pierre schaef f er’s treatise on
musical objects and music theory
“The main fault of this book is in fact that it is still the only one. More than six
hundred pages devoted to objects weigh down one pan of the scale. To counterbalance it, the author should also have produced a Treatise on Musical Organization
of equal weight.”1 This statement appears on the first page of the “Penultimate
Chapter” of the Treatise. It could be construed as a mitigating disclaimer, although
this would be a grave mistake. But we should not forget that the Treatise is a work
by Pierre Schaeffer; his prose style, along with the scrupulous care with which he
used the French language, is part and parcel of his message. Consequently, the passage must be read within the context of the book and its overall formal plan. I
could have begun with another apparently alarming sentence written some eleven
years earlier: “It is possible to devote six hundred pages to not saying what one had
to say” (659). But neither of these passages is an admission of failure or regret. On
the contrary, they represent a deliberate rhetorical strategy. In addition to closely
argued sections on linguistics, acoustics, classification, and description, Schaeffer’s
writing contains many self-effacing remarks and wry comments on contemporary
music (these are often directed to “a priori” methods of composition). His language is, therefore, integral to the book’s subject matter and its methodology. With
commendable honesty Schaeffer acknowledged there are areas where more still
needs to be done, but rather than suppressing such sentiments, he identifies them
and invites readers to acknowledge that as far as music is concerned, “making” and
“doing” are ongoing processes.
1. Pierre Schaeffer, Traité des objets musicaux: Essai interdisciplines (Paris: Seuil, 1977), 663. Subsequent citations of this edition are given parenthetically in the text.
xxix
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 1/4/20 8:12 PM
xxx
Schaeffer’s Treatise and Music Theory
How, then, can we situate this unique and, I would argue, indispensable book
within the broad field of music theory? There can be little doubt that the Treatise
deserves respect, owing not only to its considerable length but also to the formidable range of disciplines to which Schaeffer referred. To make a claim for its status
as music theory, albeit a distinctive type of contemporary music theory, we must
turn to Schaeffer’s writing. A good starting point is to examine the work’s structure: seven books each drawing on subjects such as making, hearing, acoustics,
linguistics, physics, physiology, and even philosophy. The books are divided into
chapters (plus three appendices) that deal systematically with the specific topic
under consideration. Moreover, each of the thirty-six chapters contains several
subsections (nineteen in the case of chapter 35). The aforementioned “Penultimate
Chapter” is, in fact, the book’s final section. As a result, the adjective penultimate
immediately presents the reader with a conundrum challenging traditional notions
about how authors bring their books to a satisfactory conclusion. This “Penultimate Chapter” was added in 1977 as an addendum to the original 1966 publication
and demonstrates Schaeffer’s methodology, which is simultaneously playful and
serious. Despite the passage of eleven years between the two editions the aims of
Schaeffer’s book remained consistent: research into the sound object and the
importance of this research for music in general. The final pages from the first edition are rather lyrical in tone. Schaeffer referred to the special status of music and
claimed that sound objects and musical structures “are man described to man, in
the language of things” (662). This style is maintained throughout much of the
“Penultimate Chapter,” where it becomes obvious that the real conclusion, if
indeed conclusion is the correct term, will be the body of musical compositions
resulting from the research conducted by Schaeffer and his colleagues (Schaeffer
always acknowledged his research was a “group” project). If, therefore, a final
chapter in the conventional sense was problematic in 1966, it was, without a doubt,
impossible in 1977. The practical work of composition would be informed by the
research presented in the Treatise, and practice would in turn elaborate a new
music theory. The activities of homo faber would exist in mutual cooperation with
those of homo sapiens.
Schaeffer was no doubt fully aware of the implications of calling his book a Treatise. A long and distinguished tradition can be identified of theoretical treatises in
French. For example, Jean-Philippe Rameau (1683–1764) wrote his Traité de
l’harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels in 1722, and François-Joseph Fétis (1784–
1871) produced his Traité complet de la théorie et de la pratique de l’harmonie in
1844. These are just two of the many important Traités written in French since the
Middle Ages. But neither of these provides a satisfactory model for Schaeffer’s Treatise. Fétis assumed that his work was, in effect, an exhaustive summary of a deterministic, historical development. Chords were evaluated as part of an evolutionary
process culminating in tonality as defined by Fétis himself. Rameau’s Treatise con-
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 1/4/20 8:12 PM
Schaeffer’s Treatise and Music Theory
xxxi
vincingly demonstrated the natural foundations of harmony, which was in turn
based on physical phenomena observable in acoustical studies. Rameau’s theories
of chord generation and fundamental bass are still recognized as crucial stages in
our understanding of tonality. Scholars continue to contextualize both of these
works as major contributions to the development of musical thought. Self-evidently,
Schaeffer’s Treatise is too recent for such a historically based comparison.
