Guia II 1cuatr2015 FINAL
Guia II 1cuatr2015 FINAL
Guia II 1cuatr2015 FINAL
DEPARTAMENTO DE ECOLOGÍA, GENÉTICA Y EVOLUCIÓN
FACULTAD DE CIENCIAS EXACTAS Y NATURALES
UNIVERSIDAD DE BUENOS AIRES
1° CUATRIMESTRE 2015
GUÍA Nº 2
BIOGEOGRAFIA HISTORICA
ESPECIACIÓN
EVOLUCIÓN Y DESARROLLO (EVODEVO)
MACROEVOLUCIÓN
EVOLUCIÓN HUMANA
REPASO 2° PARCIAL
Cronograma 1º Cuatrimestre 2015
Fecha Tema Teórica Fecha Tema TP
Teórica TP
Mi 18/3 Introducción
Vi 20/3 Historia del pensamiento evolutivo
Mi 25/3 Variabilidad genética Ju 26/3 Historia del pensamiento evolutivo I
Vi 27/3 Genética de Poblaciones I Ma 31/3 Historia del pensamiento evolutivo II
Mi 1/4 Genética de Poblaciones II Ju 2/4 Feriado
Vi 3/4 Feriado Ma 7/4 Genética de Poblaciones I
Mi 8/4 Genética de Poblaciones III Ju 9/4 Genética de Poblaciones II
Vi 10/4 Teoría Neutralista Ma 14/4 Genética de Poblaciones III
Mi 15/4 Plasticidad Fenotípica Ju 16/4 Teoría Neutralista I
Vi 17/4 Arquitectura Genética Ma 21/4 Teoría Neutralista II
Mi 22/4 Filogenia I Ju 23/4 Filogenia I
Vi 24/4 Filogenia II Ma 28/4 Filogenia II
Mi 29/4 Filogenia III Ju 30/4 Filogenia III
Vi 1/5 Feriado Ma 5/5 Repaso
Mi 6/5 Repaso Ju 7/5 Libre
Viernes 8/5 1º Parcial Teórico - Práctico
Mi 13/5 Teoría y Realidad de Especie Ma 12/5 Libre
Vi 15/5 Especiación I Ju 14/5 Libre
Mi 20/5 Especiación II Ma 19/5 Biogeografía histórica
Vi 22/5 Especiación III Ju 21/5 Especiación I
Mi 27/5 Especiación IV Ma 26/5 Especiación II
Vi 29/5 Evo Devo Ju 28/5 Especiación III
Mi 3/6 Macroevolución Ma 2/6 Evo Devo I
Vi 5/6 Adaptación Ju 4/6 Evo Devo II
Mi 10/6 Evolución del Sexo Ma 9/6 Macroevolución I
Vi 12/6 Evolución Humana I Ju 11/6 Macroevolución II
Mi 17/6 Evolución Humana II Ma 16/6 Evolución Humana I
Vi 19/6 Evolución Humana III Ju 18/6 Evolución Humana II
Mi 24/6 Repaso Ma 23/6 Evolución Humana III
Vi 26/6 Libre Ju 25/6 Repaso
Ma 30/6 Libre
Miércoles 1/7 2º Parcial Teórico - Práctico
Lunes 13/7 Recuperatorio 1º Parcial
Jueves 16/7 Recuperatorio 2º Parcial
3
4
MÓDULO V:
BIOGEOGRAFÍA
HISTÓRICA
5
6
INTRODUCCIÓN GENERAL
Ana Liza Tropea
El trabajo práctico a continuación constituye el inicio del segundo bloque temático de la
materia en el que se estudiarán los procesos que modelaron la diversidad biológica por encima del
nivel poblacional. Para ello, no sólo se requieren los conceptos estudiados anteriormente
(procesos microevolutivos) sino que también es necesario introducir nuevos elementos para lograr
comprender el surgimiento de las especies, sus patrones de variabilidad genética, su distribución
geográfica y temporal y, sus relaciones de parentesco (nivel macroevolutivo) como resultados de
un largo proceso histórico, único pero a la vez contingente. En particular, el concepto de tiempo
geológico es de vital importancia para el estudio de la historia de la vida en la Tierra, muy
diferente a la escala temporal generacional en la que se enmarcan los estudios microevolutivos.
En este nuevo contexto, es interesante destacar cómo, para inferir aquellos procesos que
ocurrieron en el pasado y construir escenarios evolutivos, se deben estudiar los correspondientes
patrones observables en el presente.
Como una primera aproximación a esta nueva mirada del mundo vivo, y previo a la lectura
del módulo, le proponemos la lectura del siguiente material y lo invitamos a reflexionar sobre las
preguntas a continuación:
S.J. Gould. “Los signos insensatos de la historia” en El pulgar del Panda (capítulo 2). Ed. Crítica.
1994. Pp.24‐30.
1. ¿Por qué la evolución es una ciencia histórica? ¿Cuáles son las preguntas que se formula? ¿Qué
metodología/s utiliza? ¿Cuál es el estatus epistemológico de las inferencias sobre el pasado
evolutivo?
2. ¿Qué son los patrones y los procesos en el marco de la biología evolutiva? ¿A qué hace
referencia el autor con la frase “Las rarezas, en términos del presente, son las señas de identidad
de la historia”? Sintetice el ejemplo de las tortugas presentado por el autor.
3. ¿Qué tipo de información, distinta a la conocida por ud. hasta el momento, se utiliza para inferir
el pasado evolutivo de las especies, familias u otros clados?
4. ¿Por qué se suele afirmar que la historia evolutiva ocurrida es “uno de muchos caminos
posibles”?
7
8
9
10
11
12
INTRODUCCIÓN A LA
BIOGEOGRAFÍA HISTÓRICA
Alexandra M. Gottlieb
Objetivos
1‐ Conocer el desarrollo histórico de las ideas en Biogeografía.
2‐ Familiarizarse con los conceptos utilizados por esta disciplina.
3‐ Aplicar los conocimientos adquiridos en el planteo de hipótesis que expliquen a través de procesos
evolutivos, los patrones de distribución geográfica observados.
Introducción
La Biogeografía es una disciplina histórica que estudia la distribución de los seres vivos en
el tiempo y el espacio, e incluye temáticas como Geología, Geografía y Biología.
El padre de la nomenclatura binomial, C. Linneo (1707‐1778), intentó explicar las causas de
la distribución geográfica de los organismos siguiendo, en su tradición creacionista y fijista, el
relato bíblico del Jardín del Edén. Ciertos autores reconocen en el Conde de Buffon (1707‐1788),
opositor al sistema linneano, los comienzos de la Biogeografía. Fue su sistema alternativo de
clasificación lo que le permitió a Buffon agrupar los animales de acuerdo a su geografía y
organizarlos en faunas. Además, fue Buffon quien introdujo el concepto de centros de origen
aunque asociado al creacionismo.
El botánico A. P. de Candolle (1778‐1841), en 1820 reconoció dos enfoques en la
investigación biogeográfica: el ecológico y el histórico. Si bien antiguamente estos eran dos
enfoques excluyentes, en la actualidad se reconoce que todo patrón biogeográfico es el resultado
de la combinación de ambos tipos de procesos. La Biogeografía Ecológica analiza patrones de
distribución a nivel local, de poblaciones o de especies, teniendo en cuenta procesos de
adaptación al ambiente y las relaciones entre dichas poblaciones o especies. La Biogeografía
Histórica se ocupa de estudiar a escala global, cómo los procesos históricos que suceden a través
de millones de años (v.g.: la tectónica de placas, los movimientos orogénicos, los procesos
macroevolutivos, etc.) afectan los patrones de distribución de especies y de taxones superiores.
Los datos biogeográficos fueron muy importantes en el desarrollo de las ideas evolutivas
de C. R. Darwin (1809‐1882) y de A. R. Wallace (1823‐1913). En su libro “Viaje de un naturalista
alrededor del mundo” (1831‐1835), Darwin se cuestiona acerca de los patrones de distribución de
plantas y animales, e interpreta los fósiles como restos de los antecesores de los organismos vivos.
Para Darwin, el clima y las barreras geográficas condicionan y limitan la distribución actual de los
seres vivos. Más tarde, Darwin dedicó un capítulo de su “Origen…” (1859) a explicar muchos
hechos biogeográficos (como por ejemplo el aislamiento de Australia y la evolución de los
marsupiales), al mismo tiempo que el pasado fósil de los organismos actuales fue tratado en otro
capítulo de dicha obra. Wallace, gran naturalista inglés contemporáneo a Darwin, contribuyó
significativamente a la Biogeografía con su libro “La Distribución Geográfica de los Animales”
(1876). Darwin y Wallace consideraban que las especies se originaban en un centro a partir del
cual algunos individuos se dispersaban al azar y posteriormente evolucionaban por selección
natural. Esta visión fue rebatida por Lyell y Hooker, entre otros, ya que consideraban poco
probable la dispersión a larga distancia a través de barreras amplias. En cambio, sostenían que las
especies se habrían distribuido a través de grandes puentes terrestres y continentes, ahora
13
sumergidos. La tradición de Darwin –Wallace tuvo sus defensores más prominentes en el genetista
E. Mayr (1904‐2005) y el paleontólogo G. G. Simpson (1902‐1984), entre muchos otros.
Entre las décadas de 1950 y 1960, el paradigma dominante en Biogeografía era el
paradigma dispersalista debido principalmente a la influencia de Simpson, y a que muchos
biólogos ignoraban conceptos geológicos como el de Deriva Continental (luego la Tectónica de
Placas). Justamente fue esta teoría la que dio sustento a la visión vicariante de la distribución
biológica, opuesta al dispersalismo, antes mencionado. No obstante, Simpson distinguió la
dispersión por medio de corredores, puentes filtro y rutas al azar (o “sweepstakes”). Así, los
animales pueden desplazarse libremente en ambas direcciones a través de corredores, y en
consecuencia, las regiones conectadas tendrían una gran similitud faunística. Los puentes filtro
constituían un medio más selectivo para la dispersión, ya que sólo ciertas clases de animales
podría atravesarlo y en una dirección. Las rutas al azar son aquellas que son cruzadas
fortuitamente por algunos organismos al ser arrastrados por las corrientes, o al estar adheridos a
otros organismos, o simplemente al estar sobre un tronco flotante.
En 1958 el botánico L. Croizat (1894–1982) planteó que las barreras geográficas
evolucionaron conjuntamente con las biotas 1 , y que las áreas disyuntas 2 constituyen relictos de
las distribuciones ancestrales. Croizat desarrolló el método denominado panbiogeografía para
reconstruir biotas ancestrales, poniendo énfasis en el análisis de los patrones de distribución
comunes de taxones animales y vegetales, y no en la capacidad de dispersión de cada uno de ellos.
Este fue uno de los primeros enfoques que consideró a la vicarianza como un proceso
fundamental en la Biogeografía Histórica (ver más adelante).
Por su parte, W. Hennig (1913‐1976) postuló la existencia de una relación estrecha entre
las especies y el espacio que ocupa cada una de ellas. Con el desarrollo de la Cladística y su
aplicación a la Biogeografía, surgió la disciplina conocida como Biogeografía Cladística. Este
enfoque emplea cladogramas para inferir la historia biogeográfica de un grupo, en particular, el
interés de esta corriente reside en el estudio de la historia de grupos monofiléticos en el tiempo y
el espacio.
Deriva Continental y Tectónica de Placas
El meteorólogo A. Wegener (1880‐1930) propuso en 1915 su teoría de la Deriva
Continental, la cual sostenía que los continentes se deslizaban lentamente sobre la superficie de la
corteza terrestre debido a la fuerza de las mareas. Si bien Wegener no fue el primero en notar que
muchas líneas de la costa (como América del Sur y África) parecieran encajar juntas como un
rompecabezas, fue uno de los primeros en proponer que los continentes pudieron haber estado
ensamblados juntos en algún punto en el pasado formando el supercontinente Pangea (ver Fig.
1). Esta propuesta fue apoyada por paleontólogos que encontraron fósiles de especies muy
similares entre continentes ahora separados por una gran distancia geográfica (v.g.: restos de la
planta fósil Glossopterys en África, Sudamérica, Australia e India; restos de fósiles de un reptil del
Paleozoico, Mesosaurus, en Brasil y África). Las ideas de Wegener fueron muy polémicas porque
carecían de una explicación mecánica para el movimiento o deriva de los continentes. Muchos
geólogos anti‐movilistas creían que el planeta pasaba por ciclos de calentamiento y enfriamiento,
lo que causaba la dilatación y contracción de las masas de la tierra. Los movilistas, en cambio,
apoyaban las ideas de Wegener. Aunque la teoría de la Deriva Continental fue posteriormente
refutada, sentó las bases para el desarrollo de la Tectónica de Placas.
1
Biotas: conjuntos de taxones que habitan un área geográfica determinada.
2
Areas disyuntas: áreas sin continuidad geográfica.
14
FIGURA 1. Esquema cronológico en el que se muestran las masas de tierra emergidas en el Pérmico,
Triásico, Jurásico, Cretácico y en la época actual, producto del movimiento de las placas tectónicas.
En los años 1960 una serie de sismómetros instalados para vigilar una prueba nuclear,
reveló que los terremotos, los volcanes, y otros procesos geológicos activos, se alineaban a lo
largo de cinturones alrededor del mundo, definiendo los bordes de placas tectónicas. Los estudios
paleomagnéticos mostraron que el Polo Norte Magnético vagó aparentemente sobre todo el
globo. Esto fue interpretado como que, o bien las placas se movían, o bien el Polo Norte era móvil.
Excepto los períodos de revocaciones magnéticas en los cuales los Polos Norte y Sur se invierten,
el Polo Norte se encuentra fijo. Los geólogos y los geofísicos descubrieron que la corteza terrestre
en el fondo oceánico, tenía registro de estas revocaciones, lo que constituiría una prueba de que la
litosfera 3 tuvo que estar en movimiento. La evidencia geológica, geofísica y sismológica fortaleció
la idea de la tectónica de placas.
Hacia finales de la década de 1960, la comunidad científica aceptó a la Tectónica de Placas
como un paradigma explicativo coherente acerca de la dinámica del planeta y su interacción con
los ecosistemas. Esta teoría explicó por ejemplo, la existencia de marsupiales en Sudamérica y
Australia considerando que durante el Eoceno (hace 40 millones de años, Ma) (ver Fig. 2) estas
regiones se encontraban cercanas entre sí y con la Antártica, que para aquel entonces poseía un
clima cálido.
3
Litosfera: capa superficial de la Tierra sólida formada por corteza y manto.
15
La ruptura y separación (es decir, el cambio de posición) de las masas de tierra hace que
esas regiones estén sometidas a cambios de clima y aislamiento y, en consecuencia, a cambios de
presión de selección sobre los organismos y divergencia. Contrariamente, las fusiones de
continentes y las migraciones bidireccionales homogeneizan áreas y producen un aumento en la
competencia por el espacio y los recursos. La disposición de las tierras continentales, el
surgimiento de islas, la apertura y cierre de plataformas marinas y oceánicas, etc., afectaron
profundamente la distribución y la historia de los seres vivos.
FIGURA 2. Esquema cronológico de los Eones, Eras, Períodos y Épocas geológicas de la Tierra
(escala cronoestratrigráfica).
Áreas de distribución, áreas de endemismo y centros de origen
Desde sus orígenes la Biogeografía intenta comprender por ejemplo, por qué algunos
taxones poseen distribución más amplia que otros; o cómo explicar las distribuciones disyuntas de
los miembros de un mismo taxón; o por qué un taxón es más diverso en ciertas regiones, etc. Por
distribución disyunta se entiende aquella donde los miembros de un mismo taxón habitan
localidades muy distantes, sin una continuidad geográfica entre ellas.
Responder estas preguntas requiere delimitar las áreas de estudio; y para ello se emplean
dos conceptos fundamentales: área de distribución y área de endemismo. El área de distribución
es la región total dentro de la cual se distribuye una unidad taxonómica cualquiera. Se relaciona
con factores como el clima, el hábitat, la competencia intra e interespecífica, etc. Un parámetro
importante del área de distribución es su carácter continuo o discontinuo (área disyunta). La
16
distribución de una especie evolutivamente “nueva” es naturalmente continua, pero los cambios
climáticos estocásticos, las epidemias y/o la competencia ecológica pueden conducir a la
fragmentación de su distribución y a la posterior divergencia de las poblaciones aisladas
(especiación alopátrica). La delimitación de las áreas de distribución de un taxón suele ser una
simplificación de la distribución de los organismos en la naturaleza debido a que, muchas veces
éstas representan las localidades donde el taxón ha sido encontrado o coleccionado. Los mapas de
distribución pueden elaborarse a partir de las áreas de distribución para cualquier nivel de la
jerarquía linneana (v.g.: especies, familias, órdenes, etc.). Mediante la elaboración de mapas de
distribución, la Tierra fue dividida en ocho regiones biogeográficas para la fauna y otras seis
regiones para la flora. Por otro lado, los límites a la distribución están determinados por los
atributos ecológicos (nicho fundamental, nicho realizado) e históricos de un taxón. Así una especie
puede ser ecológicamente apta para vivir en un lugar pero estar ausente porque nunca migró y/o
logró establecerse. Los cambios climáticos ocurridos en el pasado, como las glaciaciones, trajeron
como consecuencia que el rango de distribución de muchas especies del Hemisferio Norte se
desplazara más hacia el sur por migración. Alternativamente, también pudo haber ocurrido que el
rango de distribución se contrajera y se desplazara más hacia el sur por la muerte de los individuos
que habitaban las zonas más frías (sin migración).
Más controvertida es la delimitación del área de endemismo ya que existe cierta
dependencia de la escala de estudio y, a su vez, no existe un consenso en la comunidad científica
acerca de su definición. Nelson y Platnick (1981) definieron áreas de endemismo como áreas
relativamente pequeñas que presentan un número significativo de especies que no están
presentes en ninguna otra área. Más tarde, Platnick (1991) la definió como aquella área delimitada
por las distribuciones congruentes de dos o más especies. Una especie es endémica (es un
endemismo) cuando se presenta en un área muy restringida. Un endemismo puede encontrase en
el área donde se originó, en cuyo caso decimos que es un neoendemismo. Un paleoendemismo es
una especie cuya distribución restringida representa sólo una pequeña parte de otra distribución
anterior más amplia, generalmente lejos del área en la que surgió evolutivamente. Decimos en
este caso que la especie ocupa un área relicta o relictual.
Los organismos se dispersan desde su centro de origen tanto como se lo permitan sus
habilidades y las condiciones del medio. Los datos del registro fósil son esenciales para determinar
los centros de origen, si bien existen numerosos criterios para su delimitación. Entre los criterios
más empleados se pueden mencionar: (i) aquel donde actualmente se encuentra la mayor
diversidad del taxón; (ii) la mayor cantidad de individuos; (iii) los individuos de mayor tamaño; (iv)
la mayoría de los genes dominantes, etc.
Extinción, dispersión y vicarianza
La Tierra ha permanecido en un estado de flujo durante 4.000 Ma. A lo largo del tiempo, la
abundancia y diversidad de linajes varió abruptamente. Los linajes evolucionan y radian
empujando a otros linajes hacia la extinción, o hacia una existencia relictual en refugios protegidos
(o microhábitats adecuados). Se han distinguido tres procesos principales en el tiempo‐espacio
que pueden modificar la distribución espacial de los organismos: las extinciones, las dispersiones y
la vicarianza.
La extinción biológica es la desaparición de un taxón y representa la terminación de su
linaje o clado. La transformación de una especie ancestral en otra derivada se denomina
pseudoextinción.
17
En términos generales, la diversidad ha aumentado desde el comienzo de la vida. Sin
embargo, el aumento se ha interrumpido numerosas veces por las extinciones en masa. Estas
implican una reducción de la diversidad biológica debida a la muerte de todos los individuos de
una población local, especie o taxón de rango superior, aproximadamente al mismo tiempo. Las
extinciones masivas están seguidas de periodos de radiación en los que evolucionan nuevas
especies que ocupan los nichos vacantes. Por tanto las extinciones moldean el patrón general de la
macroevolución. Muchos investigadores consideran que sobrevivir a una extinción en masa es,
mayormente, una cuestión de suerte o una lotería, y que las reglas que rigen estos periodos son
diferentes a las de los tiempos “normales”. Es así que la contingencia jugaría un gran papel en los
patrones de la macroevolución. En clases posteriores veremos cómo la modificación ambiental
puede ser el impulsor de más cambio evolutivo.
El vulcanismo, el impacto de asteroides o cometas, o una reacción en cadena de estos
procesos, originaron el colapso de los ecosistemas y el consecuente cambio climático (v.g.:
glaciaciones, descenso o aumento de temperaturas, oscilaciones en el nivel de los mares, etc.). Se
supone que estos procesos han participado como causas de muchas extinciones.
Los datos paleontológicos indican que las extinciones masivas han sido periódicas, algunas
más extensas que otras. Son eventos “rápidos” en términos geológicos, es decir, se encuentran en
el orden de miles a decenas de miles de años. Como ejemplo, podemos mencionar que la biota del
Mesozoico tuvo su declive y caída durante 1 o 2 Ma, esta cifra representa tan sólo el 0,55% de los
180 Ma que duró el Mesozoico. Se han registrado numerosas extinciones, aunque cinco de ellas
son las más destacadas debido a su intensidad en exterminación. La primera extinción (hace unos
440 Ma) marca el final del Período Ordovícico (ver Fig. 2). El cambio climático se caracterizó por
ser severo y acompañado de un enfriamiento global repentino, constituyéndose como la causa
próxima de esta extinción que ocasionó cambios profundos principalmente en la vida marina, pues
en ese tiempo no existen evidencias de vida terrestre. Se calcula que aproximadamente el 25% de
las familias de organismos marinos desapareció. La segunda extinción (hace unos 370 Ma) cerca
del final del Período Devónico, podría haber sido el resultado de cambios climáticos globales. Aquí,
llegaron a su fin el 19% de las familias. La tercera extinción (hace unos 245 Ma) se produjo hacia el
final del Período Pérmico (ver Figs. 1 y 2) y se la considera la mayor extinción de la historia de la
vida en la Tierra (por lo menos hasta ahora!). Evidencias recientes sugieren que el impacto de un
asteroide, similar al evento ocurrido al final del Cretácico, puede haber sido la causa de esta
extinción. En esa época también se produjo un descenso mundial del nivel del mar. Se estima que
desapareció el 96% de todas las especies existentes (50‐54% de todas las familias). La cuarta
extinción (hace unos 210 Ma), al final del Período Triásico, tuvo lugar poco después de la
evolución de los dinosaurios y los primeros mamíferos; sus causas aún son desconocidas. Se
estima que el 23% de las familias de organismos vivientes desapareció. La quinta extinción (hace
unos 65 Ma) al final del Período Cretácico (en el límite entre los periodos Cretácico y Terciario o
Límite K/T), es quizás la más famosa y la más reciente de las extinciones. Se ha llegado al consenso
de que este evento fue causado por una colisión (o múltiples) entre la Tierra y un asteroide,
generando un desequilibrio ambiental. Sin embargo, algunos geólogos apuntan a una cadena de
eventos físicos que perturbaron severamente los ecosistemas. Aquí, se perdió el 17% de las
familias, y marcó el fin de todos los linajes de dinosaurios, excepto el de las aves, y la desaparición
de los amonites marinos, así como de muchas otras especies del espectro filogenético y de todos
los hábitats. Con la erradicación de los dinosaurios, los mamíferos, confinados principalmente a
nichos insectívoros nocturnos, radiaron ocupando los nichos vacantes. Actualmente, la alteración
humana de la ecósfera está provocando una extinción en masa global, considerada por algunos
científicos como la sexta extinción.
18
Como mencionamos, la dispersión y la vicarianza (ver Fig. 3) fueron originalmente
consideradas como dos explicaciones mutuamente excluyentes para dar cuenta de la distribución
disyunta de los grupos de organismos. Actualmente se acepta que ambos procesos ocurren en la
naturaleza.
DISPERSION VICARIANZA
A
B xyz C p
Poblaciones ancestrales y barreras Población ancestral
B A C
x y p p
z
Dispersión sobre las barreras Aparece una barrera
B A C A B
x
x z p1 q
y z
Diferenciación o divergencia de las poblaciones derivadas
B A C B
A q1 q2
x1 y p1
x2 z2
z1 p2
r C
Más diferenciación
A B A A C B B C A A
x1 x2 y z1 z2 q1 q2 r p1 p2
FIGURA 3. Explicación de la distribución disyunta. Diferencias en el marco de la Biogeografía Histórica entre
los procesos de dispersión y vicarianza. Modificado de Crisci et al. (2000) y Avise (2000).
NOTA: las letras mayúsculas indican áreas de distribución; las letras minúsculas indican taxones.
La explicación por dispersión señala que el/los ancestro/s común/es de los taxones con
distribución disyunta se dispersaron por migración a partir de centros de origen atravesando
barreras geográficas preexistentes, hacia donde se encuentran hoy los descendientes. Por lo
tanto, la barrera geográfica debería ser más antigua que la disyunción.
19
La explicación por vicarianza sostiene que el ancestro común de los taxones con
distribución disyunta, se encontraba ampliamente distribuido en un área que comprendía las
áreas actualmente disyuntas, las cuales representan restos o relictos de una distribución ancestral.
La población ancestral se divide en subpoblaciones por el surgimiento de una barrera geográfica
infranqueable (v.g.: el levantamiento de una cadena montañosa, la ruptura de continentes, la
subdivisión de cuerpos de agua, etc.). Por lo tanto, la barrera no podría ser más antigua que la
disyunción. Los eventos de vicarianza afectan conjuntamente a todos los taxones que se
distribuyen en un área, mientras que la dispersión afecta por lo general, a uno o a unos pocos
taxones.
En general, cuando distintos grupos taxonómicos muestran distribuciones correlativas o
congruentes, éstas fueron probablemente producidas por vicarianza. En cambio, si las diversas
especies se dispersaron independientemente de su centro de origen entonces no tendrán una
distribución congruente. Bajo vicarianza, la filogenia de los taxones se corresponde con el orden
de separación de las áreas, mientras que bajo la hipótesis de dispersión las áreas y los taxones
pueden mostrar relaciones históricas más variadas (Fig. 3).
Métodos de la Biogeografía
La reconstrucción que la Biogeografía Histórica hace de los eventos del pasado puede
abordarse desde tres perspectivas diferentes: (i) desde los grupos individuales (taxones); (ii) desde
las áreas de endemismo y; (iii) desde las biotas.
La mayoría de los métodos biogeográficos emplean cladogramas como herramienta básica
de inferencia de relaciones históricas. Los biogeógrafos testean sus ideas mediante el estudio de
los patrones de división (cladogénesis) de un grupo de organismos y su correspondencia, o no, con
la historia geológica y geográfica de la región en la que vivía dicho grupo. Para esto, construyen un
cladograma de áreas (ver Fig. 3) reemplazando los nombres de los taxones terminales por las
áreas de endemismo donde se distribuyen. Este procedimiento es simple si cada taxón es
endémico de un único área o si cada área posee un único taxón. Cuando este no es el caso, es
decir cuando los taxones están ampliamente distribuidos o cuando existen distribuciones
redundantes y/o hay áreas ausentes, deben aplicarse ciertas reglas metodológicas para resolver
los cladogramas. Como mencionamos anteriormente, si la cladogénesis fue causada por procesos
geológicos (vicarianza), la filogenia del grupo reflejará la secuencia definida de eventos tectónicos.
Al examinar cladogramas de otros taxones de las mismas áreas, éstos deberían ser congruentes
(deberían coincidir en el orden de ramificación). Este análisis sólo es válido cuando se trabaja con
grupos monofiléticos, lo que implica que la Biogeografía se sustenta en clasificaciones naturales.
La metodología general puede resumirse como sigue:
1. obtención del cladograma del grupo en estudio;
2. proyección del cladograma sobre un mapa de áreas de distribución;
3. individualización del centro de origen del grupo mediante la aplicación de reglas
específicas;
4. formulación de una hipótesis sobre la biogeografía del grupo;
5. confrontación de la hipótesis con la geología del área y otras fuentes de datos
independientes.
20
Existen al menos nueve metodologías básicas. Algunos de estos métodos asumen que sólo
operó el proceso de dispersión, mientras que otros métodos consideran también a la vicarianza
como proceso que modeló el patrón de distribución observado. Al mismo tiempo, ciertos métodos
reconstruyen la historia de biotas; otros reconstruyen la distribución de biotas individuales o la
historia de las áreas; mientras que otros trabajan sobre biotas y áreas conjuntamente. Respecto al
rango taxonómico de aplicación, la Filogeografía es la única metodología que se aplica al nivel
poblacional. Las metodologías restantes trabajan a nivel de especies o de taxones de rango
superior.
La Biogeografía Cladística basa sus inferencias en el supuesto que establece que los
miembros más primitivos de un taxón se hallan más cercanos al centro de origen. A su vez, la
hipótesis nula contra la cual se testean los resultados es que la distribución de grupos
taxonómicos es determinada por eventos de vicarianza dentro del rango de la especie ancestral;
mientras que generalmente la hipótesis alternativa propone que la distribución observada está
determinada por dispersión.
Lectura adicional (optativa)
En la página de la materia encontrará los siguientes trabajos:
1‐ Webb DS (2006) The Great American Biotic Interchange: patterns and processes. Ann. Missouri Bot.
Gard. 93: 245–257.
2‐ Marshall LG, Webb DS, JJ Sepkoski Jr, Raup DM (1982) Mammalian evolution and the Great American
Interchange. Science 215: 1351‐1357.
Bibliografía Consultada
Avise JC. (2000). Phylogeography. The history and formation of species. Harvard Univ. Press. London
England.
Beardsley PM, Getty SR & P Numedahl (2009) Explaining Biogeographic data: Evidence for Evolution. The
American Biology Teacher 71 (2): 5‐9.
Crisci JV, Katinas L, Posadas P. (2000). Introducción a la teoría y práctica de la Biogeografía Histórica.
Sociedad Argentina de Botánica. Pp.169
Damborenea MC & Cigliano MM. (2006). Cladística y sus aplicaciones en Biogeografía Histórica y co‐
evolución (capítulo 13). En: Sistemática Biológica: fundamentos teóricos y ejercitaciones. Lanteri
AA, Cigliano MM Eds. 203‐219. Universidad Nacional de La Plata.
Eldregde N. (1989) Life Pulse: Episodes from the story of the fossil record. FOF Publication. NY, UK, pp. 246.
Fernández‐López SR (2000). La naturaleza del registro fósil y el análisis de las extinciones. Coloquios de
Paleontología 51: 267‐280.
Nelson GJ, Platnick NI (1981) Systematics and biogeography: cladistics and vicariance. Columbia Univ. Press,
NY.
Platnick NI (1991) On areas of endemism. Australian Systematic Botany 4: 11‐12.
Ridley M. (2004). Evolutionary Biogeography (Capítulo 17). En: Evolution. 3rd Ed. Blackwell Publishing.
21
DESARROLLO DEL TRABAJO PRÁCTICO
PRIMERA PARTE
Como se mencionó anteriormente, la noción de “profundidad del tiempo geológico”
constituye un eje fundamental sobre el que se articulan las inferencias o reconstrucciones del
pasado evolutivo de las especies o, taxones de orden superior. Sin embargo, resulta muy difícil
incorporar dicha escala de tiempo dado que excede ampliamente los rangos temporales
compatibles con la historia humana y, más aun, con la esperanza de vida de nuestra especie.
En un esfuerzo por hacer comprender la velocidad relativa con que se sucedieron las
diversas etapas desde que se formó el Universo, Carl Sagan, el conocido astrónomo de la
Universidad de Cornell, en su libro Los Dragones del Edén, ha incluido lo que él llama "El
Calendario Cósmico": supongamos que pudiéramos comprimir los quince mil millones de años
que han transcurrido desde la Gran Explosión hasta nuestros días en un sólo año. Así, cada mil
millones de años corresponderían a 24 días del Calendario Cósmico, en tanto que un segundo del
año cósmico equivaldría a 475 vueltas de la Tierra alrededor del Sol. A esta escala, la evolución del
universo transcurre a una gran velocidad. Sin embargo, para poder completar la historia de la vida
en nuestro planeta y el desarrollo de la historia en esta perspectiva, Sagan dividió este calendario
en tres etapas, las fechas precámbricas, el mes de diciembre y finalmente el último día del año
cósmico (ver figura 4).
El Calendario Cósmico fue elaborado a partir de la información más confiable con que
contamos hoy en día y es posible sin lugar a duda que admita modificaciones a medida que se
profundice el conocimiento científico. Sin embargo, no cambiará la conclusión de que somos parte
de un proceso de evolución que se inició con el origen mismo del Universo, además, como dice
Sagan, la conciencia de que las grandes hazañas del hombre ocupan apenas unos cuantos
segundos de este primer año.
1.1. A partir de la figura 4, destaque los principales hechos de interés para la biología evolutiva.
¿En qué porción del tiempo han ocurrido dichos eventos?
1.2. ¿En qué momento surge la vida? ¿Y nuestra especie?
22
Figura 4: Calendario Cósmico, Carl Sagan
23
SEGUNDA PARTE
Usted es un investigador interesado en realizar un estudio biogeográfico de las faunas de
mamíferos de América del Norte y del Sur de los últimos 12 millones de años.
2.1. ¿En qué período geológico se enmarca este estudio? ¿Cómo se ubicaban las placas
continentales de la actual América en dicho período? Utilice las figuras 1 y 2 de la
introducción teórica y la figura 5 de la parte práctica.
2.2. A partir del esquema de la figura 6, complete la tabla 1 con:
‐ el número de registros de fósiles de los linajes indicados en cada uno de los 6 sitios;
‐ la sumatoria del número de registros y la datación aproximada del fósil más antiguo, para
cada una de las dos regiones, tanto América del Norte como América del Sur.
3. Responda el siguiente cuestionario:
3.1. Considerando el rango de 11 a 4 millones de años antes del presente (AP), indique las
familias de mamíferos endémicas para Norteamérica y Sudamérica.
3.2. Indique el tiempo aproximado de arribo, o introducción, de animales endémicos de
Sudamérica en Norteamérica y el tiempo de arribo de los linajes endémicos sudamericanos
en Norteamérica. ¿En qué datos se basó?
3.3. ¿Cómo explicaría el arribo de animales endémicos sudamericanos a América del Norte (y
viceversa)?
3.4. Examine el registro del linaje de los rinocerontes. ¿En qué rango de tiempo hay
evidencias de estos organismos? ¿Qué inferencias puede hacer acerca de la historia de los
rinocerontes? Proponga hipótesis alternativas.
3.5. ¿Cuál es la evidencia fósil más temprana del linaje de los mamuts? ¿Cómo explicaría la
ocurrencia repentina de mamuts en el registro fósil? ¿Hay evidencias de estos organismos en
Sudamérica?
3.6. Para un tiempo geológico dado, ¿considera que cada sitio muestra todos los animales
que se desarrollaron allí? Justifique.
FIGURA 5. Formación del istmo de Panamá.
24
FIGURA 6. Esquema de registros paleontológicos de seis secciones geológicas. Los fósiles de 12 familias de mamíferos identificados por sus
iniciales, se presentan en función de la edad geológica (Ma, millones de años).
12
25
TABLA 1.
Camélido (Cm)
Cánido (C)
Capibara (Cp)
Equido (E)
Félido (F)
Gliptodonte (Gl)
Mamut (M)
Opósum (O)
Perezoso (P)
Puercoespín (Pu)
Rinoceronte (R)
26
Concepción diagramática de Simpson (1940) sobre la migración a través de puentes.
(Traducción: Los puentes NO: 1) permiten que solo pase un tipo de animal, 2) permiten
viajar en una única dirección y 3) transportan fauna completamente desbalanceada.)
27
Ejercitación adicional
Entre la fauna del archipiélago de Los Cocos se encuentran los caracoles terrestres del género
Gouldiana. Estos caracoles están presentes en casi la totalidad de las islas que conforman el
archipiélago pero se discute cómo llegaron a poblarlas.
Sabiendo:
‐ Que la distribución de las especies reconocidas en el archipiélago es la informada en la Figura 1.
‐ Que algunas especies de caracoles presentan bandas coloreadas es su concha.
‐ Que todas las especies de caracoles son vegetarianos.
‐ Que la filogenia más reciente y completa del grupo es la informada en la Figura 2.
‐ Que durante la última glaciación el nivel del mar estaba 100 metros por debajo del nivel actual, y
todas las islas conformaban una masa terrestre denominada Antiguos Cocos.
Responda:
a. ¿Qué proceso biogeográfico considera compatible con el patrón de distribución de especies
entre islas? Justifique.
b. ¿Qué evidencia o prueba adicional aportaría mayor soporte a su hipótesis?
c. ¿Cuál es el modelo geográfico de especiación que explicaría la evolución de las diferentes
especies de caracoles entre las distintas islas? Justifique brevemente.
d. Utilice un modelo alternativo para explicar la divergencia y especiación dentro de las islas y
enuncie las condiciones necesarias para que este modelo pueda aplicarse.
e. Bajo el modelo que Ud. postuló en c): ¿cómo ocurrió la divergencia genética entre las especies?
¿Cuántos genes y qué tipo de caracteres fueron los involucrados?
28
Figura 1: Archipiélago de Los Cocos
Figura 2: Reconstrucción filogenética a partir de secuencias de genes nucleares y mitocondriales.
29
30
MÓDULO VI:
ESPECIACIÓN
31
32
SEMINARIO I: REALIDAD Y CONCEPTOS DE ESPECIES
Marcela Rodriguero & Abel Carcagno
En este seminario se discutirá la existencia de las especies como entidades reales y válidas
como objeto de estudio. Además, se reflexionará sobre los distintos conceptos de especie y
los criterios, principalmente metodológicos, ligados a su adopción.
Nota: Se recomienda especialmente la lectura crítica del trabajo “The meaning of species
and speciation: a genetic perspective”, de Alan Templeton (versión traducida al español),
disponible en http://www.ege.fcen.uba.ar/materias/evolucion/material.htm
Parte I: Realidad de las especies
• Hey J. 2001. The mind of the species problem. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 16 (7): 326‐
329.
• Hey J., Waples R.S., Arnold M.L., Butlin R.K. & Harrison R.G. 2003. Understanding and
confronting species uncertainty in biology and conservation. Trends in Ecology and
Evolution 18 (11): 597‐603. (Fragmento).
1‐ Para comenzar a discutir: ¿cree Ud. en la realidad de las especies?
2‐ ¿En qué consiste el “problema de las especies”?
3‐ De acuerdo a lo discutido en el item anterior, en las clases teóricas y a lo que le dicta el
sentido común… ¿cuáles son los posibles significados que pueden otorgarse a la palabra
“especie”?
4‐ De acuerdo a lo discutido en los item 2 y 3 anterior, ¿qué clases de ambigüedad pueden
desprenderse de las definiciones de especie enunciadas y cómo se podría confrontar este
problema?
5‐ ¿Cuál es el resultado del proceso evolutivo según Hey (2001) y de qué manera podría
abordarse su estudio? ¿Qué problemas podrían surgir al encarar un trabajo de esta
magnitud?
6‐ ¿Cree que existe alguna correspondencia entre las especies y los grupos evolutivos?
Fundamente su respuesta.
Parte II: Conceptos de especie
• Gross L. (2007) Who needs sex (or males) anyway? PLoS Biology 5(4): e99.
• de Meeûs T., Michalakis Y. & Renaud F. (1998) Santa Rosalia revisited : or why are there so
many kinds of parasites in “the garden of earthly delights”? Parasitol. Today 14(1): 10‐
13.
33
• “Species in Time”, fragmento del miniensayo “The Species concept”, de Richard Cowen
(Departamento de Geología de la Universidad de California Davis).
• Schlick‐Steiner B.C., Seifert B., Stauffer C., Christian E., Crozier R.H., Steiner F.m. 2007.
Without morphology, cryptic species stay in taxonomic crypsis folowing discovery.
Trends Ecol. Evol. 22(8): 391‐392.
7‐ ¿Cuál es la principal característica de la clase Bdelloidea y cómo repercute en la aplicación
del CBS a este taxón?
8‐ De acuerdo al Concepto Biológico de Especie… ¿cuántos grupos esperaría encontrar
dentro de la clase? ¿Cómo podría explicar entonces la ocurrencia de discontinuidades dentro
de Bdelloidea?
9‐ ¿Qué otro concepto podría explicar a las categorías existentes dentro de esta clase?
Discuta los potenciales problemas de cada alternativa propuesta.
10‐ Enuncie al menos dos características que dificulten la aplicación del Concepto Biológico
de Especie a los organismos parásitos.
11‐ De acuerdo a los problemas analizados y a los conceptos que Ud. conoce… ¿cuáles
aplicaría a las discontinuidades identificadas dentro de los grupos de organismos que
exhiben un modo de vida parasitario? (Como antes, considere las posibles desventajas).
12‐ Teniendo en cuenta la diversificación de los organismos estrictamente asexuales y de los
parásitos, por ejemplo… ¿Considera al sexo como a una condición sine qua non para el
origen de los grupos evolutivos?
13‐ ¿Cuál es el problema que encaran los paleontólogos al incluir el factor tiempo en el
estudio de la diversidad biológica y cómo redunda esto en la aplicación del Concepto
Biológico de Especie a organismos extintos?
14‐ ¿Cómo solucionaría Ud. estos inconvenientes? (No olvide discutir ventajas y desventajas
de sus propuestas).
15‐ ¿Cómo repercute la existencia de las especies crípticas en el concepto de especies
morfológico? ¿Puede nombrar otro inconveniente para la aplicación de este concepto?
Preguntas unificadoras
16‐ De acuerdo a lo discutido, está en condiciones de contestar la siguiente pregunta:
¿Cuáles son las dificultades que impiden la adopción de un único concepto de especie?
17‐ ¿Cree que algún día se arribará a una “solución radical al problema de las especies”
(Ghiselin 1974)?
18‐ Explique la siguiente afirmación: “… [como el Concepto Biológico de Especie] se enfoca
en el resultado y no en el proceso, ha resultado perjudicial para los estudios de los
mecanismos de especiación…”.
19‐ ¿Qué fuerza/s mantiene/n la cohesión dentro de cada “especie”, y a la vez permite/n
que estas se conserven como entidades discretas? ¿Qué concepto de especie hace alusión a
esta cuestión?
34
326 Opinion TRENDS in Ecology & Evolution Vol.16 No.7 July 2001
http://tree.trends.com 0169–5347/01/$ – see front matter © 2001 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. PII: S0169-5347(01)02145-0
35
Opinion TRENDS in Ecology & Evolution Vol.16 No.7 July 2001 327
theory15, but, for those needing the single best By taking this approach, we are not acting like
definition, that is beside the point. scientists. We are acting like some philosophers,
It is best to be plain about these and other similar particularly Aristotle, who addressed and supposedly
efforts to find a definition that dispels the species solved questions of the natural world by giving words
problem. Descriptive definitions are not great containers to intuited essences; that is, by making up definitions18.
of knowledge and they are not great tools for arbitrating
the natural world. Individually, descriptive definitions An untapped source of information
are but small bundles of information or theory, and if Fortunately, we can learn rather a lot from our
they seem to be of any great aid in arbitration, it is unscientific behavior. Not only do we see in it a sure sign
because they are backed up by a far larger fund of that we lack information about the species problem, but
knowledge. In short, if you have got the knowledge we also find a place in which to look for that information.
then the definitions are the easy part and fall readily That place is within ourselves, in the ways that our
into place. If your knowledge is incorrect or incomplete, minds handle questions about species. To be clear, I am
no amount of wordplay will set it right. Those who have saying that one source of new information and insight,
tried to puzzle out the species problem by focusing on to which we should turn if we are to solve the species
definitions are missing something, and that something problem, is our own behavior. Note that several authors
is bigger and more important than any definition. have concluded that we demand too much of species
But how could our knowledge, upon which the species concepts and that some of our demands are inherently
debates have been built, be missing something? Do not contradictory2,19–22. It is but a short step (and a great leap)
evolutionary biologists know of genetics, fossils, to cast such arguments in terms of the question: what is
geography and the vast organismal diversity that exists it about our minds and our motives that mislead us?
on our planet? Does not every evolutionary biologist Once we are introspective in this way, we
know, from theory and mountains of evidence, that immediately obtain one clear answer to the question
evolution gives rise to organismal groups, within which ‘what are species?’. In our minds and in our language,
individuals are similar and closely related, and between species are categories. That is to say, the names for
which divergence can and does accrue? But, despite species and the usage of those names take an entirely
these intellectual riches, we must recognize that our conventional syntactical role that is taken by all
knowledge of species has not been sufficient to resolve categories. Just as ‘planet’ is the name of a category,
the species problem. Our obdurate debates16 and our and appears as a predicate in sentences (e.g. ‘The
misplaced ambitions for ‘species’ definitions are a slap Earth is a planet.’), so ‘polar bear’ is also a category
in the face – they forcefully remind us that there are and a frequent predicate in sentences. Whatever else
some things that we just do not know about or they are, categories are things in the mind and in our
understand sufficiently to describe them adequately17. language, and they are used for organizing our
The awkward juxtaposition of apparent ignorance and thoughts and language about organismal diversity.
seemingly complete knowledge can also be seen in one
of our most common modes of explanation. Consider the Taxa
now traditional method in which the nature of species and Of course, ‘species are categories’is just a starting point,
the meaning of ‘species’ are addressed first by summing but it is one that helps us to tap into a large tradition of
up the inadequate state of affairs, followed by an exertion inquiry on the connections between categories in the
of pure reason. There are dozens, if not hundreds, of mind and things in the real world17,23–26. Categories are
elegant articles that employ this approach. These articles motivated by recurrent observations about the world27.
are permeated with the presumption that new argument, Humans are great observers of patterns of repetition,
and not new information, will settle the question. Species and we devise our categories as a response. These so-
pundits do not ask ‘what new information do we need?’. called ‘natural kinds’ are in our heads, but they are also
http://tree.trends.com
36
328 Opinion TRENDS in Ecology & Evolution Vol.16 No.7 July 2001
out there in the world, in some way. For example, frozen Fundamental conflicts
wispy crystals of water sometimes fall to earth in great Now let us compare and contrast the idea of a species
numbers and we identify them as snowflakes. The taxon with the idea of a species as an evolutionary
‘snowflake’category exists in our minds, but in some group. To begin with, these two meanings of ‘species’
sense it is also a feature of the world outside ourselves, a refer to things that are fundamentally and ontologically
world that is disposed to repeatedly generate individual dissimilar. To the extent that instances of either of them
falling wispy crystals of water. Each of the species that exist, they do so in very different ways. An evolutionary
we identify is a category, but it is also a natural kind that group is an entity, somewhat discrete in space and time,
exists as a pattern of recurrence in the world. We call and capable of changing and being acted upon30–34. It
these natural kinds ‘taxa’ and, whatever else they are, does not matter that its parts (individual organisms) can
there is no escaping the fact that we identify them first move around with respect to one another, and it does
on the basis of recurrent patterns that we find in nature. not matter that it is not entirely distinct and separate
What does it take to make such a species taxon? One from other such entities. Evolutionary groups share
answer is that it does not take much: given a simple these properties with all sorts of other entities, and the
observation of a few organisms that seem similar to one arguments about their ontology (the way they exist) are
another, and different from others, and a biologist is off fairly simple, at least compared with those for categories
and thinking about devising a new taxon. Another and taxa32. Whether natural kinds exist is an often-
answer is that it varies tremendously with the debated question, but even if they do, it is an altogether
observer. Not surprisingly, biologists cannot agree on different sort of existence than for individual entities35–37.
how distinct a seemingly new pattern must be to Another major difference between the two viewpoints
motivate a new named category. These lumper/splitter is the role that distinction plays in their existence. We
debates go round and round, much as they have for recognize and devise species taxa pretty much as a direct
hundreds of years. Consider the situation with birds, result of having perceived a seemingly distinct pattern of
which for people are probably the most observable recurrence. We devise taxa because they usefully serve
animals on the planet. Conventional classifications our drive to categorize things, and so their very existence
place the number of bird species worldwide at around (such as it is) goes hand-in-hand with their perceived
9000. But some feel that a proper evaluation would degree of distinction. By contrast, evolutionary groups
yield a count closer to 20 000 (Refs 28,29). exist regardless of our recognition of them, and they
So now we have one answer to ‘what are species?’. might or might not be distinct. Note that as much as
They are categories and, more particularly, they are the word ‘group’ can be taken to convey distinction, in
named natural kinds of organisms: taxa. We also fact the world is full of things that exist and are not at
know what causes them, and that they are the result all distinct. Some that we are familiar with are clouds,
of two processes: (1) the evolutionary processes that populations, and ecosystems. Since the early 20th
have caused biological diversity; and (2) the human century, evolutionary biologists have been well trained
mental apparatus that recognizes and gives names to in the many ways that evolving groups of organisms
patterns of recurrence. might not be distinct. Genes can be and are exchanged
at varying rates between such groups, and there are
Evolutionary groups myriad ways that levels of gene exchange can be
For many biologists, however, species taxa are entirely structured to create groups within groups38.
inadequate for many of the purposes for which we use Finally, consider our very different motivations
‘species’. These biologists are interested in the causes towards the different usages of ‘species’. Names of taxa
of species, not our mental contributions to taxa, but are among children’s very first words (not the technical
rather the evolutionary processes that create patterns jargon, of course, but words like ‘dog’and ‘bird’) and
of biodiversity. Of the many concepts listed by Mayden3, adult biologists employ taxa in exactly the same manner:
many either strongly imply or explicitly state that a that is, as named categories. Consider too that all
species is a group of related organisms, one that is human societies have taxa that are part of taxonomic
enjoined by evolutionary processes that go on within systems that share some remarkable similarities with
it, and that is separate from other groups because of each other and with those systems used by professional
the absence of shared evolutionary processes with biologists25,39. Surely humans have been devising and
those other groups (Box 1). It is these theoretical ideas using taxa ever since their ancestors evolved the capacity
of evolving groups that descend fairly directly from for language. If there is one thing at which our brains are
Darwin’s teachings, and they mark a drastic adept, it is recognizing and devising different kinds of
departure from purely categorical or taxonomic ideas organisms. But the idea of species as evolutionary groups
of species. But be sure to note the vagueness of these is in stark contrast to this categorical tradition that is
commonplace ideas of evolutionary groups. As much imbedded within our minds. The tradition of thinking of
as they are backed by strong theory, any attempt to species as evolutionary groups is only 140-years old, and
translate this theory into strict criteria for the it is knowledge that comes to a person late in life, at least
unequivocal identification of evolutionary groups compared with the knowledge of categories of organisms.
requires much work (and if the history of the species In short, we have two widely differing ways of
problem is any indication, is bound to fail). appreciating biological diversity17,21,33. We have the
http://tree.trends.com
37
Opinion TRENDS in Ecology & Evolution Vol.16 No.7 July 2001 329
ages-old instinct to categorize, and we have the modern different human observers will find different taxa. It is
tradition of scientific inquiry. Our instincts give us taxa, also useful to imagine a thought experiment of the taxa
but our inquires have only recently led us to understand that would be devised by an alien observer, by one who
evolutionary groups. The taxa are relatively easy to uses different senses and who operates on a different
find and invent, whereas the evolutionary groups are scale of observation.
difficult to study, for they are often truly indistinct (2) Real evolutionary groups need not be distinct, and
with fuzzy boundaries between groups, and the forces can overlap or be nested within one another, whereas
that conjoin them can be subtle. Research on a species, categories are created as a direct function of perceived
as an evolutionary group, requires study of the very distinction. Attempts to delimit evolutionary groups by
processes of direct and indirect interaction among the boundaries of the categories will cause some groups
organisms, including reproduction and competition, to be missed and others to be wrongly circumscribed.
that can cause those organisms to be a species. (3) Most importantly, we must keep in mind that the
evolutionary processes that caused the patterns that we
The causes of the species problem recognize, and which we use to form taxa, are processes
In addition to carrying conflicting ideas of species, we that acted long ago. As time passes, the wave front of
evolutionary biologists also try to do something else – evolutionary processes leaves behind strong patterns of
we try to find a way to have the taxa be the same as the similarity and differences among organisms. It is those
evolutionary groups. The two things are ontologically patterns that we use for the taxa, but the place where
different, but they can correspond when all those evolutionary groups exist is at that wave front – they are
organisms that we would place in a category also caused by the evolutionary processes that are going on
collectively and completely constitute an evolutionary right now. The patterns of similarity that we recognize
group. The human species is probably our most accessible are the remnants of former evolutionary groups that
example of a species taxon that also corresponds well to might have long since shifted and splintered.
an evolutionary group. In general, our taxa can serve as The species problem is caused by two conflicting
hypotheses of the organisms that constitute evolutionary motivations; the drive to devise and deploy categories,
groups. Evolutionary biologists are very familiar with and the more modern wish to recognize and understand
this mode of thought. However, we will fail in our studies evolutionary groups17. As understandable as it might be
if we forget the reasons why the two sorts of things that we try to equate these two, and as reasonable and
might have little correspondence with one another. correct as it might be to use taxa as starting hypotheses
(1) The patterns that we observe are a function of of evolutionary groups, the problem will endure as long
our own capacity for perception and judgment. as we continue to fail to recognize our taxa as inherently
Furthermore, there is no reason why our senses should subjective, and as long as we keep searching for a
be as subtle as all of nature. When we devise taxa, we magic bullet, a concept that somehow makes a taxon
are not objective, and we must keep in mind that and an evolutionary group both one and the same.
References pp. 28–59, Sinauer Associates University of Chicago Press
1 Mayr, E. (1982) The Growth of Biological Thought, 13 Cracraft, J. (1997) Species concepts in systematics 25 Berlin, B. (1992) Ethnobiological Classification,
Harvard University Press and conservation biology – an ornithological viewpoint. Princeton University Press
2 Stebbins, G.L. (1969) Comments on the search for a In Species: the Units of Biodiversity (Claridge, M.F. 26 Rosch, E. (1978) Principles of categorization. In
‘perfect system’. Taxon 18, 357–359 et al., eds), pp. 325–339, Chapman & Hall Cognition and Categorization (Rosch, E. and Lloyd,
3 Mayden, R.L. (1997) A hierarchy of species concepts: 14 Mayr, E. (1992) A local flora and the biological B.B., eds), pp. 28–48, Lawrence Arlbaum Associates
the denouement in the saga of the species problem. species concept. Am. J. Bot. 79, 222–238 27 Landesman, C. (1971) Introduction. In The Problem of
In Species: the Units of Biodiversity (Claridge, M.F. 15 Avise, J.C. and Wollenberg, K. (1997) Phylogenetics Universals (Landesman, C., ed.), pp. 3–17, Basic Books
et al., eds), pp. 381–424, Chapman & Hall and the origin of species. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 28 Graham, M. (1996) Birds in double trouble. Nature
4 de Queiroz, K. (1999) The general lineage concept U. S. A. 94, 7748–7755 380, 666–667
of species and the defining properties of the species 16 Wheeler, Q.D. and Meier, R., eds (2000) Species 29 Zink, R.M. (1996) Bird species diversity. Nature
category. In Species (Wilson, R.A., ed.), pp. 49–89, Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory: a Debate, 381, 566
MIT Press Columbia University Press 30 Ghiselin, M.T. (1966) On psychologism in the logic
5 Keller, E.F. and Lloyd, E.A. (1992) Keywords in 17 Hey, J. Genes Categories and Species, Oxford of taxonomic controversies. Syst. Zool. 15, 207–215
Evolutionary Biology, Harvard University Press University Press (in press) 31 Ghiselin, M.T. (1987) Species concept, individuality,
6 Wilhite, D. and Glantz, M.R. (1987) Understanding 18 Popper, K.R. (1962) The Open Society and its and objectivity. Biol. Philos. 2, 127–143
the drought phenomenon: the role of definitions. Enemies, Routledge and Kegan Paul 32 Ghiselin, M.T. (1997) Metaphysics and the Origin
In Planning for Drought (Wilhite, D. et al., eds), 19 Levin, D.A. (1979) The nature of plant species. of Species, State University of New York Press
pp. 11–27, Westview Press Science 204, 381–384 33 Hull, D.L. (1976) Are species really individuals?
7 Dracup, J.A. et al. (1980) On the definition of 20 Endler, J.A. (1989) Conceptual and other problems Syst. Zool. 15, 174–191
droughts. Water Resour. Res. 16, 297–302 in speciation. In Speciation and its Consequences 34 Hull, D.L. (1978) A matter of individuality. Philos.
8 Caplan, A.L. et al., eds (1981) Concepts of Health (Otte, D. and Endler, J.A., eds), pp. 625–648, Sci. 45, 335–360
and Disease, Addison–Wesley Sinauer Associates 35 Hacking, I. (1983) Representing and Intervening:
9 Mayr, E. (1942) Systematics and the Origin of 21 Hull, D.L. (1997) The ideal species concept – and Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural
Species, Columbia University Press why we cannot get it. In Species: the Units of Science, Cambridge University Press
10 Mayr, E. (1996) What is a species and what is not? Biodiversity (Claridge, M.F. et al., eds), pp. 357–380, 36 Dennett, D.C. (1991) Real patterns. J. Philos. 88,
Philos. Sci. 63, 262–277 Chapman & Hall 27–51
11 Cracraft, J. (1983) Species concepts and speciation 22 Heywood, V.H. (1998) The species concept as a 37 Haugeland, J. (1993) Pattern and being. In
analysis. Curr. Ornithol. 1, 159–187 socio-cultural phenomenon – a source of the Dennett and his Critics (Dahlbom, B., ed.),
12 Cracraft, J. (1989) Speciation and its ontology: the scientific dilemma. Theor. Biosci. 117, 203–212 pp. 53–69, Blackwell Science
empirical consequences of alternative species 23 Smith, E.E. and Medin, D.L. (1981) Categories and 38 Dobzhansky, T. (1950) Mendelian populations and
concepts for understanding patterns and Concepts, Harvard University Press their evolution. Am. Nat. 84, 401–418
processes of differentiation. In Speciation and its 24 Lakoff, G. (1987) Women, Fire, and Dangerous 39 Atran, S. (1990) Cognitive Foundations of Natural
Consequences (Otte, D. and Endler, J.A., eds), Things: What Categories Reveal About the Mind, History, Cambridge University Press
http://tree.trends.com
38
Review TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.18 No.11 November 2003 597
Recent essays on the species problem have emphasized species, but the problem endures with a steadily increas-
the commonality that many species concepts have with ing literature on how to define ‘species’. A recent listing of
basic evolutionary theory. Although true, such consen- species concepts found 24 in the modern literature [1] and
sus fails to address the nature of the ambiguity that is new books appear steadily [2 – 4].
associated with species-related research. We argue that In recent years, a recurring claim with regard to the
biologists who endure the species problem can benefit species problem is that most species concepts have strong
from a synthesis in which individual taxonomic species implicit similarities, and that most are consistent with the
are used as hypotheses of evolutionary entities. We dis- idea that species are evolving lineages or evolving
cuss two sources of species uncertainty: one that is a populations [1,3,5,6]. We agree with this consensus.
semantic confusion, and a second that is caused by the However, we remain concerned that it does little to
inherent uncertainty of evolutionary entities. The for- address the fundamental cause of the species problem,
mer can be dispelled with careful communication, which is the inherent ambiguity of species in nature. Here,
whereas the latter is a conventional scientific uncer- we focus directly on the nature of this ambiguity and
tainty that can only be mitigated by research. This review a modern synthesis under which species-related
scientific uncertainty cannot be ‘solved’ or stamped research and conservation efforts can proceed without
out, but neither need it be ignored or feared. suffering from, and without fear of, the ambiguity of
species.
For researchers, few ideals are as sought after as those of
the independent observer; preferably, a scientist should Background and synthesis
discover and transmit his or her story, and not be a part of Prominent in species debates are questions regarding the
it. But what if that cannot be arranged? In some fields, role played by human investigators in the creation of
most notably quantum physics and human behavioral species taxa, particularly with regard to taxonomic rank
research, observation per se can have a direct effect on
designations. Darwin argued that decisions to apply the
outcomes, so that studies must be designed to incorporate
taxonomic rank of species were sometimes arbitrary, and
those effects. Of course, research in these fields does not
that species are not different essentially from varieties [7].
come to a halt. Neither does research halt in other fields
Spurway drew upon the ways that animals learn to
where the impact of the observer cannot be avoided or
identify different kinds of organism to argue that species
ignored safely, but rather is addressed directly as part of
designations are caused by basic human instincts, and
the research program. Here, we argue that biological
that we could not expect to find a universally applicable
research on species will benefit from an explicit recog-
definition of ‘species’ [8]. Haldane supported this view [9],
nition of the inherent limitations that biologists experi-
ence as investigators of species. and it has been articulated more recently from different
Many evolutionary biologists, systematists and ecolo- directions by Levin [10] and Nelson [11]. Yet, these
gists struggle with the related questions of how to identify skeptics notwithstanding, the view has emerged since
species and how to define the word ‘species’. These Darwin that species have special properties that set them
persistent questions constitute what is known as the apart from taxa of other ranks, and that species are
‘species problem’. The problem is not new. Indeed, Darwin objective and real to some extent because of these
drew upon the persistence of wide taxonomic disagree- properties. Dobzhansky’s Genetics and the Origin of
ments to support his arguments for the evolution of Species portrayed species as real genetical and evolving
entities that could be studied with modern genetic
Corresponding author: Jody Hey (hey@biology.rutgers.edu). approaches [12]. Huxley’s The New Systematics [13] is
39
http://tree.trends.com 0169-5347/$ - see front matter q 2003 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.tree.2003.08.014
598 Review TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.18 No.11 November 2003
the historical touchstone for modern systematic research might be simply confirmed or rejected, although more
programs that see species not just as categories with typical outcomes are likely to be fuller descriptions of the
representatives in museums, but also as dynamic evolving evolutionary processes that occur among the organisms
entities that exist independently of human observers and that would be identified as members of a taxon. Some
of human-assigned categories [14,15]. species taxa can be expected to be highly explanatory as
These two ideas – that species are categories that are evolutionary hypotheses, in which case they are likely to
created essentially by the biologists who study them, and be affirmed by the discovery of additional characters that
that species are objective, observable entities in nature – are shared uniquely among the organisms assigned to the
have long been in conflict. On the one hand, we have taxon. At some point following research on these evol-
species taxa that have been identified traditionally on the utionary processes, a taxon might come to be paired with a
basis of distinctive characteristics. On the other hand, we full description of the population or populations that it
have an idea of a species as a kind of entity in nature, an represents, including the degrees of isolation and distinc-
evolutionary unit made up of related organisms that are tion that occur among populations. Also, the degree or
evolving together. Over the years, various authors have quality of correspondence between a taxon and its evolving
recognized this fundamental distinction [3,16 –22]. Yet, is counterparts might be used to devise more taxa as
it possible that these two perspectives on species can be necessary.
joined? That has been the intended purpose of some
popular species concepts, and much of the modern debate The ambiguity of species entities
over species concepts has been a struggle over how best to From a purely ontological perspective, entities are real
describe species in a way that preserves both the accepted things that have a location in space and time, and that can
taxonomic traditions and the modern understanding of be acted upon or can change [36]. Entities have a different
evolutionary processes. Both the Biological Species Con- kind of existence than do categories, such as taxa, which
cept of Mayr [23,24] and the Phylogenetic Species Concept have defining properties. To be clear, by way of a deliberate
of Cracraft [25,26] are intended to help biologists identify example, consider the species taxon Ursus maritimus
species taxa that are real evolutionary role players in (polar bear). The defining properties of this taxon were
nature. Neither view admits a distinction between species described first by Constantine Phipps [37]. Today, many
taxa and species as evolutionary entities. animals that we assign to this taxon live in zoos, but most
But, hidden partly in the debates over the nature of constitute a circumpolar arctic population, comprising
species lies a direct and complementary connection multiple connected regional populations; that is, an
between species as taxa and species as entities. The evolving entity [38]. Even if this entity were to disappear,
connection represents a conceptual linkage that circum- and the natural population of polar bears were to become
vents many aspects of the species problem and that leads extinct, the species taxon would still exist as a set of
directly to ways that research can proceed without species defining characteristics and would still have representa-
conflicts. To see this connection, consider that newly tives in museums or zoos.
devised species taxa serve as hypotheses that might be Species are but one kind of multi-organismal entity, and
supported by new data and that, notwithstanding the rule organisms can also be components of social groups within
of precedence, might require later revision. Growing species as well as parts of commensal interspecies
collections, improving methods of morphological analysis, assemblages. Biologists also recognize ecological entities
and the increasing use of ecological, behavioral and genetic that consist of many different kinds of organisms, and
data have moved biologists necessarily away from the view individual organisms are parts of ecosystems, both on very
of taxa as fundamentally static to a view in which species local and broad scales. To complete the point, we need not
taxa can be revised on the basis of increasing information be monistic with regard to species entities and so might
from diverse sources [13– 15,27,28]. This view, that our wish to consider different kinds of species entities as a
ideas regarding a particular species should be subject to function of how they arise and persist. Templeton [39]
examination in light of data from natural populations, has articulated two general processes that will cause a group of
also emerged in the population genetic literature [29,30]. organisms to evolve together: gene exchange and ecologi-
In particular, Templeton argues that population genetic cal equivalence (or demographic exchangeability). Both
data should be used to test whether populations do indeed processes, alone or together, can cause genetic drift and
exist as cohesive species [31]. adaptations to be shared by a group of organisms, and
These twin strands of thought on the hypothesis-testing cause that group to evolve cohesively and separately from
aspect of species designations, from the perspectives of other such groups.
both systematics and population genetics, lead to the idea Our perceptions of an evolving group of organisms will
that a species taxon can serve as a hypothesis of a species be least ambiguous for those taxa whose only representa-
as an evolutionary and ecological unit in nature [3,32– 35]. tives exist in a single, small distinct population (e.g. a
This synthesis draws directly upon the practice in species restricted to a single lake or mountain peak). But
systematics in which taxa are subject to revision, but, in even small populations that appear cohesive and well
addition, there is the idea that a species taxon presents a bounded in some respects might not be in others. The
general hypothesis that all existing organisms that would population of finches of the species taxon Geospiza fortis
be assigned to that taxon actually constitute a biological that lives on Isla Daphne Major in the Galapagos is not
entity in nature. separated completely from populations on other islands,
In principle, species taxa that are used as hypotheses neither is it completely separate from populations that are
http://tree.trends.com
40
Review TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.18 No.11 November 2003 599
general research protocol that is not hindered by some of The common assertions, that we must be able to both count
the traditional species-problem debates. Of course, the species and to distinguish species, are directly answerable:
method is not thereby made easy or simple. No synthesis (1) species taxa can be counted, and they are distinguished
can do that because species in nature are difficult subjects. in the course of their devising; whereas, (2) evolutionary
However, we can appreciate that the difficulty of studying entities will often be truly indistinct, and will sometimes
species is a conventional scientific difficulty; it is caused by not be countable strictly or distinguishable unambigu-
the need to devise and test hypotheses, just as in other ously no matter how thoroughly they are studied [34].
fields with difficult subjects.
