° f ¡f ¡ = 0:
@Zs @Zs @eks+1 1+n @Zs `s @Zs
(15.36)
482 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

Di¤erentiating (15.34) with respect to the state variables e ks and Zs¡1 gives
¸
@ª (s) ° @ª (s + 1)
= [1 + f 0] ; (15.37)
@e
ks 1+n @e
ks+1

and ¸ ¸
@ª (s) ° @ª (s + 1) @xss¡1 1
=¡ : (15.38)
@Zs¡1 1+ n @kes+1 @Zs¡1 1+n
Equations (15.37) to (15.39) provide the characterisation of the optimal policy.
The structure of the optimal policy is easily seen if the move is now made
to the steady state. In a steady state @ª(e s) = @ª(e s+1) = @ªe so that (15.38)
@ ks @ ks+1 @k
reduces to
1 + n = ° [1 + f 0 ] ; (15.39)
which is the modi…ed Golden rule. Unrestricted lump-sum taxes can therefore
take the economy to the modi…ed Golden rule equilibrium, even with variable
labour supply, since they cause no distortion on any of the markets. This result
should be contrasted to the results on social security in Chapter 14 Section 4.1
where the pension a¤ected the retirement decision. This e¤ect is absent in the
present framework.
In the steady state, (15.39) reduces to
¸ ¸
@ª ° @ª @x 2 1
=¡ ; (15.40)
@Z 1 + n @e k @Z 1 + n

where x i is the steady state level of consumption in the ith period of life. From
the budget constraint (15.21) di¤erentiation with respect to Z shows that in the
steady state
@` @x 1 1 @x 2
w ¡ =1+ : (15.41)
@Z @Z 1 + r @Z
Substituting from (15.41) and (15.42) then yields
¸
@V ° @ª
= : (15.42)
@Z 1 + n @e k

Since @V
@Z is the private marginal utility of income, (15.40) and (15.43) show that
the optimal lump-sum tax policy will achieve the modi…ed Golden rule and will
equate the private marginal utility of income to the discounted return of further
investment in capital.

15.3.3 Summary
This section has detailed the connections between lump-sum tax policy and
debt policy and has shown the equivalence of unrestricted lump-sum tax poli-
cies to combinations of debt and restricted lump-sum taxes. Combined with
the analysis of optimal lump-sum taxes, these results show how the modi…ed
15.4. DEBT NEUTRALITY 483

Golden rule equilibrium can be sustained by a number of combinations of policy


instruments.
In assessing these results, it should be borne in mind that the economy under
consideration was restricted by the assumption of an homogeneous population.
This limits the scope for the worthwhile di¤erentiation of lump-sum taxes, since
consumers are only distinguished by their date of birth, and therefore makes
feasible a policy that achieves the optimal outcome. If there were further de-
grees of di¤erentiation of the consumers, for example by endowment of labour,
then lump-sum taxes could be di¤erentiated across the lifecycle and over the
endowment. A debt policy and a uniform lump-sum tax policy would then not
be equivalent to the optimal fully-di¤erentiated set of lump-sum taxes. There
would then be less justi…cation for expecting the optimum to be achievable since
this would also require intragenerational redistribution which could not be fully
undertaken with uniform lump-sum taxes. However, as shown by Park (1991),
the modi…ed Golden rule will be satis…ed by the correct choice of uniform lump-
sum taxes and debt policy even with a heterogeneous population but other
taxes will be required to supplement them in order to achieve intragenerational
distributional aims. Since, in practice, populations are not homogeneous, this
observation justi…es the study of policies that are not equivalent to the set of
optimal lump-sum taxes.

15.4 Debt neutrality


The concept of debt neutrality, or Ricardian equivalence, can be traced back to
Ricardo (1817). A brief summary of some aspects of debt neutrality relevant
for the analysis of social security has already been given in Chapter 14. In
this section the emphasis will be upon proving the basic neutrality result and
exploring its limitations.
The essence of debt neutrality is that the real economy is una¤ected by
whether the government chooses to raise revenue by using taxation or through
the issue of debt. Although the payment of taxes clearly reduces wealth, the
issue of debt would seem to leave the wealth of consumers intact since it simply
displaces private capital from the portfolios of consumers. However, this over-
looks the fact that the issue of debt implies future tax liabilities for its servicing
and redemption. Discounted back to the present, these future liabilities reduce
the present value of wealth by precisely the same amount as the tax payment.
Since wealth is identical in both cases, so must the equilibrium outcome. This
simple argument is the foundation of the theory of debt neutrality.
The next subsection will formally demonstrate the neutrality result for two
extreme cases. The …rst considers debt which is redeemed after a single pe-
riod and the second involves consumers with in…nite lives. The second case is
intended to motivate the mechanism by which intergenerational altruism gener-
ates the neutrality result in the case of …nite lives. The main neutrality result
is then presented and some extensions and limitations are discussed.
484 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

15.4.1 Two special cases


Debt neutrality will now be demonstrated for two special cases in which the
mechanism behind the result is particularly transparent. These follow the sim-
plifying approach of Barro (1974) in which the government gives an equal num-
ber of bonds to each of the identical consumers in the economy. If after the
receipt of these bonds, the consumers do not perceive their wealth to have in-
creased, then debt neutrality is said to apply.
It is assumed that the gift of debt is a one-o¤ event and that taxation must be
used to service the debt and to meet its repayment. When future tax liabilities
are taken into account, the present discounted value of wealth becomes

- 1 = - 0 + D ¡ DT L; (15.43)

where -0 is the consumers wealth before receiving the bonds, - 1 the level of
wealth after receiving the bonds, D the value of bonds received and DT L the
discounted tax liabilities arising due to the issue of the debt. Two di¤erent as-
sumptions on the structure of repayment of the debt are now shown to generate
the same neutrality conclusion.
Under the …rst set of assumptions the bond is paid o¤ with interest the year
after issue and the same set of consumers is alive in both years. In this case,
with interest rate r, the interest and principle paid the year after issue is given
by [1 + r] D. Discounting this back to the present shows that DT L has value

[1 + r] D
DT L = = D: (15.44)
1+r
Substituting from (15.45) into (15.44) shows immediately that the issue of the
debt has no net e¤ect upon wealth. This is a consequence of the recipients of the
bonds realising that they face the tax liability for its repayment. The receipt of
the bond is therefore not treated as an increase in wealth.
The second set of assumptions involve a bond that is never redeemed but on
which interest is paid in perpetuity and consumers who have in…nite lifespans.
In this case the discounted tax liabilities must be equal to the discounted value
of the stream of interest payments. This gives
Z 1
DT L = rDe¡rt dt; (15.45)
0

where rD is the tax payment per period. Thus DT L = D and the bond again
has no e¤ect upon net wealth.
The special feature of these two cases that makes the neutrality result so
transparent is that the consumers who receive the bonds also pay the future
taxes used to …nance them. In an overlapping generations economy, it would
appear at …rst sight that such a result could only apply in very particular cir-
cumstances since the set of living consumers changes each period. The impor-
tant insight of Barro (1974) was to show how intergenerational altruism could
support the neutrality result in general circumstances.
15.4. DEBT NEUTRALITY 485

Figure 15.7: Receipts and Payments for One-Period Debt

15.4.2 Intergenerational altruism


The discussion of the examples above emphasised the importance of the recipient
of debt …nancing its servicing and repayment via taxation. In an overlapping
generations economy this will in general not occur. For example, Figure 15.5
indicates the pattern of receipts and payments if a one-period bond was given
to the young of generation t and redeemed through taxes upon generation t + 1.
If the generations were not linked in any way, the gift of debt in this economy
would raise the wealth of generation t, reduce that of generation t + 1 and would
have real e¤ects upon the equilibrium.
The linkages between generations that are needed to support the neutrality
result in an overlapping generations economy can be introduced by assuming
that each consumer gives birth to a number of descendants. If the consumer
cares about the welfare of their descendants, so that intergenerational altruism
is present, then it is likely that they will choose to leave a bequest. The e¤ect of
the debt transfer can then be neutralised by changes in the size of the bequest
and, as will be shown below, since the initial size of bequest was optimal it will
also be optimal to neutralise the e¤ect of the debt issue. Conversely, it may be
the case that a consumer cares about their forebear and re‡ects this by giving
a gift to their forebear. The neutrality result can then be attained by changes
in the size of the gift o¤setting the debt issue.
To formalise these arguments, consider …rst the case of concern for descen-
dants. Assume that each consumer has 1 + n descendants and that the utility
of a typical member of generation t is assumed to be dependent upon the utility
they derive from consumption and the return from the well-being of their de-
scendants. Adopting an additively separable functional form for simplicity, the
utility function can then be written as

¡ ¢ U ¤ (t + 1)
U (t) = U xtt ; x t+1
t + ; (15.46)
1+±

where U ¤ (t + 1) is the welfare level of each descendent and ± is the discount


rate. The budget constraints of the consumer, incorporating the taxes required
to …nance the debt and the bequests given and received, are

xtt + s t = wt ¡ T t ; (15.47)

and
xtt +1 + [1 + n] b t = [1 + rt+1 ] [st + b t¡1 ] : (15.48)
486 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

These budget constraints embody the assumptions that each consumer in gener-
ation t has 1 + n descendants and leaves a bequest of b t. They receive a bequest
of bt¡ 1 in the second period of their lives and, since this was actually bequethed
in the previous period, it receives interest at the market rate. Lump-sum taxes,
T t , are paid in the …rst period of life.
The necessary conditions for the optimal choice of consumption and bequest
can be derived from (15.47) - (15.49) as
@U
@xtt
@U
= 1 + rt+1 ; (15.49)
@xt+1
t

and ¸
@U 1 @U ¤ (t + 1)
t+1 [1 + n] ¸ ; (15.50)
@x t 1+± @b t
with b t = 0 if (15.51) is a strict inequality. Noting that an increase in the bequest
is simply an increase in second period lump-sum income for the descendants
which, after the addition of interest, must be valued at the marginal utility
@U ¤ (t+1)
of consumption, it follows that @b t = [1 + rt+2 ] @x@ t+2
U
so (15.51) can be
t+1
written as
@U
@xtt 1 + rt+2
@U
¸ : (15.51)
t+2 [1 + ±] [1 + n]
@xt+1

Letting Dt be the value of bonds issued in period t the budget constraint of


the government in period t is

[1 + rt ] Dt¡1 = Dt + Ht T t : (15.52)
Dt
By de…ning dt = Ht , (15.53) can be alternatively written

[1 + rt ] dt¡1 = [1 + n] dt + [1 + n] Tt : (15.53)

With bequests, equilibrium in period t satis…es the usual conditions ((13.39)


and (13.40)) for the determination of the interest rate and wage rate, and the
capital market equilibrium condition

s t + bt¡ 1 = [1 + n] kt¡1 + dt : (15.54)

To characterise the steady state, the level of debt and the lump-sum tax
rate are held constant at d and T . Substituting from the steady state ver-
sion of (15.53) and (15.54) into (15.48) and (15.49), the steady state levels of
consumption satisfy
¸ ¸
1 + f0
x1 = f ¡ kf 0 ¡ [1 + n] k + b ¡ d ; (15.55)
1+ n
and ¸ ¸
1 + f0
x 2 = [1 + n] [1 + f 0 ] k ¡ [1 + n] b ¡ d : (15.56)
1+n
15.4. DEBT NEUTRALITY 487

The steady state conditions for consumer choice (15.50) and (15.52) reduce to
@U
@x1
@U
= 1 + f 0; (15.57)
@x2

and
[1 + n] [1 + ±] ¸ 1 + f 0: (15.58)
From (15.59) the bequest motive will only be operative in the steady state if
[1 + n] [1 + ±] = 1 + f 0 . Since ± > 0, this implies that the equilibrium interest
rate must be above the growth rate of population so the capital-labour ratio
must be below the Golden rule level for bequests to be positive.
It is now possible to prove the …rst neutrality result.

Theorem 70 (Barro) If the bequest motive is operative, so that bequests are


positive both before and after any change in the level of bonds, such a change has
no e¤ect upon either the short run equilibrium or the steady state equilibrium.

Proof. To see that there is no e¤ect upon the steady state equilibrium, it is
su¢cient to observe that the consumption levels hare determined
i by conditions
0
(15.56) dependent upon the values of k and b ¡ 1+f 1+n d. It is then clear that
any change in d can be o¤set by a change in b, leaving k and the steady state
consumption levels unchanged. Such a change also leaves (15.58) and (15.59)
satis…ed.
To show that a change in the level of debt is neutral in the short run, consider
the government wishing to increase d to d + de starting at time t. It can achieve
this by giving each member of generation t ¡ 1 a quantity e
h i d of bonds, which
they will sell to generation t, and by selling bonds 1+n n
de to each member of
generation t. Toh …nance
i the interest payments on the bonds held by generation
rt ¡n e
t ¡ 1 a tax of 1+n d is levied on each member of generation t. With these
changes, the budget constraint of a member of generation t ¡ 1 in period t is
e
xtt¡ 1 = [1 + rt] [st¡ 1 + bt¡ 2 ] ¡ [1 + n] b t¡1 + [1 + rt ] d; (15.59)

and the constraints facing generation t are


¸
rt ¡ n e
x tt = w t ¡ T t ¡ st ¡ d; (15.60)
1+n

and
x t+1
t = [1 + rt+1 ] [st + b t¡1 ] ¡ [1 + n] b t : (15.61)
The capital market equilibrium condition becomes
e
st + b t¡1 = [1 + n] kt + dt + d: (15.62)

To show that the change in the level of debt can


h be neutralised
i byha changes
i
rt e 1+rt+1 e
in the level of bequests, let b t¡1 be increased by 1+
1+n d and b t by 1+n d
488 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES
h i
and let s t fall by rt ¡n e Substituting these changes in (15.60) to (15.63)
d.
1+n
shows that the change in debt is cancelled from the equilibrium conditions and
that the levels of consumption remain unchanged. Neutrality therefore applies.

