EMPIRICAL STUDIES IN COMPARATIVE POLITICS
Empirical Studies in Comparative Politics
Edited by
MELVIN J. HINICH
University of Texas-Austin
and
MICHAEL C. MUNGER
Duke University
Reprinted from Public Choice, Volume 97, No.3, 1998
Springer-Science+Business Media, B.V.
A c.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress.
ISBN 978-1-4419-5072-7
ISBN 978-1-4757-5127-7 (eBook)
DOl 10.1007/978-1-4757-5127-7
Printed on acid-free paper
All rights reserved
©1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht
Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1998
No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or
utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical,
including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system,
without written permission from the copyright owner.
CONTENTS
MJ. Hinich and M.C. Munger, Empirical studies in comparative
politics
F.U. Pappi and G. Eckstein, Voters' party preferences in mUltiparty systems and their coalitional and spatial implications: Germany after unification
11
N. Schofield, AD. Martin, K.M. Quinn and AB. Whitford, Multiparty electoral competition in the Netherlands and Germany:
A model based on multinomial probit
39
S.E. Macdonald, G. Rabinowitz and O. Listhaug, Issue competition in the 1993 Norwegian national election
77
K.T. Poole and H. Rosenthal, The dynamics of interest group evaluations of Congress
105
J.W. Endersby and S.E. Galatas, British parties and spatial competition: Dimensions of party evaluation in the 1992 election
145
J.F-S. Hsieh and D. Lacy, Retrospective and prospective voting in
a one-party- dominant democracy: Taiwan's 1996 presidential
election
165
M.J. Hinich, M.e. Munger and S. de Marchi, Ideology and the
construction of nationality: The Canadian elections of 1993
183
M.M. Kaminski, G. Lissowski and P. Swistak, The "revival of
communism" or the effect of institutions?: The 1993 Polish parliamentary elections
211
J.K. Dow, A spatial analysis of candidate competition in dual
member districts: The 1989 Chilean senatorial elections
233
A.M.A van Deemen and N.P. Vergunst, Empirical evidence of
paradoxes of voting in Dutch elections
257
M. Myagkov and P.e. Ordeshook, The spatial character of Russia's new democracy
273
Public Choice 97: 219-227, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
219
Empirical studies in comparative politics
MELVIN J. HINICW & MICHAEL C. MUNGER 2
1Department of Government, University of Texas-Austin, Austin, TX 78712, U.S.A.; e-mail:
hinich@maiI.LA.utexas.edu; 2Department of Political Science, Duke University, Durham,
NC 27708, U.S.A.; e-mail: munger@acpub.duke.edu
The study of political science has been substantially transfonned by the work of public
choice scholars over the past 40 years ... [Butl public choice in political science is seen as an
offshoot, or related discipline, rather than as a substantive field in and of itself
(Dow and Munger, 1990: 604)
Nowhere in political science is the above statement truer than in the study
of comparative politics. There have been many publications by public choice
scholars, and many more by researchers who are at least sympathetic to the
public choice perspective. Yet little of this work has been integrated into the
main stream of comparative political science literature, and still less has made
its way onto graduate readings lists.
That is not to say there are not examples of successful recent works on the
interplay of economics and politics, because there are. Three notable examples come easily to mind: Verdier (1994), Haggard and Kaufman (1995), and
Bates (1997) have each made a substantial, and widely recognized, contribution in political science. However, this work is considered (and probably conceived) to be "international political economy", rather than comparative politics. In general, it is far more difficult to find examples of empirically oriented
studies of the politics, bureaucratic organization, and regulated economies of
particular nations in the canon of the comparativist.
This is not because there is no high quality work. Space limitations preclude a representative literature review, but public choice scholars have produced first rate, book-length studies on budgetary politics (Kraan, 1996),
coalition politics (Laver and Schofield, 1991; Shepsle, 1994), and voting
systems (Grofman and Lijphart, 1992; Cox, 1997). One difficulty, of course,
is that the attention within the public choice community to a genuinely comparative perspective is recent. Another is that empirical testing of comparative
models requires sources of data not as easily available as data on U.S. politics.
[ 1]
220
If these are the reasons that public choice has not yet had a significant impact
on political science, then it may just be a matter of time.
There is another problem, one that can be addressed immediately. The
scathing critique Green and Shapiro (1994) direct toward "rational choice"
focused on a lack of empirical testing. Now, it isn't true that public choiceoriented empirical research has never been published in comparative politics
journals (see, e.g., Cox and Niou, 1994; Lin et al., 1996; Montinola et al.,
1995; or Ordeshook and Shvetsova, 1997). But there hasn't been very much.
That is where this issue of Public Choice comes in.
In this special issue, the editors hope to make available to students of
comparative politics a compendium of work that meets two criteria: (1) In
every case, a model of human behavior or of institutional impact is specified.
(2) Also in every case, this model is confronted with data appropriate for
evaluating whether this model is useful for understanding politics in one or
more nations.
Theoretical framework
The political systems of the world exhibit many more differences than do
economic systems. This variation is both an opportunity and a trap. The fact
that political systems contrast so sharply represents a chance to "explain" the
differences. On the other hand, it is easy to get trapped into studying unimportant details, because it is by definition those characteristics of a polity that
are different that make it interesting. If one takes the conventional descriptive
approach to the study of political systems, one may never get beyond these
differences. After all, the null hypothesis has to be that each nation, at each
point in time, is unique, so that there are no useful generalizations.
To make real progress we need to quantify the similarities and differences
and build theories which go beyond simple correlations. Of course, political
scientists have recognized this since the 1950s, led by such works as Duverger
(1951) and Almond (1956). What we want to argue (humbly, we hope) is that
there is room for the contributions of public choice scholars in advancing
this program, and that the unique abilities of the public choice approach to
unify and generalize will make this contribution an important one. There have
been significant attempts at high-level synthesis already (see, e.g., Rowley
and Vachris, 1994; or Schneider, 1995), but this work has only indicated
a direction. We would like to provide a public choice view at the level of
nations, not of systems.
[2]
221
Organization of this issue
Three distinct factors characterize a nation's political system. These factors
are as follows:
•
•
•
Election procedures: The set of voting rules, in most cases a variant either of plurality or proportional representation. Each "variant", however,
has unique and perhaps unexpected properties.
Institutions and legislature: The rules that govern agenda formation and
voting methods in the legislature, and the relationships between an executive branch (if a separate entity exists) and the legislature.
Ideological cleavage: The collection of issues and cleavages that determine the nature of ideological conflict for that nation. Empirically, policy positions cluster, but the way that they cluster can differ dramatically
over space and time.
The first two of these are well-established as explananda in public choice
research; the third has received a great deal of attention in the last few years
(Hinich and Munger, 1994; Poole and Rosenthal, 1997). This spatial theory
of mass electoral competition implies that "issues" link with a small number of latent ideological dimensions. One dimension links with issues that
constrain the economic system. Another dimension links with issues which
determine the personal, or civil, freedoms. In some countries this cleavage is
over religious beliefs while in others it is more diffuse.
When national security issues loom large, there is another dimension linking with these security issues. In contemporary Israel, for example, the major
cleavage is about the political status of the Arab West Bank. Spatial theory
explains the revealed patterns of political preferences for ordinary votes and
elites. The structure allows a theorist to study how changes in voting rules
with determine outcome given a spatial configuration. Several of the papers in
this special issue show how spatial theory can be applied to study the politics
of different nations. We want to encourage other researchers, who may find
these results intriguing, to test and refine the claims made in these papers.
Papers in the special issue
Each of the first two papers uses a classic public choice approach: What if?
The first paper, by Franz Pappi and Gabriele Eckstein, asks a deceptively simple question: How should party preferences of voters in a multi-party system
be measured, compared, and aggregated? The paper has two parts, with the
[3]
222
first focusing on pairwise comparisons of parties from surveys of voters Pappi
and Eckstein derive implied coalition preferences, and find that if voters could
choose over coalitions, the actual governing coalition of CDU/CSU and FDP
is dominated by at least two other combinations of parties. The second part of
the paper analyzes the common structure of the party rankings. Interestingly,
though many voters do not fit the classical "left-right" ideological scale, there
exists no competing means of organizing a one-dimensional ordering of parties that correctly classifies more voters. Further, Pappi and Eckstein find that
what was West Germany is more "ideological", by this standard, than the
former East Germany.
Norman Schofield, Andrew Martin, Kevin Quinn, and Andrew Whitford
also use a "what if" approach, though their question focuses more on voter
choice among parties than on coalition outcomes. They want to know what if
voters had the preferences registered in the 1979 Euro-barometer surveys, and
European elite-study data, and parties chose positions so as to maximize vote
share. The paper incorporates both pre-election electoral estimation and postelection expectations about coalition formation. Schofield et al. show quite
convincingly that maximizing expected vote share is generally dominated
as a rational party strategy, and demonstrate further that the parties in the
Netherlands and Germany did not appear to follow such a strategy.
Every collection should contain a few dissenting voices. Stuart Macdonald, George Rabinowitz, and ala Listhaug advance a longstanding research
program, using "directional theory", in their study of the 1993 elections in
Norway. Long skeptical of proximity voting and the classical public choice
model, the authors find an interesting potential counterexample to their directional approach in the strong showing of a traditional centrist party, the aptly
named "Center Party", representing agrarian interests. Directional theory implies that voters ask two questions of a party or candidate: "Are you on my
side?" and "Are you responsible?" The results illustrate an interesting tension
in directional theory: To answer the first questions successfully, parties must
stake out strong positions and look for divisive "wedge" issues. But to answer
the second question, which has more to do with the ability to run the country,
parties must often converge toward the center, or toward expert opinion, on
many other issues. Macdonald et al. aver that the conventional wisdom about
the interplay of elections and governing may have it reversed: elections cause
conflict, but having to govern forces moderation and compromise.
Keith Poole and Howard Rosenthal also have a long-term, and very successful, research agenda. The paper they have contributed to this volume ties
up a loose end in this agenda, by considering interest group ratings, and the
implied shared (but latent) ideological dimension, as the product of a dynamic
data generating process. Using more than 200,000 observations by 59 interest
[4]
223
groups over the period 1959-1981, Poole and Rosenthal are able to demonstrate three results not found in any of their other work. First, the spatial
coordinates of the interest groups and members of the U.S. Congress can be
approximated as polynomial functions of time, otherwise showing surprising
consistency. Second, the first recovered ideological dimension accounts for
about three-quarters of the variance in group rating of members, with the
second dimension adding only about an additional five percent in variance
accounted for. Third, both interest groups and members of congress appear
to be logically, as well as temporally (see above) consistent: members and
groups are generally either liberal on both dimensions, or conservative on
both.
The next five papers are analyses of elections in Britain, Taiwan, Canada,
Poland, and Chile. James Endersby and Steven Galatas employ data from the
1992 British Election Study to analyze the factors that contribute to voter attitudes toward the Conservative and Labour parties. Many scholars of British
politics have claimed the foremost features of voters are partisan identification and social class. The 1992 election is a particularly interesting test
case, as it saw parties move more toward the ideological center of the British
electorate. Perceptions of the parties, however, are found by Endersby and
Galatas to be multidimensional, and to have more to do with issues than
traditional party identification would imply.
John Fuh-sheng Hsieh, Dean Lacy, and Emerson Niou ask a venerable
question (are voters prospective, or retrospective?) in an entirely new setting.
Taiwan is a fascinating context for a study of retrospective voting, as there
has been only one party (KMT, or Kuomintang) for the past five decades.
Only recently, in fact, has Taiwan even begun to held genuinely contested
elections, with the end of martial law and the lifting of many of the restrictions
on dissent and on freedom of the press. How will voters react? Hsieh et al.
present the first scholarly analysis of the 1996 election, and find voters appear
relatively more prospective in all of the statistically significant variables used
to predict vote choice, including managing the economy, ethnic relations,
domestic safety, and international security.
Melvin Hinich, Michael Munger, and Scott de Marchi examine the Canadian national election of 1993, trying to measure the changing ideological
context. Canadian politics has always been different, because Canada is a
combination of two very ditIerent cultures: the French-identifying Quebec,
and the British or aboriginal peoples in the rest of the nation. The main principle around which political conflict has been organized, at least since 1960,
has been regionalism-nationalism-continentalism. The debate over national
industrial policy, trade restrictions, and subsidies for agriculture and mining
have all been handled fairly well by this cleavage. However, the issue of
[5]
224
autonomy for, or even outright secession by Quebec, threatens the stability of
a national politics organized around a distributional or redistributional dimension. Hinich et al. find that attitudes toward Quebec sovereignty constitute a
coherent dimension of conflict, quite distinct from economic or social issues.
Further, they find that the Quebec sovereignty issue/dimension, alone, is capable of classifying more than three-quarters of the vote choice of Quebec
voters in supporting, or opposing, the increasingly powerful Bloc Quebeoise.
Marek Kaminski, Gregorz Lissowski, and Piotr Swistak analyze the 1993
Polish parliamentary elections. The continued electoral attractiveness of neocommunist parties seems surprising, given the strident, and nearly universal,
rejection of communism as a form of social organization in Poland in the
1980s. Using game theory as a simulation tool, Kaminsky et al. demonstrate
how sensitive the Polish electoral system is to small, even trivial, changes in
expressed preferences. Where some observers have attributed the resurgence
of post-communist candidates and candidates of the "Peasant Left" to a shift
back to the left by voters, Kaminski et al. argue that the size of the shift was
actually too small to have caused the electoral victory by the left, and that this
victory would not have happened if (1) previous election laws had still been
in place, or (2) the fractious parties of the Right had been more unified. The
authors conclude that the need for "fine-tuning" electoral institutions to avoid
exaggerated swings in partisan representation may be a generic problem in
developing democracies.
Jay Dow analyzes privately collected data on the 1989 Senate elections in
Chile. These elections use the d'Hondt system to choose two senators from
each district. This form of election rule appears to cause candidates on the
right to locate on the periphery of the space, and gives them few incentives
for more centrist positions. Dow also analyzes the apparent underlying ideological dimensions that organize political conflict in Chile, finding that one,
or at most two, latent dimensions characterized voter positions in the election.
Ad van Deemen and Noel Vergunst investigate the empirical occurrence of
two types of voting paradoxes in Dutch elections. The first type of paradox is
the Condorcet paradox, where a party a majority prefers to another party may
receive fewer seats, because no majority rule equilibrium exists. The second
type is the "majority-plurality" paradox, where a Condorcet winner exists,
but does not win a majority of seats because of the idiosyncrasies of voting
rules. Van Deemen and Vergunst illustrate the possibility of three alternative
majority-plurality paradoxes and seek evidence of the actual occurrence of
each type of paradox in the national elections held in the Netherlands in 1982,
1986, 1989 and 1994. In no case did the authors find an instance of a true
Condorcet paradox (i.e., the aggregate relation appears transitive), but they
did find that voting rules appeared to cause many cases of majority-plurality
[6]
225
paradoxes. The most frequent type of voting paradox they found was the type
where a party which would receive a majority against another party gets fewer
seats as a result of the actual multi-party election.
Misha Myagkov and Peter Ordeshook, the final paper in the collection,
investigate the broad outlines of political conflict in Russia. The authors note
that previous research on Russian elections has used an approach similar to
that employed in the U.S. in the 1950s and 1960, focusing on attitudes toward
candidates or self-reported participation histories. Myagkov and Ordeshook
seek to identify the issues, and candidate locations, in a spatial context, using county (rayon) level data. The primary issue in Russian political conflict
continues to be beliefs about "reform", with a potential second main dimension, "nationalism", so far having only limited power to organize opinion in
the electorate. The most interesting intercandidate contest the authors identify is between Lebed (pro-reform, mildly nationalist) and Zhirinovsky (antireform, and virulently nationalist). If this type of conflict becomes dominant,
the stability of an electoral system built around the reform issue may be
questionable.
Each of these papers offers evidence on at least one, and in many cases
two, of our differentiating factors election rules, legislative institutions, and
ideological cleavage. While the papers reach no consensus, there is an impressive array of theory and evidence brought to bear on these differentiating
factors. We thank the authors for their impressive contributions.
Conclusion
In closing, it should be noted without equivocation that we reject Green and
Shapiro's (1994) claim that empirical testing is privileged as an epistemological basis for understanding, as this is clearly a confused view of the
philosophy of science. It is possible, however, that Green and Shapiro are
right for the wrong reasons: public choice studies of comparative politics
must build a record of success in both prediction and prescription if this work
is to be recognized as a useful model of theorizing. Peter Ordeshook makes
a comparison between science (identifying first principles) and engineering
(solving practical problems), and claims we have too many "scientists" and
too few "engineers" for the rational choice approach to have much relevance
to world politics. We may have learned some things about voting systems, but
little has been done to make this learning available to people struggling with
the problem of reforming a political system, or designing a new democracy.
Unfortunately, there are profoundly important problems that require our
attention: designing a stable democratic federalism for Russia or Ukraine,
[7]
226
understanding the nature of strategic threats in Central Europe, and formulating viable political constitutions nearly everywhere. Such matters
are, at present, mostly the purview of politicians and pundits. With some
notable exceptions, political scientists have reserved for themselves the
role of bystanders who merely describe or offer after-the-fact explanations. Of course, one might object to this characterization by noting that,
as political scientists, our job is merely to develop theoretical propositions
and methodologies that can assist those who act. But we cannot do the job
if we are unwilling to take the bits and pieces of theory and methodology
available to us and propose alternative institutional designs and constitutional structures as solutions to specific problems (Ordeshook, 1996:
187-188).
In closing, then, let us echo Ordeshook's challenge. Some bridges stand,
and some planes fly. Engineers have applied theoretical principles to these
practical problems, and solved them. Public choice scholars know a lot about
why some governments work, but all too little attention has been focused on
the solution of practical problems in other nations. In this volume, we have
gathered a collection of papers analyzing the political systems of ten nations.
It is our hope that this work will provoke a self-conscious effort to compare,
and investigate, the public choice of comparative politics.
References
Almond, G. (1956). Comparative political systems. Journal of Politics 18: 391-409.
Bates, R. (1997). Open economy politics: The political economy of the World Coffee Trade.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cox, G. (1997). Making votes count: Strategic coordination in the world's electoral systems.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Cox, G. and Niou, E. (1994). Seat bonuses under the single nontransferable vote system:
Evidence from Japan and Taiwan. Comparative Politics 26: 221-235.
Dow, J. and Munger, M. (1990). Public choice in political science: We don't teach it, but we
publish it. PS 23: 604-610.
Duverger, M. (1951). Political parties: Their organization and activity in the modern state.
London: Methuen.
Green, D. and Shapiro, 1. (1994). The pathologies of rational choice theory: A critique of
applications in political science. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Grofman, B. and Lijphart, A. (1992). Parliamentary versus presidential government. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Haggard, S. and Kaufman, R. (1995). The political economy of democratic transitions.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hinich, M. and Munger, M. (1994). Ideology and the theory of political choice. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Kraan, D.-J. (1996). Budgetary decisions: A public choice approach. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
[8]
227
Laver, M. and Schofield, N. (1991). Multiparty government: The political of coalition in
Europe. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lin, T.-M., Chu, Y.-H. and Hinich, MJ. (1996). Conflict displacement and regime transition
in Taiwan: A spatial analysis. World Politics 48: 453-481.
Montinola, G., Qian, Y. and Weingast, B. (1995). Federalism, Chinese style: The political
basis of economic success in China. World Politics 48: 50-81.
Ordeshook, P.C. (1996). Engineering or science: What is the study of politics? In J. Friedman
(Ed.), The rational choice controversy, 175-188. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Ordeshook, P.e. and Shvetsova, O. (1997). Federalism and constitutional design. Journal of
Democracy 8: 27-42.
Poole, K. and Rosenthal, H. (1997). Congress: A political economic history of roll-call voting.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Rowley, C.K. and Vachris, M.A. (1994). Why democracy does not necessarily produce
efficient results. Journal of Public Finance and Public ChoicelEconomia Delle Scelte
Pubbliche 12: 95-111.
Schneider, F. (1995). Is there a European public choice perspective? Kyklos 48: 289-296.
Shepsle, K. (1994). Cabinet ministers and parliamentary government. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Verdier, D. (1994). Democracy and international trade. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
[9]
Public Choice 97: 229-255, 1998.
229
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Voters' party preferences in multiparty systems and their
coalitional and spatial implications: Germany after unification
FRANZ URBAN PAPPI & GABRIELE ECKSTEIN
University of Mannheim, Department of Political Science I, P.O. Box, D-68131 Mannheim,
Germany; e-mail: fupappi@sowi.uni-mannheim.de;geckstein@sowi.uni-mannheim.de
Abstract. How should party preferences of voters in a multiparty system be measured,
compared and aggregated? We use city block metric of distances between the pairwise comparisons of the five German parties (1995 survey data for West and East Germany). Neither in
West nor in East Germany, a party gains the absolute majority of voters' preferences. We derive
coalition preferences from the party rankings; the governing coalition of CDU/CSU and FDP
is not the winner, compared with other feasible coalitions of the German party system. But
the party rankings of the CDU/CSU-FDP coalition leaners are more homogeneous than other
groups of coalition leaners. In the second part of the article, we analyze the common structure
of all consistent party rankings. Do voters apply the same criteria to evaluate the political
parties? Although only a slight majority of individual rankings fit the often used ideological
left-right scale, there does not exist a competing one-dimensional order of the parties that
would capture more voters. The joint scale of individual party rankings is interpreted as the
collective order which facilitates political orientation of voters. This collective order is more
pronounced in West than in East Germany where individuals are almost as consistent in their
party rankings but where the rankings fit the collective order less well than in West Germany.
1. Introduction
In parliamentary systems with proportional representation and multiple parties, the prime minister and his or her cabinet are normally dependent on the
support and confidence of more than one parliamentary party. These coalition
governments are formed anew after each election in which voters choose
parties and not coalitions or governments. Coalitional options are discussed
during election campaigns, but not all options turn out to be feasible once
the election:s returns become known. Contrary to two-party parliamentary
systems, the electorate's signals for a new government are ambiguous, giving the party leaders some leeway in coalition bargaining. But in modern
democracies with structured party systems and attentive publics, there also
exist restraints for the coalition game. As far as parties are policy seeking,
they look for coalition partners close to them in policy or ideological terms.
On the other hand, the re-election motive of politicians guarantees that party
[ 11 ]
230
leaders will seldom act contrary to what they have promised during the election campaign. In order to fulfill most of their promises, parties not only have
to enter a winning coalition, but they have to reach a coalition agreement that
puts the promised policies on the government agenda. The construction of
policy spaces (cf. Laver and Hunt, 1992) is a very helpful tool to predict the
party composition of coalition governments (cf. Laver and Schofield, 1990;
Schofield, 1995), since distance in these spaces indicates the difficulties in
reaching agreements.
What makes policy spaces even more attractive is the Downsian assumption of parties competing for votes in those spaces, trying to find optimallocations under given distributions of voters' ideal points (Downs, 1957; Enelow
and Hinich, 1984; Shepsle, 1991). Students of European multiparty systems
picked up the Downsian spatial framework first of all for descriptive purposes: What is the ideological party space underlying sympathy ratings of
parties (cf. for Germany Norpoth, 1979; Pappi, 1973, 1983). How do national
electorates perceive the positions of their parties on a self-anchoring leftright scale and what is the shape of voters' self placements on this same
scale (Inglehart and Klingemann, 1976). What is the predictive power of the
distance between a voter's ideal point and the perceived party positions on a
self-anchoring left-right scale for party preference (van der Eijk, Franklin and
Oppenhuis, 1996: 354)? Concepts as the equilibrium position of parties or of
the electoral heart (Schofield, 1993) are not strictly applied in empirical studies, but some authors have systematically analyzed the relationships between
changes of party positions and voter reactions (cf. Nannestad, 1994).
A strict empirical application of spatial models to determine party positions and voter ideal points aiming finally at good predictions of voting
behavior has to be based on a correctly specified statistical model. Hinich and
his collaborators have proposed factor analytic techniques to identify latent
ideological dimensions with either party sympathy scores or perceptions of
party positions on a set of issue scales as input (cf. Enelow and Hinich, 1984:
207-215). We applied both approaches to German data, with mixed results.
The two-dimensional configuration of parties is very robust and the first and
most important dimension is easy to interpret as a socio-economic left-right
dimension (cf. Pappi, 1990, 1992; Eckstein, 1995). But the predictive power
of the distance between a voter's bliss point and his or her closest party for
electoral choice is poor, the wrong predictions running up to 50%. For party
sympathy scores we are able to improve the model fit by adding a nonpolitical
factor as suggested by Enelow and Hinich (1984: 82-90): competence to
rule the country. This factor favors the two larger parties of the Christian
Democrats (CDU/CSU) and Social Democrats (SPD) being the ones whose
leaders are perceived as candidates for chancellorship. Even then, however,
[12]
231
the necessary second ideological dimension raises problems of interpretation.
As our analyses of the perceptions of party positions on issue scales show, a
major problem is population heterogeneity. The assumption of a common
ideological space may be violated for larger subgroups whose judgements
are based on a different - one-dimensional - view of the party system. The
result would be a two-dimensional space at the aggregate level, consisting of
the combination of the one-dimensional views of two population subgroups.
On the other hand, experts (cf. Laver and Hunt, 1992) do indeed diagnose
a two-dimensional space for Germany, due mainly to the liberal party (Free
Democrats, FDP) with its position right of the CDU in socio-economic terms
and in-between CDU and SPD in other domestic policies: law and order issues, abortion and similar issues sometimes categorized as social issues (cf.
Enelow and Hinich, 1984: 182-205). In this case, the two dimensions result
from different party locations on two ideological or issue dimensions, as more
or less unanimously perceived by the same voters.
In this paper, we shall use an alternative route to learn about the coalitional and spatial implications of voters' party ratings or rankings focusing on
overall party preferences and not on issue perceptions or issue preferences.
We will not accept the available data as input for statistical data reduction
techniques, but we shall first test the preference judgements of East and West
German respondents for individual consistency, and then aggregate only the
consistent party preferences to study the coalition leanings of these respondents and we shall then construct party spaces analytically starting from consistent party rankings as opposed to statistical data reduction. Aggregating
individual preferences leads to a social choice which, under specific conditions, can be compared with the policy position of the coalition government
negotiated by the party leaders.
2. The party preference concept and its measurement
Party preference is often used as a self-evident concept which has not to be
defined. We depart from this practice and explicate our usage of the concept
both in substantive and measurement terms.
We assume that citizens evaluate parties all the time and that the results of
this ongoing process at a specific point in time are the actual party preferences
of these citizens. This is why party preference questions are always meaningful, irrespective of whether an election is upcoming or we are in the middle of
the legislative period. Evaluations can be based on different criteria, on policy
preferences, ideologies, impressions about the party's performance in government, characteristics of party leaders etc. Whenever political messages have
party cues, the citizens add and substract evaluation points from the accounts
[13 ]
232
they have for the parties. Fiorina (1981: 84) used this idea to reconceptualize
party identification as a "running tally of retrospective evaluations of party
promises and performance".
Transferring this idea to multiparty systems, calls specific attention to two
points:
(1) Each party must have a separate account, so that the plus point for one
party is not automatically a minus point for the other party, and
(2) the evaluation criteria for the different parties need not necessarily be
the same. We shall have to come back to this point when we discuss
consistent preferences and, later, their spatial implications.
Conventional measures of party preference in multiparty systems are often
incomplete due to the restriction of asking only for one most preferred party.
The frequently used alternative of rating the sympathy towards each party
separately, asks for a special criterion of party evaluation and has the disadvantages of measurement by fiat. The assumption of equal intervals cannot be
tested, one has to assume that the respondents used the scales consistently. We
rely instead on paired comparisons between the parties, asking each respondent which of each pair of parties she prefers or whether he is indifferent.
With these data we are able to construct a preference relation over a set of
parties, resulting at least in a weak ordering of the parties.
The elements of a set are weakly ordered if the pairwise preference relations between the elements are reflexive, complete and transitive. A linear or
strict order satisfies the same conditions and is, in addition, antisymmetric,
allowing no ties between elements (cf., e.g., van Deemen, 1991). In our case,
the elements are political parties and the reflexive, complete and transitive
preferences between the parties are those of individual citizens. Restricting
our analysis to the subset of respondents with weak or strict preference orders
leads to the classical social choice problem of how to aggregate the set or
profile of individual preferences to get a collective choice. In this article, we
are not interested in voting systems; we shall use, however, the aggregation
results of different procedures as information about the support level of single
parties and party coalitions within the electorate and as evidence of the dominant policy dimension at a specific period. For this latter purpose, we shall
apply a city block metric of distances between strict and/or weak preference
orders (Kemeny and Snell, 1963: 9-23) and the notion of betweenness of
preferences to recover linear profiles (van Deemen, 1991: 194-204).
A preference order can be represented in a dominance matrix A with i (i =
1,2 ... m) rows and j (j = 1,2... m) columns, i and j indexing the parties, and an
entry of aij = 1 if party i is preferred to j, aij =-1 if j dominates (is preferred
[ 14 ]
233
=
to) i, and aij 0 for indifference. Then Kemeny and Snell define the following
distance function, in the literature also known as Hamming distance function
(cf. van Deemen, 19991: 194-196), between two preferences or dominance
matrices A and B.
.
dlstance(A, B) =
1
"2
L I aij - bijl
ij
For a group of people, their median preference or consensus ranking is the
one to which the sum of distances is a minimum, and the heterogeneity of
their preferences can be computed analogously to the mean path distance of
a weighted graph. Let d ij be the distance between preference i (i = 1,2... m)
and j (j = 1,2 ... m) and fi and fj indicate the respective frequencies of these to
preferences (2:: fi = 2:: fj = n), then heterogeneity (h) of the preferences of
this group of n people is defined as follows:
h=
L L d lJj/n
i
2
i
We shall use this measure to characterize the heterogeneity of various
groups of coalition supporters.
The last building block we need for our analysis is the concept of a linear
profile, that is a set of individual preferences which can be combined to form
a path. Following van Deemen's proof (1991: 201), we only exemplify the
concept, with preferences for three parties a, b, c, and four voters (see Table
1).
For three parties, a strict preference consists of three ordered couples, the
set of voter 1 being e.g. {<a,b>,<a,c>,<b,c>}. The preference relation of this
voter is between that of voter 2 and that of voter 4, since his or her ordered
couples are a subset of the union of the sets of voters 2 and 4 and the intersection of these two sets {<a,c>} is a subset of the set of voter 1 (definition
7.9 in van Deemen, 1991: 200). A simple rule to verify betweenness is the
addition rule for the respective distances (van Deemen's theorem 7.2), for our
example:
=
A linear profile then consists of preferences i, j, k 1,2 ... n and i ::: j ::: k such
that j is in-between i and k (van Deemen's definition 7.10). The other linear
profiles of our example are shown in Table I: 2 is in-between 1 and 3, 4 is
in-between 1 and 3. But all four preferences cannot be combined to form a
linear profile.
[ 15]
234
Table 1. Examples of linear profiles for four voters {1,2,3,4} and three parties {a,b,c}
Preferences
Distances
1
2
Voter 1:
a>-b>-c
1
0
2
Voter 2:
b>-a>-c
2
Voter 3:
c>-b>-a
3
Voter 4:
a>-c>-b
4
2
6
2
Linear profiles
4
0
3
6
4
4
4
0
4
4
4
0
2
Corresponding joint party scale
2
distances
4
2
3
4
2
voters
midpoints
a
voters 1
alb
a: c
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
I
b:e
b
, 2 ,
I
I
I
I
I
I
,
3
distances
no joint scale
3 voters
4
2
2
4
I _____________
4
2
distances
J
no joint scale
3 voters
If the preferences forming a linear profile end up in only two least-preferred
parties, not only the preferences but also the parties can be arranged on a
straight line. This is Coombs (1964) unfolding idea for one dimension, exemplified by the joint scale a, b, c corresponding to the linear profile of the set of
voters {I ,2,3 }. The ideal point of voter 1 is somewhere left of the midpoint
between a and b on the joint scale. Voter 2 already went across this midpoint
resulting in a preferences with b as the closest party, then a and c being last.
Going further right on the joint scale, the next midpoint is the one between a
and c. Once we go across this midpoint, we get a preference which is missing
in our example: b :>- c :>- a. It would be in-between voter 2 and 3, not violating
the linear profile, since it has a distance of 2 to both 2 and 3. We shall use the
concept of linear profiles and its correspondence with unfolding to derive
spatial implications of party preferences in multiparty systems.
Distinguishing between weak and strict preference and indifference, in
empirical studies one has to decide which preference judgements the respondents have to make. They Can be asked whether party a is at least as good
[16]
235
for them as party b (weak preference) for all ordered pairs of parties, that is
both the pair a, b, and the pair b, a. We have chosen the other alternative
and asked the respondents whether they (strictly) prefer a to b, b to a or
whether they are indifferent, restricting the pairs to be nonredundant dyads.
The burden of proof for consistent judgements rests on the indifference relation, since respondents are supposed to distinguish between indifference
between two known parties, noncomparability, and lack of knowledge which
should prevent a judgement (cf. Fishburn, 1970: 12). Thus a direct question
concerning indifference may overestimate the completeness of the answers
because respondents hesitate to admit their unfamiliarity with specific parties.
But the transitivity of judgements can be tested, both for strict preference and
for indifference.
We will analyze paired comparison data on the preferences of West and
East German respondents concerning give parties. The parties are the Christian Democrats (CDU together with its Bavarian sister party CSU), the Social
Democrats (SPD), the Free Democrats (FDP), the united party of The Greens
and Biindnis '90, the latter being a branch of the opposition movement of
the late GDR, and the Democratic Socialists (PDS) as the offspring of the
former East German governing communist party. These five parties hold all
the seats in the Federal Parliament (Bundestag) of the 13th legislative period,
for which Kohl was elected chancellor by the Christian Democrats (294 seats)
and the Free Democrats (47 seats). The SPD is the largest opposition party
(252 seats) with the Greens as its future possible ally (49 seats). The PDS has
its strong hold almost exclusively in East Germany, i.e., within only a fifth of
the all-German electorate, and its small share of seats in the Bundestag (30)
makes it a dummy player.
The field work for our survey was in December 1995, 14 months after the
1994 federal election. The East German electorate was oversampled resulting
in 951 respondents with valid data, compared to the 1900 respondents of the
West German representative sample.
An important precondition for our research agenda is a substantial amount
of consistent or rational respondents with transitive and complete party rankings. American studies report figures between 73 and 81 % of respondents
coming up with transitive orderings of five presidential candidates. Radcliff
(1993) identified 73% of the 1980 electorate who had to rank five presidential
candidates, whereas Brady and Ansolabehere (1989) asked only adult Californians who were either Democrats or Independents about the preferences
for five Democratic presidential aspirants in 1976. We expected a higher figure than the 73% of Radcliff (1993), at least for the West German electorate,
since we assumed that voters are more familiar with parties as permanent
players in politics than with candidates who come and go.