The framework of treating species taxa as hypotheses of Identifying units for conservation
species entities leads us to distinguish those aspects of The contrast between species taxa and evolutionary
species uncertainty that are inherent to research and entities is stark when considering conservation. Species
discovery of biological diversity, and to set aside some taxa can often be preserved in the sense of having living
aspects of species-related debate that are avoidable. Two representatives by culturing organisms in zoos and
basic questions are inescapable. First, by what criteria botanical gardens; that is, by maintaining living counter-
shall species taxa be identified? For systematists, this parts to the taxon representatives that are kept in
question lies at the heart of species-concept debates museums. But if species taxa are to have representatives
[2,15,50,51]. However, when a taxon is to be a tool for the living in nature, then they must be part of evolving
study of evolutionary entities, then the question becomes populations. In recent decades, this simple realization of
the following: what criterion will aid best in the discovery the fundamental insufficiency of taxa as the focus of
of the locations, boundaries and properties of evolutionary conservation efforts has shifted those efforts towards
entities? Importantly, the answer might not be the same research on how best to conserve evolving populations [54].
for all kinds of organisms. For population-based conservation efforts to be effec-
The second question is when does one decide that there tive, goals must be articulated clearly both in terms of
is one, or more than one, evolving entity? Two kinds of what kinds of populations are to be conserved and in terms
answer come fairly readily. One is simply not to decide that recognize the inherent difficulties and ambiguities. To
whether or where to draw lines of demarcation, but rather appreciate how such apparently offsetting demands (for
to present the full picture that research has revealed, and conservation criteria that recognize inherent ambiguities)
to do so in its full complexity rather than to reduce that can be implemented, and to appreciate the issues raised by
complexity artificially. A second kind of resolution, which their application, we consider the entity-based idea of an
might be demanded because of practical concerns, is to evolutionary significant unit (ESU) [55– 58]. An ESU is a
make a decision regarding demarcations, while also population, or group of closely connected populations, that
recognizing the decision as an oversimplification belong to a species taxon. Furthermore, an ESU shows
demanded by the practical concerns. evidence of being genetically separate from other
The principal aspect of the species problem that is populations, and contributes substantially to the
avoided by our proposed synthesis is the traditional debate ecological or genetic diversity found within the species
over a ‘best’ species concept. Consider that if taxa are to taxon as a whole.
serve as hypotheses, then there are several common In recent years, the ESU concept has been applied
species concepts and associated taxonomic criteria that broadly to salmon populations on the west coast of the
could provide a good starting point for the study of USA, as well as to a variety of other species [58,59]. The
populations. In particular, the use of reproductive traits intent in defining salmon ESUs has been to identify
and the use of diagnostic characters are both well entities that are on largely independent evolutionary
motivated by evolutionary theory, and each is expected trajectories. Although it is problematic to predict which
to provide a rough guide to the presence of evolutionary ESUs will be important to the future evolution of the
units in nature [6]. This is not to say that one is as good as taxon, conservation of as many ESUs as possible should
another in a particular context, simply that each is minimize anthropogenic constraints on natural evolution-
justifiable in principle, and that it remains to inves- ary processes and maximize the probability that the taxon
tigators to make that justification for their particular and some of its populations will persist into the future.
subjects of research. However, this formulation provides no specific, quantitat-
A key inspiration of the species-concept debate is the ive standards and offers no guarantees that type II
often-described need for species-related clarity. These uncertainties will be resolved. Thus, several variations
appeals say in part that we need a common concept of of the ESU concept have been proposed, and the concept
species to handle the uncertainties that arise in species- has been criticized as being too broad [60], too narrow
related research. Although true in strictly systematic [61,62] or non-operational [52,63]. Two different kinds of
contexts, the same arguments have also been applied in approach have been suggested to address the apparent
reference to the study of evolving populations in nature vagueness of the ESU concept. One suggestion is that, for
[26,52,53]. However, no species concept or protocol can the purposes of efficiency, ESU status should be decided
remove the inherent difficulty and ambiguity of research using a uniform standard of genetic cohesiveness and
on evolving populations. The demarcation of two different uniqueness. For example, Moritz [60] suggested a specific
sources of species uncertainty leads to a fairly straightfor- genetic cutoff (based on mitochondrial DNA monophyly
ward parsing of conventional demands for species-related and nuclear gene differences) for conferring ESU status.
clarity into those that are tractable and those that are not. The obvious concern that application of that standard will
http://tree.trends.com
42
Review TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.18 No.11 November 2003 601
appear arbitrary in many applications, or capricious in the taxa as a strategy to serve conservation goals, or to shift
face of other kinds of evidence of cohesiveness and the rank of a taxon solely as a way to preserve biodiversity
uniqueness is perhaps answered by the considerable [71]. In other words, legitimate conservation concerns,
need for a readily applicable, if imperfect, yardstick. combined with a reliance on taxa as conservation units,
Given that mitochondrial DNA diversity will often be a can have the unfortunate consequence of shifting taxo-
poor indicator of demographic boundaries [64– 66], this nomic decisions away from biological criteria and towards
particular proposal might not be ideal. However, this does political or economic concerns.
not mean that some standardized method might not Second, the uncertainty of species entities is not
provide a reasonable balance between biological realism different in kind to that associated with other scientific
and the needs for efficiency. subjects. Importantly, many scientific pursuits have high
A different kind of suggestion is that the current ESU levels of uncertainty and also play a highly visible role in
criteria should be replaced by a single, better criterion that the formation of public policy. Consider droughts, for
would, inherently by its nature, dispel uncertainty. The example, which, as phenomena, are not circumscribed
principal claim of this sort is that ESUs should be groups easily, their intense environmental and financial impact
of individuals that share a unique character, or suite of notwithstanding. Meteorologists, hydrologists and policy
characters, that distinguish them from individuals of planners have worked to develop practical guidelines for
other ESUs [52,63]. In other words, an ESU should be drought identification, even as they debate how best to do
identified by the criteria used in one version of the so [72]. Consider as well the difficulties associated with
Phylogenetic Species Concept [67,68], not for reasons of medical diagnosis and the identification of health-risk
efficiency (which could also be claimed), but because such factors. Physicians must make judgment calls regularly in
criteria are inherently unambiguous indicators of real the care of their patients, and they must also provide
evolutionary entities. These proposals, which equate the public health guidelines that are as unambiguous as
presence of a disjunct pattern of characters with the possible, often in the face of substantial inherent
presence of an evolving population, have two limitations. ambiguity.
First, they assume accuracy on the part of taxonomic The question of how best to identify populations for
criteria and overlook the reasons why species taxa will conservation has much in common with questions of how
often be a poor guide for elucidating evolutionary entities. to identify droughts, and to prevent or treat disease, and
Second, by directly equating ESUs with species taxa they with other areas where imperfect scientific knowledge is
have nothing to offer to the question of how best to used to shape public policy. The choices of what to conserve
conserve diversity below the species level. must often be made with regard to populations that are not
In the case of Pacific salmon, the recognized species separate completely from others, or when information
taxa that are based on diagnostic characters are consider- regarding the relationships and degrees of distinction
ably more inclusive than ESUs that have been identified, among populations is very incomplete. Such decisions,
each of which is limited to the populations in a restricted although difficult because of the uncertainties that are not
geographic area [58]. For this species, taxa based on mitigated easily, are not different in kind from those
diagnostic characters appear to be too coarse a guide for decisions made in other contexts where scientists have
identifying evolutionary entities, which is not surprising imperfect knowledge or where nature does not present
given the highly structured populations of anadromous clear boundaries.
fish. In other contexts, it might happen that a strong focus
on diagnostic characters could lead to taxa that are less Prospects
inclusive than true evolutionary entities, either because of Biologists cannot hope to avoid or eradicate species
the vagaries of sampling or because of the near infinity of uncertainty. Whether such hope arises from a wish to
possible characters to examine [69]. ‘solve’ the species problem, or from a wish to simplify the
tasks of biodiversity conservation, or from fear that policy-
Policy implications of species uncertainty making and legal institutions cannot accommodate uncer-
If conservation efforts do focus on evolving populations and tainty about species, we should recognize that there is not
treat species taxa as research guides, then the ambiguity a single species concept, nor a research protocol, that can
of evolving populations and their uncertain connection to remove the inherent difficulty and uncertainty that
taxa will often be manifest. If biologists making conserva- accompanies research on evolving populations. These are
tion recommendations are revealed as being uncertain in conventional scientific uncertainties, and we cannot
their species assessments, will this hinder the legal and shelter ourselves from them.
policy-making components of species conservation? Per- The first reward of treating species taxa as hypotheses
haps if biologists admitted uncertainty over species, then and by recognizing the inherent uncertainties of species-
they could not play as constructive a role in conservation related research is a research protocol that is convention-
efforts [70]. For two reasons, we think that such a concern ally hypothetico-deductive. But beyond this aspect, which
is misplaced. already characterizes the work of many investigators, the
First, the traditional practice of treating species taxa as largest gains will be in the area of explanation. Research-
the primary focus of conservation efforts has a cost, quite ers of biological diversity are sometimes entangled by
apart from that associated with the possible misidentifica- species-problem-related questions that come from col-
tion of evolving populations. A strong reliance on taxa as leagues and biologists in other specialties, as well as from
conservation units creates a pressure to devise new species laypersons, students and professionals in fields who rely
http://tree.trends.com
43
602 Review TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.18 No.11 November 2003
upon the conservation recommendations of biologists. By Consequences (Otte, D. and Endler, J.A., eds), pp. 28 –59, Sinauer
explaining how research begins with taxa and proceeds to Associates
26 Cracraft, J. (1997) Species concepts in systematics and conservation
the study of populations, many species puzzles can be biology – an ornithological viewpoint. In Species: the Units of
explained in the familiar language of the uncertain Biodiversity (Claridge, M.F. et al., eds), pp. 325 – 339, Chapman & Hall
relationship between our hypotheses and the realities of 27 Constance, L. (1951) The versatile taxonomist. Brittonia 7, 225 –231
nature. 28 Ertter, B. (2000) Floristic surprises in North America north of Mexico.
Ann. Miss. Bot. Gard. 87, 81 – 109
29 Sites, J.W. and Crandall, K.A. (1997) Testing species boundaries in
Acknowledgements
biodiversity studies. Conserv. Biol. 11, 1289 – 1297
We are grateful to three reviewers for very helpful comments and to John
30 Templeton, A.R. (1994) The role of molecular genetics in speciation
Avise for input on the article. Jim Mallet provided valuable input
studies. In Molecular Approaches to Ecology and Evolution (Schier-
throughout much of the preparation of the paper, although he disagrees
water, B. et al., eds), pp. 455 – 477, Birkhäuser-Verlag
with some important aspects. M.L.A. acknowledges support from the
31 Templeton, A.R. (2001) Using phylogeographic analyses of gene trees
National Science Foundation, grant DEB-0074159.
to test species status and processes. Mol. Ecol. 10, 779 –791
32 Baum, D.A. and Donoghue, M.J. (1995) Choosing among alternative
References ‘phylogenetic’ species concepts. Syst. Bot. 20, 560 – 573
1 Mayden, R.L. (1997) A hierarchy of species concepts: the denouement 33 Council, N.R. (1995) Science and the Endangered Species Act, National
in the saga of the species problem. In Species: the Units of Biodiversity Academy Press
(Claridge, M.F. et al., eds), pp. 381 – 424, Chapman & Hall 34 Baum, D.A. (1998) Individuality and the existence of species in time.
2 Wheeler, Q.D., Meier, R. eds (2000) Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Syst. Biol. 47, 641– 653
Theory: A Debate Columbia University Press 35 Judd, W.S. et al. (1999) Plant Systematics: A Phylogenetic Approach,
3 Hey, J. (2001) Genes Categories and Species, Oxford University Press Sinauer Associates
4 Wilson, R.A. ed. (1999) Species MIT Press 36 Ghiselin, M.T. (1997) Metaphysics and the Origin of Species, State
5 de Queiroz, K. (1998) The general lineage concept of species: species University of New York Press
criteria and the process of speciation. In Endless Forms: Species and 37 Phipps, C.J. (1774) A Voyage towards the North Pole undertaken by His
Speciation (Howard, D.J. and Berlocher, S.H., eds), pp. 57 – 75, Oxford Majesty’s Command 1773, W. Bowyer and J. Nichols
University Press 38 Paetkau, D. et al. (1999) Genetic structure of the world’s polar bear
6 Avise, J.C. and Wollenberg, K. (1997) Phylogenetics and the origin of populations. Mol. Ecol. 8, 1571– 1584
species. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 94, 7748– 7755 39 Templeton, A.R. (1989) The meaning of species and speciation: a
7 Darwin, C. (1859,1964) On the Origin of Species: A Facsimile of the genetic perspective. In Speciation and its Consequences (Otte, D. and
First Edition, Harvard University Press Endler, J.A., eds), pp. 3 – 27, Sinauer Associates
8 Spurway, H. (1955) The subhuman capacities for species recognition 40 Grant, B.R. and Grant, P.R. (1998) Hybridization and speciation in
and their correlation with reproductive isolation. In Proceedings XI Darwin’s finches. In Endless Forms: Species and Speciation (Howard,
International Ornithological Congress, Basel, 1954 (Portmann, A. and D.J. and Berlocher, S.H., eds), pp. 404 – 422, Oxford University Press
Sutter, E., eds), pp. 340 – 349, Birkhäuser Verlag 41 Grant, P.R. and Grant, B.R. (1994) Phenotypic and genetic effects of
9 Haldane, J.B.S. (1956) Can a species concept be justified? In The hybridization in Darwin’s finches. Evolution 48, 297 –316
Species Concept in Paleontology (Sylvester-Bradley, P.C., ed.), 42 Rieseberg, L.H. and Burke, J.M. (2001) The biological reality of
pp. 95 –96, Systematics Association species: gene flow, selection, and collective evolution. Taxon 50, 47 –67
10 Levin, D.A. (1979) The nature of plant species. Science 204, 381 – 384 43 Ehrlich, P.R. and Raven, P.H. (1969) Differentiation of populations.
11 Nelson, G. (1989) Species and taxa: systematics and evolution. In Science 165, 1228– 1232
Speciation and its Consequences (Otte, D. and Endler, J.A., eds), 44 Mayr, E. (1963) Populations, Species and Evolution, Harvard
pp. 60 –81, Sinauer Associates University Press
12 Dobzhansky, T. (1937) Genetics and the Origin of Species, 1st edn, 45 Blackwelder, R.E. (1967) Taxonomy: A Text and Reference Book, John
Columbia University Press Wiley & Sons
13 Huxley, J.S. (1940) The New Systematics, Oxford University Press 46 Ghiselin, M.T. (1966) On psychologism in the logic of taxonomic
14 Mayr, E. et al. (1953) Methods and Principles of Systematic Zoology, controversies. Syst. Zool. 15, 207 – 215
McGraw-Hill 47 Hull, D.L. (1978) A matter of individuality. Philos. Sci. 45, 335 – 360
15 Simpson, G.G. (1961) Principles of Animal Taxonomy, Columbia 48 Mallet, J. (2001) Species, Concepts of. In Encyclopedia of Biodiversity
University Press (Levin, S.A., ed.), pp. 427 – 440, Academic Press
16 Maheshwari, J.K. (1967) The Plant Species in an Age of Experiment, 49 Hendry, A.P. et al. (2000) Questioning species realities. Conserv. Genet.
National Institute of Sciences of India 1, 67 – 76
17 Blackwelder, R.E. (1962) Animal taxonomy and the new systematics. 50 Mayr, E. (1942) Systematics and the Origin of Species, Columbia
Surv. Biol. Prog. 4, 1 – 57 University Press
18 Gilmour, J.S.L. (1940) In Taxonomy and philosophy In The New 51 Slobodchikoff, C.N. (1976) Concepts of Species, Hutchinson & Ross,
Systematics (Huxley, J.S., ed.), pp. 461 –474, Oxford University Press Dowden
19 Dobzhansky, T. (1951) Genetics and the Origins of Species, 2nd edn, 52 Goldstein, P.Z. et al. (2000) Conservation genetics at the species
Columbia University Press boundary. Conserv. Biol. 14, 120– 131
20 Stevens, P.F. (1992) Species: historical perspectives. In Keywords in 53 Claridge, M.F. et al. (1997) Practical approaches to species concepts for
Evolutionary Biology (Keller, E.F. and Lloyd, E., eds), pp. 302 – 311, living organisms. In Species: the Units of Biodiversity (Claridge, M.F.
Harvard University Press et al., eds), pp. 1 – 15, Chapman & Hall
21 Endler, J.A. (1989) Conceptual and other problems in speciation. In 54 Ehrlich, P.R. (1988) The loss of diversity: causes and consequences. In
Speciation and its Consequences (Otte, D. and Endler, J.A., eds), Biodiversity (Wilson, E.O., ed.), pp. 21 – 27, National Academy Press
pp. 625– 648, Sinauer Associates 55 Ryder, O.A. (1986) Species conservation and systematics: the dilemma
22 Rojas, M. (1992) The species problem and conservation: what are we of subspecies. Trends Ecol. Evol. 1, 9 – 10
protecting? Conserv. Biol. 6, 170 – 178 56 Waples, R.S. (1991) Pacific salmon, Oncorhynchus spp., and the
23 Mayr, E. (1987) The ontological status of species: scientific progress definition of ‘species’ under the Endangered Species Act. Mar. Fish
and philosophical terminology. Biol. Philos. 2, 145–166 Rev. 53, 11 – 22
24 Mayr, E. (1996) What is a species and what is not? Philos. Sci. 63, 57 Dizon, A.E. et al. (1992) Rethinking the stock concept: a phylogeo-
262 – 277 graphic approach. Conserv. Biol. 6, 24– 36
25 Cracraft, J. (1989) Speciation and its ontology: the empirical 58 Waples, R.S. (1995) Evolutionarily significant units and the conserva-
consequences of alternative species concepts for understanding tion of biological diversity under the Endangered Species Act. In
patterns and processes of differentiation. In Speciation and its Evolution and the Aquatic Ecosystem: Defining Unique Units in
http://tree.trends.com
44
Review TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.18 No.11 November 2003 603
Population Conservation (Nielsen, J.L., ed.), pp. 8 –27, American a classic Drosophila species group. Proc. R. Soc. London B. Biol. Sci.
Fisheries Society 270, 1193– 1202
59 Waples, R.S. et al. (2001) Characterizing diversity in salmon from the 67 Cracraft, J. (1983) Species concepts and speciation analysis. Curr.
Pacific Northwest. J. Fish Biol. 59, 1 – 41 Ornithol. 1, 159– 187
60 Moritz, C. (1994) Defining ‘evolutionary significant units’ for con- 68 Nixon, K.C. and Wheeler, Q.D. (1990) An amplification of the
servation. Trends Ecol. Evol. 9, 373 – 375 phylogenetic species concept. Cladistics 6, 211 – 223
61 Pennock, D.S. and Dimmick, W.W. (1997) Critique of the evolutionary 69 Avise, J.C. and Ball, R.M.J. (1990) Principles of genealogical
significant unit as a definition for ‘Distinct Population Segments’ concordance in species concepts and biological taxonomy. In Oxford
under the U.S. Endangered Species Act. Conserv. Biol. 11, 611 – 619 Surveys in Evolutionary Biology (Harvey, P.H. and Partridge, L., eds),
62 Dimmick, W.W. et al. (1999) The importance of systematic biology in pp. 45– 67, Oxford University Press
defining units of conservation units. Conserv. Biol. 13, 653– 660 70 Milius, S. (2000) What’s worth saving: a fracas over a biological term
63 Vogler, A.P. and DeSalle, R. (1994) Diagnosing units of conservation could have huge consequences for conservation. Sci. News 158,
management. Conserv. Biol. 8, 354– 363 250– 252
64 Hudson, R.R. and Turelli, M. (2003) Stochasticity overrules the ‘three- 71 Karl, S.A. and Bowen, B. (1999) Evolutionary significant units versus
times rule’: genetic drift, genetic draft, and coalescence times for geopolitical taxonomy: molecular systematics of an endangered sea
nuclear loci versus mitochondrial DNA. Evolution 57, 182– 190 turtle (genus Chelonia). Conserv. Biol. 13, 990 – 999
65 Hudson, R.R. and Coyne, J.A. (2002) Mathematical consequences of 72 Wilhite, D. and Glantz, M.R. (1987) Understanding the drought
the genealogical species concept. Evolution 56, 1557 –1565 phenomenon: the role of definitions. In Planning for Drought (Wilhite,
66 Machado, C.A. and Hey, J. (2003) The causes of phylogenetic conflict in D. et al., eds), pp. 11 – 27, Westview Press
Endeavour
the quarterly magazine for the history
and philosophy of science
featuring
The pathway to the cell and its organelles: one hundred years of the Golgi apparatus by M. Bentivoglio and P. Mazzarello
Joseph Fourier, the ‘greenhouse effect’ and the quest for a universal theory of terrestrial temperatures by J.R. Fleming
The hunt for red elixir: an early collaboration between fellows of the Royal Society by D.R. Dickson
Art as science: scientific illustration 1490–1670 in drawing, woodcut and copper plate by C.M. Pyle
The history of reductionism versus holistic approaches to scientific research by H. Andersen
Reading and writing the Book of Nature: Jan Swammerdam (1637–1680) by M. Cobb
Coming to terms with ambiguity in science: wave–particle duality by B.K. Stepansky
The role of museums in history of science, technology and medicine by L. Taub
The ‘internal clocks’ of circadian and interval timing by S. Hinton and W.H. Meck
The troubled past and uncertain future of group selectionism by T. Shanahan
A botanist for a continent: Ferdinand Von Mueller (1825–1896) by R.W. Home
Rudolf Virchow and the scientific approach to medicine by L. Benaroyo
Darwinism and atheism: different sides of the same coin? by M. Ruse
Alfred Russel Wallace and the flat earth controversy by C. Garwood
John Dalton: the world’s first stereochemist by Dennis H. Rouvray
Forensic chemistry in 19th-century Britain by N.G. Coley
Owen and Huxley: unfinished business by C.U.M. Smith
Characteristics of scientific revolutions by H. Andersen
and much, much more . . .
Locate Endeavour in the BioMedNet Reviews collection.
Log on to http://reviews.bmn.com, hit the ‘Browse Journals’ tab and scroll down to Endeavour
http://tree.trends.com
45
Who Needs Sex (or Males) Anyway?
Liza Gross | doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050099
As is the case for free-living species, a very large number of Limitations of the BSC for parasites
parasitic species are not described adequately by the biological Parasitic organisms constitute a large proportion of
species concept. Furthermore, Thierry de Meeûs, Yannis the cases problematical to the BSC. Many parasite taxa
Michalakis and François Renaud argue that because hosts exhibit extremely restricted cross fertilization. Such
represent a highly heterogeneous and changing environment restrictions may be due to extreme rates of clonal
as well as a breeding site, favouring the association of host- reproduction, selfing or biparental inbreeding such as
adaptation and host-choice genes, sympatric speciation may sib-mating. Parthenogenesis is very well documented
occur frequently in parasitic organisms. Therefore, parasites in numerous families of nematodes parasitic on plants
appear to be ideal biological models for the study of ecological and animals12. The large controversy concerning the
specialization and speciation. Beyond the relevance of such clonality of many microparasites illustrates clearly the
considerations in fundamental science, the study of the origin opposition between parasites and the BSC13–15. The
and evolution of parasite diversity has important implications most spectacular examples of selfing lie within the
for more applied fields such as epidemiology and diagnosis. cestode group. Taenia solium, which is nearly always
found alone in the human intestine, can only self-
The biological species concept (BSC) which emphasizes reproduce16. In the Cyclorchida genus, because of ana-
the role of reproductive isolation1 remains widely used tomical constraints of the genitalia, self-fertilization is
despite the fact that it cannot account satisfactorily for a the only possibility16. Sib-mating is also often encoun-
large number of biological examples2. Furthermore, be- tered among parasites. For instance, in many hymen-
cause it focuses on the outcome and not the process, it opteran parasitoid wasps, such as Nasonia vitripennis,
has been detrimental to studies on mechanisms of speci- mating occurs only between brothers and sisters17.
ation3 and, in particular, it has served as a background Finally, many species undergo phases of asexual
to the main arguments against the existence of sympat- reproduction and sib-mating. For example, in many
ric speciation. Santa Rosalia was first mentioned by helminths the intermediate host is infected only by one
Hutchinson4 to provide a functional explanation for the individual, which undergoes asexual multiplication.
origin and apportionment of animal species. Several The products of this asexual multiplication in the inter-
authors subsequently referred to him in order to discuss mediate host are likely to mate together in the defini-
the existence of non-allopatric modes of speciation5,6. tive host. Such a mating system, genetically synony-
As mentioned previously by Lymbery7,8, for some mous with selfing, occurs in cestodes8 and trematodes18.
parasites the BSC has many limitations. Indeed, it fo- Applying the BSC to any of the previous examples
cuses on reproductive isolation as the unique criterion to would lead us to consider each individual as a single
delimit the species boundaries. Thus, the BSC confuses species and each egg hatching as a speciation event.
one consequence and its cause: reproductive isolation ‘Too much’ sex, however, is also encountered in
and the processes leading to it3. Given these limitations, parasites. The most well-known example concerns
several alternatives to the BSC have been proposed2,3,8. the genus Schistosoma, where hybridizations have
Many examples illustrate the inadequacy of the been described between different species19,20. This is
BSC. Indeed, large parts of the living world lie out- also known to occur between Echinostoma species21.
side the BSC’s logical domain, because they display Furthermore, bacteria can exchange DNA even be-
either ‘too little’ or ‘too much’ sex3. Obviously, the BSC tween distant ‘species’22,23. Hybridization itself may
is applicable only to sexually reproducing organisms9. also lead to speciation through polyploidization in
Moreover, self-mating and sib-mating organisms and parasites as, for example, in Paragoni-mus flukes24,
any other closed system of mating cannot be ac- thus fully contradicting the BSC. This process is
counted for satisfactorily by the BSC. In addition, probably largely overlooked in parasites and the few
many species are able to hybridize with others with- examples available concern human parasites.
out losing their ecological and genetic identities
through time3,10. Paradoxically, in some cases it is the Sympatric speciation in parasites
hybridization itself that leads to new species. Indeed, All these examples illustrate the fact that the BSC
many polyploid lineages are known to result from a cannot be applied to a large number of parasite
hybridization event between two different species11. species. These considerations are, arguably, only
semantic, requiring a solution only for the excep-
tions. However, BSC, by definition, brings problems
Thierry de Meeûs and François Renaud are at the Laboratoire
de Parasitologie Comparée, UMR 5555 CNRS, Université Montpellier of another order: it may lead to the mechanisms
II, Place E. Bataillon, 34095 Montpellier Cedex 05, France. Yannis * ‘The Garden of Earthly Delights’ refers to the triptych by Hieronymus
Michalakis is at the Laboratoire d’Ecologie URA 258, Université Bosch (c. 1500; Museo del Prado, Madrid) and, particularly, to its right panel
Paris 6 CC 237, 7 quai Saint Bernard, Bât. A, 75252 Paris Cedex 05, which exhibits an impressive collection of tormenting creatures that a biolo-
France. Tel: +33 4 67 14 37 09, Fax: +33 4 67 14 46 46, gist could recognize as the likely outcomes of recombination, hybridization
e-mail: renaud@crit.univ-montp2.fr and mutation combined with diversification.
10 48
Copyright © 1998, Elsevier Science Ltd All rights reserved 0169–4758/98/$19.00 PII: S0169-4758(97)01163-0 Parasitology Today, vol. 14, no. 1, 1998
Reviews
responsible for reproductive isolation being over-
Box 1. Concepts of Allopatry and Sympatry in
looked3. Indeed, even if many sexually reproducing Parasitic Organisms
species can be recognized through the BSC, one can
consider that the reproductive isolation they display
against other species originated from other processes,
independent of those that led to such an isolation.
Thus, any evidence of reproductive isolation between
two closely related species provides no information on
the processes responsible for such an outcome. The
real problem here is less to testify the existence of
reproductive isolation than to understand the under-
lying mechanisms. When speciation is allopatric, repro-
ductive isolation is coincidental: while the different gene
pools are allopatric, selection will not act in favour of
isolating mechanisms. Characters diverge between gene
pools either by chance, or to adapt to different environ-
ments or genomic composition. Reproductive isolation
on secondary contact may arise only coincidentally to
this divergence. Selection for such isolating mechanisms
comes into action only after secondary contact, ie. when
different genetic entities are sympatric.
Under the BSC, the factors responsible for repro-
ductive isolation in general play no direct role in
species divergence3; therefore, all theoretical attempts
using the BSC as a basis have failed to describe sym-
patric speciation as a probable event5,25. Indeed, the
evolution of reproductive isolation per se is unlikely Different entities will be allopatric only if isolated geo-
because it will behave as a deleterious character when graphically. Individuals belonging to allopatric groups
rare, ie. in any case at the initial stage of the process. cannot interact. This is the case when different parasite
Alternatively, sympatric speciation may occur with- species live on different host species in areas where hosts
out the need to invoke reproductive isolation, through are separated by physical barriers (a; solid lines), or in
adaptive polymorphism and habitat preference26. As areas where vicariant host species replace one another
without any obvious physical barriers (b). On the con-
a recent study shows27, the result of these mechanisms trary, when encountered in the same geographical areas,
may be reinforced by any non-habitat-associated such entities will be considered sympatric, even if ex-
assortative mating. This process has been supported ploiting different resources. Indeed, in such co-existing
by some experimental work28 but the most convincing groups, individuals may still interact during their life
evidence is provided by the natural example of the cycle. For example, all helminths parasitizing the verte-
phytophagous insect Rhagoletis pomonella29 – a parasite. brates living in a pond are sympatric, because of all the
Because parasites provide particular situations, existing ecological interconnections between the hosts
Box 1 illustrates the difference between true allopatric and their parasites (c). More spectacular sympatric cases
and true sympatric situations found in host–parasite arise when parasites specialize on different organs of the
systems. Allopatric speciation alone can hardly ac- same host species (d). G, geographical areas; H, host
species (triangles), partitioned into different organs (inter-
count for the diversity of unambiguous species of nal triangles); closed circles represent parasites.
related parasites often encountered in a single host
(Fig. 1). Considering the parasitological literature this
situation is far from marginal. Among the platy- by at least seven species of mallophagous insects,
helminths, the monogeneans and cestoda provide each of which is specialized on a single feather type31.
the most striking examples. In the Tchad Basin (West Less spectacular in diversity, but necessarily recent, is
Africa) the characid fish Alestes nurse is known to the case of the three species of human lice32.
harbour on its gills eight monogenean species of the Furthermore, the most relevant evidence of on-
Anulotrema genus, each of which displays specific going sympatric divergences comes from the parasito-
genitalia (Fig. 1). These parasites, as well as their host, logical literature. In the Caribbean, the acquisition of
live only in this area so that their divergence and a murine host by the human parasite Schistosoma
speciation probably occurred in sympatry. In the mansoni leads to an adaptive divergence depending on
Mediterranean, the gills of the fish Liza saliens the periodic behaviour of the host towards water33.
(Mugilidae) are parasitized by four species of Ligo- The sea louse Lepeophtheirus europaensis also displays
phorus. In both cases, different parasite species are a sympatric divergence between the two flatfishes it
distributed non-randomly on different parts of the parasitizes in the Mediterranean (brill and flounder) –
gills (Fig. 1). Niche differentiation and specialization a supposedly recent phenomenon34. However, the
most likely led to speciation of these parasites on the better-documented studies come from insect parasites
same host species in a single geographical area. Among of plants35–38. Among these, Rhagoletis pomonella rep-
the Cestoda, four species of Acanthobothrium are de- resents a well-studied model29,39.
scribed in the spiral valve of the stingray Dasyatus When one considers the realm of microparasites,
longus from the Gulf of Nicoya (Costa Rica)30. reproductive isolation appears irrelevant as a mecha-
Other examples can be found among terrestrial nism for discriminating species. The tremendous
arthropods (lice). The bird Ibis falcinellus is parasitized diversity observed in groups such as the yeast Candida
Parasitology Today, vol. 14, no. 1, 1998 49 11
Reviews
factor is supported by comparative
analyses of herbivorous insects. Phy-
tophagy is encountered in only nine
of the 13 orders of insects44, but
these orders account for approxi-
mately half of all insect species.
Furthermore, phytophagous taxo-
nomic groups are significantly more
speciose than homologous groups
of the same evolutionary age with
a non-parasitic feeding habit44. A
possible explanation for this di-
versifying role of parasitism may
lie in the fact that sympatric speci-
ation is much more likely in
parasitic species. Indeed, as stated
previously, hosts provide ample
opportunities for niche diversific-
ation among parasite populations,
a necessary condition for sym-
patric speciation. Thus, sympatric
speciation may play a much more
central role in parasite evolution
and evolutionary biology as a whole,
with parasites representing ideal
biological models for the study
of ecological specialization and
speciation mechanisms.
Fig. 1. Two relevant examples of multiple monogenean congeners found in one host In the face of this acute potential
species and for which allopatric speciation alone cannot explain the observed diver- for diversification, hosts have
sity16. Morphology of male and female genitalia of eight species of Annulotrema failed to eliminate all their para-
observed on Alestes nurse in Tchad (a). Morphology of genitalia and hamuli haptors of sites. For instance, even though
the four species of Ligophorus parasitizing the Teleost Liza saliens in the Mediter- mankind has managed to elimi-
ranean (b). (Reproduced, with permission, from Ref. 16.) nate (almost) all of its competitors
and predators, current knowledge
indicates that it has been unable to
albicans16 suggests other modes of speciation instead eliminate any of its parasites (smallpox being the
of the classical allopatric model. exception that proves the rule). This is illustrated by
modern prophylactic campaigns against malaria that
Does the parasitic way of life favour phylogenic are followed by the emergence of more and more
diversification? Plasmodium strains resistant to nivaquine. As previ-
Parasitism represents the conquest of life by life. ously underlined45, this genetic variability is crucial
The living environment evolves continuously. Thus, in both therapy and susceptibility to immune attack.
in order to persist in their living environments para- There is a need to obtain the most precise knowledge
sites must continuously adapt to their hosts. Hosts of parasite diversity before developing therapeutics
represent a major part of the ecological needs of their or vaccines. In the same way, the identification of the
parasites (habitat, resource, etc.)40. Hosts may repre- existing diversity of parasitic organisms must be
sent many different kinds of resources and habitats taken into account in epidemiological surveys. This
(communities, species, populations, cohorts, sexes, may allow us to discriminate more effectively, within
individuals, organs, cells and molecules). Further- parasite communities, those that are pathogenic and
more, hosts develop defences against such intruders, those that are not. This can be illustrated by the gen-
by behavioural, physiological and demographic means. etic divergences found between strains of C. albicans,
Such defences impose an additional source of selec- which are comparable to that existing between the
tive and diversifying pressures on parasites. Such con- different mammalian species of the same genus16.
tinuous mutual aggressions resulting from the never- Moreover, genetic distances between C. albicans sam-
ending modifications of the living environment have pled in one human host46 exceeded that seen between
largely shaped the life history traits and the evolu- great apes and humans47, which diverged 5–7 million
tionary pathways in host–parasite systems (Red years ago48. In addition, when compared with the
Queen concept)41. protozoan species Trypanosoma cruzi, for example, the
The potential number of diversifying factors is overall genetic variability of the species C. albicans is at
much larger for parasitic organisms than for free- least four times lower (M. Tibayrenc, pers. commun.).
living organisms. All living species are involved in
parasitism, either as parasites or as hosts42 and, as Concluding remarks: many or no species concepts?
suggested by Timm and Clauson43, parasites consti- Providing a general and satisfactory species defini-
tute the main part of the known species diversity. tion appears to be a very difficult task, especially
That the parasitic way of life might be a diversifying given the very large number of potential applications
12 50 Parasitology Today, vol. 14, no. 1, 1998
Reviews
with different functional requirements (taxonomy, or ‘clonal’ populations? Parasitol. Today 7, 232–235
conservation biology, functional ecology, evolution- 15 Pujol, C. et al. (1993) The yeast Candida albicans has a clonal
mode of reproduction in a population of infected human
ary biology and medicine). In fact, we do not believe immunodeficiency virus-positive patients. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci.
that it is possible to reach a species definition that will U. S. A. 90, 9456–9459
satisfy everybody. In this paper, our aim is not to pro- 16 Euzet, L. and Combes, C. (1980) in Les Problèmes de l’Espèce dans
le Règne Animal (Vol. 3), Mem. Soc. Zool. 40, 238–285
vide a new species definition because we feel the 17 Werren, J.H. (1980) Sex ratio adaptations to local mate compe-
extant ones (typological, BSC, etc.) will continue to tition in a parasitic wasp. Science 208, 1157–1159
work in their different domains of application. Our 18 Combes, C. (1988) in L’Adaptation, Pour La Science, pp 166–173, Belin
goal is to draw attention to the fact that the most cur- 19 Brémond, P. et al. (1993) Argument en faveur d’une modi-
fication du génome (introgression) du parasite humain
rently used concept (the BSC) might not be very help- Schistosoma haematobium par les gènes de S. bovis, au Niger.
ful in parasitology, because of the reasons outlined C. R. Acad. Sci. Life Sci. 316, 667–670
above, and that it may prevent researchers from con- 20 Tchuem Tchuente, L.A. et al. (1993) Choice of mate, a repro-
sidering several evolutionary processes. The strong ductive isolating mechanism between Schistosoma intercalatum
and S. mansoni in mixed infections. Int. J. Parasitol. 23, 179–185
potential for diversification displayed by parasites, 21 Voltz, A. et al. (1988) Isoenzyme analysis of Echinostoma liei:
possibly due to the larger opportunities for sympatric Comparison and hybridization with other African species.
speciation in such groups, should allow parasitolo- Exp. Parasitol. 66, 13–17
gists to play a major role in different fields of biology. 22 Maynard-Smith, J. et al. (1991) Localised sex in bacteria. Nature
349, 29–31
In evolutionary biology, parasites appear as ideal 23 Heinemann, J.A. (1991) Genetics of gene transfer between
models for the study of specialization and speciation species. Trends Genet. 7, 181–185
and much can be learned from them. In phylogenetic 24 Agatsuma, T. et al. (1992) Electrophoretic evidence of a hybrid
studies the genetic consequences of such potential for origin for tetraploid Paragonimus westermani discovered in
north-eastern China. Parasitol. Res. 78, 537–538
diversification should allow different hypotheses, such 25 Fialkowski, K.R. (1988) Lottery of sympatric speciation. A com-
as the molecular clock, to be tested, in particular in puter model. J. Theor. Biol. 130, 379–390
groups where such a diversification is evident (eg. 26 De Meeûs, T. et al. (1993) Polymorphism in heterogeneous
monogeneans and bird lice). Too few such studies are environments, habitat selection and sympatric speciation: soft
and hard selection models. Evol. Ecol. 7, 175–198
available at the present time. Parasite communities 27 Johnson, P.A. et al. (1996) Conditions for sympatric speciation
should provide very useful models for studying the – a diploid model incorporating habitat fidelity and non-
interaction between species, competition and exclu- habitat assortative mating. Evol. Ecol. 10, 187–205
sion and biological diversity maintenance, because 28 Rice, W.R. and Salt, G.W. (1988) Speciation via disruptive
selection: experimental evidence. Evolution 131, 911–917
the ecological niche of a parasite will often be easier 29 Bush, G. L. (1992) Host race formation and sympatric speciation
to define (as it is concentrated in the host). In medi- in Rhagoletis fruit flies (Diptera: Tephrtidae). Psyche 99, 335–357
cine, the mechanisms involved in parasite diversific- 30 Marques, F. et al. (1995) Five new species of Acanthobothrium
ation (in the wide sense) should allow a better under- van Beneden, 1849 (Eucestoda: Tetraphyllidea: Onchobothri-
idae) in stingrays from the gulf of Nicoya, Costa Rica. J. Parasitol.
standing of eradication failures. Also, it should be 81, 942–951
considered more often that what appears to be a sin- 31 Dogiel, V.A. (1964) General Parasitology, Oliver and Boyd
gle pathogenic entity might actually comprise several 32 Ludwig, H.W. (1982) Host specificity in anoplura and coevolu-
very different genetic entities. As mentioned previ- tion of anoplura and mammalia. Mem. Mus. Natn. Hist. Nat.
Paris 123, 145–152
ously, the tremendous levels of genetic diversity found 33 Théron, A. and Combes, C. (1995) Asynchrony of infection tim-
within C. albicans and T. cruzi reveal that these taxa ing, habitat preference, and sympatric speciation of schisto-
are complex and surely made up of different biologi- some parasites. Evolution 49, 372–375
34 De Meeûs, T. et al. (1995) Maintenance of two genetic entities
cal entities (species). Because they co-exist, these dif- by habitat selection. Evol. Ecol. 9, 131–138
ferent biological entities might have different ecologi- 35 Wood, T.K. and Guttman, S.I. (1983) Euchenopa binotata com-
cal niches (ie. needs) and thus different sensitivities to plex: sympatric speciation? Science 220, 310–312
one or another treatment. 36 Craig, T.P. et al. (1993) Behavioural evidence for host-race for-
mation in Eurosta solidaginis. Evolution 47, 1696–1710
References 37 Ronquist, F. (1994) Evolution of parasitism among closely related
1 Mayr, E. (1942) Systematics and the Origin of Species, Columbia species: phylogenetic relationships and the origin of inquilinism
University Press in gall wasps (Hymenoptera, Cypinidae). Evolution 48, 241–266
2 Mallet, J. (1995) A species definition for the modern synthesis. 38 Emelianov, I. et al. (1995) Genetic differentiation in Zeiraphera
Trends Ecol. Evol. 10, 294–299 diniana (Lepidoptera: Tortricidae, the larch budmoth): poly-
3 Templeton, A.R. (1989) in Speciation and its Consequences (Otte, morphism, host races or sibling species? Heredity 75, 416–424
D. and Endler, J.A., eds), pp 3–27, Sinauer 39 Berlocher, S.H. and McPherson, B.A. (1996) Population structure
4 Hutchinson, G.E. (1959) Homage to Santa Rosalia or why are of Rhagoletis pomonella, the apple maggot fly. Heredity 77, 83–99
there so many kinds of animal species? Am. Nat. 93, 145–159 40 Renaud, F. et al. (1996) Biodiversity and evolution in host–
5 Felsenstein, J. (1981) Skepticism towards Santa Rosalia, or why parasite associations. Biodiv. Conserv. 5, 963–974
are there so few kinds of animals? Evolution 35, 124–138 41 Van Valen, L. (1973) A new evolutionary law. Evol. Theor. 1, 1–30
6 Bush, G.L. (1993) in Evolutionary Patterns and Processes (Leeds, 42 Barbault, R. (1988) Population biology and evolutionary ecol-
D.R. and Edwards, D., eds), pp 229–249, Academic Press ogy in France: current state prospects. J. Evol. Biol. 1, 211–231
7 Lymbery, A.J. (1992) Interbreeding, monophyly and the Genetic 43 Timm, R.M. and Clauson, B.L. (1987) in Coevolution, pp 212–214,
Yardstick: species concepts in parasites. Parasitol. Today 8, 208–211 McGraw–Hill
8 Lymbery, A.J. and Thompson, R.C.A. (1996) Species of 44 Mitter, C. et al. (1988) The phylogenetic study of adaptive
Echinococcus: pattern and process. Parasitol. Today 12, 486–491 zones – has phytophagy promoted insect diversification? Am.
9 Vrba, E.S. (1985) in Species and Speciation (Vrba, E.S., ed.), pp Nat. 132, 107–128
ix–xviii, Transvaal Museum Monograph No. 4 45 Cox, F.E.G. (1991) Variation and vaccination. Nature 349, 193
10 Harrison, R.G. and Rand, D.M. (1989) in Speciation and its Conse- 46 Reynes, J. et al. (1996) Simultaneous carriage of Candida albi-
quences (Otte, D. and Endler, J.A., eds), pp 111–133, Sinauer cans strains from HIV-infected patients with oral candidiasis:
11 Futuyma, D.J. (1986) Evolutionary Biology (2nd edn), Sinauer multilocus enzyme electrophoresis analysis. FEMS Microbiol.
12 Bell, G. (1982) The Masterpiece of Nature, University of California Press Lett. 137, 269–273
13 Tibayrenc, M. and Ayala, F.J. (1991) Toward a population 47 Bruce, E.J. and Ayala, F.J. (1979) Phylogenetic relationships
genetics of micro-organisms: the clonal theory of parasitic between man and the apes: electrophoretic evidence. Evolution
protozoa. Parasitol. Today 7, 228–232 33, 1040–1056
14 Walliker, D. (1991) Malaria parasites: randomly interbreeding 48 Ridley, M. (1996) Evolution (2nd edn), Blackwell Science
Parasitology Today, vol. 14, no. 1, 1998 51 13
52
53
Update TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.22 No.8 391
aspects of avian sex chromosome evolution that are 6 Shetty, S. et al. (1999) Comparative painting reveals strong
chromosome homology over 80 million years of bird evolution.
inevitable from those that are due strictly to chance.
Chrom. Res. 7, 289–295
Additionally, even though the palaeognathous sex 7 Charlesworth, B. (1991) The evolution of sex-chromosomes. Science
chromosomes are as old as those of the Neognathae, some- 251, 1030–1033
thing has slowed the process of sex chromosome evolution 8 Ellegren, H. and Carmichael, A. (2001) Multiple and independent
in the group. This presents a living series of slow-motion cessation of recombination between avian sex chromosomes.
Genetics 158, 325–331
time-shots in the progression of avian sex chromosomes,
9 Handley, L.L. et al. (2004) Evolutionary strata on the chicken Z
from the largely undifferentiated ostrich and emu Z and W, chromosome: implications for sex chromosome evolution. Genetics
to the distinguishably different intermediate tinamou Z 167, 367–376
and W, to the terminal neognathous sex chromosomes that 10 Tsuda, Y. et al. (2007) Comparison of the Z and W sex chromosomal
only recombine in a small and highly constrained pseudo- architectures in elegant chrested tinamou (Eudromia elegans) and
ostrich (Struthio camelus) and the process of sex chromosome
autosomal region (Figure 1). These characteristics offer a differentiation in palaeognathous birds. Chromosoma 116, 159–
powerful clade for the study of sex chromosome evolution, 173
which future sequence, linkage and cytogenetic analysis 11 Ogawa, A. et al. (1998) The location of Z- and W-linked marker genes
can exploit. and sequence on the homomorphic sex chromosomes of the ostrich and
the emu. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 95, 4415–4418
Acknowledgements 12 Pigozzi, M.I. and Solari, A.J. (1999) The ZW pairs of two paleognath
We thank the Wenner-Gren Foundation and the Swedish Research birds from two orders show transitional stages of sex chromosome
Council for support, as well as two anonymous reviewers for helpful differentiation. Chrom. Res. 7, 541–551
suggestions. 13 Matsubara, K. et al. (2006) Evidence for different origin of sex
chromosomes in snakes, birds, and mammals and step-wise
differentiation of snake sex chromosomes. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.
References
S. A. 103, 18190–18195
1 Bachtrog, D. (2006) A dynamic view of sex chromosome evolution. Curr.
14 de Kloet, R.S. and de Kloet, S.R. (2003) Evolution of the spindlin gene in
Opin. Genet. Dev. 16, 578–585
birds: independent cessation of the recombination of sex chromosomes
2 Ezaz, T. et al. (2006) Relationships between vertebrate ZW and XY sex
at the spindlin locus in neognathous birds and tinamous, a
chromosome systems. Curr. Biol. 16, R736–R743
palaeognathous avian family. Genetica 119, 333–342
3 Ellegren, H. (2000) Evolution of the avian sex chromosomes and their
15 Berlin, S. and Ellegren, H. (2006) Fast accumulation of
role in sex determination. Trends Ecol. Evol. 15, 188–192
nonsynonymous mutations on the female-specific W chromosome in
4 Fridolfsson, A.K. et al. (1998) Evolution of the avian sex chromosomes
birds. J. Mol. Evol. 62, 66–72
from an ancestral pair of autosomes. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 95,
8147–8152
5 van Tuinen, M. and Hedges, S.B. (2001) Calibration of avian molecular 0169-5347/$ – see front matter ß 2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
clocks. Mol. Biol. Evol. 18, 206–213 doi:10.1016/j.tree.2007.05.003
Letters
Recently, Bickford et al. [1] highlighted the importance of taxonomically valid names on the basis of name-bearing
exploring cryptic diversity. Their biology-focused contri- specimens (types). Types often date back to Linnaeus’ time
bution is a reminder of the original questions regarding the and are frequently unsuitable for molecular studies,
current debate between molecular and traditional taxon- despite progress in this field [5], even setting aside that
omy [2], and a call for synergies between these approaches. museum curators usually refuse molecular sampling of
Only an integration of all disciplines can promote biological fragile type specimens. MOBAT can link cryptic species
research at the tempo set by the biodiversity crisis [3,4]. to Linnean nomenclature and to established biological
But one point is left unemphasized: the undiminished knowledge. Once discovered, many cryptic species can be
relevance of morphology-based alpha taxonomy (MOBAT), identified by means of external physical characters [6],
which is still the most important discipline for assigning especially with methods of morphometric statistics [7].
Badly under-resourced [8], MOBAT cannot keep pace
Corresponding author: Schlick-Steiner, B.C. (birgit.florian@gmail.com).
Available online 15 June 2007. with the discovery of cryptic species, as illustrated by a
54
www.sciencedirect.com
392 Update TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution Vol.22 No.8
topical example. An integrative approach revealed at least tions for evolutionary theory, biogeography and conserva-
seven sympatric species hidden in two nominal species of tion planning’ [1] is to be realised.
western Palearctic Tetramorium ants [9]. Because most of
these species are both common and widespread, it is risky to References
guess which were used for types by previous taxonomists; 1 Bickford, D. et al. (2007) Cryptic species as a window on diversity and
conservation. Trends Ecol. Evol. 22, 148–155
approximately 50 taxon names in synonymy, and their types 2 Smith, V.S. (2005) DNA barcoding: perspectives from a ‘Partnerships for
(the oldest from 1850), demand scrutiny [10]. More than 500 Enhancing Expertise in Taxonomy’ (PEET) debate. Syst. Biol. 54, 841–
publications over 150 years contain information on life 844
history, ethology, social biology, semiochemistry, ecology 3 Will, K.W. et al. (2005) The perils of DNA barcoding and the need for
and invasion biology of these ant species. But of which integrative taxonomy. Syst. Biol. 54, 844–851
4 Whitfield, J. (2007) We are family. Nature 446, 247–249
ant species? Biological knowledge that would help elucidate 5 Hajibabaei, M. et al. (2006) A minimalist barcode can identify a
patterns and consequences of cryptic diversification [1] lies specimen whose DNA is degraded. Mol. Ecol. Notes 6, 959–964
idle. Only analysing historical voucher material could tap 6 Saez, A.G. and Lozano, E. (2005) Body doubles. Nature 433, 111
these resources. However, the current working capacity of 7 Seifert, B. (2002) How to distinguish most similar insect species –
improving the stereomicroscopic and mathematical evaluation of
ant MOBAT is slight. Just two of >200 European myrme-
external characters by example of ants. J. Appl. Entomol. 126, 1–9
cologists work in numerical MOBAT as full-time pro- 8 Wheeler, Q.D. et al. (2004) Taxonomy: impediment or expedient? Science
fessionals. We guess that the situation is similar with 303, 285
other groups of organisms. While the discovery of cryptic 9 Schlick-Steiner, B.C. et al. (2006) A multidisciplinary approach
species increases exponentially [1], the number of experi- reveals cryptic diversity in western Palaearctic Tetramorium ants
(Hymenoptera: Formicidae). Mol. Phylogenet. Evol. 40, 259–273
enced MOBATists stagnates.
10 Bolton, B. et al. (2007) Bolton’s catalogue of ants of the world: 1758–
Even when uncovered by modern methods, many cryptic 2005. Harvard University Press
species remain taxonomically cryptic. Investment in all
disciplines contributing to integrative taxonomy, including 0169-5347/$ – see front matter ß 2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
MOBAT, is essential if the promise of ‘profound implica- doi:10.1016/j.tree.2007.05.004
Book Review
Organisms as diverse as yeast and moose Beginning with an historical account, d’Arcy Thompson
show striking similarities in their growth is introduced as the godfather of mathematical thinking in
trajectories, initially growing quickly, but biology. In a letter to a former student Thompson writes
then gradually slowing their growth as that, to understand growth patterns in foraminifera, ‘I
they get larger, eventually stopping altog- have taken to Mathematics . . .’. This quote is the leitmotiv
ether. They also follow Kleiber’s rule; that of Whitfield’s book, culminating in a modern version in
is, their metabolic rate is proportional to which Brown and Enquist did not literary ‘take Mathemat-
their mass raised to the 3/ 4 power. Many ics’, but joined forces with West. However, before these
scholars have tried to find laws valid for contemporaries are discussed, their predecessors in the
all life forms that could explain these two quest are presented. Max Rubner, Max Kleiber and Lud-
regularities, but none have yet convinced the scientific wig von Bertalanffy feature, among many others.
community as a whole. By the end of the previous century, Such mix of an historical sketch and a description of the
the subject was receiving little if any attention; however, lives and work of present-day scientists who have only
work by the physicist Geoffrey West and ecologists Jim recently launched ideas that are still debated, is, for
Brown and Brian Enquist has since revitalized the topic various reasons, a risky exercise. I found it amusing to
[1,2]. John Whitfield, an evolutionary biologist turned read that 18 years after signing a contract on a second
science writer, has followed their work and, following a edition of On Growth and Form, Thompson received a
popular paper [3], his debut science book In the Beat of a letter from his publisher with the remark ‘I must warn
Heart explores the quest for general laws on metabolism you that you have already slightly exceeded the correction
and growth. allowance . . .’. I find it less diverting to hear that my
contemporaries always buy lots of beer when they go on
Corresponding author: van der Meer, J. (jaap.vander.meer@hetnet.nl). a field trip or that they are ‘foaming at the mouth of
Available online 9 May 2007. excitement’ when they discuss their own ideas. But this
55
www.sciencedirect.com
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 1
¿Qué es una especie? Esta cuestión fundamental debe ser respondida antes de que el
proceso de formación de las especies pueda ser investigado. Como cualquier vistazo general
a la literatura evolutiva rápidamente revelará, existen muchas definiciones de especie. Estas
diferentes definiciones reflejan los diversos tipos de preguntas evolutivas y/o de organismos
con los cuales sus autores estaban principalmente interesados. En consecuencia, un concepto
de especie sólo puede ser evaluado en términos de una meta o propósito particular. Mi meta
es entender la especiación como un proceso genético evolutivo. Una asunción fundamental
tras esta meta es que para la especiación, independientemente de una definición precisa de
especie, lo mejor es una aproximación mecanística examinando las fuerzas evolutivas que
operan sobre los individuos dentro de poblaciones o subpoblaciones y siguiendo sus efectos
hacia arriba hasta que en último término causen que todos los miembros de esa población o
subpoblación adquieran atributos fenotípicos que le confieran al grupo el status de especie.
Este énfasis en los mecanismos evolutivos genéticos que operan dentro de las
poblaciones de individuos ubica completamente a la especiación dentro del dominio de la
genética de poblaciones. De acuerdo con esto, lo que se requiere es un concepto de especie
que pueda ser relacionado directamente con el marco mecanístico de la genética de
poblaciones. Para alcanzar esta meta, repasaré en primer lugar tres conceptos de especie que
poseen fuertes partidarios en la literatura actual: el concepto evolutivo de especie, el
concepto biológico de especie, y el concepto de especie de reconocimiento. Todos estos
conceptos de especie consideran a las especies como entidades biológicas reales e intentan
definir a las especies en términos de alguna propiedad biológica fundamental. En este
aspecto, todas estas definiciones son conceptos biológicos de especie, aunque una de ellas es
referida usualmente como ‘el concepto biológico de especie’. Dado que ‘el concepto
biológico de especie’ define a las especies en términos de mecanismos de aislamiento, es
mejor conocida como el concepto de aislamiento (Patterson, 1985). La terminología de
Patterson será utilizada en el resto de este capítulo.
Luego de revisar los puntos fuertes y los débiles de estos tres conceptos, propondré
un cuarto concepto biológico de especie, el concepto de cohesión, el cual intenta utilizar los
puntos fuertes de los otros tres mientras evita sus puntos débiles con respecto a la meta de
definir las especies de una forma que sea compatible con el marco mecanístico de la
genética de poblaciones. De esta manera, puede lograrse una definición de especie que
ilumine, en vez de oscurecer o desencaminar, a los mecanismos de especiación y a sus
consecuencias genéticas.
Bajo esta definición, una especie consiste en una población o grupo de poblaciones
que comparten un destino evolutivo común a través del tiempo. Esta definición tiene la
ventaja de ser aplicable tanto a grupos vivientes como a grupos extintos y a organismos
sexuados y asexuados. Además, pone énfasis en el hecho de que una unidad de especie
puede mantenerse unida no sólo a través del flujo génico sino también a través de
restricciones del desarrollo, genéticas y ecológicas. Finalmente, este concepto es útil debido
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
56
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 2
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
57
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 3
Paterson (1985) ha argumentado fuertemente que esta confusión puede ser evitada
viendo a los así llamados mecanismos de aislamiento desde otra perspectiva. Por ejemplo,
considérense los mecanismos de aislamiento precopulatorios listados en la Tabla 1. En la
literatura evolutiva es común hallar afirmaciones de que complejos rituales de cortejo,
señales para el apareamiento, etc. funcionan como barreras de aislamiento precopulatorias
que existen para impedir la hibridación con otras especies. Los trabajos de Dobzhansky
(1970) indican cuán dominante era esta idea en el pensamiento de uno de los principales
arquitectos y proponentes del concepto biológico de especie. No obstante, como Tinbergen
(1953) señaló, tales mecanismos precopulatorios tienen varias funciones además del
aislamiento: la supresión o escape del comportamiento agresivo en el animal cortejado, la
sincronización de las actividades del apareamiento, la persuasión de la pareja potencial para
continuar con el cortejo, la coordinación en el tiempo y en el espacio del patrón de
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
58
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 4
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
59
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 5
aislamiento porque éstos podían evolucionar por razones distintas al aislamiento, sus
mecanismos ‘de fertilización’ de igual forma pueden evolucionar por razones distintas a la
fertilización.
Puede hacerse otra crítica menor al concepto de Paterson (Templeton, 1987), pero
deseo concentrarme en dos dificultades serias y fundamentales que comparten ambos
conceptos, el de aislamiento y el de reconocimiento. Como muchos otros problemas en el
mundo biológico, estos problemas son causados por el sexo -o demasiado, o demasiado
poco.
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
60
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 6
Demasiado sexo.
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
61
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 7
recombinación genética es obviamente mayor que la especie taxonómica y que los grupos
que se comportan como entidades evolutivamente independientes. Una solución es
simplemente negar el status de especie de los miembros del grupo de especies singámicas.
Por ejemplo, Grant (1981) se refiere a los miembros del grupo de las especies singámicas
como ‘semiespecies’. Bajo el concepto de reconocimiento, el propio grupo de especies
singámicas sería la especie, dado que la definición de especie singámica de Grant es
virtualmente idéntica a la definición de especie de Paterson (1985). Sin embargo, los
botánicos no han tomado estas decisiones taxonómicas arbitrariamente. Las especies dentro
de un grupo singámico son a menudo unidades reales en términos de morfología, ecología,
genética y evolución. Por ejemplo, el registro fósil indica que dos especies de álamos
americanos (los ‘balsam poplars’ y los ‘cottonwoods’, ambos del género Populus) han
divergido hace al menos 12 millones de años y han generado híbridos a lo largo de este
período (Eckenwalder, 1984). Aún cuando los híbridos se encuentran muy extendidos, son
fértiles y antiguos, estas especies de árboles poseen y mantienen una cohesión genética,
fenotípica y ecológica entre ellas y una distinción que las separa y se han mantenido como
linajes evolutivos distintivos por al menos 12 millones de años (Eckenwalder, 1984). Por
tanto, estos álamos son unidades biológicas reales que no deberían ser ignoradas.