To prove an identical result for the case of concern about forebears, assume
that the utility of a consumer in t takes the form
¡ ¢ U ¤ (t ¡ 1)
U (t) = U xtt ; xt+
t
1
+ ; (15.63)
1+±
where U ¤ (t ¡ 1) is the welfare level of the consumer’s forebearer. Denoting the
gift received by a forebear by gt , the budget constraints are
¸
1
xtt + st + gt = w t ¡ T t; (15.64)
1+n

and
xt+1
t = [1 + rt+1 ] st + gt+1 ; (15.65)
where these follow from the observation that each forebearer has [1 + n] descen-
dants. The necessary conditions for the optimal choice of consumption and gift
can be calculated to be
@U
@xtt
@U
= 1 + rt+1 ; (15.66)
t+1
@xt

and ¸
@U 1+n @U ¤ (t ¡ 1)
t+1 [1 + rt+ 1 ] ¸ ; (15.67)
@x t 1+± @gt
with g t = 0 if (15.68) is a strict inequality. Exploiting the fact that an increase
in gift is equivalent to an increase in lump-sum income, (15.68) can be written
as
@U ¤ (t ¡ 1) @U
= : (15.68)
@gt @x tt¡1
The steady state levels of consumption satisfy
¸
1
x 1 = f ¡ kf 0 ¡ [1 + n] k ¡ [g + [1 + f 0 ] d] ; (15.69)
1+n

and
x 2 = [1 + n] [1 + f 0 ] k + [g + [1 + f 0] d] (15.70)
and the steady state version of (15.68) is
1+n
1 + f0 ¸ : (15.71)
1+±
Gifts can be positive only when (15.72) is an equality which requires the economy
to be overcapitalised relative to the Golden rule.
Using these conditions, the second neutrality theorem follows.
15.4. DEBT NEUTRALITY 489

Theorem 71 (Carmichael) If the gift motive is operative, so that gifts are pos-
itive, both before and after any change in the level of bonds, such a change has
no e¤ect upon either the short run equilibrium or the steady state equilibrium.

Proof. The proof is essentially identical to that of Theorem 15.4. In the


steady state it is the value of g + [1 + f 0 ] d that is relevant so that under the
conditions of the theorem any change in d can be o¤set by a change in g. In the
short run a change in the level of gifts and savings can also be found that will
o¤set the change in level of debt.
After the publication of Barro’s (1974) demonstration of the neutrality re-
sult for economies with bequests, the comments of Feldstein (1976), Buchanan
(1976) and Barro’s (1976) reply were directed to the discussion of whether the
neutrality proposition was applicable when the rate of interest was less than
the rate of growth. As shown in Theorem 15.5, which is based on Carmichael
(1982), neutrality does apply in this latter case if the gift motive, rather than the
bequest motive, is operative. This latter result, and the related work of Buiter
(1980), has itself been criticised by Burbidge (1983) for the form of utility func-
tion employed. The contention of Burbidge is that consistency of treatment
between descendants and forebears places additional restrictions upon the rates
of discounting that can be employed. However, as noted in the reply of Buiter
and Carmichael (1984), the utility function is constructed as the representa-
tion of an underlying preference ordering and if the preference ordering does
not restrict discount rates nor should the utility function. Viewed in this ways,
the discount factors in (15.47) and (15.64) implicitly adjust for the number of
descendants and forebears respectively.
Given the importance of an operative bequest motive, it is worth clarifying
the conditions under which bequests will be positive. Drazen (1978) provided
a partial analysis of this issue but the …rst substantive result was given in Weil
(1987). To demonstrate this result, assume that in the economy with concern
for descendants there is no debt and that the utility function is also additively
separable in consumption with the form

¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ U ¤ (t ¡ 1)
U (t) = U x tt + ¯U xt+1
t + (15.72)
1+±
The steady state equilibrium in then the solution to

x1 = f ¡ kf 0 ¡ [1 + n] k + b = w (k) ¡ [1 + n] k + b; (15.73)

x 2 = [1 + n] [1 + f 0] k ¡ [1 + n] b = [1 + n] [1 + r (k)] k ¡ [1 + n] b; (15.74)
and
[1 + n] [1 + ±] = 1 + f 0 = 1 + r (k) ´ 1 + r¤ : (15.75)
The equality in (15.77) captures the assumption that the bequest motive is
operative.
If the optimal level of bequests is zero, (15.76) will be satis…ed when eval-
uated at b = 0. Substituting (15.74) and (15.75) into (15.76) then shows that
490 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

the optimal value of the bequest will satisfy

sgn: fbg = sgn: fU 0 (w (k) ¡ [1 + n] k) ¡ ¯ [1 + r¤ ] U 0 ([1 + r ¤ ] [1 + n] k)g :


(15.76)
Now denote the savings function of the equivalent economy without bequest
motive (i.e. the solution to U 0 (w ¡ s) - ¯ [1 + r] U 0 ([1 + r] s) = 0) by s =
s (w; r). Using this de…nition, (15.78) is equivalent to

sgn: fbg = sgn: f[1 + n] k ¡ s (w; r)g : (15.77)

Assuming that the identity [1 + n] k ¡ s (w; r) = 0 has a unique solution k,


which would be the steady state capital labour ratio in the economy without
bequest motive, the following theorem can be proved.
¡ ¢
Theorem 72 (Weil) If s (w; r) ¡ [1 + n] k > 0 8 k 2 0; k and s (w; r) ¡
[1 + n] k < 0 8 k > k, then the bequest¡ motive
¢ is operative in the steady state if
1
and only if 1+± > 1+n
1+r , where r = f 0
k is the steady state interest rate of the
corresponding economy without bequest motive.

Proof. From (15.79), the bequest will only be positive if [1 + n] k ¡ s (w; r)


> 0. The implies, from the assumptions of the theorem, that the steady state
capital stock, k ¤ , of an economy with an operative bequest motive satis…es
k ¤ > k. From (15.77), the economy with bequest motive satis…es 1+1 ± = 1+r 1+n
¤

and, since k > k, r < r. Hence the bequest motive can only be operative
¤ ¤
1
when 1+± > 1+n
1+r
.
The assumptions employed in the proof of this theorem regarding the relation
of s (w; r)¡[1 + n] k to k are equivalent to the assumption that the unique steady
state of the economy without bequest motive is stable. From the conclusion of
the theorem, it can be seen that the bequest motive will be operative provided
the discount factor applied to descendants utility is su¢ciently great. That is,
there must be a su¢cient degree of intergenerational concern for bequests to be
positive.
This section has shown how bequest and gift motives can extend the two-
period lived consumers of the overlapping generations economy into in…nitely
lived dynasties connected by intergenerational altruism. Once this has been
done, it is not surprising that neutrality results which apply for in…nitely lived
consumers then apply in the overlapping generations framework. It is important
to stress that these results rely on changes in the level of bequests or gifts being
able to o¤set changes in the pattern of debt and taxes. If neither of these
motives are operative or the level of transfer is small, this may not be possible.

15.4.3 Generalisations
One aspect of the neutrality results described above that has received attention
is the assumption of certainty. Blanchard (1985) has considered the possibility
that the lifespan of each consumer may be of random length. The introduction
of such uncertainty has the implication that those who bene…t from any debt
15.4. DEBT NEUTRALITY 491

issue will have a probability of less than one of being alive to face any future
tax payments. In the analysis of Blanchard each consumer has a constant prob-
ability of their life continuing (which gives rise to the description of such an
economy as embodying perpetual youth) and the population remains constant
as new consumers are born at each point in time to replace those who have died.
To prevent unintended bequests, a life insurance market o¤ering insurance at
fair terms is assumed to be operational. When there is no bequest motive, neu-
trality does not hold in such an economy. This analysis is extended by Buiter
(1988) to show that a necessary and su¢cient condition for debt neutrality to
apply in such an economy is that the sum of the probability of death and the
growth rate of population is identically zero. This is clearly violated in the
Blanchard analysis except when the consumers have a zero probability of death
and are therefore in…nitely lived.

Although the focus to this point has been upon debt neutrality, an economy
with an operative gift or bequest motive is capable of neutralising a broad range
of …scal policies. Since Bernheim and Bagwell (1988) show that almost any pol-
icy can be neutralised, the fact that this seems refuted by practice suggests
that the economy in which such propositions can be derived is not a successful
representation of reality. To attempt to achieve debt neutrality without the
neutrality of all policy, Abel and Bernheim (1991) note that changes in the level
of debt are often neutralised by exploiting only a few links in the intergenera-
tional chain whereas the neutralisation of other policies requires the exploitation
of many links. This observation motivates the introduction of friction into the
intergenerational altruism via the derivation of utility from the act of giving,
imperfect knowledge of the later generation’s preferences and social norms that
govern bequests. The …rst two allow approximate neutrality in the short run
but drive the marginal propensity to consume to zero. The third avoids this
conclusion but does lead to the conclusion that an exogenous increase in wealth
of any one consumer can never be a Pareto improvement. Due to these unpalat-
able conclusions, the introduction of friction in this way cannot be claimed to
be a successful mechanism for retaining debt neutrality whilst eliminating more
general neutralities.

Finally, it should be noted again that debt neutrality fails if the gift or be-
quest motives are not operative. In addition, it can also fail when the change in
policy leads to redistribution between consumers with di¤ering marginal propen-
sities to consume. This did not occur in the theorems above since all consumers
were identical and the policy a¤ected each equally. It can also occur when life-
times are uncertain and insurance markets are imperfect (Abel (1986)) and when
the tax instruments are not lump-sum. As yet, neither empirical evidence (see
Bernheim (1987) and Sweeney (1988)) nor experimental evidence (Cadsby and
Frank (1991)) has con…rmed or refuted whether neutrality applies in practice.
492 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

15.5 Income and interest taxation


In a dynamic economy an income tax leads to the double taxation of savings:
once when the income is received and then again when the interest income from
savings is received. This fact has often been used to support the contention,
for example in Meade (1975), that an expenditure tax which avoids the double
taxation would be preferable to an income tax. This view overlooks the fact that
it is necessary to establish that the double taxation leads to an inferior outcome.
Simply counting the number of instances of distortion is not a su¢cient analysis.
More relevant for the present discussion is the potential dynamic ine¢ciency of
an overlapping generations economy. If the economy is on a path with excessive
capital accumulation then there may be a gain to introducing a distortion into
the savings decision that reduces the level of capital. Since interest and income
taxes have di¤erent e¤ects upon the steady state equilibrium of the economy,
the design of the tax system should take advantage of this by combining the
two instruments. These issues are now addressed for nonlinear taxes on income
and interest in an economy with a heterogeneous population.
The optimal combination of income and interest taxation has been ap-
proached using two di¤erent methods. Atkinson and Sandmo (1980) and Park
(1990) employ the dynamic programming method described in Section 3. The
results of Atkinson and Sandmo are restricted to an economy in which consumers
only di¤er with respect to their date of birth and are otherwise homogeneous.
Such a setting does not explore the full potential of the taxes for e¤ecting intra-
generational transfers. Although Park considers an heterogeneous population,
few concrete results are derived. The alternative approach, developed in Or-
dover and Phelps (1975, 1979), Ordover (1976), and Phelps and Riley (1978), is
based on the observation that what links generations t and t + 1 are the capital
stock provided by the members of generation t and their claim to consumption
in the second-period of life. The maximisation of social welfare can then be
reduced to a single-period problem by assuming that the welfare of generation
t is maximised subject to the constraints that the capital stock provided for
generation t + 1 does not fall below some chosen level and that second-period
consumption is not above some …xed level. This alternative approach is now
described.
The details of the analyses di¤er in the objective functions of the government
and the manner in which the constraining levels of capital stock and second-
period consumption are chosen. Ordover and Phelps (1975), Ordover (1976),
and Phelps and Riley (1978) all employ a Rawlsian maxi-min objective for
the government whereas Ordover and Phelps (1979) consider a more general
Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function. In Ordover and Phelps (1975) the
levels of capital stock and second-period consumption were arbitrarily chosen
and it was required that they were held constant over time. Although simple,
this procedure cannot, in general, maximise any social welfare function satisfying
the Pareto criterion (2.49) since opportunities to raise welfare are being missed.
Phelps and Riley (1978) showed how the requirement that the capital stock
and level of second-period consumption be Pareto optimal in the allocations
15.5. INCOME AND INTEREST TAXATION 493

between generations could be given a simple representation and incorporated


into the optimisation and this made possible the general analysis of Ordover
and Phelps (1979) which is now described.
The heterogeneous population is introduced by combining the Mirrlees econ-
omy of Chapter 5 with the Diamond overlapping generations economy. Each
consumer lives for two periods, consuming in both but working only in the
…rst period. Within a generation, consumers are di¤erentiated by their level
of ability. Denoting the ability level by s, 0 s S, S …nite, the cumula-
tive distribution of s is given by ¡ (s) with the normalisation ¡ (S) = 1. This
normalisation restricts the generations to be of equal size. The corresponding
density function is ° (s). Writing the consumption levels and labour supply (in
hours) of a consumer of ability s born in t as x tt (s) ; x t+1
t (s) and ` t (s), the
consumption levels and e¤ective labour supply per member of generation t are
Z S
1
xt (s) = xtt (s) ° (s) ds; (15.78)
0
Z S
x 2t (s) = x t+1
t (s) ° (s) ds; (15.79)
0
and Z S
zt (s) = s`t (s) ° (s) ds: (15.80)
0
¡ ¢
The preferences of each consumer are given by the utility function U = U xtt ; xt+
t
1
; `t
and this is maximised subject to the budget constraint

xt+ 1 ¡ ¢
x tt + t
= wt s`t ¡ T ` (wt s` t) ¡ Ts x t+1
t : (15.81)
1 + rt+1
In ¡(15.83),
¢ T ` (wt s` t) is the income tax function, with w t the wage rate, and
T s x t+1
t the tax on second-period consumption. The latter tax is essentially
equivalent to a tax on savings. To simplify the analysis by eliminating the
need for discounting in the government budget, it is assumed that the tax on
second-period consumption is pre-paid in the …rst period of life.
Given consumer choices xtt (s) ; xt+
t
1
(s) and ` t (s), total di¤erentiation of the
utility function with respect to s gives
dU z0 z0
= Ux tt xt0
t + Uxt+1 xt+10
t + U`t t ¡ U`t 2t : (15.82)
ds t s s
Applying
³ the argument ´of (5.13) - (5.15) that s0 = s must minimise U (s0) -
U x tt (s) ; x t+1
t (s) ; zts(s)
0 , it follows that

z0t
Uxtt x t0 t+10
t + Uxt+1x t + U` t = 0; (15.83)
t s
and hence that
dU z0
= ¡U`t 2t ¸ 0: (15.84)
ds s
494 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

