Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Predicate Logic

Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 33

MIT Lecture 5

Predicate logic

Attique Ur Rehman
Lecturer BZU Lahore

attiquere@gmail.com

Propositional logic: limitations


Propositional logic: the world is described in terms of
elementary propositions and their logical
combinations
Typically statements:
refer to objects, their properties and relations.
Elementary
But these are not explicitly represented in the propositional
logic
Example:
John is a UPitt student.
John

a Upitt student

object

a property

Objects and properties are hidden in the statement, it is


not possible to reason about them

Propositional logic: limitations


(1) Statements that hold for many objects must be enumerated
Example:
John is a CS UPitt graduate John has passed cs441
Ann is a CS Upitt graduate Ann has passed cs441
Ken is a CS Upitt graduate Ken has passed cs441

Solution: make statements with variables
x is a CS UPitt graduate x has
cs441
passed

Propositional logic: limitations


(2) Statements that define the property of the group of objects
Example:
All new cars must be registered.
Some of the CS graduates graduate with honor.
Solution: make statements with quantifiers
Universal quantifier the property is satisfied by all
members of the group
Existential quantifier at least one member of the group
satisfy the property

Predicate logic
Remedies the limitations of the propositional logic
Explicitly models objects and their properties
Allows to make statements with variables and
them
quantifylogic:
Predicate
Constant models a specific object
Examples: John, France, 7
Variable represents object of specific type (defined by the
universe of discourse)
Examples: x, y
(universe of discourse can be people, students, numbers)
Predicate - over one, two or many variables or constants.
Represents properties or relations among objects
Examples: Red(car23), student(x), married(John,Ann)

Predicates
Predicates represent properties or relations among
objects
A predicate P(x) assigns a value true or false to each x
depending on whether the property holds or not for x.
The assignment is best viewed as a big table with the
variable substituted for objects from the universe of
discourse

Example:
Assume Student(x) where the universe of discourse are people
Student(John) . T (if John is a student)
Student(Ann) . T (if Ann is a student)
Student(Jane) .. F (if Jane is not a student)

Predicates
Assume a predicate P(x) that represents the statement:
x is a prime number
Truth values for different x:
P(2)
T
P(3)
T
P(4)
F
P(5)
T
P(6)
F
All statements P(2), P(3), P(4), P(5), P(6) are propositions

But P(x) with variable x is not a proposition

Compound statements in predicate logic


Compound statements are obtained via logical connectives
Examples:
Student(Ann) Student(Jane)
Translation: Both Ann and Jane are students
Proposition: yes.
Country(Sienna) River(Sienna)
Translation: Sienna is a country or a river
Proposition: yes.
CS-major(x) Student(x)
Translation: if x is a CS-major then x is a student
Proposition: no.

Quantified statements
Predicate logic lets us to make statements about groups of
objects
To do this we use special quantified expressions
Two types of quantified statements:
universal
Example: all CS Upitt graduates have to pass
cs441
the statement is true for all graduates
existential
Example: Some CS Upitt students graduate with honor.
the statement is true for some people

Universal quantifier
Quantification converts a propositional function
a
intoproposition by binding a variable to a set of values from the
universe of discourse.
Example:
Let P(x) denote x > x - 1.
Is P(x) a proposition? No. Many possible substitutions.
Is x P(x) a proposition? Yes. True if for all x from the
universe of discourse P(x) is true.

Universally quantified statements


Predicate logic lets us make statements about groups of objects
Universally quantified statement
CS-major(x) Student(x)
Translation: if x is a CS-major then x is a student
Proposition: no.

x CS-major(x) Student(x)
Translation: (For all people it holds that) if a person is a
CS-major then she is a student.
Proposition: yes.

Existentially quantified statements


Statements about groups of objects
Example:
CS-Upitt-graduate (x) Honor-student(x)
Translation: x is a CS-Upitt-graduate and x is an honor
student
Proposition: no.
x CS-Upitt-graduate (x) Honor-student(x)
Translation: There is a person who is a CS-Upitt-graduate
and who is also an honor student.
Proposition: yes.

Summary of quantified statements


When x P(x) and x P(x) are true and false?
Statement

When true?

When false?

x P(x)

P(x) true for all x

x P(x)

There is some x for P(x) is false for all


which P(x) is true. x.

There is an x
where P(x) is false.

Suppose the elements in the universe of discourse can be


enumerated as x1, x2, ..., xN then:
x P(x) is true whenever P(x1) P(x2) ... P(xN) is true
x P(x) is true whenever P(x1) P(x2) ... P(xN) is true.