Es común en los zoólogos reconocer que el concepto de aislamiento posee
dificultades cuando es aplicado a las plantas superiores, exogámicas, pero luego argumentar
que el concepto de aislamiento funciona razonablemente bien para animales multicelulares
que se reproducen sexualmente. Sin embargo, esta visión ya no puede ser sostenida con la
creciente resolución que proveen las técnicas del ADN recombinante. Por ejemplo, en
mamíferos, se están llevando a cabo estudios en mi laboratorio en babuinos, ganado salvaje,
cánidos, roedores subterráneos y ratas, ejemplos, respectivamente, de primates, ungulados,
carnívoros y roedores -los cuatro grupos principales de mamíferos. En cada caso, existe
evidencia de que ocurre hibridación interespecífica en forma natural (Baker et al., 1989;
Davis et al., 1988; datos no publicados). A pesar de la hibridación, muchas de las unidades
taxonómicas dentro de estos grupos representan unidades biológicas reales en el sentido
morfológico, ecológico, genético y evolutivo. Por ejemplo, los lobos y los coyotes pueden
formar híbridos, y de hecho lo hacen. No obstante, son bastante distinguibles
morfológicamente unos de otros, poseen comportamientos extremadamente diferentes en
términos de estructura social y caza, y representan linajes evolutivos distintivos con
diferencias genéticas diagnósticas (Figura 1). Además, el registro fósil indica que han
evolucionado como linajes distintivos y continuos por al menos 0,5 millones de años (Hall,
1978) y quizás por tanto tiempo como 2 millones de años (Nowak, 1978). Aunque estos taxa
no satisfacen el criterio del concepto de especie por aislamiento, Hall (1978) argumenta que
son grupos biológicamente reales y que el status de especie es claramente apropiado.
Las especies singámicas animales no se encuentran de ninguna manera limitadas a
los mamíferos. Drosophila heteroneura y D. silvestris son dos especies hawaianas de
Drosophila con las cuales hemos trabajado. Aunque son filogenéticamente muy cercanas y
en gran medida simpátridas en la isla de Hawaii (Carson, 1978), son extremadamente
distinguibles morfológicamente, siendo la diferencia más dramática que silvestris posee una
cabeza redonda y heteroneura una cabeza con forma de martillo (Val, 1977). Pueden ser
hibridadas en el laboratorio, y los híbridos y los F2 y retrocruzamientos subsiguientes son
completamente fértiles y viables (Val, 1977; Templeton, 1977; Ahearn y Templeton, 1989).
Debido a que la morfología de los híbridos es conocida gracias a estos estudios de
laboratorio, Kaneshiro y Val (1977) fueron capaces de descubrir que la hibridación
interespecífica ocurre en la naturaleza. Nuestros estudios moleculares (DeSalle y Templeton,
1987) confirmaron que los híbridos realmente se forman en la naturaleza, y, lo que es más,
que estos híbridos pueden retrocruzarse, y de hecho lo hacen, hasta tal punto que un
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
62
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 8
Ahora es posible una nueva definición biológica de especie, la que llamo el concepto
cohesivo de especie. La especie en el concepto cohesivo es la población más inclusiva de
individuos que poseen el potencial para la cohesión fenotípica a través de mecanismos
intrínsecos de cohesión (Tabla 2). Trataré ahora sobre el significado de este concepto de
especie, mostrando cómo toma partes prestadas de los conceptos evolutivo, de aislamiento y
de reconocimiento, mientras que evita sus serios defectos.
Al igual que el concepto evolutivo de especie, el concepto cohesivo de especie define
a la especie en términos de cohesión genética y fenotípica. Como consecuencia, el concepto
de cohesión comparte con el concepto evolutivo su fortaleza de poder ser aplicable a los taxa
que se reproducen asexualmente (o por intermedio de otros sistemas cerrados o casi cerrados
de apareamiento), y a los taxa que pertenecen a grupos singámicos. Al contrario que el
concepto evolutivo de especie, el concepto de cohesión define a las especies en términos de
los mecanismos que producen la cohesión más que de la manifestación de la cohesión en el
tiempo evolutivo. Este es un enfoque mecanístico similar al que toma el concepto de
aislamiento, si bien en este caso el foco se encuentra sobre mecanismos de cohesión en vez
de mecanismos de aislamiento. Al definir una especie en términos de mecanismos de
cohesión, el concepto cohesivo puede ser fácilmente relacionado con un marco mecanístico
de genética de poblaciones y puede guiar en la comprensión de la especiación como proceso
evolutivo. En particular, la especiación es ahora considerada como la evolución de los
mecanismos de cohesión (como opuestos a los mecanismos de aislamiento). Esto significa
también que el concepto de cohesión se centra principalmente en los taxa vivientes más que
en los taxa fósiles.
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
63
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 9
Como fue señalado por Paterson (1985), es útil definir los mecanismos subyacentes
al status de especie de tal forma que las definiciones reflejen la función evolutiva más
probable de los mecanismos durante el proceso de especiación. De acuerdo con esto, los
mecanismos de cohesión serán definidos para que reflejen su función evolutiva más
probable. La tarea básica es identificar esos mecanismos de cohesión que contribuyen a
mantener a un grupo como un linaje evolutivo. La esencia misma de un linaje evolutivo
desde una perspectiva de la genética poblacional es que nuevas variantes genéticas pueden
surgir en él, extenderse, y reemplazar a las variantes viejas. Estos eventos suceden por
intermedio de las fuerzas microevolutivas estándar como el flujo génico, la deriva genética,
y/o la selección natural. El hecho de que las variantes génicas presentes en un linaje
evolutivo puedan ser rastreadas hasta un ancestro común significa también que los
individuos que componen este linaje deben mostrar un alto grado de relacionamiento
genético. Los mecanismos de cohesión que definen el status de especie son, por tanto,
aquellos que promueven el relacionamiento genético y que determinan las fronteras
poblacionales de la acción de las fuerzas microevolutivas.
Los conceptos de aislamiento y de reconocimiento se centran exclusivamente en el
relacionamiento genético promovido a través del intercambio de genes vía reproducción
sexual. Estas definiciones han elevado a una única fuerza microevolutiva -el flujo génico-
como criterio concluyente y exclusivo del status de especie. No hay ninguna duda de que el
flujo génico es una de las principales fuerzas microevolutivas, y por tanto los factores que
definen los límites de dispersión de las nuevas variantes génicas a través del flujo génico son
criterios válidos para el status de especie. De acuerdo con esto, la intercambiabilidad
genética se incluye en la Tabla 2 como una importante clase de mecanismos de cohesión. La
intercambiabilidad genética se refiere simplemente a la capacidad de intercambiar genes por
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
64
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 10
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
65
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 11
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
66
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 12
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
67
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 13
de los mecanismos de cohesión más importantes que mantienen a las especies dentro de
grupos singámicos, como es demostrado por lo que sucede dentro de estos grupos cuando
las restricciones se alteran. Por ejemplo, bajo la mayoría de las condiciones ambientales, los
robles rojos y negros viven juntos en los mismos bosques y desarrollan polinización
cruzada. No obstante, pqermanecen como dos poblaciones distintas y cohesivas, debido a
que las bellotas híbridas de la F1 no germinan bien bajo las condiciones oscuras y frescas de
un bosque maduro. Cuando un bosque es parcialmente aclarado y raleado (principalmente
por la acción humana), las bellotas de los robles rojos y las de los robles negros germinan
mal, mientras que las bellotas híbridas lo hacen muy bien. Como resultado, muchos bosques
actuales consisten en una intergradación continua entre robles negros y rojos. Por tanto, la
cohesión normal de las poblaciones de robles rojos y negros se pierde cuando las
restricciones ecológicas son alteradas.
Las resticciones ecológicas son también importantes en los taxa asexuales debido a
que éstas restricciones a menudo determinan los límites poblacionales de la fijación
selectiva, lo cual es, como se mencionó previamente, un importante mecanismo de cohesión
en los taxa con sistemas cerrados de reproducción. Además, el trabajo de Roughgarden
(1972) predice que las poblaciones asexuales pueden desarrollar amplitudes de nichos más
nítidamente delimitadas de lo que podrían las poblaciones sexuales equivalentes. Esta
propiedad puede contribuir a explicar el hecho de que las especies asexuales sean más
fácilmente reconocibles que las especies sexuales (Holman, 1987).
Las restricciones del desarrollo constituyen la segunda clase de mecanismos de
cohesión relacionados al destino de la variación heredable en las transiciones adaptativas.
Cuando existe una fuerte selección sobre detrminado rasgo, la pleiotropía (una forma de
restricción del desarrollo) se asegura de que otros rasgos también evolucionen. Por tanto, la
pleiotropía puede facilitar los cambios evolutivos que de otra forma no ocurrirían. Aunque
muchos investigadores han puesto énfasis en la naturaleza no adaptativa, incluso mal
adaptativa, de estos cambios pleiotrópicamente inducidos, Wagner (1988) ha mostrado que
la pleiotropía es esencial para la evolución de rasgos adaptativos complejos. Examinó un
modelo en el cual la eficacia darwiniana depende de los estados simultáneos de varios rasgos
y luego contrastó modelos de evolución adaptativa en los cuales todos los rasgos eran
genéticamente independientes (no había pleiotropía ni restricciones del desarrollo) con un
modelo al cual se le imponían restricciones del desarrollo. Halló que, cuando no hay
restricciones del desarrollo, la tasa de evolución adaptativa decrece dramáticamente a
medida que aumenta el número de caracteres involucrados en la integración funcional. Por
tanto, las restricciones del desarrollo y la pleiotropía parecen ser necesarias para la evolución
de fenotipos funcionalmente integrados.
Aún más evolución adaptativa puede ser facilitada incluso cuando la adaptación
primaria induce efectos pleiotrópicos que son no adaptativos. Este fenómeno puede ser
ilustrado por las adaptaciones a la malaria en humanos (Templeton, 1982). Las adaptaciones
primarias a la malaria (tales como la condición falciforme) a menudo inducen efectos
pleiotrópicos altamente deletéreos (como la anemia), los cuales, a su vez, generan procesos
adaptativos secundarios en modificadores para disminuir o eliminar los efectos deletéreos
(tales como la persistencia de la hemoglobina fetal para suprimir la anemia). De esta forma
una sóla transición adaptativa puede disparar una cascada de transiciones secundarias, las
cuales se acumulan y pueden tener un gran impacto en la intercambiabilidad demográfica.
Otro mecanismo de cohesión que restringe el destino evolutivo de la variabilidad
fenotípica es la restricción histórica. La evolución es un proceso histórico y, en
consecuencia, el potencial evolutivo de un linaje está modelado por sus transiciones
adaptativas pasadas. Por ejemplo; un prerequisito para la evolución de la coloración
aposemática en insectos con larvas gregarias es la evolución de la mala palatabilidad. Sin la
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
68
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 14
existencia previa del sabor desagradable, no hay fuerza selectiva a favor de la coloración de
advertencia dentro de la progenie (Templeton, 1979). Por tanto, la adaptación del mal sabor
es una restricción histórica para la evolución de la coloración aposemática y las larvas
gregarias. Esta predicción fue puesta a prueba recientemente por Sillen-Tullberg (1988),
quien mostró a través de un análisis filogenético que en todos los casos en los que la
resolución era posible, el mal sabor evolucionó previamente a la evolución de larvas
gregarias y aposemáticas. Como muestra este ejemplo, una adaptación puede hacer que una
segunda sea más probable, reforzando así la cohesión del linaje que comparte estas
transiciones adaptativas.
Las restricciones de la genética de poblaciones también limitan el destino evolutivo
de la nueva variabilidad fenotípica. Estas restricciones emergen de la interacción de la
estructura poblacional (sistema de apareamiento, tamaño poblacional, subdivisión
poblacional) con la arquitectura genética subyacente a los rasgos seleccionados (la relación
genotipo-fenotipo, número de loci, relaciones de ligamiento, etc.). Por ejemplo, en 1924
Haldane mostró que los genes dominantes selectivamente favorecidos son mucho más
probables de ser fijados que los genes recesivos selectivamente favorecidos en las
poblaciones con apareamientos al azar. Sin embargo, esta restricción desaparece si el
sistema de apareamiento cambia desde apareamientos al azar hacia la endogamia
(Templeton, 1982). De este modo, una alteración del sistema de apareamiento puede alterar
la cohesión genética y fenotípica de una población haciendo que clases enteras de
variabilidad genética nueva respondan a la selección natural.
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
69
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 15
domina la intercambiabilidad genética porque los factores que determinan los límites del
flujo génico también limitan la acción de la deriva y la selección en las poblaciones
mendelianas exogámicas. En este dominio, los conceptos de aislamiento y de
reconocimiento son válidos, y por tanto, ambos constituyen casos especiales del concepto
cohesivo más general de especie. Finalmente, si nos movemos hacia el extremo del contínuo
de los grupos singámicos, decrece la importancia de la intercambiabilidad genética en
relación a las restricciones ecológicas que definen la intercambiabilidad demográfica.
Esta continuidad en la aplicación del concepto de cohesión es consistente con la
realidad biológica de que existe un continuo en el grado de apertura genética de los sistemas
de reproducción que se encuentran en el mundo orgánico. Esta es una ventaja tremenda
sobre los conceptos de aislamiento y de reconocimiento que son aplicables sólo al rango
medio de este continuo reproductivo y que tratan con el resto del rango o bien negando la
existencia de especies fuera de este rango (por ejemplo, Vrba, 1985) o utilizando conceptos
de especies cualitativamente distintos (por ejemplo, Mayr, 1970) para imponerle al continuo
reproductivo un carácter discreto artificial.
Otro punto fuerte del concepto de cohesión es que clarifica lo que se quiere decir con
una ‘buena especie’ y la naturaleza de las dificultades que pueden ocurrir con los conceptos
de aislamiento y de reconocimiento. Las ‘buenas especies’ son consideradas generalmente
como taxa geográficamente cohesivos que pueden coexistir por largos períodos de tiempo
sin ninguna ruptura en su integridad genética. El hecho de que no haya ruptura en la
integridad genética a pesar de la simpatría implica la falta de intercambiabilidad genética
entre los taxa. Sin embargo, la condición de coexistencia prolongada también implica que
poseen nichos ecológicos diferentes (Mayr, 1970). Luego, las ‘buenas especies’ son aquellas
que se encuentran bien definidas tanto por la intercambiabilidad genética como por la
demográfica. (En forma similar, los miembros de un taxón superior ‘bueno’ carecen tanto de
intercambiabilidad genética como demográfica.) Dada esta definición de ‘buena especie’,
hay dos maneras principales de desviarse de este ideal. Una sucede cuando las fronteras
poblacionales definidas por la intercambiabilidad genética son más estrechas que las
definidas por la intercambiabilidad demográfica. Este es precisamente el problema de los
taxa asexuales previamente discutido. La otra forma de desviación sucede cuando las
fronteras definidas por la intercambiabilidad genética son mayores que las definidas por la
intercambiabilidad demográfica -en otras palabras, el problema propuesto por las especies
singámicas. Por tanto, estos dos problemas aparentemente tan dispares bajo los conceptos de
aislamiento y de reconocimiento poseen de hecho un causa subyacente común: las fronteras
definidas por la intercambiabilidad demográfica son diferentes de las definidas por la
intercambiabilidad genética.
La especiación es generalmente un proceso, no un evento (Templeton, 1981).
Mientras el proceso esté ocurriendo, la tendencia es a tener ‘malas’ especies. Aunque los
taxa asociados con este proceso incompleto de especiación son la perdición para el
taxónomo, proveen la mejor visión dentro de la especiación. Al proveer una definición
precisa de ‘mala especie’ (el conflicto entre la intercambiabilidad genética y la
demográfica), el concepto de cohesión es una herramienta útil para obtener una visión
profunda dentro del proceso de especiación. Las ‘malas especies’ ya no deben ser
consideradas como un diverso grupo de casos especiales; más bien, el concepto de cohesión
provee los medios para ver los patrones observados en estos taxa problemáticos. Por
ejemplo, Levene (1953) postuló un modelo hace mucho tiempo en el cual diferentes
genotipos desarrollaban diferentes eficacias darwinianas en nichos demográficamente
independientes. Sin embargo, en este modelo, hay intercambiabilidad genética completa y
aún hay suficiente intercambiabilidad demográfica entre todos los genotipos dentro de los
varios nichos realizados (a través del desplazamiento selectivo dentro del nicho) que se trata
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
70
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 16
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
71
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 17
ESPECIACIÓN
RESUMEN
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
72
Lecturas traducidas. Laboratorio de Evolución, Facultad de Ciencias ______________________________________ 18
-------------------------------------------------------------
Templeton, A.. 1989.The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. En Speciation
and its consequenes editado por D. Otte y J. Endler. Sianuer, Sunderland
73
74
75
76
SEMINARIO II: MECANISMOS DE AISLAMIENTO Y
MODELOS DE ESPECIACIÓN
Marcela Rodriguero & Abel Carcagno
En este seminario se analizarán dos modelos de especiación vinculados a distintos
Mecanismos de Aislamiento Reproductivo (MARs) por medio de la discusión de dos casos
particulares: el modelo de especiación infecciosa y el modelo de especiación simpátrica.
Preguntas Introductorias
1‐ ¿Qué son los Mecanismos de Aislamiento Reproductivo (MARs) y qué concepto de especie
los contempla? Clasifíquelos y de ejemplos.
2‐ ¿Cuál es la clasificación de los procesos especiogénicos de acuerdo con la escala
geográfica en la que se producen?
Modelo I: Especiación infecciosa
• Wade M.J. (2001) Infectious speciation. Nature 409: 675‐677.
• Bordenstein S.R., O’Hara F.P. & Werren J.H. (2001) Wolbachia – induced incompatibility
precedes other Irbid incompatibilities in Nasonia. Nature 409: 707‐ 710.
3‐ ¿La especiación infecciosa es un evento especiogénico dirigido por el hospedador o por el
parásito? ¿Cuáles serían las implicancias evolutivas de cada caso?
4‐ ¿Considera que la incompatibilidad citoplasmática unidireccional podría conducir al
aislamiento reproductivo?
5‐ ¿Cuáles son las diferencias entre el modelo génico y el infeccioso planteado en la figura 2
del trabajo de Wade?
6‐ ¿Cuáles son las hipótesis de trabajo de Bordenstein y colaboradores? Exprese su
respuesta en términos de hipótesis nula y alternativa.
7‐ ¿Qué concepto de especie las sustentan?
8‐ Analice la figura 1. A partir de estos resultados obtenidos ¿es posible refutar la hipótesis
nula?
9‐ ¿Qué aproximaciones experimentales utilizaron posteriormente los autores para sostener
su argumento? ¿Qué tipos de MARs analizaron a través de ellas y cómo incidieron los
resultados en las hipótesis de trabajo (i.e. nula y altenativa)?
10‐ ¿Qué crítica podría realizar al sistema bajo estudio?
77
Modelo II: Especiación simpátrica
• Linn C., Feder J.L., Nojima S., Dambroski S.H., Berlocher S.H. & Roelofs W (2003) Fruit odor
discrimination and sypatric host formaion in Rhagoletis. PNAS 100: 11490‐11493.
11‐ ¿Cuáles son los rasgos de Rhagoletis pomonella que la señalan como una especie
adecuada para el estudio de la especiación simpátrica?
12‐ Desde el punto de vista aislacionista propugnado por Mayr y Dobzhansky ¿qué tipo de
MARs esperaría que tuvieran mayor incidencia en la especiación simpátrica? Señale los
supuestos del modelo.
13‐ ¿Qué tipo de estímulo podrían utilizar las razas de R. pomonella para distinguir a su
hospedador? Vincule esta respuesta a los supuestos enunciados anteriormente.
14‐ Analice cuidadosamente la figura 1. ¿Qué conclusión extrae ante cada estímulo
presentado a las razas bajo estudio?
15‐ ¿Existe consenso entre los resultados obtenidos bajo condiciones de laboratorio y los
obtenidos a partir de condiciones naturales?
16‐ ¿La capacidad de discriminación de la especie hospedadora por parte de la raza de la
manzana sería una característica derivada o primitiva? ¿Cómo arribaron los investigadores a
este resultado?
Preguntas unificadoras
17‐ ¿Cómo describiría un modelo de especiación por aislamiento geográfico? Suponiendo
que antes de completarse el aislamiento reproductivo se restableciera el flujo génico y que
los grupos previamente aislados produjeran una F1... ¿qué ocurriría si esa F1 tuviera menor
fitness que ambos parentales? ¿Qué pasaría si esa F1 tuviera mayor fitness que sus
parentales?
18‐ ¿Considera posible revertir la aparición de los MARs? ¿Por qué?
78
Coyne, J. A. & Orr, H. A. 2004. Speciation. Sinauer, Sunderland, MA. Clasificación
de los mecanismos de aislamiento reproductivo (MARs)
79
Ridley, M. 2004. Evolution. 3rd Edition. Blackwell Publishing. Malden, MA.
Reproductive isolation is the main The crucial event for the origin of a new species is reproductive isolation. As we saw in
topic in research on speciation Chapter 13, the members of a species usually differ genetically, ecologically, and in their
behavior and morphology (that is, phenetically) from other species, as well as in who
they will interbreed with. Some biologists prefer to define species not by reproductive
isolation but by other properties, such as genetic or ecological differences. Probably no
single property can provide a universal species definition, applicable to all animals,
plants, and microorganisms. However, many species do differ by being reproductively
isolated, and even if the evolution of reproductive isolation is not always the crucial
event in speciation, it is certainly the key event in research on speciation. The topic of
this chapter is the evolution of reproductive isolation. The aim is to understand how a
barrier to interbreeding can evolve between two populations, such that one species
evolves into two.
Reproductive isolation can be caused by many features of organisms (see Table 13.1,
p. 356). However, for most of the research in this chapter, we only need a distinction
between prezygotic and postzygotic isolation. Prezygotic isolation exists when, for
instance, two species have different courtship or mate choices, or different breeding
seasons. Postzygotic isolation exists when two species do interbreed, but their hybrid
offspring have low viability or fertility. Some of the theories of speciation apply only to
prezygotic isolation, some only to postzygotic isolation, and some to both.
We can start with a distinction between different geographic conditions in the speciat-
ing populations. If a new species evolves in geographic isolation from its ancestor, the
Speciating populations can have process is called allopatric speciation. If the new species evolves in a geographically con-
various kinds of geographic tiguous population, it is called parapatric speciation. If the new species evolves within
relations the geographic range of its ancestor, it is called sympatric speciation (Figure 14.1). The
distinctions between these three kinds of speciation can blur, but we shall begin the
chapter with the most important of the three processes: allopatric speciation. Almost
all biologists accept that allopatric speciation occurs. The importance of parapatric and
sympatric speciation are more in doubt, and we shall come on to them later.
In allopatric speciation, new species evolve when one (or more) population of a
species becomes separated from the other populations of the species, in the manner of
Figure 14.1a. This kind of event often happens in nature. For example, a species could
split into two separate populations if a physical barrier divided its geographic range.
The barrier could be something like a new mountain range, or river, cutting through
the formerly continuous population. Or the intermediate populations of a species
may be driven extinct, perhaps by a local disease outbreak, leaving the geographically
80
..
CHAPTER 14 / Speciation 383
(a)
Space
Time
(b)
Figure 14.1
Three main theoretical types of speciation can be distinguished
according to the geographic relations of the ancestral species
(c) and the newly evolving species. (a) In allopatric speciation the
new species forms geographically apart from its ancestor;
(b) in parapatric speciation the new species forms in a contiguous
population; and (c) in sympatric speciation a new species emerges
from within the geographic range of its ancestor.
extreme populations cut off from each other. Or a subpopulation may migrate (actively
or passively) to a new place, outside the range of the ancestral species, such as when a
few individuals colonize an island away from the mainland. Such a population, at the
edge of the main range of a species, is called a “peripheral isolate.”
Geographic separation alone is not One way or another, a species can become geographically subdivided, consisting of a
reproductive isolation number of populations between which gene flow has been cut off. This is not, in itself,
an isolating barrier in the sense of Table 13.1 (p. 356). An isolating barrier is an evolved
property of a species that prevents interbreeding. When two populations are geograph-
ically cut off, gene flow ceases but only because members of the population do not
meet. The two populations have not yet evolved a genetic difference. The evolution of
an isolating barrier requires some new character, such as a new courtship song, to
evolve in at least one of the populations a a new character that has the effect of prevent-
ing gene flow. In the theory of allopatric speciation, the cessation of gene flow between
allopatric populations leads, over time, to the evolution of intrinsic isolating barriers
between the populations. Let us see what happens to the reproductive isolation
between these populations over evolutionary time.
We have two main kinds of evidence that reproductive isolation evolves when
geographically separate populations are evolving apart. One comes from laboratory
experiments and the other comes from biogeographic observations.
81
..
CHAPTER 14 / Speciation 409
populations. Within one population, natural selection will not favor a genetic change
that is incompatible with genes at other loci.
Prezygotic isolation, however, does not require incompatible genetic change at sev-
eral loci. Prezygotic isolation can evolve as a by-product of divergence if the characters
that have diverged between populations are genetically correlated with characters caus-
ing prezygotic isolation. This theory is less strongly tied to the theory of allopatric spe-
ciation. The process can indeed occur between populations that are separately evolving
in different places. But adaptive divergence can also occur within one population, as we
shall see, and that at least raises the possibility that speciation could occur non-
allopatrically.
Reinforcement works in sympatry The other theory was reinforcement. Reinforcement only occurs in sympatry.
Natural selection only favors discrimination among potential mates for the range of
mates that are present in a particular place. The theory of reinforcement is only weakly
tied to the theory of allopatric speciation. Indeed, it is hardly an allopatric theory of
speciation at all. Reinforcement was only used in the allopatric theory to “finish off ”
speciation that was incomplete in allopatry.
Thus, in the theories we have met so far, speciation in non-allopatric populations
is relatively unlikely. One well supported theory, the Dobzhansky–Muller theory, is
allopatric. Reinforcement is a sympatric process, but (as we saw) little supported by
evidence and problematic in theory. However, non-allopatric speciation has not been
ruled out, and in the next two sections we shall look some more at whether speciation
could occur parapatrically or sympatrically.
82
..
410 PART 4 / Evolution and Diversity
C. cornix
C. corone
Figure 14.13
Hybrid zone between the carrion crow (Cornix corone) and
hooded crow (C. cornix) in Europe. Here the two crows are
shown as two separate species, but some taxonomists classify
them as subspecies. Redrawn, by permission of the publisher,
from Mayr (1963). © 1963 President and Fellows of Harvard
College.
because the hooded crow is gray with a black head and tail, whereas the carrion crow is
black all over. The two species (or near species) are now known to differ in many other
respects too. The fact that the crows interbreed in the hybrid zone means that speci-
ation between them is incomplete. We shall meet some more examples of hybrid zones
in Section 17.4 (p. 497).
The conditions in a hybrid zone (or a stepped cline) are particularly ripe for
Many hybrid zones are tension speciation if it is a tension zone. A tension zone exists when the hybrids between the
zones . . . forms on either side of the boundary are selectively disadvantageous. (A hybrid zone
is not a tension zone if the hybrids have intermediate, or superior, fitness to the
pure forms.) For instance, if one homozygote (AA) is adapted to one environment,
and another homozygote (aa) to another environment, heterozygotes (Aa) will be
produced where the two environments meet up. If the heterozygotes are disadvant-
ageous, the meeting place is an example of a tension zone. Most known hybrid zones
are in fact tension zones (see, for example, Barton & Hewitt’s (1985) review of
170 hybrid zones).
. . . in which reinforcement may In a tension zone, the conditions are exactly the preconditions for reinforcement
operate (Section 14.6.1). Matings within a type are advantageous, and matings between types
produce disadvantageous hybrids. Natural selection favors assortative mating. We can
therefore imagine a sequence where a stepped cline initially evolves, and then becomes
distinct enough to count as a hybrid zone. We are near the border of the origin of a new
species. Reinforcement could then finish speciation off, eliminating hybridization
from the hybrid zone. That sequence of events constitutes parapatric speciation.
The strong point of the theory of parapatric speciation is that the environment
“stabilizes” the preconditions for reinforcement. We saw that these conditions are
liable to autodestruct, as the two forms interbreed, or as one eliminates the other. But
if the environment varies in space, the clinal variation will be maintained. Parapatric
speciation could work, in theory.
83
..
CHAPTER 14 / Speciation 411
In sympatric speciation, a species splits into two without any separation of the ancestral
species’ geographic range (see Figure 14.1). Sympatric speciation has been a source of
recurrent controversy for a century or so. Mayr (1942, 1963) particularly cast doubt on
it, and in doing so has stimulated others to look for evidence and to work out the theor-
etical conditions under which it may be possible.
In the theory of parapatric speciation, the initial stage in speciation is a spatial
polymorphism (or stepped cline). In sympatric speciation, the initial stage is a poly-
morphism that does not depend on space within a population. For instance, two forms
of a species may be adapted to eat different foods. If matings between the two are dis-
advantageous, because hybrids have low fitness, reinforcement will operate between
84
..
412 PART 4 / Evolution and Diversity
them. Most models of sympatric speciation suppose that natural selection initially
establishes a polymorphism, and then selection favors prezygotic isolation between
the polymorphic forms. “Host shifts” in a fly called Rhagoletis pomonella provide a case
study that may illustrate part of the process.
The apple maggot fly has only Rhagoletis pomonella is a tephritid fly and a pest of apples. It lays its eggs in apples
recently moved on to apples and the maggot then ruins the fruit, but this was not always so. In North America,
R. pomonella’s native larval resource is the hawthorn. Only in 1864 were these species
first found on apples. Since then it has expanded through the orchards of North
America, and has also started to exploit cherries, pears, and roses. These moves to new
food plants are called host shifts. In the host shift of R. pomonella, speciation may be
happening before our eyes.
The R. pomonella on the different hosts are currently different genetic races. Females
prefer to lay their eggs in the kind of fruit they grew up in: females isolated as they
emerge from apples will later choose to lay eggs in apples, given a choice in the labor-
atory. Likewise, adult males tend to wait on the host species that they grew up in, and
mating takes place on the fruit before the females oviposit. Thus there is assortative
mating: male flies from apples mate with females from apples, males from hawthorn
with females from hawthorn.
The races on apples show some The races are presumably about 140 generations old (given that they first moved on
isolation from the ancestral races to apples nearly one and a half centuries ago). Is this long enough for genetic differences
on hawthorn between the races to have built up? Gel electrophoresis shows that the two races have
evolved extensive differences in their enzymes. They also differ genetically in their
development time: maggots in apples develop in about 40 days, whereas hawthorn
maggots develop in 55–60 days. This difference also acts to increase the reproductive
isolation between the races, because the adults of the two races are not active at the
same time.
Apples and hawthorns differ and selection will therefore probably favor different
characters in each race; this may be the reason for their divergence. If it is, selection may
also favor prezygotic isolation and speciation. If flies from the different races are put
together in the lab, however, they mate together indiscriminately. Either reinforcement
has not operated when it might have been expected, or, alternatively, the differences in
behavior and development time in the field may be enough to reduce interbreeding
to the level natural selection favors. Selection would then not be acting to reinforce
the degree of prezygotic isolation. We do not know which interpretation is correct;
we need to know more about the forces maintaining the genetic differences between
the races. Once again, the evidence for reinforcement is the weak point in a theory of
speciation.
But the example is incomplete In the case of host shifts, we can be practically certain that the initial host shift, and
formation of a new race, has happened in sympatry. The shift took place in historic
time. However, it is not a full example of sympatric speciation because the races have
not fully speciated. Indeed, we do not know whether they will, or whether the current
situation, with incomplete speciation, is stable.
85
..
news and views
the relative production of thorium to urani- to find more examples of such stars, as our
um because these elements are separated by surveys of the Galactic halo with the new
only two atomic numbers. And the different generation of very large telescopes is just
decay rates of 232Th and 238U ensure that the beginning. With new discoveries, more age
abundance ratio of these two elements will estimates will be found, further nailing down
be a sensitive function of their age. Cayrel et the exact age of the Universe. ■
al.1 propose that the neutron-capture mat- Christopher Sneden is in the Department of
erial in the atmosphere of CS31082-001 has Astronomy, University of Texas at Austin, Austin, 100 YEARS AGO
an age of 12.5 Gyr with an uncertainty of 3.3 Texas 78712, USA. Dr. R. A. Daly, of the Department of Geology
Gyr, a more accurate estimate of the age of e-mail: chris@verdi.as.utexas.edu and Geography of Harvard University, is
the Universe. Further analysis of the whole 1. Cayrel, R. et al. Nature 409, 691–692 (2001). endeavouring to organise a geological and
range of neutron-capture elements in this 2. Chaboyer, B. Phys. Rep. 307, 23–30 (1998). geographical excursion in the North Atlantic
3. Beers, T. C., Preston, G. W. & Schectman, S. Astron. J. 103,
star will refine this age estimate, narrowing 1987–2034 (1992).
for the summer of 1901. Conditionally on the
the uncertainty. 4. Butcher, H. R. Nature 328, 127–131 (1987). formation of a sufficiently large party, a
We now know of a handful of stars born 5. Sneden, C. et al. Astrophys. J. 533, L139–L142 (2000). steamer of about 1000 tons, specially
6. Westin, J., Sneden, C., Gustafsson, B. & Cowan, J. J. Astrophys. J.
early in our Galaxy’s history that are anom- 530, 783–799 (2000).
adapted for ice navigation, and capable of
alously enriched in radioactive thorium, and 7. Cowan, J. J. et al. Astrophys. J. 521, 194–205 (1999). accommodating sixty persons, will leave
at least one with uranium. We may expect 8. Goriely, S. & Clerbaux, B. Astron. Astrophys. 346, 798–804 (1999). Boston on or about June 26… The main object
of the voyage will be to offer to the members
of the excursion party opportunity of studying
Evolution the volcanic cones and lava-fields, the
geysers, ice-caves and glaciers of Iceland,
Infectious speciation the fiords and glaciers of the west coast of
Greenland, and the mountains and fiords of
Michael J. Wade Northern Labrador… A hunting party may
take part in the expedition; it could be landed
The bacterium Wolbachia has strange and wonderful effects on for a fortnight or three weeks in Greenland
reproduction in its many invertebrate host species. In effect, the creation and for about the same period in Labrador.
of new species can now be added to the list. From Nature 7 February 1901.
F
or a new species to arise, a single popu- 50 YEARS AGO
lation must somehow be split into two Males Females Surprisingly little of the information obtained
reproductively isolated populations with microscopes has been quantitative; most
that cannot interbreed. Such reproductive observers are content to sit at the microscope
No
isolation usually stems from genetic incom- and regard the image, or to photograph it.
X offspring
patibility. It is easy to see how that arises W+ Theoretically, it is possible to scan the image
W-
when a geographical barrier divides one or its photograph mechanically; but this has
population of an organism into two, which seldom been done in practice. The whole
then diverge genetically. On page 707 of this method of obtaining resolution by lenses
issue, however, Bordenstein, O’Hara and Offspring involves so much loss of light, lack of control
X
Werren1 show that in two species of para- W- W+ of contrast, and other difficulties, that it is
sitoid wasp it is microbial infection that is the difficult to provide a good display or method
barrier to gene exchange. of scanning. Some of these difficulties can be
The microbe concerned, Wolbachia pipi- Offspring avoided by using a wholly different means of
entis, is a member of a highly diverse group of X obtaining resolution and amplification. The
bacteria that is thought to include the ances- W+ W+ essence of the problem of resolution is to
tor of the mitochondrion — the powerhouse separate in some way the light passing
of multicellular organisms that was originally through very close regions of an object. The
free-living. Wolbachia are endosymbionts, Offspring conventional microscope does this by using
X
living inside the cells of certain host organ- W- W-
refraction by lenses to separate the light
isms, and like mitochondria they are almost from neighbouring regions. An alternative
always inherited through the maternal line. method is to use the lens system the other
Their host range is broad, for the bacteria are Figure 1 Wolbachia and cytoplasmic way round, namely, to produce a minute
found in association with about 20–75% of incompatibility. Cytoplasmic incompatibility spot of light. Discrimination between
the insects, crustaceans, mites and nematode means that when a male host infected with neighbouring points is then produced by
worms that have been surveyed with molec- Wolbachia (W& ) mates with an uninfected passing the light through them at different
ular markers2,3. Such is the range of effects female (W1 ), no offspring are produced. All times by making the spot scan it. After
of the microbe on its host — positive and other matings are fully compatible and result in passing through the preparation, the spot is
negative — that it is not always possible to the production of offspring. The consequence made to fall on a photocell, with subsequent
characterize Wolbachia simply as a mutual- of this system is that the maternally transmitted amplifcation and display as required. Such a
ist, symbiont or pathogen. Wolbachia tend to spread through the host flying-spot microscope depends on scanning
Among the variety of reproductive species. different parts at different times, and will
anomalies caused by Wolbachia is the only give accurate information about objects
phenomenon of cytoplasmic incompati- residing in host males are not typically that are stationary or moving only at a rate of
bility (Fig. 1), which results in the failure transmitted to offspring, but they eliminate a different order from that of the spot.
of infected host males and uninfected host competing uninfected maternal lineages From Nature 10 February 1951.
females to produce offspring. Wolbachia from the host population by their incompat-
NATURE | VOL 409 | 8 FEBRUARY 2001 | www.nature.com © 2001 Macmillan Magazines Ltd 675
86
news and views
ible matings. So the bacteria in males are Figure 2 Genetic and infectious models of
a
essential to the spread of their maternally speciation. a, A standard genetic model in which
Ancestral A 0 A 0 B0 B0
transmitted relatives through the host population the initial state is an ancestral population of a
population. Geographically
species that is homozygous at both of two gene
Typical cytoplasmic incompatibility falls isolated loci, and so is A0A0B0B0. Following geographical
daughter A 0 A 0 B0 B0 A 0 A 0 B0 B0
short of speciation because the barrier to populations
isolation, each of two daughter populations is
reproduction between infected and unin- gradually modified as new alleles (A1 and B1)
fected populations works only in one direc- Different arise by mutation and then become fixed in the
mutations
tion, not reciprocally. Although females become fixed genome by random genetic drift and natural
A 1 A 1 B0 B0 A 0 A 0 B1 B1
of the uninfected host population cannot in the genomes selection. Because the A1B1 gene combination
interbreed with males of the infected host causes complete inviability or sterility in
Reproductive
population, the reciprocal cross is fully isolation and hybrids, the daughter populations are new,
Mating results
fertile. But there is evidence4,5 that different speciation because
in inviable or
descendant species. b, Infectious speciation,
of the incompatible
genetic strains of Wolbachia can cause gene combination A1B1 infertile hybrids which parallels the genetic model. The initial
reciprocal, two-way reproductive isolation state is an ancestral species, W1 , not infected
b
between host populations in some parasitoid Uninfected (W-)
with Wolbachia. Two daughter populations
A 0 A 0 B0 B0
wasps, mosquitoes and fruit flies6. This ancestral W-
arise which have become infected by different
observation has led some evolutionary biol- population strains of Wolbachia (A and B) after
ogists to speculate that Wolbachia might Geographically A 0 A 0 B0 B0 A 0 A 0 B0 B0
transmission from a parasite or parasitoid. The
be an agent of infectious speciation6,7. isolated
W- W- different strains then become fixed in each
daughter
Such speculation is controversial, for two populations genome by cytoplasmic incompatibility.
reasons. First, it is widely accepted that, Reciprocal cytoplasmic incompatibility between
Independent
when two host populations become repro- infection and WA males and WB females, and WB males and WA
A 0 A 0 B0 B0 A 0 A 0 B0 B0
ductively isolated, so do the populations of spread of
WA
females, prevents hybridization, so in effect the
Wolbachia WB
their respective endosymbionts. Hence, in a daughter populations are new species even
process called co-speciation, a host may Reproductive though they remain genetically identical to one
cause subsequent speciation of its endo- isolation due to another and to the ancestor.
Reciprocal
Wolbachia
symbionts, an explanation suggested for the infection incompatibility
genetic divergence of strains of Wolbachia8.
The hypothesis of infectious speciation
turns this view on its head. Second, so the
theory goes, speciation occurs when repro- and natural selection operate independently How common might infectious speci-
ductive isolation arises as the incidental on each daughter population. Eventually, ation be? It is not possible to draw a con-
by-product of the gradualistic, genetic one gene undergoes mutation to allele A1, clusion from this single example — which
divergence of two populations. Microbial and becomes fixed in one daughter popu- has of course to be contrasted with the many
speciation, in contrast, might be compara- lation, while a second mutation, to allele B1 examples of genetic speciation10. But there
tively rapid (as seen for instance in polyploid at the other gene, becomes fixed in the sec- are several reasons why it is unlikely to
or hybrid speciation in some plants9), and ond daughter population. The two daughter happen often. First, incomplete cytoplasmic
could occur without any genetic evolution populations become reproductively isolated incompatibility (where incompatible cross-
of the host. Polyploid speciation occurs because matings between them result in the es produce some progeny instead of none)
through a doubling, or more, of chromo- A1B1 deleterious gene combination. In this seems to be more common than complete
some number. classic model, genetic barriers to reproduc- cytoplasmic incompatibility. Reciprocal but
Bordenstein and colleagues1 provide evi- tion and genetic exchange, and so speci- incomplete incompatibility is not a barrier
dence that microbes have acted faster than ation, arise as a by-product of local, gradual to gene flow. Second, genetic models of
genes in producing reproductive isolation evolution. Wolbachia–host coevolution indicate that
between the wasps Nasonia giraulti and N. Microbially driven speciation could the favoured trajectory is from complete
longicornis; this can be taken as the first stage occur in much the same way, stemming from to incomplete cytoplasmic incompatibility.
of speciation. First, the authors showed that cytoplasmic incompatibility between two Finally, we know little of the initial stages of
each wasp harbours a genetically distinct different strains of Wolbachia infecting the Wolbachia infection in natural populations.
strain of Wolbachia that causes cytoplasmic same host species (Fig. 2b). Here, however, When artificially introduced into new hosts,
incompatibility with the other uninfected infectious transmission of incompatible Wolbachia can be difficult to transmit11.
host species. They then used antibiotics to Wolbachia strains, one in each daughter pop- So the experimental results are consistent
create an uninfected strain of each host ulation, replaces the incompatible gene with the scheme outlined in Fig. 2b, but may
species and demonstrated that in Wolbachia- combinations. Predatory mites and para- not reflect the actual historical sequence
free wasps there are no genetic barriers in sitoid wasps are the most likely candidates of events.
first- or second-generation hybrids to free for spreading Wolbachia between different Nevertheless, with the paper by Borden-
interbreeding between the two wasps. species of host. Previous cases of reciprocal stein et al., host speciation can now be
How might these findings fit into a stan- cytoplasmic incompatibility have been added to the list of modifications to repro-
dard genetic model of speciation, as shown between species pairs, which also exhibited duction caused by Wolbachia infection.
in Fig. 2a? In this model, incompatible gene evidence of genetic barriers to gene Given the ubiquity of Wolbachia, infectious
combinations (such as A1B1) cause sterility exchange. Whenever both are present, it is barriers to gene exchange may be much
or inviability of offspring, and so speciation. difficult to determine which — the incom- more common in the early stages of speci-
Events begin with an ancestral species, patible gene combinations or the microbes ation than we realize. ■
A0A0B0B0, that becomes split by geological — came first. The report by Bordenstein Michael J. Wade is in the Department of Biology,
events into two geographically isolated et al. provides evidence that, at least in this Indiana University, Bloomington, Indiana 47405,
daughter populations. The evolutionary case, microbially induced reproductive iso- USA.
forces of mutation, random genetic drift lation preceded genetic isolation. e-mail: mjwade@bio.indiana.edu
676 © 2001 Macmillan Magazines Ltd NATURE | VOL 409 | 8 FEBRUARY 2001 | www.nature.com
87
news and views
1. Bordenstein, S. R., O’Hara, F. P. & Werren, J. H. Nature 409, 6. Hurst, G. D. D. & Schilthuizen, M. Heredity 80, 2–8 (1998). typical values. The first studies from this
707–710 (2001). 7. Thompson, J. N. Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 32, 385–393 (1987). period are now published in a special issue of
2. Werren, J. H., Windsor, D. & Gao, L. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 262, 8. Futuyma, D. J. Evolutionary Biology 541 (Sinauer, Sunderland,
197–204 (1995). MA, 1998). Geophysical Research Letters1.
3. Jeyaprakash, A. & Hoy, M. A. Insect Mol. Biol. 9, 393–405 (2000). 9. Reiseberg, L. H. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 28, 359–389 (1997). When the density dropped, many aspects
4. Wade, M. J., Chang, N. W. & McNaughton, M. Heredity 75, 10. Wu, C. I. & Palopoli, M. F. Annu. Rev. Genet. 28, 283–308 of the magnetosphere’s behaviour were as
453–459 (1995). (1994).
5. Shoemaker, D. D., Katju, V. & Jaenike, J. Evolution 53, 11. Clancy D. J. & Hoffmann, A. A. Am. Nat. 149, 975–988
scientists had predicted, which was a satisfy-
1157–1164 (1999). (1997). ing triumph for current theories. But the
event also had some puzzling characteristics.
Some of these are apparent in the data pre-
Astronomy sented in these initial papers, although not
all are commented on. Others aspects are so
The day the solar wind nearly died intriguing that further study is required.
Earth’s magnetic field is confined to the
Mike Lockwood low-density, high-field magnetosphere by
the dynamic pressure of the solar wind on the
On 11 May 1999, the density of the solar wind dropped almost to zero. side of the Earth facing the Sun, and by ther-
Space scientists are now giving their first reports of this rare opportunity to mal pressure on the long tail that trails away
study the complex relationship between the Sun and Earth. from the Sun (Fig. 1). Both these pressures
depend on the concentration of the solar
wind, so the magnetosphere grew to excep-
T
he study of space is generally passive, as solar wind, which varies in concentration,
the input factors to an environment flux, speed, temperature and composition. tionally large dimensions (100 times its typi-
cannot be adjusted in a controlled man- All of these factors affect the magnetosphere cal volume) as the solar wind decayed.
ner to study one isolated mechanism, as they — the cavity formed by the Earth’s magnetic Another feature was the appearance of high-
can in a laboratory. Instead scientists have to field in the solar wind — and separating their ly energetic flows of electrons parallel to the
monitor all the inputs and try to disentangle various effects is difficult. This is why rare direction of the magnetic field in the vicinity
the various effects that are taking place events such as the one centred around 11 of Earth. These so-called ‘strahl’ electrons
simultaneously. For instance, the Sun emits a May 1999 are so valuable. In this period, the (red arrows in Fig. 1) are continuously emit-
continuous stream of ionized gas (contain- solar wind remained completely normal ted by the Sun but their flow is usually dis-
ing mostly protons and electrons) called the except that its density plummeted to 5% of rupted by the solar wind, making their fluxes
Overdraped
open field line
NATURE | VOL 409 | 8 FEBRUARY 2001 | www.nature.com © 2001 Macmillan Magazines Ltd 677
88
letters to nature
for the separation of the moa, which was consistent with the estimated emu/cassowary .................................................................
Wolbachia-induced incompatibility
split at 30±35 Myr. The analysis was a simple extension of a described method29 to allow
more than four taxa. The assumption of rate constancy among the ratites was tested using
a likelihood ratio test of the molecular clock model30. With a likelihood ratio of 12.68, rate
constancy can be rejected (P , 0.01). However, Fig. 2 suggests that the ostrich may have an
elevated rate of substitution, so the test was repeated with the ostrich allowed a different
precedes other hybrid
rate from those of other ratites. The resulting likelihood ratio of 0.449 (P = 0.92) shows
that this two-rate model is consistent with clock-like behaviour. The two-rate model has incompatibilities in Nasonia
little effect on the divergence estimates (Table 2), with ostrich dates becoming younger by
5% of the largest change. Seth R. Bordenstein, F. Patrick O'Hara & John H. Werren
Received 12 July; accepted 26 October 2000.
Department of Biology, The University of Rochester, Rochester, New York 14627,
1. Cracraft, J. Phylogeny and evolution of the ratite birds. Ibis 116, 494±521 (1974). USA
2. Sibley, C. G. & Ahlquist, J. E. Phylogeny and Classi®cation of Birds (Yale Univ. Press, London, 1990). ..............................................................................................................................................
3. Cooper, A. et al. Independent origins of the New Zealand moas and kiwis. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA
89, 8741±8744 (1992). Wolbachia are cytoplasmically inherited bacteria that cause a
4. Cooper, A. & Penny, D. Mass survival of birds across the Cretaceous±Tertiary: Molecular evidence. number of reproductive alterations in insects, including cytoplas-
Science 275, 1109±1113 (1997). mic incompatibility1,2, an incompatibility between sperm and egg
5. Feduccia, A. The Origin and Evolution of Birds (Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1997).
6. Van Tuinen, M., Sibley, C. & Hedges, S. B. Phylogeny and biogeography of ratite birds inferred from
that results in loss of sperm chromosomes following fertilization.
DNA sequences of the mitochondrial ribosomal genes. Mol. Biol. Evol. 15, 370±376 (1998). Wolbachia are estimated to infect 15±20% of all insect species3,
7. Olson, S. L. in Avian Biology Vol. VIII (eds Farner, D. S., King, J. R. & Parkes, K. C.) 79±238 (Academic, and also are common in arachnids, isopods and nematodes3,4.
Orlando, 1985). Therefore, Wolbachia-induced cytoplasmic incompatibility could
8. Lee, K., Feinstein, J. & Cracraft, J. in Avian Molecular Evolution and Molecular Systematics (ed. Mindell,
D.) 173±208 (Academic, New York, 1997).
be an important factor promoting rapid speciation in
9. Houde, P. Ostrich ancestors found in the Northern Hemisphere suggest new hypothesis of ratite invertebrates5, although this contention is controversial6,7. Here
origins. Nature 324, 563±565 (1986). we show that high levels of bidirectional cytoplasmic incompat-
10. Bledsoe, A. H. A phylogenetic analysis of postcranial skeletal characters of the ratite birds. Ann.
ibility between two closely related species of insects (the parasitic
Carnegie Mus. 57, 73±90 (1988).
11. Cooper, A. in Avian Molecular Evolution and Molecular Systematics (ed. Mindell, D.) 345±373
wasps Nasonia giraulti and Nasonia longicornis) preceded the
(Academic, New York, 1997). evolution of other postmating reproductive barriers. The pre-
12. Handt, O., Krings, M., Ward, R. H. & PaÈaÈbo, S. The retrieval of ancient human DNA sequences. Am. J. sence of Wolbachia severely reduces the frequency of hybrid
Hum. Genet. 59, 368±376 (1996).
13. Krings, M. et al. Neandertal DNA sequence and the origin of modern humans. Cell 90, 19±30 (1997).
offspring in interspecies crosses. However, antibiotic curing of
14. Cooper, A. in Ancient DNA (eds Herrmann, B. & Hummel, S.) 149±165 (Springer, New York, 1993). the insects results in production of hybrids. Furthermore, F1 and
15. Boles, W. E. Hindlimb proportions and locomotion of Emuarius gidju (Patterson & Rich, 1987) (Aves: F2 hybrids are completely viable and fertile, indicating the absence
Casuariidae). Memoirs of the Queensland Museum 41, 235±240 (1997). of F1 and F2 hybrid breakdown. Partial interspeci®c sexual isola-
16. Lawver, L. A., Royer, J-Y., Sandwell, D. T. & Scotese, C. R. in Geological Evolution of Antarctica (eds
Thomson, M. R. A., Crame, J. A. & Thomson, J. W.) 533±539 (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge,
tion occurs, yet it is asymmetric and incomplete. Our results
1991). indicate that Wolbachia-induced reproductive isolation occurred
17. Cooper, R. A. & Millener, P. R. The New Zealand biota: Historical background and new research. in the early stages of speciation in this system, before the evolu-
Trends Ecol. Evol. 8, 429±433 (1993).
tion of other postmating isolating mechanisms (for example,
18. Fleming, C. A. The Geological History of New Zealand and its Life (Univ. Auckland Press, Auckland,
1979).
hybrid inviability and hybrid sterility).
19. Stevens, G. R. Lands in collision. N. Z. Dept Sci. Ind. Res. Inf. Serv. 161 (1985). Symbiotic microorganisms are widespread in nature and often
20. Storch, G. in The Africa±South America Connection (eds George, W. & Lavocat, R.) 76±86 (Clarendon, have intimate associations with their hosts, ranging from mutua-
Oxford, 1993).
21. Martin, P. G. & Dowd, J. M. Using sequences of rbcL to study phylogeny and biogeography of
listic to parasitic relationships. It has been suggested that these
Nothofagus species. Aust. Syst. Bot. 6, 441±447 (1993). associations may act as a source of evolutionary innovation for their
22. Herzer, R. et al. Reinga Basin and its margins. N. Z. J. Geol. Geophys. 40, 425±451 (1997). hosts, leading to differentiation between host populations and
23. Sauer, E. G. F. Ratite eggshells and phylogenetic questions. Bonn Zool. Beitr. 23, 3±48 (1972). ultimately to the evolution of new species8. Wolbachia are particu-
24. Krause, D. W., Prasad, G. V. R., von Koenigswald, W., Sahni, A. & Grine, F. E. Cosmopolitanism
among Gondwanan Late Cretaceous mammals. Nature 390, 504±507 (1997).
larly good candidates for symbiont-induced speciation, because
25. Sampson, S. D. et al. Predatory dinosaur remains from Madagascar: Implications for the Cretaceous these bacteria can modify compatibility between eggs and sperm of
biogeography of Gondwana. Science, 280, 1048±1051 (1998). hosts, and thus directly cause reproductive isolation without long-
26. Cooper, A. & Poinar, H. Ancient DNA: Do it right or not at all. Science 289, 1139 (2000).
term coevolution of the host and symbiont5. There is some empiri-
27. Swofford, D. L. PAUP*. Phylogenetic Analysis Using Parsimony (*and Other Methods) (Sinauer,
Sunderland, Massachusetts, 1999). cal evidence for a role of Wolbachia in speciation in mushroom-
28. Huelsenbeck, J. P., Hillis, D. M. & Jones R. in Molecular Zoology: Strategies and Protocols (eds Ferraris, feeding Drosophila9, the ¯our beetle Tribolium10, and parasitic
J. & Palumbi, S.) 19±45 (Wiley, New York, 1996). wasps11. However, the view that Wolbachia are involved in inverte-
29. Rambaut, A. & Bromham, L. Estimating divergence dates from molecular sequences. Mol. Biol. Evol.
15, 442±448 (1998).
brate speciation is still controversial5±7. Here we present evidence
30. Felsenstein, J. Evolutionary trees from DNA sequences: a maximum likelihood approach. J. Mol. Evol. that Wolbachia-induced reproductive isolation precedes the evolu-
17, 368±376 (1981). tion of other postmating isolating mechanisms in Nasonia. The
®nding supports the view that Wolbachia can play a role in
Supplementary information, including clone and primer sequences is
available on Nature's World-Wide Web site (http://www.nature.com), or on
reproductive isolation and speciation.
http://evolve.zoo.ox.ac.uk/data/Ratites/, or as paper copy from the London editorial of®ce Nasonia is a complex of three closely related species of haplodi-
of Nature. ploid parasitic wasps. Nasonia vitripennis is found worldwide, and is
a generalist that parasitizes a variety of ¯y species. Nasonia giraulti
Acknowledgements occurs in eastern North America and N. longicornis in western
We thank W. Boles, R. Cooper, R. Herzer, P. Houde, C. Mourer-ChauvireÂ, D. Penny and North America, where they parasitize the pupae of blow¯ies in
T. Worthy for valuable comments, and M. Sorenson for allowing us access to unpublished birds' nests12. Genetic and molecular evidence shows that N. giraulti
rhea and ostrich sequences. We are grateful to T. Worthy and the staff of the Museum of and N. longicornis are more closely related sister species. Estimates
New Zealand for the moa samples. Modern samples were kindly provided by A. C. Wilson
(deceased), M. Potter and M. Braun, and laboratory space by R. Thomas, J. Bertranpetit
place the divergence of these two species at around 0.250 Myr ago
and the Oxford University Museum. A.C. was supported by the NERC, the Leverhulme and their divergence from N. vitripennis at around 0.800 Myr13.
Fund, the New Zealand Marsden Fund and the Royal Society. C.L.F. was supported by the All three species are infected with Wolbachia, and individuals of
Comissionat per a Universitats i Recerca (Catalan Autonomous Government), and A.R. each species are typically infected with two different bacterial types,
was supported by the Wellcome Trust.
each belonging to the two major subgroups of arthropod Wolbachia
Correspondence and requests for materials should be addressed to A.C. (e-mail: (A and B)14. Furthermore, phylogenetic analysis (data not shown)
alan.cooper@zoo.ox.ac.uk). Software is available at http://evolve.zoo.ox.ac.uk/software. indicates that the A group bacteria of each species are not closely
89
NATURE | VOL 409 | 8 FEBRUARY 2001 | www.nature.com © 2001 Macmillan Magazines Ltd 707
letters to nature
related to each other, and therefore have been independently their own species or males of the other species (N. giraulti female ´
acquired by horizontal transmission. Thus, the Nasonia system N. giraulti male, 100.2 6 5.6 versus N. giraulti female ´ N. longicornis
appears to be prone to the acquisition of Wolbachia, and is a male, 99.0 6 4.0; and N. longicornis female ´ N. longicornis
promising system for studying the role of these bacteria in repro- male, 68.5 6 4.1 versus N. longicornis female ´ N. giraulti male,
ductive isolation. 78.5 6 4.8). As only females are hybrids in a haplodiploid insect, we
Previous studies have shown Wolbachia-induced bidirectional also compared the number of female offspring produced in intra-
incompatibility between two diverged species, N. vitripennis and and interspeci®c crosses (Fig. 1). There was no reduction in the
N. giraulti11. F1 hybrids are not formed unless Wolbachia are number of F1 hybrid females relative to intraspeci®c controls.
removed by antibiotic curing. However, several other isolating Finally, we compared the number of eggs laid during a 6-h
barriers exist between these species, including high levels of F2 oviposition period to the number of adult offspring emerging in
hybrid lethality, abnormal courtship behaviours in F2 hybrid hybrid crosses. No signi®cant differences were found (N. giraulti
males (behavioural sterility), and partial premating (sexual) isola- female ´ N. longicornis male, 22.5 6 6.4 eggs versus 20.7 6 7.1
tion (refs 15, 16, and F.P.O'H., A C. Chawla and J.H.W., manuscript adults; reciprocal cross, 25.0 6 9.2 eggs versus 24.3 6 3.2 adults).
in preparation). It is therefore unclear whether Wolbachia-induced Therefore, results clearly indicate that there is no signi®cant F1
cytoplasmic incompatibility (CI) evolved before the evolution of hybrid inviability. They also show that there is no reduction in
other isolating barriers or after the divergence of the species. If fertilization of eggs based on whether the sperm came from hetero-
Wolbachia play a causal role in speciation, cases where Wolbachia- speci®c or homospeci®c males, indicating no incompatibilities in
induced CI evolved before other mechanisms of reproductive the fertilization mechanism between these species.
isolation should exist. The level of F1 hybrid female fertility was measured by counting
Here we investigate the role of Wolbachia in reproductive incom- eggs laid by females during a time-limited oviposition period. F1
patibility in a younger species pair, using the more closely related hybrid females did not show reduced fertility relative to non-hybrid
species N. giraulti and N. longicornis. First, we screened ®eld- control females (Fig. 2). In fact, hybrid females with the N. long-
collected insects to determine the frequencies of infections in icornis cytoplasm laid signi®cantly more eggs than non-hybrid
natural populations of the three species. A polymerase chain N. longicornis females (Mann±Whitney U-test (U), P , 0.001).
reaction (PCR) method was employed using previously published Sterility and/or mortality of F2 progeny (hybrid breakdown) is
speci®c primers17. In all three species, 100% of the individuals from one of the earlier manifestations of genetic incompatibility between
various geographical areas were found to be infected (N. giraulti, recently evolved species20,21. This is believed to be due to the general
n = 29; N. longicornis, n = 31; N. vitripennis, n = 31). All samples recessivity of genes involved in hybrid inviability and infertility20±22.
were doubly infected with A and B, except for one N. longicornis The haploidy of males in Nasonia offers an advantage to the study of
strain with a single A infection. Sequence analysis of PCR-ampli®ed recessive incompatibility factors, as such factors will be readily
products of the wsp gene18 from a subset con®rms that the species expressed in haploid males15,22. We investigated inviability by
are infected with species-speci®c Wolbachia, and that the Wolbachia comparing the number of F2 eggs laid by F1 virgin females to the
from different intraspeci®c strains form monophyletic groups (data
not shown), with little sequence variation within a host species.
We undertook experiments to determine whether Wolbachia a
cause reproductive incompatibility between the `young' species 100
Number of hybrid (female) offspring
708 © 2001 Macmillan Magazines Ltd NATURE | VOL 409 | 8 FEBRUARY 2001 | www.nature.com
letters to nature
number of F2 males that survived to adulthood. (Virgin females N. longicornis, 95.8% (n = 24); N. giraulti, 96.0% (n = 25);
produce haploid male progeny from unfertilized eggs in this X2 = 0.97, 2 d.f., P = 0.62). However, males did differ in their ability
haplodiploid insect.) There are no signi®cant differences in mor- to copulate with N. longicornis females (hybrids, 52.9% (n = 68);
tality levels among the F2 hybrid males relative to the non-hybrid N. longicornis, 95.2% (n = 21); N. giraulti, 21.2% (n = 19);
controls (Fig. 2). Mortality was found among F2 males of hybrid X2 = 22.74, 2 d.f., P , 0.001). This difference cannot be attributed
females from the N. longicornis male ´ N. giraulti female cross to hybrid breakdown, because hybrid males with N. longicornis
(mean 6 s.d. = 19.3 6 0.4% (ref. 23) mortality; U, egg versus adult females copulate at signi®cantly higher rates than do N. giraulti
number, p = 0.002). However, a similar level of mortality was also males (X2 = 6.08, 1 d.f., P = 0.014).
observed among non-hybrid N. giraulti males (F2 males from the The above results are therefore best explained as mate discrimi-
N. giraulti male ´ N. giraulti female cross; 14.3 6 0.3% mortality, P nation of N. longicornis females against F2 hybrid males, rather than
= 0.009). No signi®cant differences were found between these to F2 hybrid `sickness'. In contrast, our ®ndings with F2 hybrid males
crosses in the number of F2 eggs (U, P = 0.595) or F2 surviving from the older species pair (N. giraulti and N. vitripennis) indicate
adults (U, P = 0.862). Therefore, there is not elevated mortality high levels of reproductive incompetence throughout the various
among hybrids. This ®nding is quite different from what is found in stages of courtship and mating. For example in the older species
the older species pair (N. giraulti ´ N. vitripennis), which has high cross, 27.6% of F2 hybrid males failed to locate and mount females,
levels (70±85%) of F2 hybrid male mortality15. Such recessive and of those that did mount females, 26.8% failed to perform the
genetic incompatibilities have apparently not yet evolved between ritualized courtship display. As a result, a total of 53.2% of F2 hybrid
N. giraulti and N. longicornis. males in the older species cross fail to successfully mount females
We assessed the fertility of F2 hybrid and non-hybrid males by and perform the courtship display (compared to only 13.8% who
dissecting testes and categorizing sperm motility into three groups: fail to do so in the younger species cross, not signi®cantly different
normal, reduced or absent. All males possessed some motile sperm. from controls). We conclude that the genetic incompatibilities
The percentage of males with normal quantities of motile sperm was responsible for these problems have not arisen since the more
94.7% (n = 19) and 95.0% (n = 20) for the two hybrid genotypes and recent divergence of N. giraulti and N. longicornis.