Equation (15.86) is the …rst-order condition for self-selection that must constrain
the choice of tax functions. The¡ …nal part of the description¢ of the consumer is
to solve the identity U (s) = U x tt (s) ; x t+1
t (s) ; ` t (s) to write
¡ ¢
x tt (s) = x tt U (s) ; x t+1
t (s) ; `t (s) : (15.85)

The production ³function´ for the economy is given by the constant returns
to scale function F e
kt; z t where e kt is the level of capital stock per member
³ ´ ³ ´
of the young generation. The identities w t = F z e kt; zt and rt = F k ekt ; zt
determine the wage rate and interest rate via optimal choice of factors by …rms.
The capital stock left to generation t + 1 is given by
³ ´
e
kt+1 = F e kt ; zt + ekt ¡ x1t ¡ x 2t¡1 : (15.86)

The optimisation problem facing the government in period t is to maximise


the welfare level of generation t determined by the social welfare function
Z S ¡ ¢
t
W = U xtt (s) ; xt+1
t (s) ; ` t (s) ° (s) ds; (15.87)
0

subject to the constraints


Z S
x 2t ¸ xt+1
t (s) ° (s) ds; (15.88)
0

³ ´ Z S
F ek t; z t + e
kt ¡ x tt (s) ° (s) ds ¡ x2t¡ 1 ¸ e
k t+1 ; (15.89)
0

and the di¤erential equation (15.86). In (15.90) is the maximum permissible


mean level of second period consumption to which the members of generation t
are entitled and in (15.92) e
kt+ 1 is the minimum level of capital stock they must
endow to the next generation. For this maximisation, xt+ t
1
(s) and ` t (s) are
t
the control variables, U (s) is the state variable and x t (s) is determined from
(15.87). This formulation leads to the Hamiltonian
£ ¤
H (s) = U (s) ° (s) + ¸ t x2t ¡ x t+1
t (s) ° (s)
h ³ ´ i ¸
t e e t 2 e t U` `t (s)
+½ F kt ; zt + kt ¡ xt (s) ¡ x t¡1 ¡ k t+1 ° (s) + ¹ (s) ¡ ;
s
(15.90)

where ¸t and ½t are the Lagrange multipliers on the constraints and ¹t (s) is
the co-state variable.
The next step is to exploit the requirement that x 2t and e kt+ 1 are Pareto
optimal to simplify (15.92). It follows from the interpretation of Lagrange mul-
t¤ t¤
tipliers that @W
@x2
= ¸t > 0 and @W = ¡½t < 0 where W t¤ is the maximum
t @e
k t+1
15.5. INCOME AND INTEREST TAXATION 495

value function for the optimisation. From these

@W t¤
@e
k t+1 @x2 ¸t
2 jW
t¤ = ¡
@W
t
t¤ = > 0: (15.91)
@x t ½t
@e
k t+1

Similarly,
@W t¤
@e
kt @x2
t¡1 1
2 jW t¤ = ¡
@W t¤ = ³ ´; (15.92)
@x t¡1 et 1 + Fk ekt ; z t
@k

which, when stepped one period forward, gives

@W t+1¤
@e
kt+ 1 @x2 1
t
jW t+1¤ = ¡ @W t+1¤ = ³ ´: (15.93)
@x 2t e 1 + F e
k ; z
@ k t+1 k t+1 t+1

The allocation is Pareto e¢cient when the gradients given in (15.93) and (15.95)
are equal so that the indi¤erence curve of the social welfare function, de…ned
over x 2t and e
kt+1 , are tangential for periods t and t + 1. Therefore, at a point
on the lo cus of Pareto optima,

¸t 1
t
= ³ ´: (15.94)
½ 1 + Fk ekt+1 ; zt+1

The restriction in (15.96) can be substituted into the Hamiltonian to give the
simpli…ed form
¸
U` `t (s)
H (s) = U (s) ° (s) + ¹t (s) ¡
s
2 3
x 2
¡ x t+1
(s) ³ ´
+½t 4 t ³ t ´ +F e
kt ; zt + e
kt ¡ xtt (s) ¡ x 2t¡1 ¡ e
k t+1 5 ° (s) :
1 + Fk e kt+1 ; zt+1
(15.95)
³ ´
e t+1 ; zt+1 and denote ¢¤ = x2
Next de…ne r¤t+1 = F k t
t
1+r¤
¡e
kt+1 . From the
t+1
second-period budget constraint of consumers it can be seen that ¢¤t is the
market value in period t of one-period bonds sold to consumers of generation t
and which will be redeemed in t + 1. The Hamiltonian can then be written as
¸
t U` `t (s)
H (s) = U (s) ° (s) + ¹ (s) ¡
s
t+1 ³ ´ ¸
t ¤ xt (s) e e t 2 e
+½ ¢t ¡ ¤
+ F kt; zt + kt ¡ x t (s) ¡ x t¡1 ¡ k t+1 ° (s) : (15.96)
1 + rt+1
496 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES

Optimising with respect to xt+ t


1
(s) provides the necessary condition
¸ ¸¸
t 1 @xtt (s) t `t @x tt (s)
½ ¡ ¡ ° (s) + ¹ (s) ¡ U`xtt t+1 + U`xt+1 = 0;
1 + r¤t+1 @xt+
t
1
(s) s @x t (s) t

(15.97)
for the determination of the tax schedule T s (¢).
From condition (15.99), two theorems can be proved.

Theorem 73 (Ordover and Phelps) The marginal rate of interest income tax,
T s0 (¢), is zero at s = S.

Proof. The transversality condition for the optimisation is that ¹t (S) = 0.


At s = S this reduces (15.99) to
¸
1 @x tt (S)
½t ¡ ¡ ° (S) = 0: (15.98)
1 + r¤t+1 @x t+1
t (S)

As ½t > 0 and ° (S) > 0, (16.73) shows that there is no distortion in choice.

Theorem 74 (Ordover and Phelps) When the utility function is separable be-
tween consumption and labour, interest income is tax exempt.
¡ ¡ ¢ ¢
Proof. The separable utility function is written as U ª x tt ; xt+1
t ; `t .
Then
@x tt (s) @x tt (s)
U `xtt + U`xt+1 = U`ª ªxtt + U`ªª xtt+1
@x t+1
t (s) t
@xt+
t
1
(s)
= ¡U`ª ª xt+1 + U`ª ªxtt+ 1 = 0; (15.99)
t

@ xt(s) ªxt +1
where the second equality follows from using @xt+1 t
(s)
= ¡ ªt t . Equation
h i t x
t
@xtt (s)
(15.101) implies that ½t ¡ 1+r1¤ ¡ @xt+1 (s)
° (s) = 0 for all s which proves the
t+1 t
theorem.
The argument behind Theorem 15.7 is essentially equivalent to that of The-
orem 5.6: given the upper-bound upon ability, there is no gain from having
the choices of that consumer distorted. Theorem 15.8 is di¤erent in nature and
shows that the tax on interest income is redundant when the utility function is
weakly separable and an optimal income tax is employed. Despite the di¤erent
e¤ects of the two taxes, there is nothing to be gained by having an interest tax
in addition to a nonlinear income tax when preferences are separable. Without
separability, both taxes will be employed.

15.6 Conclusions
The analysis of tax policy in dynamic economies involves consideration of both
intragenerational and intertemporal allocations. Compared with the static analy-
sis, there is also a broader range of instruments available since the use of debt
15.6. CONCLUSIONS 497

becomes a meaningful option. This chapter has attempted to capture these


issues and to illustrate alternative methods of analysis.
The e¤ects of debt were demonstrated in an economy without intergener-
ational altruism. Although an increase in external debt can rarely lead to an
increase in welfare, in an overcapitalised economy an increase in internal debt
will. The policy relevance of this …nding has to be considered in the light of the
Ricardian equivalence proposition that changes in debt have no real e¤ect upon
the economy. A proof of this proposition was given but it was also argued that
it required a particular form of intergenerational altruism and that there were
numerous circumstances in which equivalence does not apply.
In dynamically e¢cient economies with a homogeneous population, the in-
troduction of an income tax or an interest tax simply adds a distortion and
reduces welfare. With a heterogeneous population intragenerational distribu-
tion also becomes relevant. Despite this, an interest tax is redundant when the
utility function is separable and the optimal nonlinear income tax is employed.
498 CHAPTER 15. DEBT AND TAXES
Chapter 16

References

Aaron, H. (1966) “The social insurance paradox”, Canadian Journal of Eco-


nomics and Political Science, 32, 371 - 374.
Aaron, H. (1982) Economic E¤ects of Social Security, Washington: The
Brookings Institute.
Abel, B. (1986a) “Capital accumulation and uncertain lifetimes with adverse
aelection”, Econometrica, 54, 1079 - 1097.
Abel, A.B. (1986b) “The failure of Ricardian equivalence under progressive
wealth taxation“, Journal of Public Economics, 30, 117 - 128.
Abel, A.B. and B.D. Bernheim (1991) “Fiscal policy with impure intergen-
erational altruism“, Econometrica, 59, 1687 - 1711.
Abrams, B.A. and M.A. Schmitz (1984) “The crowding out e¤ect of govern-
ment transfers on private charitable contributions: cross sectional evidence“,
National Tax Journal, 37, 563 - 568.
Ahmad, E. and N.H. Stern (1984) “The theory of reform and Indian indirect
taxes“, Journal of Public Economics, 25, 259 - 298.
Allen, F. (1982) “Optimal linear income taxation with general equilibrium
e¤ects on wages“, Journal of Public Economics, 17, 135 - 143.
Allingham, M.G. and A. Sandmo (1972) “Income tax evasion: a theoretical
analysis“, Journal of Public Economics, 1, 323 - 338.
Andersen, P. (1977) “Tax evasion and labour supply“, Scandinavian Journal
of Economics, 79, 375 - 383.
Anderson, R. and J.G. Ballentine (1976) “The incidence and excess burden
of a pro…ts tax under imperfect competition“, Public Finance, 31, 159 - 176.
Andreoni, J. (1988a) “Privately provided public goods in a large economy:
the limits of altruism“, Journal of Public Economics, 35, 57 73.
Andreoni, J. (1988b) “Why free ride?, Journal of Public Economics, 37, 291
- 304.
Andreoni, J. (1989) “Giving with impure altruism: applications to charity
and Ricardian equivalence“, Journal of Political Economy, 97, 1447 - 1458.
Andreoni, J. (1990) “Impure altruism and donations to public goods: a
theory of warm-glow giving“, Economic Journal, 100, 464 -477.

499
500 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Aoki, M. (1971) “Marshallian external economies and optimal tax-subsidy


structure“, Econometrica, 39, 35 - 53.
Arrow, K.J. (1950) “A di¢culty in the concept of social welfare“, Journal
of Political Economy, 58, 328 - 346.
Arrow, K.J. (1951a) “An extension of the basic theorems of welfare eco-
nomics“, in J. Neyman (ed.), Proceedings of the Second Berkeley Symposium
on Mathematical Statistics and Probability, Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Arrow, K.J. (1951b) Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: Wiley.
Arrow, K.J. (1963) “The role of securities in the optimal allocation of risk-
bearing“, Review of Economic Studies, 31, 91 - 96.
Arrow, K.J. (1965) Aspects of the Theory of Risk-Bearing, Helsinki: Yrjo
Jahnssonin Saatio.
Arrow, K.J. (1969) “The organisation of economic activity: issues perti-
nent to the choice of market versus non-market allocation“ in The Analysis and
Evaluation of Public Expenditures: The PPB System, Washington D.C.: Joint
Economic Committee of the Congress of the United States.
Arrow, K.J. and G. Debreu (1954) “Existence of equilibrium for a competi-
tive economy“, Econometrica, 22, 265 - 290.
Arrow, K.J. and F. Hahn (1971) General Competitive Analysis, San Fran-
cisco: Holden Day.
Arrow, K.J. and R.C. Lind (1970) “Uncertainty and the evaluation of public
investment decisions“, American Economic Review, 60, 364 - 378.
Ashenfelter, O. and J. Heckman (1973) “Estimating labour supply functions“
in G.C. Cain and N.W. Watts (eds.), Income Maintenance and Labour Supply,
Chicago: Rand McNally.
d’Aspremont, C. and L.-A. Gérard-Varet (1979) “Incentives and incomplete
information“, Journal of Public Economics, 11, 25 - 45.
Atkinson, A.B (1972) “Maxi-min and optimal income taxation“, (unpub-
lished).
Atkinson, A.B. (1970) “On the measurement of inequality“, Journal of Eco-
nomic Theory, 2, 244 - 263.
Atkinson, A.B. (1987) “On the measurement of poverty“, Econometrica, 55,
749 - 764.
Atkinson, A.B. and A. Sandmo (1980) “Welfare implications of the taxation
of savings”, Economic Journal, 90, 529 - 549.
Atkinson, A.B. and N.H. Stern (1974) “Pigou, taxation and public goods“
Review of Economic Studies, 41, 119 - 128.
Atkinson, A.B. and J. E. Stiglitz (1972) “The structure of indirect taxation
and economic e¢ciency”, Journal of Public Economics, 1, 97 - 119.
Atkinson, A.B. and J.E. Stiglitz (1976) “The design of tax structure: direct
versus indirect taxation“, Journal of Public Economics, 6, 55 - 75.
Atkinson, A.B. and J.E. Stiglitz (1980) Lectures on Public Economics, Lon-
don: McGraw-Hill.
Auerbach, A.J. (1979) “Wealth maximisation and the cost of capital”, Quar-
terly Journal of Economics, 93, 433 - 446.
501