[ 17]
236
The percentage of Germans with incomplete or intransitive preferences is
within the range expected from the American studies. In West Germany, only
20.5% belong to this group, coming close to the California study of a more
politically involved group than the general electorate (see Table 2). The East
German figure is higher (27.9%), indicating less familiarity with the party
system whose major parts were imported from West Germany. In addition,
the East German come up with significantly less strict orders between the
five parties than the West Germans (27.5% compared to 37.2%). Tied ranks
between parties are especially prone to end up in intransitivities since it is
well known that people have difficulties with the equivalence relation for
indifference judgements (cf. e.g., Brady and Ansolabehere, 1989). The most
common error is to be indifferent between party a and band band c, but not,
as it would be necessary for transitivity, between a and c. When a, band c
follow each other on a policy scale, one may doubt whether the above example of an intransitivity is an error at all, since the sum of two small intervals
may be beyond the threshold of the just discernible differences whereas the
two smaller distances are not. And with an increasing number of ties, errors
of this type increase, too (cf. Brady and Ansolabehere, 1989: 144). Thus,
the outstanding result about the East Germans is the smaller percentage of
respondents with a complete ranking of the five parties and not that they seem
to be less rational voters in the first place.
The percentage of voters ranking all five parties alike is almost the same
in both parts of Germany (10%). Sometimes, this category is used as an indicator of political alienation whose level would then be equal in East and
West Germany, too. We will omit the respondents of this category and the
ones with intransitive and incomplete rank orders in most of the following
analyses. The other respondents were able to come up with a weak or strict
ordering of five parties, and one reason why they are able to do that is that
they could economize the criteria used to evaluate the parties. Doing that as
individuals, the range of criteria within the electorate as a whole may still be
rather broad and heterogeneous.
People have a tendency to be much more indifferent between low than
high ranked parties. A little more than one-fourth of all respondents evaluated
the last four, three or two parties alike. And among these parties, the smaller
parties FDP, Greens or PDS are overrepresented, either in combinations comprising only small parties or paired with one of the two larger parties, the FDP
with the CDU or the SPD with both the Greens and the PDS (see footnotes
of Table 2). The two larger parties CDU and SPD are never tied at the bottom
end of the individual preference scales. This is a first hint of two political
cleavages running through the German party system, one between left and
[18]
237
Table 2. Types of party preferences of the West and East German electoratea
Preference order
Linear
West Germany
East Germany
%
%
37.2
27.5
Weak
Ties between two last parties
6.4b
Ties between last three parties
Ties between last four parties
Other types of ties, except
8.5c
1I.5d
lO.od
6.1
9.8
20.5
6.3
10.5
27.9
1900
951
TIes between all parties
Intransitive or incomplete
preferences
n
9.4b
79.5
72.1
8.4c
a Representative samples of West and East Germans eligible to vote (18 years and older,
German citizenship); field work December 1995.
b The three most frequent combinations are GreensIPDS, FDPIPDS and CDUIFDP, summing up to 85% in West and 87% in East Germany, with GreensIPDS alone amounting to
43% in West and CDUIFDP alone amounting to 65% in East Germany.
c The two most frequent West German combinations are SPD/GreensIPDS (33%) and
CDUIFDPIPDS (35%), whereas the East German combinations are more equally distributed.
d The two most frequent combinations in the West are SPDIFDP/GreensIPDS (47%) and
CDUIFDP/GreensIPDS (38%), whereas the East Germans distribute their first preference
more equally between the parties, with the exception of the FOP.
right parties and one between small and large parties. We shall come back to
this point when we discuss the spatial implications of party preferences.
3. Aggregating individually consistent party preferences
Monitoring public opinion and observing the strengths within the electorate is
nowadays a routine job of pollsters working for governments, party headquarters and the mass media. In Germany, the figures regularly reported are the
marginals of a vote intention question: If we had a Bundestag election next
Sunday, which party would you vote for? We present an overview of the vote
intentions in West and East Germany, first, for all respondents, and second, for
the subsets of consistent respondents with whose distribution we compare the
percentages of first ranked parties (see Table 3). In West and East Germany,
the Christian Democrats are ahead of their major rival, the Social Democrats,
even at a lower level in the East due to the remarkable third party status there
[ 19]
238
Table 3. Vote intentions and highest ranked parties of West and East German respondents
Vote intention
Party of first preference
All respondents
Respondents with consistent party rankings
West East
West
East
West
East
%
%
%
%
%
%
CDU/CSU
37.1
30.9
39.4
32.5
40.1
30.0
SPD
33.9
23.2
32.2
22.1
31.5
19.2
FDP
2.7
0.7
2.8
0.9
2.7
1.9
B'90lGreens
9.4
9.1
8.8
9.5
10.3
11.0
PDS
0.7
17.3
0.5
18.4
0.6
20.5
14.8
17.5
1511
684
Parties
Other parties
No vote intention/no answer
1.3
3.3
1.2
2.6
14.7
15.5
15.1
14.0
First preference tied
N
1900 951
1511
684
of the former communist party. The differences between vote intention and
most preferred party are small, even if East Germans have a slight tendency
to rank the PDS, Greens and FDP a little bit higher than expected from their
vote intentions.
A first past the post voting system would very likely guarantee the CDU a
majority of seats in parliament, turning the opposition role almost exclusively
to the Social Democrats as the other major party, at least in West Germany.
Proportional representation complicates the aggregation of preferences, especially if we keep in mind the necessity to form coalition governments. In this
section, we will first ask how robust the leading position of the CDU would
be under various aggregation devices apart from counting first preferences
before we discuss coalition learnings of West and East Germans.
It is well known that different aggregation devices may result in different
collective choices. We tum this theoretical insight around and argue, that, empirically, the leading position of a party within a multiparty system is robust
if this position is corroborated by various voting systems, starting from the
same individual party preferences. One could coin the phrase "robust plurality
winner" for a party with more first preferences than the other parties, if this
same party is also the Condorcet winner and the number one according to the
Borda rule.
[20 ]
239
The Condorcet winner is the party which beats all other parties in pairwise
contests. Assuming that respondents who are indifferent between two parties
will abstain from this pairwise contest, the Condorcet winner is the pairwise
majority party, and, therefore, a strong candidate as the leading party in a
democracy. The problem of this system of majority decision (cf. van Deemen,
1991: 64) is that this solution does not always exist because of voting cycles.
The Borda count is a positional procedure which is computed as the mean
rank of each party. Black has outlined this procedure even for the special case
of tied ranks for which he recommends the adjusted Borda count instead of
the original one (1987: 61-64). Its operational definition is the number of
dominated parties, i.e., parties ranked lower than the focal party, minus the
number of parties dominating the focal one. With five parties, the resulting
scale has a maximum of +4 and a minimum of -4.
In Table 4, we have computed the percentage differences between the
respective row and column parties as an evidence for the Condorcet winner,
showing at the same time that the relatively high percentage of indifferent
respondents (see lower triangle of table) do not hinder the existence of a
Condorcet winner. The percentages of indifferent respondents between the
respective party pairs show the pattern which we have already discussed in
Section 2 and which is most clearly observable in West Germany. The number of indifferent respondents is lowest when the two larger parties have to
be compared, i.e., the Christian Democrats and the Social Democrats. The
percentage of indifferent respondents increases when we compare one of the
two larger parties with one of the three smaller parties and this percentage
is the highest for comparisons among the group of smaller parties. From this
pattern, we learn that there must be many respondents whose party system
consists mainly of a comparison of the two major parties whereas they are
indifferent between some or all of the minor parties.
The pairwise majority party in Table 4 (upper triangle) has minus signs in
its column and plus signs in its row starting from the main diagonal and going
to the right. In West Germany, this criterion fits the CDU pattern, whereas in
East Germany the SPD is the Condorcet winner, thereby surpassing the CDU
as the plurality winner. The margin in favor of the SPD is 7.4 percentage
points; this is not trivial, compared to the smaller difference of 3.5 percentage
points in West Germany, this time in favor ofthe CDU/CSU.
When we now add the insights of the Borda count, we are confronted with
even more deviations from the position of a robust plurality winner, a role, we
had hypothesized, the CDU could play in both parts of Germany. According
to the adjusted Borda count, the SPD is the winner in both parts of Germany,
as a party, we might add, which has much less enemies (Le., respondents who
rank it last) than the CDU.
[21 ]
240
Table 4. Difference of pairwise choice between row and column partya and percentage
of consistently indifferent respondentsb
West Germany
Adjusted
Against
PDS
For:
PDS
B ' 90/Greens
Borda
B ' 90/Greens
SPD
CDUlCSU
FDP
count
-57.9
-69.5
-57.2
-46.8
-2.31
-40.4
-lS.l
4.3
0.04
30.0
1.37
35.7
-3.5
SPD
26.3
25.4
CDU/CSU
25.3
20.1
17.1
FDP
35.1
28.5
23.4
3S.S
27.9
East Germany
Adjusted
Against
PDS
For:
PDS
B '90/Greens
Borda
B '90/Greens
SPD
CDU
-10.2
-21.2
-8.3
-lS.7
32.8
SPD
27.2
27.9
CDU
23.6
23.1
23.4
FDP
33.1
34.0
29.5
a
b
l.18
-0.26
FDP
count
9.6
-0.30
-0.1
29.8
-0.21
7.4
4S.1
0.95
31.9
0.34
-1.19
39.7
Upper triangle: Percentage of row party choice minus percentage of column
party choice in pairwise comparison of consistent respondents (n-West = 1511,
n-East = 684).
Lower triangle: Percentage of indifferent respondents between respective party
pairs.
This pattern is quite interesting for East Germany, where about one-fifth
of the voters rank the SPD highest, and another fifth the PDS. But according
to the Borda count, the SPD is the party with the best result, whereas the
PDS is more dominated by other parties than being itself the dominating
party (negative Borda count). A glimpse at the percentages of East Germans
ranking each party last helps to explain the results of the Borda count. Even in
East Germany, 20% of the respondents rank the PDS last, compared to only
1% for the SPD and 9% for the CDO. This makes it plausible that the SPD
is the Borda winner, a victory which is not very convincing since it is more
based on a lack of opponents than on a plurality of aficionados.
Thus, coming out as a plurality winner from a proportional election does
not guarantee a strong leading position in a multiparty system. The political
[22]
241
interpretation of an election result or of the marginals of vote intention question becomes even more difficult when possible coalition governments have
to be taken into account. The addition of the percentages of two parties is just
not enough if one is interested in coalition support within the electorate (cf.
Downs, 1957: 147 ff.). Concerning coalition support, we argue that the consistent supporters of a coalition are those respondents who rank the respective
coalition parties higher than any of the opposition parties. Thus, irrespective
of the coalitional options being discussed by political elites and the mass
media, we derive a measure of coalition support from the frequencies of the
two highest-ranked parties in voters' consistent party preferences. To avoid
misunderstandings, we term this derived measure coalition leaning, distinguishing it from an outspoken coalition preference which may be formed
during an election campaign. Shortly before elections, parties argue in favor
of specific coalitions and many voters form a specific coalition preference
which they reveal if asked directly. These coalition preferences are formed
with respect to feasible coalitions, i.e., coalitions which have a chance to win
the necessary majority and which are at the same time not excluded explicitly
by the respective parties. With this background of information, the individual
voter can form a coalition preference and choose a party or two parties on
election day (Germany has a two-ballot system), thereby hoping to increase
the probability that the preferred coalition will indeed be formed. What we
call coalition leaning is a measure derived from the ranking of parties in one's
party preference which should have an impact on coalition preference, but
which is meaningful in itself, especially in-between elections, when coalition
possibilities are not publicly discussed. Coalition leaning is supposed to be
the support infrastructure of the logically possible coalitions which well restrict in the following to all possible two-party coalitions, omitting coalitions
of three or more parties.
With five parties, ten two-party coalitions are possible, and even if each
party is a member of four coalitions, so that the participating parties overlap between coalitions, the consistent supporters of the ten coalitions form
disjunct and complete subsets of all those respondents with clear first and
second party preferences, ties for the two top parties included. A second
set of respondents strictly prefers one of the five parties to all others, but
is indifferent between some of the other four parties so that the second rank
is already involved. This criterion leads to another five disjunct subsets of
respondents with a larger than usual distance between the first and the other
parties. This is the set of the one party adherents. A third set consists then of
respondents for whom we cannot tell which one or two parties are at the top of
the preference order. Empirically, these are overwhelmingly respondents who
are indifferent between all five parties. We omit this third set when we now
[23 ]
242
identify the consistent supporters of the ten different two-party coalitions.
These respondents consist first of all of the ten subsets of the first set and
then the five subsets of the second set. The latter respondents do not have
consistent coalition preferences, since they concentrate their party choices
more than the first group on a single party.
The simplest aggregation mechanism is to identify the plurality winner
among the possible two-party coalitions. In Table 5, the total percentages of
the ten possible two-party coalitions and the five groups of one-party-Ieaners
are presented both for West and East Germany. The outstanding result for
West Germany is the concentration of the two top ranked parties to only three
possible two-party coalitions, first of all the coalition between the Social Democrats and the Greens (25.7%), second the coalition between the CDU and
the FDP (22.9%) which is the governing coalition at the time of the field work,
and third the coalition between CDU and SPD (19.4%). All other coalitions
would be rather implausible due to the usual vote shares of the parties in
general elections. The East Germans do not favor these latter coalitions, even
if we have data only on party preferences and thereby coalition leanings and
not on actual coalition preferences which may be more influenced by realistic
expectations about the feasible coalitions.
The East Germans deviate from the West German pattern, since they disperse their coalition leanings much more than the West Germans. Their coalition leanings are less constrained by their realistic coalitional alternatives, i.e.,
those possible two-party coalitions which can be expected to gain majority
support. The plurality winner in East Germany would be the CDU/SPDcoalition with 18.4%, followed by a coalition of the Greens and the former
communists with 15.3%, then a coalition between SPD and Greens (13.1 %),
and finally a coalition between the Social Democrats and the former communists (12.4%). The governing coalition in the federal capital is placed only at
rank 5 (9.3%).
What do these relative frequencies of groups of coalition leaners mean
for elections when coalition leanings get transformed into coalition preferences? Even if not all respondents will form a specific coalition preference,
a more or less large subset will form such preferences and in this process,
political communication among citizens is important. We argue that a second
important aspect of coalition leaning, besides, its relative frequency among
the population, is the political homogeneity of the supporters measured in
terms of a consensus concerning the ranks of all parties and not only the top
two. Even if two respondents rank the SPD and the Greens first and second,
they can disagree more or less with respect to the parties ranked third, fourth
and fifth, and with respect to the ordering of the coalition parties. In a dynamic
system, citizens continually evaluate parties and a coalition will gain extra
[24 ]
243
Table 5. Two-party coalition pluralities and percentages of single party
preference profiles a
West Germany
CDU/CSU
SPD
FDP
CDU/CSU
SPD
FDP
B'90/Greens
PDS
9.2
19.4
22.9
4.1
0.1
2.0
19.4
7.3
4.1
25.7
22.9
4.1
0.5
0.9
B'90/Greens
4.1
25.7
0.9
2.6
PDS
0.1
2.0
1.3
1.3
n == 1317
East Germany
CDU
SPD
FDP
B ' 90/Greens
PDS
CDU
SPD
PDP
8.4
18.4
9.3
6.7
1.9
18.4
4.7
1.6
13.1
12.4
9.3
1.6
0.5
0.7
0.2
B'90/Greens
6.7
13.1
0.7
2.4
15.3
PDS
1.9
12.4
0.2
15.3
4.3
n== 580
aTotal percentages of all respondents with clear first and second (offdiagonal) or only clear first rank preference (main diagonal).
leverage out of the political discussions of citizens if its supporters speak with
one voice due to the homogeneity of their party preferences. Heterogeneous
support groups tend to decay under stress, as, for example, during election
campaigns.
We use the heterogeneity measure based on the Kemeny-Snell metric and
introduced above, to measure the internal heterogeneity of the various coalition leaning groups. In addition, we present in Table 6 the median ranking
of parties within the most frequent groups of coalition leaners. This is the
ranking of parties with minimum distance to the other rankings present within
the respective groups.
A first rough indicator of the heterogeneity of a group is the number of
different party rankings being represented within the group. The surprising
finding here is that the East German respondents whose size as a group within
our survey is only half of the West German group entertain the same number
of rankings as the more popular West Germans. Thus, the East Germans show
much less agreement of party rankings than the West Germans who are part
of a more established party system. Agreements between individuals are an
[25 ]
244
attribute of social order, not of an individualistic consistent world view. We
have already seen that the percentage of East Germans with consistent party
rankings is slightly less than the respective percentage of West Germans. But
these differences appear to be small compared to the greater incoherence of
the East German social order. Irrespective of coalitions, the heterogeneity
measure for all West German respondents with clear first and/or second party
rankings amounts to 7.36 compared to a mean of 8.94 for East Germans.
This is a large difference, especially if one considers the large number of ties
within the East German party rankings which should have the consequence
of lowering the distances between rankings.
When we focus our attention now to the three largest groups of coalition leaners in West Germany and the five largest groups in East Germany,
we present the results of the heterogeneity measure with the hypothesis in
mind that homogeneity of a coalition leaning group is an advantage for the
preference formation concerning coalitions. And from this perspective, it is
interesting that the governing coalition of Christian Democrats and Liberals
does not enjoy the largest support group within the West and especially not
within the East German electorate, but its respective support groups are the
least heterogeneous ones in both parts of Germany. For this group, the West
German heterogeneity measure is 1.94 and the East German one is slightly
higher with 2.28, but this latter figure is nevertheless the lowest heterogeneity
measure for all East German groups. The major rival of the present coalition,
i.e., the SPD/Green coalition, is characterized by the highest heterogeneity
measure, again in both parts of Germany. This result is of course partially
due to the fact that there are three left parties and only two right or conservative parties represented in our party population. But since this system
delineation is not made ad hoc but is based on the criterion which parties are
represented in the Bundestag, the heterogeneity measures are the results of
a correctly delineated party system. Besides this advantage for the two incumbent parties, another factor improving the position of incumbents is their
better ability to define the terms of public debate than that of the opposition
parties, thereby building up internal strength. The median party ranking of
the CDUIFDP-coalition leaners is identical in East and West Germany with
the CDU preferred most and the PDS preferred least, whereas the SPD/Green
leaners in West Germany reject the PDS most and the respective East German
support group is indifferent between the PDS on one side and the CDU and
FDP on the other side. The attitude of the two established left parties, the Social Democrats and the Greens, towards the former Communists is a probable
source of conflict, especially when one takes into account the polarization of
the East Germans, one fifth of whom rank the PDS highest and another fifth
ranking it lowest.
[26]
245
Table 6. Party-preferences of most frequent groups of coalition leaners: Median
party ranking and heterogeneity
Median ranking a
Heterogeneityb
25.7
S >- G >- C,F >- P
3.42
CDU/CSU - FDP
22.9
CDU/CSU - SPD
19.4
C>-F>-S>-G>-P
C >- S >- F,G >- P
2.62
Coalition
Percent leaners
SPD - B'90/Greens
West Germany
1.94
East Germany
CDU-SPD
PDS - B'90/Greens
SPD - B'90/Greens
18.4
C >- S >- F,G >- P
3.11
15.3
13.1
P >- G >- S >- C,F
S >- G >- C,F,P
2.34
3.68
SPD-PDS
12.4
P >- S >- G >- C,F
3.04
CDU-FDP
9.3
C>-F>-S>-G>-P
2.28
a
b
Preference order among CCDU/CSU), S(PD), F(DP),G(reens), P(DS).
The heterogeneity measure is computed like a mean path distance measure of
a weighted graph. Given the distances dij between party preferences i and j
with the respective frequencies fi and fj.
Heterogeneity is defined as:
LLdilifj/Lff, since LLfifj = Lff·
i i i
i
The median rankings within the three largest groups of coalition leaners in
West Germany and of the five largest in East Germany reduce the complexity
of party preferences to a manageable number. Since we already know that the
CDU is the West German Condorcet winner and the SPD the East German
one, we could now argue that the majority winner is able to choose among
the possible two-party coalitions in whose median ranking it is leading. Thus,
the CDU could form either a coalition with the PDP or with the SPD in the
West, whereas the SPD as the East German majority winner would only have
the option of an SPD/Green-coalition in which it ranks first, compared to its
second rank in a coalition with the CDU. These arguments could be more convincing if these coalitions could be chosen from a linear profile of coalition
options, for which a majority choice is guaranteed (cf. van Deemen, 1991:
204), and which would answer the coalition question at the same time. We
will discuss this problem of how to combine party preferences to form linear
profiles or one-dimensional party orderings as the problem of collective order
in the next section.
[27]
246
4. Combining party preferences to a collective order
Individuals are able to rank parties consistently if they apply the same criteria of evaluation to the parties. This task is easiest to solve with only one
criterion. If the public debate would be focused overwhelmingly on one outstanding criterion, i.e., the solution of one central policy problem, we can
imagine a one-dimensional policy scale on which the parties are placed according to their promised solutions concerning this problem. Citizens would
agree that the solution of this one-policy problem is central for the welfare
of the country, but they would disagree concerning the ideal solution. They
identify parties as providers of different standard solutions, and, depending
on their ideal points on their one-dimensional policy scale, evaluate parties
according to the proximity of the respective party solution to their respective ideal point. Under these conditions, the median solution would be the
majority winner.
The more public opinion is focused on the solution of one central problem,
the higher the probability of the existence of a one-dimensional collective
order, in which both parties and voters hold specific positions. It is important
to understand that this collective order is derived from policy or party preferences, not from party perceptions. The policy or ideological space underlying
specific multiparty systems is often multi-dimensional. For Germany, for instance, experts and citizens agree that the liberal party is right of the CDU
in economic and social welfare terms, but left of the CDU in "social" or
new politics issues (cf. supra p. 231), making the perceived policy space
two-dimensional. But at a specific point in time, either economic or "social"
issues are pressing, and, therefore, at the center of public attention, so that
the "decision space" may be one-dimensional, compared to the underlying
two-dimensional "perception space". The reduction of the perception space
to a decision space is, among other factors, also determined by the coalition
government of the day. A conservative government of CDU/CSU and FDP
is based on economic policy agreements, whereas the SPDIFDP coalition of
the period 1969 to 1982 got started with communalities in "social" issues and
foreign policy. German unification brought the socio-economic dimension
even more to the forefront than was true for the 1980s when environmental
issues challenged the priority of the socio-economic policy of the first Kohl
governments.
The most plausible left-right placement of the five German parties on
the socio-economic policy dimension is as follows: The former communists
(PDS) as the left-most party, then the Greens left of the Social Democrats,
with the Christian Democrats in-between the SPD, and the classical German
party favoring market as against state solutions, i.e., the FDP. We will test
whether this party ordering can be derived from the pattern of marginals of
[28]
247
pairwise comparisons (see Table 4), from the median party rankings of the
most frequent groups of coalition leaners (see Table 6) and finally from the
profile of linear orderings of the five parties.
In Table 4, we have arranged the parties from left to right in the order
of the socio-economic dimension. Applying Feld and Grofman's (1988) concept of collective ideological consistency, the differences of the margins of
collective preference for all party pairs are assumed to give hints about their
one-dimensional party ordering at the aggregate level. "To the extent that
collectivities are ideological, this ideology should be reflected by ideologically consistent regularities among the various vote margins between pairs
of mutually exclusive alternatives, as well as by a single-peaked majority
preference ordering at the aggregate level" (Feld and Grofman, 1988: 776).
If we have ordered the parties correctly from the leftmost to the rightmost
alternative, the percentage of respondents choosing a specific left party of
a pair does not decrease, when the respective second party becomes more
rightist. The cumulative logic should guarantee that once a left party has
reached a certain percentage of respondents at one point on the underlying
continuum, that percentage has at least to remain the same, if not to increase,
when the comparison task is made easier for the left side by a confrontation
with the more rightist party. This cumulative logic may apply for a majority
of voters, even if the individuals within the group deviate to a certain extent
from the joint scale.
In Table 4, the cumulative logic has to show up in the figures above the
main diagonal. Across rows, this difference has to become less negative or
more positive the further we move from the left side of the table to the right
side. The second regularity pertains to the columns. The further we move
down in one column towards the main diagonal, the less negative or the more
positive the percentage differences have to become. Take, for example, the
FOP column for West Germany. When contrasted with the PDS, a majority
of voters decide in favor of the Free Democrats, making the percentage difference negative. Contrasted with the Greens, this less leftist party has a slight
majority which grows larger the less leftist the comparison parties for the
most rightist party, i.e., the Free Democrats, become, since the comparison
gets more favorable for the leftist side, the less leftist the party is with which
we compare the Free Democrats.
For West Germany, we observe more or less ideological consistency at
the aggregate level, with the exception of the comparison between the former communists and the Greens. The comparison between the PDS and the
B '90/Greens should be less favorable for the PDS, making the percentage
difference quite large, than the comparison of the PDS with the Social De-
[ 29]
248
mocrats. Since this expectation does not hold, there is this one deviation from
a perfect aggregate pattern of ideological consistency in West Germany.
In East Germany, we observe the same type of deviation for the pair
PDS vs. Greens as in West Germany, and, in addition, a large deviation for
the pair CDU vs. PDP. What all these deviations from the expected pattern
have in common are two things: The respective parties are neighbors on the
left-right-scale and the percentage of indifferent respondents for these pairs
is especially high. The high number of ties makes the percentages for and
against the respective parties lower than the ones for the other pairs, thereby
deflating the percentage point differences. Thus, we do not accept the deviations from the expected pattern as evidence against our "decision space"
hypothesis.
A second test of this hypothesis is based on the Hamming distances between the median rankings of the largest groups of coalition leaners in East
and West Germany. The existence of a linear profile made up of these altogether six median rankings in the correct order from the PDS-Ied coalitions on
the left to the CDUIFDP-coalition on the right would support out hypothesis,
even if this evidence is based on an ad hoc selection of preferences: First,
on the selection of the largest groups of coalition leaners and, second, on the
identification of the respective median rankings.
As shown in Diagram 1, the median rankings form indeed a linear profile with the PDS/Green-coalition at the leftmost and the present CDUIFDPcoalition at the rightmost position, the distance between these rankings being
19 units. This distance can either be computed by the formula given supra
page 233 or by summing up all the intermediate distances, thus proving the
existence of a linear profile. Due to the leading position of the CDU both in
the coalition with the FDP and with the SPD, the distance between these two
coalition options is only half the size of the distance between the CDU/SPD
and the SPD/Green-coalition. In an all-German party space, the Social Democrats may become the median party, but they will have to pay the price of
a very heterogeneous support group.
Both collective ideological consistency and linear profiles of median rankings indicate one-dimensionality at the aggregate level. It would be more
convincing to build up a linear profile from individual party preferences, in
the same way as this is tried with unidimensional unfolding. We rely on the
unfolding logic but do not use it heuristically with the original, noisy data.
Instead, we restrict the analysis first to respondents with consistent party
preferences and second to linear orderings, thereby avoiding tied ranks. The
reason for this second restriction is our knowledge of the large/small party
split of the German party system which does not fit the left-right logic. The
electorate seems to be stratified according to the completeness of its view of
[30 ]
249
Median rankings
P
G
P
S
S
G
S
C,F
G
C,F,P
C,F
G
S
C,F
P
C
C
S
F,G
P
G
F
S
P
Diagram J. Hamming distances between median party rankings of largest groups of coalition
leaners in East and West Germany (see Table 6).
the party system. Some voters have only the CDU and the SPD on their choice
set, being indifferent between the lower ranked smaller parties. Contrary to
this pattern, a left-right logic would only allow ties of neighboring parties on
this scale, between Greens and SPD, for example, or CDU and FDP, but not
between Greens and FDP. Analytically, it therefore makes sense to test the
one-dimensionality of the decision space solely for respondents with linear
orderings of the parties.
The disadvantage of this procedure is the small size of the group comprising our target population, 37.2% of the West German and 27.5% of the East
German respondents. We justify this procedure by pointing at the characteristics of a collective ordering of parties. There exist many possibilities for
idiosyncratic worldviews, but as soon as a core group of voters responds to a
focused public debate by rearranging its party preferences along the underlying policy dimension, a collective order or linear profile becomes crystallized,
which facilitates communication between parties and voters. "Communication is not regarded as a process of exchanging pockets of information ...
Rather, it is a kind of guessing game. A person carries with him his cognitive
field as a map of the world. He responds not to the world, but to the map.
When he receives the communication, the meaning it has is a consequence of
how it can be fitted into the map" (Coombs, 1964: 122).
Such a common map of a core group of voters and the party elites is a
precondition of a meaningful public debate about policies. In Germany after
unification, it was and is an even more difficult task than usual to come up
with a common, all-German map. East and West Germans do not have to
agree in their ideal solutions for the socio-economic policy problems of the
country, but they should agree in their views about the major problems, if the
parties should be able to compete for votes or support in an all-German campaign. Competing for votes on a single policy dimension is a rational strategy
if the common or joint policy scale is based on single-peaked preferences of
[31]
250
the voters. And single-peakedness is not a characteristic of individuals, but of
the collective order.
A linear profile consists of an ordered set of preferences based on the
relation of betweenness whereas a joint policy scale positions parties and
voters on a straight line so that the preferences of voters can be computed
from the varying distances of a voter's ideal point to the parties. As Coombs
(1964: 84ff.) has shown, five object of evaluation on a straight line are compatible with 16 individual preference orders if metric implications for the
various intervals between parties are ignored. The percentage of respondents
with preferences which fit a specific joint scale is a rough indicator of the
prevalence of this policy scale within a collective order. In West Germany,
58% of the respondents with linear preferences rank the five parties in a way
compatible with our hypothesized socio-economic left-right-scale, in East
Germany 42%. These percentages indicate the prevalence of this policy scale,
under the condition that rival scales do not receive almost as much support.
We tested two other policy scales, one standing for "social" or new politics
issues with the Greens and the Christian Democrats at opposing ends (Greens
- PDS - SPD - FDP - CDU/CSU) and one where only CDU and FDP switch
positions and the PDS remains the leftmost party. The latter scale was more
prominent during the SPDIFDP coalition period, and is, even nowadays, the
major competitor of the socio-economic left-right scale, with 45% compatible
party rankings in West and 27% in East Germany. 21 %, respectively 8%, of
the preferences fit both scales. The new politics scale picks up only 2% in
West and 18% of the preferences in East Germany. Overall, we interpret these
findings as supporting the prevalence of the socio-economic left-right scale,
even if the position of the FDP within this collective order is not unchallenged. The most important reason for the rightmost position of the FDP on
the socio-economic policy scale is the rejection of this party by left-leaning
respondents; they reject the FDP more than the CDU, whereas the liberal selfimage is quantitatively less important. But even if many voters still perceive
the Liberals as holding middle-ground in the German party system, they see
this party to the right of the CDU in specific economic and social welfare
policies.
The East German respondents still have more problems than the West
Germans to fit into a collective order, since they afford the luxury of a lot
of ideo-syncratic world views. But despite this fact, the best candidate for
a collective order is the same socio-economic scale in both East and West
Germany (see Diagram 2).
Diagram 2 allows a closer look at the party preferences compatible with
the. socio-economic left-right scale. The Hamming distance between two
neighboring party rankings in two units, the lines between preferences in-
[32]
251
West
East
Preferences
n
n
~
7
GSCPF
29
GSCFP
73
SGCFP
54
SCGFP
36
SCFGP
I
I
I
4
PGSCF
4
GPSCF
11
GSPCF
4
I
I
1
~
9
SGPCF
2
9
SGCPF
8
6
SCGPF
1
I
I
CSGPF
17
I
~
I
109
CSFGP
112
CFSGP
29
FCSGP
I
~
48
I
CSGFP
4
17
24
12
I
Diagram 2. Hasse-Diagram of the 16 linear profiles compatible with the joint socio-economic
scale peDS), G(reens), S(PD), C(DU), F(DP)
dicating immediate neighbors. There exist 12 unique paths from the leftmost
(top) to the rightmost (bottom) preference and these paths correspond to the
12 quantitative joint scales being compatible with the same qualitative scale
(see Coombs, 1964). We choose the paths which pick up most respondents
in West and East Germany and show the spatial implications on the interval
scales of Diagram 3.
In both parts of Germany, the distance between CDU and SPD is larger
than the distance of each major party to its junior ally, leading to a bi-polari-
[33]
252
West Germany
PDS
Greens
SPD
eDU
FDP
eDU
FDP
East Germany
PDS
Greens
SPD
Diagram 3. The best fitting quantitative joint socio-economic scale for West and East Germany
zation of the party system on the socio-economic dimension. Such a configuration would not be supportive for a grand coalition of Christian and Social
Democrats. The East German pattern departs from the West German one as
far as the PDS is concerned. For West Germans, the distance between PDS
and Greens is larger than the distance between SPD and CDU, whereas for
East Germans, it is shorter, unifying the left camp of three parties more than
in West Germany, where the PDS is clearly an outlier at the extreme left of
the party system.
On the socio-economic policy scale, only the Christians or the Social Democrats have a chance to become the median party. In an all-German context,
the chances of the Social Democrats to hold a median position have been
improved by German unification, since the East Germans lean more to the
three left parties than to the CDU or FDP. But which of the two major parties
will become the median or Condorcet winner in the next election, will also
depend on voters whose choice sets are focused on the CDU and SPD. On
the socio-economic scale, these parties are neighbors, thereby facilitating the
existence of a Condorcet winner. This winner will then be able to decide
which coalition should be formed, but its options will be restricted by the
prevalent socio-economic policy scale and the policy distances on this scale.
5. Conclusions
Voter preferences in multiparty systems contain a lot of information beyond
the distribution of first preferences, i.e., the type of data retrieved by proportional voting systems. We derived information on coalition leanings from the
party rankings and we analyzed their spatial implications. With five parties 5!
= 120 linear orderings are logically possible, and allowing tied rankings, this
number increases to 541. A null-hypothesis about party preferences would
[34]
253
predict a random sample of party rankings for an electorate, the next step
being the enforcement of prior probabilities for the first ranked parties according to past election results. Both the first and the second null-hypothesis
does not predict the distribution of party rankings in West or East Germany.
On the other hand, multi- or uni-dimensional unfolding would have its
problems, too, to reveal a space in which both parties and voters are located
such that the party rankings of voters can be reconstructed from distances to
the parties within the joint space. Normally, the data used as input are too
noisy to reach convincing solutions. We have first of all identified the 3/4 to
4/5 of the respondents who were able to form at least a weak order among five
parties. But this step of the analysis is not yet enough for a construction of a
collective order out of the universe of individually consistent party rankings.