In his introduction Schaeffer writes that the book is not a “theory of music” (11)
(the quote marks are Schaeffer’s) constituting a manual for composers. The Treatise is “the summation of a body of research presented as it developed, rather than
a logical presentation of results and possible applications” (665). In yet another
self-deprecating statement Schaeffer refers to a “zigzag run-through” (11). Despite
this apparent repudiation of systematic thinking, however, there are features in
common between the Treatise on Musical Objects and earlier works. Many treatises draw on contemporary studies in acoustics. There are references to tuning
systems investigated via monochords and Pythagorean ratios. Classification of
chords and the systematization of mensural notation as promulgated by Philippe
de Vitry (1291–1361) (with whom Schaeffer has been compared) are also common.
Schaeffer was aware of these and certainly made use of contemporary findings in
physics, for which his technical training makes him particularly suited. There are
many references to scientists such as Helmholtz, Fourier, and Fletcher. But Schaeffer remained skeptical of an excessive reliance on scientific positivism and constantly reminded the reader that musicians hear not only with their ears but also
with their brains. It is the interaction between cognitive capacities and sound (or
the “sonorous”) from which music will emerge—man described to man. Similarly,
he identified potential similarities in how language systems operate and investigated theoretical paradigms such as structuralism in order to discover the possibility of fundamental, perhaps even permanent, ways in which humans structure
their materials, be they sounds, words, or myths. He quoted scholars such as LéviStrauss, Malmberg, and Jakobson. Research in the Treatise clearly benefited from
the dual nature of music as both an art and a science. This is clearly one of its great
strengths, and in Schaeffer’s opinion music became the supreme example of interdisciplinary research. But here another linguistic conceit demands attention (and
Schaeffer must accept full responsibility for it!). The book’s subtitle is Essai interdisciplines.2 Schaeffer’s research does indeed draw on various fields of study. For
example, in his discussion on transients there are references to the acoustics of
instruments and how stretched strings behave when struck or plucked. With the
support of images, Schaeffer investigated the effects of such events on the processes of hearing. Such wide-ranging references to physics and human physiology
2. “Across disciplines”: here Schaeffer uses the word interdiscipline, which he apparently coined,
rather than interdisciplinaire, the more usual term.
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 1/4/20 8:12 PM
xxxii
Schaeffer’s Treatise and Music Theory
are by definition interdisciplinary in that two independent fields of study are used
to corroborate the results of a specific experiment. But the term interdisciplines,
coined by Schaeffer, implies an intellectual area across the disciplines, one that
demands to be studied on its own terms and might even emerge as a research field
in its own right. Consequently, measurable physical data and physiological predispositions still cannot tell us what these transients mean in a musical sense. Science
can be enlisted for factual information, but it cannot provide a satisfactory
solution to the mystery of music. We are, once again, left with man confronting
himself.
The value of the Treatise for musicians lies in Schaeffer’s insistence on asking
fundamental questions relevant to all aspects of music. He adopted a position of
Cartesian doubt, where everything had to be interrogated and reevaluated. The
starting point for this project was the sound object. But this object is not merely
something in the world that is separate from us and that demands our attention.
As suggested in the previous comments on transients, the sound object is both an
acoustic event and the listening intention of the musician. It is a correlation
between the outer world of objective physical occurrences and the inner world of
subjective human experience. Two consequences stem from this. The first is that
musicians can reassess the communicative potential of all sound material. Careful
experimentation will go beyond a simplistic assumption that all perceptible characteristics are equivalent and that spectral detail and dynamic level can be used in
the same way as pitch. By repeated, focused listening, previously disregarded features move to the fore and suggest themselves as candidates for new musical structures. Second, the whole enterprise might appear to be fixated on the single sound
object. But the book’s title is Treatise on Musical Objects. A sound object in isolation cannot create relationships; it can only be examined for its form-creating
potential. The individual sound object must be placed within a structure that
encourages perception and comparison of its features between other objects. It is
precisely here that values and characteristics are identified and differentiated and
that the transformation into a musical object occurs. Schaeffer even suggested that
a single musical object does not exist (670): its musical status is conditioned on the
creation of relationships with other objects. At this point we come full circle to the
missing second volume. The next stage, that of musical organization at all levels of
structure, can only really be undertaken by composers.