Auerbach, A.J. (1983) “Taxation, corporate …nancial policy and the cost of
capital”, Journal of Economic Literature, 21, 905 - 940.
Auerbach, A.J. and M.A. King (1983) “Taxation, portfolio choice, and debt-
equity ratios: a general equilibrium model”, Quarterly Journal of Economics,
97, 587 - 609.
Aumann, R.J. (1964) “Markets with a continuum of traders“, Econometrica,
34, 1 - 17.
Averch, H. and L.L. Johnson (1962) “Behaviour of the …rm under regulatory
constraint“, American Economic Review, 52, 1053 - 1069.
Balasko and Shell (1980) “The overlapping-generations model, I: the case of
pure exchange without money“, Journal of Economic Theory, 23, 281 - 306.
Balasko and Shell (1981) “The overlapping-generations model, II: the case
of pure exchange with money“, Journal of Economic Theory, 24, 112 - 142.
Balasko, Y., D. Cass and K. Shell (1980) “Existence of competitive equilib-
rium in a general overlapping-generations model“, Journal of Economic Theory,
23, 307 - 322.
Balcer, Y. (1980) “Taxation of externalities: direct versus indirect“, Journal
of Public Economics, 13, 121 - 129.
Baldry, J.C. (1986) “Tax evasion is not a gamble“, Economics Letters, 22,
333 - 335.
Ball, M.J. (1973) “Recent empirical work on the determinants of relative
house prices“, Urban Studies, 10, 213 - 233.
Ballantine, J.G. and I. Eris (1975) “On the general equilibrium analysis of
tax incidence”, Journal of Political Economy, 83, 633 - 644.
Baron, D. (1989) “The design of regulatory mechanisms and institutions“,
in R. Schmalansee and R. Willig (eds), Handbook of Industrial Organisation,
Amsterdam: North Holland.
Barone, E. (1935) “The ministry of production in the collectivist state“, in
F.A. von Hayek (ed.), Collectivist Economic Planning, London: Routledge.
Barro, R. J. (1974) “Are government bonds net wealth?”, Journal of Political
Economy, 82, 1095 - 1117.
Barro, R.J. (1976) “Reply to Feldstein and Buchanan”, Journal of Political
Economy, 84, 343 - 349.
Baumol, W.J., E.E. Bailey and R.D. Willig (1977) “Weak invisible hand
theorems on the sustainability of multiproduct natural monopoly“, American
Economic Review, 67, 350 - 365.
Baumol, W.J. and D.F. Bradford (1970) “Optimal departures from marginal
cost pricing”, American Economic Review, 60, 265 - 283.
Baumol, W.J. and J. Benhabib (1989) “Chaos: signi…cance, mechanism and
economic applications“, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3, 77 - 105.
Baumol, W.J. and W.E. Oates (1988) The Theory of Environmental Policy,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Becker, W., H.-J. Büchner and S. Sleeking (1987) “The impact of public
transfer expenditures on tax evasion“, Journal of Public Economics, 34, 243 -
252.
502 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Beckerman, W. (1979) “The impact of income maintenance payments on


poverty in Britain 1975“, Economic Journal, 89, 261 - 279.
Berge, C. (1963) Topological Spaces, London: Oliver and Boyd.
Bergson, A. (1938) “A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics“,
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 68, 233 - 252.
Bergson, A. (1973) “On monopoly welfare losses“, American Economic Re-
view, 63, 853 - 870.
Bergstrom, T.C. (1976) “Regulation of externalities“, Journal of Public Eco-
nomics, 5, 131 - 138.
Bergstrom, T.C. and R.C. Cornes (1983) “Independence of allocative e¢-
ciency from distribution in the theory of public goods“, Econometrica, 51, 1753
- 1765.
Bergstrom, T.C., L. Blume and H. Varian (1986) “On the private provision
of public goods“, Journal of Public Economics, 29, 25 - 49.
Bergstrom, T.C., L. Blume and H. Varian (1992) “Uniqueness of Nash equi-
librium in private provision of public goods“, Journal of Public Economics, 49,
391 - 392.
Bernheim, B.D. (1987) “Ricardian equivalence: an evaluation of theory and
evidence“, NBER Macro Annual, 263 - 304.
Bernheim, B.D. and K. Bagwell (1988) “Is everything neutral?‘, Journal of
Political Economy, 96, 308 - 338.
Besley, T. and I. Jewitt (1990) “Optimal uniform taxation and the structure
of consumer preferences“, in G.D. Myles (ed.), Measurement and Modelling in
Economics, Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Beveridge, W. (1942) Social Insurance and Allied Services, Cmd. 6404, Lon-
don: HMSO.
Bhatia, K.B. (1981) “Intermediate goods and the incidence of the corpora-
tion income tax”, Journal of Public Economics, 16, 93 - 112.
Bhatia, K.B. (1982a) “Intermediate goods and the theory of tax incidence”,
Public Finance, 37 , 318 - 338.
Bhatia K.B. (1982b) “Value-added tax and the theory of tax incidence”,
Journal of Public Economics, 19, 203 - 223.
Bhatia, K.B. (1986) “Taxes, intermediate goods, and relative prices: the
case of variable coe¢cients”, Journal of Public Economics, 31, 197 - 213.
Bierwag, G. O., M. A. Grove and C. Khang (1969) “National debt in a
neo-classical growth model: comment“, American Economic Review, 59, 205 -
210.
Bigelow, J.P. (1993) “Inducing e¢ciency: externalities, missing markets, and
the Coase theorem“, International Economic Review, 34, 335 - 346.
Blackorby, C. and D. Donaldson (1978) “Measures of relative inequality and
their meaning in terms of social welfare“, Journal of Economic Theory, 18, 59
- 80.
Blanchard, O.J. (1985) “Debt, de…cits and …nite horizons”, Journal of Po-
litical Economy, 93, 223 - 247.
Blundell, R. (1992) “Labour supply and taxation: a survey“, Fiscal Studies,
13, 15 - 40.
503

Blundell, R. and A. Lewbel (1991) “The information content of equivalence


scales“, Journal of Econometrics, 50, 49 - 68.
Boadway, R.W., M. Marchand and P. Pestieau (1991) “Optimal linear in-
come taxation in models with occupational choice“, Journal of Public Eco-
nomics, 46, 133 - 162.
Boadway, R.W. and D.E. Wildasin, (1989) “A median voter model of social
security”, International Economic Review, 30, 307 - 328.
Bohm, P. (1971) “An approach to the problem of estimating the demand for
public goods“, Swedish Journal of Economics, 73, 55 - 66.
Bohm, P. (1972) “Estimating demand for public goods: an experiment“,
European Economic Review, 3, 55 - 66.
Bohm, P. (1984) “Revealing demand for an actual public good“, Journal of
Public Economics, 24, 135 - 151.
Boldrin, M. and M. Woodford (1990) “Equilibrium models displaying en-
dogeneous ‡uctuations and chaos“, Journal of Monetary Economics, 25, 189 -
222.
Bonnisseau, J.-M. (1991) “Existence of Lindahl equilibria in economies with
nonconvex production sets“, Journal of Economic Theory, 54, 409 - 416.
Bordignon, M. (1990) “Was Kant right? Voluntary provision of public goods
under the principle of unconditional commitment“, Economic Notes, 342 - 372.
Bordignon, M. (1993) “A fairness approach to income tax evasion“, Journal
of Public Economics, 52, 345 - 362.
Bös, D. (1986) Public Enterprise Economics, Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Bourguignon, F. (1979) “Decomposble income inequality measures“, Econo-
metrica, 47, 901 - 920.
Bradford, D.F. (1981) “The incidence and allocation e¤ects of a tax on
corporate distributions”, Journal of Public Economics, 15, 1 - 22.
Brandts, J. and C.A.M. de Bartolome (1992) “Population uncertainty, social
insurance, and actuarial bias”, Journal of Public Economics, 47, 361 - 380.
Break, G.F. (1957) “Income taxes and the incentive to work: an empirical
study“, American Economic Review, 47, 529 - 549.
Brito, D.L. and W.H. Oakland (1977) “Some properties of the optimal in-
come tax“, International Economic Review, 18, 407 - 423.
Brookshire, D.S., M.A. Thayer, W. Schulze and R. D’Arge (1982) “Valu-
ing public goods: a comparison of survey and hedonic approaches“, American
Economic Review, 72, 165 - 177.
Brown, C.V. and E. Levin (1974) “The e¤ects of income taxation on over-
time“, Economic Journal, 84, 833 - 848.
Brown, S.J. and D.S. Sibley (1986) The Theory of Public Utility Pricing,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Browning, E.K. (1975) “Why the social insurance budget is too large in a
democratic society“, Economic Inquiry, 13, 373 - 388.
Buchanan, J. M. (1976) “Barro on the Ricardian equivalence theorem”, Jour-
nal of Political Economy, 84, 337 - 342.
Buchanan, J. and M. Kafoglis (1963) “A note on public goods supply“,
American Economic Review, 53, 403 - 414.
504 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Buhmann, B., L. Rainwater, G. Schmaus and T.M. Smeeding (1989) “Equiv-


alence scales, well-being, inequality, and poverty: sensitivity estimates across
ten countries using the Luxembourg income study (LIS) database“, Review of
Income and Wealth, 34, 115 - 142.
Buiter, W.H. (1980) “Crowding out of private capital formation by govern-
ment borrowing in the presence of intergenerational gifts and bequests”, Greek
Economic Review, 2, 111 - 142.
Buiter, W.H. (1988) “Death, birth, productivity growth and debt neutral-
ity”, Economic Journal, 89, 279 - 293
Buiter, W.H. and J. Carmichael (1984) “Government debt: comment”,
American Economic Review, 74, 762 - 765.
Burbidge, J.B. (1983a) “Social security and savings plans in overlapping-
generations mo dels”, Journal of Public Economics, 21, 79 - 92.
Burbidge J.B. (1983b) “Government debt in an overlapping-generations model
with bequests and gifts”, American Economic Review, 73, 222 - 227.
Burtless, G. and J.A. Hausman (1978) “The e¤ect of taxation on labour sup-
ply: evaluating the Gary negative income tax experiment“, Journal of Political
Economy, 86, 1103 - 1130.
Bush, W.C. and L.S. Mayer (1974) “Some implications of anarchy for the
distribution of property“, Journal of Economic Theory, 8, 401 - 412.
Cadsby, C.B. and M. Frank (1991) “Experimental tests of Ricardian equiv-
alence”, Economic Inquiry, 29, 645 - 664.
Cagan, P. (1965) The E¤ects of Pension Plans on Aggregate Savings, New
York: National Bureau of Economic Research.
Callan, T. and B. Nolan (1991) “Concepts of poverty and the poverty line“,
Journal of Economic Surveys, 5, 243 - 261.
Carmichael, J. (1982) “On Barro’s theorem of debt neutrality: the irrele-
vance of net wealth”, American Economic Review, 72, 202 - 213.
Cass, D. and J.E. Stiglitz (1972) “Risk aversion and wealth e¤ects on port-
folios with many assets“, Review of Economic Studies, 39, 331 - 354.
Chamberlin, J. (1974) “Provision of collective goo ds as a function of group
size“, American Political Science Review, 68, 707 - 716.
Chamberlin, J. (1976) “A diagrammatic exposition of the logic of collective
action“, Public Choice, 26, 59 - 74.
Chen, P. (1990) “Prices vs. quantities and delegating price authority to a
monopolist“, Review of Economic Studies, 57, 521 - 529.
Chipman, J. (1970) “External economies of scale and competitive equilib-
rium“, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84, 347 - 385.
Christiansen, V. (1980) “Two comments on tax evasion“, Journal of Public
Economics, 13, 389 - 393.
Christiansen, V. (1981) “Evaluation of public pro jects under optimal taxa-
tion“, Review of Economic Studies, 48, 447 - 457.
Christiansen, V. (1984) “Which commodity taxes should supplement the
income tax?”, Journal of Public Economics, 24, 195 - 220.
Christiansen, V. (1988) “Choice of occupation, tax incidence and piecemeal
tax revision“, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 90, 141 - 159.
505