Our own earlier attempts to find a spatial representation of the German
party system were based on unrealistic assumptions about the joint party
space. We underestimated the substantive obstacles working against the formation of a collective order which should be the outcome of correct perceptions of party positions and function as the "decision space" at the same
time. In this article, we focused on the "decision space" which can be derived
from party rankings and we gave up the assumption of a joint space for all
voters. We argued instead that spatial implications from party preferences
can be drawn if a core group of voters is able to rank all the parties on the
basis of strong preferences and if a substantial amount of these preferences is
compatible with a joint or collective order of the party system.
The application of spatial models to multiparty systems needs a lot of
calibration so that the theoretically powerful models can indeed be adapted
to real-world situations. For this purpose, we have distinguished between the
perception and the decision space, outlining that party rankings have first of
all implications for the latter. Our analysis of the logically possible two-party
coalition has shown that the governing coalition is able to structure the party
rankings to a higher degree than the other possible coalitions. This structuring
power was indicated by the measure of heterogeneity of the coalition leaners'
preferences. Extrapolating from this result, we hypothesize that the governing
coalition in multiparty systems is, as the main political agenda setter, also
able to influence public opinion and, thereby, predetermining the collective
ordering of parties.
For the German party system after unification, we have shown that these
spatial implications are almost identical in West and East Germany. Thus,
we are justified to interpret our results as evidence of a common all-German
party system, not in the trivial sense that the same parties compete for votes
in East and West Germany, but in the sense that the parties compete within
the same frame of reference. The party preferences of the East Germans are
[35 ]
254
more left-leaning than those of the West Germans and the PDS, especially,
is on average higher ranked. The common socio-economic policy dimension
is the precondition of a democratic election resulting in a median party and,
probably, in a collective preference for a specific coalition government. Under these conditions, the party elites are well advised to pay attention to the
coalition leanings and the derived policy preferences of the electorate.
References
Black, D. (1987). The theory of committees and elections. Boston, Dordrecht, Lancaster:
Kluwer Academic Publishers. (First published in 1958).
Brady, H.E. and Ansolabehere, S. (1989). The nature of utility functions in mass publics.
American Political Science Review 83: 143-164.
Coombs, C.H. (1964). A theory of data. New York: Wiley.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper and Row.
Eckstein, G. (1995). Rationale Wahl im Mehrparteiensystem: Die Bedeutung von Koalitionen
im raumlichen Modell der Parteienkonkurrenz. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
Enelow, I.M. and Hinich, MJ. (1984). The spatial theory of voting: An introduction.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Feld, S. and Grofman, B. (1988). Ideological consistency as a collective phenomenon.
American Political Science Review 82: 774-788.
Fiorina, M.P. (1981). Retrospective voting in American national elections. New Haven,
London: Yale University Press.
Fishburn, P.c. (1970). Utility theory for decision making. New York: Wiley.
Inglehart, R. and Klingemann, H.-D. (1976). Party identification, ideological preference and
the left-right dimensions among western mass publics. In I. Budge, I. Crewe, and D. Farlie
(Eds.), Party identification and beyond. Representations of voting and party competition.
243-273. London et al.: Wiley and Sons.
Kemeny, J.G. and Snell, L.J. (1963). Mathematical models in the social sciences. New York,
Toronto, London: Blaisdell. Second edition.
Laver, M. and Hunt, B.W. (1992). Policy and party competition. New York and London:
Routledge.
Laver, M. and Schofield, N. (1990). Multiparty government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nannestad, P. (1994). Danisches Wahlverhalten 1971-1979: Ein Modell reaktiven Wahlens
und einige empirische Ergebnisse. In F.U. Pappi and H. Schmitt (Eds.), Parteien,
Parlamente und Wahlen in Skandinavien, 285-306. Frankfurt, New York: Campus.
Norpoth, H. (1979). The parties come to order: Dimensions of preferential choice in the West
German electorate, 1961-1976. American Political Science Review 73: 724-736.
Pappi, F.U. (1973). Parteiensystem und Sozialstruktur in der Bundesrepublik. Politische
Vierteljahresschrift 14: 191-213.
Pappi, F.U. (1983). Die Links-Rechts-Dimension des deutschen Parteiensystems und die
Parteipraferenz-Profile der Wahlerschaft. In M. Kaase and H.-D. Klingemann (Ed.),
Wahlen und politisches System, 422-441. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.
Pappi, F.U. (1990). Die Republikaner im Parteiensystem der Bundesrepuhlik: Protesterscheinung oder politische Alternative? Aus Politik und Zeitgeschichte 21/90: 37-44.
Pappi, F.U. (1992). Wahrgenommene Parteidistanzen zwischen Parteien und eigene
Politikpraferenzen der Wahler: Die Anwendung eines Raumlichen Modells der
[36]
255
Parteienkonkurrenz auf das Parteiensystem in West- und Ostdeutschland. In H.-J. Andress et al. (Eds.). Theorie, Daten, Methoden: Neue Modelle und Verfahrensweisen in den
Sozialwissenschajten, 317-341. Miinchen: OIdenbourg.
Radcliff, B. (1993). The structure of voter preferences. Journal of Politics 55: 714-719.
Schofield, N.J. (1993). Party competition in a spatial model of coalition formation. In WA.
Barnett, MJ. Hinich, and N.J. Schofield (Eds.), 135-174. Political economy: Institutions,
competition, and representation. Proceedings of the Seventh International Symposium in
Economic Theory and Econometrics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schofield, N.J. (1995). Coalition politics: A formal model and empirical analysis. Journal of
Theoretical Politics 7: 254-281.
Shepsle, K.A. (1991). Models of multiparty electoral competition. Chur, CH, et al.: Harvard
Academic Publishers.
Van Deemen, A.M.A. (1991). Coalition formation and social choice. Nijmegen: NICI.
Van der Eijk, C., Franklin, M. and Oppenhuis, E. (1996). The strategic context: Party choice.
In C. van der Eijk and M. Franklin, Choosing Europe?: The European electorate and
national politics in the face of union, 332-365. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
[37]
Public Choice 97: 257-293, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
257
Multiparty electoral competition in the Netherlands and
Germany: A model based on multinomial probit *
NORMAL SCHOFIELD, ANDREW D. MARTIN, KEVIN M. QUINN &
ANDREW B. WHITFORD
Center in Political Economy, Campus Box 1208, Washington University, St. Louis, MO
63130, U.S.A.
Abstract. A typical assumption of electoral models of party competition is that parties adopt
policy positions so as to maximize expected vote share. Here we use Euro-barometer survey
data and European elite-study data from 1979 for the Netherlands and Germany to construct
a stochastic model of voter response, based on multinomial probit estimation. For each of
these countries, we estimate a pure spatial electoral voting model and a joint spatial model.
The latter model also includes individual voter and demographic characteristics. The pure
spatial models for the two countries quite accurately described the electoral response as a
stochastic function of party positions. We use these models to perform a thought experiment
so as to estimate the expected vote maximizing party positions. We go on to propose a model
of internal party decision-making based both on pre-election electoral estimation and postelection coalition bargaining. This model suggests why the various parties in the period in
question did not adopt vote maximizing positions. We argue that maximizing expected vote
will not, in general, be a rational party strategy in multiparty political systems which are based
on proportional representation.
1. Introduction
Democratic political systems can be distinguished by whether they are based
essentially on proportional or plurality electoral rules, and whether political
parties are strongly disciplined or not (see Table 1).
Most of the polities of Western Europe have electoral systems based on
proportional representation, with relatively disciplined parties. Some of these
polities (such as Austria) only have two parties, but others (such as Finland)
may have five or six or more. In contrast, Britain has a plurality (or firstpost-the-post) electoral system, based on over 600 constituencies, each of
which returns one member of Parliament. Although the House includes at
* This paper is based on research supported by NSF Grants SBR 94-22548 and 96-17708.
Versions of this research have been presented at the Public Choice Meeting, San Francisco,
March 1997, at the European Public Choice Meeting, Prague, April 1997, and at the Political
Science Seminar, New York University, May 1997.
[39]
258
least eight parties, the effective number l is just above two (Schofield, 1997a)
as would be expected from Duverger's Law (Duverger, 1954, 1984; Riker,
1982; Fedderson, 1992).
The British system is often called a "Westminster style" polity. In contrast, the U.S. Congress is based on a plurality electoral system, but (to judge
from the heterogeneity of the voting by its members) the two parties are not
disciplined in the sense that British parties are (Poole and Rosenthal, 1991).
In some of the new democracies (such as Russia) mixed PR and plurality electoral methods have been adopted, and the polity seems to be highly
factionalized and the parties very weak. In Japan, which until recently had
a complex electoral system based on multimember constituencies, the dominant liberal Democratic Party was comprised of at least six factions all of
whose leaders were contenders for the prime ministerial position (Wada and
Schofield, 1996).
To construct a formal comparative politics, it would be desirable to build
a rational choice or game theoretic model that includes (a) a reasonable description of voters' choices, (b) a coherent description of the behavior by
political actors in the pre-election context, and (c) a model of the negotiation or bargaining by political actors, in the post-election phase, over the
formation of government. Presumably the type of electoral system would
enter into the calculation of political actors under (b) so that it would be
possible to see clearly the effect of different motivations. Similarly, the effect
of political institutions (such as Congressional committees or cabinet rule)
could be understood more readily, were a general model of (c) available.
Almost all the theoretical work of which we are aware has concentrated
either on pre-election behavior by two candidates under plurality rule, or
on post-election coalition negotiation in multiparty situations (where "multiparty" means at least three parties). It is clear enough that understanding
"multiparty" competition should also involve calculations made by candidates or parties before the election. This paper will use an empirical analysis
of electoral data from the Netherlands and Germany to argue that the usual
two-party electoral models do not generalize well to multiparty situations.
Instead we argue that a coherent model of pre-election party strategy has to
incorporate both an electoral component and prediction over post-election
coalition possibilities.
We use our model of electoral behavior, together with our account of coalition behavior, to suggest why political competition in multiparty situations
does not lead to convergence of party positions. In particular, our model of
party policy choice emphasizes the heterogeneity of preferred policies within
each party. We argue that the proposed model can in principle be used to
understand the different motivations determining political choice in electoral
[40]
259
Table 1. Types of politics
Discipline
Electoral rule
Proportional
Plurality
representation
Strong
West European model
Westminster
Weak
Factional
U.S. House
systems based on proportional representation or plurality rule, with or without
disciplined parties.
2. Elections: Models of pre-election choice by parties
The literature on formal models of elections is vast, but we can briefly review the main results of the spatial model using Table 2 as a guide. The
spatial model assumes that political choices are points in a policy space,
W, of dimension w. Each voter i E N has an ideal point, Xi E W, and each
candidate, j E K makes a "declaration" ¢j E W. The "electoral data" is then
an n x k matrix Oij = II Xi-¢j II where n = INI and k = IKI. In the pure spatial
deterministic model, voter i's "utility" Uij for the choice ¢j is a monotonically
decreasing function of Oij. A typical assumption is that uij = _{302 ij . Voter
choice is given by an n x k matrix X = (Xii) where Xij = I (i chooses j) if
II x i-<PJi 1>llxi-¢j II for I #: j, and Xii = 0 otherwise. The share of the vote of
party j is then Jr/X)(¢) = ~ L~I
Xij (¢), (where ¢ = (¢I "',¢k) is the vector
of declarations). In two-party deterministic models it is usually assumed that
each candidate desires to win. Thus for example we could assume that the
utility for candidate I, given X and ¢, is
1 if Jrl (X)(¢) > Jr2(X)(¢)
o if Jrl = Jr2
-I if Jrl < Jr2.
In the Hotelling (1929) and Downs (1957) model, vote maximizing by the
candidates (in the case w = 1 and k = 2) forces each candidate (j) to adopt
the electoral median (or Nash equilibrium) position, ¢*j = x~(n+I)'
where the
voter ideal points are ordered XI .::: X2 .::: ... Xn, etc. In the one-dimensional case
this result is robust. Thus, if each candidate has policy preferences (so that 1,
for example, prefers to win with a policy near some bliss point z I, say), then
[ 41 ]
260
Table 2. Models of election
Candidate model
Office seeking
Voter model
Deterministic
Probabilistic
Low dimension
Strong convergence
Electoral median
Nash equilibrium at
electoral mean,
High dimension
when variance is high.
Electoral heart
Policy-seeking
Weak convergence
Weak convergence for
but possibly to
some parties;
Nash equilibrium
possible divergence
by small parties
the Nash equilibrium typically satisfies ¢*, = ¢*2 (Osborne, 1995). The logic
is clear: to implement a desired policy, a candidate still must win. Attempts
to extend the Hotelling-Downs model to the case with k ::: 3, generally find
no pure Nash equilibrium (satisfying ¢*j E W for all j E K), even in one
dimension (Osborne, 1993).
The motivation of the candidates in such a multiparty model is usually
taken to be plurality maximization, so candidate j prefers that declaration,
¢j, which maximizes the differences between 7l'j and 7l'" for all I i= j. The
reasoning underlying this assumption is presumably that 7l' j is a proxy for the
power of the political agent, j, and that such an agent wishes to maximize
its power. We shall say that an agent, j, who acts to maximize 7l'j (subject to
some model X of voter behavior) is Downsian. A theme of this paper is that
Downsian behavior need not be "rational" in a more general context.
Attempts to extend the Hotelling-Downs model, with k = 2 but w ::: 2 ran
into the well-known difficulty of "generic" non-existence of a pure strategy
Nash equilibrium. (In fact, the formal proof of this comes from results by
McKelvey and Schofield, 1986; and Saari, 1997, on non-existence of a core
in a spatial committee game. We mention these results in the next section.)
This "fact" can be side-stepped either by focusing on mixed strategy Nash
equilibria (Kramer, 1978), or by introducing a more general notion such as
the "uncovered set" (McKelvey, 1986; Cox, 1987). However, the uncovered
set is a concept based on spatial committee voting theory, and it is not entirely
obvious that it is appropriate for modeling elections, even when political
agents are assumed to be Downsian. Below we shall introduce the notion
[42]
261
of the electoral and political "heart" (Schofield, 1995a), and argue that it can
be used to understand multiparty competition.
Existence of pure strategy Nash equilibria with Downsian candidates is
much easier to demonstrate when the electoral model (X) is probabilistic or
"stochastic" (see, e.g., Hinich, 1977; Enelow and Hinich, 1984; Coughlin,
1992). There are a number of varieties of such a model, but they all suppose
voter behavior is described by the probability Xij that voter i chooses j. Thus
Xij = Prob(X ij = 1), so 1:jEK Xij = 1, for each i. A typical assumption is that
Uij =Uij + Ej where Ej is a "perceptual" error term associated with candidate j
and Uij is the spatial utility of i for j. Usually the entries in the error vector E
(E I,... ,Ek) are assumed to be independently and identically distributed (iid).
The probability Xij is then the probability that Uij > Ui] for all 1 i= j. This
condition is simply that
=
E] - Ej < t3(8~
- 8ij) for all 1 i= j.
(1)
If it is assumed that each Ej is normally distributed, with zero expected
value and variance a 2j, then it is possible to compute the distribution of
the random variable ll'j(X) (cp), given the electoral model and the vector of
declarations. Since the expectation of Xij is simply Xij it follows that the
expectation of the vote share is simply given by E(JTj)(",) = ~1:
Xij(CP). As in
the deterministic case, we shall say that a candidate, or agent j, who chooses
CPj to maximize E(JTj)(cp), subject to (CPI, ... , CPj-t, cpj+j, ... ,¢k), is Downsian.
In two-party competition a more plausible assumption for party I say,
would be to maximize the probability that JT t (CPt ,CP2) exceeds JT2(CPt ,CP2).
Nonetheless, under the independence assumption, these two motivations are
effectively identical (Aranson, Hinich, and Ordeshook, 1974). A standard
result for k = 2 is that a pure-strategy Nash equilibrium exists and is strongly
convergent, in the sense that cpr = cp~,
both at the mean of the voter ideal
points. As Lin, Enelow, and Dorussen (1996) have recently shown, even when
k ::0: 3 there is a pure strategy Nash equilibrium at the voter mean (at least in
the case the variance terms
j E K, are sufficiently high). In fact, they show
(for high variance) that each expectation E(JTj)(cp) is concave in CPj. Thus the
Nash equilibrium is unique, and is at the "welfare maximum" point, cP* (so cpr
=cp* v j E K). That is to say, 1:iEN II Xi - cp* II is minimized at the convergent
Nash eqUilibrium, CP*. However, for low variance, E(JTj)(cp) may fail concavity
or quasi-concavity. Indeed, Nash equilibria may be divergent or fail to exist.
It would appear that both deterministic and probabilistic models with
Downsian agents are preoccupied with finding convergent Nash equilibria.
This seems strange, since in no political system of which we are aware do
candidate positions display strong convergence. It is true that one can weaken
the degree of convergence in 2-candidate elections, by assuming that candi-
al,
[43 ]
262
dates have policy preferences. This is done by assuming that the outcome of a
pair of declarations, «(jJ,,(/J2), is a lottery, {(Prob(rrd,(jJ,),(Prob(rr2),(jJ2)} say,
where Prob(rrj) is the probability that candidate j wins the election. As Cox
(1984) has shown, if each candidate (or party) has a Euclidean preference
based on the party's preferred point, and is committed to the implementation of its declared position if it wins, then there is a (non-convergent) pure
strategy Nash eqUilibrium.
As soon as parties have preferred positions, then the validity of the assumption of policy commitment in Downsian models becomes suspect. We
shall come back to this question later.
3. Committees: Models of post-election coalition behavior
In two-candidate elections the formal analysis is over when the election is
over and one party wins. If the candidates are parties and k ::: 3, then the
process of government formation involves creating a coalition (which mayor
may not be winning). The early work on European coalition governments was
much influenced by Riker's (1962) analysis of constant sum voting games and
his notion of minimal winning coalitions. It was soon noticed (Herman and
Pope, 1973) that coalition governments could be minority (lacking a majority) or surplus (with extra partners). This research program then focussed
on coalition negotiation between parties with preferred policies in a onedimensional policy space (Axelrod, 1970; de Swaan, 1973). Essentially, these
models implied that the party at the median "legislature" policy would belong
to the government. In fact, one could go further and argue that if parties
were only concerned with policy, then any party at the median position in
the legislature could form a minority government and implement its desired
policy. However, empirical analysis (Taylor and Laver, 1973) suggested that
these one-dimensional models did not provide a satisfactory explanation of
government formation.
During the 1980s however, theoretical work on the spatial "committee"
model of voting (Schofield, 1985) as well as empirical work on party declarations (Budge, Robertson, and Hearl, 1987) suggested that a two-dimensional
analysis of coalition behavior could be fruitful.
To illustrate, Table 3 presents the election results of the 1977 and 1981
elections in the Netherlands.
A coalition of the CDA and VVD formed in December 1977, controlling
77 seats, and lasted 41 months until the 1981 election. (It should be noted that
this coalition took 6 months to form after the May 1977 election.) After 1981,
a brief "surplus" coalition of PvdA, D66 and CDA (with 109 seats) formed
[44]
263
Table 3. Elections in the Netherlands, 1977 and
1981
Party (acronym)
1977
1981
(Seats)
Labor (PvdA)
53
44
Democrats ' 66 (D66)
8
28
26
49
(138)
48
(135)
Liberals (VVD)
Christian Dem Appeal (CDA)
17
Communists (CPN)
2
3
Dem '70 (D70)
1
0
Radicals (PPR)
3
3
3
2
Pacific Socialists (PSP)
Reform Federation (RPF)
Reform Pol Ass (GDV)
Farmers Party (BP)
0
State Reform Party (SGP)
3
(11)
3
(15)
Total
149
ISO
and then broke down to a minority, 066, COA coalition. A new election had
to be called in September 1982.
As described in Laver and Schofield (1990), if the parties do have policy
preferences, and if the space is essentially two-dimensional, then it is possible
for there to be a single "dominant" party at the "core" position. A "core" is
a preferred policy position, Z[, for party 1 say, such that no other position, y
say, is preferred by a coalition commanding a majority of the seats. Attempts
to use the spatial committee model have foundered on the difficulty of estimating party positions. The work presented in Budge, Robertson and Hearl
(1987) attempted to use content analysis of party declarations (manifestos)
to estimate party positions. However these estimated positions seemed excessively volatile. In this paper we have used the Euro-Barometer II data (Rabier
and Inglehart, 1981) and the European Political Parties Middle Level Elites
data (ISEIUM, 1983) to estimate party positions (further discussion of these
data is provided in the next section, and in Appendix A. See also Quinn et
al., 1996.) These data allow us to represent the positions of the four major
[45 ]
264
c::
0
'iii
c:
Q)
E
is
0
0
(ij
'0
WD
0
(/)
';"
-2
-1
o
2
Economic Dimension
Figure 1. Dutch voter and party positions, 1979.
parties in the Netherlands in 1979 in a two-dimensional policy space, W (see
Figure 1).
Assume for the moment that the four positions in this figure are preferred
policy choices for the four parties and that each party, j, has a Euclidean policy preference derived from a utility function of the form Uj(x) =
-llx-zjI12 (where Zj is its preferred position). Now draw the contract curves
between the three pairs {CDA, VVD}, {PvdA, VVD} and {PvdA,CDA}. U sing the election results of 1977 to determine seat strength, it is very readily
shown that the "core" is empty. To illustrate, the CDA position in Figure 1
can be beaten by a winning coalition of {PvdA,VVD} adopting a position on
their contract curve which is nearer to their preferred positions. This in turn
can be beaten by a position on the {PvdA,CDA} contract curve and this again
can be beaten by a position on the contract curve of {CDA,VVD}. The three
contract curves bound a triangle {CDA,VVD,PvdA} which has been termed
the political "heart" (Schofield, 1993).
It has recently been shown (Schofield, 1997b) that the "heart" Je can be
identified with a local version of the uncovered set. If the heart is viewed
as a correspondence Je, from the space of all party declarations and voter
behavior, to the policy space, W, then Je is lower hemi-continuous. Thus Je
admits a continuous selection (Schofield, 1995a). See Appendix C for details.
[46]
265
To be more specific, given a vector of party positions, ¢, and post-election
weights (seats), we assume that the coalition outcome is a lottery g, namely a
set of government coalitions and associated coalition probabilities, g(X)( ¢ ),
determined by ¢ and the stochastic electoral model X. Let Jf(X)(¢) be the
realization of the heart once the electorate has responded to ¢, and let it
denote all lotteries over Jf. Then our formal model assumes that the political
outcome, g(X)(¢), belongs to it(X)(¢). As ¢ varies, then g is a continuous
selection from it. If we impute preferences to political agents then, knowing
g, we may solve the implicit game, g, to deduce Nash equilibria, ¢*, to this
game. This is a model of high generality, but of little applicability if we cannot
model party preferences or the electoral response, X, appropriately.
To develop the Dutch example resulting from the 1977 election, we shall
continue with the assumption that the parties are committed after the election
to the various positions in Figure 1, and also suppose that coalitions form to
propose policy points inside the realized heart. Without a core in 1977 the
parties found great difficulty reaching an agreement. In particular the PvdA
and CDA could not find an acceptable compromise. As we have observed,
after months of negotiation the CDA and VVD eventually formed a minimal
winning coalition government.
We see this as providing some degree of empirical justification for the
heart. To pursue the example, we can chart the change in the heart resulting from the 1981 election. As Table 3 makes clear, the gain of 9 seats by
D66 meant that the {CDA,VVD} coalition lost its majority (dropping to 74
seats). The heart now contracts to become the triangle {PvdA,CDA,D66}.
It is hardly surprising that this three-party coalition first formed. Nor is it
surprising that it collapsed to the minority {CDA,D66} coalition. The rivalry
between the CDA and PvdA led to a political crisis, to a new election in
September 1982, and to a relatively long-lived coalition of {CDA,VVD}.
Observe that the very small parties in 1977 and 1981 seemed to play no
significant role in coalition bargaining. For this reason we ignore their effect
on elections and coalition bargaining.
Note that if only one dimension (the left-right economic axis) were
relevant in the Netherlands then theory would suggest that the CDA (being typically at the one-dimensional core) could form a one-party minority
government. To our knowledge, minority governments are very rare in the
Netherlands and tend to be short-lived. This suggests, contra de Swaan
(1973), that one-dimensional models of coalition behavior are inadequate,
at least in understanding Dutch politics.
The concept of the "political" heart, used here to interpret these two postelection situations in the Netherlands, is clearly based on the spatial theory
of committees, since the heart assumes that the party positions are preferred
[47 ]
266
policies, and uses the electoral strength of each of the parties to determine the
pattern of winning coalitions. However, we can use the notion of the heart to
infer something about the motivations of the parties before the elections. It is
apparent that the simple maxim of increasing electoral vote is not adequate.
Although the PvdA was the largest party in 1977, it could not find a coalition
partner with which to form the government. It should also be observed that
the principle of "maximizing electoral vote" ignores attitude to risk by the
parties. In the stochastic electoral model discussed below, our estimates for
the distribution of vote shares for the four parties show that there is a significant variance. For example, the 95% confidence interval for the number of
seats which would have been obtained by the PvdA in an election in 1979 (as
given by our estimation based on party positions) ranges from 42 to 54.
We shall argue in the next section that no party in the Netherlands could
choose an acceptable policy position, in the period under discussion, so as to
give it a reasonable probability of being at the core. In the absence of a postelection core, negotiations between the parties were bound to be as difficult
as we have observed they were.
We can contrast this core-less example with one from Germany, also for
1979. Table 4 presents the election results between 1976 and 1982. Figure 2
gives the party positions obtained from ISEIUM (1983) data (see also Appendix A and Martin and Quinn, 1997). Clearly the three parties are almost, but
not quite, colinear. If the positions were colinear, then the FDP would be at the
core. However, Schofield (1986) shows that such a core is "structurally unstable", since small perturbations in party positions destroy the core property.
Nonetheless, it can be inferred that the FDP is pivotal. The "grand" coalition
of {CDU,SPD} was possible, but appears to have had low probability. In
fact the {SDP,PDP} coalition formed in December 1976 and lasted until the
October 1980 election. This was followed by a {CDU,FDP} coalition, which
has persisted to the present. Although the Greens won 27 seats in 1982, it
is clear that they have been effectively superfluous in coalition bargaining,
at least until the present. (This may change after the forthcoming election
[Summer 1998] in Germany.)
Essentially the PDP could pick and choose between the two large parties.
In this simpler situation, there may be some reason for one of the two large
parties to seek a core position. However to be at a "structurally stable" core
in this situation means to command a majority of the seats. Our electoral
model, to be introduced below, can be used to determine whether this is
indeed possible.
We may also compare the two cases of an empty core (in the Netherlands)
or a "structurally unstable core" (in Germany) with the possibility of a structurally stable core. As with the uncovered set, the heart and the core coincide
[48]
267
N
c
0
'<Ii
cQ)
E
i:5
0
(ij
'0
0
Cf)
'7
-2
-1
o
2
Economic Dimension
Figure 2. German voter and party positions, 1979.
Table 4, Elections in West Germany, 1976, 1980 and 1982
1976
1980
1982
(Seats)
Christian Democrats (CDU)a
243
226
244
Free Democrats (FOP)
Social Democrats (SPO)
39
214
53
218
34
193
27
496
497
498
Greens (GR)
Total
aThe Christian Social Union (CSU) seats are included
with the COU.
when the core is non-empty. The post-election bargaining theory proposed
in Laver and Schofield (1990) and Schofield (1993) suggests, moreover, that
in a two-dimensional policy space, if the core is non-empty and structurally
stable, then it can only be occupied by the "dominant" party (see Schofield,
1995b for the proof, and a more precise definition of "dominant"). To give an
indication of how a structurally stable core may arise, consider an artificial
situation for the Netherlands where we suppose that the D66 is located within
[49]
268
the {CDA,VVD,PvdA} triangle, and controls 39 seats, with each of the other
three parties controlling 37 seats. It is clear, in this case, that the D66 policy
can be beaten by no other two-party coalition. The analysis provided in Laver
and Schofield (1990) suggests, moreover, that such a dominant party at the
core is likely to form a minority (one-party) government. In contrast, when
a minority government forms that is not based on the core in this fashion,
then it is nearly always short-lived. The best evidence is from Scandinavian
countries: out of 50 governments in Denmark, Norway and Sweden, twentyeight were minority, and all but three were associated with core, dominant
parties. The three minority, non-core examples were all short-lived, caretaker
governments.
If a party can control policy and obtain government perquisites from locating itself at a core, then the logical choice of any party would be to seek
the core position. However, such a strategy is feasible only if that policy
position is acceptable to the elite in the party. Note also that whether a position is core-like or not depends on the position (and strengths) of the other
parties. Thus maneuvering for the core is much more difficult than simply
maximizing expected vote. Indeed, there may be no core. In particular the
McKelvey-Schofield-Saari results on core existence imply that the core is
typically empty in weighted voting games in three dimensions.
Thus, a "counter-core" strategy by a smaller party could be to introduce
policy dimensions to destroy any possibility of occurrence of a core. However, for this to be effective the new dimension must be relevant in terms of
the true preferences of the parties and of the voters.
A second possibility, even in two dimensions, is that the underlying electoral response to party positions prohibits any party from advantageously
locating itself at the core. To examine this possibility, we shall construct
a "stochastic" model of voting for the Netherlands and Germany, based on
multinomial probit (MNP).
4. An empirical model of electoral behavior based on pure spatial
theory
Appendix A presents the empirical procedure we adopted to construct individual and party ideal points in the Netherlands and Germany. Because of the
way the scales were constructed, a respondent agreeing strongly that "greater
effort should be made to reduce inequality" would be assigned a negative
value, and thus tend to be on the left on the first "economic" dimension.
On the other hand, a respondent in the Netherlands agreeing strongly that
"women should be free to decide for themselves in matters concerning abortion" would obtain a negative score on the second dimension. The second
[50]
269
dimension thus provides a technique for distinguishing Liberal voters (who
might tend to vote for the VVD) and others who might tend to vote for the
Christian Democratic Appeal. This second dimension in the Netherlands may
be viewed as gauging beliefs on individual liberty, with a large negative value
corresponding to "Libertarian" views.
The second dimension in Germany is slightly different. A respondent with
a high negative value on this dimension would tend to agree strongly that
"greater public control should be exercised over multinational corporations"
but to disagree strongly that "nuclear energy should be developed in order
to meet future energy needs." We could identify this second dimension in
Germany with "corporatism." However, for convenience, we shall refer to
this second dimension in both countries as a "social" dimension. The factor
loadings in both countries were renormalized so that 95% of all ideal points
in each dimension lay in the range [-2,+2], with the mean position at (0,0).
Note that although both "policy" dimensions in the two countries might
appear to be correlated, our estimates of the underlying density functions (of
voter ideal points) suggest that voter responses are not highly correlated in
these dimensions. In particular, Figure 2 suggests, for example, that a German
voter may simultaneously approve of egalitarian measures as well as believing that nuclear energy should be developed and multinational companies
should be relatively unregulated.
By this method we obtain a "profile" (x) = (Xi)iEN of voter ideal positions,
where each Xi represents, in some degree, the economic and social beliefs of
voter i. Using almost identical questions asked of the party elites, and taking
the median of these elite positions (in both dimensions) for each party, we
obtain an estimate of the "profile" of party positions 4> = (4)j)jEK as given in
Figures I and 2. Given the empirical distribution of voter ideal points, we
can smooth this to approximate the underlying density function of the voters'
positions. The backgrounds in Figures I and 2 give our estimates of these
densities. The combination of (x) and (4)) gives a data matrix 0 = (Oij}if KiEN .
In both countries voting intentions were known, so this gives an array y =
(Yij)K N where Yij = 1 iff voter i intends to vote for j, and 0 otherwise. The
challenge is to estimate a probability matrix (Xij) given (Oij) and (Yij), so that
a realization(X ij ) of (Xij) is close to (Yij). Following the standard assumptions
of the pure spatial probabilistic model described in Section 2, we assume
Prob(uij > Uil for alII i= j)
= Prob(El - Ej < f:l(oJ - DB) : I
Xij
i= j)
Let ei = (EI-Ej, ... Ej-l-Ej, Ej+l-Ej, ... Ek-Ej) be a (k-l) dimensional stochastic variable, with probability density function f and let
~{
= «o~),
... , (oi O~»E9k-l.
[51]
270
Using Equation 1, and conditioning on our assumptions on the implicit
covariance matrix ~ we obtain
(2)
Here the integral is (k-l) dimensional.
The maximum likelihood estimator for X is
(3)
Unlike the usual model where the E'S are assumed to be iid, with zero
expectation, we adopt the multinomial probit (MNP) assumption that f is the
with general variance-covariance matrix, ~. (For
multivariate normal N(O,~)
a discussion of probit models, see Alvarez and Nagler, 1996.)
Markov Chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) techniques (Albert and Chib, 1993;
McCulloch and Rossi, 1994) were used to estimate ~. The details of our
estimation results for the pure spatial model for the Netherlands and Germany
are reported in Appendix A.
Figure 3 presents our estimate of (Xij) in the case of the Netherlands.
Clearly, our estimation of Xij will depend on the ideal point of voter i and the
location of party j. For example, a Dutch voter with an ideal point anywhere
along the "social" axis and at the left extreme on the economic axis "will
vote" for the PvdA with probability exceeding 0.9. On the other hand, any
voter on the extreme right of the economic axis "will vote" for the VVD with
certainty if near the libertarian extreme on the social axis and "will vote" for
the CDA with probability about 0.8 if near the opposite end of the social axis.
These probabilities make intuitive sense. To illustrate further, Figure 4 shows
the distribution of ideal points of those voters who declared in the survey
that they intended to vote for PvdA. The distribution of these voters has been
normalized to sum to unity. Clearly the distribution is unimodal, with its mode
near the PvdA position.
Obviously enough there are voters whose ideal points are nearer the D66
position for example, yet who intend to vote for the PvdA. Clearly a pure
deterministic model of voting does not suffice. Our estimation would assign
to a voter, with such an ideal point, probabilities of approximately .2 for
D66, VVD, and CDA each, and 0.4 for PvdA. Such an assignment is not
implausible.
Figure 5 shows a similar distribution for the ideal points of "CDU" voters
in Germany in 1979. Appendix B presents our estimation results for a joint
electoral model for the Netherlands and Germany, based on multinomial probit, using not only the spatial data but also individual characteristics of the
[52]
271
CI!
o
<CD
;to
"C:''''*:
~o
"!
o
o
co
°
S"!
'P 0
~"': ~
0
~
o
Figure 3a. Estimates of voter probabilities in the Netherlands for the PvdA and D66.
[53]
272
~
«'It!
00
~ Q.
0
C'!
o
o
....
!l,.
Figure 3b. Estimates of voter probabilities in the Netherlands for the CDA and VVD.
[54]
273
C\I
c
CDA
0
'<;;
c
Q)
E
(5
0
0
(ij
'0
WD
0
en
"';"
·2
·1
o
2
Economic Dimension
Figure 4. Dutch party and PvdA voter positions, 1979.
voters (derived from the Rabier, Inglehart, 1981, survey), such as occupation
and income, religion, education, size of town of domicile, etc.