The central aim of the Treatise, the investigation of the sound object, is not
compromised by this deferral of compositional practice. Instead, it asserts the role
of music theory as an active aural procedure. What Schaeffer provides for the contemporary musician is a range of methods for investigating the materials of music
and how they might ultimately be formed into structures. Naturally, there is some
urgency to this endeavor given the vast repository of sounds that modern composers have at their disposal. This highlights the role technology can play in revealing
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 1/4/20 8:12 PM
Schaeffer’s Treatise and Music Theory
xxxiii
new musical languages. Indeed, the origins of Schaeffer’s entire research project
can be traced to the technology of musique concrète, though with great foresight
he rapidly realized that his theories could be generalized to music as a whole. The
recording process is of particular significance and can be compared to other technological methods that fix temporal events. In a sense a recording, like a photograph or a film clip, provides too much sensory information. The natural tendency
when hearing a sound, even one that is unfamiliar, is to associate it with a known
one. A sound object with an abrupt attack followed by a gradual decay in dynamic
level and spectral content might simply be classed as one more member of the
“percussion-resonance” family. But recording technology and the new conditions
of acousmatic listening can also defamiliarize our presuppositions and provide the
conditions for perceiving details of shape and color that can be exploited in music.
Thus, the classification and description of sound objects by means of typology and
morphology provide examples of how all sound material—the “sonorous”—has
potential for use in music. Furthermore, typology in particular also shows how
sound objects of long duration and unpredictable dynamic and spectral behavior
can lead to entirely new, previously “unheard,” musical languages. Sounds that are
common in contemporary music (both electroacoustic and orchestral), but that
theory often consigns to the periphery of music, can now be rehabilitated. In conjunction with the four listening modes we see yet again the sound object as the
conjunction between a given sonic event and human perception. Schaeffer proposed that if the Treatise were to be renamed, it should be called a Treatise on Listening. I can think of no better legacy for musicians, whether they are composers,
performers, or analysts seeking to learn about their art, than Schaeffer’s discussions on the listening modes.
The Treatise on Musical Objects, therefore, remains relevant despite its origins
in research initiated in the immediate postwar years. If Schaeffer’s suspicions
about received wisdom forced a reconsideration of musical materials, the inevitable corollary was to revisit that most basic tool of music making: the instrument.
By means of “characterology,” as outlined in the Treatise, musicians’ attention is
now shifted to how sound objects are grouped in families according to their inherent characteristics, as well as the listener’s perceptual predispositions. The physical
sound source, whether a traditional instrument or a new interface, is not repudiated. Instruments can now celebrate a “virtual” status and take an active role in
creating musical languages where source recognition fluctuates between the real
and the imaginary, between unambiguous recognition of causality and the
unknowable and mysterious.
If readers are willing to accept Schaeffer’s research program, there is much in the
Treatise that will encourage them to consider many musical practices and theories
in an entirely new light. But no book is perfect. Doubtless, our respect for Schaeffer’s intellect and integrity is obvious. We hope we are able to exercise sufficient
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 1/4/20 8:12 PM
xxxiv
Schaeffer’s Treatise and Music Theory
self-restraint to remain objective. Proselytizing is seldom appropriate in any introduction. If readers seek a broad sweep of contemporary music theory (which is, in
any case, not the book’s subject), I must confess they will have to accommodate
Schaeffer’s prejudices. His suspicions about “a priori” methods were touched on in
the opening paragraph. The writing of complex scores without aural verification,
algorithmic procedures, the use of chance, and, in particular, serial techniques
were targets of his disapproval. Many will agree with such comments, of course.
Moreover, his remarks were entirely consistent. Schaeffer recommended that
musicians work directly with sound, and as a result, any excessive reliance on
notation methods (necessary though they often are) before hearing the result can
be misleading. But this would imply that serial composers disregard the listening
process, and this is manifestly untrue. Schaeffer failed to recognize that serialism
is a collection of different techniques. There is no one type of serial thought. It is a
way of thinking about materials and their organization that must be reconsidered
and modified for each new composition. It developed constantly, and its effects are
still in evidence today (Formel-Komposition is one example). When used by composers such as Karlheinz Stockhausen, Pierre Boulez, and Henri Pousseur (none of
whom, it must be admitted, were particularly complimentary to Schaeffer’s
research), there are moments of real, even transcendental, beauty. But Schaeffer’s
comments are not gratuitous; they always support his arguments and illustrate the
consistent nature of his viewpoints. And this must be borne in mind while reading
this book. Schaeffer starts the Treatise with a lengthy quotation from E. T. A. Hoffmann. This romantic text seemed to encapsulate for Schaeffer the “dialogue . . .
between spirit and Nature” (11). Sounds are all around us in Nature. But it is human
beings who make them into music. Schaeffer wanted to alert us to the risk posed
by “a priori” thinking in this vital relationship. On the last page of the Treatise
Schaeffer uses the image of an archer whose real target is within himself. The Treatise on Musical Objects, therefore, is not a work that sets out a single music theory.
It investigates what Schaeffer called the “phenomenon of music,” the art that is
both scientific and sensory. The contemporary musician needs to understand
both.
John Dack
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 1/4/20 8:12 PM