Christiansen, V. (1993) “A normative analysis of capital income taxes in the


presence of aggregate risk“, The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory,
18, 55 - 76..
Christiansen, V. and E.S. Jansen (1978) “Implicit social preferences in the
Norwegian system of indirect taxation“, Journal of Public Economics, 10, 217
- 245..
Clarke, E.H. (1971) “Multipart pricing of public goods“, Public Choice, 11,
17 - 33.
Clotfelter, C.T. (1983) “Tax evasion and tax rates: an analysis of individual
returns“, Review of Economics and Statistics, 65, 363 - 373.
Coase, R.H. (1960) “The problem of social cost“, Journal of Law and Eco-
nomics, 3, 1 - 44.
Collet, P. and J. Eckmann (1980) Iterated Maps on the Interval as Dynamical
Systems, Basel: Birkhauser.
Corlett, W.J. and D.C. Hague (1953) “Complementarity and the excess bur-
den of taxation”, Review of Economic Studies, 21, 21 - 30.
Cornes, R. and T. Sandler (1984a) “Easy riders, joint production and public
goods“, Economic Journal, 94, 580 - 598.
Cornes, R. and T. Sandler (1984b) “The theory of public goods: non-Nash
behaviour“, Journal of Public Economics, 23, 367 - 379.
Cornes, R. and T. Sandler (1985) “The simple analytics of pure public good
provision“, Economica, 52, 103 - 116.
Cornwall, R.R. (1977) “The concept of general equilibrium in a market econ-
omy with imperfectly competitive producers“, Metroeconomica, 29, 55 - 72.
Coulter, F.A.E., F.A. Cowell and S.P. Jenkins (1992) “Di¤erences in needs
and assessment of income distributions“, Bulletin of Economic Research, 44, 77
- 124.
Cournot, A.A. (1838) Recherches sur les Principes Mathématiques de la
Théorie des Richesses, Paris: Librairie des Sciences Politiques et Sociales.
Cowell, F.A. (1977) Measuring Inequality, Oxford: Phillip Allan.
Cowell, F.A. (1981) “Taxation and labour supply with risky activities“, Eco-
nomica, 48, 365 - 379.
Cowell, F.A. (1985a) “The economic analysis of tax evasion“, Bulletin of
Economic Research, 37, 163 - 193.
Cowell, F.A. (1985b) “Tax evasion with labour income“, Journal of Public
Economics, 26, 19 - 34.
Cowell, F.A. and J.P.F. Gordon (1988) “Unwillingness to pay“, Journal of
Public Economics, 36, 305 - 321.
Cowell, F.A. and K. Kuga (1971) “Additivity and the entropy concept: an
axiomatic approach to inequality measurement“, Journal of Economic Theory,
25, 131 - 143.
Cowling, K.G. and D.C. Mueller (1978) “The social costs of monopoly power“,
Economic Journal, 88, 727 - 748.
Cowling, K.G. and M. Waterson (1976) “Price-cost margins and market
structure“, Economica, 43, 267 - 274.
Cramer, J.S. (1969) Empirical Econometrics, Amsterdam: North-Holland.
506 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Craig, B. and R.G. Batina, (1991), “The e¤ects of social security in a life
cycle family labor supply simulation model”, Journal of Public Economics, 46,
199 - 226.
Crane, S.E. and F. Nourzad (1986) “In‡ation and tax evasion: an empirical
analysis“, Review of Economics and Statistics, 68, 217 - 223.
Crawford, V.P. and D.M. Lilien (1981) “Social security and the retirement
decision”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 95, 505 - 529.
Cremer, H. and F. Gahvari (1993) “Tax evasion and optimal commodity
taxation“, Journal of Public Economics, 50, 261 - 275.
Cremer, H., M. Marchand and P. Pestieau (1990) “Evading, auditing and
taxing“, Journal of Public Economics, 43, 67 - 92.
Cripps, M.W. and G.D. Myles (1989) “Price normalisations in general equi-
librium models of imperfect competition“, (unpublished).
Cross, R. and G.K. Shaw (1982) “On the economics of tax aversion“, Public
Finance, 37, 36 - 47.
Dales, J.H. (1968) Pollution, Property and Prices, Toronto: University of
Toronto Press.
Dalton, H. (1920) “The measurement of the inequality of incomes“, Eco-
nomic Journal, 30, 348 - 361.
Danziger, S., R. Haverman and R. Plotnick (1981) “How income transfer
programs a¤ect work, savings, and the income distribution: a critical review“,
Journal of Economic Literature, 19, 975 - 1028.
Dasgupta, D. and J.-I. Itaya (1992) “Comparative statics for the private
provision of public goods in a conjectural variations model with heterogeneous
agents“, Public Finance, 47, 17 - 31.
Dasgupta, P., P. Hammond and E. Maskin (1979) “The implementation of
social choice rules: some general results on incentive compatibility“, Review of
Economic Studies, 46, 185 - 216.
Dasgupta, P., P. Hammond and E. Maskin (1980) “On imperfect information
and optimal pollution control“, Review of Economic Studies, 47, 857 - 860.
Dasgupta, P., A. Sen and D. Starret (1973) “Notes on the measurement of
inequality“, Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 180 - 187.
Dasgupta, P. and J.E. Stiglitz (1972) “On optimal taxation and public pro-
duction“, Review of Economic Studies, 39, 87 - 103.
Davidson, C. and L.W. Martin (l985) “General equilibrium tax incidence
under imperfect competition: a quantity-setting supergame snalysis”, Journal
of Political Economy, 93, 1212 - 1223.
Davies, J.B. and P. Kuhn (1992) “Social security, longevity, and moral haz-
ard”, Journal of Public Economics, 49, 91 - 106.
Davis, O. and A. Whinston (1962) “Externalities, welfare and the theory of
games“, Journal of Political Economy, 70, 241 - 262.
Deardor¤, A.V. (1976) “The optimum growth rate for population: com-
ment”, International Economic Review, 17, 510 - 514.
Deaton, A. S. (1981) “Optimal taxes and the structure of preferences”,
Econometrica, 49, 1245 - 1260.
507

Deaton, A.S. (1977) “Equity, e¢ciency, and the structure of indirect taxa-
tion“, Journal of Public Economics, 8, 299 - 312.
Deaton, A.S. (1979) “The distance function in consumer behaviour with ap-
plications to index numbers and optimal taxation”, Review of Economic Studies,
46, 391 - 405.
Deaton, A.S. and J. Muellbauer (1986) “On measuring child costs: with
applications to poor countries“, Journal of Political Economy, 94, 720 - 744.
Deaton, A.S., J. Ruiz-Castillo and D. Thomas (1989) “The in‡uence of
household composition on household expenditure: theory and Spanish evidence“,
Journal of Political Economy, 97, 179 - 200.
Deaton, A.S. and N.H. Stern (1986) “Optimally uniform commodity taxes,
taste di¤erence and lump-sum grants”, Economics Letters, 20, 263-266.
Debreu, G. (1951) “The coe¢cient of resource utilisation“, Econometrica,
19, 273-292.
Debreu, G. (1954a) “Representation of a preference oredering by a numer-
ical function“, in R.M. Thrall, C.H. Coombs and R.L. Davis (eds.) Decision
Processes, New York: Wiley.
Debreu, G. (1954b) “Valuation equilibrium and Pareto optimum“, Proceed-
ings of the National Academy of Sciences of the U.S.A., 40, 588 - 592.
Debreu, G. (1959) Theory of Value, New York: Wiley.
Debreu, G. (1970) “Economies with a …nite set of equilibria“, Econometrica,
38, 387 - 392.
Debreu, G. (1980) “Existence of competitive equilibrium“ in K.J. Arrow
and M.D. Intriligator (eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Economics, Amsterdam:
North-Holland.
Debreu, G. and H. Scarf (1963) “A limit theorem on the core of an economy“,
International Economic Review, 4, 235 - 246.
Decoster, A. and E. Schokkaert (1989) “Equity and e¢ciency of a reform of
Belgian indirect taxes“, Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 55, 155 - 176.
Delipalla, S. and M. Keen (1992) “The comparison between ad valorem and
speci…c taxation under imperfect competition“, Journal of Public Economics,
49, 351 - 367.
Desai, M. and A. Shah (1988) “An econometric approach to the measurment
of poverty“, Oxford Economic Papers, 40, 505 - 522.
Diamond, P.A. (1965) “National debt in a neo-classical growth model“,
American Economic Review, 55, 1126 - 1150.
Diamond, P.A. (1967) “The role of the stock market in a general equilibrium
model with technological uncertainty“, American Economic Review, 57, 759 -
776.
Diamond, P.A. (1973a) “Consumption externalities and imperfect corrective
pricing“, Bell Journal of Economics, 4, 526 - 538.
Diamond, P.A. (1973b) “Taxation and public production in a growth set-
ting”, in J.A. Mirrlees and N.H. Stern (eds.), Models of Economic Growth,
London: Macmillan.
Diamond, P.A. (1975) “A many-person Ramsey tax rule”, Journal of Public
Economics, 4, 227 - 244.
508 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Diamond, P.A. (1977) “A framework for social security analysis”, Journal


of Public Economics, 8, 275 - 298.
Diamond, P. A., L.J. Helms and J. A. Mirrlees (1980) “Optimal taxation in
a stochastic economy“, Journal of Public Economics, 14, 1 - 29.
Diamond, P.A. and J. A. Mirrlees (1971) “Optimal taxation and public pro-
duction 1: Production e¢ciency and 2: Tax rules“, American Economic Review,
61, 8 - 27 and 261 - 278.
Diamond, P.A. and J. A. Mirrlees (1973) “Aggregate production with con-
sumption externalities“, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 87, 1 - 24.
Diamond, P.A. and J. A. Mirrlees (1986) “Payroll-tax …nanced social insur-
ance with variable retirement“, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 88, 25 -
50.
Diamond, P.A. and J.E. Stiglitz (1974) “Increases in risk and in risk aver-
sion“, Journal of Economic Theory, 8, 337 - 360.
Dickson, V.A. and W. Yu (1989) “Welfare losses in Canadian manufactur-
ing under alternaitve oligopoly regimes“, International Journal of Industrial
Organisation, 7, 257 - 267.
Dierckx, I, C. Matutes and D. Neven (1988) “Indirect taxation and Cournot
equilibrium“, International Journal of Industrial Organisation, 6, 385 - 399.
Dierker, H. and B. Grodal (1986) “Non-existence of Cournot-Walras equilib-
rium in a general equilibrium model with two oligopolists“, in W. Hildenbrand
and A. Mas-Collel (eds.), Contributions to Mathematical Economics, Amster-
dam: North-Holland.
Dixit, A.K. (1970) “On the optimum structure of commodity taxes”, Amer-
ican Economic Review, 60, 295 - 301.
Dixit, A.K. (1979) “Price changes and optimum taxation in a many-consumer
economy“, Journal of Public Economics, 11, 143 - 157.
Donaldson, D. and J.A. Weymark (1980) “A single-parameter generalisation
of the Gini indices of inequality“, Journal of Economic Theory, 22, 67 - 86.
Drazen, A. (1978) “Government debt, human capital, and bequests in a
life-cycle model”, Journal of Political Economy, 86, 505 - 516.
Dreze, J.H. (1964) “Some postwar contributions of French economists to the-
ory and public policy with special emphasis on problems of resource allocation“,
American Economic Review, 54, 1 - 64.
Dreze, J.H. (1970-1) “Market allocation under uncertainty“, European Eco-
nomic Review, 2, 133 - 165.
Dreze, J.H. (1974) “Investment under private ownership: optimality, equi-
librium and stability“, in J.H. Dreze (ed.) Allocation Under Uncertainty: Equi-
librium and Optimality, New York: Macmillan.
Du¢e, D. and H. Sonnenschein (1989) “Arrow and general equilibrium the-
ory“, Journal of Economic Literature, 27, 565 - 598.
Eaton, J. and H.S. Rosen (1980) “Labor supply, uncertainty, and e¢cient
taxation“, Journal of Public Economics, 14, 365 374.
Ebert, U. (1992) “A reexamination of the optimal nonlinear income tax“,
Journal of Public Economics, 49, 47 - 73.
509

Ebrahimi, A. and C. J. Heady (1988) “Tax design and household consump-


tion”, Economic Journal (Supp.), 98, 83 - 96.
Ebrill, L.P. and S.M. Slutsky (1982) “Time, congestion and public goods“,
Journal of Public Economics, 17, 307 334.
Ebrill, L.P. and S.M. Slutsky (1990) “Production e¢ciency and optimal pric-
ing in intermediate-good related industries“, International Journal of Industrial
Organisation, 8, 417 - 442.
Eckstein, Z., M. Eichenbaum and D. Peled (1985) “Uncertain lifetimes and
the welfare enhancing properties of annuity markets and social security”, Jour-
nal of Public Economics, 26, 303 - 326.
Edgeworth, F.Y. (1925) “The pure theory of monopoly“ in Papers Relating
to Political Economy, New York: Burt Franklin.
Eeckhoudt, L. and P. Hansen (1982) “Uncertainty and the partial loss o¤set
provision“, Economics Letters, 9, 31 - 35.
Eichhorn, W. (1988) “On a class of inequality measures“, Social Choice and
Welfare, 5, 171 - 177.
Enders, W. and H.E. Lapan (1992) “Social security taxation and intergen-
erational risk sharing”, International Economic Review, 23, 647 - 658.
Engel, E. (1895) “Die lebenskosten Belgischer arbeiter-familien früher und
jetzt“, International Statistical Institute Bulletin, 9, 1- 74.
Feehan, J.P. (1989) “Pareto-e¢ciency with three varieties of public input“,
Public Finance, 44, 237 - 248.
Feige, E.L. (1979) “How big is the irregular economy?”, Challenge, 5 - 13.
Feige, E.L. (1981) “The UK’s unobserved economy“, Journal of Economic
A¤airs, 1, 205 - 212.
Feige, E.L. and R.T. McGee (1983) “Sweden’s La¤er curve: taxation and
the unobserved economy“, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 85, 499 - 519.
Feldstein, M.S. (1973) “On the optimal progressivity of the income tax“,
Journal of Public Economics, 2, 236 - 376.
Feldstein, M.S. (1974) “Social security, induced retirement and aggregate
capital accumulation”, Journal of Political Economy, 82, 905 - 926.
Feldstein, M.S. (1976a) “On the theory of tax reform“, Journal of Public
Economics, 6, 77 - 104.
Feldstein, M.S. (1976b) “Perceived wealth in bonds and social security: a
comment”, Journal of Political Economy, 84, 331 - 336.
Feldstein, M.S. (1985) “The optimal level of social security bene…ts”, Quar-
terly Journal of Economics, 100, 303 - 320.
Feldstein, M.S. (1987) “Should social security bene…ts be means tested?”,
Journal of Political Economy, 95, 468 - 484.
Feldstein, M.S. (1990) “Imperfect annuity markets, unintended bequests,
and the optimal age strcture of social security bene…ts”, Journal of Public Eco-
nomics, 41, 31 - 43.
Fields, G.S. and J.C.H. Fei (1978) “On inequality comparisons“, Economet-
rica, 46, 303 - 316.
Fisher, I. (1930) The Theory of Interest, New York: Macmillan.
510 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Flemming, J.S. (1977) “Optimal payroll taxes and social security funding”,
Journal of Public Economics, 7, 329 - 349.
Fogelman, F., M. Quinzii and R. Guesnerie (1978) “Dynamic processes for
tax reform theory“, Journal of Economic Theory, 17, 200 - 226.
Foley, D.K. (1970) “Lindahl’s solution and the core of an economy with
public goods“, Econometrica, 38, 66 - 72.
Foster, J.E. (1983) “An axiomatic characterisation of the Theil measure of
income inequality“, Journal of Economic Theory, 31, 105 - 121.
Foster, J.E., J. Greer and E. Thorbecke (1984) “A class of decomposable
poverty measures“, Econometrica, 52, 761 - 767.
Friedland, N., S. Maital and A. Rutenberg (1978) “A simulation study of
income taxation“, Journal of Public Economics, 10, 107 - 116.
Friedman, J.W. (1977) Oligopoly and the Theory of Games, Amsterdam:
North-Holland.
Gabszewicz, J. J. and J.-P. Vial (1972) “Oligopoly ’a la Cournot’ in general
equilibrium analysis“, Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 381 - 400.
Gale, D. (1955) “The law of supply and demand“, Mathematica Scandinav-
ica, 3, 155 - 169.
Gale, D. (1973) “Pure exchange equilibrium of dynamic economic models“,
Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 12 - 36.
Gary-Bobo, R.J. (1989) “Cournot-Walras and locally consistent equilibria“,
Journal of Economic Theory, 49, 10 - 32.
Geanakoplos, J.D. and H.M. Polemarchakis (1984) “Intertemporally separa-
ble, overlapping-generations economies“, Journal of Economic Theory, 34, 207
- 215.
Geeroms, H. and H. Wilmots (1985) “An empirical model of tax evasion and
tax avoidance“, Public Finance, 40, 190 - 209.
Gigliotti, G.A. (1984) “Total utility, overlapping generations and social se-
curity”, Economics Letters, 15, 169 - 173.
Gini, C. (1912) Variabilita Mutabilita, Bologna.
Glazer, A. (1989) “The social discount rate under majority voting“, Public
Finance, 44, 384 - 393.
Gordon, J.P.F. (1989) “Individual morality and reputation costs as deter-
rents to tax evasion“, European Economic Review, 33, 797 - 805.
Gorman, W.M. (1959b) “Are social indi¤erence curves convex?”, Quarterly
Journal of Economics, 73, 485 - 496.
Gorman, W.M. (1978) “Tricks with utility functions“, Part 1, LSE Econo-
metrics Programme, Discussion Paper No. B1.
Gorman, W.M. and G.D. Myles (1987) “Characteristics“, in The New Pal-
grave Dictionary of Economics, London: Macmillan.
Grandmont, J.-M. (1985) On endogeneous competitive business cycles“,
Econometrica, 53, 995 - 1045.
Green, J. (1988) “Demographics, market failure and social securiy“ in S.M.
Wachter (ed.), Social Security and Private Pensions, Lexington: Lexington
Books.
511