To briefly summarize the results, we find in both countries that the f3coefficient of the pure spatial model is statistically significant while the
estimated covariance matrix is significantly different from the iid model. We
also find that the pure spatial model is statistically superior to the joint model
in the case of Germany. For the Netherlands, the joint electoral model is
superior to the pure spatial model. We attempt to account for this result in
the next section.
To illustrate the effectiveness of the pure spatial model, Table 5 compares
the national, the sample, and the "estimated" vote shares for the four parties
in the Netherlands. Since only four parties are considered in the model , we
give approximate values for the share going to each party, computed as a
percentage of the total national vote going to the four parties.
It is clear that the sample shares (based on n = 529) are quite close to the
national shares for the 1977 and 1981 elections. The estimated vote shares
are computed by finding the expected value, E(n j), of the vote for each party.
Since vote shares are derived from (Xij) and these are random variables, each
vote share is also a random variable. Empirical histograms for the vote share
of the four parties in the Netherlands are given in Figure 6.
The 95% confidence intervals on the estimated vote shares include the
values for the sample shares for three of the four parties. (See Table N2 of the
[55]
274
c
0
'0;
c
CD
E
0
0
(ij
'0
0
U)
";"
-,
-2
o
2
Economic Dimension
Figure 5. German party and CDU voter positions, 1979.
Table 5. Vote shares in the Netherlands' elections, 1977 to 1981
Party
Optimal
1981
Sample share
in 1979a
Estimated
1977
sharec
share
%
%
%
%
%
D66
6.1
12.6
10.4
10.6
II ±4
PvdA
38.0
32.4
36.9
35.3
45 ± 3
CDA
35.9
35.2
33.8
29.9
40 ± 3
40 ± 3
VVD
a
b
c
[56]
Share of national voteb
20.0
19.8
18.9
24.2
100.0
100.0
100.0
100.0
Based on Euro-barometer sample with n =529.
Vote shares are very close to seat shares, because of proportional representation. Shares are calculated on the basis of total vote to the four
large parties, using Keesing 's Contemporary Archives.
Pure spatial model, as described in Appendix A.
275
0 ,0
0.1
0,2
0.3
0.4
25
20
15
10
(ij
0
5
a
c
0
I-
(l)
()
(j)
0..
25
20
15
10
5
0
0.0
0.1
0.2
0,3
0.4
Vote Share
Figure 6. Histograms of estimated vote shares for four parties in the Netherlands (based on
1979 data).
Appendix for details.) The one anomaly to note is that, for the VVO, the national vote share (approximately 20%) and sample share (18.9%) lie outside
the 95% confidence interval (20.8%, 28%) for the estimated expected vote
share. However, the two empirical vote shares lie inside the 95% confidence
interval of (14.9%, 24.6%) obtained from the joint model. The two models
can be compared by considering Tables N2 and N3 in the Appendix.
Table 6 compares the national vote shares for the three parties in the 1976
and 1980 elections, together with the sample shares and our estimates, for
Germany. Figure 7 gives the empirical histograms of the random variables 1Tj
for each party in 1979 in Germany. The point to note is that 95% confidence
intervals for expected vote shares under the pure spatial model for the three
parties are approximately: COU (.49, .58), SPO (.34, .46) and FOP (.01, .14).
These confidence intervals are very similar to the confidence intervals for the
joint model (compare Tables G2 and G3 in the Appendix).
Although these estimates do not provide much more information than
the sample, they do allow us to draw conclusions about the electoral consequences were parties to adopt "strategic" policy positions. This we do in
the next section.
[57]
276
Table 6. Vote shares in Germany, 1976 and 1980
Party
Share of national voteb
Sample share a
% in 1976
in 1979, %
% in 1980
49.1
45.4
51.2
53.2
FDP
8.0
10.8
5.9
6.3
6.4
SPD
42.9
43.8
42.9
40.5
42.6
100.0
100.0
100.0
100.0
100.0
d
0 .2
0.4
0 .6
CD
30
I-
51.0
Based on Euro-barometer sample with n =543 in 1979.
Approximately 320,000 votes (out of over 37 million) for small parties are
not included. These parties were not represented in the Bundestag. Vote
shares are calculated as % of total vote to the three parties. In particular,
the Greens gained 15% of the vote, but no seat in 1980.
Based on the pure spatial model described in Appendix A.
Using individual characteristics, as described in Appendix B.
00
0
Estimated
% shared
CDU
a
b
iii
Estimated
% sharec
SPD
25
20
'0
c:
.5
Q)
~
<I>
a.
10
J
0
0.0
02
0 ,4
[
1i
Il
00
0.6
0.2
04
0.6
Vote Sha re
Figure 7. Histograms of estimated vote shares for the three parties in Germany (based on
1979 data).
It is worth noting, however, that the model we have constructed here, based
as it is on the assumption of "stochastic voters", suggests that the underlying
variation in vote shares is higher than might be supposed from simple analysis
of electoral samples.
5. Models of party behavior derived from the analysis
As we have emphasized, party positions (in the model just described) were
estimated by taking the median of party elite positions. Thus the positions
of the parties are not the same as "declarations" to the electorate. Nonethe-
[58]
277
less, using these estimates of party positions, we found that the pure spatial
MNP model of voting that we have just presented gives a plausible account
of how Dutch and German voters respond to party positions. Thus we may
assume that these party positions did have an effect on electoral response in
the period in question. We now show that changing party positions would lead
to an increase in expected party vote. Let us suppose that the elite members
of the parties in question had beliefs concerning electoral response that are
compatible with the spatial electoral model just discussed.
Consider the thought experiment where each party, j, considers a possible
change in position from ¢j to a "strategic" position, ¢*j, assuming all other
party positions are fixed. Based on our MNP model, we compute the optimal
¢*j, chosen as to maximize expected vote. In the Dutch case the optimal
position for each party is at the electoral mean (that is, at the mean (0,0) of
the sample ideal points). After such a move, our estimates of the vote increase
by significant amounts. Table 5 shows the estimated optimal vote shares for
the four Dutch parties. It indicates that the CDA, for example, could increase
expected vote share by up to 10%, from about 30% to 40%. Had the CDA
positioned itself at the electoral mean in 1977, we estimate that its expected
number of seats would have been 55, rather than 49. 2
Why do the parties not move to the electoral center, as predicted by the
Downsian probabilistic model? To continue the thought experiment, suppose
that during the 1977 election, the CDA positioned itself at the electoral mean,
so that it gained 55 seats, instead of 49. Let us assume further that parties
are committed to the positions they adopt. (We provide, below, an argument
for this commitment.) We shall argue that this increase of seats for the CDA
(coupled with the change of declared policy positions) would have adversely
affected the final policy outcome, from the point of view of the CDA elite. To
see this note that even with 55 seats, the CDA position at the mean, (0,0), is
not a core position. In all probability, the CDA would have been obliged to
form a coalition with the VVD. However, if the CDA were required to bargain
from its declared position, then the policy compromise could in fact be further
from its true policy position than the actual 1977 outcome. The same is true
for the 1981 election situation. More importantly, given our estimate of the
stochastic relationship between the CDA position and its share, there is no
CDA position at which the CDA could have expected to gain a straight seat
majority (given our confidence intervals). Moreover, the probability that the
CDA could have occupied the core is essentially zero.
In the same way, a thought experiment involving the PvdA suggests that
it could have won approximately 60 (±4) seats in the 1981 election, by
moving to the origin. If the PvdA were obliged to commit to that position,
then it would indeed be at a core with high probability and possibly able
[59]
278
to form a minority government. Now compare the situation in 1981 if the
PvdA declares its "true" position in contrast to the outcome resulting from
the PvdA at a core position at the origin. In the former case there is a significant probability of a {PvdA,D66,CDA} coalition in which the PvdA can
presumably affect policy. On the other hand, at the core the PvdA may be
able to implement a minority government, control all the perquisites, but be
obliged to implement a policy far from its ideal position. It is not implausible
that the PvdA party elite would prefer to declare the party's "true" position
(we explore this somewhat further below).
In a situation such as we have described in the Netherlands, we suggest
that there was an insignificant probability that any party could occupy a postelection core position and implement a policy that it found preferable to the
lottery resulting from a true declaration of preference.
The case in Germany is somewhat different. As we have seen, the FOP
is "almost" at the core position and has been in almost every government
for decades. It could be dislodged from this position were the SPD to move
sufficiently close to the FOP. However, assuming policy commitment again,
this would have obliged the SPD to implement a policy that the elite of the
party would have found highly undesirable.
We infer that if a party adopts a policy position simply to increase the
number of seats that it controls, then this may not increase the power that the
party has to implement desired policy. The willingness of a party to adopt
vote maximizing policies depends, therefore, on the trade-off in its "utility"
function between the perquisites of office and the importance of policy. However, to determine the optimal position, it would appear that the party must
compute not just the effect of a change of position on its vote share, but must
also consider how that change affects the post-election lottery over the choice
of the coalition government. If there is no policy change that leads to a potentially "dominant" party being at a core position, with significant probability,
then there are plausible arguments to be made that the declarations of a "true"
policy preference is "rational" for such a party.
To make this argument clearer, we need to examine in more detail our
notion of the preferred point, ¢j, of party j. In our estimation, we chose each
party's point to be at the median (in both dimensions) of the ideal points of
the party elite (using the ISEIUM, 1983, responses of party delegates). To
illustrate, Figure 8 represents our estimate of the density function of the ideal
points of the PvdA delegates. Comparing Figure 8 with Figure 4 (showing
PvdA voter ideal positions), it is clear that the PvdA delegate variance is much
less than PvdA voter variance. It is reasonable to suppose that the PvdA has
some leeway in declaring a pre-election position to the electorate. However, it
is also obvious that the party cannot choose any position at will. If we view the
[60]
279
c
0
'u;
0
cQ)
E
is
0
CDA
0
"iii
'5
VVD
0 '66
0
en
"';"
-2
-1
o
2
Economic Dimension
Figure 8, Empirical distribution of estimated ideal points of PvdA delegates (based on 1979
Dutch data),
PvdA delegates as a committee, then it is almost certain that an internal PvdA
core will exist (under majority decision-making by the delegates). This "internal" party core will lie at the (two-dimensional) median of the delegates'
ideal points. It is therefore sensible to regard this "internal" core position as
the party's ideal point, as we have done in the estimation just discussed.3
Indeed, we can regard this internal party core point as the sincere choice of
the party. Now consider internal party decision-making over the choice of a
policy point to declare to the electorate. Each delegate of the party has an ideal
policy point, as well as beliefs about electoral response and the nature of postelection negotiation. Thus, each delegate will have a personal choice for the
best response the party can make to the policy positions of the other parties.
It is reasonable to suppose that a delegate's "best response" is continuous in
the delegate's ideal point. Since there is a "sincere" internal party core (under
majority rule among the delegates), there will also be an unbeaten choice
among the party delegates for the policy point to offer to the electorate. Such a
point we can refer to as the strategic choice of the party. Clearly, the party may
commit to this position by choosing the leader of the party to be exactly that
delegate whose ideal point coincides with the strategic choice of the party.
Now, consider a situation where each party makes a strategic best response
to the declarations of the other parties. Since the strategic best response will
[6] ]
280
Table 7. Maximizing expected vote
Sample
"Ideal"
share
D66
PvdA
Party
Estimated
95%
point
"Strategic"
point
vote
C.1.
10.4
(-0.1, -0.2)
(-0.1, -0.2)
10.8
(4.5, 16.5)
36.9
33.8
(-1.1, +0.0)
(+0.6, +0.4)
(-1.1, +0.0)
CDA
(+0.6, +0.4)
36.4
32.8
(33.0, 40.0)
(28.0,37.0)
VVD
18.9
(+ 1.2, -0.3)
(+ 1.5, -1.0)
20.0
(16.5, 23.5)
be continuous in the other parties' positions, standard arguments can be used
to demonstrate existence of a mutual strategic best response, or Nash equilibrium. (See Schofield, 1996, for an outline of such an existence proof.) Notice
that this pre-election Nash equilibrium in party positions is credible after the
election, since each party position will be associated with the ideal point of a
member of the party elite. Moreover, this member, the "leader" of the party,
will have every incentive to bargain effectively with other party leaders in
post-election coalition negotiations.
Let us continue with this thought experiment and suppose that the four
parties in the Netherlands had adopted positions that were strategic Nash
equilibria with respect to their beliefs about the electoral response to these
positions, circa 1979-81, and also their beliefs about post-election bargaining. Assume further that the parties' electoral beliefs are generally compatible
with the model of stochastic voting that we have constructed. If we modify the
parties' positions to bring the model's estimated expected vote shares into line
with the 1981 election results, then we have a method to estimate the parties'
declared Nash equilibrium position. Since we have observed an anomaly in
the expected vote share of the VVD, as estimated by our MNP model, this
suggests that we consider a position for the VVD that differs from this party's
sincere position. If we keep the three other parties at their sincere positions
and move the VVD from its sincere position (+1.2,--0.3) to (+ 1.5,-1.0), then
(as Table 7 reports) the estimated expected vote share of the VVD drops from
24.2% to 20.0% and the 95% confidence interval for the party's vote share
changes from (20.8%,28%) to (16.5%,23.5%). This interval now includes the
sample share and the national vote shares of the VVD in the 1977 and 1981
elections. The estimated expected vote shares of the other three parties are
still close to the sample shares.
Of course we have no direct evidence that the VVD did indeed declare a
policy position to the electorate in the 1977 and 1981 elections that was more
radical than its sincere position.
[62]
281
In our view, the choice between the joint electoral model (as described
in Appendix B) and the pure spatial model (incorporating the VVD strategic
position) depends on the plausibility of a theoretical argument about why a
party such as the VVD could rationally choose to declare a policy point which
is more radical or extreme than its sincere internal core position.
Appendix C gives a stylized argument, adapted from Schofield (1993) and
Schofield and Parks (1996), to show that if post-election coalition formation
is represented as a lottery, then a party such as the VVD could indeed choose a
more extreme position. The point to note about this model of party calculation
is that although the VVD may believe that it would lose a few percent of the
vote by declaring a more radical position, it could also plausibly believe that
it would, in expectation, pull the policy compromises made either with the
PvdA or CDA towards its internal core position.
The suggestion that the VVD adopted a more extreme position also allows
us to make sense of the 1977 attempt by the CDA to form a coalition with
the PvdA. As Figure 1 illustrates, the {CDA,VVD} internal core points are
nearer to each other than the {CDA,PvdA} internal core points, and so the
former coalition might appear more likely. If, however, the VVD had adopted
the more extreme position, as we have suggested, so that a {CDA,VVD}
compromise would favor the VVD, then it would indeed be rational for the
CDA to approach the PvdA first.
Of course, such a strategic declaration by the VVD is inherently risky.
Indeed, it may have opened the way for smaller parties to enter the electoral
fray in 1981, leading to the loss of the {VVD,CDA} majority, and to the
diminution of the attractiveness of the VVD as a coalition partner.
Having argued that our analysis suggests why the VVD may have declared
a more extreme position, we can also add somewhat to our earlier suggestion
that the PvdA and CDA would be likely to declare their true, or internal core,
positions. For example, in the case of the PvdA, the more centrist delegates of
the party would presumably prefer a move by the party to the core position,
hoping for a minority PvdA government. On the other hand, more extreme
delegates of the party would prefer a leader of the party to adopt a position
on the left of the economic dimension, hoping to influence policy through
coalition negotiation.
For both the PvdA and CDA we might expect considerable internal disagreement within these parties, resulting however, in policy declarations
chosen to be compromises close to the sincere policy points of the two
parties. 4
The general model we propose emphasizes the heterogeneity of ideal
policy points within each party, j, together with the selection of a leader,
[63 ]
282
whose ideal point, Zj, coincides with the majority choice of an equilibrium
declaration, c/>j*' made by the party elite.
6. Conclusion
Models of elections have generally been based on the "Downsian" assumption of expected vote maximization. The conclusions of such models are at
variance with the observation that parties do not converge to an electoral
center.
The empirical work presented here suggests that a pure spatial electoral
model is quite satisfactory in modeling electoral response to party positions.
The estimation allows us to determine approximately how much party vote
shares would increase as a result of policy convergence to the electoral mean.
Although nominal political power may be increased by such a move, we argue
that the power to implement desired policies need not increase.
For the Netherlands we suggest that the electoral model allows us to distinguish between sincere and strategic party positions. In particular, we infer that
the two larger parties adopted policy positions that were close to their sincere,
or internal core, positions. We have also provided an argument to explain
why a small, non-centrist party such as the VVD, could reasonably adopt a
policy position that is more extreme than its sincere policy position. In Germany, on the other hand, we infer that the balance of preferences within each
party leads to the declaration of a policy point close to the sincere, internal
core, of the party. For both countries, our empirical and theoretical modeling
provides an explanation for the evident fact that parties facing proportional
representation systems do not converge to the electoral center.
We argue that understanding political choice in multiparty democracies
can be based on the following research program: (a) build a stochastic electoral model, of the kind we have constructed here, which can be used as a
proxy for the beliefs ofthe party elite, (b) assume that each party's declaration
is associated with the position of a member of the party elite, who then bargains with other party representatives using the post-election party strength as
a political resource, (c) model the post-election coalitional bargaining game in
terms of a lottery of expected coalition outcome inside the post-election heart,
(d) solve the internal pre-election party negotiation game over the choice of
party representative and party declaration.
We intend to develop this framework in future research, by rejecting the
usual assumption that each party is a unitary actor, and by studying the relationship between party declarations (or manifestos) and the distribution of
elite ideal points. We also hope to relate this model of internal party choice
[64 ]
283
to current work on post-election coalition negotiation (Schofield, Sened, and
Nixon, 1997).
We suggest that the combination of stochastic electoral models of elections together with spatial committee analysis can provide a theoretically
powerful, and substantively relevant way to understand party dynamics in
multiparty polities based on proportional representation. Although plurality
electoral systems are more difficult than proportional systems to analyse,
it should be possible, in principle at least, to extend the analysis to study
strategic behavior in Westminster style polities. Finally, since the underlying
model involves delegates, it should also be possible to deal with factional
polities without disciplined parties.
By concentrating on elite political actors, instead of parties, it may be
possible to begin to consider the question of the formation of elite groups and
the building of political parties. By this method we may gain a better understanding of the differences between the various types of polities mentioned
in the introduction, and contribute to the development of a formal theory of
comparative politics.
Notes
1. The effective number is the inverse of the Herfindahl index of concentration.
2. Note that the "electoral heart" of the sample, and presumably of the entire electorate, is
a very small set lying close to the origin (0,0). The relationship between the "electoral
heart" and the "political heart", as generated by party positions and weights, is one way
to characterize a multiparty system.
3. Even if the internal PvdA core is empty, the "heart" of the PvdA delegates, viewed as a
committee, will be a very small set centered on this two-dimensional median.
4. Of course, one could fine-tune the electoral model to equate all expected vote shares with
sample vote shares, leading us to infer that all parties "strategize". This would seem somewhat pedantic, given the margins of error. The indirect evidence for VVD strategizing
persists even if we use the delegates' mean position rather than the median.
References
Albert, J.H. and Chib, S. (1993). Bayesian analysis of binary and polychotomous response
data. Journal of the American Statistical Association 88: 669-679.
Alvarez, R.M. and Nagler, 1. (1996). Correlated disturbances in discrete choice models:
A comparison of multinomial probit models and logit models. Typescript. Pasadena:
California Institute of Technology.
Aranson, P., Hinich, M. and Ordeshook, P. (1974). Election goals and strategies: Equivalent
and non-equivalent candidate objectives. American Political Science Review 68: 135-152.
Axelrod, R. (1970). Conflict of interest. Chicago: Markham.
[65 ]
284
Budge, 1., Robertson, D. and Hearl, D. (Eds.). (1987). Ideology, strategy and party change.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chib, S. and Greenberg, E. (1996). Multinomial probit by Markov Chain Monte Carlo.
Typescript. Washington University in St. Louis.
Coughlin, P. (\ 992). Probabilistic voting theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cox, G.w. (1984). An expected utility model of electoral competition. Quality and Quantity
18: 337-349.
Cox, G.W. (1987). The uncovered set and the core. American Journal of Political Science
408-422.
de Swaan, A. (1973). Coalition theories and cabinet formations. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper and Row.
Duverger, J. (1954). Political parties: Their organization and activity in the modern state.
New York: Wiley.
Duverger, J. (1984). Which is the best electoral system? In A. Lijphart and B. Grofman (Eds.),
Choosing an electoral system. New York: Praeger.
EneIow, J.M. and Hinich, J.J. (1984). The spatial theory of voting: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Feddersen, T.J. (1992). A voting model implying Duverger's law and positive turnout.
American Journal of Political Science 34: 1005-1016.
Herman, V. and Pope, J. (1973). Minority governments in western democracies. British
Journal of Political Science 3: 191-212.
Hinich, MJ. (1977). Equilibrium in spatial voting: The median voter result is an artifact.
Journal of Economic Theory 16: 208-219.
Hotelling, H. (1929). Stability in competition. Economic Journal 39: 41-57.
ISEIUM. (1983). European elections study: European political parties' middle-level elites.
Europa-Institut, Universitat Mannheim.
Kass, RE. and Raftery, A.E. (1995). Bayes factors. Journal of the American Statistical
Association 90: 773-795.
Keesing's Contemporary Archives. Harlow: Longman.
Kramer, G.H. (1978). Existence of electoral equilibrium. In P. Ordeshook (Ed.), Game theory
and political science. New York: New York University Press.
Laver, M. and Schofield, N. (1990). Multiparty governments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lin, T., Enelow, J. and Dorussen, H. (1996). Equilibrium in multicandidate probabilistic
spatial voting. Typescript. University of Texas, Austin.
Martin, A.D. and Quinn, K.M. (1997). Evaluating theories of West German voting behavior.
Typescript. Washington University in St. Louis.
McCulloch, R and Rossi. P.E. (1994). An exact likelihood analysis ofthe multinomial probit
model. Journal of Econometrics 64: 207-240.
McKelvey, R.D. (1986). Covering, dominance and institution-free properties of social choice.
American Journal of Political Science 30: 283-314.
McKelvey, RD. and Schofield, N. (1986). Structural instability of the core. Journal of
Mathematical Economics 15: 179-198.
Osborne, M.J. (1993). Candidate positioning and entry in a political competition. Games and
Economic Behavior 5: 133-151.
Osborne, M.J. (1995). Spatial models of political competition under plurality rule: A survey
of some explanations of the number of candidates and the positions they take. Canadian
Journal of Economics 28: 261-301.
Poole, K.T. and Rosenthal, H. (1991). Patterns of congressional voting. American Journal of
Political Science 35: 228-278.
[66]
285
Quinn, K.M., Martin, A.D. and Whitford, A.B. (1996). Explaining voter choice in a multiparty democracy: A look at data from the Netherlands. Typescript. Washington University
in St. Louis.
Rabier, J.-R. and Inglehardt, R. (1981). Eurobarometer 11. April 1979: The Year of the Child
in Europe Ann Arbor: Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research.
Riker, W. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Riker, W.H. (1982). The two-party system and Duverger's Law: An essay in the history of
political science. American Political Science Review 76: 753-766.
Saari, D. (1996). The generic existence of a core for q-rules. Economic Theory 9: 219-260.
Schofield, N. (1985). Social choice and democracy. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.
Schofield, N. (1986). Existence of a 'structurally stable' equilibrium for a non-collegial voting
rule. Public Choice 51: 267-284.
Schofield, N. (1993). Political competition in multiparty coalition governments. European
Journal of Political Research 23: 1-33.
Schofield, N. (l995a). Existence of a smooth social choice functor. In W. Barnett, H. Moulin,
M. Salles, and N. Schofield (Eds.), Social Choice. Welfare and Ethics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Schofield, N. (1995b). Coalition politics: A formal model and empirical analysis. Journal of
Theoretical Politics 7: 245-281.
Schofield, N. (1996). The heart of a polity. In N. Schofield (Ed.), Collective decision making:
Social choice and political economy. Boston: Kluwer.
Schofield, N. (1997a). Multiparty electoral politics. In D. Mueller (Ed.), Perspectives on public
choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schofield, N. (1997b). The Cl topology on the space of smooth preference profiles. Social
Choice and Welfare (forthcoming).
Schofield, N. and Parks, R. (1996). Existence of a Nash equilibrium in a spatial model of
coalition bargaining. Typescript. Washington University in St. Louis.
Schofield, N., Sened, I. and Nixon, D. (1997). Nash equilibrium in multi-party competition
with 'stochastic' voters. Annals of Operations Research (forthcoming).
Taylor, M. and Laver, M. (1973). Government coalitions in Western Europe. European Journal
of Political Research I: 205-248.
Wada, J. and Schofield, N. (1996). Bargaining in the Liberal Democratic Party of Japan. In N.
Schofield (Ed.), Collective decision-making: Social choice and political economy. Boston:
Kluwer.
Appendix A: Spatial model
The Euro-barometer questionnaire (Rabier and Inglehart, 1981) asked seven
questions covering topics such as income distribution, terrorism, nuclear energy,
public control of enterprises, environmental protection, control of multinational
corporations and abortion. Seven similar questions were asked of political elites of
known party allegiance (through the Institut fur Sozialwissenschaft and the Europa
Institute, Universitat Mannheim, 1983). Exploratory factor analysis uncovered two
factors in both the Netherlands and Germany. Tables N-I and G-\ give the factor
[67]
286
Table N-l. Factor loadings, The Netherlands
Issue
Dimension 1
Dimension 2
Income distribution
+.510 (10.86)
-0.148 (1.92)
Terrorism
-0.232 (4.28)
-0.253 (2.51)
Nuclear energy
-0.297 (6.74)
Enterprises
+0.526 (12.0)
Environment
+0.306 (7.46)
MNC
+0.612 (12.6)
-0.229 (2.42)
Abortion
+0.327 (5.56)
+0.39 (2.45)
Chi-square over d.oJ. = 1.76. Sample size (n) = 529.
Table G-l. Factor loadings, Germany
Issue
Dimension 1
Dimension 2
Economic
"Corporatism"
Income distribution
.331 (5.8)
+0.156 (2.51)
Terrorism
0.351 (6.2)
-0.273 (3.73)
-0.641 (4.78)
Nuclear energy
Environment
0.668 (9.1)
-0.173 (2.62)
MNC
0.343 (5.71)
+0.222 (3.26)
Abortion
0.283 (5.24)
Chi-square over d.o.f. = 3.11. Sample size (n) = 543.
loadings on the various issues as follows (t-values in parentheses). In Germany, the
question on enterprises was redundant.
Responses to the seven questions (ranging from strongly favor (I) to strongly
oppose (4)) were renormalized to have mean 0, standard deviation I.
The factor loadings were then used to generate scoring coefficients for each of
the responses for each country. These were combined to give for each voter an ideal
point on the two dimensions. The same technique was employed for the political
elites. Knowing party allegiance we computed the median of the elite for each party
on each dimension. This was used as our estimator for each party's ideal or "sincere"
policy point.
For reasons of identification of the estimation for the Netherlands we adopted a
variant of the probabilistic model, using the D66 party as a baseline. That is, letting
¢4 be the estimated position of the D66 party we assumed that realized utility of
[68]
287
voter i for party j, given (411, ... ,414), was
Uij(41)
fJo - fJ(8ij)2
Ui4(41) = E4·
+ fJ(8i4)2 + Ej for j =
1,2,3, and
Just as in Section 4, Prob (Uij > Uil for alII =1= j) =Prob(ej < fJll\). Under the usual
assumption of independence of errors it is an easy matter to show that the variance
(EI-Ej) = variance (EI) + variance(Ej) while the covariance terms are cov( EI-Ej,Em-Ej)
=variance (Ej). In our analysis we used a statistical routine involving Markov Chain
Monte Carlo Simulation and data augmentation, due to Chib and Greenberg (1996),
that did not assume iid errors.
(Technical details can be found in Quinn, Martin, and Whitford, 1997, and Martin
and Quinn, 1997).
To present the results for the Netherlands, we use the code
{PvdA,VVD,CDA,D66} == {1,2,3,4}. We define the covariance terms aIm = COV(EIE4,E m-E4) and the variance terms a2u = var(El-E4).
Table N-2 presents our estimate for these variance, covariance terms, together
with the estimated coefficients fJo (constant) and fJ (spatial distance).
Note that the model is unchanged if all utility terms are multiplied by a constant.
Thus, to identify the model we assume a 211 = 1.0, and present the variance and
covariance estimates in terms of a211.
The logarithms of the marginal likelihood for these pure spatial models are -545
(for the Netherlands) and -506 (for Germany). The Bayes' factors (Kass and Raftery,
1995) for comparing these models with a null hypothesis (that X is not determined
by the matrix 8) gives vanishingly small probability to the null hypothesis.
The estimated 95% confidence intervals strongly suggest that the coefficients, fJo
and fJ, are significantly non-zero. Moreover, confidence intervals on the covariance
matrix indicate that the covariance terms are generally not half variance terms (as
would be true under iid).
To present the estimation for Germany, we use the code {SPD,CDU,FDP} =
{ 1,2,3} and normalize with respect to the FDP. Table G-2 presents our findings.
Again a211 is set at 1.0. Clearly the two variance terms (a 211 and a 222) are
dissimilar. It is possible, but not probable, that the covariance term a 12 is 0.5.
Appendix B: Individual factors
We also estimated a joint model utilizing the spatial matrix (8ij) but involving individual and demographic characteristics that were recorded in the Rabier-Inglehart
Survey.
[69 ]
288
Table N-2. Estimation results for the Pure Spatial Model in the Netherlands
Parameter
Party
Spatial distance
Constant
Posterior
mean
SD
95%CI
Lower Upper
0.456
0.512
0.120
0.064
0.230
0.391
0.710
0.638
1.000
-0.376
-0.107
1.012
0.384
0.696
0.000
0.261
0.188
0.289
0.200
0.248
1.000
-0.769
-0.426
0.618
0.092
0.360
1.000
0.084
0.224
1.546
0.752
1.134
0.044
0.027
0.022
0.027
0.038
0.309
0.208
0.255
0.182
0.397
0.280
0.342
Variance-covariance estimates
a 2 11
a12
a13
a 222
a23
a233
Sample vote share
D66
PvdA
VVD
CDA
0.104
0.369
0.189
0.338
Predicted vote share
D66
PvdA
VVD
CDA
0.106
0.353
0.242
0.299
Table N3 records the effect of incorporating these additional characteristics. As
the table shows, estimated vote shares for D66 and PvdA hardly shift. The high
estimated value of the VVD share now drops from 24.2% to 19.5% (close to the
sample share of 18.9%), while the low share for the CDA of 29.9% climbs to 34.9%
(close to the sample share of33.8%).
The logarithm of the marginal likelihood increases from -545 to -515.
To interpret the increase of log likelihood as we change from the pure spatial
model, to the joint model, we can compute the Bayes' Factor (Kass and Raftery,
(1995) between the two models. This is simply the ratio of the marginal likelihoods
of the joint and spatial models, and can be computed as exp (-515 + 545) =exp (30)
> 1013. This suggests that the joint model is superior, in a statistically significant
sense, to the pure spatial model. As a comparison of the confidence intervals on the
VVD vote share suggests, the joint model is statistically superior to the pure spatial
model in capturing voting behavior in the Netherlands.
Table G3 records the effects of incorporating the individual and demographic
characteristics in the model for Germany. Clearly, expected vote shares become close
[70]
289
Table G-2. Estimation results for the Pure Spatial Model in Germany.
Parameter
Party
Spatial distance
Constant
Posterior
mean
SD
95% CI
Lower Upper
0.239
1.078
0.066
0.228
0.120
0.604
0.377
1.509
1.000
0.025
3.735
0.000
0.431
2.009
1.000
-0.644
1.361
1.000
0.727
7.942
0.039
0.038
0.029
0.013
0.337
0.486
0.136
0.462
0.578
Variance-covariance estimates
U
2 11
U\2
U
2 22
Sample vote share
FDP
SPD
CDU
0.059
0.429
0.512
Predicted vote share
FDP
SPD
CDU
0.063
0.405
0.532
to the sample shares. In particular the SPD share increases from 40% to 42.6% (close
to the sample of 42.9%).
The logarithm of the marginal likelihood drops from -506 to -623.
The Bayes' Factor between the spatial and joint models for Germany is now
exp (-506 + 623) = exp (117) > 1050. This suggests that the pure spatial model is
statistically superior to the joint model in Germany, at least in the period in question.
This is intuitively obvious from the fact that all sample vote shares lie within the
95% confidence intervals of the predicted vote share.
Appendix C: Strategic party choice
Here, we briefly outline the model of post election coalition bargaining, proposed in
Schofield and Parks (1996). Suppose that three parties {A,B,C} have the ideal points
presented in Figure 9, and that the parties are committed to their declarations (in
the manner proposed in the text). For ease of presentation suppose that they believe
that, whatever their declarations, the electoral response will result in party strengths
such that any pair of parties will control a majority. If the parties' declarations are
[71]
290
Table N-3. Estimation results for the Joint Model, the Netherlands
Variable
Party
Spatial distance
Manual labor
Religion
Income
Posterior
mean
OA99
SD
95% CI
Lower
Upper
0.065
0.376
0.627
PvdA
0.926
0.252
VVD
CDA
-0.714
OA56
OA44
-1.699
0.103
0.239
0.264
-0.274
0.777
PvdA
-0.060
0.082
-0.225
0.101
1.421
VVD
-0.112
0.114
-0.353
0.092
CDA
0.504
0.098
0.339
0.735
PvdA
VVD
-0.012
0.022
0.028
-0.054
0.032
0.108
CDA
0.049
-0.010
0.021
-0.001
-0.052
PvdA
0.382
VVD
-0.131
0.103
0.137
-OA27
0.582
0.111
CDA
-0.046
0.113
-0.279
0.158
PvdA
-0.083
-0.007
0.029
-0.141
-0.028
VVD
0.038
-0.080
0.067
CDA
-0.077
0.028
-0.140
-0.026
0.256
0.239
-0.185
0.767
1.000
-0.350
0.000
0.265
1.000
-0.772
1.000
0.104
0"13
2
0"22
-0.065
0.193
-0.386
1.782
0"23
2
0"33
0.564
0.671
0.695
0.309
0.933
0.161
0.252
2.948
0.233
0.380
1.067
Town size
Education
Constant
0.179
0.031
Variance-covariance estimates
2
0" II
0"12
Sample vote share
Predicted vote share
[72 ]
D66
0.104
PvdA
0.369
1.107
VVD
0.189
CDA
0.338
D66
0.108
0.030
0.061
0.161
PvdA
0.347
0.306
VVD
0.195
0.026
0.028
0.149
0.389
0.246
CDA
0.349
0.030
0.301
OA01
291
Table G-3. Estimation results for the Joint Model, Germany
Posterior
Parameter
Party
Religion
Income
Town size
Education
95% CI
Lower
Upper
0.295
0.079
0.154
0.466
SPD
0.358
0.275
-1.174
0.910
CDU
-0.269
0.467
-1.251
0.606
Spatial distance
Manuallabor
SD
mean
SPD
-0.341
0.467
-0.641
-0.015
CDU
0.946
0.393
0.312
1.827
SPD
-0.023
0.028
-0.078
0.030
CDU
-0.056
0.047
-0.154
0.033
SPD
0.096
0.127
-0.154
0.347
CDU
-0.594
0.247
-1.146
-0.165
SPD
-0.068
0.043
-0.015
0.015
CDU
-0.117
0.082
-0.286
0.037
1.843
0.474
0.978
2.835
1.000
0.000
1.000
1.000
Constant
Variance-covariance estimates
0"2\\
0"\2
0.035
0.379
-0.584
0.670
0"222
7.292
4.106
2.442
14.936
0.026
0.026
0.111
Sample vote share
Predicted vote share
FDP
0.059
SPD
0.429
CDU
0.512
FDP
0.064
SPD
0.426
0.033
0.368
0.481
CDU
0.510
0.029
0.462
0.558
[73]
292
sincere, then coalition policy outcomes will be a lottery across the "heart" ABC. Let
U(ABC) be the von Neumann Morgenstern utility of party C for this lottery, where
U is derived from the underlying Euclidean preferences of the party. Consider a
possible declaration by party C of the position C', chosen such that the triangles
{C' ,C,B}, {C' ,C,A} and {A,B,C} are all equivalent. By symmetry each of these
lotteries occurs with probability, ~, so the von Neumann utility of party C for the
lottery across ABC' can be represented as
U(ABC') =
~U(ABC)
+ ~U(C'B)
+ ~U(C'A).