95.0% (n = 20) and 100% (n = 19) for non-hybrids. Additionally, we Finally, we investigated the level of premating isolation between
tested the ability of hybrid and non-hybrid sperm to fertilize both the two species in single pair-mating situations. During a 30-min
N. giraulti and N. longicornis eggs. Of 69 males that copulated, only mating period, N. giraulti females show no mate discrimination
one failed to produce female offspring, but this occurred in an towards N. longicornis males, mating at similar frequencies as they
intraspeci®c cross. Thus, hybrid sperm is completely functional. do to homospeci®c males (94.5% mating, n = 200 versus 95.6%,
This contrasts to many studies in Drosophila, which indicate a n = 159, P = 0.32). In contrast, N. longicornis females show
prevalence of hybrid male sterility loci24,25 and that spermiogenic partial mate discrimination towards N. giraulti males relative to
sterility evolves rapidly in the divergence between species20,21. homospeci®c males (46.9% mating, n = 113 versus 89.9%, n = 178,
F2 hybrid breakdown can also affect courtship behaviour, due to a P , 0.0001).
general `sickness' of hybrid males or to speci®c negative interactions The experiments presented here clearly indicate that the species
in genes involved in courtship behaviour26. We assessed the ability of pair N. giraulti and N. longicornis do not show signi®cant levels of F1
hybrid and non-hybrid males to (1) locate and mount females, (2) or F2 lethality, F1 or F2 reproductive sterility, or F2 `hybrid sickness'
perform the ritualized courtship display, and (3) copulate with as manifested by competence in courtship behaviour. In contrast,
females. The type of female did not in¯uence probabilities of high levels of Wolbachia-induced reproductive incompatibility are
initiating courtship and no differences were found among males present in this species pair. Therefore, we conclude that interspecies
in their ability to locate and mount females (hybrids, 93.7% bidirectional CI has preceded the evolution of these other isolating
(n = 187); N. longicornis, 97.8% (n = 46); N. giraulti, 95.7% (n = 46); mechanisms in this system. In addition to Wolbachia-induced
X2 = 1.42, 2 degrees of freedom (d.f.), P = 0.49). Among males who reproductive incompatibility, there is partial premating isolation
successfully mount females, there was a small and nearly signi®cant in one direction between these species. The strength of premating
difference in the proportion of males performing the courtship isolation, at least under the conditions tested here, is weaker than
display (hybrids, 94.2% (n = 172); N. longicornis, 100% (n = 45); the postmating reproductive incompatibilities caused by Wolbachia.
N. giraulti, 100% (n = 45); X2 = 5.44, 2 d.f., P = 0.07). Among those The role of Wolbachia in speciation is a matter of current
males who courted N. giraulti females, no differences were found in debate5±7 and so far, there is limited empirical support for it9±11.
the proportion of males copulating (hybrids, 91.5% (n = 94); We do not claim that Wolbachia are currently causing reproductive
isolation between N. giraulti and N. longicornis in nature. Other
factors, such as geographical isolation (allopatry) are likely to be
more important. However, our results do show that Wolbachia-
30
induced bidirectional CI has preceded the evolution of other
25 intrinsic, postmating reproductive isolation barriers in these
newly evolving species. The present work therefore provides further
Offspring number
20
support for the argument that the cytoplasmic bacterium Wolbachia
15 could promote host speciation. M
10
Methods
5
NATURE | VOL 409 | 8 FEBRUARY 2001 | www.nature.com © 2001 Macmillan Magazines Ltd 709
letters to nature
F2 hybrid viability 26. Noor, M. A. F. Genetics of sexual isolation and courtship dysfunction in male hybrids of Drosophila
pseudoobscura and Drosophila persimilis. Evolution 51, 809±815 (1997).
F1 hybrid and non-hybrid virgin adult females (1±2-d old) were placed on four hosts for
roughly 48 h for host feeding and egg laying. Females were immediately transferred to one
host for a 6-h laying period, after which females were removed from the vial. We limited Acknowledgements
the ovipositioning period to prevent wasps from becoming resource-limited. Half of these We thank R. Billings, M. Vaughn and B. J. Velthuis for technical assistance, and J. Bartos, A.
replicates were immediately scored for the number of F2 eggs laid in 6 h and the remaining Betancourt, J. Jaenike, J. P. Masly, T. van Opijnen and D. Presgraves for critical reading of
half were scored later for the number of adults. the manuscript. This work was supported by the NSF (J.H.W.).
710 © 2001 Macmillan Magazines Ltd NATURE | VOL 409 | 8 FEBRUARY 2001 | www.nature.com
Fruit odor discrimination and sympatric host race
formation in Rhagoletis
Charles Linn, Jr.*, Jeffrey L. Feder†, Satoshi Nojima*, Hattie R. Dambroski†, Stewart H. Berlocher‡,
and Wendell Roelofs*§
*Department of Entomology, New York State Agricultural Experimental Station, Cornell University, Geneva, NY 14456; †Department of Biological Sciences,
University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN 46556-0369; and ‡Department of Entomology, University of Illinois, 320 Morrill Hall, 505 South Goodwin
Avenue, Urbana, IL 61801
Rhagoletis pomonella is a model for incipient sympatric speciation standing sympatric host race formation and speciation in Rhago-
(divergence without geographic isolation) by host-plant shifts. letis, and potentially several other insect specialists, therefore
Here, we show that historically derived apple- and ancestral requires elucidating the mechanistic basis for differential host
hawthorn-infesting host races of the fly use fruit odor as a key choice. Here we show that host fruit odor plays a key role in this
olfactory cue to help distinguish between their respective plants. process.
In flight-tunnel assays and field tests, apple and hawthorn flies Precisely how R. pomonella distinguishes among potential
preferentially oriented to, and were captured with, chemical hosts is not known. However, studies have discerned several cues
blends of their natal fruit volatiles. Because R. pomonella rendez- that apple flies use to recognize apple trees. The major long-
vous on or near the unabscised fruit of their hosts to mate, the range stimulus drawing flies to apple trees appears to be volatile
behavioral preference for apple vs. hawthorn fruit odor translates compounds emanating from ripening apple fruit (13). In the
directly into premating reproductive isolation between the fly field, apple flies oriented upwind toward a point source of butyl
races. We have therefore identified a key and recently evolved hexanoate, a key component of the identified apple volatile
(<150 years) mechanism responsible for host choice in R. blend (Table 1), at a distance of 12 m (14). At shorter distances
pomonella bearing directly on sympatric host race formation and of ⬍1 m, visual cues become important for finding fruit within
speciation. the tree canopy (13, 15). Other visual characteristics of trees
(e.g., color, shape, and size), although used by flies for distin-
guishing trees from other objects (16), are not host-specific (13).
S peciation in sexual organisms occurs as inherent barriers to
gene flow evolve between previously interbreeding popula-
tions. To elucidate the origins of species therefore requires
The literature on host recognition in the R. pomonella apple race
therefore suggests that differences in fruit volatiles may be
understanding how and why new traits arise that reproductively critical for host discrimination.
To determine whether apple and hawthorn flies use fruit odor
isolate taxa (1). Proponents of sympatric or ecological speciation
as an olfactory cue to help distinguish between their host plants,
posit that divergence is often initiated as a result of natural
we prepared synthetic blends of apple and hawthorn volatiles
selection differentially adapting populations to alternative hab-
that contained the biologically active chemical components of
itats (2, 3). Habitat-specific mating is an ecological adaptation
fruit odors (Table 1; refs. 17 and 18). We then used these blends
central to many models of divergence-with-gene-flow speciation
in flight-tunnel assays and field trials to test whether apple- and
(4, 5). When organisms mate in preferred environments, a
hawthorn-origin flies preferentially oriented to, or were cap-
system of positive assortative mating is established that helps
tured with, their natal fruit volatiles. We report results implying
generate disequilibrium between habitat preference and perfor- that the historically derived apple fly race has evolved an
mance genes. This disequilibrium lessens the ‘‘selection- increased preference for apple fruit volatiles and decreased
recombination antagonism’’ (5, 6), making it potentially possible response to hawthorn volatiles.
for divergence to occur without geographic isolation in the face
of gene flow (i.e., in sympatry). Materials and Methods
The Rhagoletis pomonella sibling species complex is a model Insects. Apple and hawthorn flies were collected as larvae from
for sympatric speciation by host-plant shifts (7). The recently infested fruit in Grant, MI, Fennville, MI, and Urbana, IL,
derived apple (Malus pumila)-infesting population of R. during the 1999–2003 field seasons, and reared to adulthood in
pomonella, which originated by a shift from hawthorn (Crataegus the laboratory by using standard protocols (19). Apple and
spp.) in the mid-1800s, represents an example of host race hawthorn populations at these three sites have been the subject
formation in action, the hypothesized initial stage of sympatric of previous ecological and genetic studies and have been shown
speciation (2, 7). Host-specific mating is a key feature of to differ significantly from one another in allozyme frequencies
Rhagoletis biology, as it is for many phytophagous insect spe- (20–24). Eclosing adults were kept in cages in an environmental
cialists (2). Because Rhagoletis flies mate exclusively on or near chamber at 23–24°C, 16 h light兾8 h dark photoperiod, 60–70%
the unabscised fruit of its host plants (8, 9), differences in host relative humidity, and fed an artificial diet containing water,
preference translate directly into mate choice and premating sugar, vitamins, casein hydrolysate, and a salt mixture (25).
reproductive isolation (10). Rhagoletis is a vagile insect; most Sexually mature, odor-naive adults between 10 and 21 days
flies visit multiple trees in their lifetimes searching for food, posteclosion were tested in the flight tunnel. Roughly equal
mates, and fruit oviposition sites (10, 11). The potential there- numbers of males and females were tested, and no behavioral
fore exists for substantial mixing between sympatric fly popu- difference between the sexes was apparent in the flight tunnel.
lations. Despite this potential, fly migration has been estimated
to be 4–6% per generation per year (Rhagoletis is univoltine) Fruit Volatile Blends. Synthetic apple and hawthorn fruit volatile
between apple and hawthorn trees based on a mark-recapture blends were tested in the study (Table 1). The biologically active
experiment conducted at a field site with interspersed host trees
(10, 11). Studies on related sibling species in the R. pomonella
group have implied that ‘‘host fidelity’’ can potentially cause §To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: WLR1@cornell.edu.
complete premating isolation between fly taxa (12). Under- © 2003 by The National Academy of Sciences of the USA
11490 –11493 兩 PNAS 兩 September 30, 2003 兩 vol. 100 兩 no. 20 93 www.pnas.org兾cgi兾doi兾10.1073兾pnas.1635049100
Table 1. Volatile blends for apple and hawthorn fruit 3-methylbutan-1-ol with the other components added in the
Apple blend Hawthorn blend proportions shown in Table 1. Blends were prepared 60 min
before the tests, with fresh sources and spheres used for each test.
Butyl hexanoate (0.37) Butyl hexanoate (0.01) Three treatments were tested: (i) a blank red sphere with a
Pentyl hexanoate (0.05) 3-Methylbutan-1-ol (1.0) control solvent-treated rubber septum, (ii) the apple blend, and
Propyl hexanoate (0.04) Isoamyl acetate (0.4) (iii) the hawthorn blend.
Butyl butanoate (0.1) 4,8-Dimethyl-1,3(E),7-nonatriene (0.02)
Hexyl butanoate (0.44) Ethyl acetate (20.0)
Field Trials. Field trapping studies were conducted in mixed-
Dihydro--ionone (0.02)
variety apple orchards and hawthorn copses from August 27 to
The numbers in parentheses are microgram amounts per microliter of the September 9, 2002, at the Experiment Station in Geneva, NY,
solution applied to the septum. and from July 25 to September 5, 2002, at the Trevor Nichols
Research Complex near Fennville, MI. Red sphere traps (7.5-cm
diameter) coated with ‘‘Tanglefoot’’ stickum were used in New
chemical components of apple and hawthorn fruit volatiles were York, whereas clear glass spheres (5.5-cm diameter) were used
first identified by using solid-phase microextraction, coupled gas at the Michigan site to remove any visual cue provided by the red
chromatography兾electroantennogram detection, mass spec-
sphere. (Fig. 2 shows the spheres used in the study.) Three-way
trometry, and a sustained-flight tunnel assay (17, 18). The
choice experiments were performed to assess the relative pref-
compositions of the blends were determined through reiterative
erences of the host races for fruit odors. For the three-way tests,
testing such that equivalent amounts of whole-fruit extracts and
rubber septa lures containing 2 mg of apple, hawthorn, or no
the synthetic mixes elicited similar levels of behavioral activity
blend were separately attached to the tops of three spheres
from natal fly races in the flight tunnel (17, 18).
triangulated 2 m apart in host trees. Three replicate tests were
Flight Tunnel. The response of flies to fruit volatiles was measured conducted at each site in a trial period, with a trial period lasting
in a 183-cm-long, 61 ⫻ 61-cm-square flight tunnel (see refs. 17 from 1 to 2 days. Traps were checked after each trial period, with
and 18 for details of tunnel and flight conditions). Solutions of captured flies counted and removed, lures replaced, and traps
the synthetic blends prepared in hexane were applied to acetone- rotated to new positions. Statistical analyses were performed by
washed, rubber septa (Thomas Scientific, Swedesboro, NJ). A using the total number of flies captured across the three
septum was attached to a 7.5-cm-diameter red plastic sphere replicates during trial periods. Paired field trials of only the apple
(Great Lakes IPM, Vestaburg, MI) hung at the upwind end of blend vs. blank controls on clear spheres were also performed at
the tunnel. Individual flies were transferred to a screen cage, the Fennville, MI, site to assess host race attraction to apple odor
which was then placed on a screen stand 1 m downwind of the in the absence of the visual cue provided by the red sphere. For
sphere, and their behaviors were recorded (see Fig. 1 legend for the paired experiments, the apple blend was released from
description of fly behaviors). Field experiments have shown that scintillation vials prepared by Great Lakes IPM. Release rate of
apple flies can orient upwind to a point source of butyl hexano- odor from these vials was estimated at 1 mg兾h at 25°C. Baited,
ate, a key volatile of the apple odor blend, at a distance of at least clear spheres were hung 1 m from blank clear spheres fitted with
12 m (14). Fruit volatiles are therefore not just short-range empty vials. Six pairs of replicate traps were monitored and
attractants. For all flight-tunnel tests, 200-g sources of a rotated every 5 days for the paired trials. The same design was
particular fruit blend were used. For the apple blend, the 200-g used to test the apple blend in flowering dogwood (Cornus
dosage refers to the complete five-component mix (Table 1). For florida) stands in Cassopolis, MI, and Granger, IN, from Sep-
the hawthorn blend, the 200-g dose reflects the amount of tember 16 to October 13, 2002.
EVOLUTION
Fig. 1. Percentages of tested apple- (open symbols) and hawthorn-origin flies (filled symbols) displaying the indicated or greater behavioral acceptance of apple
blend (A) and hawthorn (Haw) blend (B) in flight-tunnel assays. Behavioral responses in order of increasing blend acceptance are as follows: walk and groom
(fly remaining in release cage), take flight (flight from the release cage), upwind (oriented flight toward sphere), and reach sphere. The percentage of flies
displaying walk-and-groom behavior ⫽ 100% ⫺ % take flight. Populations tested were ‚, Urbana, IL; ƒ, Urbana, IL, hawthorn flies reared on apple for two
generations; E, Grant, MI; 䊐, Fennville, MI; and 〫, Geneva, NY, apple fly colony. P ⬍ 1 ⫻ 10⫺7 for every test of behavioral difference between races at a site,
as determined by Fisher’s exact test. Populations within a race did not differ significantly from each other in their responses to their natal fruit blend. However,
significant heterogeneity occurred among apple-fly populations in their responses to hawthorn blend (G test reaching sphere ⫽ 11.3, P ⫽ 0.158, 3 df) and among
hawthorn fly populations to apple blend (G test ⫽ 15.8, P ⫽ 0.0006, 2 df).
Linn et al. 94 PNAS 兩 September 30, 2003 兩 vol. 100 兩 no. 20 兩 11491
Fig. 2. Tanglefoot-coated spheres used for field trials. (A) Clear sphere with
septum used to release volatiles for three-way choice tests at Fennville, MI. (B)
Clear sphere with scintillation vial used to release volatiles for paired apple-
blend vs. blank tests. (C) Red sphere used in New York field trials and flight
tunnel. Background is a hawthorn tree with red fruits visible.
1. Coyne, J. A. (1992) Nature 355, 511–515. 15. Aluja, M., Prokopy, R. J., Elkinton, J. S. & Laurence, F. (1989) Environ.
2. Bush, G. L. (1969) Am. Nat. 103, 669–672. Entomol. 18, 1–7.
3. Schluter, D. (2001) Trends Ecol. Evol. 16, 372–380. 16. Prokopy, R. J., Moericke, V. & Bush, G. L. (1973) Environ. Entomol. 2,
4. Johnson, P. A. & Gullberg, U. (1998) in Endless Forms: Species and Speciation, 743–749.
eds. Howard, D. J. & Berlocher, S. H. (Oxford Univ. Press, New York), pp. 17. Zhang, A., Linn, C., Jr., Wright, S., Prokopy, R., Reissig, W. H. & Roelofs,
79–89. W. L. (1999) J. Chem. Ecol. 25, 1221–1232.
5. Fry, J. D. (2003) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 57, 1735–1746. 18. Nojima, S., Linn, C., Jr., Morris, B., Zhang, A. & Roelofs, W. L. (2003) J. Chem.
6. Felsenstein, J. (1981) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 35, 124–138. Ecol. 29, 319–334.
7. Bush, G. L. (1966) Bull. Mus. Comp. Zool. 134, 431–562. 19. Feder, J. L., Chilcote, C. A. & Bush, G. L. (1989) J. Hered. 80, 277–283.
8. Prokopy, R. J., Bennett, E. W. & Bush, G. L. (1971) Can. Entomol. 103, 20. Feder, J. L., Chilcote, C. A. & Bush, G. L. (1988) Nature 336, 61–64.
1405–1409. 21. McPheron, B. A., Smith, D. C. & Berlocher, S. H. (1988) Nature 336, 64–66.
9. Prokopy, R. J., Bennett, E. W. & Bush, G. L. (1972) Can. Entomol. 104, 97–104. 22. Feder, J. L. & Bush, G. L. (1989) Heredity 63, 245–266.
10. Feder, J. L., Opp, S., Wlazlo, B. Reynolds, K., Go, W. & Spisak, S. (1994) Proc. 23. Feder, J. L., Chilcote, C. A. & Bush, G. L. (1990) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.)
Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 91, 7990–7994. 44, 570–594.
11. Feder, J. L., Berlocher, S. H. & Opp, S. B. (1998) in Genetic Structure in Natural 24. Feder, J. L. & Bush, G. L. (1990) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 44, 595–608.
Insect Populations: Effects of Host Plants and Life History, eds. Mopper, S. & 25. Neilson, W. T. A. & McAllen, J. W. (1965) J. Econ. Entomol. 58, 542–543.
Strauss, S. (Chapman & Hall, New York), pp. 408–441. 26. Berlocher, S. H. (2000) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 54, 543–557.
12. Feder, J. L. & Bush, G. L. (1989) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 43, 1813–1819. 27. Orr, M. R. & Smith, T. B. (1998) Trends Ecol. Evol. 13, 502–506.
13. Prokopy, R. J. & Roitberg, B. D. (1984) Am. Sci. 72, 41–49. 28. Via, S. (2001) Trends Ecol. Evol. 16, 381–390.
14. Green, T. A. & Prokopy, R. J., J. Chem. Ecol., in press. 29. Berlocher, S. H. & Feder, J. L. (2002) Annu. Rev. Entomol. 47, 773–815.
EVOLUTION
Linn et al. 96 PNAS 兩 September 30, 2003 兩 vol. 100 兩 no. 20 兩 11493
SEMINARIO III: GENÉTICA DE LA ESPECIACIÓN
Marcela Rodriguero & Abel Carcagno
En este seminario se discutirán dos trabajos que tratan acerca de la genética de la
especiación y de la diferentes escuelas relacionadas con los mecanismos subyacentes al
proceso especiogénico.
Nota: Se recomienda especialmente la lectura crítica del trabajo “Dualism and conflicts in
understanding speciation”, de Menno Schilthuizen (Bioessays 22(12): 1134‐1141, 2000)
disponible en http://www.ege.fcen.uba.ar/materias/evolucion/material.htm
Genética del proceso especiogénico: dos escuelas teóricas
Escuela Aislacionista Escuela Seleccionista
Punto de partida de la Interrupción del flujo Adaptación a ambientes
especiación génico diferentes
Fuerzas evolutivas Deriva genética y/o Selección natural
preponderantes durante el selección natural
progreso de la especiación
Resultado último de la Aislamiento reproductivo Diferentes acervos génicos
especiación pre y/o postcigótico adaptados
Velocidad del proceso Más rápido en focos Más rápido en simpatría,
especiogénico en relación a periféricos aislados, aunque puede darse en otra
la escala geográfica aunque puede darse en otra configuración geográfica
configuración geográfica
Escuela Aislacionista
• Schemske D.W. & Bradshaw H.D. (1999) Pollinator preference and the evolution of floral
traits in mokeyflowers (Mimulus). PNAS 96: 11910‐11915.
1‐ ¿Existen los genes de la especiación?
2‐ ¿Cuántos genes requiere un proceso especiogénico?
3‐ ¿Qué son los QTLs y qué relevancia tienen para el estudio de la especiación?
4‐ ¿Cuál es la hipótesis de trabajo de Schemske & Bradshaw (1999) y qué antecedentes la
sustentan?
5‐ ¿Qué aproximación experimental utilizaría para dilucidar la arquitectura genética del
aislamiento reproductivo mediado por polinizadores?
6‐ ¿Cómo se confeccionó la figura 2? Indique el tratamiento estadístico de los datos.
97
7‐ ¿Qué conclusión puede extraer de la figura 2 respecto de las preferencias de cada
polinizador?
8‐ Explique cómo se obtuvieron los resultados graficados en las figuras 3 y 4. Compárelos
con los de la figura 2. ¿Dichos resultados se contradicen?
9‐ A partir de estos datos, ¿cuál es la arquitectura genética del aislamiento reproductivo de
estas especies?
10‐ ¿Se puede establecer inequívocamente que los cuatro caracteres analizados son los
responsables absolutos del aislamiento reproductivo?
Escuela Seleccionista
• Fontaneto D., Ermiou E.A., Boschetti C., Caprioli M., Melone G., Ricci C., Barraclough T.G.
(2007) Independently evolving species in asexual bdelloid rotifers. PLoS Biology 5(4):
914‐ 921.
11‐ Si existen los genes de la especiación... ¿cuáles serían en este caso?
12‐ ¿Qué particularidad presenta la clase Bdelloidea? ¿Qué concepto de especie utilizaría?
¿Qué modelo de especiación?
13‐ ¿Cuáles son las hipótesis del trabajo de Fontaneto et al. (2007)? ¿Cuáles son las
predicciones de cada escenario?
14‐ Este taxón presenta una particularidad que podría oscurecer el análisis. Menciónelo y
fundamente su respuesta. A partir de dicha conclusión, ¿qué carácter emerge como la mejor
opción para contrastar las hipótesis de trabajo y cuál podría ser su valor adaptativo? ¿Siente
que la utilización de dicha característica podría llevar a circularidad en el contraste de la
hipótesis?
15‐ Una vez seleccionado el carácter morfológico a estudiar, mencione los fundamentos
teóricos y las herramientas metodológicas utilizadas para abordar la hipótesis de evolución
independiente.
16‐ ¿Cuántas entidades evolutivas se pueden distinguir en Bdelloidea? ¿Son realmente
independientes? ¿Existe congruencia entre las unidades evolutivas y las reconocidas por los
taxónomos? ¿Cómo explicaría las discrepancias?
17‐ Mencione la aproximación metodológica y teórica utilizada para el contraste de la
hipótesis de divergencia adaptativa (relacione esto con lo aprendido en la unidad de
Neutralismo).
18‐ A partir de los resultados obtenidos, ¿qué fuerza evolutiva operó en la acumulación de
cambio evolutivo dentro de Bdelloidea? ¿Qué factores apoyan este resultado?
19‐ ¿Qué unidades evidencian la acumulación de divergencia adaptativa? ¿Se le ocurre
alguna manera de reconciliar estos resultados con los derivados del contraste de la hipótesis
de evolución independiente?
20‐ Una vez comprendidos los objetivos y resultados del trabajo, ¿cuántos conceptos de
especie diferentes podría aplicar a los rotíferos de la clase Bdelloidea?
98
Preguntas unificadoras
21‐ Comparando ambos trabajos... ¿En qué caso la selección natural desarrolla un papel
principal en el proceso especiogénico? ¿Qué papel juega entonces en el otro caso de estudio
durante el proceso de especiación?
22‐ ¿Por qué cree que la teoría de especiación por selección natural tuvo menos adeptos en
el pasado y actualmente está resurgiendo?
99
Pollinator preference and the evolution of floral traits
in monkeyflowers (Mimulus)
Douglas W. Schemske*† and H. D. Bradshaw, Jr.‡
*Department of Botany and ‡College of Forest Resources, University of Washington, Seattle, WA 98195
Edited by Barbara Anna Schaal, Washington University, St. Louis, MO, and approved August 11, 1999 (received for review June 10, 1999)
A paradigm of evolutionary biology is that adaptation and repro- ondary contact. Two species that show this pattern of secondary
ductive isolation are caused by a nearly infinite number of muta- contact are the predominantly bee-pollinated Mimulus lewisii
tions of individually small effect. Here, we test this hypothesis by and its hummingbird-pollinated congener Mimulus cardinalis. M.
investigating the genetic basis of pollinator discrimination in two lewisii has pink flowers, a wide corolla with inserted anthers and
closely related species of monkeyflowers that differ in their major stigma, a small volume of nectar, petals thrust forward to provide
pollinators. This system provides a unique opportunity to investi- a landing platform for bees, and two yellow ridges of brushy hairs
gate the genetic architecture of adaptation and speciation because presumed to be nectar guides (Fig. 1A). M. cardinalis has red
floral traits that confer pollinator specificity also contribute to flowers, a narrow tubular corolla, reflexed petals, a large nectar
premating reproductive isolation. We asked: (i) What floral traits reward, and exserted anthers and stigma to contact the forehead
cause pollinator discrimination among plant species? and (ii) What of hummingbirds (Fig. 1C). Neither species has an odor detect-
is the genetic basis of these traits? We examined these questions able by humans, and our observations suggest that pollinator
by using data obtained from a large-scale field experiment where visitation is influenced primarily by flower color, size, shape, and
genetic markers were employed to determine the genetic basis of nectar reward.
pollinator visitation. Observations of F2 hybrids produced by cross- Despite striking morphological differences, these two mon-
ing bee-pollinated Mimulus lewisii with hummingbird-pollinated keyflowers are very closely related. A phylogeny based on DNA
Mimulus cardinalis revealed that bees preferred large flowers low sequence from the internal transcribed spacer of nuclear ribo-
in anthocyanin and carotenoid pigments, whereas hummingbirds somal RNA places M. cardinalis and the Sierra Nevada form of
favored nectar-rich flowers high in anthocyanins. An allele that M. lewisii together and distinct from Rocky Mountain and
increases petal carotenoid concentration reduced bee visitation by Cascade Range populations of M. lewisii and other members of
80%, whereas an allele that increases nectar production doubled the section Erythranthe (A. Yen, R. G. Olmstead, H.D.B. and
hummingbird visitation. These results suggest that genes of large D.W.S., unpublished work). Crosses between these two species
effect on pollinator preference have contributed to floral evolution produce fertile hybrids (20). Their geographic distributions are
and premating reproductive isolation in these monkeyflowers. This largely nonoverlapping, with M. lewisii found principally from
work contributes to growing evidence that adaptation and repro- mid-to-high elevation, and M. cardinalis found from low-to-mid
ductive isolation may often involve major genes. elevation. The two species co-occur in a narrow altitudinal zone
at 1400 m in the Sierra Nevada.
reproductive isolation 兩 adaptation 兩 speciation 兩 natural In 1998, we conducted observations (⬎80 hr) in a sympatric
selection 兩 pollination area along the South Fork of the Tuolumne River, California,
and found that bees were the only visitors to M. lewisii (100% of
233 visits), and that hummingbirds were the primary visitors to
O ne of the principal goals of evolutionary biology is to
discover the genetic architecture of adaptation. Fisher’s
‘‘infinitesimal’’ model of evolution proposes that adaptation is
M. cardinalis (97% of 146 visits). Only once did we observe a
pollinator visit both Mimulus species in succession. These results
show that pollinator discrimination results in strong premating
due to the fixation of many genes with small individual effects,
reproductive isolation in the zone of sympatry.
and is based on the assumption that large-effect mutations move
Two experiments are required to elucidate the genetic archi-
a population farther from, rather than closer to, its phenotypic
tecture of reproductive isolation by pollinator-mediated selec-
optimum (1). This micromutationist view of ‘‘adaptive geome-
tion. First, the genetic basis of traits such as flower color, size,
try’’ (2) has had widespread support, but was challenged recently
shape, and nectar reward must be determined for plant species
by a theory suggesting that mutations of large effect can often be
with different pollinators. Second, the response of wild pollina-
beneficial during the early stages of adaptation as populations
tors to each floral trait must be evaluated in a geographic region
move toward their optimum phenotype (3). There have been too
where the plant species co-occur. We have completed the first
few empirical studies to resolve the debate, and it is therefore
experiment, using linkage mapping with molecular markers to
important to identify systems in which both the genetic basis and identify quantitative trait loci (QTL) that control complex floral
ecological significance of adaptive traits can be identified (4, 5). traits in M. lewisii and M. cardinalis. We found that most floral
Adaptations that reduce the frequency of mating among traits had at least one QTL of large effect (explaining ⬎25% of
neighboring populations are of special interest, as these may the F2 phenotypic variance), suggesting that pollinator-mediated
contribute to the origin of new species. Although evidence from selection in this system could involve ‘‘major’’ genes (21, 22).
Drosophila suggests that premating isolation may evolve quickly Here, we report results from the second experiment, identifying
(6), and can have a simple genetic basis (7, 8), there are few the ecological significance of floral traits and the effect of simple
comparable data from other organisms and no studies investi- genetic changes on pollinator visitation in nature.
gating the genetics of premating reproductive isolation in natural
populations (9, 10).
Pollinator-mediated selection on floral traits is widely re- This paper was submitted directly (Track II) to the PNAS office.
garded as a common mechanism of adaptation and speciation in Abbreviation: QTL, quantitative trait loci.
plants (11–19). The traditional view is that adaptation to the †To whom reprint requests should be addressed. E-mail: schem@u.washington.edu.
most abundant or efficient pollinators in geographically isolated The publication costs of this article were defrayed in part by page charge payment. This
populations results in floral divergence, and that pollinator article must therefore be hereby marked “advertisement” in accordance with 18 U.S.C.
preference prevents intercrossing if populations come into sec- §1734 solely to indicate this fact.
Fig. 1. M. lewisii (A), an F1 hybrid (B), M. cardinalis (C), and examples of variation in floral traits found in F2 hybrids (D–L).
Materials and Methods outcrossed F2 population. The F1 hybrids have pink flowers and
moderately reflexed petals, with nectar guides similar to those of
Seed of both parental species was collected in Yosemite National M. lewisii, but lacking hairs (Fig. 1B), whereas the F2 generation
Park. We crossed M. lewisii (Fig. 1 A) with M. cardinalis (Fig. 1C) displays a wide range of flower colors and morphologies (Fig. 1
to produce F1 hybrids, then mated unrelated F1s to produce an D–L).
Schemske and Bradshaw 101 PNAS 兩 October 12, 1999 兩 vol. 96 兩 no. 21 兩 11911
We examined the visitation by bees and hummingbirds to the
parental species and hybrids in an experimental population. We A 0.2
grew parental, F1, and F2 individuals to flowering in the Uni- Proportion of visits by bees
versity of Washington greenhouses as part of our QTL studies *
comprised ⬍5% of the total visits to F2s and was excluded from
EVOLUTION
our analyses. We combined all other bee species to form a single
category. The bumblebee Bombus vosnesenski was responsible
for ⬎95% of all bee visits, with the remaining visitation by Osmia
(Monilosmia) sp. and an unknown bumblebee. Bumblebees
generally visited flowers for nectar and made only passive
contact with the anthers, whereas Osmia (Monilosmia) sp.
actively collected pollen during its foraging bouts. Pollen-
collecting bumblebees were observed most often on plants with Fig. 4. Effect of marker genotype for the major nectar QTL (RAPD marker
red or orange flowers. Anna’s hummingbird (Calypte anna) was L04co; ref. 22) on nectar volume per flower (A), and the visitation rate (visits
the only species of hummingbird observed. Although we did not per flower per day) of hummingbirds (B) and bees (C). Genotypes are: LL,
individuals homozygous for the M. lewisii allele (n ⫽ 61); LC, heterozygotes
mark hummingbirds, chases between individuals with different (n ⫽ 130); CC, individuals homozygous for the M. cardinalis allele (n ⫽ 36). Bars
plumage were common, suggesting that several different hum- denote the mean ⫹ 2 SE, and bars with different letters identify means that are
mingbirds were visiting the experimental plants. significantly different (P ⬍ 0.01) based on Mann–Whitney U tests corrected for
M. lewisii was visited primarily by bees (82% of 78 visits), and multiple comparisons (31).
M. cardinalis was visited by hummingbirds (99.6% of 2,097
visits), establishing that pollinator behavior in our experimental cating a strong genetic component to visitation. The composition
plots is similar to that observed in natural populations. The of pollinators visiting the F2s (8648 visits) varied widely, from
composition of the visitors to F1 hybrids (59% bees; 1,744 visits) plants visited only by bees to those visited only by hummingbirds,
was exactly intermediate to that of the parental species, indi- with a mean of 38% bee visitation per plant.
Schemske and Bradshaw 103 PNAS 兩 October 12, 1999 兩 vol. 96 兩 no. 21 兩 11913
Increased petal anthocyanins, petal carotenoids, and nectar for the three F2 genotypic classes at the major nectar QTL (22).
volume significantly reduced the proportion of bee visitation, Our previous genetic mapping study found that this QTL
whereas greater projected area increased the proportion of bee explains 41% of the difference in nectar volume between the
visitation (Fig. 2A). These results provide clear evidence that two parental species and has an additive mode of action, with
f lower color contributes to reproductive isolation in this the M. cardinalis allele causing an increase in nectar (22).
system, despite recent statements to the contrary (24, 25). Segregation of the parental alleles at this locus produced a
Petal anthocyanin concentration significantly affected both nearly 3-fold range in mean nectar volume per f lower in our
bee and hummingbird visitation rates, but with opposite F2 field population (Fig. 4A). The average nectar volume of the
effects, whereas each of the other f loral traits had a significant heterozygous genotypic class was intermediate to that of the
effect on one pollinator, but not on the other (Fig. 2B). Bee two homozygous classes (Fig. 4 A), and the visitation rate of
visitation rate was negatively associated with petal anthocya- hummingbirds closely matched this distribution of nectar
nin and carotenoid concentration and positively associated volume (Fig. 4B). Plants homozygous for the M. cardinalis
with projected area, whereas hummingbird visitation rate was allele had twice the rate of hummingbird visitation as M. lewisii
positively associated with both petal anthocyanin concentra- homozygotes, whereas heterozygotes had an intermediate
tion and nectar volume (Fig. 2B). value (Fig. 4B). These results demonstrate that despite the
We tested the hypothesis that adaptation to different polli- bewildering array of f loral variation in the F2 population (Fig.
nators may involve genes with large phenotypic effects by 1 D–L), hummingbirds have the remarkable ability to distin-
comparing visitation rates as a function of QTL marker genotype guish the phenotypic effects of allele substitutions at the major
for petal carotenoid concentration and nectar volume, the two nectar QTL. In contrast, there was no relationship between
traits with the greatest impact on bee and hummingbird visita- bee visitation rate and marker genotype at the nectar QTL
tion, respectively (Fig. 2B). A single Mendelian locus controls (Fig. 4C). The ability of hummingbirds to quickly find rich
the distribution of carotenoid pigments in the petals (20). F2 nectar sources, and to return to them often, has also been
plants homozygous for the recessive M. cardinalis allele at the yup documented in experiments on spatial learning (29, 32, 33) and
locus (yellow upper; ref. 20) have carotenoids distributed suggests that hummingbirds are capable of exerting strong
throughout the petals, and are orange- or red-flowered (Fig. 1 selection on the nectar rewards of f lowers.
D, E, K, and L), whereas F2s carrying the dominant M. lewisii Taken together, our results provide evidence of striking
allele are pink-flowered (Fig. 1 F–J). There was no effect of yup differences in the floral preferences of bees and hummingbirds,
genotype on hummingbird visitation rate (Fig. 3A), but bee and considerable opportunity for the adaptive divergence of
visitation was 80% lower in plants homozygous for the M. floral traits through pollinator-mediated selection. This stands in
cardinalis allele (Fig. 3B). This clearly shows that genetic contrast to recent suggestions that pollinators typically have
variation for petal carotenoid concentration affects bee visi- broad preferences, and are therefore unlikely to contribute to
tation and supports earlier findings that bees visiting Mimulus floral evolution or the reproductive isolation of sympatric taxa
species in the section Erythranthe strongly prefer pink over red (25, 34, 35). Floral traits associated with bumblebee and hum-
f lowers (26). mingbird pollination, such as petal carotenoid pigments and
Although hummingbirds have been shown to exert strong nectar volume, appear to be under relatively simple genetic
selection for red coloration (27), we found only a weak rela- control, with major QTLs responsible for pollinator discrimina-
tionship between hummingbird visitation and flower color. tion and reproductive isolation in nature. This work contributes
Hummingbirds had a slight, but significant preference for flow- to the growing body of evidence that adaptation may often
ers with high petal anthocyanin concentration (Fig. 2B), but involve genes of large effect (3, 5, 36–39). Further studies are
exhibited no preference for flowers high in petal carotenoids. needed to determine whether our results can be generalized to
That petal carotenoids significantly decrease bee visitation but other plant taxa where closely related species differ in their
have no effect on hummingbirds suggests that the high concen- major pollinators.
tration of these pigments in the flowers of M. cardinalis (22) may
function primarily to discourage bee visitation. The hypothesis We thank B. Best, J. Coyne, and two anonymous reviewers for
that the red coloration of many hummingbird flowers functions thoughtful comments on the manuscript; B. Best, D. Ewing, B. Frewen,
J. McKay, K. Otto, Y. Sam, and K. Ward for technical assistance; E.
primarily to reduce visitation by insects (28) is consistent with Sugden for identifying the bees; and J. van Wagtendonk, P. Moore, and
the finding that hummingbirds do not have an innate preference the staff of Yosemite National Park for permission to conduct our
for red (29, 30). research. This work was supported by the Royalty Research Fund of
To examine the effect of nectar reward on pollinator the University of Washington and National Science Foundation Grant
visitation, we compared hummingbird and bee visitation rates DEB 9616522.
1. Fisher, R. A. (1930) The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection (Oxford Univ. 18. Grant, V. (1994) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 91, 3–10.
Press, Oxford). 19. Hodges, S. A. & Arnold, M. L. (1994) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 91, 2493–2496.
2. Barton, N. (1998) Nature (London) 395, 751–752. 20. Hiesey, W. M., Nobs, M. A. & Björkman, O. (1971) Carnegie Inst. Washington
3. Orr, H. A. (1998) Evolution 52, 935–949. Publ. 628, 1–213.
4. Coyne, J. A. & Lande, R. (1985) Am. Nat. 126, 141–145. 21. Bradshaw, H. D., Jr., Wilbert, S. M., Otto, K. G. & Schemske, D. W. (1995)
5. Orr, H. A. & Coyne, J. A. (1992) Am. Nat. 140, 725–742. Nature (London) 376, 762–765.
6. Coyne, J. A. & Orr, H. A. (1997) Evolution 51, 295–303. 22. Bradshaw, H. D., Jr., Otto, K. G., Frewen, B. E., McKay, J. G. & Schemske,
7. Coyne, J. A., Crittenden, A. P. & Mah, K. (1994) Science 265, 1461–1464. D. W. (1998) Genetics 149, 367–382.
8. Jones, C. D. (1998) Genetics 149, 1899–1908. 23. Wilbert, S. M., Schemske, D. W. & Bradshaw, H. D., Jr. (1997) Biochem. Syst.
9. Coyne, J. A. (1992) Nature (London) 355, 511–515. Ecol. 25, 437–443.
10. Coyne, J. A. & Orr, H. A. (1998) Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London B 353, 287–305. 24. Chittka, L. & Waser, N. M. (1997) Isr. J. Plant Sci. 45, 169–183.
11. Grant, V. (1949) Evolution 3, 82–97. 25. Waser, N. (1998) Oikos 81, 198–201.
12. Baker, H. G. (1959) Cold Spring Harbor Symp. Quant. Biol. 24, 177–191. 26. Sutherland, D. S. & Vickery, R. K., Jr. (1993) Great Basin Nat. 53, 107–117.
13. Takhtajan, A. (1969) Flowering Plants (Smithsonian Inst. Press, Washington 27. Campbell, D. R., Waser, N. M. & Meléndez-Ackerman, E. J. (1997) Am. Nat.
DC). 149, 295–315.
14. Stebbins, G. L. (1970) Ann. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 1, 307–326. 28. Raven, P. H. (1972) Evolution 26, 674.
15. Levin, D. A. (1978) Evol. Biol. 11, 185–317. 29. Bené, F. (1945) Condor 47, 3–22.
16. Grant, V. (1981) Plant Speciation (Columbia Univ. Press, New York), 2nd Ed. 30. Stiles, F. G. (1976) Condor 78, 10–26.
17. Kiester, A. R., Lande, R. & Schemske, D. W. (1984) Am. Nat. 124, 220–243. 31. Rice, W. R. (1989) Evolution 43, 223–225.
EVOLUTION
Schemske and Bradshaw 105 PNAS 兩 October 12, 1999 兩 vol. 96 兩 no. 21 兩 11915
PLoS BIOLOGY
Asexuals are an important test case for theories of why species exist. If asexual clades displayed the same pattern of
discrete variation as sexual clades, this would challenge the traditional view that sex is necessary for diversification
into species. However, critical evidence has been lacking: all putative examples have involved organisms with recent or
ongoing histories of recombination and have relied on visual interpretation of patterns of genetic and phenotypic
variation rather than on formal tests of alternative evolutionary scenarios. Here we show that a classic asexual clade,
the bdelloid rotifers, has diversified into distinct evolutionary species. Intensive sampling of the genus Rotaria reveals
the presence of well-separated genetic clusters indicative of independent evolution. Moreover, combined genetic and
morphological analyses reveal divergent selection in feeding morphology, indicative of niche divergence. Some of the
morphologically coherent groups experiencing divergent selection contain several genetic clusters, in common with
findings of cryptic species in sexual organisms. Our results show that the main causes of speciation in sexual
organisms, population isolation and divergent selection, have the same qualitative effects in an asexual clade. The
study also demonstrates how combined molecular and morphological analyses can shed new light on the evolutionary
nature of species.
Citation: Fontaneto D, Herniou EA, Boschetti C, Caprioli M, Melone G, et al. (2007) Independently evolving species in asexual bdelloid rotifers. PLoS Biol 5(4): e87. doi:10.1371/
journal.pbio.0050087
Author Summary branches from other such clusters (H1, Figure 2A; and [9]).
Coalescent models can be used to distinguish the two
The evolution of distinct species has often been considered a scenarios [30]. Failure to reject the null model would indicate
property solely of sexually reproducing organisms. In fact, however, a lack of evidence for the existence of independently evolving
there is little evidence as to whether asexual groups do or do not entities.
diversify into species. We show that a famous group of asexual Next, to investigate the role of adaptation to different
animals, the bdelloid rotifers, has diversified into distinct species niches in generating and maintaining diversity within the
broadly equivalent to those found in sexual groups. We surveyed
clade, we extend classic methods from population genetics to
diversity within a single clade, the genus Rotaria, from a range of
habitats worldwide, using DNA sequences and measurements of jaw test directly for adaptive divergence of ecomorphological
morphology from scanning electron microscopy. New statistical traits. If trait diversity evolves solely by neutral divergence in
methods for the combined analysis of morphology and DNA geographic isolation, we expect morphological variation
sequence data confirmed two fundamental properties of species, within and between entities to be proportional to levels of
namely, independent evolution and ecological divergence by neutral genetic variation (H0, Figure 2B, Materials and
natural selection. The two properties did not always coincide to Methods). If, instead, different entities experience divergent
define unambiguous species groups, but this finding is common in selection on their morphology, we expect greater morpho-
sexual groups as well. The results show that sex is not a necessary logical variation between clusters than within them, relative
condition for speciation. The methods offer the potential for to neutral expectations (H1, Figure 2B; and [31]). Past work
increasing our understanding of the nature of species boundaries
has often discussed sympatry of clusters as evidence for niche
across a wide range of organisms.
divergence [1], but, in theory, coexistence can occur without
niche differences [32]; hence, we introduce an alternative,
genomes contain only divergent copies of nuclear genes more direct approach.
present as two similar copies (alleles) in diploid sexual Our results demonstrate that bdelloids have diversified not
organisms rules out anything but extremely rare recombina- only into distinct genetic clusters, indicative of independent
tion [25–27]. Yet, bdelloids have survived for more than 100 evolution, but also into entities experiencing divergent
million y and comprise more than 380 morphologically selection on feeding morphology, indicative of niche diver-
recognizable species and 20 genera [28]. The diversity of the gence. In common with findings of cryptic species in sexual
strictly asexual bdelloids poses a challenge to the idea that sex organisms [33,34], the morphologically coherent groups
is essential for long-term survival and diversification [29]. experiencing divergent selection often include several genet-
However, taxonomy does not constitute strong evidence for ic clusters: this introduces difficulties in deciding which units
evolutionary species: the species could simply be arbitrary to call species, but this problem is shared with sexual
organisms [3,33]. In short, bdelloids have diversified into
labels summarizing morphological variation among a swarm
entities equivalent to sexual species in all respects except that
of clones [7]. We adopt a general evolutionary species
individuals do not interbreed. The results demonstrate the
concept, namely, that species are independently evolving
benefits of statistical analyses of combined molecular and
and distinct entities, and then break the species problem into
morphological data for exploring the evolutionary nature of
a series of testable hypotheses derived from population
species.
genetic predictions [3]. We use the word ‘‘entity’’ to refer to a
set of individuals comprising a unit of diversity according to a
given criterion or test: the question of whether to call those Results/Discussion
entities ‘‘species’’ will be returned to below. We collected all individuals of Rotaria encountered during
Focusing on the genus Rotaria (Figure 1), one of the best- 3 y searching rivers, standing water, dry mosses, and lichens,
characterized genera of bdelloids, we use combined molec- centered on Italy and the United Kingdom but also globally
ular and morphological analyses to distinguish alternative [35]. Individuals were identified to belong to nine taxonomic
scenarios for bdelloid diversification (Figure 2). First, the species (Tables S1 and S2). Most of the described species of
entire clade might represent a single species, that is, a swarm Rotaria missing from our sample are known from only one
of clones with no diversification into independently evolving record or are very rarely encountered (Protocol S1). Bayesian
subsets of individuals. Second, the clade may have diversified and maximum parsimony analyses of mitochondrial cyto-
into a series of independently evolving entities. By ‘‘inde- chrome oxidase I (cox1) and nuclear 28S ribosomal DNA
pendently evolving,’’ we mean that the evolutionary processes sequences provide strong support for the monophyly of
of selection and drift operate separately in different entities taxonomic species (Figures 3, S1, S2, and S3 and Text S1),
[8,9], such that genotypes can only spread within a single with the sole exception of R. rotatoria, which was already
entity. Possible causes of independence include geographical suspected to comprise a species complex based on disagree-
isolation or adaptation to different ecological niches [10,17]. ments among authors [36,37].
The expected outcome is cohesion within entities but genetic Morphometric analyses further support the distinctness of
and phenotypic divergence between them [9–11]. taxonomic species. Bdelloid morphology is hard to measure
We first test for the presence of independently evolving because of their shape-changing abilities; hence, we used
entities. Under the null scenario of no diversification, genetic geometric morphometrics [38] to measure the only suitable
relationships should conform to those expected for a sample trait, their hard jaws, called trophi [39] (Figures 1 and S4).
of individuals from a single asexual population (H0, Figure Trophi size and shape are not characters that have been used
2A). Under the alternative scenario that independently in the traditional taxonomy of the genus (Table S2). Trophi
evolving entities are present, we expect to observe distinct scale weakly with rough measures of body size of each species
clusters of closely related individuals separated by long (mean trophi size against log body length from [37]: r¼0.55, p¼
Clustering test for independent evolution. Under the null model to each node. Below the branch are bootstrap percentages from a
that the entire sample derives from a single population obeying a maximum parsimony search with 100 bootstrap replicates each using
single coalescent process, we calculated the likelihood of waiting a heuristic search with 100 random addition replicates, TBR branch
times, xi, between successive branching events on the DNA tree as swapping, and saving only one tree per addition replicate.
x
Lðxi Þ ¼ b eb i
ð1Þ Found at doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050087.sg001 (21 KB PDF).
Acknowledgments
Supporting Information
We thank Bill Birky, Jr., Austin Burt, Andrea Cardini, Fred Cohan,
Figure S1. Phylogenetic Relationships from Bayesian Analysis of the Brian O’Meara, Ian Owens, Andy Purvis, Vincent Savolainen, Michael
Combined Data Turelli, and two anonymous reviewers for their help.
Posterior probabilities from the Bayesian analysis are indicated next Author contributions. DF, EAH, GM, CR, and TGB conceived and
designed the experiments. DF, EAH, CB, and MC performed the Association and The Linnean Society of London Systematics Fund
experiments. DF, EAH, CB, and TGB analyzed the data. GM, CR, and travel grant to DF, a Royal Society University Research Fellowship to
TGB contributed reagents/materials/analysis tools. DF, EAH, CR, and TGB, a Royal Society Dorothy Hodgkin Fellowship to EAH, and a
TGB wrote the paper. Royal Society International Joint Project grant to CR and TGB.
Funding. This research was supported by Natural Environment Competing interests. The authors have declared that no competing
Research Council UK grant NER/A/S/2001/01133, a Systematics interests exist.
References 33. Agapow PM, Bininda-Emonds ORP, Crandall KA, Gittleman JL, Mace GM,
1. Coyne JA, Orr HA (2004) Speciation. Sunderland (Massachusetts): Sinauer et al. (2004) The impact of species concept on biodiversity studies. Q Rev
Associates. 545 p. Biol 79: 161–179.
2. Rieseberg LH, Wood TE, Baack EJ (2006) The nature of plant species. 34. Avise JC, Walker DE (1999) Species realities and numbers in sexual
Nature 440: 524–527. vertebrates: Perspectives from an asexually transmitted genome. Proc Natl
3. Hey J, Waples RS, Arnold ML, Butlin RK, Harrison RG (2003) Under- Acad Sci U S A 96: 992–995.
standing and confronting species uncertainty in biology and conservation. 35. Fontaneto D, Herniou E, Barraclough TG, Ricci C (2007) On the global
Trends Ecol Evol 18: 597–603. distribution of microscopic animals: New worldwide data on bdelloid
4. Gavrilets S (2004) Fitness landscapes and the origin of species. Princeton rotifers. Zool Stud. In press.
(New Jersey): Princeton University Press. 476 p. 36. Berzins B (1955) Rotatoriefaunan i Aneboda Fiskdammar. Skrifter utgivna
5. Sites JW, Marshall JC (2003) Delimiting species: A Renaissance issue in av Södra Sveriges Fiskeriförening Arsskrift 1954/1955: 107–243.
systematic biology. Trends Ecol Evol 18: 462–470. 37. Donner J (1965) Rotifers. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.
6. Hutchinson GE (1968) When are species necessary? In: Lewontin RC, 38. Bookstein FL (1991) Morphometric tools for landmark data: Geometry and
editor. Population biology and evolution. Syracuse (New York): Syracuse biology. New York: Cambridge University Press. 435 p.
University Press. pp. 177–186. 39. Fontaneto D, Melone G, Cardini A (2004) Shape diversity in the trophi of
7. Maynard Smith J, Szathmary E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. different species of Rotaria (Rotifera, Bdelloidea): A geometric morpho-
New York: W. H. Freeman. 346 p. metric study. Ital J Zool 71: 63–72.
8. Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford 40. Acinas SG, Klepac-Ceraj V, Hunt DE, Pharino C, Ceraj I, et al. (2004) Fine-
(England): Oxford University Press. 68 p. scale phylogenetic architecture of a complex bacterial community. Nature
9. Barraclough TG, Birky CW, Burt A (2003) Diversification in sexual and 430: 551–554.
asexual organisms. Evolution 57: 2166–2172. 41. Hudson RR (1991) Gene genealogies and the coalescent process. Oxf Surv
10. Cohan FM (2001) Bacterial species and speciation. Syst Biol 50: 513–524. Evol Biol 7: 1–44.
11. Templeton A (1989) The meaning of species and speciation: A population 42. Nee S, May RM, Harvey PH (1994) The reconstructed evolutionary process.
genetics approach. In: Otte D, Endler J, editors. Speciation and its Phil Trans R Soc Lond B 344: 305–311.
consequences. Sunderland (Massachusetts): Sinauer Associates. pp. 3–27. 43. Birky CW, Wolf C, Maughan H, Herbertson L, Henry E (2005) Speciation
12. Burt A (2000) Perspective: Sex, recombination, and the efficacy of and selection without sex. Hydrobiologia 546: 29–45.
selection—Was Weismann right? Evolution 54: 337–351. 44. Wakeley J, Aliacar N (2001) Gene genealogies in a metapopulation.
13. Sepp S, Paal J (1998) Taxonomic continuum of Alchemilla (Rosaceae) in Genetics 159: 893–905.
Estonia. Nord J Bot 18: 519–535. 45. Nielsen R (2005) Molecular signatures of natural selection. Annu Rev Genet
14. Roberts MS, Cohan FM (1995) Recombination and migration rates in 39: 197–218.
natural populations of Bacillus subtilis and Bacillus mojavensis. Evolution 49: 46. de Queiroz K (2005) Different species problems and their resolution.
1081–1094. Bioessays 27: 1263–1269.
15. Barrett SJ, Sneath PHA (1994) A numerical phenotypic taxonomic study of 47. Futuyma DJ (1987) On the role of species in anagenesis. Am Nat 130: 465–
the genus Neisseria. Microbiology (Reading, England) 140: 2867–2891. 473.
16. Konstantinos KT, Ramette A, Tiedje JM (2006) The bacterial species 48. Eldredge N (1989) Macroevolutionary dynamics. New York: McGraw-Hill.
definition in the genomic era. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B 361: 1929–1940. 226 p.
17. Cohan FM (2006) Towards a conceptual and operational union of bacterial
49. Barraclough TG, Herniou E (2003) Why do species exist? Insights from
systematics, ecology, and evolution. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B 361: 1985–1996.
sexuals and asexuals. Zoology 106: 275–282.
18. Hanage WP, Fraser C, Spratt BG (2005) Fuzzy species among recombino-
50. Balloux F, Lehmann L, de Meeus T (2003) The population genetics of clonal
genic bacteria. BMC Biol 3: 6.
and partially clonal diploids. Genetics 164: 1635–1644.
19. Hanage WP, Fraser C, Spratt BG (2006) The impact of homologous
51. Hebert PDN, Cywinska A, Ball SL, DeWaard JR (2003) Biological
recombination on the generation of diversity in bacteria. J Theor Biol 239:
identifications through DNA barcodes. Proc Trans R Soc Lond B 270:
210–219.
313–321.
20. Ochman H, Lerat E, Daubin V (2005) Examining bacterial species under the
52. Funk DJ, Omland KE (2003) Species-level paraphyly and polyphyly:
specter of gene transfer and exchange. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 102: 6595–
6599. Frequency, causes, and consequences, with insights from animal mitochon-
21. Hanage WP, Spratt BG, Turner KME, Fraser C (2006) Modelling bacterial drial DNA. Ann Rev Ecol Evol Syst 34: 397–423.
speciation. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B 361: 2039–2044. 53. Hudson RR, Coyne JA (2002) Mathematical consequences of the genea-
22. Ricci CN (1987) Ecology of bdelloids: How to be successful. Hydrobiologia logical species concept. Evolution 56: 1557–1565.
147: 117–127. 54. Will KW, Rubinoff D (2004) Myth of the molecule: DNA barcodes for
23. Birky CW (2004) Bdelloid rotifers revisited. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 101: species cannot replace morphology for identification and classification.
2651–2652. Cladistics 20: 47–55.
24. Butlin R (2002) The costs and benefits of sex: New insights from old asexual 55. De Ley P, De Ley IT, Morris K, Abebe E, Mundo-Ocampo M, et al. (2005) An
lineages. Nat Rev Genet 3: 311–317. integrated approach to fast and informative morphological vouchering of
25. Mark Welch D, Meselson M (2000) Evidence for the evolution of bdelloid nematodes for applications in molecular barcoding. Phil Trans R Soc Lond
rotifers without sexual reproduction or genetic exchange. Science 288: B 360: 1945–1958.
1211–1215. 56. Ronquist F, Huelsenbeck JP (2003) MrBayes 3: Bayesian phylogenetic
26. Mark Welch JL, Mark Welch DB, Meselson M (2004) Cytogenetic evidence inference under mixed models. Bioinformatics 19: 1572–1574.
for asexual evolution of bdelloid rotifers. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 101: 57. Rohlf FJ, Slice D (1990) Extensions of the Procrustes method for the
1618–1621. optimal superimposition of landmarks. Syst Zool 39: 40–59.
27. Mark Welch DB, Cummings MP, Hillis DM, Meselson M (2004) Divergent 58. Team RDC (2006) R: A language and environment for statistical computing.
gene copies in the asexual class Bdelloidea (Rotifera) separated before the Vienna, Austria.
bdelloid radiation of within bdelloid families. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 101: 59. Rohlf FJ (2005) Tps series. Stony Brook (New York): Department of Ecology
1622–1625. and Evolution, State University of New York at Stony Brook.
28. Melone G, Fontaneto D (2005) Trophi structure in bdelloid rotifers. 60. Sanderson MJ (2002) Estimating absolute rates of molecular evolution and
Hydrobiologia 546: 197–202. divergence times: A penalized likelihood approach. Mol Biol Evol 19: 101–
29. Holman EW (1987) Recognizability of sexual and asexual species of rotifers. 109.
Syst Zool 36: 381–386. 61. Lynch M, Hill WG (1986) Phenotypic evolution by neutral mutation.
30. Pons J, Barraclough TG, Gomez-Zurita J, Cardoso A, Duran DP, et al. (2006) Evolution 40: 915–935.
Sequence-based species delimitation for the DNA taxonomy of unde- 62. Schluter D, Price T, Mooers AO, Ludwig D (1997) Likelihood of ancestor
scribed insects. Syst Biol 55: 595–609. states in adaptive radiation. Evolution 51: 1699–1711.
31. McDonald JH, Kreitman M (1991) Adaptive protein evolution at the adh 63. Paradis E, Claude J, Strimmer K (2004) APE: Analyses of Phylogenetics and
locus in Drosophila. Nature 351: 652–654. Evolution in R language. Bioinformatics 20: 289–290.
32. Hubbell SP (2001) The unified neutral theory of biodiversity and 64. Yang Z (1997) PAML: A program package for phylogenetic analysis by
biogeography. Princeton (New Jersey): Princeton University Press. maximum likelihood. CABIOS 13: 555–556.
Summary first of these theories is the one put forward by Charles Darwin
Speciation is a central but elusive issue in evolutionary in 1859.(3) The second is the theory developed as part of the
biology. Over the past sixty years, the subject has been
studied within a framework conceived by Ernst Mayr and Modern Synthesis in the 1930s and 1940s. Since the theories
Theodosius Dobzhansky and subsequently developed differ chiefly in their emphasis on which factor drives popula-
further by numerous other workers. In this ``isolation'' tions apart, I will refer to them as the ``selection theory'' and the
theory, the evolution of reproductive isolation is a key ``isolation theory'', respectively.
element of speciation; natural selection is given only I will first recapitulate some aspects of the historical deve-
secondary importance while gene flow is considered
lopment of speciation theory, outline the basic tenets of both
prohibitive to the process. In this paper, I argue that
certain elements in this approach have produced confu- views, and highlight the conflicts between them. Then I will
sion and irreconcilability among students of speciation. review three prominent debates related to speciation and
The more prominent debates in speciation (i.e., the argue that all are reflections of those conflicts. At the same
species definition, sympatry/allopatry, and the role of time, I will describe recent data from field ecology, molecular
reinforcement) all derive from an inherent conflict
population genetics, laboratory experiments with Drosophila
between the ``isolation'' theory and Darwin's ``selection''
view on species and speciation (in which disruptive and computer analysis, which suggest that a modernised
selection is crucial). New data, mainly from field ecology, version of Darwin's view is more likely to bring progress in the
molecular population genetics, laboratory studies with field than an emphasis only on the isolation theory.