Green, J. and J.-J. La¤ont (1977) “Characterization of satisfactory mecha-


nisms for the revelation of preferences for public goods“, Econometrica, 45, 427
- 438.
Green, J. and J.-J. La¤ont (1979) Incentives in Public Decision Making,
Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Green, J. and E. Sheshinski (1976) “Direct versus indirect remedies for ex-
ternalities“, Journal of Political Economy, 84, 797 - 808.
Griliches, Z. (1971) “Hedonic price indexes for automobiles: an economet-
ric analysis of quality chage“, in Z. Griliches (ed.), Price Indexes and Quality
Change: Studies in New Methods of Measurement, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Grinols, E.L. (1985) “Public investment and social risk-sharing“, European
Economic Review, 29, 303 - 321.
Grossman, S.J. and O.D. Hart (1979) “A theory of competitive equilibrium
in stock market economies“, Econometrica, 47, 293 - 330.
Groves, T. (1973) “Incentives in teams“, Econometrica, 41, 617 - 631.
Groves, T. and J. Ledyard (1977) “Optimal allocation of public goods: a
solution to the “free rider“ problem“, Econometrica, 45, 783 - 809.
Groves, T. and M. Loeb (1975) “Incentives and public inputs“, Journal of
Public Economics, 4, 211 - 226.
Guesnerie, R. (1977) “On the direction of tax reform“, Journal of Public
Economics, 7, 179 - 202.
Guesnerie, R. and J.-J. La¤ont (1978) “Taxing price makers“, Journal of
Economic Theory, 19, 423 - 455.
Gutmann, P.M. (1977) “The subterranean economy“, Financial Analysts
Journal, 26 - 28.
Hahn, F.H. (1973) “On optimum taxation“, Journal of Economic Theory,
6, 96 - 106.
Hahn, F.H. (1982) Money and In‡ation, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Hansson, I. and C. Stuart (1989) “Social security as trade among living
generations”, American Economic Review, 79, 1182 - 1195.
Harberger, A.C. (1954) “Monopoly and resource allocation“, American Eco-
nomic Review, 45, 77 - 87.
Harberger, A.C. (1962) “The incidence of the corporation income tax”, Jour-
nal of Political Economy, 70, 215 - 240.
Harris, R.G. and J.G. MacKinnon (1979) “Computing optimal tax equilib-
ria“, Journal of Public Economics, 11, 197 - 212.
Hart, O.D. (1975a) “On the optimality of equilibrium when the market struc-
ture is incomplete“, Journal of Economic Theory, 11, 418-443.
Hart, O.D. (1975b) “Some negative results on the existence of comparative
statics results in portfolio theory“, Review of Economic Studies, 42, 615 - 621.
Hart, O.D. (1982) “A model of imperfect competition with Keynsian fea-
tures“, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 97, 109 - 138.
Hart, O.D. (1985) “Imperfect competition and general equilibrium: an overview
of recent work“ in K.J. Arrow and S. Honkapohja (eds.), Frontiers of Economics,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
512 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Hatta, T. (1986) “Welfare e¤ects of changing commo dity tax rates toward
uniformity“, Journal of Public Economics, 29, 99 - 112.
Hausman, (1985) “Taxation and labour supply“ in A.J. Auerbach and M.
Feldstein (eds.), Handbook of Public Economics, Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Heady, C. and P. Mitra (1980) “The computation of optimum linear taxa-
tion.“ Review of Economic Studies, 47, 567 - 585.
Heller, W.P. and D.A. Starrett (1976) “On the nature of externalities“, in
S.A.Y. Lin (ed.), Theory and Measurement of Economic Externalities, New
York: Academic Press.
Hellwig, M.F. (1981) “Bankruptcy, limited liability, and the Modigliani-
Miller theorem“, American Economic Review, 89, 155 - 170.
Hellwig, M.F. (1986) “The optimal linear income tax revisited“, Journal of
Public Economics, 31, 163 - 179.
Helpman, E. and E. Sadka (1978) “The optimal income tax“, Journal of
Public Economics, 9, 383 - 393.
Hicks, J.R. (1939) Value and Capital, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hildenbrand, W. and A. Kirman (1988) Equilibrium Analysis, Amsterdam:
North-Holland.
Hirshleifer, J. (1964) “E¢cient allocation of capital in an uncertain world“,
American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 54, 77 - 85.
Hirshleifer, J. (1966) “Investment decisions under uncertainty: applications
of the state-preference approach“, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 80, 252 -
277.
Holmstrom, B. (1979) “Groves’ scheme on restricted domains“, Economet-
rica, 47, 1137 - 1144.
Houthakker, H.S. (1960) “Additive preferences“, Econometrica, 28, 244 -
257.
Hu, S.C. (1978) “On the dynamic behaviour of the consumer and the optimal
provision of social security”, Review of Economic Studies, 45, 437 - 445.
Hu, S.C. (1979) “Social security, the supply of labor, and capital accumula-
tion”, American Economic Review, 69, 274 - 283.
Hu, S.C. (1982) “Social security, majority-voting equilibrium and dynamic
e¢ciency”, International Economic Review, 23, 269 - 287.
Hurwicz, L. (1979a) “Outcome functions yielding Walrasian and Lindahl
allocations at Nash equilibrium points“, Review of Economic Studies, 46, 217 -
225.
Hurwicz, L. (1979b) “On allocations attainable through Nash equilibria“,
Journal of Economic Theory, 21, 140 - 165.
Intriligator, M.D. (1971) Mathematical Optimization and Economic Theory,
Englewood Cli¤s: Prentice Hall.
Ireland, N.J. (1977) “Ideal prices vs. prices vs. quantities“, Review of Eco-
nomic Studies, 44, 183 - 186.
Ireland, N.J. (1978) “Roy’s identity and monopoly welfare loss“, in D.A.
Currie and W. Peters (eds.), Contempory Economic Analysis, London: Croom
Helm.
513

Isaac, R.M., K.F. McCue and C.R. Plott (1985) “Public goods in an exper-
imental environment“, Journal of Public Economics, 26, 51 - 74.
Isaac, R.M. and J.M. Walker (1988) “Group size e¤ects in public goods provi-
sion: the voluntary contribution mechanism“, Quarterly Journal of Economics,
102, 179 - 199.
Isaac, R.M., J.M. Walker and S.H. Thomas (1984) “Divergent evidence
on free riding: an experimental examination of possible explanations“, Pub-
lic Choice, 43, 113 - 149.
Isachsen, A.J. and S. Strom (1980) “The hidden economy: the labour market
and tax evasion“, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 82, 304 - 311.
Jenkins, S.P. (1991) “The measurement of income inequality“, in L. Osberg
(ed.), Economic Inequality and Poverty: International Perspectives, New York:
M.E. Sharpe.
Johansen, L. (1963) “Some notes on the Lindahl theory of determination of
public expenditures“, International Economic Review, 4, 346 358.
Johansen, L. (1977) “The theory of public goods: misplaced emphasis?”,
Journal of Public Economics, 7, 147 - 152.
Jones, R.W. (1965) “The structure of simple general equilibrium models”,
Journal of Political Economy, 73, 557 - 572.
Jones, R.W. (1971) “Distortions in factor markets and the general equilib-
rium model of production”, Journal of Political Economy, 79, 437-459.
Kaizuka, K. (1965) “Public goods and decentralisation of production“, Re-
view of Economics and Statistics, 47, 118 - 120.
Kanbur, S.M.R. (1980) “Risk taking and taxation“, Journal of Public Eco-
nomics, 15, 163 - 184.
Kanbur, S.M.R. and G.D. Myles (1992) “Policy choice and political con-
straints“, European Journal of Political Economy, 8, 1 - 29.
Kanbur, S.M.R. and M. Tuomala (1994) “Inherent inequality and the opti-
mal graduation of marginal tax rates“, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 96,
275 - 282.
Karni, E. and I. Zilcha (1986) “Welfare and comparative statics implications
of fair social security”, Journal of Public Economics, 30, 341 - 357.
Katona, G. (1964) Private Pensions and Individual Savings, Ann Arbor:
Survey Research Centre, Institute for Social Research, University of Michigan.
Kay, J.A. (1983) “A general equilibrium approach to the measurement of
monopoly welfare loss“, International Journal of Industrial Organisation, 1,
317 - 331.
Kay, J.A. and M. Keen (1983) “How should commodities be taxed?”, Euro-
pean Economic Review, 23, 339 - 358.
Kay, J.A. and M.A. King (1990) The British Tax System, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Kehoe, T.J. and D.K. Levine (1985) “Comparative statics and perfect fore-
sight in in…nite horizon economies“, Econometrica, 53, 433 - 453.
Kemp, M.C. and Y.-K. Ng (1976) “On the existence of social welfare func-
tions, social orderings and social decision functions“, Economica, 43, 59 - 66.
514 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Kihlstrom, R.E. and J.-J. La¤ont (1983) “Taxation and risk taking in general
equilibrium models with free entry“, Journal of Public Economics, 21, 159 - 181.
Kim, O. and M. Walker (1984) “The free rider problem: experimental evi-
dence“, Public Choice, 43, 3 - 24.
King, M.A. (1975) “Taxation, corporate …nancial policy, and the cost of
capital”, Journal of Public Economics, 4, 271 - 279.
King, M.A. (1977) Public Policy and the Corporation, London: Chapman
and Hall.
Kolm, S.-C. (1969) “The optimal production of social justice“, in J. Margolis
and H. Guitton (eds.), Public Economics, London: Macmillan.
Kolm, S.-C. (1973) “A note on optimum tax evasion“, Journal of Public
Economics, 2, 265 - 270.
Kolm, S.-C. (1976) “Unequal inequalities I and I I“, Journal of Economic
Theory, 12, 416 - 442 and 13, 82 - 111.
Konishi, H. (1990) “Final and intermediate goods taxes in an oligopolistic
economy with free entry“, Journal of Public Economics, 42, 371 - 386.
Koopmans, T.C. (1957) Three Essays on the State of Economic Science,
New York: McGraw-Hill.
Koskella, E. (1983) “On the shape of tax schedule, the probability of detec-
tion, and the penalty schemes as deterrents to tax evasion“, Public Finance, 38,
70 - 80.
Kotliko¤, L.J. (1979) “Social security and equilibrium capital intensity”,
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 93, 233 - 253.
Kotliko¤, L.J. (1989) “On the contribution of economics to the evaluation
and formation of social insurance policy”, American Economic Review, Papers
and Proceedings, 77, 184 - 190.
Kotliko¤, L.J., A. Spivak and L.H. Summers (1982) “The adequacy of sav-
ings“, American Economic Review, 72, 1056 - 1069.
La¤ont, J.-J. (1977) “More on prices vs. quantities“, Review of Economic
Studies, 44, 177 - 82.
La¤ont, J.-J. (1987) “Incentives and the allocation of public goods“, in A.J.
Auerbach and M. Feldstein (eds.), Handbook of Public Economics, Amsterdam:
North-Holland.
La¤ont, J.-J. and E. Maskin (1982) “The theory of incentives: an overview“,
in W. Hildenbrand (ed.), Advances in Economic Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lambert, P. (1989) The Distribution and Redistribution of Income: A Math-
ematical Analysis, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Lancaster, K.J. (1966) “A new approach to consumer theory“, Journal of
Political Economy, 74, 132 - 157.
Landskroner, Y., J. Paroush and I. Swary (1990) “Tax evasion and portfolio
decisions“, Public Finance, 45, 409 - 422.
Lange, O. (1942) “The foundations of welfare economics“, Econometrica,
10, 215-228.
Layard, P.R.G. and A.A. Walters (1978) Microeconomic Theory, London:
McGraw-Hill.
515