C'
B
Figure 9. Strategic party choice
By symmetry again U(ABC)=U(C'CB) = U(C'CA), so U(ABC') = U(ABC).
If the lotteries are continuous in the declarations, and U is continuous then there
exists a point C" on the arc [C,C'] which maximizes U. This point C" is the best
response of party C to the declarations, A and B. Similar arguments show existence
of a Nash equilibrium, namely mutual best responses of j}(' by A to B", e", etc.
Obviously, the best response C" by e depends on the assumptions made on the
nature of the lottery. Schofield and Parks (1996) have made specific assumptions on
the nature of this lottery, which permit computation of best response. To illustrate
suppose after the declarations {A,B,C}, that coalition {A,B} chooses as a policy
compromise the mid-point !(A + B) = D, etc., and that coalitions occur with probability inversely proportional to the distance between coalition members. Thus, when
party C declares position C, then coalition {C,B} chooses the midpoint E = ! (B+C),
and when party C chooses C', then the same coalition {C,B} chooses E' = !(C' +B).
It is evident from Figure 9 that the best response by C to {A,B} is a point C", such
[74 ]
293
that the midpoint E" = ~(C"
+B) minimizes the distance between C and the arc EE'Thus best response by C is to adopt a more extreme position than its ideal point.
Under the above assumptions on the coalition lottery, Schofield and Parks show
that with the given configuration of ideal points, parties A and B will converge to
one another in Nash equilibrium, while C will "diverge." If non-policy portfolios are
added to the calculations, the extent of convergence by A and B will increase, while
C's divergence will decrease.
To extend this model to the case of heterogeneous preferences within party C, for
example, note that any delegate of the party with an ideal point in a neighborhood of
C will have a best response that is further from the line AB than is their ideal point.
We suggest that such a model of best response accounts for our empirical inference
that the VVD adopted a more extreme strategic position than its ideal, or internal
core, point.
Computation of best response and of Nash equilibrium is highly nonlinear and
can only be analytically computed in simple symmetric situations such as described
by Figure 9. In general, asymmetries in the configuration of the parties' sincere
choices will become even more exaggerated when the parties adopt best responses
to each others' positions. These inferences appear to be rohust with respect to the
specific assumptions made about the coalition lotteries.
[75]
Public Choice 97: 295-322, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
295
Issue competition in the 1993 Norwegian national election *
STUART ELAINE MACDONALD 1, GEORGE RABINOWITZ 1 & OLA
LISTHAUG2
1Department of Political Science, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, Chapel Hill,
NC 27599-3265, U.S.A.; 2 Department of Sociology and Political Science, Norwegian
University of Science and Technology, N-7055 Dragvoll, Norway
Abstract. We investigate the role of issues in the 1993 Norwegian election. We are interested
in comparing two spatial models of issue evaluation, the directional model and the familiar
proximity model. The directional model implies that voters ask two questions of parties:
Are you on my side? and Can I trust you to be responsible? This contrasts with the classic
proximity question: How close are your positions to mine?
Prior analysis of Norwegian voters has favored the directional model. The empirical story
in 1993, however, features a traditional centrist party, the agrarian Center Party, running quite
strongly, which on the surface, at least, challenges the directional model, and presents an
interesting case to observe. We also extend our analysis to examine more generally the impact
of issues on the election. This unrestricted analysis adds texture to our understanding of the
role of issues, while its results dovetail with the analysis of the specific models. When people
evaluated parties on the basis of issues in Norway in 1993, the directional model describes
that dynamic well.
1. Introduction
In democracies, voters often use issues to make judgments about political
parties. In the traditional proximity world, voters ask of parties: "How close
are your positions to mine?" (e.g., Downs, 1957; Davis, Hinich, and Ordeshook, 1970; Enelow and Hinich, 1984; Hinich and Munger, 1994).1 In the
directional world, voters ask: "Are you on the same side of the issues I am,
and can I trust you to be responsible?" (Rabinowitz and Macdonald, 1989;
Macdonald, Listhaug, and Rabinowitz, 1991; Macdonald and Rabinowitz,
1993). The directional model argues that voters only have preferences for
policy direction, and that parties stimulate support by taking strong stands in
* We are grateful to Roar Haskjold for research assistance, and to the Norwegian University
of Science and Technology and the Arts and Sciences Foundation of the University of North
Carolina at Chapel Hill for financial support. The 1993 Norwegian National Election Study,
directed by Bernt Aardal and Henry Valen, was made available by the Norwegian Social Science Data Services. Neither the principal investigators nor the archive bear any responsibility
for our interpretation of the data.
[77]
296
the direction voters favor. Parties must develop intensity in order to generate
issue-based support, but are constrained in their intensity by the need to be
viewed as responsible.
Like the proximity model, the directional model is both rational and spatial. As will become clearer in the discussion of the theories below, the key
difference between the models is the lack of precision in voter preference in
directional theory. This leads issues to be dichotomous rather than multipositional, and voters to assess pragmatic capability as well as specific issue
agreement from party issue position.
What types of party systems are expected to emerge in multiparty systems? The directional model makes the specific prediction that parties located
in the center of the directional space - a position which lacks intensity should be electorally weak (Macdonald, Listhaug, and Rabinowitz, 1991).
In general in directional theory the strongest positions should be noncentrist
and nonextreme. It is more difficult to answer this question for the proximity model. Based on the work of Cox (1990), we can generally assume that
parties will tend to be widely dispersed in the political space in a multiparty
system. Beyond that, the traditional spatial model has little to say about party
strategy in such systems.
In Norway seven parties seriously compete for seats in the Storting, the
Norwegian Parliament. The two largest vote-getting parties are Labor, a traditional social democratic party, and the Conservatives, the traditional party
of the moderate right. On Labor's left is the Socialist Party, and on the Conservatives' right is the Progressive Party, a Norwegian version of a party of
the reactionary right. There are three parties that traditionally fall in the center
of the left-right spectrum, the Center Party, the Christian People's Party, and
the Liberal Party. The Center Party normally receives the bulk of its support
from farmers and those sympathetic to farm interests. The Christian People's
Party represents the moral perspective of the Church, and draws support from
the more religious in the society. The Liberals have traditionally been the
one true center party in Norway. They are somewhat like the more familiar
Liberals (now Liberal Democrats) in Britain, in that they were originally the
main opposition party to the Conservatives only to be outflanked by Labor
when the working class became politically active. The Liberals were the only
one of the seven major parties to fall below the 5% threshold in 1989; hence
they had no representatives in the Storting prior to the 1993 election.
In terms of governmental control, after the 1989 election, the Center, Christian, and Conservative parties formed a minority government, which collapsed in the fall of 1990 on the European Union issue. From 1990 to 1993
the Labor Party controlled the government, although with a minority of seats.
[78]
297
LEFT
i
i
-4
-3
•
I
-2
RIGHT
i
-1
i
i
2
3
0
Intensity
Neutral
Center
I
4
.
Intensity
Figure 1. Political ideology.
Traditionally Labor has refused to allow other parties to share government
with them, a strategy that has been quite effective. 2
In prior work (Macdonald, Listhaug, and Rabinowitz, 1991), we have
studied the Norwegian system in the 1989 election, and found a politics that
looked strikingly directional in character. The 1993 election presents a second
look at Norway, a look which might hold some surprises. The largest single
change in support for any party from 1989 to 1993 was a strong surge in
support for the Center Party. Could this be an instance in which the center
has become a lively source of support? We shall see. Before turning to the
analysis of the role of issues, it is useful to review the theories and observe
how we would expect evaluation to depend on issue position under the two
models.
2. An overview of directional theory
For illustrative purposes, Figure 1 shows a directional continuum of political
ideology. The selection of ideology is simply for convenience - directional
theory is oriented toward policy issues, but ideology provides a familiar referent and facilitates the use of the terms "left" and "right" to designate the
opposing sides. 3 In the figure notice that the continuum is clearly separated
into two sides with a neutral center point. An individual is on one side or the
other of an issue, or neutral. Position in directional theory reflects the intensity
with which a voter supports her side on the issue. The neutral point is the
position of zero intensity where the voter favors neither side. In the figure,
the center point is given a score of zero. Negative values signify support for
the left and positive values support for the right. The designation of signs is
arbitrary, so we follow the normal convention that values go from negative
to positive as they move from left to right. The values increase in absolute
magnitude to indicate increasing intensity.
Parties as well as individuals can be placed on the directional continuum.
Parties are positioned more distant from the neutral center as a consequence
of how strongly they advocate positions of the left or the right. Parties that
[79]
298
are consistent and vocal advocates of left policies would be positioned well
to the left, those that are more equivocal yet generally favorable toward the
left would be located on the moderate left, and so on across the spectrum.
Of course, party position is not solely a function of the party's own efforts; it
can be influenced by opposition strategy as well as by the media and ongoing
events.
Notice on the continuum in Figure 1 a short vertical line near each end of
the scale. These lines delimit an area called the "region of acceptability." In
directional theory there is the explicit idea that parties may be perceived as
responsible and trustworthy in government or as irresponsible and not to be
trusted. This perception is tied to the issue positions they advocate. Parties
that are outside the region of acceptability are penalized by at least some
voters. The placement of the lines on the ideology continuum is a bit artificial
because being outside the region of acceptability is a function of the entire
set of positions a party advocates. Nevertheless, it serves to illustrate the idea
that parties with consistently extreme positions are likely to lose support.
In directional theory, voters are attracted to parties by clear cues for their
preferred side. Hence, parties generate support from voters on their side by
being fairly intense; they need only temper their appeal enough to avoid being
perceived as extremist. Voters who are intense are more receptive to party
cues. They are more enthusiastic about cues for "their side" and more opposed
to cues for "the other side." Voters in the center are neutral, and thus will
support all parties within the region of acceptability about the same. Similarly,
center parties provide no cues to either side, so they tend to be evaluated the
same by people across the issue spectrum.
These ideas are reflected in the form of the utility or affect function for a
party. In directional theory, affect is a monotonic function of Aij, where
(1)
where
Iik is the position of voter i on the directional continuum for issue k,
Ijk is the position of party j on issue k,
Sk is the general importance of the issue to the election, and
P ij = 0 when bkITk :::: r2; Pij > 0 when bkIJk > r2
where r defines the maximum intensity level of a party before it is penalized.
Notice that the function captures the essential ideas of the theory. When
the party and voter are on the same side, the product IikIjk will be positive; if
the party and voter are on opposite sides, the product will be negative. The
more intense either the voter or the party, the higher the absolute value of
the product will be. The affect function implies than a party will draw more
[80 ]
299
favorable ratings from voters on its side when it is more intense, at least until
it reaches the boundary of the region of acceptability. Thus, within the region,
utility is dependent on the scalar product between the voter and party vectors,
CEkIikIjk). Issues are allowed to have differential salience, but it is a general
rather than personal salience. 4 And, finally, notice that a party at the neutral
center will be evaluated the same by voters anywhere because the party's
scale value Ijk will be zero.
3. Comparing the theories
We have said less about the traditional proximity model because it is more
familiar. In the model each voter is assumed to have a specific ideal point that
represents the policy she most prefers. And each party offers a set of policy
alternatives that locate the party at a particular point in a multidimensional
issue space. According to the model a voter will evaluate most favorably the
party whose position is closest. Therefore, utility declines with Euclidean distance (or, equivalently, distance squared). Thus, utility is a monotone function
of A ij , where
(2)
where
8ik is the position of voter i on the proximity continuum for issue k,
8 jk is the position of party j on issue k, and
Sk is the general importance of the issue to the election.
Now let us see how parties would be evaluated under the two models as a
function of issue position. Figure 2 illustrates the predictions for four parties:
a center party (C), a moderate right party (MR), a moderate left party (ML),
and a far right party (FR).5 The most marked contrast in prediction is for the
center party (C). According to directional theory, this party offers no cues
about which side of the issue it supports; thus it will activate no particular
evaluation based on the issue. If this issue were the sole criterion of judgment,
voters anywhere on the spectrum would feel the same way about the party.
Therefore, the directional curve is flat. Under the proximity model, the party
at the center matches precisely the desires of center voters and they respond
with high evaluations for the center party. Moving away from the center in
either direction, voter affinity for the policies of the party decreases and thus
their evaluation. The resulting relationship is clearly peaked.
Next we consider a party at a moderate right location (MR) on the scale.
According to directional theory, this party will be liked by voters on the right
and disliked by voters on the left, while voters in the center will be neutral.
[81]
300
Proximity Illustration
Directional Illustration
100
100
E
v
a
" FR
80
80
MR
I
U
a
~-c
I
i
o
,,
60
60
MR
,,
C
40
40
n
"
20
""
ML
20
ML
0
~
4
~
4
~
0
1
Left-RighI
2
3
4
5
-5
-4
-3
-2
-1
0
1
2
3
4
5
Left-RighI
Figure 2. Illustrative sketches comparing the two theories.
Notice that the highest evaluation comes from voters farthest to the right.
These voters are the most enthusiastic for the right side of the issue and thus
endorse the party most fully, This is different from the proximity model. The
voters who will be the strongest supporters for the moderate right party in
the proximity model are the voters who share its particular policy mix. Thus,
the highest evaluation will come from voters themselves at a moderate right
location. Voters at the far right will not like the party as well because its
policies do not match their ideal point. Again the support curve is peaked; the
peak has just shifted to the right. Peak support in proximity theory is always
at the party location.
The directional curve for the center party is flat while the curves for the
moderate right and moderate left parties have a clear slope. In general, in
directional theory the more extreme the party, the steeper the slope will be. In
the figure the curves for the center and moderate parties intersect at the point
of neutrality. In directional theory, the support curves of all parties within
the region of acceptability cross at the neutral point. This is important for it
implies that voters on the right side of the neutral point - even those who
are closer to the center - will like the right party more than the center party,
and voters on the left will like the left party more. Thus, center parties are
clearly disadvantaged in directional theory; they lose voters on the right to
moderate right parties and voters on the left to moderate left parties. Center
parties are not even advantaged among centrist voters; they are simply on an
even footing with the other parties among these voters who care little about
the issue.
[82]
301
The last curve in Figure 2 is drawn for a far right party (FR). This party
is hypothetically beyond the region of acceptability in directional theory and
hence has a lower utility for most voters. The proximity curve for the party
peaks at the far right position. Like the directional curve, the proximity curve
is virtually monotonic in this case, reflecting the fact that the theories make
similar predictions for extreme parties.
4. The 1993 Norwegian election
In order to test the theories we need several pieces of information. Most critically we need to know where the voters stand on a set of issues relevant to the
campaign, where the parties stand on those same issues, and how the voters
evaluate the parties. We also need demographic information about the voters,
so that the analyses will not attribute to issues, effects that are a function of
social circumstance. All this information is available in the 1993 Norwegian
Election Study.
The hot new issue in the 1993 election centered on whether or not Norway should join the EU. It was not the first time the issue had come before
Norwegian voters. There had been a divisive referendum in 1972. In the referendum the Labor Party had supported joining the Common Market, and
had paid a price for that in the '73 election. There was good reason to think
that history would repeat itself. Once again the leadership of the Labor Party
was supporting membership and a substantial block of their supporters were
opposed.
But this is getting a bit ahead of the data-analytic story. The 1993 election
survey contained five issue questions on which respondents were asked to
place themselves and the seven parties. Each of these was a lO-point scale
with the endpoints labeled with extreme positions. The questions dealt with
left-right position, environmental protection, immigration policy, unemployment policy, and EU membership. The full wording of the questions appears
in the Appendix. There was reason to think that all of these issues would
be important in the election. Left-right is consistently consequential in voter
choice, and immigration, environmental protection, and unemployment policy remained controversial. The national referendum on EU was just a year
away.
The mean positions of the parties and the voters are displayed in Table 1.
The positions are on a centered scale which ranges from -4.5 to +4.5, rather
than the original 1 to lO. When appropriate, the scales have been reflected
so that negative values represent positions on the political left and positive
values positions on the right. The parties are arranged in what is generally
thought of as their left to right order. This matched their public perception
as measured by the surveys in 1989 but not in 1993. Labor was placed to
[83 ]
302
the right of the Liberal Party, although remaining distinctly on the left side of
the scale. The three center parties (Liberal, Center, and Christian People's) all
made a distinct leftward shift in 1993, while both Labor and the Conservatives
moved rightward. The population mean also took a clear shift in the left direction. While all the changes were modest (within a half unit on the lO-point
scale), there was quite a lot of movement. Perhaps it was not coincidental that
every change was consistent with party position on the EU scale. The Center,
Liberal, and Christian parties were all on the anti-EU side, which is generally
seen as the left side of the issue in Norway. Both Labor and the Conservative
Party were on the pro-EU side. The respondent mean position was distinctly
anti-EU. Notably on unemployment policy, the specific issue that conforms
most closely to traditional left-right distinctions, the parties order in the more
traditional way with Labor well to the left of the Liberals.
5. Analytic models
We will estimate three models of candidate evaluation, one based on the proximity model, one based on the directional model, and one based on a model
that we have elsewhere called the mixed model (Rabinowitz and Macdonald,
1989). We will discuss the mixed model shortly.
As a first step in the analysis, we set the issue scales so that the middle
value is zero. This is consistent with the way we presented the party positions,
and operationally fixes the directional neutral point at the middle value of
the scale. In describing the regression equations we will use the notation Xik
and Xjk to refer to the position of voter i on issue k and party j on issue k,
respectively. This common notation across the models emphasizes that all
estimation is made on exactly the same data.
The general structure of the estimation for the proximity and directional
models is as follows:
5.1. Proximity model
Affectij = interceptj + I;mbjm demographYim + I;kbklxik - xjkl
+ errOrij
where
Affectij is the evaluation of party j by individual i,
interceptj is the intercept for party j,
bjm is the effect of demographic variable m for evaluating party j,
demographYim is the status of individual i on demographic variable m,
bk is the effect of issue k in the election,
Xik is the position of individual i on issue k,
[84]
(3)
Table I. Mean position of respondents and mean perceived positions of parties on political issues in Norway in
1993 (SD in parentheses)
Issue
Left-right
-.23
Environment
0.92)
-.56
(2.36)
Immigration
European Union
Unemployment
00
Ul
Respondent
1.70
(2.36)
-1.34
(3.12)
.18
(2.78)
Socialist
Labor
Liberal
Center
Christian
Conserv
Progress
-3.12
(1.26)
-2.12
(2.21)
-1.24
(1.77)
-.50
( 1.73)
-.37
( 1.60)
-1.67
(1.92)
-1.92
(2.12)
-1.02
(1.61 )
-.54
(1.50)
.65
(1.42)
-.46
3.43
(1.60)
1.89
(2.32)
.10
(1.56)
.89
(1.73)
3.72
(1.63)
2.67
(1.94)
-1.37
(2.22)
-4.10
(1.43)
0.68)
-1.08
(1.88)
-.63
(2.19)
3.09
( 1.33)
.66
( 1.77)
3.18
(2.03)
2.17
(2.30)
-1.82
(1.87)
-.73
-.32
( 1.99)
.09
(1.58)
2.35
(2.11)
3.08
(2.06)
-1.90
(1.88)
-2.70
(2.29)
-2.64
(1.77)
( 1.65)
-.90
(2.08)
w
ow
304
Xjk is the mean perceived position of party j on issue k, and
IXik - xjkl is the absolute value of (Xik - Xjk).
5.2. Directional model
Affectij = interceptj + Lmbjm demographYim
+ Lkbk(xik . Xjk) + errOrij
(4)
where
all terms are defined as above.
Notice several features of the estimation. The analysis is pooled over all
the parties, so the entire political system is analyzed within a common frame.
Note, too, that each party is allowed a unique intercept and unique demographic effects. Thus demographic factors and unmeasured general popularity
factors are controlled, assuring the model is reasonably specified. A party
intercept nullifies the need to add an explicit penalty term, but assumes implicitly that the penalty is a constant across respondents. Finally note that in
the proximity model distance is assessed using a city-block metric.
In each model we include 12 demographic factors, each as a dummy variable. These are subjective class, union membership, education level, income,
sector of employment, farm-related occupation, religiosity, gender, urbanrural, region, language preference, and alcohol use. 6 The dependent variable
in each regression is the generalized affect the respondent feels toward the
party. This is measured using a 100-point sympathy thermometer. The full
wording of the sympathy question appears in the Appendix.
6. Results
The issue coefficients and summary statistics from the regression analyses are
reported in Table 2. Intercepts and demographic effects were estimated but are
omitted in order to make the table more readable. Because each regression is
based on an identical set of cases and explains the same dependent variable,
the adjusted R-square values provide an appropriate summary of the relative
efficacy of the models in explaining party evaluation. The demographic analysis, shown at the top of the table, includes only the party intercepts and the
demographic variables. It is presented to give a sense of how well non-issue
factors explain evaluation in Norway in 1993.
Of greatest interest is the report of the proximity and directional analyses. In both models left-right has the strongest impact, but after that the two
models diverge slightly with the EU issue more important than immigration
in the proximity specification, but immigration more important in the directional specification. These three issues dominate in both sets of estimates.
[86]
305
Table 2. Comparison of models explaining party evaluation: Pooled
regression analysis
Demographic model
Adjusted R-square
Model standard error
.243
21.502
Proximity model
Adjusted R-square
.370
Model standard error
19.617
Issue
Coefficient
Std Error
t-ratio
Prob
Distance
-4.384
.126
-34.710
.000
Environment
.004
.115
.042
Immigration
-1.130
.106
-10.613
.966
.000
European Union
-1.969
.083
-23.620
.000
Unemployment
-.211
.100
-2.113
.034
Left-right
Directional model
Adjusted R-square
Model standard error
0405
19.074
Issue
Coefficient
Std Error
t-ratio
Prob
Scalar product
Left-right
Environment
1.593
.162
Immigration
.707
European Union
Unemployment
.622
.147
N of cases
.044
.054
.046
.022
.035
35.512
2.959
15.305
.000
.003
.000
27.387
4.170
.000
.000
12,866
As for the other two issues, environment is estimated to have absolutely no
consequence in the proximity specification. However, environment is of clear
significance in the directional specification, with a slightly larger effect than
unemployment. For each issue, the ratio of coefficient to standard error is
higher in the directional than the proximity analysis. This is consistent with
the overall better fit of the directional model, which improves significantly on
the proximity model.
[87 ]
306
To shed more light on the comparative performance of the models, it is
useful to consider a model which allows a natural nesting of the theories.
7. Mixed model analysis
The mixed model is based on the idea that squared Euclidean distance is readily decomposed into two components, one being the scalar product and the
other the length of the party and individual voter vectors. 7 These components
tend to be only weakly correlated, providing a particularly clean test. Using
the notation from the regression equations,
-bk(Xik - Xjk)2 = [2bk(Xik . Xjk)] - [bk(Xik)2
+ bk(Xjk)2]
(5)
where the left-hand term is squared Euclidean distance and the right-hand
terms are respectively, twice the scalar product and the sum of the two vector
lengths. The model is operationalized as follows:
7.1. Mixed model
Affectij
interceptj + bmbjm demographYim
+ bkbsPk(xik . Xjk) + bkblenk[(xrk + x;k)/2] + errOrij
(6)
where
all terms other than bSPk and blenk are defined earlier,
bSPk is the effect of the scalar product term associated with issue k,
blenk is the effect of the length term associated with issue k.
Notice that we preserve the correct 2 to 1 ratio of scalar product to length
by halving the lengths. If the analysis conforms to a squared Euclidean metric,
then the ratio of bSPk to b1enk will be -1. As the ratio gets higher in absolute
value, the results are increasingly directional. A positive length coefficient
would entirely violate the proximity model and a negative scalar product term
would violate both models.
In addition to its use as a statistical device for comparing the theories,
Rabinowitz and Macdonald (1989) presented the mixed model as a behavioral
model which, they showed, has some of the same implications as directional
theory without the region of acceptability concept. Both Iversen (1994) and
Merrill (1995) have argued for the mixed model as a generic description
of how voters use issues to evaluate parties. 8 In addition, Grofman (1985)
has constructed a model in which voters discount party position based on
the likelihood of the party's enacting specific policies, which also implies
[88]
307
Table 3. Mixed model explaining party evaluation: Pooled regression
analysis
Mixed model
Adjusted R-square
.405
Model standard error
19.072
Issue
Coefficient
Std Error
t-ratio
Prob
Scalar product
1.593
.044
35.525
.000
Environment
.154
.055
2.788
.005
Immigration
.711
.046
15.362
.000
European Union
.622
.022
27.411
.000
Unemployment
.147
.035
4.170
.000
.196
Left-right
Length
-.094
.072
-1.292
Environment
.024
.051
.477
.633
Immigration
-.084
.046
-1.813
.069
European Union
-.033
.043
-.772
.440
.029
.046
.628
.530
Left-right
Unemployment
N of cases
12,866
a mixed model. Hence, if it offers more than the directional or proximity
model in terms of understanding voter behavior, the mixed model could be
theoretically consequential.
The mixed model analysis for the parties is presented in Table 3. Quite
strikingly the mixed model explains virtually no additional variance over and
above the directional model. For the five issues, all of the scalar product
coefficients are significant, and virtually mirror those of the pure directional
analysis. None of the length components has a significant effect, a truly remarkable result given the large number of cases in the pooled regression. With
no significant length coefficients, it is not even meaningful to compute the
ratios. There is no evidence for either a proximity or a mixed calculus for Norwegian voters in 1993. Directional theory clearly provides a better accounting
of issue effects than either of the alternative theories. This corresponds well
with the conclusion we reported based on the 1989 election.
[89]
308
8. Unrestricted analysis
Critical to any rational choice model is the idea that voters use consistent criteria in relating their own issue positions to party preference. We imposed that
constraint by the way we operationalized the regression models. Yet in reality
nothing forces voters to use a consistent calculus when evaluating parties. Nor
is there any guarantee that the models under consideration are adequate for
capturing the process voters use. Hence, it is useful and prudent to approach
the issue-evaluation linkage in as unconstrained a fashion as possible. 9
To do this, we will estimate separately for each party and each issue two
parameters, one representing a linear effect and the other a squared effect of
the issue. The following model is evaluated for each party:
Affectij = interceptj + ~mbj
+ ~kbljXi
demographYim
+ Lkb2jkXfk + errOrij
(7)
where
b1jk is the effect of issue k for evaluating party j,
b2jk is the effect of issue k squared for evaluating party j, and
all other terms are defined earlier.
The unrestricted analysis will perfectly match any pattern that can be fit
by a parabolic shape (including straight lines), and any single-peaked function should be matched reasonably well. No theory of issue effects that we
are aware of implies mUltiple peaks nor is there any empirical evidence for
systematic multimodal evaluation patterns. Hence the method should be sufficiently general to approximate most evaluation patterns, and sufficiently
parsimonious to provide good insight into the impact of issues.
Operationally we will start with each issue centered at the 0 point. This
duplicates the centering we did in the prior analyses, but here it has a different
purpose - to facilitate the interpretation of the results and to avoid potential
collinearity problems. When the variables are centered, the coefficient for the
linear term shows the basic direction of the relationship. A positive value
means the party receives a higher evaluation from those on the right; a negative value implies those on the left evaluate the party more highly. Centering
reduces collinearity because values in the middle of the simple linear scale
form one end of the squared issue scale while values from the two extremes of
the linear scale form the other end of the squared scale. Thus the methodology
allows for approximating any single-peaked pattern and assures there is little
correlation between the two variables representing respondent issue position.
The coefficients for each issue will give a sense of what the curve looks
like, and allow us to relate it to the theories. Proximity theory predicts that the
peak evaluation for a party should occur among respondents positioned at the
[90]
309
same location as the party, with support declining on either side. This implies
a significant negative coefficient for the squared issue variable to insure the
curve is concave with a definable maximum. lo Directional theory implies that
in general the estimated coefficient for the variable in squared form should be
small. A positive coefficient for the squared term is usually not a problem for
directional theory - it simply adjusts the shape of the monotonic curve.
Now let us use this approach to consider the interplay between issues and
evaluation in Norway.
9. Results of the unrestricted analysis
An unrestricted analysis was run for each of the parties using the five issues
and the demographic controls. Table 4 shows the results. Coefficients for both
the linear issue scale and the squared issue scale are displayed in the table,
along with the mean party positions. When the coefficient for the squared
term is negative and the estimated peak of the curve is within the -4.5 to
+4.5 range of the issue scale, the peak position is also shown in the table.
The demographic effects are not shown to save space.
A good starting point for exploring the issue impacts is the left-right ideology of the parties. To facilitate the interpretation of the various coefficients, a
curve reflecting the impact of left-right on evaluation is drawn for each party
in Figure 3. The intercepts for the curves reflect the estimated evaluation of
the party by a person at the neutral center on all five issues. The intercepts
give a flavor of the general popUlarity of the parties. II
The three parties that have the most dramatic left-right effects are the Conservatives, the Socialists, and the Progressives. Directional theory predicts
that slope should be a monotonic function of party location, and these are
the three parties with the most extreme locations on the left-right scale. After
these three, the next steepest slope is for the Labor Party. Recall that Labor
was perceived to be nearer the center than the Liberals in 1993, so the relative
slopes of these two parties run against the prediction of directional theory. It
could be that the emotional attraction of Labor to the left remains high even
when the perceived position switches. In any event, the relatively steep slope
for Labor compared to the Liberals is the only aspect of the left-right results
that does not conform well to the expectations of directional theory.
The evaluation lines show relatively little curvature. The only party with
a peak on the scale is the Center Party, but the impact of left-right for this
party is modest, as reflected in the barely significant coefficient for the linear
term and the insignificant coefficient for the squared term. The most curvature
occurs for the Conservative and Progressive parties, and for both of those
[91 ]
310
Table 4. Issue effects from an unrestricted analysis of party evaluation in Norway in 1993
Issue
Socialist Labor
Liberal
Center
Christian Conserv Progress
Left-right
Linear
Squared
Peak
Party
-5.42**
.04
none
-3.12
-3.44** -1.19**
-.15
-.11
-.82*
1.41 **
-.23
-.14
off scale off scale -1.79
-1.24
-1.67
off scale
-.54
.65
6.()()**
5.21**
.28*
.43**
none
none
3.09
3.43
Environment
Linear
Squared
Peak
Party
-.62*
.02
none
-2.12
-.73**
-.28
-.22
-.02
-.19
.05
.81**
.10
.04
.01
-.06
-.07
none
-.50
none
none
none
-.14
-1.37
.66
1.89
.95**
2.71**
-1.92
-.90
-.46
Immigration
Linear
-.72*
1.14**
-.92**
.42
Squared
-.12
-.20
-.26**
-.15
Peak
Party
.51
-.35**
-.20*
.18
none
3.72
-2.91
2.92
-1.80
1.41
.73
2.31
-1.90
-.37
-1.02
.10
-1.08
.89
-1.25**
1.74**
-.57** -3.58**
-.71**
1.29**
-.12
-.11
-.04
-.05
European Union
Linear
Squared
Peak
Party
-.00
off scale off scale -2.69
-2.70
2.67
-1.37
.12
none
-4.10
.32
-.15
off scale off scale
-.63
3.18
1.03
2.17
-.14
Unemployment
Linear
Squared
-.96**
-.09
.17
-.73**
.09
.58**
.00
.09
-.07
.07
.04
.08
none
none
none
none
none
-.55*
Peak
off scale
off scale
Party
-2.64
-1.82
-.73
-.32
.09
2.35
3.08
Constant
43.925
63.029
49.236
39.064
43.056
56.794
30.718
Adj R-square
.424
.240
.139
.420
.185
.468
.339
Model std err
18.577
18.052
17.582
19.078
18.780
16.822
21.031
Note. Analyses included the full set of demographic controls. N of cases in each analysis
is 1800.
**Significant at the .001 level; *Significant at the .01 level.
[92]
311
10~-c
80
c
.2
~
60
iii
:l
- . --- . -.
-"
-
-.
-_a~
.-:~
W
40
.
--- . --
enl
oc
20
o+-__________-.__________-,.-__________.-__________
-4.50
-2.25
.00
2.25
~
4.50
Left-Right Position
Figure 3. Party evaluation by left-right position.
parties the curve picks up an accelerating trend on the right side of the scale,
reflecting their rapidly increasing popularity among those on the far right.
Of some interest is the support curve for the Christian People's Party modestly sloped to the right with a peak off the scale. Two things make the
curve of interest. The Christian People's Party is located within one unit of
the center of the scale, just slightly right of center. And it is the party with
the third sharpest image - the Socialists and the Conservatives were more
consistently placed, but it was solidly third. Yet, support for the party shows
nothing that resembles a clear peak in the middle of the scale as predicted by
proximity theory. This type of flat, slightly rightward leaning slope is a direct
prediction of directional theory, and is consistent with the view that matching
issue positions is not the key link in the evaluation process. At least, not in
Norway in 1993 with regard to left-right. Rather, being weakly to one side
seems to draw weak support from those on that side.
One other feature of the support curves merits attention. The general pattern of party support fits closely the theoretical pattern shown for the directional model, if we assume that the Progressives were penalized for their
extreme positions. The Progressives are by far the furthest from the center
of any party in Norway across the full set of issues, so that assumption seems
[93]
312
quite credible. There is, however, an exception. While support for most of the
parties crisscrosses around roughly the same value, Labor generally sits above
the other parties. Unlike the penalty for the Progressives, there is nothing
in directional theory that predicts the generally high evaluations that Labor
receives. But let us consider the remaining issues before we return to confront
the general pattern of results.