Drosophila and computer analysis, all suggest that the
isolation theory may no longer be the most desirable
vantage point from which to explore speciation. Instead, The conflict
environmental selection in large populations, often
Species and speciation form the basis of one of the longest-
unimpeded by ongoing gene flow, appears to be the
decisive element. The traditional preoccupation with standing debates in biology. Dedicated attempts to define
reproductive isolation has created gaps in our knowledge species were made as early as the 17th century.(4± 6) No single
of several crucial issues, mainly regarding the role of early author, however, devoted as much time to it as Darwin,
environmental selection and its connection with mate whose expertise in taxonomy made him the foremost authority
selection. BioEssays 22:1134±1141, 2000.
on species in the mid-19th century. In On the Origin of Species
ß 2000 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
by Means of Natural Selection, he elaborated the point that
Introduction species are no more than ``well-marked varieties'', and that the
Speciation, the evolution of new species, is a central but un- term was ``arbitrarily given for the sake of convenience to a set
resolved issue in evolutionary biology.(1) What is the essence of individuals closely resembling each other''.(3) He added that
of speciation? What geographical conditions are required for it the ``search for the undiscovered and undiscoverable essence
to happen? What evolutionary forces are crucial? Many of the term species'' was in vain, as it was an attempt at
answers have been given to these questions and often appear ``defining the undefinable''.(7)
irreconcilable.(2) This has given rise to the conviction that Most present day biologists consider Darwin's opinion
speciation is a very multifarious phenomenon, which defies outdated and mainly accept the ``biological species concept''
any generalisation. As I will argue in this paper, this confusion (BSC). The BSC, which was developed during the 1930s by
stems largely from a conflict between two theories on specia- Ernst Mayr and Theodosius Dobzhansky, hinges (unlike
tion that have existed side-by-side for the past sixty years. The Darwin's concept) primarily on reproductive barriers. Mayr
defined species as ``groups of actually or potentially inter-
breeding natural populations, which are reproductively iso-
lated from other such groups''.(8) Dobzhansky consequently
applied the BSC to define the process by which species arise
Laboratory of Genetics, Wageningen University, Wageningen, The
Netherlands. Present address: Institute for Tropical Biology and
(i.e., speciation) as ``that stage of the evolutionary process at
Conservation, Universiti Malaysia Sabah, Locked Bag 2073, 88999 which the once actually or potentially interbreeding array of
Kota Kinabalu, Sabah, Malaysia. E-mail: schilthuizen@excite.com forms becomes segregated into two or more separate arrays
which are physiologically incapable of breeding''.(9)
1134 BioEssays 22.12 BioEssays 22:1134±1141, ß 2000 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
114
Problems and paradigms
It is important to realise that the BSC was not primarily able to make a single species change by adaptation, but also to
intended as a convenient criterion for sorting taxa. Instead, it make a single species split in two.
was an essential part of a multidisciplinary theory of specia- Darwin observed that an assemblage of species is more
tion. This theory developed in a number of logical steps. Mayr's efficient at exploiting a patch of habitat than a single species.
vast ornithological experience with geographic variation and By analogy, he reasoned that, under conditions of severe
endemism in New Guinea and Polynesia, and similar data from competition, natural selection will favour those individuals
other groups of organisms, had convinced him that geogra- within a population that have the most extreme phenotypes,
phical isolation (allopatry) was cardinal to the speciation and therefore suffer the least from competition with relatives.
process. His 1942 book Systematics and the Origin of ``Consequently, I cannot doubt that in the course of many
Species, was intended to show that the ``crucial process in thousands of generations, the most distinct varieties of any
speciation is not selection [ . . . ], but isolation''.(10) The fact that one species [ . . . ] would always have the best chance of
isolation was crucial meant that the processes responsible succeeding and of increasing in numbers, and thus of sup-
for allopatric differentiation would break down under gene planting the less distinct varieties; and varieties, when
flow. So, sympatry would only be possible once reproductive rendered very distinct from each other, take the rank of
isolation had evolved. In the absence of reproductive isolation, species''.(3)
two differentiated populations would fuse again upon second- The main difference between Darwin's view and the one
ary contact. Therefore, reproductive isolation needed to be elaborated by Mayr and Dobzhansky, then, is the role of
the decisive criterion for what constitutes a species, and the natural selection. To Darwin, natural selection could make a
evolution of reproductive isolation would define the point single population change to suit a changing environment
where speciation has been completed. (adaptation) or it could force a single population in two, to
The processes responsible for generating reproductive better exploit the available niches (speciation). Mayr and
isolation among populations were considered to be a subtle Dobzhansky, in contrast, decoupled adaptation from specia-
combination of genetic drift, natural selection, and epistasis, tion; environmental selection is a causative agent only in
acting in small ``peripherally isolated'' populations. Mayr adaptation. As I hope the following paragraphs will show, much
proved (1954, 1963) that, under the right circumstances, the of the confusion about speciation is the result of the fact that
combined effects of these forces could produce new co- the isolation theory has become embedded in the selection-
adapted gene complexes with reconstituted reproductive based neodarwinian school. Three conflicts in evolutionary
systems, i.e., new species under the BSC.(4,11) So, the theory biology are probably the direct result from this irreconcilability.
of speciation developed by Mayr and Dobzhansky relies These are the species definition, the allopatry/sympatry, and
almost exclusively on the evolution of reproductive isolation the reinforcement debates.
for explaining the origin and maintenance of species. To
many biologists, the development of this theory was an The species definition debate
improvement on Darwin, who had not realised the importance In Mayr's writings, two views on species appear. The first is
of reproductive isolation and hence lacked a clear theory on that all individuals of a species share the same well-integrated
speciation. complex of epistatically and pleiotropically interacting genes.
Both these claims about Darwin, however, are not entirely This is the species concept, and Mayr writes that the evolution
correct. Contrary to popular belief, Darwin was well-aware of of two well-integrated gene complexes from a single ancestral
reproductive isolation between species. For example, he one is ``the essence of speciation''.(4) At the same time,
starts chapter 8 of On the Origin of Species with: ``The view however, the biological species definition makes no mention
generally entertained by naturalists is that species, when of gene complexes, but rather of devices for reproductive
intercrossed, have been specially endowed with the quality of isolation. Consequently, Mayr can also be found writing that
sterility, in order to prevent the confusion of all organic ``speciation is characterized by the acquisition of these
forms''.(3) Darwin, however, knew that hybridisation is com- devices''.(4) What transpires is that Mayr did not claim that
mon among many groups of animals and plants, without reproductive isolation per se was essential, but that new
affecting the distinctness of species. This was one of the gene complexes can not evolve nor persist before such
reasons why he did not consider reproductive isolation of barriers to gene flow were in place: ``Reproductive isolation
crucial importance, writing that ``neither sterility nor fertility refers to the protective devices of a harmoniously coadapted
affords any clear distinction between species or varieties''.(3) gene pool against destruction by genotypes from other gene
To Darwin, then, speciation (or, as he called it, ``divergence of pools''.(4)
character'') was not brought about by the evolution of The contrast between Mayr's species concept (coadapted
reproductive barriers, but by a mechanism that would force a gene complexes) and his species definition (reproductive
single species in two directions, reproductively isolated or not. isolation) is illustrated by his discussion of cytoplasmic incom-
This mechanism was natural selection, which would not just be patibility in insects. This phenomenon, which is now known to
115
Problems and paradigms
be caused by the bacterium Wolbachia,(12,13) can produce full occur without geographic isolation? If so, how easily, how
reproductive isolation between populations infected by differ- quickly and under what circumstances does it occur? In
ent strains of the symbiont. Hence, Laven(14) suggested that Darwin's theory of speciation (see above), sympatry is an
cytoplasmic incompatibility could be a mechanism for instan- implied prerequisite. Here, speciation is fueled by intraspecific
taneous speciation. Mayr,(4) however, objected that two competition. The most extreme phenotypes are selected,
cytoplasmically incompatible populations ``answer the defini- since they suffer least from mutual exclusion. By necessity,
tion of [...] species, yet there is serious doubt whether it would this process takes place only in full sympatry. In the isolation
be legitimate to label as species allopatric strains that may theory, on the contrary, there is no place for sympatry. Since in
differ by only a single genetic factor.'' Apparently, even though this framework any gene flow is expected to disrupt the
this single factor conveyed complete intersterility, Mayr hesi- evolution of new coadapted gene complexes, it is inconcei-
tated to apply the BSC, because the evolution of two different, vable that two different gene complexes could diverge within
coadapted gene complexes had not taken place.(15) the same population, without any prior reproductive isolation.
Recent molecular population genetic data, however, sug- Dobzhansky wrote: ``Species are distinct because they carry
gest that the BSC with its reproductive-isolation criterion does different constellations of genes. Interbreeding [ . . . ] results in
not automatically follow from a concept of a species as a co- a breakdown of these systems [ . . . ]. Hence, the maintenance
adapted gene complex, because the latter can persist in spite of species as discrete units is contingent on their isolation.
of the absence of reproductive barriers. In the fruit fly species Species formation without isolation is impossible''.(9)
complex Rhagoletis pomonella, for example, an estimated Empirical data exist for both allopatric and sympatric
gene flow of 6% does not negate the effects of disruptive speciation, however. On the one hand, Mayr's work remains
selection for an apple- and a hawthorn-feeding species.(16) one of the most comprehensive enumerations of evidence for
Another example comes from microsatellite studies of two allopatric speciation, listing numerous instances where popu-
European oak species. In spite of pervasive interspecific lations isolated by geographic barriers have genetically
hybridization and gene flow, the two sympatric species remain diverged to a small or large extent.(4) On the other hand,
morphologically, ecologically and genetically distinct.(17) evidence for speciation in sympatry has also been accumulat-
Furthermore, based on mtDNA and microsatellite data, ing steadily, especially in the past two decades. Some of this
vertebrate species(18,19) have been shown to exhibit consider- evidence is indirect: molecular phylogenetics of sympatric
able gene flow across ecotones. Nevertheless, this has not groups of freshwater fish in constricted environments (small
prevented the divergent environmental selection pressures lakes, the waters around rocky islands or a single stream
on either side of the ecotones resulting in the build-up of system) has revealed monophyly.(22± 24) Other evidence is
differently coadapted gene complexes.(20) more direct: observed host shifts in several groups of insects
These new data suggest that species differences can have led to the origin and maintenance of genetically differen-
persist in the face of gene flow. Therefore, the importance of tiated host-specialists.(25± 29)
``protective devices'' in the form of reproductive isolation These conflicting observations have produced a consen-
mechanisms may have been overstated. Consequently, since sus among many evolutionary biologists that speciation is
the relevant characteristics of species can also be attained multifarious. It can be allopatric, when it is caused by isolation,
without the protection of complete reproductive isolation, the or sympatric, when selection is the driving force. Differences of
case for using this property as a sine qua non for characterising opinion revolve primarily about the prevalence of either mode.
species has been considerably weakened. What remains is The two modes may not be so different, however, and, instead,
the valuable insight that species are stable coadapted gene they could be two ends of a continuum of gene-flow opport-
complexes. Disconnected from reproductive isolation, it is not unities, with selection as the driving factor across the range. To
possible or desirable to formalise this notion into a strict assess the merits of this view, it may be worthwhile to investi-
species definition. In evolutionary biology, it should be suf- gate in more detail the respective roles of selection and iso-
ficient to study the evolution of such gene complexes, without lation in allopatry.
any reference to the category assigned to them. In taxonomy, To begin with the latter, indications exist that even in
the BSC has only incidentally been used as a standard to test classical cases of allopatry (populations isolated in caves, on
systematic revisions against and Darwin's motto that ``the islands, or in habitat fragments) residual gene flow remains
opinion of naturalists having sound judgement and wide among the supposedly isolated populations. Populations of
experience seems the only guide to follow'',(3) has never cave organisms, for example, have been shown to be inter-
ceased to be important. connected by subterranean populations living in minute rock
crevices,(30) while land snail populations on isolated limestone
The sympatry/allopatry debate hills probably exchange genes via low-density populations on
The single most conspicuous conflict in speciation undoubt- non-calciferous soils.(31) The degree of isolation, then, may
edly is the sympatry/allopatry debate.(1,4,21) Can speciation often have been overestimated.
116
Problems and paradigms
The role of selection, in contrast, may have been under- gence corresponds well with the geological age of the barrier.
valued in models of allopatric speciation. In the basic allopatry Nevertheless, there can be no doubt that the populations have
model, a species' range becomes bisected by a physical always been very large, which rules out any bottleneck effects
barrier, producing two very large daughter populations. With or genetic drift. In contrast, transisthmian environmental
this model, since selective differences are likely to be small, differences are considerable, including tidal influence, nutrient
and the populations so large that genetic drift is close to zero, content and temperature fluctuations, which might better
speciation will proceed slowly, if at all. Stebbins,(32) for explain the genetic differentiation.
example, pointed out that American and Asian sycamore Laboratory studies, too, have shown that reproductive
trees, after millions of years of isolation, have failed to evolve isolation can build up in ``allopatric'' populations exposed to
reproductive isolation. According to Mayr,(33) the rise of the different selection regimes. Rice and Hostert(34) cite numerous
Isthmus of Panama, which partitioned entire marine biotas into experiments using Drosophila that resulted in prezygotic
a Pacific and a Caribbean portion 3.5 million years ago, had reproductive isolation. Some experimenters(43,44) also tested
produced ``two collossal gene pools'', and ``differences are still the development of reproductive isolation between allopatric
either nonexistent or they are so slight that one doesn't really populations that experienced the same selection pressure,
like to rank these as species.'' and obtained negative results. These developments indicate
In the isolation framework, where founder effects and that in both allopatric speciation and sympatric speciation,
genetic drift play an important role, large isolated populations adaptation to different niches is the driving force, although
are not expected to be the ideal situation for the evolution stronger selection pressures are required to produce specia-
of new coadapted gene complexes. Stebbins's sycamore tion in the latter. This selection pressure will often be met
enigma, for example, was explained by Mayr(4) by arguing that because of strong competition in sympatry.
the two populations had been too large to be genetically
restructured and hence continued to share the same balancing The reinforcement debate
systems. An alternative for basic allopatry is the bottleneck The reinforcement model of speciation says that populations
model, in which geographically isolated populations are that have attained a certain degree of postzygotic reproductive
founded by a very small number of colonists. In such a small isolation in allopatry (as shown by reduced hybrid fitness),
population, random changes in gene frequencies and the are expected to improve prezygotic reproductive isolation
ensuing changes in epistasis could, theoretically at least, on secondary contact, given natural selection for assortative
cause a genetic revolution, leading to a new coadapted gene mating.(9,45± 47) In view of its reliance on reproductive isolation
complex, which subsequently could possibly shift into a new alone, reinforcement can thus be seen as fully consistent with
niche. the ``isolation'' view of speciation.
Little evidence for bottleneck speciation exists, however. To better define the role of reinforcement in speciation,
Five small-scale(34) and three large-scale(35 ±37) laboratory Butlin distinguished between the processes of reproductive
studies have largely yielded negative results. Molecular data character displacement (namely, the adaptive increase of
from field populations also do not support the idea. Ancient assortative mating between populations that have already
allele polymorphisms in island species flocks, long regarded experienced full postzygotic reproductive isolation) and
as prime examples of speciation by founder effects, were dis- reinforcement (that is, adaptive increase of assortative mating
covered to be high. Enzyme polymorphisms in the Hawaiian between populations that have experienced only partial
Drosophilas are just as high as those in their mainland postzygotic reproductive isolation).(45,46) With this distinction
counterparts,(38) and in the GalaÂpagos finches, 21 ancient in mind, we see that reproductive character displacement is
allele variants were found at an Mhc locus.(39) The persistence not a speciation process under the isolation theory, whereas
of high numbers of ancient haplotypes is inconsistent with very reinforcement is. Nevertheless, the basic evolutionary me-
small numbers of colonists. In the case of the GalaÂpagos chanism (selection for assortative mating) is identical in both
finches, the founding populations must at least have been as processes.
large as forty birds, and probably several hundred. Butlin's papers, which also carried criticism against the
At the same time, new data tend to favour the basic probability of reinforcement actually operating in nature, were
allopatry model. The Panama Isthmus, regarded by Mayr as followed by a number of theoretical,(47 ±49) comparative(50,51)
ineffective in producing allopatric speciation, is now known and empirical(52,53) studies. Liou and Price(49) showed that,
to have caused the evolution of numerous reproductively under conditions of low hybrid fitness and considerable initial
isolated species in various groups of marine organisms.(40) genetic divergence between the two hybridising populations,
Knowlton and co-workers(41,42) for example, have shown that reinforcement could indeed reduce gene flow to zero. The
the isthmus separates almost twenty pairs of sister species of empirical studies, which were done on flycatchers(53) and
snapping shrimp. All species pairs are reproductively isolated Drosophila,(52) supported this, as they showed an increase in
while morphologically very similar, and their mtDNA diver- assortative mating in sympatry, whereas hybrid fitness was
117
Problems and paradigms
low but not zero. The comparative studies on Drosophila, are involved in male±male sperm competition, sexual
finally, showed that sympatric species have relatively stronger manipulation of females by males, and the female prevention
prezygotic isolation than allopatric species, which also lends of the latterÐa set of selective pressures referred to as
support to reinforcement as a relevant speciation mode in this sexually antagonistic selection.(60) Again, if males and females
group. do not coevolve (as in allopatric populations), their compat-
From the viewpoint of the isolation theory, then, these ibility will decrease, resulting eventually in both prezygotic and
recent data suggest that reinforcement can and does indeed postzygotic isolation.
produce new species. From the viewpoint of the selection All the situations mentioned above should result in a
theory, however, the relevance of reinforcement is reduced. situation where isolation is attained first, unrelated to environ-
As the process acts only on pairs of populations that are mental selection, after which the resultant genetic partitioning
already genetically and ecologically diverged and that have a would allow for independent adaptation in both daughter
strong (though not complete) degree of reproductive isolation, populations. Will the latter actually happen? Two facts make
it can be argued that reinforcement is not a speciation mode subsequent niche shifts unlikely in the ``instantaneous'' situa-
because it is not instrumental in the populations' divergence. tions. First, the reproductive isolation trait will usually be the
It only serves to reduce gene flow to zero. If the selection only genetic difference between populations that are incom-
viewpoint is adopted, reinforcement represents the same patible due to Wolbachia infection, coil reversal, or polyploidy.
phenomenon as reproductive character displacement: it is Second, the environment will remain unaltered. In coil reversal
adaptation within two populations that have already speciated. and Wolbachia infection, respectively, the conditions for the
establishment(61) and maintenance(15) of the isolation are
Redefining the role of reproductive isolation restrictive, and empirical evidence is rare.(54,58,62) Allopoly-
In the previous paragraphs, I have argued that the selection ploid (rather than autopolyploid) plants, however, are an
view may eventually be a preferable platform for discussing exception. The combination of two different genomes may
species and speciation than the isolation view. Selection, allow the new polyploid to be preadapted to a niche that is
rather than reproductive isolation, appears to be what drives intermediate between those of its parents. In fact, studies of
and keeps species apart, both in allopatric and in sympatric recently originated allopolyploids show that these establish
situations. It will be interesting, however, to examine in more successfully in such intermediate habitats (e.g., Tragopogon
detail the precise role of reproductive isolation, for two in North America see Refs. 63,64). Possibly, allopolyploid
reasons. (1) Models and observations exist where full pre- speciation may be a case where the isolation view is more
zygotic and/or postzygotic isolation evolves between popu- appropriate than the selection view. However, the same may
lations without any obvious environmental selection. (2) not be true for situations where isolation is attained through
Reproductive isolation is still important, as it will act as a sexual selection and/or sexually antagonistic selection.
catalyst of speciation processes that are initiated by selection. On the one hand, there is no doubt that speciation is often
Two types of ``non-environmental'' reproductive isolation, associated with strong divergence in traits for assortative
i.e., without any direct connection to environmental selection, mating and/or postzygotic isolation. For example, Odysseus, a
can be envisaged. First, there are situations of the ``instanta- gene responsible for hybrid male sterility between Drosophila
neous kind, where a single trait becomes fixed in a population, simulans and D. mauritiana has turned out to be a homeobox
rendering it reproductively isolated from other populations. gene, expressed in the testes, which evolves extremely rapidly
Examples include bidirectional cytoplasmic incompatibility due to an unknown selection pressure.(65,66) (See the article
in arthropods due to infection by the bacterial symbiont by Orr and Presgraves, this issue.) The fact that molecular
Wolbachia, as mentioned above,(14,15,54,55) coil reversal in phylogenies of the Drosophila simulans clade using this gene
globular snails, which causes mechanical incompatibility of show better resolution than those using other genetic markers,
the genitalia,(56± 58) and polyploidy in plants, which leads to suggests that it has been important in the speciation process
inviability of hybrids due to aneuploidy.(4) Second, recent from a very early stage onwards.(67) Many other genes in-
advances in the field of sexual selection suggest that isolated volved in reproduction show similar evidence for strong
populations can easily diverge in their systems for sexual selection, although usually it is not known if these genes are
signalling. Computer analysis of ``runaway'' sexual selection responsible for reproductive isolation between species.(68 ± 70)
has shown that this process exhibits unpredictable, cyclical Other evidence comes from comparative studies of speciation
behaviour, which is likely to run out of phase in allopatric rates in birds, which generally show that polygamous clades
populations.(59) This means that, soon after geographic (where ``runaway'' sexual selection will be more prevalent),
separation, male signals in one population may no longer show higher speciation rates.(71,72) In effect, sexual selection
coincide with a preference in females of the other population, can play a major role in incipient isolation.
leading to prezygotic isolation. Moreover, allopatric popula- On the other hand, however, sexual selection and sexually
tions are likely to diverge in the complicated sets of traits that antagonistic selection may often be chanelled by natural
118
Problems and paradigms
Speciation initiated by: Disruption of gene flow due to geographical, temporal, ecological, Adaptation to different environments
or any other type of gene-pool segregation; most rapid in
peripheral isolates, but also possible in other geographic settings
Speciation progresses by: Genetic drift and founder effects, natural selection or both Natural selection and superimposed sexual
selection
Speciation completed when: Pre- and/or postmating reproductive isolation has evolved Differently adapted gene pools have
evolved
Accompanying species Biological species concept Darwin's species definition
concept:
Geographic setting: Most rapid in peripheral isolates, but also possible in other Most-rapid in sympatry, but also possible in
geographic settings other geographic settings
selection. Colour variation in male guppies(73) and possibly natural selection. Reproductive isolation is then seen to take a
also cichlids,(74) for example, is influenced by the presence or catalytic, rather than an instrumental role. This view on species
absence of predatory birds, and mate selection in fishes is and speciation is surprisingly compatible with Darwin's ideas
often by body size, which is also an environmentally selected on the subject.
trait.(75) In addition, many types of reproductive isolation have Future work on the role of environmental selection should
been shown to be caused secondarily by environmental fill conspicuous gaps in our knowledge of speciation. The
selection. For example, flowering time in monkeyflowers has experiments by Kilias and co-workers(43) and Dodd,(44) which
diverged due to water regimes of the soil(76) and diurnal mating showed that prezygotic and weak postzygotic isolation
rhythms in melon flies have been shown to diverge as a evolved in ``allopatric'' laboratory populations of Drosophila
correlated response to larval development time.(77) Therefore, under conditions of different selection regimes, but not under
possibly, even in cases where species appear to have formed identical selection, urgently need a detailed follow-up. These
primarily due to the evolution of reproductive isolation, this studies indicate that reproductive isolation may often be a
reproductive isolation may have been actually superimposed by-product of selection, whereas theory(59,60) suggests that
on an underlying environmental selection. it might also build up independently. We may only have
In general, then, the role for reproductive isolation may be scratched the surface of the full extent of interactions between
seen as catalytic, rather than instrumental in speciation. The natural and sexual selection.
buildup of differently adapted gene pools will be disrupted by
recombination. Because assortative mating and postzygotic Acknowledgements
isolation can prevent this, selection and reproductive isolation For the development of the ideas presented in this paper, I am
are probably best viewed as mutually reinforcing, as has been indebted to several people who have helped shape my view-
pointed out by Rice and Hostert: once an initial episode of points, namely, John Endler, Jeffrey Feder, Arne Mooers, Bill
strong environmental selection causes partial reproductive Rice, Michael Rosenzweig, Ulrich Schliewen, Dolph Schluter,
isolation as a by-product, weaker selection (which otherwise and Chung-I Wu. The constructive comments by Jacques van
would have been hampered by gene flow) will then be able to Alphen, Jeroen Roelfsema, Jeffrey Feder, Ole Seehausen,
differentiate the two populations further, which in turn causes Chung-I Wu and two anonymous reviewers on an earlier
further reproductive isolation, and so on.(34) version of the manuscript are also gratefully acknowledged.
For the contents of this paper, however, only I am responsible.
Conclusions
In this paper, I have attempted to argue that many of the References
1. Berlocher SH. Origins; a brief history of research on speciation. In
debates concerning speciation are the result of conflicts Howard DJ, Berlocher SH. ed; Endless Forms; Species and Speciation.
between the ``selection'' and ``isolation'' views on species and Oxford. Oxford University Press. 1999. p3±15
speciation. The biological species concept, the scepticism 2. Futuyma DJ. Mechanisms of speciation. Science 1983;219:1059±1060.
3. Darwin C. On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection or
towards sympatric speciation, the emphasis on genetic drift, Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. London: Murray.
and the popularity of reinforcement are all features of the 1859.
isolation theory, which views speciation as a process that 4. Mayr E. Animal Species and Evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press. 1963.
begins and ends with the acquisition of reproductive isolation. 5. Dover G, Gittenberger E, Mallet J. A species definition: a functional
Recent data, however, allow a re-appreciation of the role of approach. Trends Ecol Evol 1995;10:489±491.
119
Problems and paradigms
6. Mallet J. A species definition for the Modern Synthesis. Trends Ecol Evol 34. Rice WR, Hostert EE. Laboratory experiments on speciation: what have
1995;10:294±299. we learned in 40 years? Evolution 1993;47:1637±1653.
7. Milner R. The Encyclopedia of Evolution; Humanity's Search for its 35. Moya A, Galiana A, Ayala FJ. Founder-effect speciation theory: failure
Origins. New York: Henry Holt & Co. 1993. of experimental corroboration. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1995;92:
8. Mayr E. Speciation phenomena in birds. Am Nat 1940;74:249±278. 3983±3986.
9. Dobzhansky T. Genetics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia 36. Rundle HD, Mooers Aé, Whitlock MC. Single founder-flush events and
University Press. 1937. the evolution of reproductive isolation. Evolution 1998;52:1850±1855.
10. Mayr E. Introduction, 1999. In Mayr E. ed; Systematics and the Origin of 37. Mooers Aé, Rundle HD, Whitlock MC. The effects of selection and
Species from the Viewpoint of a Zoologist. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard bottlenecks on male mating success in peripheral isolates. Am Nat
University Press. 1999. p xiii±xxxv 1999;153:437±444.
11. Mayr E. Change of genetic environment and evolution. In Huxley J, 38. DeSalle R, Hunt JA. Molecular evolution in Hawaiian Drosophilids. Trends
Hardy AC, Ford EB. eds; Evolution as a Process. London: Allen & Unwin. Ecol Evol 1987;2:212±216.
1954. p 157±180. 39. Vincek V, O'Huigin C, Satta Y, Takahata N, Boag PT, Grant PR, Grant BR,
12. Yen JH, Barr AR. New hypothesis of the cause of cytoplasmic incom- Klein J. How large was the founding population of Darwin's finches? Proc
patibility in Culex pipiens. Nature 1971;232:657±658. R Soc Lond Ser B 1997;264:111±118.
13. O'Neill SL, Hoffmann AA, Werren JH. Influential Passengers: Inherited 40. Lessios HA. The first stage of speciation as seen in organisms separated
Microorganisms and Arthropod Reproduction. Oxford: Oxford University by the Isthmus of Panama. In Howard DJ, Berlocher SH. ed; Endless
Press. 1997. FormsÐSpecies and Speciation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1998.
14. Laven H. Speciation by cytoplasmic isolation in the Culex p 186±201.
pipiens complex. Cold Spring Harbor Symp. Quant. Biol. 1959;24: 41. Knowlton N, Weigt LA, SoloÂrzano LA, Millis DK, Bermingham E. Diverg-
166±173. ence in proteins, mitochondrial DNA, and reproductive compatibility
15. Schilthuizen M, Stouthamer R. Can selfish symbionts drive parapatric across the Isthmus of Panama. Science 1993;260:1629±1632.
speciation? Proc Appl Exp Ent NEV 1999;10:29±35. 42. Knowlton N, Weigt LA. New dates and new rates for divergence across
16. Feder JL, Opp S, Wlazlo B, Reynolds K, Go W, Spisak S. Host fidelity is the Isthmus of Panama. Proc R Soc Lond Ser B 1998;265:2257±2263.
an effective pre-mating barrier between sympatric races of the apple 43. Kilias G, Alahiotis SN, Pelecanos N. A multifactorial genetic investigation
maggot fly. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1994;91:7990±7994. of speciation theory using Drosophila melanogaster. Evolution 1980;34:
17. Muir G, Fleming CC, SchloÈtterer C. Species status of hybridizing oaks. 730±737.
Nature 2000;405:1016. 44. Dodd DMB. Reproductive isolation as a consequence of adaptive
18. Schneider CJ, Smith TB, Larison B, Moritz C. A test of alternative models divergence in Drosophila pseudoobscura. Evolution 1989;43;
of diversification in tropical rainforests: ecological gradients vs. rainforest 1308±1311.
refugia. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1999;96:13869±13873. 45. Butlin RK. Speciation by reinforcement. Trends Ecol Evol 1987;2:8±13.
19. Smith TB, Wayne RK, Girman DJ, Bruford MW. A role for ecotones in 46. Butlin RK. Reinforcement of premating isolation. In Otte D, Endler JA. ed;
generating rainforest biodiversity. Science 1997;276:1855±1857. Speciation and its Consequences. Sunderland, Mass.: Sinauer. 1989.
20. Schilthuizen M. EcotoneÐspeciation prone. Trends Ecol Evol 2000;15: p 158±179.
130±131. 47. Howard DJ. Reinforcement: origin, dynamics, and fate of an evolutionary
21. Futuyma DJ, Mayer GC. Non-allopatric speciation in animals. Syst Zool hypothesis. In Harrison RG. ed; Hybrid Zones and the Evolutionary
1980;29:254±271. Process. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1993. p 46±69.
22. Schliewen UK, Tautz D, PaÈaÈbo S. Sympatric speciation suggested by 48. Kelly JK, Noor MAF. Speciation by reinforcement: a model derived from
monophyly of crater lake cichlids. Nature 1994;368:629±632. studies of Drosophila. Genetics 1996;143:1485±1497.
23. Owen RB, Crossley R, Johnson TC, Tweddle D, Kornfield I, Davison S, 49. Liou LW, Price TD. Speciation by reinforcement of premating isolation.
Eccles DH, Engstrom DE. Major low levels of Lake Malawi and their Evolution 1994;48:1451±1459.
implications for speciation rates in cichlid fishes. Proc R Soc Lond Ser B 50. Coyne JA, Orr HA. Patterns of speciation in Drosophila. Evolution 1989;
1990;240:519±553. 43:362±381.
24. Taylor EB, Foote CJ, Wood CC. Molecular genetic evidence for parallel 51. Coyne JA, Orr HA. Patterns of speciation in Drosophila revisited.
life-history evolution within a Pacific salmon (sockeye salmon and koka- Evolution 1997;51:295±303.
nee, Oncorhynchus nerka). Evolution 1996;50:401±416. 52. Noor MA. Speciation driven by natural selection in Drosophila. Nature
25. Feder JL, Chilcote CA, Bush GL. Genetic differentiation between 1995;375:674±675.
sympatric host races of the apple maggot fly Rhagoletis pomonella. 53. Saetre G-P, Moum T, Bure S, Krl M, Adamjan M, Moreno J. A sexually
Nature 1988;336:61±64. selected character displacement in flycatchers reinforces premating
26. Smith DC. Heritable divergence of Rhagoletis pomonella host races by isolation. Nature 1997;387:589±592.
seasonal asynchrony. Nature 1988;336:66±67. 54. Werren JH. Wolbachia and speciation. In Howard DJ, Berlocher SH. ed;
27. Phillips PA, Barnes MM. Host race formation among sympatric apple, Endless FormsÐSpecies and Speciation. Oxford: Oxford University
walnut, and plum populations of the codling moth, Laspeyresia pomo- Press. 1999. p 245±260.
nella. Ann Ent Soc Am 1975;68:1053±1060. 55. Hurst GDD, Schilthuizen M. Selfish genetic elements and speciation.
28. Rice WR, Salt GW. Speciation via disruptive selection on habitat prefer- Heredity 1998;80:2±8.
ence: experimental evidence. Am Nat 1988;131:911±917. 56. Gittenberger E. Sympatric speciation in snails; a largely neglected
29. Rice WR, Salt GW. The evolution of reproductive isolation as a correlated model. Evolution 1988;42:826±828.
character under sympatric conditions: experimental evidence. Evolution 57. Orr HA. Is single-gene speciation possible? Evolution 1991;45:764-769.
1990;44:1140±1152. 58. Asami T, Cowie RH, Ohbayashi K. Evolution of mirror images by sexually
30. Culver D. Cave Life: Evolution and Ecology. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard asymmetric mating behavior in hermaphroditic snails. Am Nat 1998;152:
University Press. 1982. 225±236.
31. Schilthuizen M, Vermeulen JJ, Davison GWH, Gittenberger E. Population 59. Iwasa Y, Pomiankowski A. Continual change in mate preferences. Nature
structure in a snail species from isolated Malaysian limestone hills, 1995;377:420±422.
inferred from ribosomal DNA sequences. Malacologia 2000;41:271±284. 60. Rice WR. Intergenomic conflict, interlocus antagonistic coevolution, and
32. Stebbins GL. Variation and Evolution in Plants. New York: Columbia the evolution of reproductive isolation. In Howard DJ, Berlocher SH. ed;
University Press. 1950. Endless FormsÐSpecies and Speciation. Oxford: Oxford University
33. Mayr E. Evolutionary challenges to the mathematical interpretation of Press. 1999. p 261±270.
evolution. In Moorhead PS, Kaplan MM. ed; Mathematical Challenges 61. van Batenburg FHD, Gittenberger E. Ease of fixation of a change in
to the Neo-Darwinian Interpretation of Evolution. Philadelphia: Wistar coiling: computer experiments on chirality in snails. Heredity 1996;76:
Institute Press. 1967. p 47±58. 278±286.
120
Problems and paradigms
62. Breeuwer JAJ, Werren JH. Microorganisms associated with chromosome melanogaster and Drosophila virilis group species. J Mol Evol 1995;41:
destruction and reproductive isolation between two insect species. 1085±1095.
Nature 1990;346:558±560. 70. Wyckoff GJ, Wang W, Wu C-I. Rapid evolution of male reproductive
63. Novak SJ, Soltis DE, Soltis PS. Ownbey's Tragopogons: 40 years later. genes in the descent of man. Nature 2000;403:304±309.
Am J Bot 1990;78:1586±1600. 71. Mitra S, Landel H, Pruett-Jones S. Species richness covaries with mating
64. Soltis DE, Soltis PS. Polyploidy: recurrent formation and genome evolu- system in birds. Auk 1996;113:544±551.
tion. Trends Ecol Evol 1999;14:348±352. 72. Mùller AP, Cuervo JJ. Speciation and feather ornamentation in birds.
65. Ting C-T, Tsaur S-C, Wu M-L, Wu C-I. A rapidly evolving homeo- Evolution 1998;52:859±869.
box at the site of a hybrid sterility gene. Science 1998;282:1501± 73. Endler JA. Natural selection on color patterns in Poecilia reticulata.
1504. Evolution 1980;34:76±91.
66. Schilthuizen M. Cloning Odysseus and the seed of speciation. Trends 74. Seehausen O, van Alphen JJM, Lande R. Color polymorphism and sex
Ecol Evol 1999;14:90±91. ratio distortion in a cichlid fish as an incipient stage in sympatric
67. Ting C-T, Tsaur S-C, Wu C-I. The phylogeny of closely related species as speciation by sexual selection. Ecology Letters 1999;2:367±378.
revealed by the genealogy of a speciation gene, Odysseus. Proc Natl 75. Schluter D. Ecological causes of speciation. In Howard DJ, Berlocher
Acad Sci USA (in press). SH. ed; Endless Forms; Species and Speciation. Oxford: Oxford
68. Maiti S, Doskow J, Sutton K, Nhim RP, Lawlor DA, Levan K, Lidsey JS, University Press. 1999. p 114±129.
Wilkinson MF. The Pem homeobox gene: rapid evolution of the 76. Macnair MR, Gardner M. The evolution of edaphic endemics. In Howard
homeodomain, X-chromosomal localization, and expression in repro- DJ, Berlocher SH. ed; Endless Forms; Species and Speciation. pp. 157-
ductive tissue. Genomics 1996;34:304±316. 171. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1999.
69. Civetta A, Singh RS. High divergence of reproductive tract proteins and 77. Miyatake T, Shimizu T. Genetic correlations between life-history and beha-
their association with post-zygotic reproductive isolation in Drosophila vioral traits can cause reproductive isolation. Evolution 1999;53:201±208.
121
122
MÓDULO VII:
EVOLUCIÓN
Y
DESARROLLO
(EVODEVO)
123
124
TRABAJOS PRÁCTICOS
EVOLUCIÓN Y DESARROLLO (EVODEVO)
Por Nicolás Frankel
“Evolution occurs when ontogeny is altered in one of two ways: when new characters are
introduced at any stage of development with varying effects upon subsequent stages, or when
characters already present undergo changes in developmental timing”
S.J.Gould en “Ontogeny and Phylogeny” (1977)
BREVE INTRODUCCIÓN
El término “evolución” fue usado por los preformacionistas del siglo XVIII para
describir el proceso por el cual un embrión crece hasta convertirse en un organismo
adulto. Esta es la primera connotación biológica del término y difiere claramente de su
significado actual. Los preformacionistas creían que el embrión estaba ya ubicado dentro
de la célula germinal con todas sus partes ya formadas y simplemente crecía en tamaño
hasta alcanzar el estado adulto. El ejemplo extremo de este punto de vista es el del
homúnculo, el hombrecito con proporciones de adulto dibujado dentro del esperma.
Malpighi y Bonnet (ambos representantes del Preformacionismo) habían estudiado el
desarrollo del embrión de pollo y conocían el aumento de complejidad aparente al
microscopio (poco coherente con las ideas preformacionistas). A pesar de ello afirmaban
que lo que veían era ilusorio y estaba sesgado por los instrumentos usados y los sentidos.
En el siglo XIX, con el nacimiento de la Embriología comparada, comienzan a oírse
otras voces que hablan del desarrollo. Ètienne Geoffroy SaintHilaire sugiere que la
homología de una estructura puede ser inferida por las relaciones con otras estructuras
durante el desarrollo embrionario. A diferencia de Cuvier, que dividía los animales en
cinco clases sin relación entre sí, Geoffroy sostenía que todos los animales compartían
grandes similitudes en su anatomía.
En el mismo siglo, Haeckel expone su visión recapitulacionista. Considera que la
filogenia es la que determina la ontogenia, ya que los animales pasan durante su
desarrollo por las formas adultas de otras especies “inferiores”. El cigoto humano
representa al protista adulto, la blástula humana representa a los protistas coloniales, el
estadio humano de arcos branquiales al pez adulto, etc. Las nuevas especies evolucionan
adicionando un paso más en el desarrollo. Igualmente, Haeckel manifiesta que es
factible un acortamiento del desarrollo en algún tramo para evitar un infinito tiempo de
gestación. En 1828, Karl Ernst Von Baer enuncia algunos puntos importantes en sus
leyes del desarrollo:
1. Las características generales de un gran grupo de animales aparecen antes en
el embrión que las características particulares de un grupo menor.
2. Los animales no pasan durante su desarrollo a través de formas adultas de
otros organismos “inferiores” (contradice a los recapitulacionistas).
3. Los embriones de especies emparentadas comparten estadios tempranos de
desarrollo pero divergen en los estadios más tardíos.
125
4. Los caracteres más especializados se desarrollan a partir de estructuras
generales compartidas por distintas especies.
El trabajo de Von Baer influyó fuertemente en el pensamiento de Darwin, quien
consideró las similitudes en el desarrollo de distintas especies como evidencia de
ancestralidad común. Fritz Müller (un acérrimo defensor del Darwinismo) y Francis
Balfour resaltan en sus escritos la importancia de la Embriología Comparada como
herramienta para dilucidar las relaciones filogenéticos. Afirman también, que la
selección natural debe actuar tanto en los estadios larvales como en los adultos.
En el siglo XX, el advenimiento de la “Teoría Sintética de la Evolución” acerca la
Genética a la Evolución en detrimento de la Biología del Desarrollo. Esta última es uno
de los capítulos faltantes en la “Síntesis”. Las causas de esta importante ausencia
pueden haber sido muchas, pero la más importante parecería ser la falta de
entendimiento entre genetistas de poblaciones y embriólogos. En los ‘40s Richard
Goldschmidt, sostiene que la evolución puede ocurrir sólo por cambios heredables en los
genes que regulan el desarrollo. Para él los genes son más que loci y alelos, son unidades
de desarrollo. Las nuevas especies se originan como “monstruos esperanzados” (“hopeful
monsters”) que resultan de mutaciones sistémicas que afectan el desarrollo del animal.
Su visión, al ser contraria a la neodarwinista, no es tenida en cuenta en su época. En
1977, Stephen Jay Gould, publica el libro Ontogeny and Phylogeny y reaviva en el
ambiente científico el interés por la Biología del Desarrollo como herramienta para
estudiar la evolución.
En 1978, E.B. Lewis descubre los genes Hox (los encargados de dar identidad a
cada parte del animal a lo largo del eje anteroposterior) y unos años más tarde
comienza a conocerse en profundidad el desarrollo embriológico de Drosophila
melanogaster, Caenorhabditis elegans y del ratón. Paralelamente, la Biología Molecular
avanza a pasos agigantados y provee nuevas herramientas de análisis. Estos hechos
recientes marcan el comienzo de la EvoDevo moderna.
En la actualidad la interfase entre Evolución y Desarrollo atraviesa un
renacimiento. En él convergen disciplinas como la Biología del Desarrollo, la Ecología, la
Embriología, la Paleontología, la Genómica y el Análisis Filogenético. Esta combinación
de enfoques y metodologías tiene como objetivo desentrañar los mecanismos y patrones
del desarrollo que originan la diversidad de formas vivientes que existen en nuestro
planeta.
En este momento existen dos revistas científicas cuyos artículos tratan
exclusivamente temas de Evolución y Desarrollo; estas son: “Evolution and
Development” y “Development, Genes and Evolution”.
126
BIBLIOGRAFÍA CONSULTADA
Carroll S.B., Grenier J.K. and Weatherbee S.D. 2005. From DNA to diversity, Second
Edition. Blackwell Publishing.
Gilbert S.F. 2003. Developmental Biology, 7th Edition. Sinauer Associates.
Gilbert S.F. 2003. The morphogenesis of evolutionary developmental biology.
Int.J.Dev.Biol. 47(78):46777.
Gould S.J. 1977. Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Hall B.K. 2003. EvoDevo: evolutionary developmental mechanisms. Int.J.Dev.Biol.
47(78):4915.
Wilkins A.S.2002. The evolution of developmental pathways. Sinauer Associates.
127
TRABAJO PRÁCTICO 1 : SEMINARIO
Lea atentamente los siguientes trabajos y responda las preguntas:
1. Gerhing, W.J. & Ikeo, J. 1999. PAX 6: Mastering eye morphogenesis and eye
evolution. TIG 5(9):473479.
1.1. Comente las dos hipótesis sobre el origen y evolución del ojo. Utilice el
ejemplo de Arca, Cardium y Pecten para ilustrar estas dos hipótesis.
1.2. Nombre las evidencias que sustentan a Pax6 como un gen maestro en el
desarrollo de los distintos ojos de los animales.
1.3. Según los autores la universalidad de dos importantes componentes del ojo de
los metazoos como son Pax6 y la rodopsina sugiere fuertemente la existencia de
un protoojo y por lo tanto la monofilia de esta estructura. Nilsson (Current
Biology 15: R94R95 (2005)) critica esta idea porque no tiene en cuenta que los
ojos de insectos y vertebrados tienen distintos orígenes embriológicos y usan
distintos tipos de células fotorreceptoras para la visión (células rabdoméricas en
insectos y células ciliadas en vertebrados).
¿Qué opina ud.? Muchas veces las definiciones no permiten la existencia de grises.
¿Pueden ser los ojos de los metazoos parcialmente homólogos?
1.4. Analice la figura 4, ¿qué plantea la idea de “intercalary evolution”?
1.5. Gehring e Ikeo sugieren que el protoojo pudo haber surgido por azar. Si los
autores estuviesen equivocados y el ojo surge a partir una estructura que tiene la
capacidad de sensar la luz pero no es un ojo propiamente dicho (no tiene una
célula fotorreceptora y una célula pigmentada) ¿Cuál podría ser la función de esta
estructura ancestral?
1.6. En un trabajo reciente (Arendt et al. 2004 Science 306:869871) se descubre
que el anélido Platynereis (que supuestamente conserva características del
ancestro de los animales bilaterales) tiene células rabdoméricas y células ciliadas
asociadas a la fotopercepción. ¿Qué le sugiere este hallazgo? Recuerde los tipos de
fotorreceptores (pregunta 3) que usan vertebrados e insectos.
2. Wagner, G.P. 2007. The Developmental genetics of homology. Nat.Genet. 8:473479.
2.1. ¿Cuál es la base del concepto de homología empleado por el autor para genes y
caracteres morfológicos?
2.2. Analice las implicancias de la figura 2.
2.3. ¿Qué analogías propone el autor entre genes y caracteres morfológicos?
2.4. ¿Qué propone acerca de las redes genéticas regulatorias (GRN)? ¿Cómo se
relacionan con las redes de identidad de caracteres (ChIN)?
128
2.5. ¿Cuál, y de qué tipo, es la relación de homología entre: alas delanteras, alas
posteriores, élitros y halterios? ¿Qué ChIN estaría involucrado? ¿Cómo?
2.6. Explique la morfogénesis del ojo en vertebrados y en Drosophila. Compare
con la propuesta de Gehring e Ikeo. Indique las hipótesis propuestas para explicar
las diferencias.
3. Galis, F. 1999. Why do almost all mammals have seven cervical vertebrae?
Developmental constraints, Hox genes and cancer. J.Exp.Zool. 285:926.
3.1. ¿Cuál es la restricción (constraint) al cambio sobre la que versa el trabajo?
¿Existe variación intraespecífica del número de vértebras en las distintas regiones
de la columna de los mamíferos?
3.2. ¿Qué distingue una vértebra torácica de una cervical? ¿Qué es una costilla
cervical? ¿Cuáles son las patologías asociadas con las costillas cervicales?
3.3. ¿Cuál es la función conservada de los genes Hox en animales bilaterales?
¿Qué patologías tienen los ratones mutantes de algunos genes Hox o Polycomb?
3.4. La restricción al cambio en el número de vértebras cervicales: ¿está dada por
ausencia de variación para ese carácter o por selección en contra de variantes de
ese carácter? ¿Cómo se presenta en humanos la selección estabilizadora?
3.5. ¿Cuál es la conclusión del autor en cuanto a la relación entre el número
conservado de vértebras cervicales en mamíferos, el cáncer y los genes Hox? ¿Por
qué esta relación no se presentaría en reptiles y anfibios?
129
Eye morphogenesis and evolution Perspectives
Pax 6
mastering eye morphogenesis
and eye evolution
Pax 6 genes from various animal phyla are capable of inducing ectopic eye development, indicating that Pax 6
is a master control gene for eye morphogenesis. It is proposed that the various eye-types found in metazoa are
derived from a common prototype, monophyletically, by a mechanism called intercalary evolution.
xplaining the evolution of an organ as perfect as the eye scallop, Pecten), and compound eyes that consist of 10–80
E is a great challenge for all evolutionary biologists. In his
theory ‘The Origin of Species’ Charles Darwin devoted an
ommatidia each (in Noah’s arc, Arca noae)], are found in
the same phylogenetic class, the Bivalvia (Fig. 1). All of
entire chapter to the problem. Darwin freely admitted that these types of eye are located at the same anatomical pos-
the idea of an eye that is capable of adjusting the focus to ition – the edge of the mantle. The compound eyes of Arca
different distances, of admitting different amounts of light are similar to those of arthropods, but they have only a sin-
and of correcting spherical and chromatic aberration, could gle photoreceptor cell per ommatidium, whereas insects and
have been formed by natural selection seems intuitively crustaceans generally have eight or nine visual cells per unit.
absurd. However, he subsequently found a way out of this Salvini-Plawen and Mayr interpret the compound eyes of
dilemma by postulating a simple and imperfect eye, a proto- Arca as new formations, but an equally valid interpretation
type, from which the more perfect visual organs might have of these data is to assume that the camera-, mirror- and
arisen gradually, by variation (mutation) and by natural compound eyes of clams have evolved monophyletically
selection. Darwin assumed the prototype to consist of at from a common ancestral precursor. A monophyletic origin
least two cells: an ‘optic nerve’ (photoreceptor cell) and a for the eye is also supported by the observation that all
pigment cell shielding the photoreceptor cell from one side, metazoans share the same visual pigment, rhodopsin.
covered by translucent skin, but without any lens or other Darwin was highly self-critical in his discussion of the
refractive body. Such primitive eyes are found, for example, eye prototype and admits that the origin of the prototype
in some planarians (Fig. 1). Comparative anatomists have cannot be explained by natural selection, because selection
discovered numerous intermediates between this most primi- can only drive the evolution of an eye once it is partly
tive type of eye and the vertebrate eye, such as: eye cups; functional and capable of light detection. Therefore, selec-
pinhole eyes; camera-type eyes with a single lens; reflecting tion cannot explain the origin of the eye prototype, which
mirror eyes; and compound eyes with numerous ommatidia, for Darwin represents the same problem as the origin of
all of which lends support to Darwin’s theory. life. Therefore, both the origin of life and the origin of the
On the basis of comparative anatomical and ultrastruc- eye prototype must have been very rare events, and a poly-
tural studies of the various types of eye and photoreceptor phyletic origin in over 40 different phyla is not compatible
cells, it has been postulated by Salvini-Plawen and Mayr1, with Darwin’s theory. In this review, we discuss more
two strong proponents of darwinism, that photoreceptor recent evidence in favor of a monophyletic origin of the
organs have originated independently in at least 40, but eye and propose a new hypothesis explaining how
possibly up to 65 or more different phyletic lines. However, morphogenetic pathways might have evolved. Walter J. Gehring
there are some critical facts that are not consistent with this gehring@
conclusion, and we would like to challenge this idea and Pax 6 is a master control gene for eye ubaclu.unibas.ch
argue for a monophyletic rather than a polyphyletic origin morphogenesis and evolution *Kazuho Ikeo
of the metazoan eye. Salvini-Plawen and Mayr argue purely Homeotic mutations in Drosophila have resulted in the kikeo@genes.nig.ac.jp
on morphological grounds. Their section on ‘the multiple identification of several master control genes that specify
origin of eyes’ begins with the comment that ‘it requires lit- the body plan by controlling anterior–posterior polarity, Department of Cell
tle persuasion to become convinced that the lens eye of a segmental identity, organogenesis and identity of individ- Biology, Biozentrum,
vertebrate and the compound eye of an insect are indepen- University of Basel,
ual cells in great detail. The term ‘master control genes’
Klingelbergstrasse 70,
dent evolutionary developments’. This point has been was introduced by Lewis2 for the homeotic genes of the
4056 Basel, Switzerland.
taught to biology students for over a hundred years. Bithorax Complex, and, perhaps the most impressive *Center for Information
However, in a later section (p. 237) these authors describe demonstration of their role in development has been the Biology, National
the observation that, in clams, all three major eye-types [the genetic construction of four-winged and eight-legged flies3. Institute of Genetics,
camera eye with a single lens (in the heart shell, Cardium), Targeted expression of the homeotic Antennapedia gene Mishima,
the mirror eye with a lens and a reflecting mirror (in the results in complete middle legs being induced in the antennal Yata 411, Japan.
0168-9525/99/$ – see front matter © 1999 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. PII: S0168-9525(99)01776-X TIG September 1999, volume 15, No. 9 371
130
Perspective Eye morphogenesis and evolution
A hypothetical scheme of the evolution of various eye-types from a common ancestral prototype. As a first step, photosensitive cells with a light receptor (opsin)
have evolved. Under the control of the Pax 6 gene, the photosensitive cell assembles with a pigment cell to form an organ, the prototype eye. By divergent, parallel
and convergent evolution, the various eye-types are generated from the prototype: the compound eye of insects; the camera-type eye of vertebrates; and the large
spectrum of eye-types in molluscs ranging from the primitive camera-type eye in Cardium, the mirror-plus-lens eye of Pecten, the compound eye of Arca to the highly
evolved cephalopod eye, that greatly resembles the vertebrate camera-type eye.
discs of Drosophila3. Another striking example of a master course of evolution by recombining parts of pre-existing
control gene is Pax 6. This gene was first cloned in the genes in a process that Jacob called evolutionary tinkering7.
mouse4,5 and in humans6 and subsequently shown to be The different Pax genes contain various combinations of
affected in the mouse mutant, Small eye, and in human paired domains, with homeodomains, a sequence called
Aniridia patients. In humans and mice, eye defects are as- octapeptide, or parts of the homeodomain and paired
sociated with Pax 6 mutations in heterozygotes. The domain, respectively. The murine and human PAX 6 pro-
homozygous Pax 6 mutation is lethal to mouse embryos: teins are identical in amino acid sequence. A Pax 6 homolog
they lack eyes and a nose, and also have brain damage. Pax in Drosophila8 was subsequently discovered and this also
6 is expressed from the earliest stages of eye morphogenesis shows extensive sequence similarity, both in the paired
in the optic vesicle, giving rise to the retina and pigment domain (94% identity), and in the homeodomain (90%
retina, as well as in the overlying ectoderm that later forms identity). More surprising is the finding that the Drosophila
the lens and the cornea. However, Pax 6 is also expressed Pax 6 homolog is the eyeless (ey) gene known by a mutation
in the nasal epithelium, in specific regions of the brain and affecting the eyes since 1915 (Ref. 9). This was unexpected
the spinal cord, and not exclusively in eye primordia. because of the long-standing dogma, mentioned above, that
Pax 6 encodes a transcription factor that contains a the insect compound eye was non-homologous to the verte-
paired domain and a homeodomain. The Pax gene family brate camera eye, and that the two types of eye had evolved
clearly illustrates that novel genes are generated in the independently. The observation that Pax 6 homologs of
131
Eye morphogenesis and evolution Perspectives
both mammals and insects are essential for eye morpho- Genuine Pax 6 genes have now been isolated from:
genesis led to the idea that Pax 6 might be the universal mammals; amphibians; fish; amphioxus; sea squirts; sea
master control gene for eye morphogenesis and evolution8. urchins; squid; nematodes; ribbonworms; and planarians
We tested the master control gene hypothesis by con- (Fig. 2). In Cnidarians the situation is less clear, because the
structing a gain-of-function mutation. In wild-type larvae, genes found so far are either precursors of Pax 6 or have
ey is expressed exclusively in the eye-antennal disc from the diverged too far to be clearly identified as Pax 6 homologs.
earliest stages when the disc primordia are formed in the In any case, this survey shows that Pax 6 was present in the
embryo. Therefore, we used the Gal-4-system to target gene last common ancestor of all these triploblastic phyla, much
expression into imaginal discs other than eye discs10. By the like the rhodopsin gene. In addition to the mammalian Pax
use of different genomic enhancer lines, we were able to 6 gene, its homologs from the sea squirt Phallusia and the
induce ectopic eyes on the legs, wings, halteres and the squid Loligo are also capable of inducing ectopic eyes in
antennae of the fly, and recent electrophysiological exper- Drosophila. With the exception of sea urchins and
iments show that the ectopic eyes on the antenna can gener- Caenorhabditis elegans (which presumably have lost their
ate a normal electroretinogramme, which indicates that eyes during evolution because eyes are found in other echino-
they are functional (P. Callaerts and W. Gehring, unpub- derms and nematodes), all Pax 6 genes examined so far are
lished). This illustrates the role of ey as a master control expressed prominently in the developing eyes, including
gene that is capable of switching on a cascade of some 2500 those of planarians, which come close to the darwinian
genes required for eye morphogenesis10. Of course, eye prototype. Furthermore, Pax 6 is specifically expressed in
morphogenesis cannot be induced in any tissue of the fly the differentiated eyes of the ribbonworm Lineus14 and par-
at any stage of development, but at least it does occur in ticularly during eye regeneration15, strengthening the corre-
all imaginal discs up to a certain stage of differentiation. lation between eye morphogenesis and Pax 6 expression.
The master control gene first has to interact with subordi-
nate control genes to repress the resident genetic pro- The evolution of Pax 6: twin of eyeless
gramme and to install the eye programme. If the cells have More recently, a second Pax 6 gene homolog in
proceeded too far along their pathways and are firmly Drosophila called twin of eyeless (toy) was identified16. It
locked into a different pathway, the ectopic expression of ey shares 91% sequence identity in the paired domain and
has no effect. 90% in the homeodomain with the human and murine
Our next query was whether the mammalian Pax 6 PAX 6 proteins (Fig. 2), compared with 95% and 90% for
gene can functionally substitute for the Drosophila EY. Outside of these highly conserved domains, TOY is
homolog. The ectopic expression of mouse Pax 6 in more similar to the mammalian proteins than EY, particu-
Drosophila induces ectopic compound eyes10, suggesting larly in its overall length and at the C-terminus, where it
that Pax 6 has a universal function of gene regulation in shares a transcriptional activation domain with other PAX
eye morphogenesis. The reciprocal experiment has not 6 proteins that is absent in EY. A survey by polymerase
been completed yet, but it has been reported that Xenopus chain reaction (PCR) shows that two Pax 6 genes are only
Pax 6 is capable of inducing ectopic eye lenses11. However, found in holometabolous insects (Drosophila and
by changing the timing and site of Pax 6 RNA injection Bombyx) and not in hemimetabolous (grasshopper) or
into the Xenopus embryo, it is possible to induce complete apterygote insects (springtail), nor in all other phyla
ectopic eyes (R. Chow, C. Altmann, R. Lang and tested16. This indicates that the gene-duplication event
A. Hemmati-Brivanlou, pers. commun.). These findings leading to the two paralogs occurred during insect evolu-
clearly indicate that Pax 6 is a master control gene for eye tion, a conclusion that is also supported by the molecular
morphogenesis in both insects and vertebrates. phylogenetic analysis (Fig. 3). Besides the sequence simi-
The protein-coding regions of Pax 6 are highly con- larity, the localization of the intron splice sites clearly indi-
served in evolution, as are some of the regulatory cates that both paralogs are bona fide Pax 6 genes (Fig. 2).
sequences in the promoters and enhancers. Consequently, The first splice site at the N-terminus of the paired domain
the regulatory mechanisms that direct ocular expression is missing in toy, but present in ey, whereas the second
are also conserved between flies and mice. The eye-specific splice site in the homeodomain is present in toy and absent
enhancer region of the Drosophila ey gene8,12, when in ey, indicating that the ancestral gene had all four splice
inserted upstream of either of the two mouse Pax 6 pro- sites in the two boxes. The same four splice sites are also
moters (P1 or P0), directs eye- and CNS-specific expres- found in the nematode Caenorhabditis elegans and three
sion in transgenic mice that accurately reproduces features out of four can be traced back to platyhelminths
of endogenous Pax 6 expression13. In a reciprocal exper- (Dugesia). This indicates that these introns are very old
iment, the mouse P1 element is able to direct lacZ reporter (precambrian) and that a bona fide Pax 6 gene must have
gene expression into the eye imaginal discs of Drosophila. been present in the last common ancestor of triploblastic
Here, the expression is restricted to the photoreceptor animals. Vertebrates share a splice site at codon 44/45 that
cells, although lacZ expression is delayed and occurs only is vertebrate-specific and is used for differential splicing in
posterior to the morphogenetic furrow, whereas endogen- the paired box. It is absent in amphioxus and ascidians,
ous ey expression is confined to the undifferentiated cells indicating that this intron arose later in evolution, after
anterior to the morphogenetic furrow. However, the vertebrates had separated from invertebrates.
Drosophila ey enhancer itself shows the same spatio– Following gene duplication during insect evolution, the
temporal expression pattern as the mouse promotor, two paralogs ey and toy began to diverge in function. In
that could reflect perdurance of b-galactosidase or lack particular, toy is expressed much earlier, at the blastoderm
of regulatory sequences that confer repression posterior to stage, when the Drosophila body plan is laid down,
the morphogenetic furrow12. Overall, there is evidence whereas ey is expressed only later, during germband
for conservation of Pax 6 gene regulation, but there is extension. The spatial patterns at later stages are very
uncertainty about the extent of the conservation. similar although not identical. This earlier divergence with
132
Perspectives Eye morphogenesis and evolution
(a) b1 b2 a1 a2 a3
1 10 20 30 40 50 60 70
a4 a5 a6
(b) a1 a2 a3 / 4
1 10 20 30 40 50 60
Comparison of the amino acid sequences for PAX 6 proteins from various metazoa. The paired domains are indicated in (a) and the homeodomains in (b). PAX 6
protein-specific amino acids are shaded more darkly. The positions of the intron splice sites are indicated by arrowheads. These have not yet been determined for
Amphioxus, Paracentrotus and Loligo. The numbers indicate the percentage amino acid sequence identity as compared with the mouse and human proteins. For
comparison the closely related Pax sequences from the mouse (m) are shown. Pax 2, 5 and 8 have only partial homeodomains. a, a-helices; b, b-sheets.
respect to temporal rather than spatial patterns of gene mental pathway18 by directly regulating the eye-specific
expression has been found in other duplicated develop- enhancer of the ey gene12,16. This observation reveals
mental control genes, like sloppy-paired 1 and 2 (Ref. 17), an interesting facet of the evolution of morphogenetic
and might be a more general feature of evolution. Like ey, pathways: the single Pax 6 in vertebrates is autoregulated
toy is also capable of inducing ectopic eyes in Drosophila, by a positive feedback loop in which the PAX 6 protein
but toy requires a functional ey gene to induce eyes, binds to the enhancer in its own gene and activates its
suggesting that toy is upstream of ey in the genetic cascade transcription19. In Drosophila, after gene duplication
controlling eye morphogenesis. Epistasis experiments, as this positive autocatalytic feedback loop appears to
well as biochemical and transgenic analyses, support the have evolved into a heterocatalytic loop in which
notion that toy acts upstream of ey in the eye develop- one of the paralogs regulates the other, leading to the
133
Eye morphogenesis and evolution Perspectives
integration of ey into the eye developmental pathway genes interact. It has been proposed that the two protein
underneath toy. products can form a heterodimer, which is compatible
with the findings mentioned above30.
The genetic cascade specifying the eye One of our aims is to compare the genetic cascade from
developmental pathway Drosophila with that of the mouse or other vertebrates to
Following the discovery of ey as a master control gene, find out how many other genes besides Pax 6 and the
several groups have embarked upon the analysis of the rhodopsin gene have been conserved during evolution.
genetic cascade leading to eye morphogenesis by identifying Several homologs for so and eya have been identified in ver-
target genes and genetic interactions. However, the direct tebrates, and a second so-like gene has also been isolated
nature of a given genetic interaction and the molecular basis from Drosophila31. However, sequence conservation of the
of the interaction has been demonstrated in only a few protein-coding region does not necessarily imply that the
cases. In Drosophila, evidence for a direct activation of ey function in eye morphogenesis is also conserved in evolution.
transcription by binding of TOY protein to the eye-specific For example, the mouse Rx gene that belongs to the paired-
enhancer of the ey gene has been described above. This puts like class of homeobox genes was shown to be expressed
the toy gene on top of the hierarchy and ey underneath16. both in the developing retina and forebrain. Loss-of-function
The toy gene requires ey to induce eye formation; in turn, ey mutants in mice do not form optic cups and, as a conse-
induces and requires sine oculis (so) and eyes absent (eya) quence, lack eyes32. Furthermore, misexpression of Rx
for the induction of ectopic eyes18. There is strong evidence induces ectopic retinal tissue in frogs32. However, a
that so is a direct target for EY protein20. However, as more Drosophila homolog of Rx that has 100% sequence identity
and more pieces are filled into the puzzle, the simple linear in the homeodomain is expressed only in the developing
pathways turn into a complex network and several other brain, but not in the embryonic or the larval eye primordia33.
genes have been found to be capable of ectopic eye induc- Eventually, it will be interesting to find how many new genes
tion. The so gene encodes a homeodomain protein that is must be recruited into the eye-developmental pathway to
required for the development of the entire visual system in generate either a mouse or a Drosophila eye, and how many
Drosophila21,22. The eya gene encodes a novel type of of these genes are common. However, the major changes
nuclear protein involved in the development of the visual occurring during evolution are likely to occur at the level of
system as well as in the somatic gonadal precursors23,24. gene regulation, and very different types of eye might be
A gene called dachshund (dac) encodes a novel nuclear generated by the same set of regulatory genes.
protein that is required for differentiation of the ommatidia,
but is also essential for leg development25,26. The ectopic The evolution of the different types of eye
expression of eya or dac alone or in combinations of eya The evolution of light-sensitive cells is intimately con-
with so or dac induces ectopic eye formation, but also nected to the evolution of the visual pigment rhodopsin.
activates ey expression. The ey, eya and dac genes are all Rhodopsin is the molecule of ultimate sensitivity because
activated during eye induction18 and there is evidence that it is capable of sensing a single light quantum. Absorption
the EYA protein forms a complex with SO (Ref. 27) and of a single quantum of light converts all-trans retinal, that
DAC (Ref. 28) proteins. Taken together, these findings can is covalently bound to the opsin protein molecule, into
be explained by a model in which ey induces the initial 11-cis retinal. This conversion causes a conformational
expression of so and eya that regulates the activity of all change of the protein that is amplified by transducin, a
four genes by positive feedback loops required for eye G-protein and results in an electrical nerve impulse34.
induction16.