Translation with quantifiers


Sentence:
All Upitt students are smart.
Assume: the domain of discourse of x are Upitt students
Translation:
x Smart(x)
Assume: the universe of discourse are students (all students):
x at(x,Upitt) Smart(x)
Assume: the universe of discourse are people:
x student(x) at(x,Upitt) Smart(x)

Translation with quantifiers


Sentence:
Someone at CMU is smart.
Assume: the domain of discourse are all CMU affiliates
Translation:
x Smart(x)
Assume: the universe of discourse are people:
x at(x,CMU) Smart(x)

Translation with quantifiers


Assume two predicates S(x) and P(x)
Universal statements typically tie with implications
All S(x) is P(x)
x ( S(x) P(x) )
No S(x) is P(x)
x( S(x) P(x) )
Existential statements typically tie with conjunctions
Some S(x) is P(x)
x (S(x) P(x) )
Some S(x) is not P(x)
x (S(x) P(x) )

Nested quantifiers
More than one quantifier may be necessary to
the
capture meaning of a statement in the predicate logic.
Example:
Every real number has its corresponding negative.
Translation:
Assume:
a real number is denoted as x and its negative as y
A predicate P(x,y) denotes: x + y =0
Then we can write:
x y P(x,y)

Nested quantifiers
More than one quantifier may be necessary
to meaning of a statement in the predicate
logic.
Example:
There is a person who loves everybody.
Translation:
Assume:
Variables x and y denote people
A predicate L(x,y) denotes: x loves y
Then we can write in the predicate logic:
x y L(x,y)

capture the

Order of quantifiers
The order of nested quantifiers matters if quantifiers are of
different type
xy L(x,y) is not the same as yx L(x,y)
Example:
Assume L(x,y) denotes x loves y
Then: xy L(x,y)
Translates to: Everybody loves somebody.
And: y x L(x,y)
Translates to: There is someone who is
loved
The meaning of the two is different.

by everyone.

Order of quantifiers
The order of nested quantifiers does not matter if quantifiers
are of the same type
Example:
For all x and y, if x is a parent of y then y is a child of x
Assume:
Parent(x,y) denotes x is a parent of y
Child(x,y) denotes x is a child of y
Two equivalent ways to represent the statement:
x y Parent(x,y) Child(y,x)
y x Parent(x,y) Child(y,x)

Translation exercise
Suppose:
Variables x,y denote people
L(x,y) denotes x loves y.
Translate:
x L(x,Raymond)
Everybody loves Raymond.
Everybody loves somebody.
xy L(x,y)
There is somebody whom everybody loves. yx L(x,y)
There is somebody who Raymond doesn't love.

yL(Raymond,y)

There is somebody whom no one loves.


y x L(x,y)

Negation of quantifiers
English statement:
Nothing is perfect.
Translation: x Perfect(x)
Another way to express the same meaning:
Everything is imperfect.
Translation: x Perfect(x)
Conclusion: x P (x) is equivalent to x P(x)

Negation of quantifiers
English statement:
It is not the case that all dogs are fleabags.
Translation: x Dog(x) Fleabag(x)
Another way to express the same meaning:
There is a dog that is not a fleabag.
Translation: x Dog(x) Fleabag(x)
Logically equivalent to:
x ( Dog(x)
Fleabag(x) )
Conclusion: x P (x) is equivalent to x P(x)

Negation of quantified statements


(aka DeMorgan Laws for quantifiers)
Negation
x P(x)
x P(x)

Equivalent
x P(x)
x P(x)

Theorems and proofs


The truth value of some statements about the world is obvious
and is easy to assign
The truth of other statements may not be obvious,
. But it may still follow (be derived) from known facts
about
To the
show
the truth value of such a statement following from other
world
statements we need to provide a correct supporting argument
- a proof
Problem:
It is easy to make a mistake and argue the support incorrectly.
Important questions:
When is the argument correct?
How to construct a correct argument, what method to
use?

Theorems and proofs


Theorem: a statement that can be shown to be true.
Typically the theorem looks like this:
(p1 p2 p3 pn ) q
Premises (hypotheses)

conclusion

Example:
Fermats Little theorem:
If p is a prime and a is an integer not divisible by p,
then: a p 1 1 mod p

Theorems and proofs


Theorem: a statement that can be shown to be true.
Typically the theorem looks like this:
(p1 p2 p3 pn ) q
Premises (hypotheses)

conclusion

Example:
Premises (hypotheses)
Fermats Little theorem:
If p is a prime and a is an integer not divisible by p,
then: a p 1 1mod p
conclusion

Formal proofs
Proof:
Provides an argument supporting the validity of the statement
Proof of the theorem:
shows that the conclusion follows from premises
may use:
Premises
Axioms
Results of other theorems
Formal proofs:
steps of the proofs follow logically from the set of premises and
axioms

Formal proofs
Formal proofs:
show that steps of the proofs follow logically from the set of
hypotheses and axioms
hypotheses

conclusion

+
axioms

In this class we assume formal proofs in the propositional logic

Rules of inference
Rules of inference: logically valid inference patterns
Example;
Modus Ponens, or the Law of Detachment
Rule of inference
p
p q q

Given p is true and the implication p q is true then q is true.

Rules of inference
Rules of inference: logically valid inference patterns
Example;
Modus Ponens, or the Law of Detachment
Rule of inference
p
p q q
implicat
ion
p q is true then q is true.
Given p is true and the
p
False
False
True
True

q
False
True
False
True

pq
True
True
False
True

Rules of inference
Rules of inference: logically valid inference patterns
Example;
Modus Ponens, or the Law of Detachment
Rule of inference
p
p q
q
p q is true then q is true.
Given p is true and the implicat
ion
pq
p
False
False
True
True

q
False
True
False
True

True
True
False
True

Rules of inference
Rules of inference: logically valid inference patterns
Example;
Modus Ponens, or the Law of Detachment
Rules of inference
p
p q q

Given p is true and the implication p q is true then q is true.


Tautology Form: (p (p q)) q

You might also like