The most interesting issue in 1993 was the European Union question. The
support curves for EU are shown in Figure 4 while the coefficients appear in
Table 4. For two parties support peaks on the issue scale - for the Liberals
and the Progressives. In neither case is the squared coefficient significant, and
in the case of the Progressives the linear coefficient is not significant either.
As we might have anticipated, neither party's evaluation is based much on its
EU position. The same can be said of the Christian People's Party for which
the curve has a very modest slope. Far and away the most potent effect is
for the Center Party. The EU issue is more than twice as consequential for
the Center Party as it is for Labor, where the issue has its second greatest
impact. Unsurprisingly, the Center Party took the most extreme stand on the
issue; and its strong opposition to EU membership was clearly established
in public perceptions. Tn this regard it is interesting to contrast the relatively
weak effect of the EU for the Socialists compared to the Center Party. While
the Socialists were strongly anti-Eu, they did not come close to the Center
Party in either the extremeness of their position or the clarity with which they
projected their views.
The Labor and Conservative parties anchored the pro-EU side of the scale.
While the Conservatives were seen as somewhat more pro-EU than Labor,
the issue had a greater impact on the evaluations of the Labor Party. Perhaps
this should not be surprising. In the year prior to the election the Labor government had agreed to participate in the European Economic Area, and was
clearly going to actively support joining the EU in the upcoming 1994 referendum. As the governing party, Labor's EU position had particular salience.
In addition, the Conservatives pursued an intentionally lOW-key strategy. They
recognized that to win the referendum, the pro-EU forces would need to
obtain support on the social democratic left. To do this, it was important
to downplay Conservative rhetoric as much as possible.1 2 Overall, the EU
issue is similar to the left-right issue in showing evaluation patterns that are
direction-like, even if they are not perfectly directional. The patterns tend to
be either uniformly increasing or decreasing through the range of the scale,
and the extremity of the party stand strongly influences the importance of the
issue in judging the party.
The only issue on which the majority of the parties appear to be judged on
a more proximity-like basis is the immigration issue. Indeed, six of the seven
[94 ]
313
10~-'
80
__- - - - i
C60~
~
=.---0--
~>
------ ------
_._.-.-.-.';:::.._ ....::-_
-----------
---
ab
ens
UJ
40
_---------------------------------------------------Pro9
20
0+------------.------------.-----------.------------4
-4.50
-2.25
.00
2.25
4.50
EU Position
Figure 4. Party evaluation by EU position.
parties are estimated to have a peak evaluation on the immigration scale. The
Progressive Party is the only exception. The immigration issue is a complex
one for parties in Norway. Public sentiment clearly runs in favor of making
it more difficult to immigrate into Norway. Yet showing out and out hostility
to immigrants risks putting the party in a bad light. The general response has
been for the Progressives to use the issue to generate support and for the rest
of the parties to hedge. This is reflected for the most part in the support curves,
which are shown in Figure 5. Noticeably, even when support peaks on the
scale, there is little to suggest very favorable evaluations from respondents
located at the same position as the party. The sharpest curvature is for the
Christian People's Party, but even there the predicted range in evaluation is
modest, and the curve peaks right rather than left of the center.
Once again there is a surprise in the figure. The Labor Party. which is
perceived to be slightly on the pro-immigrant side of the issue, has the second
strongest effect, and the effect is to produce generally rising support from
those who are anti-immigrant. This runs contrary to theoretical expectations
given that Labor is perceived slightly to the left of center. Neither directional
nor proximity theory, nor indeed any theory with which we are familiar, predicts rising support for a party from those who are opposed to its position. As
[95 ]
314
100r--------------------------------------------------,
80
~_-tab
c:
.2
60~
1ii
::>
(ij
>
w
--20
O+-r,.~
-4.50
-2.25
.00
2.25
4.50
Immigration Position
Figure 5. Party evaluation by immigration position.
with most surprises, there are certainly post-hoc stories to tell. Perhaps the
most compelling is that the actual policy of the Labor government has been
to toughen immigration standards even as party leaders espouse generally
pro-immigrant sympathies.
In any event, for an issue which ostensibly shows lots of curvilinearity, the
impact of immigration for the parties with the curvilinearity is quite weak,
and not sharply peaked. The Progressive and Labor parties are the two for
which the issue has the greatest impact on evaluation. For the Progressives
the results follow directional expectations quite nicely; for Labor they require
post-hoc explanation.
The effects for environment and unemployment are weaker than for the
other three issues. We show the support curves in Figures 6 and 7, but forego
a full discussion. Perhaps of some interest is the fact that Labor's curve for
the environment, as with immigration, slopes in the "wrong" direction. This
anomaly is also consistent with Labor's policy making. The Labor government has been more inclined to trade off environmental protection against
living standards than their pro-environment rhetoric would suggest.
Where does this leave us? In general, the unrestricted analysis is consonant with directional theory. For the most part, issue effects tend to be
[96]
315
10~-,
80
L_-----i
Bb
60
F:-,_~"';7·.?
~oc
40
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Prog
20
o+-__________. -__________~-_.
-4.50
-2.25
.00
2.25
4.50
Environment Position
Figure 6. Party evaluation by environment position.
monotonically increasing or decreasing, or else weak; and when a party draws
differential evaluations based on an issue, it is usually associated with a strong
stand. While this is impressionistic based on the figures we have examined,
the observation has some analytic support as well. We replicated the pooled
analysis using the unrestricted methodology.13 The analysis provides a summary measure of fit which is interesting to contrast with those of the earlier
pooled analyses. The unrestricted pooled analysis has an adjusted R-square
of .429 - greater than the .405 estimated for both the pure directional model
and the mixed model, but only a modest improvement given the addition
of 60 parameters to obtain unique issue estimates for each party. In sum,
after running the unrestricted analysis, a reasonable conclusion is that the
directional model fits the data well, if not perfectly.
The most intriguing finding from the unrestricted analysis is the evaluation
pattern for the Labor Party. There are two features of the result for Labor that
are noteworthy. First, the party has a higher base evaluation than the other
parties. This is not predicted by either of the issue theories, and is almost
surely not due to its issue strategy. Issues simply do not explain why Labor is
as generally popular as it is.
[97 ]
316
10~-,
80
60
r-----------------Ji8b
...
;;;
.;;.
........
..
.
....
.:.
=~enl
40
r>oc
- - - - - - - - - - - - _____________________________________ - - -frog
20
0+-~_r1
-4.50
-2.25
.00
2.25
4.50
Unemployment Position
Figure 7. Party evaluation by unemployment position.
The second feature is more suggestive_ It appears that Labor - at least with
regard to some issues - was judged more on what it did in government than
on how it was perceived at the time of the election. This finding - really this
conjecture, if we are appropriately cautious in our interpretation - dovetails
nicely with an on-line processing model. The thrust of the on-line model is
that voters maintain a running evaluation counter that is updated as new information appears (Hastie and Park, 1986; Lodge, McGraw, and Stroh, 1989;
Lodge and Steenbergen with Brau, 1995). The new information need not be
remembered; what is important is its impact on the running counter. For a
party actually making policy it does seem reasonable that people's rolling
evaluation would be influenced by what the party does in office. This need
not be reflected in their long-term memory but would show up in a specific
analysis of issue effects such as we have done. While speculative, this would
account for the two anomalous findings we observed for Labor as well as its
relatively steep EU curve.
[98]
317
10. Labor's popularity
For political scientists to note that issue positions do not entirely account
for a party's popularity is hardly novel. Issues have always been seen by
empirically-oriented researchers as just one of several factors that determine
a person's feelings toward a party. The standard triumvirate of factors that
came out of the early Michigan studies were issues, candidates, and party
identification (Campbell, Converse, Miller, and Stokes, 1960). To those three
factors, one must surely add a retrospective consideration of how effectively
a party in power has managed government (see, for example, Stokes, 1966;
Fiorina, 1981; Lewis-Beck, 1991). Hence, a base assessment of any party
should hinge on the quality of the candidate or candidates the party is presenting, long-term attitudes toward the party, and consideration of the party's
immediate past performance, all in addition to whatever influence its issue
stands might have.
The 1993 election took place in a year with low inflation and general economic growth, despite rising unemployment. If not wildly optimistic about
the economic future, Norwegians were becoming more upbeat. With its vast
supply of energy resources including exportable oil and natural gas, the country seemed on an unusually strong economic footing compared to its Scandinavian compatriots as well as its other European neighbors. The future was
likely to be better than the immediate past. Labor had presided over government and was generally seen to have managed things well. 14 Moreover, the
Labor Prime Minister, Gro Harlem Brundtland, was extremely popular. Her
mean evaluation exceeded the party's by approximately six and a half rating
points, an unusually large gap and a factor that certainly helped her party.15
11. Conclusion
Our analysis of the Norwegian 1993 election clearly substantiates the greater
explanatory power of directional theory in accounting for the role of issues
in elections. The surge of the Center Party in the election was caused by its
avid opposition to Norway's joining the European Union. The Center Party
was the party of choice for those who wanted to signal their disapproval of
EU membership for Norway. What the rising strength of the Center Party
most clearly did not signal was a surge in support for moderation and centrist
policies. Based on the pooled analyses or the set of unrestricted parabolic
regressions, there is simply no evidence that centrism produces support. In
all instances, the issue politics has a distinctly directional cast.
The analysis also reveals an interesting anomaly. In the two instances
in which Labor rhetoric did not match its governing behavior, voters as-
[99]
318
cribed to Labor a position based on the rhetoric but appear to have judged
it based on the reality. In this regard, the results are consistent with a combination of directionally-based evaluation and on-line cognitive processing.
As Lodge, Steenbergen with Brau (1995) argue, on-line evaluation actually
provides mass politics a higher degree of rationality than is commonly assumed. People do not simply buy a campaign message; they incorporate a
stream of information in their political judgments that is less manipulable
and more policy-wise than survey instruments geared to the electoral cycle
are able to uncover. By the time of the election most voters have forgotten the
information on which they based their judgments.
More generally, the real world is politically consequential. When a party
comes to power, it experiences pragmatic demands quite different from those
of a campaign. Frequently parties that have been dramatically opposed on
the campaign trail look more alike if they exchange positions in control of
government. The role of expertise and the requirement that people impose on
parties to perform well, often force real governments to steer a fairly narrow
course. We introduce this idea because there is a mythology about elections
which merits discussion. The myth is that electoral politics encourages party
systems to converge, while the leadership of the various parties is eager for
the parties to diverge. The truth is likely more complex.
To the extent that directional theory provides better insight into electoral
dynamics than proximity theory - and our work in the U.S., Great Britain,
the Netherlands, and Norway suggests that it does - then electoral politics in
multiparty systems encourages divergence. Basic to directional theory is the
view that politics tends to be conflictual, with party leaders staking out fairly
strong positions. Staking out sides and looking for "wedge issues" is natural
to competitive politics. Actually running a country is a different matter. The
pressures toward convergence often arise out of objective situations that provide little latitude for leaders. The fact that ruling parties will be judged at
least in part on how they perform encourages parties to follow expert advice
fairly closely. In this regard, the conventional wisdom about the interplay of
elections and governance might well be entirely backwards. Electoral politics
encourages cleavage and conflict; governing itself might be the source of
moderation.
Notes
1. While the proximity model has extended its scope to include concern for voter cognition
and spatial stability, the basic message of the model is unchanged: voters choose based
on a direct match between their desired policies and the policies that parties are likely to
produce when in charge of government.
[ 100]
319
2. For a discussion of coalition formation in European systems, see Laver and Schofield
(1990).
3. The discussion of the theories draws extensively from Listhaug, Macdonald, and Rabinowitz (1994).
4. This departs from the tradition in spatial theory for salience to be individual specific.
From an empirical standpoint, personal salience across a broad set of issues has not been
effective in predicting candidate or party utility (e.g., Niemi and Bartels, 1985), while
there is clear evidence that issues generally do take on differential importance. Further,
personal salience cannot be estimated without overparameterizing the model. Hence, we
specify the salience component of the model in terms that are operationally meaningful.
5. The center party is located at 0; the moderate left and moderate right parties are located at
-2 and +2, respectively; the far right party is located at +4. The curves for both theories
are drawn to reflect the idea of monotonicity.
6. Detailed information about the operationalization of the variables is available from the
authors on request.
7. Howard Rosenthal first suggested this nested testing strategy.
8. Iversen (I 994) interprets the mixed model as a policy leadership model. Merrill and Grofman (1997) present another variant of the mixed model which makes voter intensity a
variable component.
9. The most unconstrained analysis would allow any relationship between respondent issue
position and evaluation. Using a conventional regression methodology, this would involve
"dummying up" each issue so that each category represented a separate variable and then
observing the pattern of coefficients. While this approach is common for demographic
variables, the disadvantage of the approach with regard to issues is that it entails the
estimation of quite a large number of parameters. The five issues we examine in this
analysis would generate 45 issue coefficients, along with the 12 controls and an intercept,
for a total for 58 parameters per party. This could be challenging to interpret, and would
create the potential for odd results that were simply statistical artifacts. Clearly a simpler
approach is desirable.
10. Peak evaluationjk = bljkl - 2b2jk for the case (b2jk < 0).
II. The intercept was calculated in a separate set of regressions which included all the issues
in both linear and squared form but excluded the demographic factors. We used this approach to estimate an intercept that was demographically neutral rather than one which
reflected a certain demographic prototype.
12. The Conservative Party had used the same tactic in 1972 (Aardal and Valen, 1995: 131).
13. Of necessity the estimated coefficients are identical to those in the separate party equations.
14. Clearly part of Labor's appeal was focussed on BrundtIand (see note 14 below), but there
was also a sense that Labor was the party most trusted to manage government. A little
background is helpful here. The Labor Party had lost support in the local elections of
1991 compared to the national election in 1989. The two winners were the Center Party
and the Socialists, with the Center substantially increasing its vote share. This was widely
interpreted as an effect of the rise of the EU issue (Aardal and Val en, 1995: 15). In the
opinion polls after the local elections Labor continued to do badly, and by early 1993 in
some polls the Conservative Party received a higher level of support than Labor. Then
in June, Mr. Thorbj0rn Jagland, the newly elected party chairman of Labor, issued a
statement saying that if Labor did not receive more votes than the Conservatives, the party
would resign its position in government. This immediately began to consolidate support
[ 101 ]
320
for Labor, as many who were not particularly enamored with Labor policy saw it as the
only viable governing party (Aardal and Valen, 1995: 16--18).
15. The rating of Brundtland at the election was a record for any leader. At 71.1 she was
far more popular than Lahnstein of the Center Party in second place with 59.4. Using the
1989-93 panel, we were able to estimate the effect of leader evaluation on party evaluation
and vice-versa. Our results suggest about a 0.3 change in sympathy rating for the party
for each point in the sympathy rating of the leader. That would mean that Brundtland
contributed somewhere between 2 and 3 points to Labor's overall evaluation. We should
note that leaders were typically evaluated somewhat better than their parties in 1993. The
differences in the rating for the leader compared to the party were as follows: Socialist,
+ 1.44; Labor, +6.59; Liberal, -3.45; Center, +6.46; Christian, +2.38; Conservative, -1.93;
Progressive, +5.07.
References
Aardal, B. and Valen, H. (1995). Konflikt og opinion. Oslo: NKS-forlaget.
Campbell, A., Converse, P. E., Miller, W. E. and Stokes, D. E. (1960). The American voter.
New York: Wiley.
Cox, G.W. (1990). Centripetal and centrifugal incentives in electoral systems. American
Journal of Political Science 34: 903-935.
Davis, O. A., Hinich, M. 1. and Ordeshook, P. C. (1970). An expository development of a
mathematical model of the electoral process. American Political Science Review 64: 426448.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper & Row.
Enelow, J. M. and Hinich, M. J. (1984). The spatial theory of voting: An introduction. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Fiorina, M. (1981). Retrospective voting in American national elections. New Haven and
London: Yale University Press.
Grofman, B. (1985). The neglected role of the status quo in models of issue voting. Journal of
Politics 47: 230-237.
Hastie, R. and Park, B. (1986). The relationship between memory and judgment depends on
whether the task is memory-based or on-line. Psychological Review 93: 258-268.
Hinich, M. J. and Munger, M. C. (1994). Ideology and the theory of political choice. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Iversen, T. (1994). Political leadership and representation in West European democracies: A
test of three models of voting. American Journal of Political Science 38: 45-74.
Laver, M. and Schofield, G. (1990). Multiparty government: The politics of coalition in
Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lewis-Beck, M. S. (1991). Economics and politics: The calculus of support. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Listhaug, 0., Macdonald, S. E. and Rabinowitz, G. (1994). Ideology and party support in
comparative perspective. European Journal of Political Research 25: 111-149.
Lodge, M., McGraw, K. and Stroh, P. (1989). An impression-driven model of candidate
evaluation. American Political Science Review 83: 399--419.
Lodge, M. and Steenbergen, M. R. with Brau, S. (1995). The responsive voter: Campaign
information and the dynamics of candidate evaluation. American Political Science Review
89: 309-326.
[102]
321
Macdonald, S. E., Listhaug, O. and Rabinowitz, G. (1991). Issues and party support in
multiparty systems. American Political Science Review 85: 1107-1131.
Macdonald, S. E. and Rabinowitz, G. (1993). Direction and uncertainty in a model of issue
voting. Journal of Theoretical Politics 5: 61-87.
Merrill, S., III. (1995). Discriminating between the direction and proximity spatial models of
electoral competition. Electoral Studies 14: 273-287.
Merrill, S., III and Grofman, B. (1997). Directional and proximity models of voter utility
and choice: A new synthesis and an illustrative test of competing models. Journal of
Theoretical Politics 9: 25-48.
Niemi, R. G. and Bartels, L. M. (1985). New measures of issue salience: An evaluation.
Journal of Politics 47: 1212-1220.
Rabinowitz, G. and Macdonald, S. E. (1989). A directional theory of issue voting. American
Political Science Review 83: 93-121.
Stokes, D. E. (1966). Some dynamic elements of contests for the presidency. American
Political Science Review 60: 19-28.
Appendix: Wording of the issue questions and sympathy thermometers
1. Left-right (full wording). "There is so much talk about the conflict between left
and right in politics. Here is a scale that goes from I on the left - that is, those who
are placed politically furthest to the left - to lOon the right, that is, those who are
politically furthest to the right. Were would you place yourself on this scale? (5 and
6 are marked by neither/nor.) Where would you place the various parties on such a
scale?"
2. Environmental protection. "Value 1 denotes the wish to give much more priority
to the protection of the environment, even if it leads to a considerably lower living
standard for everyone, including yourself. Value \0 denotes the position that protection of the environment should not go so far that it hurts our standard of living."
3. Immigration policy. "Value 1 on the scale expresses the position that we should
make it easier for immigrants to come to Norway, while value 10 expresses the
opinion that the number of immigrants should be restricted more strongly than at
present."
4. European Union membership (reverse coded). "Value 1 expresses the opinion that
Norway absolutely ought to be a member of EU (EF), while value 10 expresses the
opinion that Norway absolutely ought not to be a member of EU (EF)."
5. Unemployment. "Value I on the scale expresses the view that government ought to
be active in the creation of new jobs, especially in the public sector. Value 10 denotes
the position that permanent jobs are primarily to be created by private business."
6. Sympathy thermometer. "We would like to know how you like the parties. We have
a scale from 0 to 100, which we label a 'sympathy thermometer.' At the 50-degree
[103 ]
322
mark you locate parties that you neither like nor dislike. A party which you like will
be located between 50 and 100 degrees. The more you like the party, the higher the
mark you will give it. If the party is disliked, you will place it between 0 and 50
degrees, with 0 indicating the least sympathy."
[104 ]
Public Choice 97: 323-361, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
323
The dynamics of interest group evaluations of Congress *
KEITH T. POOLE l & HOWARD ROSENTHAL 2
lCarnegie-Mellon University, 5000 Forbes Avenue, Pittsburgh, PA 15213, U.S.A.;
2Department of Politics, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ 8544, U.S.A.
Abstract. We apply a dynamic spatial model to interest group ratings of the members of
Congress over the period 1959-1981. Spatial distances between an interest group and the
members of Congress are assumed to be monotonic with the ratings. Our pooled cross-sectional
time-series data set consists of 203,387 ratings by 59 interest groups. We restrict the spatial
coordinates of the interest groups and members of Congress to be polynomial functions of
time. Two significant dimensions are recovered: the first dimension, which accounts for approximately 75% of the variance, represents liberal-conservative positions on economic issues;
the second dimension, which accounts for approximately an additional 5% of the variance, represents liberal-conservative positions on social issues. Nearly all the interest groups and most
members of Congress are ideologically consistent. They are either liberal on both dimensions
or conservative on both.
1. Introduction
The spatial theory of voting (Downs, 1957; Enelow and Hinich, 1984) must, if
it is to develop into a mature science, now pursue empirical analyses with the
intensity previously devoted to theoretical developments. Political scientists
and others have for some time created spatial representations based on factor analysis, cluster analysis, and other multivariate techniques. More recent
work, however, has emphasized scaling methods that, rather than making ad
hoc use of existing techniques, were directly responsive to a spatial model of
voting. This work has largely focused on the analysis of the National Election Study surveys of American Presidential elections (Rabinowitz, 1976;
Cahoon, Hinich, and Ordeshook, 1978; Hinich, 1978; Poole and Rosenthal, 1984a; Enelow and Hinich, 1984). These analyses have been largely
cross-sectional. 1
* This work was supported by a grant from the National Science Foundation. An earlier
version of this paper was presented at the "Information and Politics Conference", Austin,
Texas, 13-15 February 1986. Minor differences in results between this paper and the earlier
version reflect the addition of the 1981 data and improvements to the algorithm used for the
two- and three-dimensional scalings.
[105 ]
324
In many respects, it is Congress, not the Presidency, that provides the
richer environment for the study of spatial models. For one, the roll call record
provides a much lengthier time series of observations. There are several hundred roll calls per year as against one observation every four years. Moreover,
the Congressional record is not prone to the well-known deficiencies of data
collection by interview. Congress seems uniquely suited to allowing us to
study spatial voting in a dynamic framework, that is, one in which we can
study changes in spatial positions in time.
The major problem that would appear to confront a spatial analysis of
Congress would be the difficulty of analyzing a situation where logrolling
and other forms of strategic voting may predominate. The difficulties should
not be exaggerated, however. On the one hand, the roll call record itself fails
to provide any massive indication of strategic voting. Krehbiel and Rivers
(1985), Romer and Rosenthal (1987), and Ladha (1994) indicate that voting
on items with a known quantitative ordering (e.g., minimum wage levels)
is in accord with sincere spatial voting. More importantly, interest group
evaluations furnish us with all important, non-strategic source of data.
Interest groups process the roll call record to provide us with yearly evaluations of the candidates. Typically, 10 or more votes are used to score each
member of Congress. Certainly, when an interest group weights a vote positively, the interest group sincerely supports the vote so weighted. It is thus
natural to take the spatial distance between the interest group and the member
of Congress as being monotonic in the quantity (100-rating)/50. (The ratings
always range from 0 to 100; division by 50 is an arbitrary normalization.)
Assuming that distances are linear in these transformed ratings, we
recover spatial coordinates by using a generalized form of the least squares
unfolding algorithm of Poole (1984, 1990). The limitations of applying least
squares unfolding to the interest group evaluations are:
(1) the assumption that distance is linear in the rating
(2) the lower bound of 0 to the ratings limits the maximum possible distance
(3) each interest group's evaluations being derived from a relatively small
number of roll calls implies that the distances between an interest group
and the legislators have substantial measurement error. 2
Fortunately, results from scalings based on the interest group evaluations can
be cross-checked with results from the NOMINATE stochastic utility model
of roll can voting that operates directly on each legislator's roll call voting
record. At least in one dimension, the results of interest group unfolding and
NOMINATE are highly comparable (Poole and Rosenthal, 1985a,b; 1997:
Ch. 8). In addition, we present, in Appendix A, results of bootstrap Monte
[106 ]
325
Carlo experiments that suggest that the recovery of the basic two-dimensional
spatial coordinates are quite good. These results supplement evidence reported in Poole (1990) that shows the one-dimensional algorithm to be very
precise.
Unfolding of interest group evaluations should thus lead to an accurate
summary of the spatial configuration of members of Congress. Here we analyze a data set spanning the 23-year period from 1959 through 1981. This data
set was formed by adding 1981 ratings to the 1959-1980 data set assembled
by Poole (Poole and Rosenthal, 1984b; Poole and Daniels, 1985). This addition not only allows us to perform one additional check on the general tenor
of the results contained in earlier research but, more importantly, allows us
to consider the external validity of the results in terms of a widely perceived
shift in a conservative direction represented by the Reagan presidency and by
Republican control of the Senate.
There were 1,258 representatives, 261 senators and 59 interest groups
in our data set. The interest groups consist of "ideological" organizations
such as the Americans for Democratic Action and the Liberty Lobby, unions
such as the United Auto Workers and the American Federation of Teachers,
and broad trade groups such as the Chamber of Commerce of the United
States, the National Federation of Independent Business and the National
Farmers Organization. Most notably missing, relative to those organizations
with visible Political Action Committees, are specific industry groupings dairy farmers, physicians, realtors - and corporate organizations - Mobil,
General Motors, etc. Included in the interest groups are Presidential support
scores published by Congressional Quarterly. To the extent that these scores
are valid representations of the policy position of the White House, we can
use these scores to locate the presidents in the same space as the members
of Congress. Of the 59 "interest" groups, 14 represent various Congressional
Quarterly ratings, including the well-known Conservative Coalition score.
Table 1 presents a complete listing of the interest groups.
The interest groups provided 203,387 ratings over our 23 year period. Our
scaling procedure pools all these ratings in a simultaneous cross-section timeseries analysis.
In our scaling model, the legislators are represented in terms of s Euclidean
coordinates Xikt, k = 1, ... , s, where s is the dimensionality of the space, t
indexes time, and i indexes the legislators. We impose the restriction that at
time t, Xikt is a polynomial function of time. That is:
where m is the degree of the polynomial used to approximate the temporal
behavior of the legislators and interest groupS. 3 Interest group coordinates Zikt
[107 ]
326
Table 1. Description of interest groups
Abbreviation
Number
Years rating
Group
79-81
71, 72, 74-80
59-81
60,61,63-81
78,89,81
73-77
73, 75-80
American Civil Liberties Union
of years
ACLU
3
ACU
9
ACA
23
21
ADA
AFBF
AFGE
3
5
AFSCME
7
AFT
7
ASC
13
BFW
3
2
BCTD
75-81
69-81
79-81
79,81
American Conservative Union
Americans for Constitutional Action
Americans for Democratic Action
American Farm Bureau Federation
American Federation of Government Employees
American Federation of State, County and Municipal Employees
American Federation of Teachers
American Security Council
Bread for the World
Building and Construction Trades Department
(AFL-CIO)
CFSCA
3
77-80
75-81
79
76-77, 79-80
79,81
81
73-78
77, 79-81
59-81
79-81
CFSCE
2
79-80
Committee for the Survival of a Free Congress:
Economic Issues
CFSCD
2
79-80
Committee for the Survival of a Free Congress:
Defense Issues
CFSCS
2
79-80
Committee for the Survival of a Free Congress:
Social Issues
CCAUSE
2
Common Cause
CARTER
4
CCUS
7
CCUS2
CWLA
4
CV
2
CVVF
1
SANE
6
CFNFMP
4
COPE
23
Carter Support Score (CQ)
Chamber of Commerce of the United States
CCUS 2nd Rating 1979 Senate
Child Welfare League of America
Christian Voice
Christian Voters Victory Fund
Citizens for a Sane World
Coalition for a New Foreign and Military Policy
Committee on Political Education AFL-CIO
Committee for the Survival of a Free Congress: All
Issues
CW
6
CC
23
CFA
10
IKE
2
78,81
75-80
59-81
71-79, 81
59--60
PFPIKE
2
59--60
Eisenhower Presidential Support Score: Foreign
Policy (CQ)
PDPIKE
2
59--60
Eisenhower Presidential Support Score: Domestic
Policy (CQ)
[108 ]
Congress Watch
Conservative Coalition (CQ)
Consumer Confederation of America
Eisenhower Presidential Support Score: All Issues
(CQ)
327
Table 1. Continued
Abbreviation
Number
Years rating
Group
of years
FCNL
3
4
74--76
77-80
Ford Presidential Support Score CCQ)
Friends' Committee on National Legislation
LBJ
5
64--68
PFPLBJ
5
64--68
Johnson Presidential Support Score: All
CCQ)
Johnson Presidential Support Score: Foreign Policy CCQ)
PDPLBJ
5
64--68
JFK
3
61--63
PFPJFK
3
61--63
Kennedy Presidential Support Score: Foreign Policy CCQ)
PDPJFK
3
61--63
Kennedy Presidential Support Score: Domestic Policy CCQ)
59--68
71-77,79-81
71-75,77-81
61--65,67,69,
73,75,77,81
59
Larger Federal Role Support Score: (CQ)
FORD
LFR
10
LCV
10
LWV
10
LL
II
LFS
NASC
NCSC
NEA
NFO
NFU
NFIB
NTU
NWPC
NR
NIXON
REAGAN
RIPON
4
4
12
8
17
5
77, 79-81
77-80
69-79, 81
73,75-81
61-65,69-79,81
77-81
10
71,73-81
79
61-74
69-74
81
69-78, 81
77-78
69-81
79,81
1
14
6
I
11
TWR
2
UAW
13
UMW
2
Johnson Presidential Support Score: Domestic Policy CCQ)
Kennedy Presidential Support Score: All
(CQ)
League of Conservation Voters
League of Women Voters
Liberty Lobby
Lower Federal Spending Support Score
(CQ)
National Alliance of Senior Citizens
National Council of Senior Citizens
National Education Association
National Farmers Organization
National Farmers Union
National Federation of Independent Business
National Taxpayers Union
National Women's Political Caucus
New Republic
Nixon Support Score CCQ)
Reagan Support Score CCQ)
Ripon Society
Taxation with Representation
United Auto Workers
United Mine Workers
[ 109]
328
are similarly restricted. We experimented with s = 1,2,3 and m = 0, 1,2,3.
In a nutshell, we are interested in movements through time that can be
approximated by low order polynomials. 4
Imposing a low order polynomial structure represents an important advantage over earlier procedures (Poole, 1984) where each year is estimated
separately. On average, we have only 20 interest groups present in a given
year. Consequently, taking the interest group coordinates as fixed, we would
have only 20 observations with which to estimate the legislator coordinates.
Because the data exhibit a strong pattern that allows most of the variation in
the ratings to be accounted for by a simple unidimensional model, the small N
problem was not a severe handicap in obtaining one-dimensional scalings for
each year separately. On the other hand, two- or three-dimensional scalings
are more prone to unstable results when only 20 observations can be used
to estimate each legislator'S coordinates. Consequently, Poole and Daniels
(1985) gave only limited attention to multidimensional results.
Pooling, in contrast to yearly scalings, avoids small N problems. On average, a representative was present in our data set for a little over eight years. In
eight years, a representative would have about 160 ratings, quite satisfactory,
say, in terms of estimating the representative's four parameters of a twodimensional linear trend (s = 2, m = 1) model. The more precise estimation
afforded by pooling has disclosed a readily interpretable two-dimensional
configuration. Our substantive discussion emphasizes the refinements to earlier analysis developed by the two-dimensional configuration. Nonetheless,
it is important not to lose sight of the facts that nearly three-fourths of the
variation in the ratings is accounted for by a one-dimensional configuration
and that only about one-fifth of the residual variation is eliminated by adding
a second dimension.
Our analysis further discloses that coordinate positions in these low dimensional configurations are highly stable in temporal terms. On the whole,
there are only weak trends in the movements of individual legislators and
interest groups. This result is subject to the caveat that our analysis pertains only to relative movements. Our methods cannot detect any identical
movements undertaken simultaneously by all legislators and interest groups.
For example, a uniform shift to the left along one dimension would not be
recovered. More precisely, let Xikt = Xikt + akt and let Zikt = Zikt + akt
be coordinates that incorporate a general shift parameter, akt. Then, since
Zikt - Xikt = Zikt - Xikt, distances are invariant in the unidentifiable parameter
akt. Our scaling procedure assumes all akt are zero.
Our inability to identity overall shifts makes it important to benchmark
our results. We do this in the next section by identifying those senators,
representatives, and interest groups who were present over a large number
[ 110]
329
of years and exhibited little temporal movement. If one then believes, say,
that this set of political actors has become systematically more liberal over
the 23 year time series, one can make an appropriate adjustment to the results
of our analysis.
Our pooled cross-section time-series analysis was made possible by the
advent of supercomputing. The number of possible parameters (coordinates)
is given by:5
(number of legislators + number of interest groups) x
(number of dimensions) x (order of polynomial + 1) = 1578s(m + 1).
Using a Cyber 205 supercomputer at Purdue University, we were able to
carry out our largest unfolding, that with s = m = 3, in under 10 minutes.
The major substantive findings uncovered from these results are as
follows:
1. A very good first approximation to the ratings is provided by a unidimensional model where all actors are assumed to occupy a constant
spatial position. This model, the s = 1, m = 0 model, produces an R2
of 0.740 between the actual ratings of legislators by interest groups and
the distances between legislators and interest groups computed from the
recovered coordinates.
2. Significant marginal improvement is obtained by allowing for a twodimensional model with linear trend in individual positions. The R 2
increases to 0.821. Allowing for a higher dimensional space or a higher
degree polynomial did not generate substantial increases in explanatory
power.
3. Legislators appear to exhibit greater stability in position than interest
groups (including presidential support scores!). Indeed, there is little
loss in fit (R 2 = 0.818) when the legislators are constrained to have
a constant position on the second dimension.
4. Changes captured by the linear trend tend to be small in magnitude. On
the whole, to echo Poole and Daniels (1985), there are few systematic
shifts in position. Those legislators with large trends also tend to be those
legislators with poor overall fits to the model.
5. When the two-dimensional space is rotated so that the horizontal
axis is defined by the regression line connecting the Presidential support scores, the analysis strongly suggests that one axis represents
liberal-conservative positions on economic issues and the other liberalconservative positions on social issues.
[ 111 ]
330
6. Nearly all the interest groups and most members of Congress are "ideologically consistent". They are either liberal on both dimensions or
conservative on both. In contrast to the interest groups, however, a significant number of members of Congress are economic liberals but social
conservatives. Social liberals who are economic conservatives appear
to be largely absent from Congress. (Note the political fortunes of the
Libertarian party.)
7. Liberal interest groups tend to be split into two clusters. A "public"
interest cluster, including the ADA, the League of Women Voters, and
Common Cause, appears to be, holding economic liberalism constant,
relatively liberal on social issues. An economic liberal cluster, which
includes all the labor and farm organizations, is relatively conservative
on the social dimension.