Targeted expression of the gene teashirt (tsh), which
was shown to be required for the specification of the trunk
segments in the Drosophila embryo, can also induce FIGURE 3. Phylogenetic tree of the Pax 6 genes
ectopic eyes29. This gene encodes a transcription factor Dugesia
with zinc-finger motifs and induces the expression of ey,
Caenorhabditis elegans
so and dac. In turn, ey induces the expression of tsh, indi-
cating that tsh is also a member of the regulatory network Phallusia
toy
of genes that are connected to each other by positive feed- Drosophila melanogaster
back loops. However, it should be emphasized that ey is a eyeless
much more potent inducer of ectopic eyes than any single squid
gene in the later group, suggesting that no single gene can ribbon worm
recapitulate the entire spectrum of ey activity, reinforcing sea urchin
the master control gene status of Pax 6. amphioxus
A second Pax gene, eyegone (eyg) apparently acts in medaka fish
parallel with ey in determining Drosophila eye develop- zebrafish
ment30. This gene contains only a partial paired domain, Xenopus laevis
but a complete homeodomain. Loss-of-function mutations 0.05
quail
lead to a reduction of the eyes similar to ey, and ectopic
mouse
expression leads to the induction of ectopic eyes. The two
genes eyg and ey seem to have complementary functions human trends in genetics
134
Perspectives Eye morphogenesis and evolution
Rhodopsins are present in some bacteria, and some of brates and invertebrates analyzed so far, typical rhodopsins
these proteins also serve a sensory function. However, belonging to one and the same gene family have been found.
there is very little sequence conservation between bacterio- The visual system of unicellular organisms is an organelle,
rhodopsins and rhodopsins of higher organisms, even rather than an organ, and it is formed by intracellular
though both are structurally similar membrane proteins assembly processes, whereas the eyes of metazoa are organs
with seven transmembrane domains. made up of cells of at least two different types or of different
Protists have also developed visual systems that are based tissues, as already pointed out by Darwin. There is accu-
on rhodopsin. The unicellular green alga Chlamydomonas mulating evidence that Pax 6 is the universal master control
has developed a visual system that allows it to measure light gene for eye morphogenesis in metazoa ranging from platy-
intensity, as well as to determine the direction of the incident helminths to humans. The universality of rhodopsin and Pax
light. These abilities confer a strong selective advantage for an 6 suggests that the different types of eye found in metazoa
organism that depends on photosynthesis35. The direction of are derived from a single prototypic eye and are, therefore,
the incident light is determined with the help of the eyespot, a of monophyletic origin. Pax 6 serves as a regulatory gene to
carotenoid-containing vesicle that presumably operates as an assemble the different cell-types, such as photoreceptor cells
interference reflector. The action spectra for phototaxis and and pigment cells, into a light-sensing organ. This new con-
flash-induced phobic responses have a maximum close to cept of eye evolution is illustrated in Fig. 1. Originating from
550 nm like rhodopsin, and in blind retinal-deficient cells, a precambrian prototype, the various types of eye are
positive phototaxis can be restored by supplying the cells with thought to have evolved by divergent, parallel and conver-
all-trans retinal. Chlamydorhodopsin has recently been gent evolution by recruiting numerous additional genes
cloned36, and it shows some sequence homology to inverte- into the eye-developmental pathways, as discussed in the
brate rhodopsins. However, it is not a typical seven-trans- following section.
membrane receptor, and looks instead rather like an ion In higher metazoa, the eyes are connected to the brain,
channel. Therefore, this primitive plant rhodopsin probably where visual information is processed and transmitted to the
diverged from animal opsin early in evolution. In all verte- effector organs, such as muscles. In the more primitive
(ancestral) cnidarians, such as cubomedusae (which do not
have a brain, but only a nerve ring around the umbrella), the
FIGURE 4. Retrograde and intercalary evolution eyes are directly connected to the muscles in the tentacles.
This suggests that the eye evolved as an information-gather-
(a)
ing organ before the brain, the information-processing
Histidine biosynthesis organ.
135
Eye morphogenesis and evolution Perspectives
known. First, gene duplication and divergence, as de- has been termed gene sharing or recruitment. Third, the
scribed for ey and toy. The original autocatalytic feedback recombination of various coding and regulatory regions of
loop is converted to a heterocatalytic loop, where toy different genes by‘evolutionary tinkering’ might also lead
regulates ey, the latter becoming intercalated into the eye to recruitment and intercalation into a new morphogenetic
morphogenetic path-way downstream of toy16. Second, pathway.
recruitment of novel genes into the morphogenetic path- These considerations clearly have a bearing on our
way by fusion of the coding region of a gene to an eye- concepts of homology. Homology is not an all-or-
specific enhancer or promoter. Piatigorsky39 has described nothing phenomenon, because two different types of
several examples of this kind. Genes encoding enzymes like eye might only be partially homologous and they can also
enolase or lactate dehydrogenase, or small heat shock pro- have acquired analogous features as proposed by
teins are recruited into the eye morphogenetic pathway as Zuckerkandl40. This will resolve discrepancies in the inter-
lens proteins called crystallins. This evolutionary process pretation41 of these new findings in eye evolution.
References 16 Czerny, T. et al. (1999) Twin of eyeless, a second Pax 6 gene of a complex and function synergistically to induce ectopic eye
1 Salvini-Plawen, L. and Mayr, E. (1961) in Evolutionary Biology, Drosophila, acts upstream of eyeless in the control of eye development in Drosophila. Cell 91, 893–903
(Vol. 10) (Hecht, M.K., Steere, W.C. and Wallace, B., eds), development. Molecular Cell 3, 297–307 29 Pan, D. and Rubin, G.M. (1998) Targeted expression of teashirt
pp. 207–263, Plenum Press 17 Cadigan, K.M. et al. (1994) Functional redundancy: the respective induces ectopic eyes in Drosophila. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A.
2 Lewis, E.B. (1992) Clusters of master control genes regulate the roles of the two sloppy paired genes in Drosophila segmentation. 95, 15508–15512
development of higher organisms. J. Am. Med. Assoc. 267, Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 91, 6324–6328 30 Jang, C-C. et al. Two Pax genes, eye gone and eyeless, act in parallel
1524–1531 18 Halder, G. et al. (1998) Eyeless initiates the expression of both in determining Drosophila eye development. Development (in press)
3 Schneuwly, S. et al. (1987) Redesigning the body plan of sine oculis and eyes absent during Drosophila compound eye 31 Toy, J. et al. (1998) The Optx2 homeobox gene is expressed in
Drosophila by ectopic expression of the homeotic gene development. Development 125, 2181–2191 early precursors of the eye and activates retina specific genes.
Antennapedia. Nature 325, 816–818 19 Plaza, S. et al. (1993) Quail Pax 6 (Pax-QNR) encodes a Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 95, 10643–10648
4 Walther, C. and Gruss, P. (1991) Pax 6, a murine paired box gene, transcription factor able to bind and trans-activate its own 32 Mathers, P.H. et al. (1997) The Rx homeobox gene is essential for
is expressed in the developing CNS. Development 113, 1435–1449 promoter. Cell Growth Differ. 4, 1041–1050 vertebrate eye development. Nature 387, 603–607
5 Hill, R.E. et al. (1991) Mouse Small eye results from mutations in 20 Niimi, T. et al. Direct regulatory interaction of the eyeless protein 33 Eggert, T. et al. (1998) Isolation of a Drosophila homolog of the
a paired-like homeobox-containing gene. Nature 354, 522–525 with an eye-specific enhancer in the sine oculis gene during eye vertebrate homeobox gene Rx and its possible role in brain and
6 Ton, C.C.T. et al. (1991) Positional cloning and characterization induction in Drosophila. Dev. Biol. (in press) eye development. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 95, 2343–2348
of a paired box- and homeobox-containing gene from the Aniridia 21 Cheyette, B.N.R. et al. (1994) The Drosophila sine oculis locus 34 Khorana, H.G. (1992) Rhodopsin, photoreceptor of the rod cell.
region. Cell 67, 1059–1074 encodes a homeodomain-containing protein required for the J. Biol. Chem. 267, 1–4
7 Jacob, F. (1997) Evolution and tinkering. Science 196, 1161–1166 development of the entire visual system. Neuron 12, 977–996 35 Foster, K.W. et al. (1984) A rhodopsin is the functional
8 Quiring, R. et al. (1994) Homology of the eyeless gene of 22 Serikaku, M.A. and O’Tousa, J.E. (1994) sine oculis is a homeobox photoreceptor for phototaxis in the unicellular eukaryote
Drosophila to the Small eye gene in mice and Aniridia in humans. gene required for Drosophila visual system development. Chlamydomonas. Nature 311, 756–759
Science 265, 785–789 Genetics 138, 1137–1150 36 Deininger, W. et al. (1995) Chlamyrhodopsin represents a new
9 Hoge, M.A. (1915) Another gene in the fourth chromosome of 23 Bonini, N.M. et al. (1993) The eyes absent gene: genetic control of type of sensory photoreceptor. EMBO J. 14, 5849–5858
Drosophila. Am. Nat. 49, 47–49 cell survival and differentiation in the developing Drosophila eye. 37 Horowitz, N.H. (1945) On the evolution of biochemical syntheses.
10 Halder, G. et al. (1995) Induction of ectopic eyes by targeted Cell 72, 379–395 Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 31, 153–157
expression of the eyeless gene in Drosophila. Science 267, 24 Bonini, N.M. et al. (1997) The Drosophila eyes absent gene directs 38 Wilkins, A.S. (1995) Moving up the hierarchy: a hypothesis on the
1788–1792 ectopic eye formation in a pathway conserved between flies and evolution of a genetic sex determination mechanism. BioEssays
11 Altmann, C.R. et al. (1997) Lens induction by Pax 6 in Xenopus vertebrates. Development 124, 4819–4826 17, 71–11
laevis. Dev. Biol. 185, 119–123 25 Mardon, G. et al. (1994) dachshund encodes a nuclear protein 39 Piatigorsky, J. and Wistow, G.J. (1989) Enzyme/crystallins: gene
12 Hauck, B. et al. Functional analysis of an eye specific enhancer of the required for normal eye and leg development in Drosophila. sharing as an evolutionary strategy. Cell 57, 197–199
eyeless gene in Drosophila. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. (in press) Development 120, 3473–3486 40 Zuckerkandl, E. (1994) Molecular pathways to parallel evolution:
13 Xu, P-X. et al. (1999) Regulation of Pax 6 expression is conserved 26 Shen, W. and Mardon, G. (1997) Ectopic eye development in I. Gene nexuses and their morphological correlates. J. Mol. Evol.
between mice and flies. Development 126, 383–395 Drosophila induced by directed dachshund expression. 39, 661–678
14 Loosli, F. et al. (1996) Isolation of a Pax 6 homolog from the Development 124, 45–52 41 Abouheif, E. et al. (1997) Homology and developmental genes.
ribbon worm Lineus sanguineus. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 93, 27 Pignoni, F. et al. (1997) The eye-specification proteins So and Eya Trends Genet. 13, 432–433
2658–2663 form a complex and regulate multiple steps in Drosophila eye 42 Jacobs, D.K. et al. (1998) in Molecular Approaches to Ecology and
15 Tarpin, M. et al. Reverse homeosis in homeotically reconstructed development. Cell 91, 881–891 Evolution (De Salle, R. and Schierwater, B., eds), pp. 323–357,
ribbonworms. Nature (in press) 28 Chen, R. et al. (1997) Dachshund and Eyes Absent proteins form Birkhäuser
The Internet section is a regular column of news and information about web
resources for researchers in genetics and development (pp. 378–379).
Internet is compiled and edited with the help of: Steve Brenner (Department
of Structural Biology, Stanford University, Fairchild D-109, Stanford, CA
94305-5400, USA; brenner@hyper.stanford.edu); Fran Lewitter (Scientific
Computing, Whitehead Institute for Biomedical Research, Nine Cambridge
Center, Cambridge, MA 02142-1479, USA; lewitter@wi.mit.edu); and Laurie
Iten (Department of Biological Sciences, Purdue University, 1392 Lily W. Lafayette, IN 47907-1392,
USA; laurie_iten@sdb.bio.purdue.edu).
136
PERSPECTIVES
can guide us in a similar understanding of
OPINION
homology among morphological structures.
Two genes are homologous as long as they
The developmental genetics are derived from the same gene in a com-
mon ancestor, regardless of whether they
of homology have the same function and regardless of
the extent of similarity in their nucleotide
sequences. The gene retains its identity
Günter P. Wagner despite evolutionary change in its function
and sequence, as long as all changes result
Abstract | Homology is an essential idea of biology, referring to the historical from mutations at the same genomic locus.
continuity of characters, but it is also conceptually highly elusive. The main The basis of gene identity is the historical
difficulty is the apparently loose relationship between morphological continuity of the locus undergoing evolu-
characters and their genetic basis. Here I propose that it is the historical tionary change. Of course, things become
continuity of gene regulatory networks rather than the expression of individual more complicated with gene duplications
and loss or fusion of parts of genes (for
homologous genes that underlies the homology of morphological characters.
example, exon shuffling) to form new genes,
These networks, here referred to as ‘character identity networks’, enable the and when extensive sequence divergence
execution of a character-specific developmental programme. erases the evidence of shared ancestry. The
mode of evolution that preserves the histori-
Characters found in different species are can be variable. These networks control the cal identity of a gene is the replacement of
homologous if they are derived from the execution of character-specific developmental alleles at the same genomic locus.
same character in their most recent common programmes, which allow for quasi-
ancestor (MRCA), regardless of similarity independent variation of characters5 with Homology of morphological characters:
in form or function (FIG. 1). Whenever we respect to other parts of the body. what does ‘sameness’ mean? The homol-
compare two or more species, or use a model ogy of morphological characters is also a
organism to learn about the molecular What does homology mean? case of historical continuity in the face of
basis of human disease, we implicitly need In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, it descent with modification. In a population,
to identify corresponding body parts and became clear that the similarities and differ- a character exists in different states of size,
functional systems; that is, we make assess- ences among organisms are not random, but shape or colour. Evolutionary change usu-
ments about homology. Intuitively, one follow patterns that call for an explanation. ally proceeds by changing the frequency
would expect that the historical continuity of Most intriguing are the similarities among of these character states in the population,
morphological characters is underpinned by some body parts that cannot be explained by eventually leading to the replacement of
the continuity of the genes that govern the shared functional necessity. For example, the the ancestral character state by a derived
development of these characters. However, tetrapod limb shows a highly stereotypical character state (FIG. 1). Sameness, then, by
things are not that simple: one of the most pattern of bony elements (FIG. 2), regardless the definition of homology, does not refer to
important results of the past 15 years of of whether it is used for running, flying, similarity of structure or function as such,
molecular developmental genetics is the swimming or grasping. This pattern was but to historical continuity through inherit-
realization that homologous characters can conceptualized by Richard Owen as homol- ance with modification. In other words,
have different genetic and developmental ogy 6, paving the way for the theory of the homology concept can be applied to
bases1–3. This seems paradoxical, because evolutionary change. Even today, the exist- anything that forms a lineage10–13. Of
the historical continuity of morphological ence of homologous body parts in different course, things become more complicated
characters implies continuity of the (genetic) animals and plants is cited as standard when new characters arise (novelties) or
information about the characters4. But where evidence for this process7. characters duplicate like genes (for example,
else should we look for this continuity, other teeth or fins).
than in the genes? Here I review some of The easy case: homology of genes. Since At the formal phenomenological level,
the conceptual issues, and the experimen- the time of Owen and Darwin, the idea of a morphological character corresponds to a
tal results that suggest a solution to this homology has been extended to other bio- genomic locus, and a character state to an
conundrum. I argue that the continuity of logical entities, such as genes, nucleotides, allele14 (BOX 1). Hence, in a more technical
morphological characters could be under- physiological processes and behavioural sense, a character is a unit of evolutionary
written by homologous regulatory networks patterns7,8. What it means to speak of change at the phenotypic or morphological
of co-adapted transcription factor genes, homologous genes is well understood9, and level in the same way that a gene is the unit
whereas other aspects of their development I recapitulate these ideas here because they of evolutionary change at the genetic level15.
137
NATURE REVIEWS | GENETICS VOLUME 8 | JUNE 2007 | 473
© 2007 Nature Publishing Group
PERSPECTIVES
Developmental genetics and homology? other animals that is not segmented and, segment formation2. Surprisingly, the most
The semi-conservative mode by which furthermore, the insects are nested in an extensive interspecific variation has been
DNA replicates ensures that genes directly even larger clade, the arthropods, which found in the higher levels of the segment-
give rise to copies of themselves, and consists exclusively of segmented animals. ation hierarchy, namely the gap genes and
is therefore the mechanistic basis for Yet some genes that are essential for the pair-rule genes2,23. Examples are the
their historical continuity. In the case of segmentation in Drosophila melanogaster20, pair-rule genes ftz and eve, mentioned above,
morphological characters, however, the for example, the pair-rule genes fushi and the gap gene bicoid (bcd), which exists
situation is more complicated, because tarazu (ftz) and even skipped (eve), do not only in the higher Diptera, not even in the
morphological characters and even cell have pair-rule function in the grasshopper dipteran mosquito Anopheles. By contrast,
types do not usually directly spawn copies Schistocerca americana, but are instead the segment-polarity gene network, which
of themselves between generations, but expressed in the developing CNS21,22. includes the interaction of engrailed (en)
are recreated in each generation from a Clearly, the way in which segments are and wingless (wg), seems to be invariant, at
single cell, the zygote16. The recreation of formed in development has changed since least among insects2. This suggests that the
a character is controlled by developmental the MRCA of crown-group insects. genetic regulatory network (GRN) that con-
genes, so it is tempting to speculate that A solution to this conundrum can be trols the execution of the segment-specific
the continuity of morphological characters found in the fact that developmental morphogenetic processes is less variable
can be explained by the continuity of variation in homologous characters is not than the upstream processes that activate it.
genetic information. Since the beginning randomly distributed, but affects some If the pattern that is suggested by the data
of experimental developmental biology in aspects of development more than others. on insect segmentation can be generalized, it
the early twentieth century, the emerging For example, in D. melanogaster, segmenta- seems that the most conservative parts
picture has been disappointing and tion proceeds through three stages that are of the developmental process are the
confusing2,17–19. For instance, there is no controlled by particular genes: gap genes, GRNs that control the developmental
question that body segments in all orders which determine larger body regions, the programme that specifies the identity of
of insects are homologous and derived pair-rule genes, which divide the embryo the character; that is, the character identity
from a single common ancestor — there into stripes of alternating half segments, network (ChIN). For example, individual
is not a single lineage of organisms more and the segment-polarity genes, which cell types are determined by a characteristic
closely related to an insect group than to activate the actual morphogenetic process of set of regulatory genes over vast evolutionary
distances24–27. Another example is the genetic
network for the endomesoderm that starfish
and sea urchins share28. By contrast, other
aspects of development, from early pattern-
ing to the execution of the developmental
a programme, are more variable2.
Here I review evidence that shows
that these networks determine character
identity rather than character state, that
non-homologous morphological characters
are determined by non-homologous ChINs,
and that the genes participating in a ChIN
are co-adapted for their task; that is, they are
functionally non-equivalent to orthologues in
species that do not have the character, and
to paralogues that do not participate in the
development of that character.
c
b
ChIN genes determine character identity
The idea that the genes that control character
identity are distinct from the genes that
determine the special shape and state of
a character has been well documented in
the case of Ultrabithorax (Ubx) function
in insect wing development. Ancestrally,
pterygote (or winged) insects have two
pairs of proper wings associated with T2
and T3 (the second and third segments in
Figure 1 | Homology of morphological characters. The hand of a human (part a) differs greatly in
terms of detailed structure and function from the wing of a bird (part b), but both are considered
the thorax), as seen, for instance, in honey
homologous because they arose from a corresponding character in the tetrapod common bees, grasshoppers and most spectacularly
ancestor(part c) through descent with modification. This figure illustrates that morphological in butterflies (FIG. 3a). Dipterans have only
characters form lineages of descent in the same way that genes form unique lineages of descent, one pair of wings, which is localized on T2;
as long as they are not duplicated. Homology is the historical continuity of characters in multiple that is, they are forewings. A homologue of
lineages despite variations in their character state. the hind wing lies on T3 but does not take
138
474 | JUNE 2007 | VOLUME 8 www.nature.com/reviews/genetics
© 2007 Nature Publishing Group
PERSPECTIVES
Figure 2 | Homologous characters can have different shapes and func- explain the similarity of the basic construction of homologous characters.
tions. Forelimbs of seven tetrapod species exemplify the fact that This remains one of the standard arguments in favour of evolution; that
corresponding body parts have a similar design but can serve different is, that species derive from common ancestors by a process of descent
functions, from swimming to flying. Hence, functional necessity cannot with modification.
the shape of a wing blade. Instead, it is a Experimental evidence shows that this ChINs of non-homologous characters
small, club-like appendage called the haltere distinction between character identities The GRN underlying eye development
(FIG. 3b). Beetles also have only one pair of and character states is the result of different is a celebrated example of evolutionary
wing blades, but as they are associated with genetic underpinnings. ChIN genes, like conservation, as it suggests that there is
T3 they are hind wings. The forewings in Ubx and abdominal-A (abdA), determine homology between vertebrate and insect
beetles have been transformed into a pair of character identity (forewing versus hind eyes34. This assertion largely comes from the
highly scleratized structures, called elytra, wing) across species, regardless of their common role of paired-box gene 6 (Pax6) in
that function as protective covers (FIG. 3c). So, character state30. In D. melanogaster, a the two systems, but detailed studies show
butterflies, flies and beetles all have two pairs loss-of-function mutation of Ubx leads to that the rest of the network is strikingly
of dorsal appendages that are homologous, the development of a second set of wing different (see below). The most parsimoni-
because they are nested within a larger blades (FIG. 4a). This does not mean that Ubx ous interpretation is that Pax6 is part of
clade of winged insects, almost all of which function is to suppress wing development; the ancestral cell-differentiation pathway
have two pairs of wings on their T2 and T3: Warren and collaborators demonstrated for photoreceptors and was then separately
the forewings, which are flying organs in that the four-winged butterfly also expresses incorporated into the ChINs for both types
flies and butterflies but protective organs Ubx in its T3 (REF. 31). So, in general Ubx of image-forming eyes28.
in beetles, and the hind wings, which form determines hind wing identity, regardless of
functional wing blades in butterflies and whether the hind wing is shaped as a wing
beetles but are sensory organs (halteres) in blade or a haltere, as in dipterans32. This
dipteran insects. was confirmed in the flour beetle Tribolium Glossary
Hence, morphologically, we can distin- castaneum33. As in the butterfly, the beetle Orthologue
guish between two kinds of entities. On the expresses Ubx in T3, and suppression of Two genes are orthologues if their lineages are connected
through a speciation event and without a duplication event.
one hand, there are two character identities: Ubx function by RNAi leads to a second
forewings and hind wings. On the other set of elytra on T3 (FIG 4b). Clearly, Ubx Paralogue
hand, there are various character states does not determine the shape of a wing but Two genes are paralogues if their lineages are connected
that insect wings can assume: the forewing determines hind-wing identity “…regardless through a gene duplication event.
can be a wing blade or an elytra, and the of form and function” 6,30. The character
Pro-orthologue
hind wing can be a wing blade or a haltere. state can change in evolution, but it remains For example, when one species has two copies of a gene,
Distinguishing between character identi- under the control of Ubx. say Ga and Gb, and another species has a single copy G,
ties and character states also removes the The experimental evidence that is cited and the speciation event that separated the species
confusion that is inherent in the character here pertains to only one gene, Ubx, but lineages occurred earlier than the gene duplication event,
G is the pro-orthologue of Ga and Gb.
concept29 between parts, such as wings and it is unlikely that Ubx is acting alone. One
legs (character identities), and attributes would expect that Ubx is part of a small Semi-orthologue
of parts, such as size, shape and colour network that also includes abdA and other For example, if G is the pro-orthologue of Ga and Gb, then
(character states). transcription factor genes. both Ga and Gb are the semi-orthologues of G.
139
NATURE REVIEWS | GENETICS VOLUME 8 | JUNE 2007 | 475
© 2007 Nature Publishing Group
PERSPECTIVES
Box 1 | Equivalent terms for genes and morphological characters do not regulate Dach1, the homologue of
D. melanogaster dac.
Morphological characters are equivalent to a genetic locus that undergoes evolutionary There are two possible reasons for the
modification. Different instantiations of a gene are called alleles and different instantiations of a dissimilarity between the GRNs of eye develop-
character are called character states. Genes that were inherited from a common ancestor without
ment in D. melanogaster and vertebrates. It
duplication are orthologues, whereas body parts in two species that were inherited from a common
ancestor are homologues. Different instances of a gene caused by gene duplication are called
could be that the MRCA of flies and mam-
paralogues, and repeated instances of a morphological character in the same organisms are mals had a GRN that involved members from
called serial homologues. New genes can arise through gene duplication and divergence or from the all four gene families, but this network later
fusion of parts of genes. For morphological characters, a new character that creates a new lineage of changed. Alternatively, it could be that, just
descent with modifications is called an evolutionary novelty67. These can arise in various ways, for as the image-forming eye structures are inde-
instance, by duplication and differentiation, much like for new genes, or by de novo origination. pendently derived, the regulatory interactions
Genetic terms and their equivalents for morphological characters: among these genes in eye development also
evolved independently, and the GRN was not
Genetic term Morphological equivalent present in the MRCA of flies and mammals.
Locus Character The gene lineages of the Six gene family
Allele Character state suggest that the latter is the case. Although
Six and Pax genes tend to be expressed
Orthology Special homology
together in various organs and cell types41,42,
Paralogy Serial homology the different Six genes that are involved in
Origin of new genes Evolutionary novelty D. melanogaster and vertebrate eye develop-
ment are not orthologues. According to
a phylogenetic analysis of Six genes from
animals and unicellular flagellates, so of
In D. melanogaster, the gene eyeless All the genes in the D. melanogaster eye D. melanogaster and optix from vertebrates
(ey; with homology to the Pax gene ChIN are members of larger gene families are ancient paralogues predating the origin
family in vertebrates) is necessary for eye (TABLE 1). In vertebrates, genes from these of multicellular animals44,45. Hence, it is most
development and is sufficient to induce four gene families (Pax, Six, Eya and Dach) parsimonious to assume that so and the
eyes35. In fact, ey is part of a small are also involved in the development of optix genes were independently recruited
network that includes another transcrip- several other organs and tissues, such as into eye development in the vertebrate and
tion factor, sine oculis (so; with homology muscle and ear41,42. insect lineages just as their morphological
to the Six gene family in vertebrates) and However, the GRN of eye morphogen- eye structures are independently derived.
two transcriptional cofactors, eyes absent esis in vertebrates is not the same as that in This shows that ChINs differentiate as they
(eya) and dachshund (dac), and is activated D. melanogaster37,41,43 (FIG. 5). For instance, assume control of the development of a new
by a paralogue of ey called twin of eyeless Pax6/ey is upregulated by non-homologous character, so that different characters are
(toy) (FIG. 5a). Surprisingly, it was found genes in the two systems43: in insects, ey is controlled by non-orthologous sets of genes.
that homologous genes, most notably regulated by toy, whereas in vertebrates, Furthermore, the ciliary, vertebrate-type
Pax6, which is the pro-orthologue36 of ey, the transcription factor gene retinal home- photoreceptor and the rhabdomeric, insect-
are involved in eye development in all obox (Rx; also known as Rax) is upstream type photoreceptor coexist in a polychaete
animals that have been examined34,37–39, of Pax6. Although a D. melanogaster worm, Platynereis dumerilii, showing that
and can induce ectopic eyes in homologue of Rx does exist, it is not vertebrate and insect eyes derive from ‘paral-
D. melanogaster35 as well as in Xenopus involved in eye development. Similarly, in ogous’ cell populations25,46 and are therefore
laevis40. vertebrates, Eya1,2,3 (homologues of eya) likely to be non-homologous.
a b c
Figure 3 | Characters and character states. The insects shown all have two is the forewing, whereas the hind wing is transformed into a club-shaped
pairs of dorsal appendages, forewings and hind wings. They can both be wing appendage, termed the haltere (indicated by a black arrow). In beetles, the
blades that function in producing lift, as in the case of butterflies (panel a), proper wing blade is the hind wing, whereas the forewing is transformed
or only one might form a proper wing blade, as in Diptera (panel b) or beetles into a protective cover called the elytra (indicated by a white arrow). Images
(panel c). In the Diptera (flies, mosquitos and so on), the proper wing blade in panels b,c courtesy of J. Tanis and A. Andrasi, respectively.
140
476 | JUNE 2007 | VOLUME 8 www.nature.com/reviews/genetics
© 2007 Nature Publishing Group
PERSPECTIVES
141
NATURE REVIEWS | GENETICS VOLUME 8 | JUNE 2007 | 477
© 2007 Nature Publishing Group
PERSPECTIVES
142
478 | JUNE 2007 | VOLUME 8 www.nature.com/reviews/genetics
© 2007 Nature Publishing Group
PERSPECTIVES
Co-adaptation predicts that the knockdown 25. Arendt, D. Genes and homology in nervous system 51. Hsia, C. C. & McGinnis, W. Evolution of transcription
evolution: comparing gene functions, expression factor function. Curr. Opin. Genet. Dev. 13,
effects can be reversed with a gene from the patterns, and cell type molecular fingerprints. 199–206 (2003).
clade that shares this character, but not by Theor. Biosci. 124, 185–197 (2005). 52. Grenier, J. K. & Carroll, S. B. Functional evolution of
26. Allan, D. W., Park, D., Pierre, S. E. S., Taghert, P. H. & the Ultrabithorax protein. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA
genes from species that diverged before the Thor, S. Regulators acting in combinatorial codes 97, 704–709 (2000).
origin of that character. High-throughput also act independently in single differentiating 53. Galant, R. & Carroll, S. B. Evolution of a
neurons. Neuron 45, 689–700 (2005). transcriptional repression domain in an insect Hox
methods make these predictions testable at 27. Shirasaki, R. & Pfaff, S. L. Transcriptional codes and protein. Nature 415, 910–913 (2002).
a scale that would allow assessment of the the control of neuronal identity. Ann. Rev. Neurosci. 54. Hittinger, C. T., Stern, D. L. & Carroll, S. B. Pleiotropic
25, 251–281 (2002). functions of a conserved insect-specific Hox peptide
utility of the ChIN concept in explaining 28. Davidson, E. H. The Regulatory Genome: motif. Development 132, 5261–5270 (2005).
homology of morphological characters. Gene Regulatory Networks in Development and 55. Ronshaugen, M., McGinnis, N. & McGinnis, W.
Evolution 144–159, 28 (Academic, Amsterdam, 2006). Hox protein mutation and macroevolution of the
Günter P. Wagner is at the Department of Ecology 29. Ghiselin, M. ‘Definition, ’ ‘character’ and other insect body plan. Nature 415, 914–917 (2002).
equivocal terms. Syst. Zool. 33, 104–110 (1984). 56. Ranganayakulu, G., Elliott, D. A., Harvey, R. P. &
and Evolutionary Biology, 30. Deutsch, J. Hox and wings. BioEssays 27, 673–675 Olson, E. N. Divergent roles for NK-2 class homeobox
Yale University, POB 208106, New Haven, (2005). genes in cardionenesis in flies and mice. Development
Connecticut 06520-8106, USA. 31. Warren, R. W., Nagy, L., Senegue, J., Gates, J. & 125, 3037–3048 (1998).
Carroll, S. Evolution of homeotic gene regulation and 57. Lohr, U., Yussa, M. & Pick, L. Drosophila fishi tarazu:
e-mail: gunter.wagner@yale.edu function in flies and butterflies. Nature 372, 458–461 a gene on the border of homeotic function. Curr. Biol.
(1994). 11, 1403–1412 (2001).
doi:10.1038/nrg2099
32. Wagner, G. P., Chiu, C.-H. & Laubichler, M. 58. Zhao, Y. & Potter, S. S. Functional specificity of the
Published online 8 May 2007 Developmental evolution as a mechanistic science: Hoxa 13 homeobox. Development 128, 3197–3207
the inference from developmental mechanisms to (2001).
1. Hall, B. K. Evolutionary Developmental Biology evolutionary processes. Am. Zool. 40, 819–831 (2000). 59. Zhao, Y. & Potter, S. S. Functional comparison of
(Chapman & Hall, London, 1998). 33. Tomoyasu, Y., Wheeler, S. R. & Denell, R. E. the Hoxa 4, Hoxa 10, and Hoxa 11 Homeoboxes.
2. Wilkins, A. S. The Evolution of Developmental Ultrabithorax is required for membranous wing Dev. Biol. 244, 21–36 (2002).
Pathways (Sinauer, Sunderland, 2002). identity in the beetle Tribolium castaneum. Nature 60. Tour, E., Hittinger, C. T. & McGinnis, W. Evolutionarily
3. Butler, A. B. & Saidel, W. M. Defining sameness: 375, 58–61 (2005). conserved domains required for activation and
historical, biological, and generative homology. 34. Gehring, W. J. & Ikeo, K. Pax6 mastering eye repression functions of the Drosophila Hox protein
BioEssays 22, 846–853 (2000). morphogenesis and eye evolution. Trends Genet. 15, Ultrabithorax. Development 132, 5271–5281
4. VanValen, L. Homology and causes. J. Morphol. 173, 371–377 (1999). (2005).
305–312 (1982). 35. Halder, G., Callerts, P. & Gehring, W. J. Induction of 61. Lynch, V. J., Roth, J. J. & Wagner, G. P. Adaptive
5. Lewontin, R. C. Adaptation. Am. Sci. 239, 156–169 ectopic eyes by targeted expression of the eyeless evolution of Hox-gene homoedomains after cluster
(1978). gene in Drosophila. Science 267, 1788–1792 (1995). duuplications. BMC Evol. Biol. 6, 86 (2006).
6. Owen, R. On the Archetype and Homologies of the 36. Holland, P. W. H. in Homology Vol. 222 (eds Bock, G. R. 62. Sharkey, M., Graba, Y. & Scott, M. P. Hox genes
Vertebrate Skeleton (Voorst, London, 1848). & Cardew, G.) 226–236 (Wiley & Sons, Chichester, in evolution: protein surfaces and paralog groups.
7. Futuyma, D. J. Evolutionary Biology (Sinauer, 1999). Trends Genet. 13, 145–151 (1997).
Sunderland, 2005). 37. Donner, A. L. & Maas, R. L. Conservation and 63. Wagner, G. P. & Lynch, V. J. Molecular evolution of
8. Brigant, I. Homology in comparative, molecular, and non-conservation of genetic pathways in eye evolutionary novelties: the vagina and uterus of
evolutionary developmental biology: the radiation of a specification. Int. J. Dev. Biol. 48, 743–753 (2004). therian mammals. J. Exp. Zool. B Mol. Dev. Evol. 304,
concept. J. Exp. Zool. B Mol. Dev. Evol. 299, 9–17 38. Kozmik, Z. Pax genes in eye development and 580–592 (2005).
(2003). evolution. Curr. Opin. Genet. Dev. 15, 430–438 64. Davidson, E. H. & Erwin, D. H. Gene regulatory
9. Graur, D. & Li, W.-H. Fundamentals of Molecular (2005). networks and the evolution of animal body plans.
Evolution (Sinauer, Sunderland, 2000). 39. Zuber, M. E., Gestri, G., Viczian, A. S., Barsacchi, G. & Science 311, 796–800 (2006).
10. Geeta, R. Structure trees and species trees: what they Harris, W. A. Specification of the vertebrate eye by a 65. Wagner, G. P. & Stadler, P. F. Quasi-independence,
say about morphological development and evolution. network of eye field transcription factors. homology and the unity of type: a topological
Evol. Dev. 5, 609–621 (2003). Development 130, 5155–5167 (2003). theory of characters. J. Theor. Biol. 220, 505–527
11. Oakley, T. H. The eye as a replicating and diverging, 40. Chow, R. L., Altmann, C. R., Lang, R. A. & (2003).
modular developmental unit. Trends Ecol. Evol. 18, Hemmati-Brivanlou, A. Pax6 induced ectopic eyes in 66. Wiley, E. O. Homology, identity and transformation
623–627 (2003). a vertebrate. Development 126, 4213–4222 (1999). in Mesozoic fishes (eds Arrtia, G. & Schultze, H.-P.)
12. Roth, V. L. Homology and hierarchies: problems 41. Kardon, G., Heanue, T. A. & Tabin, C. J. in Modularity (in the press).
solved and unresolved. J. Evol. Biol. 4, 167–194 in Development and Evolution (eds Schlosser, G. & 67. Müller, G. B. & Wagner, G. P. Novelty in evolution:
(1991). Wagner, G. P.) 59–80 (Univ. Chicago Press, Chicago restructuring the concept. Ann. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 22,
13. Ghiselin, M. T. Homology as a relation of and London, 2004). 229–256 (1991).
correspondence between parts of individuals. 42. Schlosser, G. Evolutionary origins of vertebrate 68. Miller, D. J. et al. Pax gene diversity in the basal
Theor. Biosci. 124, 91–103 (2005). placods: insights from developmental studies and from cnidarian Acropora millepora (Cnidaria, Anthozoa):
14. Wagner, G. P. The biological role of homologues: comparisons with other deuterostomes. J. Exp. Zool. B implications for the evolution of the Pax gene family.
a building block hypothesis. N. Jb. Geol. Paläont. Abh. Mol. Dev. Evol. 304, 347–399 (2005). Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 97, 4475–4480 (2000).
195, 279–288 (1995). 43. Bailey, T. J. et al. Regulation of vertebrate eye 69. Hadrys, T., DeSalle, R., Sagasser, S., Fischer, N. &
15. Wagner, G. P. in The Character Concept in development by Rx genes. Int. J. Dev. Biol. 48, Schierwater, B. The Trichoplax PaxB gene: a putative
Evolutionary Biology (ed. Wagner, G. P.) 1–10 761–770 (2004). proto-PaxA/B/C gene predating the origin of nerve and
(Academic, San Diego, 2001). 44. Bebenek, I. G., Gates, R. D., Morris, J., Hartenstein, V. sensory cells. Mol. Biol. Evol. 22, 1569–1578 (2005).
16. Wagner, G. P. The biological homology concept. & Jacobs, D. K. sine oculis in basal Metazoa.
Ann. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 20, 51–69 (1989). Dev. Genes Evol. 214, 342–351 (2004). Acknowledgements
17. Hall, B. K. in Evolutionary Biology Vol. 28 45. Stierwald, M., Yanze, N., Bamert, R. P., The author gratefully acknowledges the financial support for
(eds Hecht, M. K., MacIntyre, R. J. & Clegg, M. T.) Kammermeier, L. & Schmid, V. The sine oculis/Six class the research that led to the ideas expressed in this article:
1–30 (Plenum, New York, 1994). family of homeobox genes in jellyfish with and without NSF IBN#0321470, OIB#0445971 and the Research Prize
18. Wray, G. A. & Abouheif, E. When is homology not eyes: development and regeneration. Dev. Biol. 274, from the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation. I also want to
homology? Curr. Opin. Genet. Dev. 8, 675–680 (1998). 70–81 (2004). thank the reviewers of this paper as well as M. Laubichler,
19. Hall, B. K. Descent with modification: the unity 46. Arendt, D., Tessmar-Raible, K., Snyman, K., M. Ghiselin, E. Wiley, M. Donaghue, A. Monteiro and the
underlying homology and homoplasy as seen through Dorresteijn, A. W. & Wittbrodt, J. Cilliary members of my laboratory for discussion and inspiration.
an analysis of development and evolution. Biol. Rev. photoreceptors with a vertebrate-type opsin in an
Camb. Philos. Soc. 78, 409–433 (2003). invertebrate brain. Science 306, 869–871 (2004). Competing interests statement
20. Pankratz, M. J. & Jackle, H. in The Development 47. Nilsson, D.-E. Eye evolution: a question of genetic The author declares no competing financial interests.
of Drosophila melanogaster (eds Bate, M. & promiscuity. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 14, 407–414
Martinez-Arias, A.) 467–516 (Cold Spring Harbor (2004).
Laboratory Press, Plainview, 1993). 48. Ogura, A., Ikeo, K. & Gojobori, T. Comparative
DATABASES
21. Patel, N. H., Ball, E. F. & Goodman, C. S. Changing role analysis of gene expression for convergent evolution
The following terms in this article are linked online to:
of even-skipped during the evolution of insect pattern of camera eye between octopus and human. Genome
Entrez Gene: http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.
formation. Nature 357, 339–342 (1992). Res. 14, 1555–1561 (2004).
fcgi?db=gene
22. Dawes, R., Dawson, I., Falciani, F., Tear, G. & Akam, M. 49. Chan, S. K., Jaffe, L., Capovilla, M., Botas, J. &
abdA | bcd | dac | Dach1 | dpp | en | eve | ey | eya | ftz | HoxA4 |
Dax, a locust Hox gene related to fushi-tarazu but Mann, R. S. The DNA binding specificity of
HoxA10 | HoxA11 | HoxA13 | Pax6 | Rx | so | Srf | tin | toy |
showing no pair-rule expression. Development 120, Ultrabithorax is modulated by cooperative
Ubx | wg
1561–1572 (1994). interactions with extradenticle, another homeoprotein.
23. Peel, A. D., Chipman, A. D. & Akam, M. Arthropod Cell 78, 603–615 (1994). FURTHER INFORMATION
segmentation: beyond the Drosophila paradigm. 50. McGinnis, N., Kuziora, M. A. & McGinnis, W. Human Wagner laboratory homepage:
Nature Rev. Genet. 6, 905–916 (2005). Hox-4.2 and Drosophila deformed encode similar http://pantheon.yale.edu/%7Egpwagner/index.html
24. Arendt, D. Evolution of eyes and photoreceptor cell regulatory specificities in Drosophila embryos and Access to this links box is available online.
types. Int. J. Dev. Biol. 47, 563–571 (2003). larvae. Cell 63, 969–976 (1990).
143
NATURE REVIEWS | GENETICS VOLUME 8 | JUNE 2007 | 479
© 2007 Nature Publishing Group
JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL ZOOLOGY (MOL DEV EVOL) 285:1926 (1999)
ABSTRACT Mammals have seven cervical vertebrae, a number that remains remarkably con-
stant. I propose that the lack of variation is caused by developmental constraints: to wit, changes
in Hox gene expression, which lead to changes in the number of cervical vertebrae, are associated
with neural problems and with an increased susceptibility to early childhood cancer and still-
births. In vertebrates, Hox genes are involved in the development of the skeletal axis and the
nervous system, among other things. In humans and mice, Hox genes have been shown also to be
involved in the normal and abnormal (cancer) proliferation of cell lines; several types of cancer in
young children are associated with abnormalities in Hox gene expression and congenital anoma-
lies. In these embryonal cancers the incidence of a cervical rib (a rib on the seventh cervical
vertebra, a homeotic transformation of a cervical vertebra towards a thoracic-type vertebra) ap-
pears to be increased. The minimal estimate of the selection coefficient acting against these muta-
tions is about 12%.
In birds and reptiles variations in the number of cervical vertebrae have frequently occurred
and there is often intraspecific variability. A review of the veterinary literature shows that cancer
rates appear lower in birds and reptiles than in mammals. The low susceptibility to cancer in
these classes probably prevents the deleterious pleiotropic effect of neonatal cancer when changes
in cervical vertebral number occur.
In mammals there is, thus, a coupling between the development of the axial skeleton and other
functions (including the proliferations of cell lines). The coupling of functions is either a conserved
trait that is also present in reptiles and birds, but without apparent deleterious effects, or the
coupling is new to mammals due to a change in the functioning of Hox genes. The cost of the
coupling of functions in mammals appears to be an increased risk for neural problems, neonatal
cancer, stillbirths, and a constraint on the variability of cervical vertebral number. J. Exp. Zool.
(Mol. Dev. Evol.) 285:1926, 1999. © 1999 Wiley-Liss, Inc.
The exceedingly low level of interspecific varia- Intraspecific variations in the number of cervi-
tion in the number of cervical vertebrae of mam- cal vertebrae in mammals are extremely rare,
mals has puzzled biologists for more than 150 years. whereas intraspecific variations in the number of
In birds, reptiles, and amphibians the number of more caudal vertebrae are common, especially of
cervical vertebrae varies considerably, and in mam- the lumbar, sacral, and coccygeal regions (e.g.,
mals the number of vertebrae in other vertebral Lebouck, 1898; Schulz, 61). However, one varia-
regions is variable as well (Lebouck, 1898; Schulz, tion of cervical vertebrae does occur infrequently:
61). Swans long necks have a striking 2225 cer- cervical ribs. A cervical rib is on the seventh cer-
vical vertebrae, while ducks have 16 (Woolfenden, vical vertebra, is a partially or wholly homeotic
61), and swifts 13 (Starck, 79). Giraffes and drom- transformation of the seventh cervical vertebra
edaries, however, have only seven vertebrae (Fig. into the first thoracic vertebra and, thus, reduces
1), as do the Dugong (Fig. 2) and whales with their the number of cervical vertebrae (and increases
short necks (Starck, 79). There are only three gen-
era with an exceptional number of cervical verte-
brae, manatees (Trichechus) and sloths (Bradypus
and Choloepus). Thus, there seems to be an evolu- *Correspondence to: Frietson Gailis, Institute for Evolutionary and
Ecological Sciences, University of Leiden, PO Box 9516, 2300RA
tionary constraint towards the development of vari- Leiden, The Netherlands. E-mail: Galis@rulsfb.leidenuniv.nl
ability in the cervical region in mammals. Received 28 October 1998; Accepted 16 December 1998.
144
20 F. GALIS
Fig. 1. Skeleton of a dromedary (Camelus dromedarius). Note the large cervical verte-
brae. From Owen (1866).
the number of thoracic vertebrae). Further study toms. Research on this syndrome has revealed that
of this naturally occurring variation seems rel- cervical ribs are invariably associated with changes
evant with respect to the evolutionary constraint in the brachial plexus (a different contribution of
on cervical vertebral number, and more specifi- motor and sensory nerves to the brachial plexus)
cally, to the study of the selective factors against and other structural abnormalities (Makhoul and
this variation. Machleder, 92; Roos, 96). The correlation of
symptoms must be due to mutual influences of
PATHOLOGIES ASSOCIATED WITH the notochord, neural tube, neural crest, and
CERVICAL RIBS somites at the time of somite formation (Gossler
Consideration of the pathologies in humans that and Hrabe de Angelis, 98).
are associated with cervical ribs reveals two types, Early childhood cancer is a considerably more
thoracic outlet syndrome (TOS) and early childhood serious pathology. Childhood cancers tend to re-
cancer. TOS involves pressure on the nerves of the sult from aberrant developmental processes and
brachial plexus and on the subclavian artery, some- are generally embryonal in origin. They are asso-
times leading to severe degenerative symptoms in ciated with a high incidence of congenital abnor-
the arm (Fig. 3; Makhoul and Machleder, 92; Roos, malities. This association is assumed to be caused
96). Often surgery is performed to relieve symp- by a common underlying genetic abnormality
Fig. 2. Skeleton of a dugong (Dugong dugon). Note the small cervical vertebrae. From
Owen (1866).
145
CERVICAL VERTEBRAE: HOX GENES AND CANCER 21
Fig. 3. Illustration of the thoracic outlet in a person with by permission from Adson AW. 1947. Surgical treatment for
a cervical rib showing how arteries and axons are compressed symptoms produced by cervical ribs and the scalenus anticus
when the m. anterior scalaenus contracts. The cervical rib is muscle. Surg Gynecol Obstet 85:687700.)
incomplete and fused with the first thoracic rib. (Reproduced
(Schumacher et al., 92; Anbazhagan and Raman, unique epidemiologic, clinical, and genetic char-
97). A high incidence of vertebral anomalies, es- acteristics compared with cancers that occur in
pecially cervical ribs, was found in a study spe- older children. Some of the early onset cases are
cifically devoted to finding vertebral anomalies, familial cases, which are rare and generally char-
of 750 children with embryonal cancers (Schu- acterized not only by an early onset, but also by a
macher et al., 92). An incidence of around 25% cer- worse prognosis (Brodeur, 95; Breslow et al., 96;
vical ribs was found for the following embryonal Gurney et al., 96). This phenomenon is explained
cancers: neuroblastoma, brain tumour (astrocytoma by Knudsons (84) model for embryonal childhood
and medulloblastoma), acute lymphoblastic and cancers in which two (or only a few) mutational
myeloid leukemia, soft tissue sarcoma, Wilms tu- events occur before the onset of cancer. In famil-
mour and Ewing sarcoma (Table 1). This finding ial cases one of these mutations has occurred in
confirms the observations by Adson and Coffey the germ line and is transmissible to the offspring.
(27), who found that cervical ribs are sometimes The germ-line mutation has been identified for
discovered in children because of the presence of familial retinoblastoma (reviewed in Brodeur, 95).
a tumor in the neck. In addition, a high correla- The timing of mutational events should influence
tion between malformations of ribs (without fur- the incidence and type of congenital anomaly and
ther specification) and cancer of all types was these differences in timing can, thus, explain that
found in a large study on childhood cancers (Narod not all cases of childhood cancer have congenital
et al., 97). defects and that the anomalies are variable.
In agreement with the hypothesis of a common
genetic abnormality underlying both early child- THE ROLE OF HOX GENES IN
hood cancer and cervical ribs is the observation PATTERNING OF THE SKELETAL AXIS
that the relation between congenital anomalies AND IN CELL PROLIFERATION
and cancer is stronger in infants than in older Hox genes play an important role in the pat-
children (Brodeur, 95; Breslow et al., 96; Gurney terning of the axial skeleton in all vertebrate
et al., 96). Many infants with cancer demonstrate classes (Krumlauf, 94). Hox gene mutants display
Neuroblastoma 88 33%
Brain tumour 234 27.4%
Leukemia 227 26.8%
Soft tissue sarcoma 98 24.5%
Wilms tumour 68 23.5%
Ewing sarcoma 35 17.1%
1
Data from Schumacher et al. (92).
146
22 F. GALIS
abnormalities of the vertebral column. Particu- genes (Epstein et al., 97), also display both ver-
larly common phenotypic abnormalities in mice tebral abnormalities and a predisposition for in-
mutants are cervical ribs. At least four knock-out testinal cancer (He et al., 97). Furthermore,
mutants of hox genes in mice have an increased rostral overexpression of Hoxb-8 leads to cervical
incidence of cervical ribs (Hoxa-4, Hoxd-4, Hoxa- ribs in mice, whereas overexpression in bone mar-
5 and Hoxa-6) (reviewed in Horan et al., 95). In row is associated with leukemia (Perkins and
addition, transgenic mice overexpressing Hoxb-7 Cory, 93) and overexpression in fibroblasts with
or Hoxb-8 and mice mutants lacking the polycomb- fibrosarcoma (a cancer) (Aberdam et al., 91).
group genes bmi-1 and mel-18 (involved in the Thus, in mammals Hox genes are involved in
regulation of Hox genes) display cervical ribs patterning of the skeletal axis and in the prolif-
(McLain et al., 92; Charité et al., 94; Akasaki et eration of cell lines (among other functions) and
al., 96; van der Lugt et al., 96). Thus, the forma- aberrations in the regulation of Hox genes may
tion of cervical ribs is a process that seems to be lead to abnormalities in both these functions.
particularly susceptible to perturbations in Hox
gene expression (Horan et al., 95). Most of these Selection against cervical ribs
mutant mice have a severely impaired viability. The occurrence of cervical ribs in various mam-
At the same time Hox genes have been shown malian species and the particularly frequent occur-
to be involved in the proliferation of cell lines in rence of cervical ribs in experimental mice mutants
mice and humans (e.g., Corte et al., 93; Lawrence indicate that there is not a lack of genetic variation
et al., 96; Anbazhagan et al., 97). In a study in for this phenotype. Thus, there must be strong sta-
which cells of the myeloid, macrophage, erythroid, bilizing selection against the establishment of this
and B- and T-lymphoid lingeages were investi- trait. The correlated incidence of cervical ribs and
gated for expression of homeotic genes, up to 20 childhood cancer presents a strong case for ap-
different Hox genes were found to be activated parent selection against cervical ribs due to del-
(Kongsuwan et al., 88). Some of the genes were eterious pleiotropic effects. This correlation is
ubiquitously expressed, while others were re- strengthened by the mice mutants that not only
stricted to particular cell lineages or lines (see also display variations in cervical vertebral number, but
Lawrence et al., 96). When the cells were induced also have cancer and a much reduced fitness
to differentiate, the pattern of Hox gene expres- (Akasaki et al., 96; van der Lugt et al., 96;
sion changed. Changes in Hox gene expression Schumacher et al., 96; Coré et al., 97; He et al.,
have been demonstrated for several types of can- 97). The incidence of cervical ribs in the general
cer, including some childhood cancers that were human population averaged over several large stud-
found to have a high incidence of vertebral anoma- ies (Adson and Coffey, 27; Etter, 44; Sycamore, 44;
lies: neuroblastoma, Wilms tumour, and leukemia Crimm, 52; Menárguez Carretero and Campo
(Corte et al., 93; Lawrence et al., 96; Manohar et Muñoz, 67) is approximately 0.2% (347 cases out
al., 96; Anbazhagan et al., 97). The coupling be- of 220,026; percentages varied from 0.030.5). The
tween these two functions of Hox genes is clearly frequency of these embryonal cancers added to-
demonstrated in mice with mutations of the gether in the U.S. and Europe is approximately
Polycomb- and trithorax-group genes (Pc-G and 0.1% (0.01% Wilms tumour (15), 0.0330.075% leu-
trx-G genes). The evolutionary-conserved Pc-G and kemia (Stiller and Parkin, 96), 0.014% neuroblas-
trx-G genes are involved in the maintenance of toma (Gurney et al., 96); braintumours 0.020.06%).
expression of homeobox genes including Hom and Assuming a chance for embryonal cancers of 0.1%
Hox genes. Mice lacking or overexpressing Pc-G and a chance for cervical ribs associated with em-
and trx-G genes have altered expression areas of bryonal cancers of 25% (Shumacher et al., 92) im-
Hox genes and display both vertebral anomalies plies a 0.025% chance for children to have both a
(including cervical ribs and other changes in the cervical rib and early childhood cancer. Assuming a
number of cervical vertebrae) and leukemia or re- frequency of cervical ribs of 0.2% in the general
lated cancers (Corte et al., 93; van der Lugt et al., population after early childhood and an average sur-
94; Yu et al., 95; Akasaki et al., 96; Schumacher vival of 60% for early childhood cancers (Miller et
et al., 96; Coré et al., 97). One of these genes is the al., 95) implies that the total incidence of cervical
trx-G gene Mll, the most commonly involved gene ribs at birth is 0.21%, of which 11.9% will develop
in infant leukemias (Pui et al., 95). Mice heterozy- an embryonal cancer. This suggests that children
gous for the knock-out allele of the caudal gene with embryonal cancers have a 125-fold increased
Cdx2, which is involved in the regulation of Hox incidence of cervical ribs (25% vs. 0.2%), and that
147
CERVICAL VERTEBRAE: HOX GENES AND CANCER 23
children born with a cervical rib have an almost bolic rate (McNab, 88; Ricklefs et al., 96). How-
120-fold chance of early childhood cancer (11.9% vs. ever, there is evidence (from canaries and pigeons)
0.1%). Thus, neonatal cancer alone seems to present that birds have a remarkably low free radical pro-
sufficient apparent selection against the establish- duction and, thus, a low amount of oxidative dam-
ment of cervical ribs. age (Perez-Campo, 98).
In addition, the symptoms of TOS will enhance In addition, cancer in birds, especially in young
natural selection against cervical ribs by direct birds, is generally believed in the majority of cases
stabilizing selection. The seriousness of the symp- to be induced by viruses (Effron et al., 77; Reece,
toms is correlated with the amount of manual 96; Misdorp and Kik, personal communication).
labour that is being performed. Therefore, under In mammals viral cancers are estimated to occur
natural circumstances the selective disadvantage in 15% of cases, mainly liver cancer, cervical can-
will be larger than in the sheltered present-day cer, and Hodgkins disease in children (Pisani et
human environment. Adults with a rudimentary al., 97). A survey of 343,600 young chickens
first rib (a partial transformation towards eight showed that none developed a non-virally associ-
cervical vertebrae) often have TOS, suggesting ated cancer in the first five weeks of life whereas
natural selection against this variation in cervi- 53 developed a virally associated cancer (Helmsley,
cal vertebral number as well (Gelabert et al., 97). 66). This pattern, confirmed by Reece (96), is in
A further selection factor against cervical ribs striking contrast to that in human infants where
could be an increased chance of stillbirths. A large in the first month of life almost all cancers are non-
minority (>30%) of fetuses between 49 and 150 mm virally associated embryonal cancers, predomi-
has ossification centers in the seventh cervical nantly neuroblastoma (35%; Gurney et al.,96).
prevertebra (Peters, 27; Noback, 51; Meyer, 78). In reptiles the viral induction of cancer has been
These ossification centers appear in the same posi- studied much less. However, reptilian cancers
tion as those of thoracic prevertebraes future ribs. seem more similar to cancers in birds than in
An explanation of this phenomenon could be that mammals (Effron et al., 77) and the viruses that
the high percentage of ossification centers (cervical induce cancer in reptiles also seem more similar
ribs) is related to the causes that have led to the to those in birds than in mammals (Trubcheninova
premature death of these fetuses. Again the inter- et al., 77). In addition, reptiles with cancer at
active nature of the early processes which involve necropsy are usually very old, and one study has
Hox genes may present a link between cervical ribs shown that snakes with cancer are even older on
and other abnormalities, as it is unlikely that the average than snakes without cancer (Ramsay et
ossification centers themselves cause stillbirths. It al., 96). In amphibians the situation is even less
is possible that the problems in the proliferation of well documented; however, the one type of cancer
cell lines that lead to neonatal cancer are also caus- that is well documented, Luckés tumour in Rana
ally related to the stillbirths. pipiens, is a virally induced cancer (McKinnell and
Carlson, 97).
A COMPARISON OF MAMMALS, There are a few mammalian species with an ab-
REPTILES AND AMPHIBIANS errant number of cervical vertebrae: manatees and
The number of cervical vertebrae is variable in sloths. Sloths especially show a spectacular break-
amphibians, reptiles, and birds, in strong contrast down of the constraint on variation as the num-
to mammals (in fishes no cervical vertebral re- ber of cervical vertebrae varies from 6 to 9 (Giffin
gion is distinguished). The selection against such and Gillett, 96). There is no explanation for these
variation in the number of cervical vertebrae must exceptions, but I suggest as hypothesis that the
be considerably weaker or absent in these other extremely low metabolic rate of manatees and
vertebrate classes. In necropsy studies of zoo ani- sloths (e.g., McNab 88; Gallivan and Best 89;
mals, cancer rates of birds and reptiles are low Koteja 91; Hammond and Diamond, 97) is asso-
compared to mammals (Fox, 12; Ratcliffe, 33; ciated with low oxidative DNA damage and, thus,
Ippen, 59; Lombard and Witte, 59; Effron et al., with a low susceptibility to cancer (Adelman et
77). The low susceptibility to cancer in reptiles al., 88; Shigenaga and Ames, 93). This hypoth-
makes intuitive sense because of their low meta- esis needs to be tested.
bolic rate, which leads to an expectation of low
oxidative DNA damage (cf. Adelman et al., 88; CONCLUSIONS
Perez-Campo et al., 98). The low susceptibility in It appears, therefore, that the cause of the con-
birds may seem surprising given their high meta- servation of seven cervical vertebrae should be
148
24 F. GALIS
sought (1) in a genetic link between early child- Schilthuizen, Jan Sevenster, Elisabeth van Ast-
hood cancer and stillbirths and variation in cer- Gray, Günter Wagner, Adam Wilkins, Ole See-
vical vertebrae number, and (2) in the neuronal hausen and an anonymous referee gave many
problems leading to the thoracic outlet syndrome helpful comments on the manuscript. Thanks to
in adults associated with cervical ribs. The in- David Povel and Frank Alders for their help in
volvement of Hox genes in the cancers that are collecting literature and to Adri t Hooft and Mar-
associated with cervical ribs in mice and men tin Brittijn for help with the figures.
points to a coupling between functions of Hox
genes that appears to be lacking in birds, reptiles, LITERATURE CITED
and amphibians, or at least has no apparent con- Aberdam D, Negreanu V, Sachs L, Blatt C. 1991. The onco-
sequences when cervical vertebral number is genic potential of an activated Hox-2.4 homeobox gene in
mouse fibroblasts. Mol Cell Biol 11:554557.
changed. There are two possible explanations for Adelman R, Saul RL, Ames BN. 1988. Oxidative damage to
the observed coupling in mammals: (1) the cou- DNA: relation to species metabolic rate and life span. Proc
pling of functions of Hox genes has newly ap- Natl Acad Sci USA 85:27062708.
peared in mammals due to a change in the Adson AW. 1947. Surgical treatment for symptoms produced
functioning of Hox genes (e.g., a new function in by cervical ribs and the scalenus anticus muscle. Surg
Gynecol Obstet 85:687700.
proliferation in mammals); and (2) the coupling Adson AW, Coffey JR. 1927. Cervical rib. Ann Surg 85:
of functions was already present in reptiles, but 839857.
hidden because of the low susceptibility to can- Akasaki T, Kanno M, Balling R, Mieza MA, Taniguchi M,
cer. This coupling has only become detectable in Koseki HA. 1996. A role for mel-18, a polycomb groupre-
mammals because of an increase in susceptibility lated vertebrate gene, during the anteroposterior specifica-
tion of the axial skeleton. Development 122:15131522.
to cancer. And this increase in cancer susceptibil- Albertazzi E, Cajone F, Lakshmi MS, Sherbet GV. 1998. Heat
ity can be the direct result of the increase in meta- shock modulates the expression of the metastasis associ-
bolic rate, which is associated with an increase in ated gene MTS1 and proliferation of murine and human
oxidative damage (Adelman et al., 88; Shigenaga cancer cells. DNA Cell Biol 17:17.
and Ames, 93). Alkema MJ, Lugt NMT, Bobeldijk RC, Berns A, van Lohuizen
M. 1995. Transformation of axial skeleton due to over-
The increase in cancer susceptibility and the expression of bmi-1 in transgenic mice. Nature 374:724727.
presumed increase in stillbirths are pleiotropic Anbazhagan R, Raman V. 1997. Homeobox genes: molecular
deleterious effects, whereas the neuronal prob- link between congenital anomalies and cancer. Eur J Can-
lems are a direct consequence of the change in cer 33:635637.
cervical vertebral number. The fact that the pleio- Bardeen CR. 1904. Numerical vertebral variation in the hu-
man adult and embryo. Anat Anz 25:497519.
tropic effect of cancer recurs for what presum- Breslow NE, Olsen J, Moksness J, Beckwith JB, Grundy P.
ably are a large number of different mutations 1996. Familial Wilms tumor: a descriptive study. Med
allows us to classify these collectively as a devel- Pediatr Oncol 27:398403.
opmental constraint. To further understand the Brodeur GM. 1995. Genetics of embryonal tumours of child-
constraint on changes in the number of cervical hood: retinoblastoma, Wilms tumour and neuroblastoma.