Lee, M.L. and S.-W. Chao (1988) “E¤ects of social security on personal
saving”, Economic Letters, 28, 365 - 368.
Lerner, A. (1970) “On optimal taxes with an untaxable sector“, American
Economic Review, 60, 284 - 294.
Lewbel, A. (1989) “Household equivalence scales and welfare comparisons“,
Journal of Public Economics, 39, 377 - 391.
Lewbel, A. (1991) “Cost of characteristics indices and household equivalence
scales“, European Economic Review, 35, 1277 - 1293.
Lewis, G.W. and D.T. Ulph (1988) “Poverty, inequality and welfare“, Eco-
nomic Journal, 98, 117 - 131.
Lindahl, E. (1919) Positive Losung, die Gerechtigkeit der Besteuerung, Lund,
reprinted as “Just Taxation - A Positive Solution“ in R.A. Musgrave and A.T.
Peacock (eds.), Classics in the Theory of Public Finance, London: Macmillan.
Lipsey, R.G. and K. Lancaster (1956) “The general theory of second best“,
Review of Economic Studies, 24, 11 - 32.
Little, I.M.D. (1950) A Critique of Welfare Economics, Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Lockwo od, B. (1995) “Multi-…rm regulation without lump-sum taxes“, Jour-
nal of Public Economics, (forthcoming).
Lopez-Garcia, M.-A. (1991) “Population growth and pay-as-you-go social
security in an overlapping generations model“, Public Finance, 46, 93 - 110.
Lorenz, M.C. (1905) “Methods of measuring the concentration of wealth“,
Publications of the American Statistical Association, 9, 209 - 219.
Lydall, H.F. (1968) The Structure of Earnings, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Mailath, G. and A. Postlewaite (1990) “Asymmetric-information bargaining
problems with many agents“, Review of Economic Studies, 57, 351 -368.
Mangasarian, O.L. (1969) Nonlinear Programming, New York: McGraw-Hill.
Marrelli, M. (1984) “On indirect tax evasion“, Journal of Public Economics,
25, 181 - 196.
Marrelli, M. and R. Martina (1988) “Tax evasion and strategic behaviour of
the …rms“, Journal of Public Economics, 37, 55 - 69.
Marwell, G. and R.E. Ames (1981) “Economists free ride, does anyone else?”,
Journal of Public Economics, 15, 295 - 310.
Mas-Collel, A. (1980a) The Theory of General Economic Equilibrium, Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mas-Colell, A. (1980b) “E¢ciency and decentralization in the pure theory
of public goods“, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84, 625 - 641.
Mas-Colell, A. and J. Silvestre (1989) “Cost share equilibria: a Lindahlian
approach“, Journal of Economic Theory, 47, 239 - 256.
McClements, L.D. (1977) “Equivalence scales for children“, Journal of Public
Economics, 8, 191 - 210.
McGuire, M. (1974) “Group homogeneity and aggregate provision of a pure
public good under Cournot behaviour“, Public Choice, 18, 107 - 126.
McKenzie, L. (1955) “Competitive equilibrium with dependent consumer
preferences“, in National Bureau of Standards and Department of the Air Force,
The Second Symposium on Linear Programming, Washington, D.C.
516 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

McLure, C.E. (1972) “A diagrammatic exposition of the Harberger model


with one immobile factor”, Journal of Political Economy, 80, 56 - 82.
McLure, C.E. (1975) “General equilibrium incidence analysis: the Harberger
model after ten years”, Journal of Public Economics, 80, 56 - 82.
Meade, J.E. (1952) “External economies and diseconomies in a competitive
situation“, Economic Journal, 62, 54 - 67.
Meade, J.E. (1975) The Intelligent Radical’s Guide to Economic Policy, Lon-
don: Allen and Unwin.
Meyer, R.A. (1971) “Externalities as commodities“, Amercian Economic
Review, 61, 736 - 740.
de Meza, D. (1982) “Generalised oligopoly derived demand with an applica-
tion to tax induced entry“, Bulletin of Economic Research, 34, 1 - 16.
Mieszkowski, P.M. (1967) “On the theory of tax incidence”, American Eco-
nomic Review, 75, 250 - 262.
Mieszkowski, P.M.(1969) “Tax incidence theory: the e¤ects of taxes on the
distribution of income”, Journal of Economic Literature, 7, 1103 - 1124.
Milleron, J.-C. (1972) “Theory of value with public goods: a survey article“,
Journal of Economic Theory, 5, 419 - 477.
Mirrlees, J.A. (1971) “An exploration in the theory of optimum income tax-
ation“, Review of Economic Studies, 38, 175 - 208.
Mirrlees, J.A. (1972) “On producer taxation“, Review of Economic Studies,
39, 105 - 111.
Mirrlees, J.A. (1975) “Optimal commodity taxation in a two-class economy”,
Journal of Public Economics, 4, 27 - 33.
Mirrlees, J.A. (1976) “Optimal tax theory: a synthesis”, Journal of Public
Economics, 6, 327 - 358.
Mirrlees, J.A. (1986) “The theory of optimal taxation“ in K.J. Arrow and
M.D. Intrilligator (eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Economics, Amsterdam:
North-Holland.
Modigliani, F. and M.H. Miller (1958) “The cost of capital, corporation
…nance and the theory of investment”, American Economic Review, 48, 261 -
297.
Montgomery, W.D. (1972) “Markets in licenses and e¢cient pollution control
programs“, Journal of Economic Theory, 5, 395 - 418.
Moore, J. and R. Repullo (1988) “Subgame perfect implementation“, Econo-
metrica, 56, 1191 - 1220.
Mork, K.A. (1975) “Income tax evasion: some empirical evidence“, Public
Finance, 30, 70 - 76.
Mossin, J. (1968) “Taxation and risk-taking: an expected utility approach“,
Economica, 35, 74 - 82.
Muellbauer, J. (1974) “Household composition, Engel curves and welfare
comparisons between households“, European Economic Review, 5, 103 - 122.
Muellbauer, J. (1977) “Testing the Barten model of household composition
e¤ects and the cost of children“, Economic Journal, 87, 460 - 487.
Muench, T.J. (1972) “The core and the Lindahl equilibrium of an economy
with public goods: an example“, Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 241 - 255.
517

Munk, K.J. (1978) “Optimal taxation and pure pro…t“, Scandinavian Jour-
nal of Economics, 80, 1 - 19.
Munk, K.J. (1980) “Optimal taxation with some non-taxable commodities”,
Review of Economic Studies, 47, 755 - 765.
Murakami, Y. and T. Negishi (1964) “A formulation of external economy“,
International Economic Review, 5, 328 - 334.
Murty, M.N. and R. Ray (1987) “Sensitivity of optimal commodity taxes to
relaxing leisure/goods separability and to the wage rate“, Economics Letters,
24, 273 - 277.
Muzondo, T.R. (1978) “Mixed and pure public goods, user charges and
welfare“, Public Finance, 33, 314 - 330.
Myerson, R.B. and M.A. Satterthwaite (1983) “E¢cient mechanisms for
bilateral trading“, Journal of Economic Theory, 29, 265 - 281.
Myles, G.D. (1987) “Tax design in the presence of imperfect competition:
an example“, Journal of Public Economics, 34, 367 - 378.
Myles, G.D. (1989a) “Ramsey tax rules for economies with imperfect com-
petition.“, Journal of Public Economics, 38, 95 - 115.
Myles, G.D. (1989b) “Imperfect competition and the taxation of intermedi-
ate goods“, Public Finance, 44, 62 - 74.
Myles, G.D. (1994a) “Welfare loss with intermediate goods“, in W. Eichhorn
(ed.), Models and Measurement of Welfare and Inequality, Berlin: Springer-
Verlag.
Myles, G.D. (1994b) “Ramsey pricing in imperfectly competitive economies“,
(unpublished).
Myles, G.D. (1995) “Imperfect competition and industry-speci…c input taxes“,
Public Finance Quarterly, (forthcoming).
Myles, G.D. and R.A. Naylor (1995a) “A model of tax evasion with group
conformity and social customs“, European Journal of Political Economy, (forth-
coming).
Myles, G.D. and R.A. Naylor (1995b) “Optimal auditing and social cus-
toms“, (unpublished).
Nash, J.F. (1950) “The bargaining problem“, Econometrica, 18, 155 - 162.
Negishi, T. (1961) “Monopolistic competition and general equilibrium“, Re-
view of Economic Studies, 28, 196 - 201.
Newbery, D.M. (1970) “A theorem on the measurement of inequality“, Jour-
nal of Economic Theory, 2, 264 - 266.
Newbery, D.M. (1986) “On the desirability of input taxes“, Economics Let-
ters, 20, 267 - 270.
Ng, Y.-K. (1985) Welfare Economics, Basingstoke: MacMillan.
Nicholson, J. (1976) “Appraisal of di¤erent methods of estimating equiva-
lence scales and their results“, Review of Income and Wealth, 22, 1 - 11.
Oakland, W.H. (1972) “Congestion, public goods and welfare“, Journal of
Public Economics, 1, 339 - 357.
Oakland, W.H. (1987) “Theory of public goo ds“ in A.J. Auerbach and M.
Feldstein (eds.), Handbook of Public Economics, Amsterdam: North-Holland.
518 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Ordover, J.A. (1976) “Distributive justice and optimal taxation of wages and
interest in a growing economy”, Journal of Public Economics, 5, 139 - 160.
Ordover, J.A. and E.S. Phelps (1975) “Linear taxation of wealth and wages
for intragenerational lifetime justice: some steady-state cases“, American Eco-
nomic Review, 65, 660 - 673.
Ordover, J.A. and E.S. Phelps (1979) “The concept of optimal taxation in
the overlapping-generations model of capital and wealth”, Journal of Public
Economics, 12, 1 - 26.
Osana, H, (1972) “Externalities and the basic theorems of welfare eco-
nomics“, Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 401 - 414.
Osana, H. (1973) “On the boundedness of an economy with externalities“,
Review of Economic Studies, 40, 321 - 331.
Otani, Y. and J. Sicilian (1977) “Externalities and problems of nonconvexity
and overhead costs in welfare economics“, Journal of Economic Theory, 14, 239
- 251.
Pareto, V. (1909) Manuel d’Économie Politique, Paris: Girard and Briere.
Parish, R.M. (1972) “Economic aspects of pollution control“, Australian
Economic Papers, 11, 32 - 43.
Park, N.-H. (1991) “Steady-state solutions of optimal tax mixes in an overlapping-
generations mo del”, Journal of Public Economics, 46, 227 - 246.
Parks, R.P. (1991) “Pareto irrelevant externalities“, Journal of Economic
Theory, 54, 165 - 179.
Peacock, A. and G.K. Shaw (1982) “Tax evasion and tax revenue loss“,
Public Finance, 37, 269 - 278.
Peck, R.M. (1989) “Taxation, risk and returns to scale“, Journal of Public
Economics, 40, 319 - 330.
Pencavel, J.H. (1979) “A note on income tax evasion, labor supply, and
nonlinear tax schedules“, Journal of Public Economics, 12, 115 - 124.
Pezzey, J. (1992) “The symmetry between controlling pollution by price and
controlling it by quantity“, Canadian Journal of Economics, 25, 983 - 991.
P…ngsten, A. (1986) “Distributionally-neutral tax changes for di¤erent in-
equality concepts“, Journal of Public Economics, 30, 385 - 393.
Phelps, E.S. and J.G. Riley (1978) “Rawlsian growth: dynamic program-
ming of capital and wealth for intergeneration “maxmin” justice”, Review of
Economic Studies, 45, 103 - 120.
Pigou, A.C. (1920) The Economics of Welfare, New York:Macmillan.
Pissarides, C.A. and G. Weber (1989) “An expenditure-based estimate of
Britain’s black economy“, Journal of Public Economics, 39, 17 - 32.
Pollak, R.A. and T.J. Wales (1979) “Welfare comparisons and equivalence
scales“, American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 69, 216 - 221.
Prais, S.J. (1953) “The estimation of equivalent-adult scales from family
budgets“. Economic Journal, 63, 791 - 810.
Prais, S.J. and H.S. Houthakker (1955) The Analysis of Family Budgets,
Department of Applied Economics Monograph 4, Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
519

Pratt, J.W. (1964) “Risk aversion in the small and in the large“, Economet-
rica, 32, 122 - 136.
Pyatt, G. (1985) “An axiomatic approach to the Gini coe¢cient and the
measurement of welfare“, Advances in Econometrics, 3, 87 - 109.
Rader, T. (1972) The Theory of General Equilibrium, New York: Academic
Press.
Radner , R. (1982) “Equilibrium under uncertainty“, in K.J. Arrow and
M.D. Intrilligator (eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Economics, Amsterdam:
North-Holland.
Ramsey, F.P. (1927) “A Contribution to the theory of taxation”, Economic
Journal, 37, 47-61.
Rao, V.V. (1981) “Measurement of deprivation and poverty based on the
proportion spent on food“, World Development, 9, 337 - 353.
Rapanos, V.T. (1991) “The incidence of corporate income tax under variable
returns to scale: comment”, Public Finance, 44, 335 - 336.
Ray, R. (1986a) “Sensitivity of “optimal” commodity tax rates to alternative
demand functional forms”, Journal of Public Economics, 31, 253 - 268.
Ray, R. (1986b) “Redistribution through commodity taxes: the non-linear
Engel curve case”, Public Finance, 41, 277 - 284.
Reddaway, W.B. (1970) E¤ects of the Selective Employment Tax, London:
HMSO.
Regan, D.H. (1972) “The problem of social cost revisited“, Journal of Law
and Economics, 15, 427 - 437.
Reinganum, J. and L. Wilde (1985) “Income tax compliance in a principal-
agent framework“, Journal of Public Economics, 26, 1 - 18.
Reinganum, J. and L. Wilde (1986) “Equilibrium veri…cation and reporting
policies in a model of tax compliance“, International Economics Review, 27,
739 - 760.
Revesz, J.T. (1986) “On some advantages of progressive indirect taxation“,
Public Finance, 41, 182 - 199.
Rey, M. (1965) “Estimating tax evasions: the example of the Italian General
Sales Tax“, Public Finance, 20,366 - 392.
Ricardo, D. (1817) The Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, Lon-
don: M. Dent and Sons.
Rob, R. (1982) “Asymptotic e¢ciency of the demand revealing mechanism“,
Journal of Economic Theory, 28, 207 - 220.
Rob, R. (1989) “Pollution claim settlements under private information“,
Journal of Economic Theory, 47, 307 -333.
Robbins, L. (1932) An Essay on the Nature and Signi…cance of Economic
Science, London: George Allen and Unwin.
Roberts, D.J. (1973) “Existence of Lindahl equilibrium with a measure space
of consumers“, Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 355 - 381.
Roberts, D.J. (1974) “The Lindahl solution for economies with public goods“,
Journal of Public Economics, 3, 23 - 42.
Roberts, J. and H. Sonnenschein (1977) “On the foundations of the theory
of monopolistic competition“, Econometrica, 45, 101 - 113.
520 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Roberts, K.W.S. (1980a) “Possibility theorems with interpersonally compa-