8. The Democratic presidents are closely grouped and appear to be (on
both dimensions) just to the right of the core of the Democratic party.
In contrast, Republican presidents are located well away from the core
of the Republican party. Indeed, the three presidents prior to Reagan
occupy a region of the space that represents economic conservatism
combined with social moderation. This region is largely devoid of other
actors, be they legislators or interest groups. And while Reagan is, as
expected, closer to the party core than any other Republican president,
even his support score coordinates show a surprising degree of relative
moderation.
9. The standard result that the Senate is more liberal than the House is
confirmed - until 1981 when the shift to a Republican Senate majority
reversed the relationship. The greater liberalism of the Senate in our results can largely be attributed to the result that Senate Republicans were
substantially more liberal than House Republicans. (Also see Kernell,
1973.)
10. Positions appear to have polarized along party lines over the period
spanned by the data. (Also see Poole and Rosenthal, 1984b.)
In the next section of the paper, we develop these findings in detail.
[ 112]
331
Table 2. R2 Between input and recovered distances
Degree of polynomial
Dimensionality
Constant
Linear
Quadratic
Cubic
of space
m=O
m= 1
m=2
m=3
s= 1
.740
.765
.776
.782
.832
.844
.839
s= 2
.793
.821
s=3
.802
.831
.851
2. Results
2.1. Evaluations can be represented in a low dimensional space with minor
linear trends
An overall view of the recovery is provided in Table 2. It can be seen that
the interest group evaluations are essentially unidimensional and stable. The
s = 1, m = 0 model "explains" 74.0% of the variation in the original ratings.
The biggest marginal change in explained variation is brought about by
adding a second dimension. Adding a second dimension to any of the polynomial specifications in the table adds over 5% to the explained variation. In
contrast, adding a third dimension adds only around 1%.
The second largest marginal change results from adding a linear trend.
Including the linear term adds over 2.5% to the explained variation whereas
a quadratic term adds only around 1% and a cubic term even less.
In the two-dimensional model with linear trend, interest groups have
movement along both dimensions whereas legislators appear to demonstrate
trend solely on the first, main dimension. The R 2 for the full s = 2, m = 1
model is 0.821. Eliminating 1218 legislator trend parameters (Xi2\) on the
second dimension lowers R2 only to 0.818. In contrast, dropping the second dimension trend parameters for just the 43 interest groups with a linear
term (rating three or more years), lowers R2 to 0.8138 while dropping the
legislator second dimension parameters in addition to those for the interest
groups results in negligible further loss, with an R2 of 0.8136. There is more
sensitivity to dropping a linear trend for the legislators on the first dimension.
If the legislators are constrained to constant positions on both dimensions, the
R2 falls to 0.803.
We believe that adding polynomial terms beyond linear trend only results
in fitting noise in the data. Table 3 presents supporting evidence. We split
the sample in terms of whether the interest group or legislator was present
in our dataset for 10 or more years vs. less than 10 years. For each set of
[113 ]
332
Table3. Magnitude of annual change in spatial coordinate given by estimated linear
trend parameters
Group
Interest groups
In sample 3 to 9 years
In sample 10 to 23 years
Average
SD
Average
SD
.0513
0.517
27
.0169
.0206
16
.0397
.0398
27
.0201
.0170
16
.0452
.0488
103
.0173
.0195
110
.0422
.0428
591
.0201
.0199
414
.0378
.0432
81
.0218
.0234
42
.0394
.0387
423
.0198
.0207
215
N
N
first dimension
Interest groups
second dimension
Senators
first dimension
Representatives
first dimension
Legislators
entering Congress
after 1959
Senators
first dimension
Representatives
Notes. (I) No linear terms was estimated for groups or legislators in sample for
only one or two years. (2) Table based on two dimensional model with legislators
constrained to constant position on second dimension.
interest groups, senators, and representatives, we then computed the average
and standard deviation of the absolute value of the annual change in position
implied by the estimated trend coefficients. Those present in the sample for
relatively short periods had substantially higher average annual movements
and exhibited greater variability about this average. 6
The above results might be contaminated by the fact that many individuals
in our sample for only a short period were in fact senior members of Congress
approaching the ends of their careers in 1959. Both to guard against this
possibility and to make a quick examination of possible cohort effects, we
consequently redid the computations in Table 3 using only those legislators
who began service after 1959. The work indicates that the results are robust
to this modification. We therefore conclude that much of what is picked up
by the trend estimates computed over short-time intervals is not true trend but
simply fit to a (possibly autoregressive) random walk. Put differently, from
one year to the next, a legislator'S position will appear to change as the set of
interest groups changes, as the roll calls chosen to form the ratings change,
[ 114 ]
333
and as the legislator's "true" position changes. In the short run, these nonsystematic changes can be captured as trend, but in a longer run, these effects
will cancel out. Additional evidence that our computations exaggerate the
degree of trend for individual legislators and interest groups is contained in
the Appendix and in Poole (1990).
These results strongly indicate that there is substantial long-term stability
in spatial positions. Note that, for legislators serving 10 or more years, the annual change in position averages on the order of 0.02 or less than one percent
of the length of the main dimension. Overall, linear trend makes only a minor
improvement in the R2 fit of the model. But much of the improvement in fit
is illusory, reflecting short-term changes rather than true long-term trends.
Similarly, adding dimensions will be sensitive to noise in the data. Consequently, we look skeptically at adding 2780 parameters to move from a full
s = 2, m = I model to a s = 3, m = I model when R2 increases only by
0.01. Insisting on parsimony, therefore, we restrict our remaining discussion
to coordinates estimated in a two-dimensional model with linear trend on both
dimensions for the interest groups and on the first (untranslated) dimension
only for the legislators. Discussion that does not refer to trends is based on
coordinates representing the middle of each political actor's rating period.
Our finding of low dimensionality in the interest group ratings matches
our similar findings for roll call voting in Congress (Poole and Rosenthal,
1997). These results strongly support a body of spatial theory the posits a
fundamental or basic ideological space of low dimensionality that generates
individuals' issue positions (Ordeshook, 1976; Hinich and Pollard, 1981;
Hinich and Munger, 1994). Indeed, Hinich and Munger (1994) argue that a
low dimensional space is virtually inevitable in most real world circumstances
of political conflict.
2.2. The Presidential translation
The two-dimensional results are more readily interpretable if we perform a
simple translation of the space produced by the unfolding algorithm. Noticing
that the Presidential support scores for both Democrats and Republicans prior
to Reagan form relatively tight party clusters, we defined the horizontal axis
of the translated space to be the regression line over the set of pre-Reagan
Presidential support scores. 7 The origin was chosen to represent a point on the
regression line with a zero first dimension coordinate in the original scaling.
The results of this translation can be seen in Figures 1-4. Figure 1 shows
the average coordinates for all 59 interest groups. A key to the displayed
abbreviations can be found in Table 1. For each interest group, Figure 2
shows the coordinates for its first and last years in the data set. To clarify
the plot as much as possible, we have eliminated those interest groups who
[ 115]
334
Social
Dimension
Two Dimensions, Constant Postion
1.2
Cons.
LL
0.8
0.4
N~S
BCTD NFO
REAGAN
NIXON
0
PFP KE
IKJ:DPIKE
S~IPON
-0.4
AD~
-0.8
C
SAN
Lib.
NTU
V
TWR
-1.2
-1.5
-1
Liberal
-0.5
o
Economic
Dimension
0.5
1
1.5
Conservative
Figure 1. Positions of interest groups on the economic and social dimensions. The positions
in the plot are from an estimation where interest groups and legislators are constrained to have
a fixed, constant position over the 23 years of the estimation. See Table I for a key to the
interest group abbreviations.
were present fewer than three years. Groups with negligible trend have only
one plotted point. Figures 3 and 4 display average coordinates for senators
and representatives, respectively.
To provide a basic interpretation of the translation, we return to Figure l.
The specification of the translation forces the six presidents prior to Reagan
to have an average second dimension coordinate of zero. Moreover, all the
presidents are close to the horizontal axis, with Carter and Eisenhower being
relatively liberal, Kennedy, Johnson, and Nixon relatively conservative. Although Reagan is, as expected, more conservative than the other Republican
presidents (see Figure 1), the differences are minor. If Reagan had been used
in the regression defining the translation, the remaining results in this paper
would be virtually unchanged. Other political actors with ratings above 0.3
are more Conservative on the second translated dimension than are all the
[ 116]
335
Social
Dimension
1.2
Cons.
r
Two Dimensions, Linear Endpoints
I
. - -....
II
ACU LL
0.8
as{:C aca
NAd!/
ACA
ASC
nfo
0.4
NMJ"'hCSFCA
ccusalbf
ford
nfu
NFO
aE
0
a
S~
-0.8 I
L
-1.2
-1.5
-1
ntu
r
ADA CFA
I
Lib.
FK
"lwv6~
-0.4
nixoncsfca
NIXON
tN .
FORD
ripon
1\
Iwv RIPmN
I
nr
-0.5
Liberal
o
Economic
Dimension
0.5
1
1.5
Conservative
Figure 2. Positions of interest groups on the economic and social dimensions. The positions in
the plot are from an estimation where interest group positions can change linearly in time. The
lowercase letters show the group at the beginning of its rating period. The uppercase letters
show the group at the end of its rating period. See Table 1 for an interest group's abbreviation
and rating period.
presidents (or at least their support scores) while those below -0.3 are more
liberal.
2.3. A nearly unidimensional space
Inspection of the figures immediately discloses that our two-dimensional scaling is basically a refinement of a nearly unidimensional space. The figures all
form relatively fiat ovals with the basic, unidimensional orientation running
from the lower left to the upper right. This orientation represents the axis of
the first dimension before translation. Coordinates on the untranslated first
dimension, in turn, are virtually identical to those estimated in a simple unidimensional model with no time trends (s = 1, m = 0) over our 23 year
period. Squared correlations between the two sets of results all exceed 0.98
as seen in the first row of Table 4.
[ 117]
336
Social
Dimension
Two Dimensions, Linear Time Model
1.2
Cons.
0.8
0.4
0
-0.4
-0.8
Lib.
-1.2
-1.5
-1
o
-0.5
Economic
Dimension
Liberal
1
0.5
1.5
Conservative
Figure 3. Positions of senators on the economic and social dimensions. The positions in
the plot are from an estimation where legislator positions can change linearly in time. For
each legislator, the mean position is shown. Northern Democrats are displayed as "d" tokens,
Southern Democrats as "s" tokens, and Republicans as "r" tokens.
Table 4. Squared correlations between unidimensional coordinates and
two-dimensional results
Two-dimensional
Interest groups
Senators
Representatives
0.982
0.989
0.993
0.012
0.009
0.013
0.956
0.929
0.951
0.934
0.668
0.775
scaling
Recovered
first dimension
Recovered
second dimension
Translated
first dimension
Translated
second dimension
[ 118 ]
337
Social
Dimension
Two Dimensions, Linear Time Model
1.2
5
Cons.
0.8
0.4
0
-0.4
-0.8
Lib.
-1.2
-1.5
-1
Liberal
o
-0.5
Economic
Dimension
0.5
1
1.5
Conservative
Figure 4. Positions of representatives on the economic and social dimensions. See also the
caption to Figure 3.
The dominance of the untranslated first dimension, seen graphically in
the figures, is confirmed in Table 5 where it is shown that the standard deviation of the distribution of coordinates on the first untranslated dimension is
roughly three times as great as on the second dimension.
2.4. Substantive interpretation of the axes
In the translated space seen in Figure 1, widely known features of the interest
groups readily suggest the content of the new axes. The first dimension clearly
represents the major distinction between Democratic and Republican administrations. Those favoring, grosso modo, larger government non-defense
spending and government regulation of business are on the left. These interest
groups include unions of industrial workers, public employees, teachers, the
environmentalists and the Naderites. The opposite, conservative positions are
on the right. The second dimension just as clearly distinguishes social liberals
from social conservatives. Among the economic conservatives, groups such
[ 119]
338
Table 5. Standard deviations of coordinates
Coordinate
Interest groups
Senators
Representatives
0.772
0.628
0.650
0.313
0.231
0.200
Recovered
First dimension
Second dimension
Translated
First dimension
0.724
0.585
0.592
Second dimension
0.412
0.324
0.334
Translated weighted!
First dimension
0.780
0.566
0.581
Second dimension
0.454
0.326
0.337
! Note. In the case of interest groups, "weighted" means that all Congressional Quarterly ratings were eliminated. The resulting N is 43. In the case
of legislators, each legislator is weighted by the number of years he or she
appeared in the sample.
as Christian Voice which are close to Jesse Helms on abortion, school prayer,
and other issues, can be distinguished from the more moderate Ripon Society
and National Taxpayers Union. Among economic liberals, the group with
the largest, most conservative score on the second dimension is the Building
and Construction Trades Union, not known as an avid proponent of minority
hiring. In contrast, known social liberal groups like the ADA and ACLU have
large negative coordinates on the second dimension.
Our contrast between social and economic dimensions based on an analysis of the interest groups is confirmed by the legislator coordinates. On the
economic dimension, for all 23 years and for both houses, Northern Democrats have an average position that is more liberal than that of Southern
Democrats which is more liberal than that of Republicans. (See Figure 6.) But
on the social dimension, again for all years and for both houses, the positions
of Southern Democrats and Republicans are reversed. Southern Democrats
are the most conservative of the three groups. (See Figure 7.)
This reversal suggests that the issue content of the social dimension is
largely that of desegregation, voting rights and other civil rights issues. While
the social dimension indeed includes civil rights, it also appears that it must
be more broadly defined. To see this, consider Table 6, which lists, for each
year and party group, the individuals with the most extreme positions on each
dimension. In both houses, a Southern Democrat - typically from the deep
South - is almost always the most conservative individual on the social di-
[120]
339
mension. On the other hand, the most socially liberal individual is frequently
not a Northern Democrat with a large minority constituency. For six years
in the Senate and ten in the House, the most socially liberal individual was
a Republican. Among the social liberals, we find those as identified with
opposition to the Vietnam war (McCloskey, Harrington, Drinan) or feminist
issues (Fenwick) as with civil rights advocacy. Indeed, the liberal end of the
social dimension appears to capture all the issues that have been the cause
celebre du jour of White urban liberals. In the early part of our time period,
civil rights was perhaps the central issue in the White liberal agenda, but in
the middle and later part, antiwar, environmental, and consumer issues also
occupied this agenda. The emphasis we have placed on White liberal issues
is confirmed by the finding that African-American and Hispanic members of
the House do not anchor the social dimension but frequently (Clay, Badillo,
Garcia) anchor the economic dimension. Issues such as affirmative action,
welfare, and food stamps that involve redistributional benefits to minorities no
longer appear as ones of civil rights but as issues along the primary, economic
dimension. 8
It is noteworthy that while minority group legislators tend to anchor the
liberal end of the economic dimension, among interest groups this dimension
is anchored by organized labor. From the viewpoint of many economists, this
spatial grouping would seem anomalous since many policies dear to labor,
such as minimum wage and Davis-Bacon, would appear to restrict employment in a manner detrimental to the very poor. Two explanations appear worth
considering. On the one hand, African-American and Hispanic members of
the House may not have the very poor as their critical constituency but instead
represent those minority individuals with a stake in the system by holding
industrial or civil service jobs. On the other hand, these same members might
realize that extreme redistributional policies have little chance of passing and,
therefore, coalesce with organized labor in order to obtain the best possible
deal for their constituents. The latter case suggests that coalition formation
may play a key role in the near unidimensionality in our results. Although
the interests of minorities and labor could give rise to two distinct economic
dimensions, relatively permanent coalition decisions could show only one
dimension in the data. In tum, the permanency of the coalitions will make roll
call voting appear to be "sincere" even though it results from a fundamentally
strategic process.
2.5. Liberal interest groups: Middle class vs. labor and farming
To return to the social dimension, our claim of a White liberal pole is perhaps
best documented by the separation of liberal interest groups into two distinct
clusters apparent in Figure 1. The bottom cluster is middle class, college
[121]
340
Table 6. Most extreme legislators
A. Most liberal - Economic dimension - Senate
Years
1959-66
1967-68
1969-70
1971
1972
1973-74
1975
1976
1977
1978
1979
1980
1981
All Senators
No. Democrat
So. Democrat
Republican
Morse (D-OR)
Morse (D-OR)
Yarborough (D-TX)
Javits (R-NY)
Morse (D-OR)
Morse (D-OR)
Yarborough (D-TX)
Hatfield (R-OR)
Schwieker (R-PA)
Gravel (D-AK)
Yarborough (D-TX)
Schweiker (R-PA)
Schwieker (R-PA)
Gravel (D-AK)
Fulbright (D-AR)
Schweiker (R-PA)
Gravel (D-AK)
Gravel (D-AK)
Fulbright (D-AR)
Schweiker (R-PA)
Hartke (D-IN)
Hartke (D-IN)
Huddleston (D-KY)
Schweiker (R-PA)
Durkin (D-NH)
Durkin (D-NH)
Huddleston (D-KY)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Hartke (D-IN)
Hartke (D-IN)
Huddleston (D-KY)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Durkin (D-NH)
Durkin (D-NH)
Huddleston (D-KY)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Durkin (D-NH)
Durkin (D-NH)
Allen, M. (D-AL)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Durkin (D-NH)
Durkin (D-NH)
Huddleston (D-KY)
Case C. (R-NJ)
Kennedy, E. (D-MA)
Kennedy, E. (D-MA)
Huddleston (D-KY)
Javits (R-NY)
Dodd, C. (D-CT)
Dodd, C. (D-CT)
Huddleston (D-KY)
Javits (R-NY)
Republican
Note. A Northern Democrat is always the most liberal Democrat.
B. Most liberal - Economic dimension - House
Years
All Reps.
No. Democrat
So. Democrat
1959
1960
1961-62
1963-64
1965
1966
1967
1968
1969
1970-72
1973-76
1977
1978
1979-80
1981
Green E. (D-OR)
Green, E. (D-OR)
Edmondson (D-OK)
Fino (R-NY)
Hargis (D-KS)
Hargis (D-KS)
Edmondson (D-OK)
Canfield (R-NY)
Bailey (D-WV)
Bailey (D-WV)
Edmondson (D-OK)
Halpern (R-NY)
Olsen (D-MT)
Olsen (D-MT)
Edmondson (D-OK)
Reid (R-NY)
Ford, W. (D-MI)
Ford, W. (D-MI)
Farnsley (D-OK)
Reid (R-NY)
Rees (D-CA)
Rees (D-CA)
Thomas, L. (D-TX)
Reid (R-NY)
Ford, W. (D-MI)
Ford, W. (D-MI)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Heckler, M. (R-MA)
Podell (D-NY)
Podell (D-NY)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Whalen (R-OH)
Clay (D-MO)
Clay (D-MO)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Reid (R-NY)
Collins (D-IL)
Collins (D-IL)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Reid (R-NY)
Badillo (D-NY)
Badillo (D-NY)
Young, A. (D-GA)
Whalen (R-OH)
Badillo (D-NY)
Badillo (D-NY)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Whalen (R-OH)
Garcia (D-NY)
Garcia (D-NY)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Whalen (R-OH)
Garcia (D-NY)
Garcia (D-NY)
Leland (D-TX)
Rinaldo (R-NJ)
Savage (D-IL)
Savage (D-IL)
Leland (D-TX)
Rinaldo (R-NJ)
Note. A Northern Democrat is always the most liberal Democrat.
[122 ]
341
Table 6. Continued
C. Most conservative - Economic dimension - Senate
Years
All Senators
No. Democrat
So. Democrat
Republican
1959-60
1961-64
1965
1966
1967
1968
1969-71
1972
1973-76
1977
1978
1979-80
1981
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Lausche (D-OH)
Thurmond (D-SC)
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Lausche (D-OH)
Byrd, H.F. (D-VA)
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Simpson (R-WY)
Lausche (D-OH)
Byrd, H.F. (D-VA)
Simpson (R-WY)
Simpson (R-WY)
Lausche (D-OH)
Robertson (D-VA)
Simpson (R-WY)
Tower (R-TX)
Lausche (D-OH)
Byrd, Jr. (D-VA)
Tower (R-TX)
Curtis (R-NE)
Lausche (D-OH)
Byrd, Jr. (D-VA)
Curtis (R-NE)
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Bible (D-NV)
Byrd, Jr. (D-VA)
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Bible (D-NV)
Edwards (D-LA)
Goldwater (R-AZ)
Helms (R-NC)
Proxmire (0-WI)
Allen (D-AL)
Helms (R-NC)
Helms (R-NC)
Zorinsky (D-NE)
Allen (D-AL)
Helms (R-NC)
Helms (R-NC)
Hatfield, P. (D-MT) Eastland (D-MS)
Helms (R-NC)
Zorinsky (D-NE)
Stennis (D-MS)
Helms (R-NC)
Helms (R-NC)
Mattingly (R-GA)
Zorinsky (D-NE)
Stennis (D-MS)
Mattingly (R-GA)
Note. A Southern Democrat is always the most conservative Democrat, except in 1978.
D. Most conservative - Economic dimension - House
Years
All Reps.
No. Democrat
So. Democrat
Republican
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963-64
1965-66
1967-68
1969-70
1971-72
1973
1974
1975
1976
1977-78
1979-81
Hall (D-NC)
Cannon (D-NV)
Hall (D-NC)
Mason (R-IL)
Mason (R -IL)
Cannon (D-NV)
Haley (D-FL)
Mason (R-IL)
Mason (R-IL)
Cannon (D-NV)
Williams (D-MS)
Mason (R-IL)
Mason (R-IL)
Hull (D-MO)
Williams (D-MS)
Mason (R-IL)
Hoffman (R-IL)
Hull (D-MO)
Williams (D-MS)
Hoffman (R-IL)
Walker P. (R-MS)
Jones, P. (D-MO)
Williams (D-MS)
Walker, P. (R-MS)
Gross, H. (R-IA)
Jones P. (D-MO)
Rarick (D-LA)
Gross, H. (R-IA)
Crane (R-IL)
!chord (D-MO)
Rarick (D-LA)
Crane (R-IL)
Crane (R-IL)
Byron (D-MO)
Rarick (D-LA)
Crane (R-IL)
Treen (R-LA)
Byron (D-MO)
Rarick (D-LA)
Treen (R-LA)
Treen (R-LA)
!chord (D-MO)
Rarick (D-LA)
Treen (R-LA)
Treen (R-LA)
!chord (D-MO)
McDonald (D-GA) Treen (R-LA)
Paul R. (R-TX)
!chord (D-MO)
McDonald (D-GA) Paul, R. (R-TX)
McDonald (D-GA)
Stump (D-AZ)
McDonald (D-GA)
Symms (R-ID)
Paul R. (R-TX)
Stump (D-AZ)
McDonald (D-GA)
Paul R. (R-TX)
Note. A Southern Democrat is always the most conservative Democrat.
[ 123]
342
Table 6. Continued
E. Most liberal - Social Dimension - Senate
Years
All Senators
No. Democrat
So. Democrat
Republican
1959-62
1963-64
1965-66
1967-68
1969-72
1973
1974
1976
1976
1977-81
Proxmire (D-WI)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Kefauver (D-TN)
Cooper (R-KY)
Proximire (D-WI)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Edmondson (D-NE)
Cooper (R-KY)
Cooper (R-KY)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Harris (D-OK)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Harris (D-OK)
Hatfield, M. (R-OR)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Harris (D-OK)
Saxbe (R-OH)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Chiles (D-FL)
Saxbe (R-OH)
Metzenbaum (D-OH) Metzenbaum (D-OH) Chiles (D-FL)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Bumpers (D-AR)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Proxmire (D-WI)
Bumpers (D-AR)
Case, C. (R-NJ)
Chafee (R-RI)
Metzenbaum (D-OH)
Bumpers (D-AR)
Chafee (R-RI)
Note. A Northern Democrat is always the most liberal Democrat.
F. Most liberal - Social dimension - House
Years
All Reps.
No. Democrat
So. Democrat
Republican
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963-64
1965
1966
1967-68
1969-70
1971
1972-73
1974
1975
1976-77
1978
1979
1980
1981
Boyle (D-IL)
Boyle (D-IL)
Johnson, B. (D-TX)
Canfield (R-NJ)
Canfield (R-NJ)
Kastenmeier (D-WI)
Johnson, B. (D-TX)
Canfield (R-NJ)
Kastenmeier (D-WI)
Kastenmeier (D-WI)
Wickersham (D-OK) Merrow (R-NH)
Kastenmeier (D-WI)
Kastenmeier (D-WI)
Fascell (D-FL)
Cameron (D-CA)
Cameron (D-CA)
Fascell (D-FL)
Mathias (R-MD)
Jacobs (D-IN)
Jacobs (D-IN)
Fascell (D-FL)
Mathias (R-MD)
Jacobs (D-IN)
Jacobs (D-IN)
Thomas, L. (D-TX)
Kupferman (R-NY)
McCloskey (R-CA)
Jacobs (D-IN)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
McCloskey (R-CA)
McCloskey (R-CA)
Harrington (D-MA)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
McCloskey (R-CA)
Frenzel (R-MN)
Drinan (D-MA)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Frenzel (R-MN)
Drinan (D-MA)
Drinan (D-MA)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
McCloskey (R-CA)
Drinan (D-MA)
Drinan (D-MA)
Eckhardt (D-TX)
Mosher (R-OH)
Fenwick (R-NJ)
Maguire (D-NJ)
Fisher (D-TX)
Fenwick (R-NJ)
Maguire (D-NJ)
Maguire (D-NJ)
Fisher (D-TX)
Fenwick (R-NJ)
Green (R-NY)
Maguire (D-NJ)
Fisher (D-TX)
Green (R-NY)
Green (R-NY)
Maguire (D-NJ)
Leland (D-TX)
Green (R-NY)
Maguire (D-NJ)
Maguire (D-NJ)
Leland (D-TX)
Green (R-NY)
Schneider (R-RI)
Frank, B. (D-MA)
Leland (D-TX)
Schneider (R-RI)
Note. A Northern Democrat is always the most liberal Democrat.
[124 ]
Merrow (R-NH)
343
Table 6. Continued
G. Most conservative - Social dimension - Senate
Years
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963-64
1965-71
1972-77
1978
1979-80
1981
All Senators
No. Democrat
Langer (R-ND)
So. Democrat
Republican
Frear (D-CT)
Talmadge (D-GA) Langer (R-ND)
Talmadge (D-GA) Frear (D-CT)
Talmadge (D-GA) Young (R-ND)
Talmadge (D-GA)
Talmadge (D-GA) Young (R-ND)
Bible (D-NV)
Talmadge (D-GA) Bible (D-NV)
Talmadge (D-GA) Bottum (R-SD)
Talmadge (D-GA) Bible (D-NV)
Talmadge (D-GA) Young (R-ND)
Ellender (D-LA)
Bible (D-NV)
Ellender (D-LA)
Young (R-ND)
Eastland (D-MS)
Bible (D-NV)
Eastland (D-MS)
Young (R-ND)
Long, R. (D-LA)
Hatfield, P. (D-MT) Long, R. (D-LA)
Young (R-ND)
Long, R. (D-LA)
Exon (D-NE)
Long, R. (D-LA)
Young (R-ND)
Long, R. (D-LA)
Exon (D-NE)
Long, R. (D-LA)
Grassley (R-IA)
Note. A Southern Democrat is always the most conservative Democrat.
H. Most conservative - Social dimension - House
Years
All Reps.
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963
1964
1965
1966-68
1969-70
1971-72
1973-74
1975
1976
1977-78
1979-80
1981
Hall (D-NC)
Barden (D-NC)
No. Democrat
So. Democrat
Republican
Brock, L. (D-NE)
Hall (D-NC)
Weaver (R-NE)
Brock, L. (D-NE)
Barden (D-NC)
Weaver (R-NE)
Riley (D-SC)
Cannon (D-NV)
Riley (D-SC)
Weaver (R-NE)
Blitch (D-GA)
Cannon (D-NV)
Blitch (D-GA)
McVey (R-KS)
Whitten (D-MS)
Cannon (D-NV)
Whitten (D-MS)
Foreman (R-TX)
Winstead (D-MS)
Baring (D-NV)
Winstead (D-MS)
Nygaard (R-ND)
Whitten (D-MS)
Baring (D-NV)
Whitten (D-MS)
Reifel (R-SD)
Long, S. (D-LA)
Baring (D-NV)
Long, S. (D-LA)
Reifel (R-SD)
Caffery (D-LA)
Baring (D-NV)
Caffery (D-LA)
Reifel (R-SD)
Baring (D-NY)
Baring (D-NV)
Long, S. (D-LA)
Price (R-TX)
Teague (D-TX)
Byron, G. (D-MD)
Teague (D-TX)
Price (R-TX)
Teague (D-TX)
!chord (D-MO)
Teague (D-TX)
Harsha (R-OH)
Teague (D-TX)
!chord (D-MO)
Teague (D-TX)
Quillen (R-TN)
Teague (D-TX)
Ichord (D-MO)
Teague (D-TX)
Young, O. (R-FL)
Roberts (D-TX)
!chord (D-MO)
Roberts (D-TX)
Young, O. (R-FL)
Chappel (D-FL)
Byron, B. (D-MD)
Chappel (D-FL)
Young, O. (R-FL)
Note. A Southern Democrat is always the most conservative Democrat, except in 1971 and
1972.
[ 125 ]
344
educated liberals with "public" interest orientations. It includes the ADA, the
League of Women Voters, the League of Conservation Voters, the Consumer
Federation of America, the anti-nuclear SANE, Congress Watch, the Friends
Committee on National Legislation, the Coalition for a New Foreign and Military Policy, Taxation with Representation, Common Cause, and the ACLU.
The other cluster is overwhelmingly made up of labor and farming groups.
The Democratic presidents fall in this cluster. The distinction between these
clusters did not escape Ronald Reagan the campaigner who frequently sought
to pose as the candidate of Roosevelt and Kennedy Democrats. These messages might be read as: "My opponent is really up there in the other cluster
with all those crazy Brie eaters".
In addition to the interest group clusters, three other aspects of the figures
of translated coordinates are especially worth noting.
2.5.1. Extreme positions of interest groups
First. Interest groups are generally more extreme than legislators. No senator,
for example, is as far "Southwest" as either Taxation With Representation
or SANE or as far "Northwest" as the BCTD. Similarly, no senator is as
economically conservative as the National Taxpayers Union or as socially
conservative as the Liberty Lobby. Another way to state this conclusion about
the extremity of the interest groups is to note, in Table 5, that the standard
deviations of interest group coordinates are greater than those of either house
of Congress. This result is especially striking given that the standard deviation of the interest groups is substantially reduced by the moderate positions
embodied in the Presidential support scores. As the table shows, when all
Congressional Quarterly ratings are removed, including not only the Presidential support score but also the highly conservative Conservative Coalition
score, the standard deviations for the interest groups are increased.
2.5.2. Consistent and inconsistent positions
Second. The 45 authentic (non-Congressional Quarterly scores) interest
groups are largely polarized into two opposite quadrants. Accounting for 82%
of the interest groups, these quadrants represent the "consistent" positions
of "liberal-liberal" and "conservative-conservative". In contrast, a significant
portion of the Congressional membership can be said to have had "inconsistent" positions. While none of the three groups of actors contain significant
numbers in the economic conservative-social liberal quadrant (4% of the interest groups, 2% of the senators, and 1% of the representatives), there were
many members of Congress in the opposite, economic liberal-social conservative quadrant (28% of the senators and 27% of the representatives as against
only 13% of the interest groups.) These individuals were disproportionately
Democrats, since 45% of Senate Democrats and 44% of House Democrats
[ 126]
345
were economic liberals but more "socially" conservative than the average
pre-Reagan presidential position. Within the Democrats, Southern Democrats
were overwhelmingly socially Conservative. The two quadrants above the
Presidential regression line contain 96% of both House and Senate Southern
Democrats.
American polities would be more truly two-dimensional if there was a
significant representation of the missing quadrant of economic Conservatives
and social liberals. The sparse dots in this quadrant in both Figures 3 and
4 all represent Republicans. There is, of course, very little current impetus
to the development of socially liberal Republicans. In contrast, Congress is
gradually polarizing along the lines of the interest groups?
2.5.3. Republican presidents and political compromise
While the Democratic presidents were all close to the high density areas in
Figures 3 and 4 that show the core group of liberal legislators, the social positions of postwar Republican presidents preceding Reagan were very far from
those of the core conservative group on the social dimension. Of course, this
distinction has been echoed in Ronald Reagan's ascendancy to dominance
in the Republican party. Nonetheless, Reagan's support score position in the
space is still more liberal than that of the conservative core.
One readily suspects that Reagan's relative moderation reflects the desire
of the White House to take winning positions on legislation. Winning involves
building consensus, thereby compromising one's position. The need to win
will have the greatest impact on Republican presidents who, up until Reagan,
were faced with Democratic control of Congress during the period covered
by our data. We thus suspect that the Presidential positions calculated from
the support score ratings are less extreme than positions taken in campaigning. Indeed, our earlier work using mass electorate survey data also showed
polarization of Presidential campaign positions (Poole and Rosenthal, 1984a).
The distinctions we have made between the social and economic realms
should not mask the basically unidimensional character of American politics.
As seen in the figures, there is a strong correlation between positions on the
two dimensions. Moreover, as seen in Table 4, the R2 values between position
on the economic dimension and position in the unidimensional scaling all
exceed 0.92. The R2 between the social dimension and the unidimensional
results for the interest groups is an equally high 0.934. The squared correlations for the two houses of Congress are less strong but still substantial.
The Senate has the lowest R2 between the social dimension and the unidimensional coordinate; relative to the House (see Table 5), it also has less
variance on the first recovered dimension but more variance on the second.
These results echo the finding of Poole and Rosenthal (1985b, 1997) that the
[127]
346
Senate fits a one-dimensional model less well than the House. This lesser
fit in part reflects the Senate's greater involvement with civil rights issues
during this period. Analysis in Poole and Rosenthal (1985b; 1991; 1997: 109111) also indicates that civil rights is basically a perturbation in a long-run
unidimensional pattern. Even this perturbation, however, can be reasonably
approximated within a one-dimensional structure, as the R 2 values indicate.
In other words, the basic story is left-right. The two-dimensional plot simply
refines this story.
2.6. Intertemporal change
The results presented in Figures 3 and 4 are useful for presenting a longrun or average spatial description of the national political system. But what
of change over time? Improvements in fit here are scant compared to what
was achieved by expanding the dimensionality from one to two. For onedimensional unfoldings, the improvement achieved by a cubic polynomial is
less than that available from assuming constant spatial positions in a twodimensional space. Systematic trends are thus minor.