Cancer Surv 25:6799.
vertebrae that exists in virtually all mammals, a Charité J, de Graaff W, Deschamps J 1994. Ectopic expres-
study of the function of Hox genes in cell prolif- sion of Hoxb-8 causes duplication of the ZPA in the fore-
eration and carcinogenesis in birds, reptiles, and limb and homeotic transformation in axial structures. Dev
amphibians is urgently needed. Furthermore, it Dyn 204:1321
should be an interesting experiment to select for Crimm PD. 1952. Evaluation of a five year minifilm program.
Am J Roentg 68:240246.
complete cervical ribs in a mammalian species to Coré N, Bel S, Gaunt SJ, Aurrand-Lions M, Pearce J, Fisher
see whether a healthy strain can be produced, or A, Djabali M. 1997. Altered cellular proliferation and me-
whether this would lead to the predicted increase soderm patterning in Polycomb-M33-deficient mice. Devel-
in susceptibility for cancer, stillbirths, and neu- opment 124:721729.
ronal problems. Corte G, Airoldi I, Briatat P, Corsetti MT, et al. 1993. The
homeotic gene products in the control of cell differentiation
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS and proliferation. Cancer Detect Prev 17:261266.
Dongen PAM van. 1998. Brain size in vertebrates. In:
I thank Hans Metz, Rogier Versteeg, Günter Nieuwenhuys R, ten Donkelaar HJ, Nicholson C, editors.
Wagner, Jacques van Alphen, and Adam Wilkins The central nervous system of vertebrates, volume 3. Ber-
for stimulating discussions and ideas, and Maja lin: Springer Verlag. p 20992134.
Effron M, Griner L, Benirschke K. 1977. Nature and rate of
Kik, Elliott Jacobson, Hans Feuth, and Professor neoplasia in captive wild mammals, birds and reptiles at
Misdorp for medical and veterinary information. necropsy. J Natl Cancer Inst 59:185198.
Russ Lande, Gerard Mulder, Louise Roth, Menno Epstein M, Pillemer G, Yelin R, Yisraeli JK, Fainsod A. 1997.
149
CERVICAL VERTEBRAE: HOX GENES AND CANCER 25
Patterning of the embryo along the anterior-posterior axis: Maris JM, Brodeur GM. 1997. Are certain children more likely
the role of the caudal genes. Development 124:38053814. to develop neuroblastoma? J Pediatr 131:656657.
Etter LE. 1944. Osseous abnormalities of the thoracic cage McKinnell RG, Carlson DL. 1997. Lucké renal adenocarci-
seen in forty thousand consecutive chest photoroentgeno- noma, an anuran neoplasm: studies at the interface of pa-
grams. Am J Roentg 5:359363. thology, virology, and differentiation competence. J Cell
Fox H. 1912. Observations upon neoplasms in wild animals Physiol 173:115118.
in the Philadelphia Zoological Gardens. J Path Bact 17:217. McNab BK. 1983. Energetics, body size, and the limits to
Gelabert HA, Machleder HI. 1997. Diagnosis and manage- endothermy. J Zool Lond 199:129.
ment of arterial compression at the thoracic outlet. Ann Vasc Meyer DB. 1978. The appearance of cervical ribs during early
Surg 11:359366. human fetal development. Anat Rec 190:481.
Gossler A, Hrabe de Angelis M. 1998. Somitogenesis. Curr Menárguez Carretero L, Campo Muñoz M. 1967. Estudio
Top Dev Biol 38:225287. radiologico y tipos morfologicos de costillas cervicales en el
Gurney JG, Davis S, Severson RK, Fang J-Y, Ross JA, Robison sexo femenino. Enferm Torax 16:285308.
LL. 1996. Trends in cancer incidence among children in the Miller RW, Young JL, Novakovic B. 1995. Childhood cancer.
U.S. Cancer 78:532541. Cancer 75(suppl):395405.
He T-C, Costa LT, Thiagalingam S. 1997. Homeosis and poly- Narod SA, Hawkins MM, Robertson CM, Stiller CA. 1997.
posis: a tale from the mouse. Bioessays 19:551555. Congenital anomalies and childhood cancer in Great Brit-
Helmsley LA. 1966. The incidence of tumours in young chick- ain. Am J Hum Genet 60:474485.
ens. J Path Bact 92:9196. Noback CR, Robertson GG. 1951. Sequences of appearance
Hoeven F van der, Sordino P, Fraudeau N, Izpisúa-Belmon- of ossification centers in the human skeleton during the
teand JC, Duboule D. 1996. Teleost HoxD and HoxA genes: first five prenatal months. Am J Anat 89:128.
comparison with tetrapods and functional evolution of the Perez-Campo R, López-Torres M, Cadenas S, Rojas C, Barja
HoxD complex. Mech Dev 54:921. G. 1998. The rate free radical production as a determinant
Horan GSB, Nagy Kovacs E, Behringer RR, Featherstone MS. of the rate of aging: evidence from the comparative ap-
1995. Mutations in paralogous Hox genes result in overlap- proach. J Comp Physiol B 168:149158.
ping homeotic transformations of the axial skeleton: evi- Perkins AC, Cory S. 1993. Conditional immortalization of mouse
dence for unique and redundant function. Dev Biol 169: myelomonocytic megakaryocytic and mast cell progenitors by
359372. te Hox-2.4 homeobox gene. EMBO J 12:38353846.
Ippen R. 1985. Geschwülste. In: Ippen R, Zwart P, Schröder Peters H. 1927. Varietäten der Wirbelsäule menschlicher
H-D, editors. Handbuch der zootierkrankheiten, band 1, Embryonen. Gegenbaurs Morph Jahrbuch 58:440477.
reptilien. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. p 270301. Pisani P, Parkin DM, Muñoz M, Ferlay J. 1997. Cancer and
Knudson AG. 1984. Genetic predisposition to cancer. Cancer infection: estimates of the attributable fraction in 1990. Can-
Det Prev 7:18. cer Epidemiol Biomarkers Prev 6:387400.
Kongsuwan K, Webb E, Housiaux P, Adams JM 1988. Ex- Pui C-H, Kane JR, Crist WM. 1995. Biology and treatment
pression of multiple homeobox genes within diverse mam- of infant leukemias. Leukemia 9:762769.
malian haematopoietic lineages. EMBO J 7:21312138. Ramsay EC, Munson L, Lowenstine L, Fowler L, Fowler ME.
Krumlauf R. 1994. Hox genes in vertebrate development.Cell 1996. A retrospective study of neoplasia in a collection of
78:191201. captive snakes. J Zoo Wildl Medicine 27:2834.
Kusewitt DF, Reece RL, Miska KB. 1997. S-100 immunore- Ratcliffe HL. 1933. Incidence and nature of tumors in cap-
activity in melanomas of two marsupials, a bird, and a rep- tive wild mammals and birds. Am J Cancer 17:116135.
tile. Vet Pathol 34:615618. Reece RL. 1996. Some observations on naturally occurring
Lawrence HJ, Sauvageau G, Humphries RK, Largman C. neoplasms of domestic fowls in the state of Victoria Austra-
1996. The role of Hox homeobox genes in normal and leu- lia 19771987. Avian Pathol 25:407447.
kemic hematopoiesis. Stem Cells 14:281291. Ricklefs RE, Konarzeweski M, Daan S. 1996. The relation-
Leboucq H 1898. Recherches sur les variations anatomiques ship between basal metabolic rate and daily energy expen-
de la première côte chez lhomme. Archiv Biol 15:9178. diture in birds and mammals. Am Nat 147:10471071.
Lombard LS, Witte EJ. 1959. Frequency and types of tu- Roos DB. 1996. Historical perspectives and anatomic consid-
mors in mammals and birds of the Philadelphia zoological erations. Semin Thorac Cardiovasc Surg 8:183189.
garden. Cancer Res 19:127141. Satgé D, Sasco AJ, Carlsen NLT, Stiller CA, et al. 1998. A
Lugt NMT van der, Domen J, Linders K, van Roon M, lack of neuroblastoma in Down Syndrome: a study from 11
Robanus-Maandog E, Riele H, van der Valk M, Deschamps European countries. Cancer Res 58:448452.
Y, Sofronio M, van Gohuinen M, Berns A. 1996. Posterior Schulz AH. 1961. Vertebral column and thorax. In: Hofer H,
transformation, neurological abnormalities, and severe he- Schultz AH, Starck D, editors. Primatologia, handbook of
matopoietic defects in mice with a targeted deletion of the primatology. S. Karger. p 5/15/66.
bmi-1 proto-oncogene. Genes Dev 8:757769. Schumacher A, Faust C, Magnuson T. 1996. Positional clon-
Makhoul RG, Machleder HI. 1992. Developmental anomalies ing of a global regulator of anterior-posterior patterning in
at the thoracic outlet: an analysis of 200 consecutive cases. mice. Nature 383:250253.
J Vasc Surg 16:534545. Schumacher R, Mai A, Gutjahr P. 1992. Association of rib
Manohar CF, Salwen HR, Furtado MR, Cohn SL. 1996. Up- anamalies and malignancy in childhood. Eur J Pediatr
regulation of Hoxc6, Hoxd1, and Hoxd8 homeobox gene ex- 151:432434.
pression in human neuroblastoma cells following chemical Shigenaga MK, Ames BN. 1993. Oxidants and mitogen-
induction of differentiation. Tumor Biol 14:3447. esis as causes of mutation and cancer: the influence of
McLain K, Schreiner C, Yager KL, Stock JL, Potter SS. 1992. diet. In: Bronzetti G, editor. Antimutagenesis and anti-
Ectopic expression of Hox-2.3 induces craniofacial and skel- carcinogenesis mechanisms III. New York: Plenum Press.
etal malformations in transgenic mice. Mech Dev 39:316. p 419436.
150
26 F. GALIS
Starck D. 1979.Vergleichende Anatomie der Wirbeltiere. Ber- virus infection: tumorigenicity of Rous sarcoma virus for
lin: Springer Verlag. reptiles. Neoplasma 24:319.
Stiller CA, Parkin DM. 1996. Geographic and ethnic varia- Turner HN. 1847. Observations on the distinction between
tions in the incidence of childhood cancer. Brit Med Bull the cervical and dorsal vertebrae in the class mammalia.
Proc Zool Soc Lond 15:110114.
52:682703.
Woolfenden GE. 1961. Postcranial morphology of the water-
Sycamore LK. 1944. Common congenital anomalies of the fowl. Bull Florida State Museum Biol Sci 6:1129.
bony thorax. Am J Roentg 51:593599. Yu BD, Hess JL, Horning SE, Brown GA, Korsmeyer SJ. 1995.
Trubcheninova LP, Khutoryansky AA, Svet-Moldavsky GJ, Altered Hox expression and segmental identity in Mll-mu-
Kuznetsova LE, et al. 1977. Body temperature and tumor tant mice. Nature 387:505508.
151
152
TRABAJO PRÁCTICO 2 : EJERCITACIÓN
Problema 1.
Responda verdadero o falso y justifique TODOS los casos.
1) La homología serial a nivel estructural es un concepto análogo a la duplicación y
divergencia a nivel genético. A manera de ejemplo, se asume que a partir de una
vértebra ancestral se generó un mayor número de vértebras en los taxa derivados a
través de su duplicación, y análogamente el origen de una familia multigénica de varios
genes parálogos a través de la duplicación de un gen ancestral con la posterior
divergencia.
2) Las heterocronías son cambios en el tiempo de desarrollo de una estructura dada en
diferentes taxa. Es decir que, si dos grupos hermanos tienen el mismo tiempo de
desarrollo de la estructura estudiada, no hubo procesos heterocrónicos a lo largo de la
evolución del linaje.
3) La ontogenia recapitula la filogenia.
Problema 2.
La evolución de los apéndices es uno de los temas más estudiados bajo una perspectiva
filogenética, de embriología comparada y experimental. En particular dentro de los
tetrápodos, los anfibios son un grupo de gran diversidad en cuanto al número de dígitos
y falanges.
Entre los anfibios, existen dos grandes órdenes: los Anuros (ranas) y los Urodelos
(salamandras), ambos, por lo general, poseen 5 dígitos en sus apéndices posteriores.
Diferentes estudios sugieren que el ancestro de estos dos grupos poseía un apéndice
posterior caracterizado por 2 falanges en el primer dígito, 3 en el segundo, 4 en el
tercero, 4 en el cuarto y 3 en el quinto (formula del número de falanges: 23443).
Por lo general, las especies de Anuros son muy conservadas en el número de falanges
con una fórmula de falanges de 22343 (ver Figura 1). Por el contrario, en los
Urodelos la fórmula del número de falanges es mucho más variable que en los Anuros.
153
En la Tabla I se esquematiza la secuencia de diferenciación de las falanges durante la
ontogenia en dos especies modelo Xenopus laevis y Ambystoma mexicanus, anuro y
urodelo, respectivamente. De acuerdo a esta información:
2.1. ¿es sincrónico el desarrollo de los dígitos en cada especie?
2.2. ¿Qué clase de homología está implícita en esta comparación? Defínala.
154
Pere Alberch, gran embriólogo evolutivo, abordó de manera experimental el problema de
la variación en el número de falanges en los anfibios, tratando con un inhibidor mitótico
(colchicina) durante las etapas tempranas del desarrollo de los apéndices posteriores de
ambas especies. Como resultado de este experimento se observó una reducción en el
número de falanges en los 5 dígitos de cada especie. La información de dicho
experimento se resume en las Figuras 1 y 2.
2.3. ¿Encuentra algún tipo de patrón que relacione la reducción del número de
dígitos con el tiempo de desarrollo de los mismos? Formule una hipótesis que
vincule ambos resultados.
En la naturaleza se puede observar especies de anfibios con 4 dedos, tanto en el orden de
los Anuros como en el de los Urodelos. Tal es el caso de la especie Psyllophryne didactyla
(Anuros) cuya fórmula de numero de falanges es: 02341, como la especie
Salamandrina terdigitata (Urodelo) cuya fórmula es de: 12320. Si este patrón natural
concuerda con la hipótesis planteada anteriormente por Ud.:
2.4. ¿El dedo “pulgar” (el primer dígito con falange) de ambas especies es
homólogo (primario)? Justifique su respuesta utilizando los criterios de homología.
Defina los términos alometría evolutiva y alometría ontogenética e identifique un
ejemplo de ambos en el caso de estudio.
155
Problema 3.
Las alas son una adaptación muy importante de los insectos, la cual les permite escapar
de los predadores, explotar recursos y dispersarse a nuevos nichos. Pese a las supuestas
ventajas evolutivas de las alas, casi todos los órdenes de insectos alados poseen linajes
con reducción parcial o total de las alas. En este sentido, cientos de transiciones
independientes de formas aladas a no aladas han ocurrido durante la evolución de las
alas. Sin embargo, una reversión de una forma sin alas a una con alas nunca ha sido
demostrada claramente, dado que tal reversión sería muy improbable dadas las
complejas interacciones entre nervios, músculos, y escleritos que se requieren para el
vuelo.
3.1. Bajo esta hipótesis inicial: ¿son homólogas las alas de los distintos insectos? ¿Y
el primer y segundo par dentro de cada especie? Indique que información utilizaría
para estudiar alometrías estáticas, ontogenéticas y evolutivas del ala dentro de
algún género en particular.
3.2. Un estudio reciente de la evolución de las alas dentro del orden Phasmatodea
(los llamados “bichos palo”) mostró el siguiente resultado:
Grupos externos
Referencias. Estrella: ganancia de alas. Triángulo: pérdida de alas. Circulo vacío:
especies con alas.
156
¿Modifica este resultado su respuesta anterior? Justifique.
3.3. Un tercer estudio mostró que los genes involucrados en el patrón de desarrollo
de las alas están presentes en todos los insectos, incluso los ápteros. Proponga una
hipótesis para explicar este resultado y (de ser necesario) reconciliar las hipótesis
anteriores.
Problema 4.
Adams y Nistri (BMC Evolutionary Biology 2010) estudiaron la morfología de las patas
de ocho especies de salamandras europeas del género Hydromantes para poner a prueba
la hipótesis de que la morfología del adulto constituye una adaptación relacionada con
sus hábitos arborícolas. Estos autores observaron que cinco especies habitantes de la isla
de Cerdeña alcanzan un tamaño mayor que las otras tres especies pertenecientes al
continente. Sin embargo, todas las especies muestran valores similares y relativamente
bajos de sinuosidad lo que implica la presencia de más tejido interdigital (Fig. 1).
Figura 1: Esquemas de la pata de las salamandras estudiadas que muestran la mayor
sinuosidad y menor presencia de tejido interdigital en individuos pequeños (a la izquierda) en
comparación con individuos grandes (a la derecha).
Cuando estos autores analizaron la morfología a lo largo del desarrollo de cada especie,
encontraron patrones muy diferentes (Tabla 1). Por un lado, la mayoría de la especies no
mostró cambios en el nivel de sinuosidad (o en la abundancia de tejido interdigital) a
través de la ontogenia. Por otro lado, en tres especies habitantes de la isla, se observó
que el nivel de sinuosidad disminuye (o que la cantidad de tejido interdigital aumenta) a
medida que los animales crecen.
157
Tabla 1: Principales resultados de los análisis de regresión de la sinuosidad versus el tamaño
total. Para cada especie se muestra el valor de la pendiente de la recta de regresión y la
significación asociada. p < 0,05 indicado en negrita, c: especie continental, i: especie isleña.
158
Figura 2: Relaciones filogenéticas de las especies de salamandras europeas estudiadas basadas
en una filogenia molecular realizada utilizando datos de secuencias de ADN mitocondrial y
nuclear. Los esquemas muestran el patrón de alometría asociado a cada especie. c: especie
continental, i: especie isleña.
b) En base a estos resultados, ¿qué conclusiones puede extraer acerca de la homología
del patrón de crecimiento alométrico observado en las tres especies isleñas? ¿Cómo
podría explicar estos resultados considerando el concepto de heterocronía?
Posteriormente, se estudió la trayectoria ontogenética de una especie de salamandra
norteamericana (H. platycephalus) la cual exhibe un crecimiento alométrico similar al
observado en las especies isleñas. Cuando se incluyó a H. platycephalus en el análisis,
los patrones descriptos anteriormente no cambiaron pero si lo hizo la condición ancestral
de todo el género la cual pasó a ser alométrica.
c) ¿Modifica este resultado su hipótesis de homología expuesta en el punto anterior?
Justifique.
159
Finalmente, los autores extendieron estos análisis a más especies de salamandras
pertenecientes a otros géneros y observaron que las trayectorias ontogenéticas de las
especies europeas se asemejan, por un lado, a especies que poseen hábitos similares (es
decir, especies trepadoras) y, por otro lado, a especies cavadoras las cuales presentan
una posición más basal en la filogenia de las salamandras.
d) ¿Cómo podría explicar estos resultados en términos de exaptación?
Problema 5.
Relacione cada uno de los siguientes gráficos con uno de los enunciados a continuación.
Justifique sus respuestas.
a. El estudio comparado de las alometrías a nivel craneofacial no permite inferir
procesos heterocrónicos dado que en la muestra se hallan subrepresentados algunos
estadios ontogenéticos de ambas especies. También se sospecha que una de las
muestras ontogenéticas incluye ejemplares de más de una especie.
b. Un proceso heterocrónico de tipo pedomórfico actuó a nivel craneofacial en
humanos mientras que no se puede postular un cambio en los tiempos de desarrollo
de dichas estructuras en chimpancés.
c. La relación entre la forma del neurocráneo y la forma de la cara en humanos
presenta un desarrollo desacelerado desde la adolescencia a la adultez con respecto a
estadios anteriores de su ontogenia.
d. El estudio de las alometrías a nivel craneofacial no permite inferir procesos
heterocrónicos en la divergencia entre los linajes de humanos y chimpancés.
e. Nuestra especie se caracteriza por una acentuada aceleración de los ritmos de
desarrollo.
160
161
MÓDULO VIII
MACROEVOLUCIÓN
162
163
TRABAJO PRÁCTICO N° 1
MACROEVOLUCIÓN
NIVELES EN LOS SISTEMAS COMPLEJOS
Sobre los niveles, sus límites y Borges
INTRODUCCIÓN GENERAL
“Todos estamos familiarizados con la [clase de cosas que pueden ser comprendidas en
diferentes niveles]. Sin embargo, por algún motivo algunos de ellos nos resultan más fáciles de
imaginar e integrar a nuestra vida cotidiana o a nuestro conocimiento sin que ello nos ocasiones
mayores inconvenientes. (…) Por ejemplo, todos sabemos que los seres humanos están
integrados por una enorme cantidad de células (veinticinco trillones, aproximadamente), y que,
en consecuencia, todo lo que hacemos podría estar descrito, en principio, en función celular. O
bien la descripción podría hacerse, inclusive, en el nivel de las moléculas. La mayoría de nosotros
acepta esto de una manera bastante limitada; vamos al médico para que examine lo que
consideramos nuestros niveles inferiores. Leemos sobre el ADN y la “ingeniería genética” y
sorbemos nuestro café. Pareciera que hemos conciliado estas dos imágenes increíblemente
distintas de nosotros mismos mediante el simple recurso de desconectarlas entre sí. No contamos
prácticamente con ninguna forma de relacionar una descripción microscópica de nosotros mismos
con lo que imaginamos que somos, y de ahí que sea posible el almacenamiento de
representaciones disociadas de nosotros mismos en “compartimientos” de nuestra mente
disociados por completo entre sí. Rara vez nos vemos en situación de alternar entre uno y otro de
estos conceptos, preguntándonos, “¿cómo estas dos cosas totalmente diferentes pueden ser el
mismo yo?””.
Fragmento extraído del libro “Gödel, Escher, Bach, un eterno y grácil bucle” de Hofstadter (pág. 316)
OBJETIVOS
164
PRIMERA PARTE: El debate sobre la unicidad o la multiplicidad de niveles
Lea atentamente el texto Furmiga, fragmento seleccionado y adaptado correspondiente al
Capítulo X del libro: “Gödel, Escher, Bach: un eterno y grácil bucle” de Douglas Hofstadter.
Responda:
1.1 ¿Qué se entiende por “holismo”? ¿Qué por “reduccionismo”?
1.2. ¿Qué son los niveles de un sistema según el autor?
1.3 ¿Pueden tener diferentes propiedades estos niveles? ¿Pueden los sistemas estar
correlacionados entre sí a distintos niveles u operar procesos similares a distintos niveles?
Analice los casos presentados por Hofstadter.
165
TERCERA PARTE: El debate sobre la unicidad o la multiplicidad de niveles
Lea atentamente los fragmentos seleccionados del artículo “Acquiring Genomes: A Theory of the
Origins of Species” de L. Margulis & D. Sagan, 2002, Perseus Books Group (traducidos al
español).
Responda:
3.1. ¿Qué entienden Magulis y Sagan por simbiosis? ¿Qué por simbiogénesis? ¿Considera
Ud. que éstas son fuerzas evolutivas de importancia? ¿Por qué?
3.2. ¿Cuál es la crítica que realizan Margulis y Sagan al concepto biológico de especie?
¿Cree Ud. que esta crítica puede ser salvada utilizando otro concepto de especie tal
como los que ha visto anteriormente?
3.3. a) ¿Cuál es la crítica de Margulis al concepto de “competencia”? ¿Qué alcances
empíricos tiene dicho concepto según los autores?
b) ¿Dónde radica según los autores este “olvido” de la teoría de la simbiogénesis como
fuerza evolutiva? ¿Qué cree Ud. al respecto? Responda relacionando lo anterior con lo
visto en el primer práctico de la materia acerca de factores internos y externos.
- Relacione este cuento con el problema planteado en “Funes, el memorioso”. ¿En qué
sentido esta historia se relaciona con el “olvidar diferencias” de Funes?
- ¿Qué conclusiones generales se obtienen del cuento?
4.4. Utilizando los tres cuentos simultáneamente, ¿qué relación cree Ud. que tiene todo esto
con la Teoría de la Evolución?
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
El libro Ficciones, escrito por Jorge Luis Borges, Italia, Alemania y España.
incluye una serie de cuentos que pertenecen “a Uno de los cuentos que relata y que
la clásica categoría de las piezas antológicas”. reproducimos en esta edición de Petrotecnia es
Traducido a varios idiomas, fue galardonado en “Funes el memorioso” que, según el propio
1961 con el Premio Internacional otorgado por autor, “es una larga metáfora del insomnio”.
editores de Francia, Estados Unidos, Inglaterra,
Funes el memorioso
Por Jorge Luis Borges
Se agradece a la Fundación Internacional Jorge Luis Borges el permiso para su publicación. © María Kodama
L
o recuerdo (yo no tengo derecho a pronunciar ese
verbo sagrado, sólo un hombre en la tierra tuvo
derecho y ese hombre ha muerto) con una oscura
pasionaria en la mano, viéndola como nadie la ha visto,
aunque la mirara desde el crepúsculo del día hasta el de la
noche, toda una vida entera. Lo recuerdo, la cara taciturna y
aindiada y singularmente remota, detrás del cigarrillo.
Recuerdo (creo) sus manos afiladas de trenzador. Recuerdo
cerca de esas manos un mate, con las armas de la Banda
Oriental; recuerdo en la ventana de la casa una estera amari-
lla, con un vago paisaje lacustre. Recuerdo claramente su
voz; la voz pausada, resentida y nasal del orillero antiguo,
sin los silbidos italianos de ahora. Más de tres veces no lo vi;
la última, en 1887... Me parece muy feliz el proyecto de que
todos aquellos que lo trataron escriban sobre él; mi testimo-
nio será acaso el más breve y sin duda el más pobre, pero no
el menos imparcial del volumen que editarán ustedes.
Mi deplorable condición de argentino me impedirá incu-
rrir en el ditirambo –género obligatorio en el Uruguay, cuan-
do el tema es uruguayo. Literato, cajetilla, porteño; Funes nos
dijo esas injuriosas palabras, pero de un modo suficiente me
consta que yo representaba para él esas desventuras. Pedro
Leandro Ipuche ha escrito que Funes era un precursor de los
superhombres, “un Zarathustra cimarrón y vernáculo”; no lo
discuto, pero no hay que olvidar que era también un compa-
drito de Fray Bentos, con ciertas incurables limitaciones.
Mi primer recuerdo de Funes es muy perspicuo. Lo veo
en un atardecer de marzo o febrero del año ochenta y cua-
tro. Mi padre, ese año, me había llevado a veranear a Fray
Bentos. Yo volvía con mi primo Bernardo Haedo de la
estancia de San Francisco. Volvíamos cantando, a caba-
llo, y ésa no era la única circunstancia de mi felicidad.
Después de un día bochornoso, una enorme tormenta
color pizarra había escondido el cielo. La alentaba el
viento del Sur, ya se enloquecían los árboles; yo tenía
el temor (la esperanza) de que nos sorprendiera en un
descampado el agua elemental. Corrimos una especie de
carrera con la tormenta. Entramos en un callejón que se
ahondaba entre dos veredas altísimas de ladrillo.
Había oscurecido de golpe; oí rápidos y casi secretos
pasos en lo alto; alcé los ojos y vi un muchacho que corría
Esta imagen fue realizada en 1976, por el prestigioso ilustrador
argentino Osavaldo Pérez D’Elías (hoy residiendo en España) para la por la estrecha y rota vereda como por una estrecha y rota
revista Temas de Petroquímica General Mosconi. pared. Recuerdo la bombacha, las alpargatas, recuerdo el
1942
pájaro y cada rama tuviera un nombre propio; Funes pro-
yectó alguna vez un idioma análogo, pero lo desechó por
parecerle demasiado general, demasiado ambiguo. En efec-
to, Funes no sólo recordaba cada hoja de cada árbol de cada
monte, sino cada una de las veces que la había percibido o
imaginado. Resolvió reducir cada una de sus jornadas preté-
ritas a unos setenta mil recuerdos, que definiría luego por
Todos, alguna vez, hemos padecido esos debates inapelables en que una dama, con acopio de
interjecciones y de anacolutos, jura que la palabra luna es más (o menos) expresiva que la palabra
moon. Fuera de la evidente observación de que el monosílabo moon es tal vez más apto para
representar un objeto muy simple que la palabra bisilábica luna, nada es posible contribuir a tales
debates; descontadas las palabras compuestas y las derivaciones, todos los idiomas del mundo (sin
excluir el volapük de Johann Martin Schleyer y la romántica interlingua de Peano) son igualmente
inexpresivos. No hay edición de la Gramática de la Real Academia que no pondere “el envidiado
tesoro de voces pintorescas, felices y expresivas de la riquísima lengua española”, pero se trata de
una mera jactancia, sin corroboración. Por lo pronto, esa misma Real Academia elabora cada tantos
años un diccionario, que define las voces del español… En el idioma universal que ideó Wilkins al
promediar el siglo XVII, cada palabra se define a sí misma. Descartes, en una epístola fechada en
noviembre de 1629, ya había anotado que mediante el sistema decimal de numeración, podemos
aprender en un solo día a nombrar todas las cantidades hasta el infinito y a escribirlas en un idioma
nuevo que es el de los guarismos1; también había propuesto la formación de un idioma análogo,
general, que organizara y abarcara todos los pensamientos humanos. John Wilkins, hacia 1664,
acometió esa empresa.
1
Teóricamente, el número de sistemas de numeración es ilimitado. El más complejo (para uso de las divinidades y
de los ángeles) registraría un número infinito de símbolos, uno para cada número entero; el más simple sólo requiere
dos. Cero se escribe 0, uno 1, dos 10, tres 11, cuatro 100, cinco 101, seis 110, siete 111, ocho 1000... Es invención de
Leibniz, a quien estimularon (parece) los hexagramas enigmáticos del I King.
198
2/3
encuadernar. (Debo este último censo a un libro impreso en Buenos Aires en 1886: el Curso de
lengua universal, del doctor Pedro Mata.)
Las palabras del idioma analítico de John Wilkins no son torpes símbolos arbitrarios; cada una de
las letras que las integran es significativa, como lo fueron las de la Sagrada Escritura para los
cabalistas. Mauthner observa que los niños podrían aprender ese idioma sin saber que es artificioso;
después en el colegio, descubrirían que es también una clave universal y una enciclopedia secreta.
He registrado las arbitrariedades de Wilkins, del desconocido (o apócrifo) enciclopedista chino y del
Instituto Bibliográfico de Bruselas; notoriamente no hay clasificación del universo que no sea
arbitraria y conjetural. La razón es muy simple: no sabemos qué cosa es el universo. “El mundo
— escribe David Hume— es tal vez el bosquejo rudimentario de algún dios infantil, que lo abandonó
a medio hacer, avergonzado de su ejecución deficiente; es obra de un dios subalterno, de quien los
dioses superiores se burlan; es la confusa producción de una divinidad decrépita y jubilada, que ya
se ha muerto” (Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, V, 1779). Cabe ir más lejos; cabe sospechar
que no hay universo en el sentido orgánico, unificador, que tiene esa ambiciosa palabra. Si lo hay,
falta conjeturar su propósito; falta conjeturar las palabras, las definiciones, las etimologías, las
sinonimias, del secreto diccionario de Dios.
La imposibilidad de penetrar el esquema divino del universo no puede, sin embargo, disuadirnos de
planear esquemas humanos, aunque nos conste que éstos son provisorios. El idioma analítico de
Wilkins no es el menos admirable de esos esquemas. Los géneros y especies que lo componen son
contradictorios y vagos; el artificio es, sin duda, ingenioso. La palabra salmón no nos dice nada;
zana, la voz correspondiente, define (para el hombre versado en las cuarenta categorías y en los
géneros de esas categorías) un pez escamoso, fluvial, de carne rojiza. (Teóricamente, no es
inconcebible un idioma donde el nombre de cada ser indicara todos los pormenores de su destino,
pasado y venidero.)
199
3/3
Esperanzas y utopías aparte, acaso lo más lúcido que sobre el lenguaje se ha escrito son estas
palabras de Chesterton: “El hombre sabe que hay en el alma tintes más desconcertantes, más
innumerables y más anónimos que los colores de una selva otoñal… cree, sin embargo, que esos
tintes, en todas sus fusiones y conversiones, son representables con precisión por un mecanismo
arbitrario de gruñidos y de chillidos. Cree que del interior de un bolsista salen realmente ruidos que
significan todos los misterios de la memoria y todas las agonías del anhelo” (G. F. Watts, 1904, pág.
88).
200
Jorge Luis Borges
Del rigore nella scienza1
Suàrez Miranda, Viaggi di uomini prudenti, libro quarto, cap. XLV, Lé-
rida, 1658.
… En aquel Imperio, el Arte de la Cartografía logró tal Perfección que el mapa de una
sola Provincia ocupaba toda una Ciudad, y el mapa del Imperio, toda una Provincia.
Con el tiempo, esos Mapas Desmesurados no satisfacieron y los Colegios de Cartógra-
fos levantaron un Mapa del Imperio, que tenía el tamaño del Imperio y coincidía pun-
tualmente con él. Menos Adictas al Estudio de la Cartografía, las Generaciones Siguien-
tes entendieron que ese dilatado Mapa era Inútil y no sin Impiedad lo entregaron a las
Inclemencias del Sol y de los Inviernos. En los desiertos del Oeste perduran despeda-
zadas Ruinas del Mapa, habitadas por Animales y Por Mendigos; en todo el País no hay
otra reliquia de las Disciplinas Geográficas.
1 [Tratto da L'artefice, Rizzoli, Milano 1963, trad. Francesco Tentori Montalto, pp. 194-195 (El hacedor,
Emercé Editores S. A., Buenos Aires 1960)].
31-05-2009
201
TRABAJO PRÁCTICO N° 2
MACROEVOLUCIÓN: DISTINTAS MIRADAS
Sobre el gradualismo, la contingencia y los calamares terrestres
INTRODUCCIÓN GENERAL
La teoría evolutiva puede ser utilizada como un “fin” en sí mismo, pero también como
un “medio”. Es un “fin”, tanto por su enorme poder explicativo como por constituir una de las
piedras fundamentales de la biología, en particular, y de la ciencia en general. Pero al mismo
tiempo, también puede ser un fascinante “medio”. ¿”Medio” para qué? “Medio” para poner en
práctica un ejercicio tan complejo como vital: realizar un análisis crítico del conocimiento
científico.
La teoría evolutiva es obviamente conocimiento. Así, como cualquier conocimiento, se
sustenta en supuestos1. Esto, por cierto, no es negativo. Más aún, es necesario2. Aquellos
supuestos que funcionan como piezas basales para la construcción de ciertos conocimientos se
llaman principios. Poder dar cuenta de ellos o no, constituye un problema que es objeto de un
debate epistemológico entre fundacionistas (quienes creen poder dar cuenta) y no fundacionistas
(quienes consideran que esto no es posible).
Por supuesto que, al tratarse de conocimiento científico, la reflexión adquiere interesantes
particularidades. La importancia de la ciencia no es algo desconocido. La ciencia no es algo
menor, ya que constituye una de las actividades distintivas (y a la vez creadora) del último gran
quiebre que se dio en la historia del hombre: la modernidad.
La particularidad principal y característica del conocimiento científico es su propio
método. Existen profundos y extensos debates al respecto, a partir de la pretensión del
positivismo de reconocer en el método que utiliza la física, al único método aceptable para definir
a la ciencia. Esta concepción, susceptible de ser analizada (y potencialmente aceptada) en
disciplinas como química o biología es sumamente controversial e inadecuada cuando se trata de
otras ciencias que parecen requerir otros métodos, tales como la sociología, la antropología, etc.
¿Dónde radica entonces la fortaleza y la garantía del conocimiento científico? La
legitimación del conocimiento científico, esta dada, no sólo por la confrontación empírica, sino
también por que ha sido consensuado en el ámbito de una comunidad científica. El juicio de los
pares, es la garantía máxima propuesta por aquellos defensores acérrimos de la objetividad
científica, el resguardo para que los supuestos establecidos como prejuicios puedan ser evitados
o, al menos, detectados y aceptados voluntariamente.
¿Cuáles son los contrargumentos frente estas posiciones en apariencia irrebatibles? Una
posible respuesta es que estos prejuicios, frecuentemente, no son del todo entendidos. En el caso
que nos ocupa, no estamos haciendo referencia a prejuicios individuales (traumas infantiles, etc.),
sino especialmente a prejuicios sociales-epocales, a aquellas características culturales generales
1
Estos, cuando no se identifican se transforman en prejuicios.
2
La falta de principios conduce, o bien a una regresión al infinito o bien, a un círculo vicioso. Cualquiera de las dos
situaciones atentan en forma directa contra la construcción de conocimiento.
202
que a su vez definen a una época. Incorporando este contexto cultural, cabe preguntarnos: ¿¡Qué
sentido tendría entonces invocar el juicio de una comunidad científica, como criterio “objetivo”,
cuando a su vez esta comunidad posee los mismos prejuicios que la sociedad en la que se
encuentra inmersa!?
Si uno considera seriamente esta observación, no son menores sus consecuencias. El
contexto cultural no sólo comprometería el marco de interpretación sino que estarían en juego
distintas miradas. Miradas. Los prejuicios nos conforman las miradas, la visión del mundo, o
peor – o mejor, dependiendo desde donde se vea-, constituyen al “mundo”mismo. Este planteo
no cuestiona la importancia del conocimiento científico, sólo se propone reconocer sus límites
identificando y reconsiderando, necesariamente, conceptos tales como “verdad”, “progreso”, etc.
“Futuro Salvaje responde a la necesidad básica de saber qué pasará en la Tierra cuando
ya no estemos aquí. La serie pretende mostrar cuál será el futuro de nuestro planeta, de
la fauna y flora que lo pueblan y, evidentemente, de la especie humana. Se trata de una
mirada a la posteridad a partir de tres posibles escenarios: dentro de 5, 100 y 200
millones de años. Tres épocas clave en las que se producirán innumerables cambios que
configurarán un mundo completamente distinto al actual. Aumentará la actividad
volcánica, el planeta se calentará y tendrá mucho vapor. Los niveles de oxígeno
aumentarán tanto que los árboles entrarán en combustión espontánea. De estas
transformaciones surgirá un mundo extraordinario poblado por extrañas criaturas y
hábitats inverosímiles. A partir de ahí, se establecerá un nuevo orden mundial en el que
las nuevas especies obtendrán la supremacía. Un escenario que, aunque parezca
ciencia-ficción, es fruto de las hipótesis y predicciones que eminentes científicos de las
teorías evolucionistas han formulado sobre el futuro de la Tierra.” Comentario extraído
de página oficial de Discovery Channel.
203
Posteriormente, se realizará un análisis colectivo de algunos de los supuestos-prejuicios
que se encuentran dicha predicción fílmica, utilizando el siguiente cuestionario como guía:
204
Figura 1. Representación esquemática de las miradas macroevolutivas discutidas en el TP. Se resumen los
principales elementos que las caracterizan y aquellos elementos que comparten.
Bajo esta mirada, llamémosla mirada A, el mundo en el que vivimos es considerado como
“el mejor de los mundos posibles” en términos de su historia evolutiva. Es decir que la diversidad
de la vida actual y sus múltiples formas y relaciones son el resultado de procesos evolutivos que
modelaron durante mucho tiempo el mejor estado posible de la biota en las condiciones
ambientales correspondientes. En cierta medida, esta mirada retoma algunos aspectos generales
de la propuesta original de Darwin y se cristaliza posteriormente de la mano de neodarwinistas
como R. Fischer, T. Dobzhansky, E. Mayr y G. Simpson.
Darwin sostenía que la materia prima de la evolución son las pequeñas diferencias
interindividuales que observamos dentro de las poblaciones. Estas variaciones se fijarían por
selección natural y serían las responsables no sólo de los patrones microevolutivos sino que,
además, producirían los patrones macroevolutivos, debido a que estos pequeños cambios se
acumularían a lo largo de millones de años originando nuevas especies, géneros, familias, etc. En
particular, bajo esta mirada se explica el origen de las especies utilizando ciertos modelos
geográficos de especiación estudiados por Ud. en el módulo correspondiente. En particular, es el
modelo de distribución alopátrica de la especie ancestral el que será inferido con mayor
frecuencia y, en menor medida, los modelos parapátrico y simpátrico.
En líneas generales y de forma característica, esta mirada macroevolutiva supone que el
tempo y el modo de la evolución son de tipo gradual (ver figura 2). El gradualismo está
205
íntimamente relacionado con la idea de evolución por selección natural. Si nuevas especies
surgen como un subproducto de la adaptación al ambiente de una especie ancestral, los cambios
deberían ser graduales, ya que un organismo con características muy diferentes a las “óptimas”
no podría tener un gran valor adaptativo (o al menos sería muy poco probable que lo tuviera), y
estos grandes cambios no pasarían a las siguientes generaciones. Por lo tanto, las huellas de
cualquier proceso de especiación estarían dadas por la existencia de formas intermedias o
transicionales entre la especie ancestral y la especie derivada. Para los gradualistas, la
observación de especies que aparecen repentinamente en el registro fósil sin ningún rastro de
formas transicionales se debe a que el mismo es incompleto. Finalmente, todos estos supuestos
aplicados al nivel macroevolutivo conllevan a una reducción de niveles, es decir, abonan la
concepción particular que los patrones y procesos a nivel macroevolutivos son el resultado
directo de los mecanismos que operan a nivel microevolutivo. La macroevolución no constituye,
en consecuencia, un nivel con características emergentes propias.
206
es concebido como el mejor mundo posible, sino como uno entre muchos otros mundos posibles.
En este sentido, esta mirada recupera muchas de las propuestas teóricas que han sido formuladas
con posterioridad a la consolidación de la síntesis evolutiva, y por lo tanto, muchas de ellas no
encuentran lugar en dicho marco teórico. Sin embargo, investigadores como Richard Lewontin
(discípulo de T. Dobzhansky), N. Eldredge y S.J. Gould, entre otros, consideran que estos
conceptos deberían ser tenidos en cuenta a la hora de expandir el neodarwinismo, con el fin de
construir un marco teórico robusto basado en una jerarquía de niveles.
Es importante comprender que bajo esta mirada no se niega que la selección natural, la
deriva y el flujo génico sean mecanismos que efectivamente han operado modelando la
variabilidad en el nivel poblacional (ver figura 1). Lo que niegan es que dichos mecanismos
hayan sido los responsables de modelar los patrones de diversidad a nivel macroevolutivo.
Existirían, en su lugar, mecanismos evolutivos con derecho propio que pueden actuar sobre
niveles superiores al de la población, como por ejemplo la simbiogénesis o la selección de
especies. Además, la diversidad de formas observadas actualmente es interpretada como un
resultado de las múltiples restricciones que operan el en proceso evolutivo tanto a nivel del
desarrollo como estructural e histórico. En consecuencia, la macroevolución se hallaría
desacoplada de la microevolución.
En líneas generales y de forma característica, esta mirada macroevolutiva supone que el
tempo y el modo de la evolución son principalmente de tipo discontinuo (ver figura 3). La teoría
de los equilibrios discontinuos (“puntuated equilibria”) fue elaborada por N. Eldredge y S.J.
Gould para explicar por qué el registro fósil no muestra transiciones evolutivas graduales. Estos
investigadores observaron que la mayor parte de los caracteres fenotípicos cambian muy poco
durante largos períodos de tiempo geológico (períodos de equilibrio o estasis), pero cuando
evolucionan, los cambios de un estado al otro ocurren relativamente rápido (períodos en los
cuales la estasis es interrumpida o “puntuada” – “puntuated” en inglés – por el cambio). Bajo este
modelo, el registro fósil refleja un patrón real: las especies aparecen repentinamente, persisten
por ciertos períodos de tiempo y luego se extinguen, dejando escasos signos de formas
intermedias entre el ancestro y el descendiente. En este sentido, un modelo de especiación de tipo
peripátrico podría explicar la rápida aparición de nuevas especies y los cambios aparentemente
direccionales dentro de un clado (las llamadas “tendencias evolutivas”), serían el producto de
fenómenos de especiación y extinción diferencial y no el resultado de la selección natural.
207
2.2. Objetivos:
• Analizar los supuestos que subyacen a las diferentes concepciones macroevolutivas.
• Comprender la complejidad que reviste el análisis de los patrones biológicos y la
reconstrucción de los mecanismos evolutivos subyacentes.
• Reconocer los principales elementos relacionados con la controversia entre equilibrios
discontinuos vs. gradualismo.
4
Este punto no es menor. La idea es que el individuo realice un análisis crítico y potencie su inventiva, por lo que el
trabajo con organismos ya conocidos podrían dificultar a estos en la medida en que se enfrenten con el conocimiento
previo.
208
Bibliografía recomendada para profundizar los temas del módulo:
• S.J. Gould. 1994. El Pulgar del Panda. Cap.17. Ed.Crítica. Barcelona. Aquí se exponen
brevemente las razones históricas que llevaron a considerar la aparición de nuevas especies como una lenta
transformación gradual, sólo documentada en parte en el registro fósil. En contrapartida, se explica el
surgimiento de un modelo alternativo, el de los equilibrios discontinuos, en donde la especiación es la
responsable de prácticamente la totalidad del cambio evolutivo. Esta transcurre por breves períodos de
explosión y largos períodos estáticos tal como el registro fósil parece indicar. El papel de la selección
natural queda, en este caso, relegado, mientras que el azar y los procesos estocásticos cobran
preponderancia.
• Foucault, Michel. Las palabras y las cosas. Pp: 5-10. Comentario por parte del filósofo
francés al pequeño fragmento del cuento de Borges que presenta a través de “cierta Enciclopedia china” los
límites de los esquemas de clasificación y la preconformación de la mirada del hombre. Posteriormente,
Michel Foucault presenta el programa que continuará en su ensayo del análisis de la génesis, características
y límites de nuestra “mirada” como hombres occidentales y modernos.
209
MÓDULO IX
EVOLUCIÓN
HUMANA
210
211
TRABAJOS PRÁCTICOS DE EVOLUCIÓN HUMANA
Ignacio Soto, Ana Liza Tropea & Fernando Ventrice
INTRODUCCIÓN GENERAL
El surgimiento de los homínidos puede ser analizado en el marco de los mecanismos
evolutivos aprendidos y discutidos durante la materia. Muchos aspectos de la evolución del linaje
humano pueden considerarse dentro del marco comprendido por la selección natural ya que todas
las especies, (los homínidos no son excepción) son inherentemente variables y esa variabilidad
afecta la capacidad de los individuos de sobrevivir y reproducirse. Por otro lado, los recursos son
limitados y por lo tanto, existe una competencia entre los individuos por los mismos que resulta en
la supervivencia y reproducción diferencial. Sin embargo, existen otros factores que pueden afectar
la supervivencia y perpetuación de los seres vivos y además, existen otros niveles en los que puede
ocurrir la evolución biológica. Algunos de estos factores constituyen el aspecto contingente de la
evolución. Por ejemplo, cambios climáticos y geológicos a gran escala pueden llevar a la extinción
de poblaciones o especies enteras o crear condiciones competitivas enteramente diferentes. Por otro
lado, el carácter de los cambios evolutivos ocurridos previamente en la historia de un linaje puede
influenciar o limitar el potencial de cambio de la especie. Este factor se conoce como la restricción
filogenética del proceso evolutivo.
A la hora de analizar la evolución humana hay que considerar otro elemento: la
potencialidad evolutiva adquirida con el desarrollo de un cerebro con capacidades no expresadas
previamente por otro organismo en la historia del planeta. Este evento trajo aparejado el
surgimiento de una evolución cultural sin antecedentes, un nuevo nivel evolutivo muy ligado al
desarrollo del lenguaje articulado. Como los mecanismos darwinianos clásicos no son enteramente
aplicables a éste nivel cultural, la cultura humana no puede ser analizada solamente desde la
perspectiva biológica, por regirse por leyes propias, intrínsecamente distintas y cuya complejidad es
irreducible a un plano biológico puro. Podemos pensar a la evolución cultural como un sistema de
cambio más de tipo “lamarckiano” en donde todo lo aprendido en una generación puede ser
transmitido directamente a la siguiente generación por medio de la enseñanza y de la escritura. Los
caracteres adquiridos son transmitidos en la tecnología y la cultura. La evolución lamarckiana es
rápida y acumulativa, es por eso que en tiempos tan pequeños – despreciables para los tiempos
geológicos – nuestra tecnología nos permitió modificar nuestro entorno de manera drástica. La
evolución biológica continúa en Homo sapiens pero lo hace a un ritmo nuevo, al compás de
cambios impuestos (ahora además) por la cultura.
Muchas características que presenta Homo sapiens lo diferencian inclusive de las especies
de primates más cercanas. La naturaleza de estos caracteres puede ser cuantitativa o cualitativa y
abarcan varios niveles de complejidad: desde las diferencias genómicas, pasando por los patrones
de desarrollo hasta llegar al comportamiento, las estrategias reproductivas, la estructura social, el
manejo de la información y la relación de la especie con el resto de la biota. Entender como se
produjeron esos cambios, como influyó el ambiente y cuales fueron las bases genéticas, de
desarrollo o cognitivas que lo permitieron son preguntas fundamentales a responder por la ciencia.
Disciplinas tan disímiles como la genómica comparada, la paleontología y la antropología social
buscan responder partes de este dilema. El desafío último consiste en la conciliación de toda la
información en una explicación completa de la evolución de nuestra especie.
A través de los trabajos prácticos del módulo de Evolución Humana se propone organizar la
discusión alrededor de tres aspectos fundamentales de la evolución de nuestro linaje.
A- ¿Qué nos diferencia de otros primates? El orden Primate incluye una gran diversidad de
familias y especies (Fig. 1). Durante el primer TP se abordará el estudio de ciertos aspectos
característicos de otras especies de primates que constituyen el grupo al cual pertenecemos:
los monos antropoideos. Asimismo, se estudiará la base biológica de nuestro parentesco con
212
los chimpancés, especie viviente más cercanamente emparentada con Homo sapiens. Este
Se propone reflexionar sobre las características que han surgido en ambos linajes luego de la
divergencia.
B- Registro fósil de los homínidos. Recientemente denominados homíninos, este grupo de
primates fósiles bípedos que constituyen nuestro linaje se conoce a través de un nutrido
registro fósil. En el segundo TP de este bloque se propone analizar el patrón que presenta
dicho registro y discutir diferentes interpretaciones posibles. Se hará hincapié en el estudio
de aquellos caracteres que evolucionaron a lo largo del linaje y las particularidades de los
distintos grupos de homíninos, con el objetivo de inferir los procesos evolutivos subyacentes
a dicho patrón.
C- Evolución de Homo sapiens modernos. En el último TP del bloque, se propone estudiar las
evidencias disponibles en la actualidad sobre cuándo y cómo surgen los humanos
anatómicamente modernos, las características anatómicas que permiten reconocerlos, y los
procesos evolutivos que habrían operado modelando dichos rasgos. Se estudiarán en
particular los modelos que existen para explicar el surgimiento del género Homo y de
nuestra especie, analizando las evidencias en las que se basan, las predicciones que elaboran
y, su nivel de correlato con la evidencia de distribución geográfica y temporal.
Figura 1: Árbol filogenético que muestra relaciones de parentesco probables entre distintos grupos de
primates, entre ellos, nuestra especie.
213
SEMINARIO I
ORDEN PRIMATES:
NUESTROS PARIENTES CERCANOS
Por Nicolás Frankel, Ignacio M. Soto & Ana Liza Tropea
Durante este TP se propone reflexionar sobre la base biológica de nuestro parentesco con el
resto de las especies del Orden Primate. Se abordará el estudio de ciertos aspectos característicos
del grupo de especies de primates más cercanamente emparentadas con el humano y que
constituyen el grupo al cual pertenecemos: los monos antropoideos.
Se analizarán luego las características que han surgido en los linajes de chimpancés y
humanos actuales luego de la divergencia desde su ancestro común. Este estudio se abordará a
distintos niveles. En primer lugar, a nivel morfológico a través de los extractos de Fleagle (1999);
en segundo lugar y a nivel molecular, se estudiará la expresión proteica diferencial utilizando parte
del trabajo pionero de King y Wilson (1975); en tercer lugar, la expresión diferencial será estudiada
a partir de los patrones de mRNA evidenciados en el trabajo de Enard et al. (2002). Por último, las
diferencias a nivel de la secuencia misma de ADN serán abordadas con el paper de Clark (2003).
Lea atentamente los siguientes artículos y responda las preguntas que se detallan a continuación:
1. Fleagle, J.G. 1999. Extractos del capítulo 7: “Apes and Humans” en Primate Adaptation and
Evolution. 2da. Ed. Elsevier.
1.1. ¿Cuántas especies de simios africanos viven en la actualidad? Explique el modelo evolutivo
propuesto para este grupo a partir de la figura 7.13.
1.2. ¿Cuáles son las principales similitudes y diferencias entre las especies de hominoideos?
1.3. ¿Por qué considera que resulta dificultoso recuperar una filogenia robusta del grupo de los
monos antropoideos? ¿Qué significa “evolución en mosaico”?
2. King & Wilson. 1975. Evolution at two levels in humans and chimpanzees. Science 188:107-116.
Responda las siguientes preguntas según el contenido de la primera página del artículo (pág. 107):
2.1. En su artículo, King y Wilson mencionan que entre humanos y chimpancés hay diferencias
anatómicas, fisiológicas y comportamentales. ¿Podría especificar algunas diferencias entre
humanos y chimpancés que caen dentro de las categorías de King y Wilson? ¿Estas diferencias
corresponden a cambios ocurridos en el linaje de los humanos o de los chimpancés?
2.2. ¿Cuál es la conclusión general de este fragmento? Preste atención al título del trabajo:
¿Cuáles son los dos niveles de los que se habla?
214
3. Enard, W. et al. 2002. Intra- and interspecific variation in primate gene expression patterns.
Science 296: 340-343.
Para una mejor comprensión del artículo de Enard, W. et al. se incluye una breve
descripción sobre la construcción y uso de los microarreglos. Esta herramienta es adecuada para
encarar estudios a nivel sistémico y es utilizada actualmente para estudiar interrogantes evolutivos.
Los microarreglos
En los últimos años se han secuenciado numerosos genomas completos y se han generado
grandes bases de datos de secuencias transcriptas (cDNAs). Esta valiosa información ha permitido
desarrollar la tecnología de microarray chips.
El microarray de DNA es un vidrio con secuencias de DNA ordenadas en muy poco espacio
físico. Está divido en miles de cuadrados que albergan fragmentos de DNA de secuencia conocida.
Los microarrays de cDNA se fabrican amplificando por PCR fragmentos de 600 a 2400 pares de
bases a partir de clones de libraries de cDNA1. Luego, estos fragmentos doble cadena son
inmovilizados en el vidrio. Los microarrays de oligonucleótidos se fabrican sintetizando in situ
oligonucleótidos de DNA simple cadena de 25 bases o inmovilizando oligonucleótidos de ~70
bases que fueron sintetizados previamente. A diferencia de los microarrays de cDNA, no es
necesario contar con clones de cDNA a partir de los cuales se hace la PCR, simplemente se necesita
tener datos de la secuencia de los genes que se quiere ubicar en el microarray. A partir de esta
secuencia se diseñan los oligonucleótidos a ubicar en el vidrio.
Uno de los usos de los microarrays es el análisis de expresión de genes. La gran cantidad de
genes representados en el arreglo, nos permite hacer estudios a gran escala. La metodología consiste
en extraer RNA en dos condiciones determinadas (o de dos especies distintas) y transformarlo a
cDNA. Al transformar el RNA en cDNA, a este último se le acopla un fluoróforo 2 diferente para
cada una de las dos condiciones. Luego, se juntan en el mismo tubo los cDNAs de las dos
condiciones y se hibridan en el mismo microarray (ver Figura 1) También está la posibilidad de
hibridar los mRNAs de cada condición en un microarray distinto. Luego de lavar el microarray con
alta rigurosidad (para asegurar un pegado específico del cDNA marcado al DNA inmovilizado en el
chip), con un láser se cuantifican las intensidades de los dos fluoróforos para cada gen. Esto nos
indicará cuantitativamente las diferencias en los niveles de expresión de un gen en dos
condiciones o especies distintas.
Los chips son fabricados por empresas (http://www.affymetrix.com;
http://www.appliedbiosystems.com; http://www.agilent.com) o son desarrollados por laboratorios
en universidades o institutos (http://www.microarray.org http://bti.cornell.edu/CGEP/CGEP.html).
1
Una library de cDNA es una colección de secuencias clonadas en plásmido u otro tipo de vector. El cDNA clonado en
el vector se obtuvo a partir de la retrotranscripción del mRNA de un tejido determinado.
2
Un fluoróforo es una molécula que emite fluorescencia en una determinada longitud de onda al ser excitada por luz.
215
sample 1 sample 2
Fluorophore quantification
Links de interés:
• http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/About/primer/microarrays.html
Recuerda las bases moleculares sobre las que se construyeron y pensaron los microarrays.
• http://www.bio.davidson.edu/courses/genomics/chip/chip.html
Una animación que permite ver claramente cómo se hace un experimento con microarrays.
3.1. ¿Por qué cree que se tomaron tres humanos y tres chimpancés para hacer este trabajo?
¿Cuáles son los riesgos de tomar sólo un individuo de orangután?
3.2. a) Los autores no mencionan en ninguna parte del artículo la edad exacta de los primates de
los cuales se obtienen las muestras. Comente los problemas de comparar la expresión de genes
en dos especies con distinta ontogenia y largo de vida.
b) En el trabajo de Enard et al. (2002) se usan muestras de cerebro provenientes únicamente
de primates machos. En un trabajo posterior que tiene similares objetivos al de Enard et al.
(Cáceres et al., 2003) se usan muestras de cerebro de humano y chimpancé de ambos sexos.
¿Cuál de las dos posibilidades le parece la más adecuada?
3.3. Figuras 1 y 2: ¿Qué indican los números sobre las ramas de los árboles? ¿Por qué comparan
los autores la expresión en distintos tejidos? ¿Qué conclusión sacan los autores de los
árboles?
3.4. ¿Para qué cree que se utiliza un grupo externo (orangután o macaco) para analizar
diferencias de expresión entre humano y chimpancé?
3.5. Con un microarray o cualquier otra técnica que mida expresión se pueden detectar
diferencias en los niveles de mRNA entre dos especies. Si el gen X muestra niveles de
mRNA distintos comparando cerebro de chimpancé y humano ¿En qué parte(s) del gen X es
factible que se encuentren diferencias entre las dos especies? ¿Se le ocurre otra hipótesis
para explicar las diferencias en los niveles de mRNA?
216
3.6. Analice la tabla 1 ¿Qué puede concluir de estos datos?
3.7. En el ya mencionado trabajo de Cáceres et al. (ver pregunta 2), se concluye que de los
genes que muestran distintos niveles de expresión en cerebro entre chimpancé y humano, el
80% presenta niveles más altos en humanos. Si se hace el mismo análisis para corazón e
hígado, se ve que de los genes que muestran distintos niveles de expresión, hay
aproximadamente un 50% que tiene mayor expresión en chimpancé y lógicamente el otro 50
% se encuentra “sobreexpresado” en humano. Entre los genes que se encuentran
“sobreexpresados” en cerebro humano comparado con chimpancé hay muchos que se
agrupan en las siguientes categorías funcionales: 1) mantenimiento y crecimiento celular, 2)
metabolismo de RNA y lípidos y 3) chaperonas.
¿Puede generar alguna hipótesis evolutiva con estos datos?
4. Clark, A.G. 2003. Inferring Nonneutral Evolution from Human-Chimp-Mouse Orthologous Gene
Trios. Science 302:1960-1963.
4.1. Para una investigación completa sobre la evolución humana a nivel genético no alcanza con conocer
y mapear las diferencias genómicas entre nuestra especie y el resto de las especies de primates. ¿Qué
otra información se necesita?
4.2. ¿Por qué los autores incluyen secuencias de ratón en el análisis? ¿Por qué se trabaja con genes
ortólogos? ¿Cómo se comprueba la relación de ortología entre genes?
4.3. Comente los análisis realizados para poner a prueba la existencia de selección sobre los genes.
4.4. Comente los resultados en relación con las funciones de los genes analizados y los caracteres
involucrados.
4.5. ¿Qué otros análisis completarían los resultados presentados en este trabajo?
4.6. En base a todo lo comentado en el TP, discuta si se puede considerar a los chimpancés como una
especie con caracteres plesiomórficos con respecto a Homo sapiens.
217
Evolution. 2da. Ed. Elsevier.
218
Evolution. 2da. Ed. Elsevier.
219
Evolution. 2da. Ed. Elsevier.
220
Evolution. 2da. Ed. Elsevier.
221
Evolution. 2da. Ed. Elsevier.
222
Fleagle, J.G. 1999. Extractos del capítulo 7: “Apes and Humans” en Primate Adaptation and
Evolution. 2da. Ed. Elsevier.
223
11 April 1975, Volume 188, Number 4184
Variation in Primate Gene corresponding value was less than 12%. Be-
cause experimental variation between the tis-
Expression Patterns
sue samples from the same individual was
small, the averages of the pairwise distances
measured between the duplicates for each
Wolfgang Enard,1* Philipp Khaitovich,1* Joachim Klose,2 tissue sample were used to estimate a tree
Sebastian Zöllner,1 Florian Heissig,1 Patrick Giavalisco,3 depicting the overall differences in gene ex-
Kay Nieselt-Struwe,4 Elaine Muchmore,5,6 Ajit Varki,5 pression measured between individuals. The
Rivka Ravid,7 Gaby M. Doxiadis,8 Ronald E. Bontrop,8 results (Fig. 1A) show that the variation in
gene expression between individuals within
Svante Pääbo1† the species is substantial, relative to the dif-
ferences between humans and chimpanzee.
Although humans and their closest evolutionary relatives, the chimpanzees, are For example, one human brain sample differs
98.7% identical in their genomic DNA sequences, they differ in many mor- more from the other human samples than the
phological, behavioral, and cognitive aspects. The underlying genetic basis of latter differ from the chimpanzee samples.
many of these differences may be altered gene expression. We have compared However, for both the brain and liver sam-
the transcriptome in blood leukocytes, liver, and brain of humans, chimpanzees, ples, the humans, as well as the chimpanzees,
orangutans, and macaques using microarrays, as well as protein expression fall into two mutually exclusive groups when
patterns of humans and chimpanzees using two-dimensional gel electrophore- their gene expression patterns are related to
sis. We also studied three mouse species that are approximately as related to that seen in the orangutan, which is evolu-
each other as are humans, chimpanzees, and orangutans. We identified species- tionarily further removed from humans and
specific gene expression patterns indicating that changes in protein and gene chimpanzees than these are from each other.
expression have been particularly pronounced in the human brain. When statistically tested by a bootstrap ap-
proach, this observation is supported in both
Striking differences in morphology and cog- rhesus macaques (Macaca mulatta). For liver and brain (7 ). Thus, a number of gene
nitive abilities exist between humans and comparative purposes, we performed similar expression differences between humans and
their closest evolutionary relatives, the chim- studies in rodent species that have diverged chimpanzees are shared among all individu-
panzees. At least some of these differences from each other approximately as much as als analyzed from each species. The amount
can be assumed to form the basis for the humans and the great apes. of gene expression differences shared among
complex and rapid cultural evolution and de- First, we compared mRNA levels in brain all humans is larger than those shared among
mographic explosions that have characterized and liver of humans, chimpanzees, and a all chimpanzees. One likely factor contribut-
recent human evolution (1). In addition, hu- orangutan using Affymetrix U95A arrays (5), ing to this is that oligonucleotides comple-
mans and chimpanzees differ in several other which contain oligonucleotides that examine mentary to human cDNAs are used to assay
traits that are of medical interest, such as approximately 12,000 human genes. From RNA levels not only in humans but also in
susceptibility to AIDS, epithelial neoplasms, the brain, gray matter from the left prefrontal chimpanzees and orangutans. Thus, nucleo-
malaria, and Alzheimer’s disease (2, 3). Al- lobe (Brodmann area 9) was removed at au- tide sequence differences between the last-
though it was pointed out 25 years ago (4) topsies from three adult male humans, three named species and humans can be expected
that many of these differences may be due to adult male chimpanzees, and one adult male to reduce the apparent expression levels mea-
quantitative differences in gene expression orangutan. For brain and liver, two indepen- sured in the apes. Such differences will be
rather than structural changes in gene prod- dent isolations of RNA from adjacent tissue assigned to the human lineage. However, the
ucts, nothing is known about how gene ex- samples were performed for each individual apparent acceleration on the human lineage is
pression profiles differ between humans and and analyzed independently (5). larger in the brain (3.8-fold) than in the liver
chimpanzees. In order to take a first step All possible pairwise comparisons among (1.7-fold), raising the possibility that gene
toward understanding the evolution of the the six human, six chimpanzee, and two or- expression patterns may have changed more
mammalian transcriptome and proteome, we angutan samples were made for each tissue, in the brain than in the liver during recent
studied mRNA expression levels, as well as and the differences in apparent expression human evolution.
protein expression patterns, in different tis- levels were used to calculate an overall dis- To investigate the latter possibility, we
sues of humans, chimpanzees (Pan troglo- tance summarized over all genes (6). For the performed a second set of experiments using
dytes), orangutans (Pongo pygmaeus), and brain samples, the distances measured among membrane-based cDNA arrays carrying
1
Max-Planck-Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology, Table 1. Brain protein pattern differences between humans and chimpanzees as analyzed by 2D gel
Inselstrasse 22, D-04103 Leipzig, Germany. 2Institut electrophoresis (16). Differences between humans and chimpanzees were scored if confirmed in three
fuer Humangenetik Charité, D-13353 Berlin, Germa- individual human-chimpanzee pairs and were analyzed in the same way as in a larger mouse study
ny. 3Max-Planck-Institute for Molecular Genetics, comparing M. musculus and M. spretus (23). Qualitative differences represent changes in electrophoretic
D-14195 Berlin, Germany. 4Max-Planck-Institute of mobility of spots, which likely result from amino acid substitutions, whereas quantitative differences
Biophysical Chemistry, D-37077 Göttingen, Germany. reflect changes in the amount of protein.