rable welfare levels“, Review of Economic Studies, 47, 409 - 420.
Roberts, K.W.S. (1980b) “Interpersonal comparability and social choice the-
ory“, Review of Economic Studies, 47, 421 - 439.
Roberts, K.W.S. (1980c) “Social choice theory: the single and multi-pro…le
approaches“, Review of Economic Studies, 47, 441 - 450.
Roberts, K.W.S. (1980d) “The limit points of monopolistic competition“,
Journal of Economic Theory, 22, 256 - 278.
Roberts, M.J. and M. Spence (1976) “E-uent charges and licences under
uncertainty“, Journal of Public Economics, 5, 193 - 208.
Romer, T. (1976) “On the progressivity of the utilitarian income tax“, Public
Finance, 31, 329 - 340.
Rosen, S. (1974) “Hedonic prices and implicit markets: product di¤erentia-
tion in pure competition“, Journal of Political Economy, 82, 34 - 55.
Rothbarth, E. (1943) “Note on a method of determining equivalent income
for households of di¤erent composition“, in C. Madge (ed.), War-Time Pattern
of Savings and Expenditure, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rothschild, M. and J.E. Stiglitz (1973) “Some further results on the mea-
surment of inequality“, Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 188 - 204.
Rothschild, M. and J.E. Stiglitz (1976) “Equilibrium in competitive insur-
ance markets: an essay in the economics of incomplete information“, Quarterly
Journal of Economics, 90, 624 - 649.
Rowntree, B.S. (1901) Poverty: A Study of Town Life, London: Macmillan.
Rowntree, B.S. (1941) Poverty and Progress, London: Longman.
Rowntree, B.S. and G.R. Lavers (1951) Poverty and the Welfare State, Lon-
don: Longman.
Rubinstein, A. (1982) “Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model“, Econo-
metrica, 50, 97 - 109.
Rubinstein, A. (1985) “A bargaining model with incomplete information
about time preferences“, Econometrica, 53, 1151 - 1172.
Sadka, E. (1976) “On income distribution incentive e¤ects and optimal in-
come taxation“, Review of Economic Studies, 43, 261 - 268.
Samuelson, P.A. (1954) “The pure theory of public expenditure“, Review of
Economics and Statistics, 36, 387 - 389.
Samuelson, P.A. (1955) “Diagrammatic exposition of a pure theory of public
expenditure“, Review of Economics and Statistics, 37, 350 - 356.
Samuelson, P.A. (1958) “An exact consumption-loan model of interest with
or without the social contrivance of money“, Journal of Political Economy, 66,
467 - 482.
Samuelson, P.A. (1964) “Discussion“, American Economic Review, Papers
and Proceedings, 59, 93 - 96.
Samuelson, P.A. (1975a) “Optimum social security in a life-cycle growth
model”, International Economic Review, 16, 539 - 544.
Samuelson, P.A. (1975b) “The Optimum Growth Rate for Population”, In-
ternational Economic Review, 16, 531 - 538.
521

Samuelson, P.A. (1976) “The optimum growth rate for population: agree-
ment and evaluations”, International Economic Review, 17, 516 - 525.
Samuelson, P.A. (1977) “Rea¢rming the existence of “reasonable“ Bergson-
Samuelson social welfare functions“, Economica, 44, 81 - 88.
Samuelson, P.A. (1986) “Theory of optimal taxation”, Journal of Public
Economics, 30, 137-143.
Sandmo, A. (1972) “Discount rates for public investment under uncertainty“,
International Economic Review, 13, 287 - 302.
Sandmo, A. (1973) “Public goods and the technology of consumption“, Re-
view of Economic Studies, 49, 517 - 528.
Sandmo, A. (1974) “A note on the structure of optimal taxation”, American
Economic Review, 64, 701 - 706.
Sandmo, A. (1975) “Optimal taxation in the presence of externalities“,
Swedish Journal of Economics, 77, 86 - 98.
Sandmo, A. (1977) “Portfolio theory, asset demand and taxation: compara-
tive statics with many assets“, Review of Economic Studies, 44, 369 - 379.
Sandmo, A. (1981) “Income tax evasion, labour supply, and the equity-
e¢ciency tradeo¤“, Journal of Public Economics, 16, 265 - 288.
Sargent, T.J. (1979) Macroeconomic Theory, New York: Academic Press.
Sawhill, I.V. (1988) “Poverty in the US: why is it so persistent?”, Journal
of Economic Literature, 26, 1073 - 1119.
Scitovsky, T. (1951) “The state of welfare economics“, American Economic
Review, 41, 303 - 315.
Scotchmer, S. (1987) “Audit classes and tax enforcement policy“, American
Economic Review, 77, 129 - 136.
Seade, J. (1977) “On the shape of optimal tax schedules“, Journal of Public
Economics, 7, 203 - 236.
Seade, J. (1980) “The stability of Cournot revisited“, Journal of Economic
Theory, 23, 749 - 752.
Seade, J. (1982) “On the sign of the optimum marginal income tax“, Review
of Economic Studies, 49, 637 - 643.
Seade, J. (1985) “Pro…table cost increases“, Warwick Economic Research
Paper, No. 260.
Sen, A.K. (1973) On Economic Inequality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sen, A.K. (1976) “Poverty: an ordinal approach to measurement“, Econo-
metrica, 44, 219 - 231.
Sen, A.K. (1977) “On weights and measures“, Econometrica, 45, 1539 -
1572.
Sen, A.K. (1979) “Issues in the measurement of poverty“, Scandinavian
Journal of Economics, 81, 285 - 307.
Sen, A.K. (1986) “Social choice theory“ in K.J. Arrow and M.D. Intriligator
(eds.) Handbook of Mathematical Economics, Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Seneca, J.J. and M.K. Taussig (1971) “Family equivalence scales and per-
sonal income tax exemptions for children“, Review of Economics and Statistics,
53, 253 - 262.
522 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Shell, K. (1971) “Notes on the economics of in…nity“, Journal of Political


Economy, 79, 1002 - 1011.
Sheshinski, E. (1972a) “Relation between a social welfare function and the
Gini index of inequality“, Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 98 - 100.
Sheshinski, E. (1972b) “The optimal linear income tax“, Review of Economic
Studies, 39, 297 - 302.
Sheshinski, E. (1978) “A model of social security and retirement decisions”,
Journal of Public Economics, 10, 337 - 360.
Sheshinski, E. and Y. Weiss (1981) “Uncertainty and optimal social security
systems”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 96, 189 - 206.
Shorrocks, A.F. (1980) “The class of additively decomposable inequality
measures“, Econometrica, 48, 613 - 625.
Shorrocks, A.F. (1983) “Ranking income distributions“, Economica, 50, 3 -
17.
Shorrocks, A.F. (1984) “Inequality decompositions by population subgroups“,
Econometrica, 52, 1369 - 1385.
Shoven, J.B. and J. Whalley (1972) “A general equilibrium calculation of
the e¤ects of di¤erential taxation of income from capital in the U.S.”, Journal
of Public Economics, 1, 281 - 321.
Simons, H.C. (1938) Personal Income Taxation, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Smith, A. (1776) An Enquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of
Nations, London: Metheun.
Smith, A. (1981) “The informal economy“, Lloyds Bank Review, 45 - 61.
Smith, A. (1982), “Intergenerational transfers as social insurance”, Journal
of Public Economics, 19, 97 - 106.
Smith, A. (1983) “Tax reform and temporary ine¢ciency“, Journal of Public
Economics, 20, 265 - 270.
Spence, M. (1977) “Nonlinear prices and welfare“, Journal of Public Eco-
nomics, 8, 1 - 18.
Spicer, M.W. and S.B. Lundstedt (1976) “Understanding tax evasion“, Pub-
lic Finance, 31, 295 - 305.
Srinivasan, P.V. (1989) “Redistributive impact of “optimal“ commodity taxes“,
Economics Letters, 30, 385 - 388.
Srinivasan, T.N. (1973) “Tax evasion: a model“, Journal of Public Eco-
nomics, 2, 339 - 346.
Starret, D.A. (1972) “Fundamental nonconvexities in the theory of external-
itites“, Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 180 - 199.
Stern, N.H. (1976) “On the speci…cation of models of optimum income tax-
ation.“, Journal of Public Economics, 6, 123 - 162.
Stern, N.H. (1987) “The e¤ects of taxation, price control and government
contracts in oligopoly and monopolistic competition”, Journal of Public Eco-
nomics, 32, 133 - 158.
Stiglitz, J.E. (1969a) “The e¤ects of income,wealth, and capital gains taxa-
tion on risk-taking“, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 83, 262 - 283.
523

Stiglitz, J.E. (1969b) “A re-examination of the Modigliani-Miller Theorem”,


American Economic Review, 59, 784 - 793.
Stiglitz, J. E. (1973), “Taxation, corporate …nancial policy, and the cost of
capital”, Journal of Public Economics, 2, 1 - 34.
Stiglitz, J.E. (1974) “On the irrelevance of corporate …nancial policy”, Amer-
ican Economic Review, 64, 851 - 866.
Stiglitz, J.E. (1976) “The corporation tax”, Journal of Public Economics, 5,
303 - 311.
Stokey, N.L. and R.E. Lucas with E.C. Prescott (1989) Recursive Methods
in Economic Dynamics, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Stone, R. (1954) “Linear expenditure systems and demand analysis: an ap-
plication to the pattern of British demand“, Economic Journal, 64, 511 - 527.
Sugden, R. (1984) “Reciprocity: the supply of public goods through volun-
tary contributions“, Economic Journal, 94, 772 787.
Sugden, R. (1985) “Consistent conjectures and voluntary contributions to
public goods: why the conventional theory does not work“, Journal of Public
Economics, 27, 117 - 124.
Svensson, L.G. and J.W. Weibull (1986) “An upper bound on optimal income
taxes“, Journal of Public Economics, 30, 165 - 181.
Sweeney, R.J. (1988) Wealth E¤ects and Monetary Theory, New York: Basil
Blackwell.
Taggart, R.A. (1980) “Taxes and corporate capital structure in an incom-
plete market“, Journal of Finance, 35, 645 - 659.
Takayama, A. (1985) Mathematical Economics, Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
Takayama, N. (1979) “Poverty, income inequality, and their measures: Pro-
fessor Sen’s axiomatic approach reconsidered“, Econometrica, 47, 747 - 758.
Theil, H. (1967) Economics and Information Theory, Amsterdam: North-
Holland.
Thompson, L.H., (1983) “The social security reform debate”, Journal of
Economic Literature, 21, 1425 - 1467
Townsend, P. (1979) Poverty in the United Kingdom, London: Penguin.
Tuomala, M. (1985) “Simpli…ed formulae for optimal linear income taxa-
tion“, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 87, 668 - 672.
Tuomala, M. (1990) Optimal Income Tax and Redistribution, Oxford: Claren-
don Press.
Varian, H.R. (1980) “Redistributive taxation as social insurance“, Journal
of Public Economics, 14, 49 - 68.
Varian, H.R. (1984) “Price discrimination and social welfare“, American
Economic Review, 75, 870 - 875.
Varian, H.R. (1992) Microeconomic Theory, New York: Norton.
Veall, M.R. (1986) “Public pensions as optimal social contracts”, Journal of
Public Economics, 31, 237 - 251.
Venables, A.J. (1986) “Production subsidies, import tari¤s and imperfectly
competitive trade“, in: Greenaway, D. and P.K.M. Tharakan (eds.), Imperfect
Competition and International Trade, Sussex: Wheatsheaf.
524 CHAPTER 16. REFERENCES

Vickrey, W. (1964) “Discussion“, American Economic Review, Papers and


Proceedings, 59, 88 - 92.
Virmani, A. (1989) “Indirect tax evasion and production e¢ciency“, Journal
of Public Economics, 39, 223-237.
von Neumann, J. and O. Morgernstern (1953) Theory of Games and Eco-
nomic Behaviour, Third Edition, Princeton: Princeton University press.
Walras, L. (1874) Elements d’Economie Politique Pure, Lausanne: L. Cor-
baz. English translation by W. Ja¤e (1954), Elements of pure economics, Lon-
don: Allen and Unwin.
Warr, P.G. (1983) “The private provision of a pure public good is indepen-
dent of the distribution of income“, Economics Letters, 13, 207 - 211.
Weber, S. and H. Wiesmeth (1991) “The equivalence of core and cost share
equilibria in an economy with public goods“, Journal of Economic Theory, 54,
180 - 199.
Weil, P. (1987) “Love thy children; re‡ections on the Barro debt neutrality
theorem”, Journal of Monetary Economics, 19, 378 - 391.
Weitzman, M.L. (1974) “Prices vs. quantities“, Review of Economic Studies,
41, 477 - 491.
Weymark, J.A. (1979a) “Generalised Gini inequality indices“, Discussion
Paper No. 79-12, Department of Economics, University of British Columbia.
Weymark, J.A. (1979b) “A reconciliation of recent results in optimal taxa-
tion theory“, Journal of Public Economics, 12, 171 - 189.
Weymark, J.A. (1981) “Undominated directions of tax reform“, Journal of
Public Economics, 16, 343 - 369.
Wilson, J.D. (1991a) “Optimal public good provision in the Ramsey tax
model: a generalization“, Economics Letters, 35, 57 - 61.
Wilson, J.D. (1991b) “Optimal public good provision with limited lump-sum
taxation“, American Economic Review, 81, 153 - 166.
Yamada, M. (1990) “An analysis of optimal taxation with tax evasion“,
Public Finance, 45, 470 - 490.
Yitzhaki, S. (1974) “Income tax evasion: a theoretical analysis“, Journal of
Public Economics, 3, 201 - 202.
Yohe, G.W. (1978) “Towards a general comparison of price controls and
quantity controls under uncertainty“, Review of Economic Studies, 45, 229 -
238.
Young, D. (1982) “Voluntary purchase of public goods“, Public Choice, 38,
73 - 86.

You might also like