5
University of California San Diego, La Jolla, CA
92093, USA. 6VA Medical Center, San Diego, La Jolla,
Differences
CA 92093, USA. 7The Netherlands Brain Bank, Am-
sterdam, the Netherlands. 8Biomedical Primate Re- Comparison Analyzed spots
search Centre, Rijswijk, the Netherlands. Qualitative Quantitative
*These authors contributed equally to this work. Human– chimpanzee 538 41 (7.6%) 169 (31.4%)
†To whom correspondence should be addressed. E- M. musculus–M. spretus 8767 668 (7.6%) 656 (7.5%)
mail: paabo@eva.mpg.de
225
340 12 APRIL 2002 VOL 296 SCIENCE www.sciencemag.org
REPORTS
21,504 DNA sequences of an average length humans. This is due to a 5.5-fold acceleration frontal cortex. As in the primates, the gene
of ⬃1,000 bp, amplified from 17,997 human of the rate of change in gene expression expression patterns within species show great
genes of the Unigene set (8). When such long levels on the lineage leading to humans. variation (Fig. 1B), as recently reported even
target sequences are used, the average nucle- Thus, the results show that the rate of evolu- for inbred mice (15). However, when the
otide sequence difference of around 0.8% tionary change of gene expression levels in more distantly related M. caroli is taken into
between human and chimpanzee cDNAs (9) the brain is accelerated in the human evolu- account, it is clear that all M. musculus and
is not expected to influence the results signif- tionary lineage relative to the chimpanzee, M. spretus individuals share gene expression
icantly. For these experiments, brain neocor- whereas no such acceleration is evident in patterns that separate them from the other
tex samples from the autopsies of seven hu- liver or blood. It should be noted, however, species, as is the case for humans and chim-
mans, four chimpanzees and two macaques that the extent of the acceleration is highly panzees. When these species-specific differ-
were used, as well as liver samples from six dependent on the metric used. ences are compared, it is found that the
humans, five chimpanzees, and four ma- To gauge whether the observations made change on the line to M. musculus is 2.1-fold
caques. In addition, blood samples were col- among the primate species are typical of and 2.3-fold that in brain and liver, respec-
lected from 10 humans, 10 chimpanzees, and mammals, we investigated the three mouse tively. Thus, as in the case of the primate
10 rhesus macaques. To allow the same filter species, Mus spretus, M. caroli, and M. mus- analyses, the species for which the oligonu-
arrays to be used throughout the experiments, culus, among which the former two species cleotide array was designed shows an appar-
equal amounts of RNA from a given species differ from M. musculus at silent sites, i.e., at ent acceleration, which is likely to be due to
and tissue were pooled, labeled, and hybrid- sites that do not change the encoded amino nucleotide sequence differences between the
ized to the cDNA arrays (10). acids, by approximately 2.5% and 4.5%, re- species analyzed. However, in the rodents,
The relative rates of evolutionary change spectively (12). Thus, their extent of diver- this acceleration is of similar magnitude in
in the transcriptomes of the three tissues were gence from M. musculus is in the same order brain and liver, and as expected from the
estimated (11), using the macaque as an out- of magnitude as that of chimpanzees (1.08%) slightly higher genomic divergence, it is
group (Fig. 2). For both blood leukocytes and and orangutans (2.98%), respectively, from slightly higher than that seen in primate liver.
liver, the human expression patterns are more humans (13, 14 ). Affymetrix arrays carrying Thus, these results show that gene expression
similar to those of the chimpanzees than to oligonucleotides specific for 12,000 M. mus- differences are substantial between closely
those of the macaques, reflecting the evolu- culus genes (5) were used to analyze samples related mammalian species and supports the
tionary relationships of the species. Further- from the frontal part of the brains and livers notion that changes in gene expression levels
more, the extent of change on the lineages from three individuals of M. musculus, three in the brain may have been especially pro-
leading to the chimpanzees and the humans individuals of M. spretus, and one individual
are equal in leukocytes and 1.3-fold different of M. caroli. To make the experiments as
in liver. In stark contrast, the expression pat- comparable as possible to the analysis of the
tern in the chimpanzee brain cortex is more humans and apes, outbred mice were used,
similar to that of the macaques than to that of and only gray matter was sampled from the
Fig. 3. Two-dimensional gel electrophoresis of proteins from the cyto- changes. For each type of variation, a few examples are indicated. From
solic fraction of human (A) and chimpanzee (B) cortex frontalis. From the identification by mass spectrometry in both humans and chimpanzees,
total pattern, comprising about 8500 protein spots, a representative these proteins spots are 1, aldose reductase (gi576365); 4, carbonic
section consisting of about 200 spots is shown. Protein patterns from dehydratase (gi4502517); 5, electron transfer flavoprotein
human and chimpanzee were compared, and changes between homolo- (gi2781202); 6, hypothetical protein DKFZp564D1378 (gi14149777);
gous spots found in all three human-chimpanzee pairs were scored. Three 10, ␦-aminolevulinate dehydratase (gi2118316); 11, CGI-105 protein
different types of variations were registered: (i) variations in electro- (gi11431155); 13, hypothetical protein XP_047816 (gi14743583); 14,
phoretic mobility of spots (7), most likely due to mutations affecting malate dehydrogenase 2 (gi5174541); 15, MAWD-binding protein
the structure of proteins (e.g., amino acid substitutions); (ii) variations in (gi16307296); 16, uncharacterized hypothalamus protein HCDASE
spot intensity (1 or 2) reflecting alterations in protein amount, possibly (gi8923864); 30, purine nucleoside phosphorylase (gi4557801); 31,
due to mutations in regulatory genes; and (iii) presence or absence purine nucleoside phosphorylase (gi4557801); and 35, aldehyde reduc-
variations (⫹ or ⫺), which may also result from quantitative tase (gi1633300).
nounced during recent human evolution. For the two rodents, the relative amounts of References and Notes
Differences in mRNA levels do not nec- quantitative protein differences are similar 1. G. Klein, The Human Career: Human Biological and
essarily translate into differences in protein to the qualitative differences. In contrast, Cultural Origins ( The Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago,
1989).
levels. Therefore, we investigated whether quantitative differences are approximately 2. P. Gagneux, A. Varki, Mol. Phylogenet. Evol. 18, 2
quantitative changes not only in RNA lev- 6 times as common as qualitative differenc- (2001).
els but also in protein levels are especially es when chimpanzee and human brains are 3. A. Varki, Genome Res. 10, 1065 (2000).
4. M. C. King, A. C. Wilson, Science 188, 107 (1975).
pronounced in the brain during recent hu- compared. Thus, the human brain has prob- 5. All apes used in this study died of natural causes. In
man evolution. We studied protein patterns ably experienced more evolutionary chang- all cases, postmortem times were shorter than 6
in the brains of humans and chimpanzees, es in gene expression both at the mRNA hours, and only minimal RNA degradation was seen
by agarose electrophoresis. Preparation of the sam-
as well as in M. musculus and M. spretus to and protein levels than the two mouse spe- ples for the Affymetrix arrays, hybridization, and
put the primate differences into perspective cies. In this regard, a recent comparison of scanning were performed as described (18). Nine of
(16 ). In each case, the tissue samples were human and great ape blood plasma proteins 10 genes that differed at least twofold between
human and chimpanzee brains could be verified by a
removed from sites adjacent to the ones (17 ) found only one human-specific differ- Northern analysis. Details of experimental proce-
used in the first set of mRNA analyses from ence. This is in contrast to the many differ- dures are available on Science Online at www.
the same individuals. Soluble proteins were ences found here for soluble brain proteins sciencemag.org/cgi/content/full/296/5566/340/DC1
isolated by differential centrifugation, sep- and supports a more rapid rate of evolution and on http://email.eva.mpg.de/⬃khaitovi/
supplement1.html.
arated on two-dimensional (2D) polyacryl- of protein expression levels in the brain. 6. Affymetrix array results were carried out with Mi-
amide gels, and visualized by silver stain- Our results show that that large numbers croarray Suite, version 4.0 (Affymetrix) by using de-
ing (Fig. 3). Two types of differences were of quantitative changes in gene expression fault settings. All arrays were normalized to the same
target intensity using all probe sets. The difference in
scored: (i) shifts in the migration positions can be detected between closely related mam- scaling factor was less than threefold among all
of proteins, which represent a shift in size mals. They furthermore suggest that such arrays. In order to build distance trees, pairwise dis-
or charge of the protein, i.e., covalent dif- changes have been particularly pronounced tances between samples were calculated as the sum
of the base-two logarithms of the absolute values of
ference that in most cases are changes in during recent evolution of the human brain. the “fold change” for all 12,000 genes represented on
amino acid sequence; (ii) differences in The underlying reasons for such expression a chip. When “absent calls” were assigned to both
quantity of proteins without a shift in mi- differences are likely to be manifold, for ex- samples in a comparison, and when the difference
call for the gene was “no change,” the fold change
gration position which represent differenc- ample, duplications and deletions of genes, value was set to zero. The resulting distance matrix
es in amounts of protein expressed in the promotor changes, changes in levels of tran- was used to build neighbor joining trees (19) as
tissue. The relative amounts of qualitative scription factors, and changes in cellular implemented in the PHYLIP package (20). The full
data set is available at http://email.eva.mpg.de/
protein differences observed between hu- composition of tissues. A challenge for the ⬃khaitovi/supplement1.html
mans and chimpanzees and between M. future is to investigate the relative contribu- 7. The reliability of the distance trees branching pattern
musculus and M. spretus, respectively, are tions of these factors to the expression differ- was estimated by 1000 bootstrap samples of the
similar ( Table 1), as expected from the ences observed. A further challenge is to 12,000 genes. The bootstrap values for the species
were ⬎99.9% in all cases except for the chimpanzee
similar extent of genomic DNA sequence clarify how many of the differences have brain branch, where in the remaining 16% of cases,
differences between the two species pairs. functional consequences. the orangutan fell among the chimpanzees. There
227
342 12 APRIL 2002 VOL 296 SCIENCE www.sciencemag.org
REPORTS
was 100% bootstrap support for the separation of tingen, and K. Krohn and Petra Süptitz from the Inter- ulating discussions. We also thank the Bundesministe-
the mouse species in both tissues. disziplinäres Zentrum für Klinische Forschung (IZKF), rium für Bildung und Forschung, the Saxonium Ministry
8. M. S. Boguski, G. D. Schuler, Nature Genet. 10, 369 Leipzig, for the help with microarray experiments; T. for Science, and the Max Planck Gesellschaft for financial
(1995). Kitano for analyzing the mouse divergence; D. Kuhl for support.
9. I. Hellmann, unpublished data. initial advice in the project; and many people at Max
10. All RNA pools were hybridized 4 to 6 times to the Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology for stim- 14 December 2001; accepted 27 February 2002
same set of filters in order to estimate interexperi-
mental errors and to minimize their effects
through the combined analysis of several experi-
ments. Signals that were at least 5 times above
background and not influenced to more than 25%
by neighboring spots were further analyzed. A gene
A MADS-Box Gene Necessary
was regarded as differently expressed if it fulfilled
two criteria: (i) The difference in signal between
two species was at least two-fold; and (ii) the
for Fruit Ripening at the
signal between the two species was significantly
different as determined by a paired t test. Sixteen
differently expressed genes were analyzed by
Tomato Ripening-Inhibitor (Rin)
Northern blots, and 1 out of 12 that were detected
by the Northern analyses yielded results contra-
dictory to the arrays, whereas the remaining 11
Locus
showed expression patterns that were both quali-
tatively and quantitatively similar in all three spe-
Julia Vrebalov,1,2 Diane Ruezinsky,2
cies to that detected by the arrays. Details of Veeraragavan Padmanabhan,2 Ruth White,1,2 Diana Medrano,1,2
experimental procedures are available on Science
Online at www.sciencemag.org/cgi/content/full/
Rachel Drake,3 Wolfgang Schuch,3 Jim Giovannoni1*
296/5566/340/DC1and on http://email.eva.
mpg.de/⬃khaitovi/supplement1.html.
11. The distance between two expression profiles of two Tomato plants harboring the ripening-inhibitor (rin) mutation yield fruits that fail
species in a given tissue was determined by summing to ripen. Additionally, rin plants display enlarged sepals and loss of inflorescence
up the absolute ratios of the included genes given by determinacy. Positional cloning of the rin locus revealed two tandem MADS-box
Although the human genome project will al- gence caused by random drift and divergence 1
Molecular Biology and Genetics, 2Biological Statistics
low us to compare our genome to that of driven by natural selection. Early observa- and Computational Biology, Cornell University, Ithaca,
NY 14853, USA. 3Applied Biosystems, 45 West Gude
other primates and discover features that are tions of unexpectedly low levels of protein Drive, Rockville, MD 20850, USA. 4Protein Informatics,
uniquely human, there is no guarantee that divergence between humans and chimpan- Celera Genomics, 850 Lincoln Centre Drive, Foster City,
such features are responsible for any of our zees led to the hypothesis that most of the CA 94404, USA. 5Celera Genomics, 45 West Gude Drive,
unique biological attributes. To identify evolutionary changes must have occurred at Rockville, MD 20850, USA. 6Celera Diagnostics, 1401
Harbor Bay Parkway, Alameda, CA 94502, USA.
genes and biological processes that have been the level of gene regulation (1). Recently,
most altered by our recent evolutionary di- much more extensive efforts at DNA se- *Present address: Department of Genetics, Case
Western Reserve University, 10900 Euclid Avenue,
vergence from other primates, we need to fit quencing in nonhuman primates has con- Cleveland, OH 44106, USA.
the data to models of sequence divergence firmed the very close evolutionary relation- †To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-
that allow us to distinguish between diver- ship between humans and chimps (2), with an mail: michele_cargill@celeradiagnostics.com
229
1960 12 DECEMBER 2003 VOL 302 SCIENCE www.sciencemag.org
REPORTS
other public sets and found to be highly the ML estimation procedure corrects for varia- Panther classification system (6, 22). We asked,
consistent (11) (table S1). We used the most tion in base composition; however, if the true for the subset of genes in each functional cate-
conservative set of 7645 genes for which we substitution rate differs across the genome in a gory, whether the distribution of P2 values for
had the highest confidence in orthology and manner that is correlated with GC content, then those genes differed significantly from the P2
sequence annotation (12) (Database S1). we should be able to detect this by simple cor- distribution for the full set of 7645 genes (6)
To identify genes that have undergone relation (6, 12) (Database S2). The synonymous (tables S2 and S3). In this way, we can gain
adaptive protein evolution, we applied two substitution rate was significantly correlated insight into higher-order biological processes
formal statistical tests that fit models of mo- with the following attributes: GC content (0.164, and molecular functions that may be under se-
lecular evolution at the codon level. Both P ⬍ 0.0001), local recombination rate in cM/Mb lective pressure in a given lineage (Tables 1 and
tests fit models of the nucleotide-substitution (21) (0.100, P ⬍ 0.001), and LINE (long inter- 2). The statistical tests of significance are valid
process by maximum likelihood (ML) (13), spersed nuclear element) density (⫺0.091, P ⬍ as formal inferences, and these lead immediately
and both include parameters specifying rates 0.0001). None of these factors was significantly to tentative biological hypotheses, only some of
of synonymous and nonsynonymous substi- correlated with either nonsynonymous substitu- which we describe here.
tution (14– 16). In the first (Model 1), we tion rate or P2-value; however, genes associated In the human lineage, genes involved in
performed a classic test of the null hypothesis with some biological processes, such as olfac- olfaction show a significant tendency to be
of dN/dS ⫽ 1 in the human lineage (17, 18). tion, do show nonrandom associations with under positive selection (PMW ⬍ 0.005) (Ta-
The second model is a modification of the genomic location [P ⬍ 10⫺4, Kolmogorov- ble 1 and Fig. 2). Nearly all the genes clas-
method described by Yang and Nielsen (16), Smirnov (K-S) test] and GC content (P ⬍ 10⫺9, sified to olfaction are olfactory receptors
which allows variation in the dN/dS ratio K-S test). We also verified that segmental dupli- (ORs). It seems likely that the different life-
Temas
- El registro fósil de los homínidos. Patrones y criterios de interpretación.
- Herramientas para un análisis comparado: elementos de morfología cráneo-facial
- Historia de las teorías y miradas sobre la evolución humana.
- Las evidencias de evolución humana como patrón macroevolutivo.
- Lenguaje y pensamiento simbólico en relación a la evidencia paleontológica.
234
Por otra parte, los restos líticos confeccionados y utilizados por los homininos también
poseen un alto potencial de conservación asociado. El patrón de distribución geográfico, su
tipología y su variabilidad son rasgos característicos de este registro arqueológico, los cuales se
analizan en conjunto con los rasgos morfológicas presentes en los restos óseos. De manera muy
general, se reconocen en el linaje homínido una serie de “industrias” líticas o “complejos
tecno-culturales” diferentes asociadas a distintas especies. Si bien cada uno de estos complejos es
identificado a través de ciertos componentes diagnósticos, los mismos incluyen una serie variable
de utensilios en cuanto a la forma, el tamaño y la materia prima utilizada. En la figura a
continuación se esquematiza la secuencia de pasos generales que implica el proceso de tallado en
roca para la obtención de utensilios:
235
Los utensilios más antiguos conocidos datan de aproximadamente 2,6 millones de años
(MA) y se hallaron asociados a los primeros restos óseos asignados al género Homo, en África. Se
trata de cantos rodados tallados en uno o dos planos de manera tal que se genera un filo y se los
denomina choppers o chopping tools. En general, estas primeras herramientas de roca se agrupan
dentro de una “industria” llamada olduvaiense:
Recién hacia los 1,7 MA aparece en África una innovación a nivel de la talla de las materias
primas seleccionadas por los homininos. Se trata de los bifaces, pieza diagnóstica que llevó a la
delimitación de una nueva “industria” lítica, la “industria” acheulense. Estas piezas poseen un
tamaño variable y se caracterizan porque el canto rodado se halla tallado en ambas caras:
236
ACTIVIDADES A REALIZAR:
Su grupo dispondrá de información sobre distintos fósiles de homínidos y patrones
paleoambientales y temporales de distribución. A partir de dicha información y de los elementos
descritos anteriormente:
1. Desarrolle una hipótesis evolutiva y confeccione un esquema de relaciones entre los
especímenes y el hombre.
2. Especifique el número de especies que quedan conformadas y las características elegidas
como claves evolutivas y criterios de agrupamiento.
237
BIBLIOGRAFÍA COMPLEMENTARIA
• Domínguez-Rodrigo, M. 2002. Hunting and scavenging by early humans: The state of debate. Journal of
World Prehistory 16:1-54.
• Foley, R. 1993. Causes and Consequences in Human Evolution. J. Roy. Anthrop. Inst. 1:67-86.
• Stiner, M. C. 2002. Carnivory, coevolution and the geographic spread of the genus Homo. Journal of
Archaeological Research 10: 31-68.
• Klein, R.G. 2003. Whither the Neanderthals? Science 229:1525-1527.
• McBrearty, S.; Brooks, A.S. 2000. The revolution that wasn’t: a new interpretation of the origin of modern
human behavior. J Hum Evol 39:453-563.
• d'Errico, F. 2003. The invisible frontier. A multiple species model for the origin of behavioral modernity.
Evolutionary Anthropology 12 (4):188-202.
238
EMERGENCE originally published in 2003
ONCE we
SHARING A SINGLE LANDSCAPE, four kinds of hominids lived about 1.8 million years ago in what is now part of northern Kenya.
Although paleoanthropologists have no idea how— or if— these different species interacted, they do know that Paranthropus boisei,
Homo rudolfensis, H. habilis and H. ergaster foraged in the same area around Lake Turkana.
239
25 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
IS THE ONLY HOMINID ON EARTH. YET FOR AT LEAST
SHARED THE PLANET. WHAT MAKES US DIFFERENT?
240
26 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
Homo sapiens has had the earth to itself
for the past 25,000 years or so, free and years ago in what is now northern Kenya, tinct geographical regions offer some in-
clear of competition from other mem- that the single-species hypothesis was triguing insights.
bers of the hominid family. This period abandoned. Yet even then, paleoanthro-
has evidently been long enough for us to pologists continued to cleave to a rather A Suite of Species
have developed a profound feeling that minimalist interpretation of the fossil F R O M T H E B E G I N N I N G , almost from
being alone in the world is an entirely record. Their tendency was to downplay the very moment the earliest hominid
natural and appropriate state of affairs. the number of species and to group to- biped— the first “australopith”— made
So natural and appropriate, indeed, gether distinctively different fossils un- its initial hesitant steps away from the
that during the 1950s and 1960s a der single, uninformative epithets such forest depths, we have evidence for hom-
school of thought emerged that claimed, as “archaic Homo sapiens.” As a result, inid diversity. The oldest-known poten-
in essence, that only one species of hom- they tended to lose sight of the fact that tial hominid is Sahelanthropus tchaden-
inid could have existed at a time because many kinds of hominids had regularly sis, represented by a cranium from the
there was simply no ecological space on contrived to coexist. central-western country of Chad [see il-
the planet for more than one culture- Although the minimalist tendency lustration on page 26]. Better known is
bearing species. The “single-species hy- persists, recent discoveries and fossil Australopithecus anamensis, from sites
pothesis” was never very convincing— reappraisals make clear that the biolog- in northern Kenya that are about 4.2
even in terms of the rather sparse homi- ical history of hominids resembles that million years old.
nid fossil record of 40 years ago. But the of most other successful animal families. A. anamensis looks reassuringly simi-
implicit scenario of the slow, single- It is marked by diversity rather than by lar to the 3.8- to 3.0-million-year-old
minded transformation of the bent and linear progression. Despite this rich his- Australopithecus afarensis, a small-
benighted ancestral hominid into the tory— during which hominid species de- brained, big-faced bipedal species to
graceful and gifted modern H. sapiens veloped and lived together and compet- which the famous “Lucy” belonged.
proved powerfully seductive— as fables ed and rose and fell— H. sapiens ulti- Many remnants of A. afarensis have
of frogs becoming princes always are. mately emerged as the sole hominid. The been found in various eastern African
So seductive that it was only in the reasons for this are generally unknow- sites, but some researchers have suggest-
late 1970s, following the discovery of in- able, but different interactions between ed that the mass of fossils described as A.
controvertible fossil evidence that hom- the last coexisting hominids— H. sapiens afarensis may contain more than one
inid species coexisted some 1.8 million and H. neanderthalensis— in two dis- species, and it is only a matter of time
241
27 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
until the subject is raised again. In any tinctive P. robustus and possibly a close- could wish for a better record of this
event, A. afarensis was not alone in ly related second species, P. crassidens. movement, and particularly of its dat-
Africa. A distinctive jaw, from an aus- I apologize for inflicting this long list ing, but there are indications that hom-
tralopith named A. bahrelghazali, was of names on readers, but in fact it actu- inids of some kind had reached China
found in 1995 in Chad. It is probably ally underestimates the number of aus- and Java by about 1.8 million years ago.
between 3.5 and 3.0 million years old tralopith species that existed. What is A lower jaw that may be about the same
and is thus roughly coeval with Lucy, as more, scientists don’t know how long age from Dmanisi in ex-Soviet Georgia
is the recently named new form Kenyan- each of these creatures lasted. Neverthe- is different from anything else yet found
thropus platyops. less, even if average species longevity [see “Out of Africa Again ... and Again?”
In southern Africa, scientists reported was only a few hundred thousand years, by Ian Tattersall; SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN,
evidence in 1999 of another primitive it is clear that from the very beginning April 1997]. By the million-year mark
bipedal hominid species. As yet un- the continent of Africa was at least pe- H. erectus was established in both Java
named and undescribed, this distinctive riodically— and most likely continual- and China, and it is possible that a more
form is 3.3 million years old. At about ly— host to multiple kinds of hominids. robust hominid species was present in
three million years ago, the same region The appearance of the genus Homo Java as well. At the other end of the
begins to yield fossils of A. africanus, the did nothing to perturb this pattern. The Eurasian continent, the oldest-known
first australopith to be discovered (in 2.5- to 1.8-million-year-old fossils from European hominid fragments— from
1924). This species may have persisted eastern and southern Africa that an- about 800,000 years ago— are highly
until not much more than two million nounce the earliest appearance of Homo distinctive and have been dubbed H. an-
years ago. A 2.5-million-year-old species are an oddly assorted lot and probably a tecessor by their Spanish discoverers.
from Ethiopia, named Australopithecus lot more diverse than their conventional About 600,000 years ago, in Africa,
garhi in 1999, is claimed to fall in an in- assignment to the two species H. habilis we begin to pick up evidence for H. hei-
termediate position between A. afaren- and H. rudolfensis indicates. Still, at delbergensis, a species also seen at sites
sis, on the one hand, and a larger group Kenya’s East Turkana, in the period be- in Europe— and possibly China— be-
that includes more recent australopiths tween 1.9 and 1.8 million years ago, tween 500,000 to 200,000 years ago. As
and Homo, on the other. Almost exact- these two species were joined not only we learn more about H. heidelbergensis,
ly the same age is the first representative by the ubiquitous P. boisei but by H. er- we are likely to find that more than one
of the “robust” group of australopiths, gaster, the first hominid of essentially species is actually represented in this
Paranthropus aethiopicus. This early modern body form. Here, then, is evi- group of fossils. In Europe, H. heidel-
form is best known from the 2.5-mil- dence for four hominid species sharing bergensis or a relative gave rise to an en-
lion-year-old “Black Skull” of northern not just the same continent but the same demic group of hominids whose best-
Kenya, and in the period between about landscape [see illustration on previous known representative was H. nean-
2 and 1.4 million years ago the robusts page and below]. derthalensis, a European and western
were represented all over eastern Africa The first exodus of hominids from Asian species that flourished between
by the familiar P. boisei. In South Africa, Africa, presumably in the form of H. er- about 200,000 and 30,000 years ago.
during the period around 1.6 million gaster or a close relative, opened a vast The sparse record from Africa suggests
years ago, the robusts included the dis- prospect for further diversification. One that at this time independent develop-
242
28 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
TUC D’AUDOUBERT CAVE in France was entered sometime between perhaps
11,000 and 13,000 years ago by H. sapiens, also called Cro Magnons, who
sculpted small clay bison in a recess almost a mile underground.
ments were taking place there, too— in- involving the cop-out of stuffing all vari- than gradual accretions. Over the past
cluding the emergence of H. sapiens. ants of Homo of the past half a million five million years, new hominid species
And in Java, possible H. erectus fossils or even two million years into the species have regularly emerged, competed, co-
from Ngandong were dated to around H. sapiens. existed, colonized new environments
40,000 years ago, implying that this area My own view, in contrast, is that the and succeeded— or failed. We have only
had its own indigenous hominid evolu- 20 or so hominid species invoked (if not the dimmest of perceptions of how this
tionary history for perhaps millions of named) above represent a minimum es- dramatic history of innovation and in-
years as well. timate. Not only is the human fossil teraction unfolded, but it is already evi-
The picture of hominid evolution just record as we know it full of largely un- dent that our species, far from being the
sketched is a far cry from the “Australo- acknowledged morphological indica- pinnacle of the hominid evolutionary
pithecus africanus begat Homo erectus tions of diversity, but it would be rash to tree, is simply one more of its many ter-
begat Homo sapiens” scenario that pre- claim that every hominid species that minal twigs.
vailed 40 years ago— and it is, of course, ever existed is represented in one fossil
based to a great extent on fossils that collection or another. And even if only The Roots of Our Solitude
have been discovered since that time. the latter is true, it is still clear that the A L T H O U G H T H I S is all true, H. sapi-
Yet the dead hand of linear thinking still story of human evolution has not been ens embodies something that is undeni-
lies heavily on paleoanthropology, and one of a lone hero’s linear struggle. ably unusual and is neatly captured by
even today quite a few of my colleagues Instead it has been the story of na- the fact that we are alone in the world
would argue that this scenario overesti- ture’s tinkering: of repeated evolution- today. Whatever that something is, it is
mates diversity. There are various ways ary experiments. Our biological history related to how we interact with the ex-
of simplifying the picture, most of them has been one of sporadic events rather ternal world: it is behavioral, which
243
29 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
HOMINIDS of modern body form most
likely emerged in Africa around 150,000
years ago and coexisted with other
hominids for a time before emerging as
the only species of our family. Until
about 30,000 years ago, they overlapped
with H. neanderthalensis (left) in Europe
and in the Levant, and they may have
been contemporaneous with the
H. erectus (right) then living in Java.
means that we have to look to our ar- who did the same, the Neandertals fur- lack the “grave goods” that would attest
chaeological record to find evidence of nish us with a particularly instructive to ritual and belief in an afterlife. The
it. This record begins some 2.5 million yardstick by which to judge our own Neandertals, in other words, though ad-
years ago with the production of the first uniqueness. The stoneworking skills of mirable in many ways and for a long
recognizable stone tools: simple sharp the Neandertals were impressive, if time successful in the difficult circum-
flakes chipped from parent “cores.” We somewhat stereotyped, but they rarely if stances of the late ice ages, lacked the
don’t know exactly who the inventor ever made tools from other preservable spark of creativity that, in the end, dis-
was, but chances are that he or she was materials. And many archaeologists tinguished H. sapiens.
something we might call an australopith. question the sophistication of their hunt- Although the source of H. sapiens as
This landmark innovation represent- ing skills. a physical entity is obscure, most evi-
ed a major cognitive leap and had pro- Further, despite misleading early ac- dence points to an African origin perhaps
found long-term consequences for hom- counts of bizarre Neandertal “bear between 150,000 and 200,000 years
inids. It also inaugurated a pattern of cults” and other rituals, no substantial ago. Modern behavior patterns did not
highly intermittent technological change. evidence has been found for symbolic emerge until much later. The best evi-
It was a full million years before the next behaviors among these hominids or for dence comes from Israel and its sur-
significant technological innovation the production of symbolic objects— cer- rounding environs, where Neandertals
came along: the creation about 1.5 mil- tainly not before contact had been made lived about 200,000 years ago or per-
lion years ago, probably by H. ergaster, with modern humans. Even the occa- haps even earlier. By about 100,000
of the hand ax. These symmetrical im- sional Neandertal practice of burying years ago, they had been joined by
plements, shaped from large stone cores, the dead may have been simply a way of anatomically modern H. sapiens, and
were the first tools to conform to a “men- discouraging hyenas from making in- the remarkable thing is that the tools
tal template” that existed in the tool- cursions into their living spaces or have and sites the two hominid species left be-
maker’s mind. This template remained a similar mundane explanation. This hind are essentially identical. As far as
essentially unchanged for another mil- view arises because Neandertal burials can be told, these two hominids behaved
lion years or more, until the invention of
“prepared-core” tools by H. heidelber- IAN TATTERSALL and JAY H. MATTERNES have worked together since the early 1990s, no-
THE AUTHOR AND THE ARTIST
gensis or a relative. Here a stone core was tably on the Hall of Human Biology and Evolution at the American Museum of Natural His-
elaborately shaped in such a way that a tory in New York City and at the Gunma Museum of Natural History in Tomioka, Japan (where
single blow would detach what was an the Tuc d’Audoubert mural on the opposite page is installed). Tattersall was born in England
effectively finished implement. and raised in East Africa. He is a curator in the department of anthropology at the Ameri-
Among the most accomplished practi- can Museum of Natural History. His books include Becoming Human: Evolution and Human
tioners of prepared-core technology Uniqueness (Harvest Books, 1999) and The Last Neanderthal: The Rise, Success, and Mys-
were the large-brained, big-faced and terious Extinction of Our Closest Human Relatives (Westview Press, 1999, revised).
low-skulled Neandertals, who occupied Matternes is an artist and sculptor who has for more than 40 years specialized in fos-
Europe and western Asia until about sil primates and hominids. In addition to his museum murals, he is well known for his illus-
30,000 years ago. Because they left an trations for books, periodicals and television, including Time/Life Books and National Geo-
excellent record of themselves and were graphic. The research for his depictions has taken him to many parts of the U.S., Canada,
abruptly replaced by modern humans Mexico, France, Colombia and Africa.
244
30 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
0 H. sapiens (Worldwide)
H. neanderthalensis
(Europe and Western Asia) in similar ways despite their anatomical
differences. And as long as they did so,
they somehow contrived to share the
H. heidelbergensis (throughout Old World)
Levantine environment.
The situation in Europe could hardly
H. erectus (Eastern Asia) be more different. The earliest H. sapi-
1 H. antecessor
(Spain) ens sites there date from only about
40,000 years ago, and just 10,000 or so
years later the formerly ubiquitous Ne-
andertals were gone. Significantly, the
H. sapiens who invaded Europe brought
H. habilis with them abundant evidence of a fully
(Sub-Saharan Africa) formed and unprecedented modern sen-
K. rudolfensis
(Eastern Africa) sibility. Not only did they possess a new
“Upper Paleolithic” stoneworking tech-
2
Homo ergaster P. robustus P. boisei nology based on the production of mul-
(Eastern Africa) (South Africa) (Eastern Africa) tiple long, thin blades from cylindrical
cores, but they made tools from bone
Au. africanus and antler, with an exquisite sensitivity
Millions of Years Ago
Competing Scenarios
Ardipithecus ramidus I N A L L T H E S E W A Y S , early Upper Pa-
5 (Ethiopia)
leolithic people contrasted dramatically
with the Neandertals. Some Neandertals
in Europe seem to have picked up new
ways of doing things from the arriving
H. sapiens, but we have no direct clues
as to the nature of the interaction be-
Orrorin tugenensis tween the two species. In light of the Ne-
(Kenya)
andertals’ rapid disappearance and of
PATRICIA J. WYNNE (drawings)
6
the appalling subsequent record of H.
sapiens, though, we can reasonably sur-
SPECULATIVE FAMILY TREE shows the variety of hominid mise that such interactions were rarely
species that have populated the planet— some identified by happy for the former. Certainly the re-
only a fragment, others known to exist for a specific time
period (solid lines). The emergence of H. sapiens has not peated pattern found at archaeological
been a single, linear transformation of one species into Sahelanthropus sites is one of short-term replacement,
another but rather a meandering, multifaceted evolution. tchadensis and there is no convincing biological ev-
(Chad)
245
31 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
The pattern of intermittent technological innovation
was gone, replaced by constant refinement.
Clearly, these people were us.
idence of any intermixing of peoples in see that, profound as the consequences sufficiently advantageous, this behav-
Europe. of achieving symbolic thought may have ioral novelty could then have spread
In the Levant, the coexistence ceased— been, the process whereby it came about rapidly by cultural contact among pop-
after about 60,000 years or so— at right was unexceptional. ulations that already had the potential to
about the time that Upper Paleolithic– We have no idea at present how the acquire it. No population replacement
like tools began to appear. About 40,000 modern human brain converts a mass of would have been necessary to spread the
years ago the Neandertals of the Levant electrical and chemical discharges into capability worldwide.
yielded to a presumably culturally rich what we experience as consciousness. It is impossible to be sure what this in-
H. sapiens, just as their European coun- We do know, however, that somehow novation might have been, but the best
terparts had. our lineage passed to symbolic thought current bet is that it was the invention of
The key to the difference between the from some nonsymbolic precursor state. language. For language is not simply the
European and the Levantine scenarios The only plausible possibility is that medium by which we express our ideas
lies, most probably, in the emergence of with the arrival of anatomically modern and experiences to one another. Rather
modern cognition— which, it is reason- H. sapiens, existing exaptations were it is fundamental to the thought process
able to assume, is equivalent to the ad- fortuitously linked by a relatively minor itself. It involves categorizing and nam-
vent of symbolic thought. Business had genetic innovation to create an unprece- ing objects and sensations in the outer
continued more or less as usual right dented potential. and inner worlds and making associa-
through the appearance of modern bone Yet even in principle this deduced sce- tions between resulting mental symbols.
structure, and only later, with the ac- nario cannot be the full story, because It is, in effect, impossible for us to con-
quisition of fully modern behavior pat- anatomically modern humans behaved ceive of thought (as we are familiar with
terns, did H. sapiens become complete- archaically for a long time before adopt- it) in the absence of language, and it is
ly intolerant of competition from its ing modern behaviors. That discrepan- the ability to form mental symbols that
nearest— and, evidently, not its dearest— cy may be the result of the late appear- is the fount of our creativity. Only when
co-inhabitors. ance of some key hardwired innovation we are able to create such symbols can
To understand how this change in sen- not reflected in the skeleton, which is all we recombine them and ask such ques-
sibility occurred, we have to recall cer- that fossilizes. But this seems unlikely, tions as “What if...?”
tain things about the evolutionary pro- because it would have necessitated a We do not know exactly how lan-
cess. First, as in this case, all innovations wholesale Old World–wide replacement guage might have emerged in one local
must necessarily arise within preexisting of hominid populations in a very short population of H. sapiens, although lin-
species— for where else can they do so? time, something for which there is no guists have speculated widely. But we do
Second, many novelties arise as “exap- evidence. know that a creature armed with sym-
tations,” features acquired in one con- It is much more likely that the modern bolic skills is a formidable competitor—
text before (often long before) being co- human capacity was born at— or close and not necessarily an entirely rational
opted in a different one. For example, to— the origin of H. sapiens, as an abili- one, as the rest of the living world, in-
hominids possessed essentially modern ty that lay fallow until it was activated cluding H. neanderthalensis, has discov-
vocal tracts for hundreds of thousands by a cultural stimulus of some kind. If ered to its cost.
of years before the behavioral record
gives us any reason to believe that they MORE TO E XPLORE
employed the articulate speech that the Dark Caves, Bright Visions: Life in Ice Age Europe. Randall White. W. W. Norton/American Museum
of Natural History, 1986.
peculiar form of this tract permits.
Language and Species. Reprint edition. Derek Bickerton. University of Chicago Press, 1992.
And finally, it is important to bear in
The Fossil Trail: How We Know What We Think We Know about Human Evolution. Ian Tattersall.
mind the phenomenon of emergence— Oxford University Press, 1995.
the notion that a chance coincidence Getting Here: The Story of Human Evolution. Updated edition. William Howells. Compass Press,
gives rise to something totally unexpect- 1997.
ed. The classic scientific example in this African Exodus: The Origins of Modern Humanity. Reprint edition. Christopher Stringer and
Robin McKie. Henry Holt, 1998.
regard is water, whose properties are
The Origin and Diversification of Language. Edited by Nina G. Jablonski and Leslie C. Aiello.
wholly unpredicted by those of hydro- University of California Press, 1998.
gen and oxygen atoms alone. If we com- The Last Neanderthal: The Rise, Success and Mysterious Extinction of Our Closest Human
bine these various observations, we can Relatives. Revised edition. Ian Tattersall. Westview Press, 1999.
246
32 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN EXCLUSIVE ONLINE ISSUE AUGUST 2005
COPYRIGHT 2005 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN, INC.
247
SEMINARIO III
SURGIMIENTO DEL HOMBRE MODERNO, OLEADAS MIGRATORIAS Y
EVOLUCIÓN DE Homo sapiens
Por Alicia Massarini, Ignacio M. Soto & Ana Liza Tropea
INTRODUCCIÓN GENERAL
Homo sapiens es, actualmente, una especie cosmopolita. La distribución actual responde a
un fenómeno que empezó hace millones de años con la/s población/es de homínidos que
abandonaron por primera vez África, el continente origen de nuestro linaje. El proceso de
poblamiento de nuestro planeta interesa tanto por sus causas como por sus consecuencias y es uno
de los aspectos en donde la adaptabilidad de nuestra especie queda más evidenciada. Sin embargo,
la reconstrucción del patrón de migraciones no se comprende plenamente y actualmente es objeto
de intenso debate.
TEMAS:
ACTIVIDADES A REALIZAR:
Wilson, A. C.; Cann, R. L.; Origen africano reciente de los humanos; Investigación y
Ciencia; Junio de 1992.
1.1. ¿Qué ventajas tendría según los autores, la utilización de datos moleculares respecto de los
datos paleontológicos tradicionales para la reconstrucción de historias de parentesco? ¿En qué
medida el ejemplo presentado de Ramaphitecus ilustra esta controversia?
1.2. ¿Por qué se utiliza ADN mitocondrial para el estudio de la evolución reciente de los humanos?
¿Cuáles son sus ventajas respecto del ADN nuclear? ¿A qué se refiere la metáfora “Eva
mitocondrial”? ¿Con qué criterios Kocher (1988) seleccionó un árbol de ADNmt entre los
múltiples posibles? ¿Qué nueva información proporcionó el estudio comparado de ADNmt de
chimpancés y humanos?
1.3. ¿Qué se observó cuando los autores utilizaron una muestra que incluía 182 tipos diferentes de
ADNmt? ¿Qué información aporta este tipo de estudios respecto de la colonización de distintas
regiones por Homo sapiens? ¿Qué sugieren acerca del concepto clásico de raza? ¿Y acerca del
escenario geográfico donde ocurrió el origen de Homo sapiens?
248
1.4. ¿Con qué criterios se estableció la datación del origen de nuestra especie? ¿Podrían relacionar
este aspecto del estudio con la discusión planteada en la introducción de trabajo acerco de la
objetividad de los datos moleculares? ¿Qué relación existe entre la hipótesis de Eva
mitocondrial y las evidencias fósiles disponibles actualmente?
1.5. ¿Qué críticas hacen los autores al modelo multirregional? ¿Qué explicaciones proponen para el
desplazamiento sin hibridación de las antiguas poblaciones de homínidos por Homo sapiens?
¿Qué nuevas perspectivas podrán ampliar la comprensión de este problema?
2.1. ¿Cómo presentan los autores su hipótesis sobre el origen del hombre moderno? ¿Cuál es la
analogía que proponen para comparar los dos modelos en disputa? ¿Cuál es la opinión de los
autores sobre los distintos tipos de datos que se utilizan para interpretar el problema?
2.2. ¿Cuáles son las premisas que según los autores deberían cumplirse en el modelo Eva
mitocondrial? ¿Por qué se afirma que el registro arqueológico estaría contradiciendo las
predicciones del modelo de Eva?
2.3. ¿Qué se propone acerca del camino anatómico a nivel regional que supone el modelo de Eva
mitocondrial? ¿Por qué se propone que si el modelo de Eva fuera correcto, la continuidad de las
formas a nivel regional debería ser “superficial”?
2.4. ¿Cómo interpretan los autores las relaciones filogenéticas existentes entre neandertales y Homo
sapiens?
2.5. Según los autores: ¿qué se espera encontrar en África si la hipótesis de Eva fuera correcta?
¿Cómo interpretan las evidencias existentes en este continente? ¿Cuál es la interpretación
alternativa a los datos de ADN mitocondrial, en el caso de afirmar que hubo hibridación entre
poblaciones locales y migrantes?
2.6. ¿Cómo afectaría a la datación del origen de Homo sapiens la pérdida azrosa de linajes de
ADNmt? ¿Por qué se propone que debe considerarse la historia demográfica de las poblaciones?
¿Qué otras objeciones se plantean al reloj molecular mitocondrial? ¿Cómo reinterpretan e
incorporan estos autores las evidencias moleculares en relación con su hipótesis?
3.1. ¿Cuál sería la relación entre el preconcepto de que la evolución se ha detenido en nuestra
especie y la Escala del Ser?
3.2. ¿Seguimos evolucionando los humanos? ¿Por procesos selectivos o por deriva? Comente
ejemplos de ambos procesos.
3.3. ¿Cuáles son las funciones o efectos de los genes con señales de selección reciente comentados
en el trabajo?
249
3.4. ¿Cuáles son las consecuencias evolutivas del desarrollo cultural y tecnológico de los humanos?
3.5. Discuta el futuro de la evolución humana, la predicción de los fenotipos por parte de la
Biología, y los posibles patrones macroevolutivos en nuestro linaje.
SÍNTESIS
Es preciso comprender que ambos modelos son, actualmente, los extremos de una gama
muy diversa de modelos que intentan explicar el "cómo" del surgimiento del hombre moderno y su
distribución posterior, revelada a través del registro fósil.
A partir de la discusión de estos trabajos fundacionales, y a modo de síntesis, los alumnos
deberían llegar a comparar ambos modelos según los siguientes criterios: (1) lugar geográfico
originario de Homo sapiens; (2) población ancestral; (3) edad de la especie humana; (4) tipos de
evidencias utilizadas; (5) posición filogenética de neandertales; (6) dinámica de poblamiento a nivel
del viejo mundo; (7) mirada macroevolutiva subyacente.
BIBLIOGRAFÍA COMPLEMENTARIA
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
N e w s Fo c u s
The goal of much of modern medicine and culture is effectively to stop evolution. Is that happening?
By deploying such methods, geneticists nucleotide base pairs long that includes the after the invention of farming, when the clear-
have identified more than two dozen genes lactase gene and confers lactase persistence ing of forests left standing pools of water in
that appear to have come under selective on people who carry it. This form of the which the vector for the disease, the Anophe-
pressures since the rise of Homo, and several haplotype is found in nearly 80% of Euro- les mosquito, could breed. Thus a cultural
of them may still be subject to such pressures peans and Americans of European ancestry change again led to a genetic one.
266
236 8 JULY 2005 VOL 309 SCIENCE www.sciencemag.org
Published by AAAS
N E W S F O C U S
The case of AIDS, and the virus that dence for positive selection was stunning: rently acting on the human genome means
causes it, HIV, suggests that the selective As the team reported in the February 2005 that humans are still evolving, even if in
advantage of a gene can shift over time. As issue of Nature Genetics, female H2 carrierssubtle ways. But can we actually predict the
HIV infects T cells in the blood, it docks had about 3.5% more children than H1 car- course of future evolution, à la Sykes’s dis-
onto a cell surface receptor called CCR5. In riers. “This study has large implications,” appearing males or the vanishing blonds?
the mid-1990s researchers discovered that a says anthropologist Osbjorn Pearson of the Most researchers’ predictions are consider-
mutation in the CCR5 gene provides strong University of New Mexico, Albuquerque. ably more narrow and cautious and are tied
protection against AIDS in homozygotes, “The European version of the H2 haplotype to known selective pressures.
people who have two copies of the protec- could sweep the entire human population if For example, researchers predict that
tive allele. The mutation, called delta 32, is it conveyed the same reproductive advan- delta 32 and other protective CCR5 muta-
found in up to 13% of European popula- tage in other people and environments.” But tions may become more common in popula-
tions but is extremely rare in other groups, deCODE CEO and research team co-leader tions widely infected with HIV, especially
including Africans. Researchers dated the Kári Stefánsson says the low frequencies of in Africa. “If there are no more advances in
origins of the delta 32 mutation the treatment of AIDS and peo-
in humans to about 700 years ple continue to die, we would
ago and concluded that a strong expect selection pressure to
selective event resulted in its increase [the mutations’] fre-
spread; this f inding was con- quency over time,” says Tyler-
firmed in 2001 using sophisti- Smith, who adds that he sees “no
cated selection tests. reason why they should not go to
Yet because the AIDS epi- f ixation”—that is, replace all
demic dates only from the late other alleles of the gene.
1970s at the earliest, researchers Whether or not these patterns
believe that the selective pressure will make a significant differ-
on the delta 32 mutation must ence in the way humans look or
have been from some other live is another question. “There
factor. Researchers have debated will be minor fluctuations over
whether the plague or smallpox, time and space in the makeup of
both of which ravaged European local human gene pools as
populations in the past, is more humans respond to local condi-
likely, although some recent stud- tions,” predicts Tattersall, “but
ies have leaned toward smallpox. they won’t be directional. I find
it hard to foresee that under cur-
Icelanders evolving? rent conditions a qualitatively
Although researchers scouring new kind of human is ever likely
the human genome for signs of Baby boost. Women with an inversion in this region of chromosome 17 to emerge. But if conditions
natural selection have uncovered have more children. change, all bets are off.”
a few examples, direct evidence Evolutionary predictions are
that a particular allele actually boosts repro- H2 outside Europe suggest that for some tied to speculation about just what kind
duction—the sine qua non of natural selec- reason, its advantages are limited to that of environment we may face. Some
tion—is hard to come by in humans. But continent. “Why, I can’t tell you,” he says. researchers suggest that changing climate
that’s just what researchers were able to do in There are several genes in the H2 region, conditions may diminish the benefits of cul-
one dramatic study in Iceland. For the past but it is not at all clear which ones cause H2 ture and medicine, creating a new era of nat-
several years, scientists at deCODE Genet- carriers to have more children; one nearby ural selection. “There has been a relaxation
ics, a biotechnology company based in gene is implicated in pregnancy complica- in selective pressures in industrialized soci-
Reykjavik, Iceland, have been gathering tions. The deCODE team is looking at the eties,” says evolutionary geneticist Peter
genetic information on the nation’s 270,000 genes to see whether differences in expres- Keightley of the University of Edinburgh,
citizens, in a government-approved effort to sion might create the selective advantage. U.K. “But our ability to sustain that relax-
isolate disease genes (Science, 24 October One lead, Stefánsson says, is that H2 carri- ation is probably temporary. We are using
1997, p. 566). In the course of this research, ers also show a higher rate of recombination up our energy resources, our population is
deCODE researchers discovered a variant of during meiosis. In an earlier study, his team growing, and the climate is changing. All
human chromosome 17 in which a 900,000 - found that mothers with high oocyte recom- this is bound to lead to greater difficulties
nucleotide-base-pair stretch of DNA was bination rates also tend to have more chil- and renewed selective pressures.”
inverted; this inversion was associated with dren, possibly because this genetic shuf- Despite such concerns, however, most
a previously identified haplotype called H2, fling helps protect against errors in meiosis, scientists remain leery of long-term fore-
which they estimate arose 3 million years which are a major cause of miscarriage in casts, in part because of the way evolution
CREDIT: NATURE GENETICS 37, 129-137 (2005)
ago. H2 carriers make up about 17.5% of older mothers. H2 carriers also appear to works. “Evolution is not directed towards a
Icelanders and 21% of Europeans, but only live longer on average. “It is fascinating to goal,” says Tyler-Smith. “It always takes the
about 6% of Africans and 1% of Asians. think that there might be an advantage asso- short-term view, operating just on what
To see whether the relatively high fre- ciated with a DNA variant at both ends of allows us to survive and reproduce better in
quencies in Europeans represented natural life,” Stefánsson says. this generation.” For now, predicting
selection, the team genotyped 29,137 Ice- humanity’s evolutionary future may be little
landers born between 1925 and 1965. When Our evolutionary future more than crystal ball gazing—better suited
these data were correlated with the island’s To many researchers, the limited but grow- to science fiction than scientific research.
extensive genealogical database, the evi- ing evidence that natural selection is cur- –MICHAEL BALTER
267
www.sciencemag.org SCIENCE VOL 309 8 JULY 2005 237
Published by AAAS
EJERCICIOS
DE
REPASO
268
269
Problema 1.
El Dr. H. estudia dos “variedades” de angiospermas (plantas con flores) que
habitan en una pradera y un bosque de una misma región geográfica. A lo
largo de varios años ha colectado la siguiente información:
i) En el año 2006 el investigador realizó un estudio con plantas de la
pradera y del bosque analizando los caracteres: largo del tallo,
número de hojas, concentración de carotenos en las flores, largo de
los estambres y número de estomas por cm3. Combinó toda esta
información en dos variables nuevas y obtuvo el siguiente gráfico:
Pradera:
Individuos originarios de la pradera: 5 ± 1 semillas/flor
Individuos originarios del bosque: 0,2 ± 0,1 semillas/flor
Bosque:
Individuos originarios de la pradera: 1 ± 0,2 semillas/flor
Individuos originarios del bosque: 20 ± 4 semillas/flor
270
a. Interprete la información de los tres estudios y explique los resultados
obtenidos.
b. Especifique cuántas especies podrían definirse para estas dos variedades de
angiospermas de acuerdo a los conceptos de especie morfológico, ecológico,
biológico y cohesivo. Justifique claramente sus respuestas.
c. Para el concepto de especie que corresponda, indique el/los mecanismo/s de
aislamiento reproductivo existentes.
d. ¿En cuál de las dos escuelas teóricas sobre el proceso de especiación
(aislacionista o seleccionista) cree Ud. que se encuadra el trabajo del Dr. H.?
Justifique.
e. Compare ambas escuelas con respecto a: el concepto de especie utilizado,
cuáles serían los “genes de especiación”, el papel de la selección natural y la
deriva génica en el proceso especiogénico y el modelo geográfico
paradigmático.
Problema 2.
En Drosophila, como en todos los insectos holometábolos, el crecimiento
corporal está restringido a los estadios larvales. Las larvas se alimentan y
crecen exponencialmente hasta alcanzar un tamaño crítico que se alcanza al
comienzo del tercer estadio larval. En este momento se inicia una cascada
hormonal que desencadena en la liberación de ecdisteroides. Un primer pico de
liberación de ecdicteroides produce que la larva deje de alimentarse y busque
un lugar para comenzar la metamorfosis. Al dejar de comer, la larva detiene su
crecimiento corporal alcanzando el tamaño corporal final (los adultos tienen un
exoesqueleto que impide posteriores incrementos en el tamaño del cuerpo).
Existe una separación temporal entre el momento en que la larva deja de
alimentarse y el momento en que se alcanza el tamaño corporal final. Este
periodo se conoce como periodo de crecimiento terminal (TGP).
En los insectos holometábolos, los órganos (como por ejemplo, las alas) se
originan como discos imaginales dentro de la larva. Como en el caso del
crecimiento corporal, los discos imaginales también crecen exponencialmente
dentro de las larvas hasta diferenciarse en órganos adultos. La finalización del
crecimiento parece estar regulada por la misma cascada hormonal que regula
el crecimiento del cuerpo.
Ud. está interesado en estudiar el desarrollo ontogenético de las alas en un
grupo de especies de Drosophila que presenta variabilidad para el tamaño de
las mismas. En la figura 1 se muestran las relaciones filogenéticas entre las
especies utilizadas en este estudio (fig. 1.a) y los resultados obtenidos al
analizar la relación entre la superficie del cuerpo (tomado como superficie del
tórax) y el área de las alas (fig. 1.b):
271
(a) (b)
C (círculos)
A (triángulos)
B (cuadrados)
Figura 1.
(a) Relaciones filogenéticas entre
las especies estudiadas. (b) Relación
entre la superficie del cuerpo
y el área de las alas.
Figura 2: L1, L2 y L3 son estadios larvales. La escala de tiempo es la misma para las
especies a, b y c. El grafico de la izquierda corresponde a las especies a y c. El grafico
de la derecha a la especie b.
272
c. Para las especies a y b: ¿son homólogos los estadios larvales tres días
después de la eclosión del huevo (flechas negras gruesas en el eje tiempo)?
¿Se podrían usar estos individuos para estudiar comparativamente los patrones
de crecimiento alométricos entre ambas especies? Justifique todas sus
respuestas.
Problema 3:
273
a. ¿Qué mirada macroevolutiva (A, B, ambas o ninguna) subyace a este
escenario particular? Justifique su respuesta.
b. ¿Qué otros elementos o procesos son característicos de dicha mirada?
Mencione al menos tres.
c. Describa sintéticamente dos debates actuales en torno a la macroevolución
especificando en qué consiste cada uno de ellos y las distintas propuestas que
encierran. (Nota: para esto se sugiere revisar el artículo de S. J. Gould (1983)
estudiado en el bloque de macroevolución).
Problema 4.
Los piojos son insectos parásitos obligados de mamíferos y aves y por ende,
poseen aspectos de su ecología e historia evolutiva íntimamente ligados a los
de sus hospedadores. Su transmisión se produce por contacto directo entre sus
posibles hospedadores y su ciclo de vida se desarrolla completamente sobre el
cuerpo de los mismos.
a. Correlacione cada una de las siguientes figuras con un modelo geográfico de
especiación para los organismos parásitos. Justifique se respuesta.
274
Figura 1. Filogenia de los primates y de sus respectivos piojos. OW monkeys: monos
del Viejo Mundo (macacos y babuinos).
275
b. A partir de esta información, proponga un modelo geográfico de especiación
para los piojos de los géneros Phtirus y Pediculus. Explique mediante el mismo
cómo pudo producirse la divergencia entre los dos géneros y entre las especies
dentro de los géneros, sin olvidar mencionar si en algún caso pudo haberse
producido un salto de hospedador.
Un análisis filogenético basado en los genes mitocondriales Cyt b y COI de las
variantes del cuerpo y de la cabeza de P. humanus mostró el siguiente
cladograma:
276
Problema 5.
Un grupo de investigación se ha dedicado durante años a estudiar un conjunto
de coleópteros que comparten varias sinapomorfías. Las 15 especies
analizadas, como la mayoría de las pertenecientes al mismo orden, poseen dos
pares de alas: un primer par coriáceo (élitros) en el segundo segmento del
tórax, y un segundo par membranoso en el tercer segmento del tórax.
Después de realizar muchos experimentos, los investigadores llegaron a la
conclusión de que el desarrollo de dichos apéndices está controlado por una
serie de genes que interactúan entre si, que prácticamente no muestra
diferencias entre las especies estudiadas.
a. ¿Puede identificar alguna/s homología/s en el caso de estudio? ¿De qué tipo?
Justifique.
Posteriormente, la investigación se centró en un par de especies hermanas (A y
B). Los investigadores obtuvieron estimaciones del tamaño de ambos pares de
alas y del tamaño corporal total, y concluyeron que las especies analizadas
sólo difieren respecto del tamaño de los élitros. Determinaron que la especie A,
que posee un primer par de alas más grande, muestra una tasa de
proliferación celular mayor en el tejido a partir del cual se genera ese par de
alas durante la metamorfosis.
b. ¿A qué tipo de alometría se refieren estos resultados?
c. ¿Qué fenómeno podría explicar dichos resultados? ¿Qué observaciones
confirmarían su hipótesis?
Dado que las especies mencionadas previamente fueron mantenidas en el
laboratorio durante muchos años, los investigadores pudieron observar la
aparición de ciertos mutantes. Particularmente, la aparición de un segundo par
de élitros en lugar del par de alas membranosas. Cuando los investigadores
obtuvieron nuevas muestras de poblaciones naturales no hallaron ningún
individuo que mostrara el fenotipo obtenido en el laboratorio.
d. ¿Cómo podría explicar estos resultados? Justifique.
277
Problema 6.
En la figura a continuación se observan los rangos de volumen cerebral que
presentan diferentes géneros de homínidos a lo largo del tiempo.
Sabiendo que dentro de cada intervalo y género puede haber más de una
especie morfológica:
a. Redacte un breve párrafo explicando el patrón observado utilizando
elementos típicos de una “mirada A” o “el mejor de los mundos posibles”. Sea
conciso y argumente claramente en no más de 15 renglones.
b. Explique el mismo patrón utilizando elementos y procesos típicos de una
“mirada B” o “un mero mundo posible”. Sea conciso y argumente claramente
en no más de 15 renglones.
NOTA IMPORTANTE: Se evalúa el contrapunto entre los tipos de mirada y NO su
conocimiento sobre el tema de encefalización en particular.
278
Problema 7.
Empleando el esquema de relaciones del linaje homínido de Tattersall 2005:
a. ¿Considera Ud. que dicho esquema avala el modelo de evolución propuesto
por los defensores de Eva mitocondrial? Justifique su respuesta
b. Utilice 5 fósiles de este esquema para proponer una hipótesis alternativa
sobre evolución de los homínidos seleccionando del siguiente listado los
términos que considere adecuados para incluir en su relato:
coexistencia de varias especies / hipótesis de la especie única / cambio
gradual / procesos contingentes / adaptación al ambiente / cooptación de
cuerdas vocales / procesos microevolutivos / grupos hermanos / selección
de especies.
c. Indique dos críticas realizadas al modelo de Eva mitocondrial por parte de
los defensores del modelo Multirregional de evolución humana y viceversa.
d. Indique qué hipótesis de evolución del hombre moderno apoyaría cada uno
de los siguientes hallazgos. Justifique brevemente
d.1) Restos fósiles con características anatómicas modernas de
aproximadamente 300000 años hallados en África.
d.2) Los restos fósiles de hombres arcaicos hallados en Asia exhiben las
características típicas de las poblaciones actuales.
d.3) La estimación del origen del HSAM utilizando secuencias del
cromosoma Y fue de 190.000 años.
279
280
Problema 8.
Ud. es un referente a nivel internacional de la escuela seleccionista de
especiación. En particular, supone que la especiación en clados como el de los
mamíferos se produce principalmente en simpatría.
Recientemente comenzó a trabajar en colaboración con paleoantropólogos con
el objetivo de indagar los mecanismos subyacentes a las radiaciones
especiogénicas observadas en el registro fósil del linaje humano. Una primera
instancia de este proyecto consiste en reconstruir el proceso responsable de la
diversificación dentro del grupo de los australopitecinos africanos.
a. Utilizando los supuestos del modelo de especiación en simpatría y sus
conocimientos sobre las diferencias morfológicas existentes entre
australopitecinos gráciles* y australopitecinos robustos**, proponga un
escenario de especiación para explicar el surgimiento de ambos morfos en
África.
Organice su respuesta en torno a los siguientes ejes:
- distribución geográfica de la especie ancestral;
- características del ambiente;
- período geológico en el que ocurrió la divergencia;
- mecanismo evolutivo responsable de la divergencia;
- genes de la especiación;
- distribución geográfica de los morfos descendientes;
- resultado/s del proceso.
* Australopitecinos gráciles: grupo que incluye a las especies Australopithecus
anamensis, Australopithecus afarensis, Australopithecus africanus entre otros.
** Australopitecinos robustos: grupo que incluye a las especies Paranthropus
boisei, Paranthropus robustus; Paranthropus aethiopicus entre otros.
281