2.7. Calibration: Actors with no trend
Given the central tendency to no trend, it is important to document those
interest groups and legislators that exhibited the least movement. It is difficult
to do this for interest groups, since we had only five interest groups (see
Table 1) that had ratings for 16 or more years. Of these, the Conservative
Coalition score exhibited the least total movement, covering a distance of
only 0.094 in 23 years. COPE was also relatively stable, moving only 0.161
in 23 years. (The entire space has a span of over 2 units.) COPE also exhibited
the least movement on the economic dimension, a total of 0.038 units while
the Conservative Coalition was the most stable of the five interest groups on
the social dimension, moving only a total of 0.020 units.
To put the interest groups in the same framework as the legislators, however, it is best to refer to the untranslated first dimension since the legislators
were constrained to move only on this dimension. Of those interest groups rating 16 or more years, only the Americans for Constitutional Action had a total
movement of less than 0.02 units. The legislators that had a total movement
of less than 0.02 were, in the Senate, Bennett (R-UT), Hart (D-MI), Hruska
(R-NE), Metcalf (O-MT), and Williams (D-NJ), and, in the House, Conyers
(D-MI), Corman (D-CA), Edwards (D-CA), Gubser (R-CA), Hechler (0WV), Howard (D-NJ), MacDonald (D-MA), and Satterfield (R-VA). These
individuals provide reasonable coverage of the political spectrum, the two
parties, and the regions of the country, with the notable exception of (see
[128]
347
below) Southern Democrats. If one believes that this set of individuals became systematically more liberal or more Conservative during the sixties and
seventies, then one would want to accordingly recalibrate our results. Our
discussion assumes these individuals were stable.
Although the linear trend explains a "significant" chunk of the variance in
the ratings, the trends are typically of very limited substantive interest. Plots
for individual years would be highly similar to Figures 3 and 4. As shown
in Table 3, the average yearly movements on the first untranslated dimension
are all similar for interest groups, representatives, and senators and are small
in relation to the overall size of the space, especially so for those present long
enough to avoid substantial upward bias in the magnitude of trend. Another
indication of limited movement is provided by Table 6 which shows substantial stability in the identity of those individuals who hold the most extreme
positions in Congress. Of particular interest is the social dimension in the
Senate. Among Northern Democrats, only two individuals, Metzenbaum and
Proxmire have held the liberal pole position in our 23-year period. On the
conservative end, for all three "parties", only four individuals have been in
the most conservative position.
2.8. Major trends in interest groups
On the whole, interest groups do move somewhat more than legislators. Three
interest groups present for 10 or more years had a total movement in excess of
0.5 units. While the Liberty Lobby offset a more conservative social position
with a more liberal one on the economic dimension, the National Taxpayers
Union lost its social liberalism while also becoming more conservative on
economic issues. Similarly, the Ripon Society, initially a middle-of-the-road
group along with Common Cause, finished by being clearly in the conservative camp. The net results of such changes was to leave the final positions of
interest groups more polarized than their initial ones.
Large movements for individual legislators are similar to those discussed
by Poole and Daniels (1985) from the results of an alternative methodology.
The reader is referred to that paper for substantive discussion of individual
cases.
2.8.1. Trend as strategic behavior
There is an important additional finding, however, concerning the characteristics of legislators who engage in relatively large movements. Having a large
trend is negatively related to the degree to which the legislator is fit by the
model. Our measure of fit is, as before, the squared correlation between the
ratings and the recovered distances. When fit is correlated with the magnitude
of average movement per year, we find (for those serving three or more years),
[129]
348
a correlation of -0.17 for the Senate and -0.30 for the House. The magnitude
of correlation increases when we restrict ourselves to those legislators for
whom we have enough years of data to have relatively reliable estimates.
For legislators serving over 9 years, the correlation is -0.37 in both houses.
Over 14 years, the figures are -0.54 in the Senate and -0.40 in the House.
What this means is that legislators with large amounts of spatial mobility
tend, to some extent, not to fit the model very well. The lack of fit to the
low-dimensional model does not mean that the movement is spurious. For
example, Richard Schweiker had the largest movement of any legislator and
John Anderson had the second largest movement in the House. Schweiker's
conversion to Reagan-style conservatism and Anderson's liberal transition
leading to a Presidential candidacy are both well known. Yet Schweiker's R2
was a quite low 0.58 as was Anderson's 0.54.
Thus, those senators who fail to fit the mold of maintaining stable reputations in terms of spatial positions also tend to fail to fit the mold of low
dimensionality. Both of these failures might be seen as indications of strategic behavior. On the other hand, the whimsical as well as the manipulative
also follow this pattern. Poorly fit by the model, William Proxmire rode his
Rosinante across a large chunk of our space. In any event, such behavior is
not sufficiently pervasive to prevent our model from capturing most of the
variation in the ratings.
The linear trend term, however, is far from capturing all the intertemporal variation in individual positions. The 82.1 % of variance explained by
the model is substantially lower than the 87% achieved by a separate twodimensional scaling for each of the first 22 years (Poole and Daniels, 1985).
While we may have omitted some important systematic effects, such as six
year senatorial cycle effects (Poole, 1981; Kalt and Zupan, 1984; Dougan
and Munger, 1989), we conjecture that most of the additional 5% picked up
in the separate scalings is very short run movements and noise. On the whole,
trends in the positions of interest organizations and individual politicians do
not appear to be of great importance to a spatial model of American politics.
The major source of change is likely to be replacement. 10
2.8.2. Replacement effects
The effect of replacement may be to lead to substantial changes in the average
positions of parties and geographical groupings within the Congress. 11 We
now proceed to a brief analysis of some of the more important changes.
In terms of the overall means of the two houses of Congress, for both
dimensions there is a picture of a stable political system as shown in Figure 5.
(We caution, however, that the all-or-none aspect of majority rule may cause
small fluctuations in the means to be associated with major changes in policy.)
[ 130]
349
0.40
~-
Social Dimension
House
Economic Dimension
-0.20
-0.40
Senate
+-----------------
-
. - .. - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - '
59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81
Figure 5. Overall average locations on the economic and social dimensions. The averages are
computed over all members serving in the relevant year.
On the economic dimension, there is very little net change in the House,
which has had a Democratic majority throughout the period of our data set.
Those fluctuations that occur are readily attributable to the electoral fortunes
of the two parties. There is a swing to the liberal side following Johnson's
landslide in 1964, a conservative rebound after the 1966 midterm elections,
a Watergate induced liberal shift, and a Reagan shift at the end. The Senate,
institutionally designed to buffer the electorate's fancy via staggered terms,
shows virtually no change until 1981. At that point, the massive Republican
gains in the 1980 elections resulted in a strong conservative surge that left the
House, for the first time in 23 years, more liberal than the Senate. As to the
social dimension, which, in any event, has less variation in coordinates than
the major, economic dimension (see Table 2), there are only very minor fluctuations, although there is a faint echo of the electoral fluctuations indicated
for the House. A very mild long-term trend to liberalism in the Senate was
completely offset by the 1980 elections.
2.9. The (once) liberal Senate
The immediate source of the historically greater liberalism of the Senate on
both dimensions is readily apparent in Figures 6 and 7. On both dimensions,
Senate Republicans have always been more liberal than their counterparts
in the House. There is very little difference in the positions of House vs.
Senate Northern Democrats on both dimensions and of Southern Democrats
[ 131 ]
350
0.80
HouseR
Sena~
0.60
_______________________
House~
0.40
Senate SD
-0.20
-0.40
-0.80
59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81
Figure 6. Overall average locations of Republicans (R), Northern Democrats (ND), and
Southern Democrats (SD) on the economic dimension.
on the social dimension. At the same time, House Southern Democrats, initially more liberal than their Senate colleagues on economic matters, have
recently been more Conservative. Thus, the only consistent and important
difference between the two Houses, in terms of the three-party split, concerns the Republicans. This situation would appear to be the result of,
grosso modo, the Republicans being gerrymandered into a relatively small
number of highly conservative districts in the House while competing in
broader constituencies for the Senate. Note, however, that the election of
a highly Conservative contingent of freshman Republican senators in 1980
greatly attenuated House-Senate differences while contributing to the strong
Conservative shift shown in Figure 5.
2.9.1. Are Southern Democrats more liberal?
The other key story told by Figures 6 and 7 concerns Southern Democrats.
Southern Democrats who entered the House since passage of the 1965 Voting
Rights Act were considerably more liberal than their predecessors (Bullock,
1981).
Southern Democrats in the Senate, in contrast, initially more Conservative than their House counterparts, did not become more conservative in the
sixties and then became much more liberal in the seventies. That the switch
to liberalism was mainly on the economic dimension, is relevant to the view
that the switch was induced by the new African-American electorate. We indicated above that minority members of Congress anchored the economic, not
[132 ]
351
0.80
SenateSD
HouseSD
0.40
0.20
0.00
HouseR
Senate R
SenateND
HouseND
-0.20
59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81
Figure 7. Overall average locations of Republicans (R), Northern Democrats (NO), and
Southern Democrats (SO) on the social dimension.
the social dimension. After the passage of the Great Society legislation, one
could argue that the Northern White liberal agenda turned to other issues and
that the new constituency left Southern Democrats free to pursue traditional
positions on these issues.
At the same time as the Southern Democrats became more liberal on
the economic dimension, a conservative trend among Senate Northern Democrats greatly attenuated the gap between the mean positions of the two
regional groupings. This result confirms our contention (Poole and Rosenthal,
1984b) that Senate elections have increasingly become polarized, competitive
contests nationwide between two increasingly homogeneous parties.
2.9.2. A polarized political system
Nonetheless, our previous analysis of polarization in the Senate requires
some modification as a result of using a two-dimensional rather than onedimensional model. The basic thrust of our earlier argument was that there
was substantial attenuation of party differences in the sixties followed by
polarization in the seventies. A similar effect is shown in Figure 8, which
combines information on means and dispersions. The mean on the economic
dimension is plotted for each party. Also plotted is one standard deviation
from the mean in the liberal direction for the RepUblicans and in the conservative direction for the Democrats. This typically creates two overlapping
bands. The extent of the overlap indicates the attenuation of party differences.
[133 ]
352
Cons.
0.80
0.60
0.40
0.20
Overlap
0.00
-0.20
-0.40
Lib.
-0.60
-0.80
59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81
- - Rep. Mean
--- R Mean - One SD
--- Dem. Mean
-------6-
D Mean + One SD
Figure 8. Senate: Party dispersion on the economic dimension. Until the late 1970s, Republicans who were one standard deviation or more liberal than the party mean overlapped
Democrats who were one standard deviation or move conservative than the party mean.
Cons.
0.80
0.60
0.40
0.20
0.00
-0.20
-0.40
Lib.
-0.60
-0.80
59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81
--- Rep. Mean
--- R Mean - One SD
---- Dem. Mean
-------6-
D Mean + One SD
Figure 9. House: Party dispersion on the economic dimension.
[134 ]
353
In comparison to our earlier results, attenuation does occur in the sixties,
but the overlap is substantially less. Moreover, by the late seventies, the overlap is still greater than it was in the early sixties. The basic story is saved,
however, by the 1981 data, not present in our earlier analysis. Interest group
ratings for 1981 show, for the first time, separation rather than overlap in the
two parties. As with the other figures, a similar plot for the social dimension
would show similar, but less pronounced, results.
The divergence between these results and Poole and Rosenthal (1984b)
is clarified by considering that our earlier work had compressed the twodimensional story into one dimension. During the early sixties, the social
dimension was likely to have dominated, for a short period, the economic
dimension in saliency on the national agenda. On the social dimension, there
is less difference between the parties as a result of the extreme conservatism
of Southern Democrats. Thus, when the space is forced into one dimension,
party differences are greatly attenuated in the sixties. In any event, the tendency to polarization identified here on the basis of data that does not extend
beyond 1981, is confirmed by the NOMINATE analysis of roll call votes for
1947 through 1996 in McCarty, Poole, and Rosenthal (1997).
Data from the House, presented in Figure 9, shows a pattern similar to that
of the Senate. Party differences are least in the mid-sixties and early seventies,
and the greatest separation occurs in 1981. In contrast to the Senate, however,
the House has always looked like a purer two-party system since there has
never been any overlap.
3. Conclusion
We believe that a body of empirical research of sufficient size has accumulated to put to rest the classical spatial theory of convergent equilibrium as a
model that is at all descriptive of American national politics. There are substantial differences in the policy positions of Democrats vs. Republicans who
alternatively or concurrently represent the same constituency, be it Presidential or Congressional (Poole and Rosenthal, 1984a,b). There is no indication
of convergent equilibrium. Moreover, the results presented here suggest that
there is little movement or spatial adaptation of the type implicit in Hotelling
competition. 12
Once elected, candidates appear to be highly constrained by reputational
effects. Bernhardt and Ingberman (1985) have developed a model with divergent equilibrium based on the notion of incumbency advantage. In their
model, voters perceive incumbents as less risky than challengers. Movement by the incumbent increases his riskiness. Given that the challenger is
a Stackelberg follower in spatial competition, no incumbent will move so
[ 135]
354
much that his riskiness exceeds the challenger's. Alesina (1988), following
earlier empirical work by Hibbs (1977) and theoretical work by Wittman
(1983) and Calvert (1985), argues that parties have policy preferences that
are known to the voters. In the Alesina framework, parties do not converge
because their campaign promises are not credible to voters who know a
party will in fact implement its preferences once in power. Further work on
both the Bernhardt-Ingberman and Alesina paradigms appears merited by our
empirical results.
Our finding of low dimensionality is consistent with recent theoretical
work on the spatial model which posits a small number of underlying dimensions that in turn produce individuals' issue positions (Ordeshook, 1976;
Hinich and Pollard, 1981; Enelow and Hinich, 1984; Hinich and Munger,
1994). In particular, Hinich and Munger argue that low dimensional spaces
are inevitable in the presence of political conflict. However, Hinich and
Munger do not address convergence, except to predict that political parties will have difficulty in moving ideologically because of problems with
credibility.
Integrating, with a large dose of speculation, the results in this paper with
those of Poole and Rosenthal (1984a), we would suggest that interest groups
are more polarized than legislators who in turn are likely to be more polarized
than the electorate. The electorate would have a unimodal distribution with
most ideal points interior to those of most legislators. In campaigns, as expressed in voter perceptions, Presidential candidates would also be largely on
the periphery of the electorate. But elected Presidents, in their support scores,
while still highly differentiated along party lines, may be less polarized.
Their campaign positions must be compromised as part of the policy-making
process in Washington.
The basis for the picture we have painted may well lie in the free-rider
problem in political participation. Only relative extremists may be sufficiently
committed (read have enough "citizen duty") or have enough at stake to
participate as money givers and doorbell ringers. In Ingberman (1985), the
presence of such polarized contributors is assumed. Candidates can use these
contributions to reduce their riskiness. Consequently, incumbents with large
contributions have greater freedom of movement. On the other hand, incumbent movement may be constrained by the need to appeal to contributors.
The change that television advertising has made in the "production function"
of political campaigns and the need to appeal to contributors may well have
resulted in the increasing polarization we have observed.
Why do presidents appear to be, although polarized, somewhat closer
to the center of the spectrum than legislators? We have suggested that the
policy process provides a possible explanation. But there are alternative
[136 ]
355
theoretical explanations. First, in the Bernbardt-Ingberman (1985) model,
convergent equilibrium does occur in the case of truly open seats. At least
every eight years, the presidential election is a relatively open contest. In
contrast, as Ingberman (1985) shows, challengers will, ceteris paribus, take
increasingly extreme positions as the incumbent's seniority grows. Given
the strength of incumbency in Congress, the rare successful challengers are
likely to be relatively extreme. Second, in Congress, particularly the House,
recognition rather than policy may well be the major aspect of campaigning.
Because Congressional candidates are so much less well known than candidates for the Presidency, they may well optimize by being mainly in tune with
contributors' preferences.
Notes
I. See, however, Poole and Rosenthal (1984a) for some limited analysis of changing spatial
positions in two National Election Study panels.
2. See Snyder (1992) and Poole and Rosenthal (1997: Ch. 8). A related problem is that
there is overlap in the roll calls used by the interest groups. However, the overlap is not
overwhelming. Poole and Daniels (1985) report that over 30% of all roll calls in 1979
were used by at least one interest group, indicating that coverage by interest groups in our
dataset is broad.
3. In the actual unfolding, we used Legendre polynomials rather than the t shown in the text.
The Legendre polynomials differ from this t only for quadratics and higher degrees. We
use Legendre polynomials because they are orthogonal on the interval [-I, + I] (Hinich
and Roll, 1982; Beck, 1983). This property allows us to pick up as much variance as
possible with the linear term before we estimate the quadratic term and so on. Because a
specification higher than linear did not greatly improve results, most readers will not need
to become concerned with the Legendre method.
4. Obviously, estimating the polynomial models runs into a problem for legislators with brief
periods of service. We estimate linear terms only for those serving three or more years;
quadratic only for four or more; and cubic only for five or more. These estimates will be
imprecise (see below) for those legislators with very few years of service. However, since
we have argued elsewhere (Poole and Rosenthal, 1991, 1997) that Congress can basically
be represented in terms of a stable, two-dimensional model with the first dimension being much more important than the second, we deliberately sought to err on the side of
overestimating trends in individual positions.
5. Because some legislators and interest groups are present for time periods too brief to permit estimation of the polynomial parameters, the actual number of parameters estimated
is somewhat less than that given in the following expression.
6. A similar result for a dynamic NOMINATE estimation is presented in Poole and
Rosenthal (1997: 73).
7. The second dimension coordinate was regressed on the first dimension coordinate for the
six presidential support scores.
8. For an analysis of this trend through the \o4th Congress, see McCarty, Poole, and
Rosenthal (\ 997).
[ 137]
356
9. Again, for an analysis of polarization through the 100th Congress, see McCarty, Poole
and Rosenthal (1997).
10. See Poole and Rosenthal (1984b, 1985b) for a discussion of the replacement literature.
11. See Poole and Rosenthal (1987) for analysis of more detailed regional breakdowns in the
context of a unidimensional model.
12. Similar results at the level of individual states can be found in Erikson, Wright, and
McIver (1993).
13. See Poole (1984, 1990) for a detailed discussion ofthe squared error loss function for this
problem.
References
Alesina, A. (1988). Credibility and policy convergence in a two-party system with rational
voters. American Economic Review 78: 796-806.
Beck, N. (1983). Time-varying parameter regression models. American Journal of Political
Science 27: 557-600.
Bernhardt, M. D. and Ingberrnan, D. (1985). Candidate reputations and the incumbency effect.
Journal of Public Economics 27: 47-67.
Bullock, C. S. III. (1981). Congressional voting and the 1982 congressional elections. Journal
of Politics 45: 767-770.
Cahoon, L. S., Melvin, J., Hinich, MJ. and Ordeshook, P. C. (1978). A statistical multidimensional scaling model based on the spational theory of voting. In P. C. Wang (Ed.),
Graphical representation of multidimensional data, 243-278. New York: Academic Press.
Calvert, R. L. (1985). Robustness of the multidimensional voting model: Candidates' motivations, uncertainty, and convergence. American Journal of Political Science 26: 69-95.
Defays, D. (1978). A short note on a method of seriation. British Journal of Mathematical and
Statistical Psychology 31: 49-53.
Dougan, W. R. and Munger, M. C. (1989). The rationality of ideology. Journal of Law and
Economics 32: 119-143.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper.
Enelow, J. M. and Hinich, M. J. (1984). The spatial theory of voting: An introduction. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Erikson, R. S., Wright, G. C. and McIver, J. P. (1993). Statehouse democracy: Public opinion
and policy in the American States. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hibbs, D. (1977). Political parties and macroeconomic policy. American Political Science
Review 71: 1467-1487.
Hinich, M. (1978). Some evidence on non-voting in the spatial theory of electoral competition.
Public Choice 33: 83-102.
Hinich, M. J. and Munger, M. I. (1994). Ideology and the theory of political choice. Ann
Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.
Hinich, M. J. and Pollard, W. (1981). A new approach to the spatial theory of electoral
competition. American Journal of Political Science 25: 323-341.
Hinich, M. J. and Roll, R. (1981). Measuring nonstationarity in the parameters of the market
model. Research in Finance 3: I-51.
Hubert, L. and Arabie, P. (1986). Unidimensional scaling and combinatorial optimization. In:
de Leeuw et al. (Eds.), Multidimensional data analysis. Leiden: DSWO Press.
[138 ]
357
Ingberman, D. (1985). Spatial competition with imperfectly informed voters. Mimeo. University of Pennsylvania.
Kalt, J. and Zupan, M. (1984). Capture and ideology in the economic theory of politics.
American Economic Review 74: 279-300.
Kernell, S. (1973). Is the Senate more liberal than the House? Journal of Politics 35: 332-363.
Khrebiel, K. and Rivers, D. (1985). Congressional roll call strategies: An application of a
new test to minimum wage legislation. Paper presented at the 1985 annual meeting of the
American Political Science Association.
Ladha, K. K. (1994). A spatial model of legislative voting with perceptual error. Public Choice
68: 151-174.
McCarty, N.M., Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (\997). Income redistribution and the
realignment of American Politics. Washington, DC: AEI Press.
Ordeshook, P. C. (1976). The spatial theory of elections: A review and a critique. In I. Budge,
I. Crewe, and D. Farlie (Eds.), Party identification and beyond. New York: Wiley.
Poole, K. T. (1981). Dimensions of interest group evaluation of the U.S. Senate, 1969-1978.
American Journal of Political-Science 25: 49-67.
Poole, K. T. (\ 984). Least squares metric, unidimensional unfolding. Psychometrika 49: 311323.
Poole, K. T. (1990). Least squares metric, unidimensional scaling of multivariate linear
models. Psychometrika 55: 123-149.
Poole, K. T. and Daniels, R. S. (1985). Ideology, party, and voting in the U.S. Congress,
1959-1980. American Political Science Review 79: 373-399.
Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (\ 984a). U.S. presidential elections: 1968-1980. A spatial
analysis. American Journal of Political Science 28: 282-312.
Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (I 984b ). The polarization of American politics. Journal ()f
Politics 46: \062-\079.
Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (1985a). A spatial model for legislative roll call analysis.
American Journal of Political Science 29: 357-384.
Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (l985b). The unidimensional Congress. Mimeo. Carnegie
Mellon University.
Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (1987). The regional realignment of Congress, 1919-1984. In
P. Galderisi and R. Simmons (Eds.), Politics in the Intermountain West: Forerunner to
realignment? Boulder CO: Westview.
Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (1991). Patterns of congressional voting. American Journal of
Political Science 35: 228-278.
Poole, K. T. and Rosenthal, H. (1997). Congress: A political-economic history of roll call
voting. New York: Oxford University Press.
Rabinowitz, G. (1976). A procedure for ordering object pairs consistent with the multidimensional unfolding model. Psychometrika 45: 349-373.
Rivers, D. (\ 987). Inconsistency of least squares unfolding. Paper presented at the Political
Methodology Meetings, Durnham, NC.
Romer, T. and Rosenthal, H. (1987). Modern political economy and the study of regulation.
In E.E. Bailey (Ed.), Public regulation: New perspectives on institutions and politics.
Cambridge MA: M.LT. Press.
Snyder, 1. M. Jr. (\ 992). Artificial extremism in interest group ratings. Legislative Studies
Quarterly 17: 319-345.
Wittman, D. (1983). Candidate motivation: A synthesis of alternatives. American Political
Science Review 77: 142-157.
[ 139]
358
Appendix: Bootstrap experiments
The statistical properties of the estimated parameters for the squared error loss function used here (the sum of the squared differences between the observed distances
and the reproduced distances) are not well understood.B Rivers (1987) has shown
that, under certain conditions in one dimension, the estimates are not consistent.
However, in one dimension, the solution can be shown to reduce to a combinatorial optimization problem (Defays, 1978; Hubert and Arabie, 1986; Poole, 1990) in
which a rank ordering determines all the parameters simultaneously. This is a much
different set of conditions than Rivers employs thus leaving the statistical properties
of the parameters unresolved. Monte Carlo evidence shown in Poole (1984; 1990)
shows no bias in the recovery of the coordinates in one dimension. Consequently,
in order to obtain some insight as to the accuracy of our recovery, we performed
a bootstrapping analysis for the two-dimension version of our unfolding procedure.
Bootstrapping analysis for the one-dimensional version is shown in Poole (1990).
We based our analysis on our recovered coordinates for s = 2 and m = 1 (legislators free to move on both dimensions). To reduce the use of computer time, however,
we restricted the legislators to the 261 senators. Using the recovered coordinates and
trend parameters, we computed distances between the interest groups and the legislators. Distances were generated only for those years for which the senator-interest
group pair bot appeared in the actual data.
These "true" distances were then converted to ratings by multiplying them by
50 and subtracting the resulting quantity from 100. These "true" ratings were then
perturbed by adding normally distributed error at low, medium and high levels (a =
5, 10, 15 respectively). The medium errorlevel corresponds closely to the actual level
of error in the interest group ratings. Negative ratings were truncated to 0 and ratings
greater than 100 were truncated to 100. This procedure was employed to simulate
some of the factors that might perturb the actual data, such as limited selection of
roll calls by the interest groups, omitted dimensions specific to individuals, etc. The
perturbed data were then submitted to our unfolding algorithm.
At each level of error, we conducted 25 replications. From these 25 replications
we were able to compute a root mean square error of recovery for each parameter. A
summary of key results is presented in Tables A-I and A-2.
Constant parameters
Positions on the main, liberal-conservative dimension appear to be recovered with
great accuracy. At medium levels of error, the root mean square errors average under
0.09 while the span of the dimension is over 2 units. In contrast, the second dimension is recovered with less accuracy. The span of the second dimension is under 1.5
units, but at medium error levels root mean square errors average just under 0.2 for
senators and 0.3 for interest groups. While the inaccuracy in recovery is still moderate with respect to the length of the dimension, discussion of individual positions
on this dimension should be taken with caution. Our translated coordinates are linear
combinations of the recovered coordinates. Since our algorithm generates minimal
[140 ]
359
Table A-I. Bootstrap results: Average root mean square errors, recovered
constant parameters
Error level Senators (XikO, k = I, 2)
I st recovered dimension
All N= 261 3 or more
years N = 213
2nd recovered dimension
All N = 261 3 or more
years N = 213
Low
Medium
High
.\09
.197
.306
.045
.089
.190
.044
.082
.179
.\09
.187
.265
Error level Interest groups (ZjkO, k = I, 2)
I st recovered dimension
2nd recovered dimension
All N= 59 3 or more
All N = 59 3 or more
years N =43
years N = 43
Low
Medium
High
.042
.074
.218
.040
.073
.2\0
.147
.280
.3\0
.150
.262
.283
Note. All entries in table based on 25 replications, each using an independent
set of normal errors.
covariance between the two recovered dimensions, it follows that the implicit errors
on our economic dimension are somewhat greater than those for the first recovered
dimension while the errors on the social dimension are somewhat less than those on
the second recovered dimension.
One apparent anomaly in Table A-I is that interest groups are recovered less
accurately on the second dimension in spite of the fact that the interest group recovery appears to be based on a larger effective sample size (261 versus 59). Two
explanations can be suggested.
First, sample size depends also on how long the interest group was in the data
set. In tum, our time series for interest groups tend to be less lengthy than those for
senators. Of the 261 senators, 110 were in the data set for over 10 years as against
only 16 of 59 "interest groups". Moreover, an interest group in the sample for only a
few years is basically rating a stable set of senators whereas a senator in the data set
for only a few years is being rated by a more rapidly changing set of interest groups.
Thus, holding length in the data set constant, more information tends to be gained
about senators than about interest groups. An indication of how length of time in the
data set affects recovery is shown in the table. The root mean square errors are less
for those interest groups and senators in the sample over two years than they are for
the entire data set.
[141]
360
Table A-2. Bootstrap results: average magnitude and root mean square errors,
linear trend per year
Error level
Senators (Xikl, k = 1,2)
I st recovered dimension
3-9 years 10 or more
N=213 years N = 110
2nd recovered dimension
3-9 years 10 or more
N=213 years N = 110
Low magnitude
.080
.021
.028
.015
RootMSE
.059
.019
.046
.014
Medium magnitude .064
.017
.027
.010
RootMSE
.106
.031
.070
.021
High magnitude
.062
.174
.018
.026
.007
.046
.099
.028
RootMSE
Error level
Interest groups (Zjkl, k = 1, 2)
I st recovered dimension
2nd recovered dimension
3-9 years 10 or more
3-9 years 10 or more
years N = 16
years N = 16
N=27
N=27
Low magnitude
.106
.050
.056
.008
.112
Medium magnitude .093
.020
.064
.013
.045
.041
.009
RootMSE
.161
.048
.067
.021
High magnitude
.068
.143
.018
.023
.009
.064
.069
.025
Root MSE
RootMSE
Note. All entries in table based on 25 replicas, each using an independent set of
normal errors.
Second, we note that in the actual recovery, interest groups are clustered at the
two poles of the main dimension whereas legislators are more spread out. These
distributional differences may affect recovery.
Trend
The results shown in Table A-2 support our claim that individual time trends are
of minimal importance. The average magnitude of the yearly change in position is
never more than twice the average root mean square error except for interest groups
serving 10 or more years in the simulations with a low degree of error. That the only
reasonably precise estimates concern interest groups supports our contention that
spatial mobility is greater among interest groups than among legislators.
As a result of our using recovered values in the bootstrap, the average magnitudes
are systematically larger for interest groups and senators present 3 to 9 years than for
[142 ]
361
those present for longer periods. However, the root mean square errors of recovery
for these parameters is so large that the recovered values appear highly dubious when
trend estimates are based on only a few years of data.
Finally, note that the discussion in this Appendix applies to individual parameters.
Estimated positions for aggregates, such as Southern Democrats, will be far more
stable.
[143 ]
Public Choice 97: 363-382, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
363
British parties and spatial competition: Dimensions of party
evaluation in the 1992 election
JAMES W. ENDERSBY' & STEVEN E. GALATAS 2
, Department of Political Science, University of Missouri, 113 Professional Building,
Columbia, MO 65211, U.S.A.; Department of Political Science, University of Missouri, 113
Professional Building, Columbia, MO 65211, U.S.A.
Abstract. Scholars of British politics traditionally characterize the electorate in terms of
partisanship and social class. This paper suggests that ideology and issue preferences also
enter into voter perceptions of British political parties and leadership. Using data from the
1992 British Election Study, the paper analyzes the factors that contribute to individual voters'
perceptions of the Conservative and Labour parties. The 1992 election saw the major parties
move toward the ideological center of British voters. Perceptions of political parties are found
to be multidimensional and issue-oriented. A spatial model incorporating issue preferences
and perceptions of party positions proves both empirically and theoretically richer than simple
models of partisanship. The analysis of British voters complements earlier applications of the
general spatial model in the context of the United States.
1. Introduction
This paper examines the role of issues in the 1992 British general election. In
particular, the paper develops a spatial model of electoral choice in which a
citizen chooses to cast a ballot for the party nearest to personal preferences on
a range of policy dimensions. The results indicate that ideological preferences
are significant factors influencing the choices of voters in the 1992 election.
Discussions of its application in British politics typically equate spatial
theory with unidimensional Downsian analysis and often reject the usefulness
of spatial models for understanding British elections. Electoral behavior is
more often linked to party affiliation and social class orientation. Compared
to parties in the United States, British parties are strong, and voters can be
characterized by party loyalty. Literature on the 1992 election point toward a
reestablishment of class voting in British politics.
If spatial models of political choice trace their origins to the works of
Downs (1957) and Black (1958), then it seems appropriate that the British
electorate should serve as a case study for modern tests of spatial assumptions. Both Black (for committees) and Downs (for mass politics) based much
of their work on an understanding of British politics. But they restrict their
[145 ]
364
spatial analogy to a single dimension. On a single policy dimension defined
by single-peaked preferences, parties should seek the equilibrium at the position of the median voter. More recent scholarship has shown that an equilibrium need not exist when preferences are nonseparable or the number of
policy dimensions grows to two or more (Hinich, 1977). Improvement in
the Downsian spatial model have extended spatial theory to a multidimensional policy space (Davis and Hinich, 1966; Hinich and Pollard, 1981), and
a number of empirical tests have confirmed the utility of the spatial model for
analysis of mass elections (Enelow and Hinich, 1984). Although this paper
focuses on the party positions on particular issues and policies, we do not
expect British voters to weigh policy alternatives in a void without a unifying
ideology (Hinich and Munger, 1994). Instead, evidence we uncover suggests
that British voters do have ideological preferences beyond group and party
affiliation and use information to evaluate which political party is more likely
to satisfy their preferences.
2. Class and party in Britain
Historically, the study of voting behavior in Great Britain grew from similar
lines of work among American political scientists. In reaction to existing
scholarship, with its emphasis on the uniqueness of the British political system and on the role of ideals in the evolution of British politics (Gamble,
1990), a new wave of political scientists focused attention on the behavior
of individuals and groups. With the rise of this new school, scholarship also
began to shift slowly toward comparisons between British and non-British
politics.
Behavioralists, equipped with early empirical models of Britain, quickly
latched onto social group theories of political behavior. Britain came to be
seen as a political system dominated by two social classes: working class
and middle class. The two major political parties, Conservative and Labour,
reflected the interests of these two classes. The model seemed simple and
efficient: the working class voted for Labour and the middle class for Conservative. The largest "natural" class won election because voters selected a
party in an election based upon social class, which in tum reflected economic
interests (Alford, 1963; Pulzer, 1967; Butler and Stokes, 1969). While the
existing social classes disagreed on the extent but not the existence of the
welfare state in modem Britain, changes in electoral behavior reflected either
the resurgence of Celtic nationalism in Scotland and Wales (Beer, 1982), or
appeared to be associated with the relative closeness of the two major parties
and the degree of consensus (Butler and Stokes, 1969).
[146 ]
365
Sparked by the rise in election support for third parties, including the Liberal party across Great Britain, the Plaid Cymru in Wales, and the Scottish
National party in Scotland, an enormous debate developed among scholars
of British voting behavior. The existing model of voting behavior fell into
disfavor by the mid-1970s as mounting evidence suggested that class voting
had diminished in importance (Crewe et aI., 1977). Parsimonius models of
voting behavior no longer required social class, according to Franklin and
Mughan (1978). Further signs of the collapse of class voting appeared in
the 1983 election when less than half the electorate supported the party of
their social class (Butler and Kavanagh, 1983). Such attacks in the literature
continued into the 1990s (Franklin, 1992).
As early evidence mounted against the social class model, other studies
began to follow the Michigan model, examining the degree of partisan identification as an explanation for voting behavior. Alt, Sarlvik, and Crewe (1976)
and Crewe et al. (1977) launched this 'Decade of Dealignment' debate, suggesting that fewer working class voters identified with the Labour party, while
fewer middle class voters saw themselves as Conservative. Sarlvik and Crewe
(1983) state that partisan identification is important for voting behavior but
increases in the volatility of partisanship occurs; this pattern finds confirmation in other research (LeDuc, 1985; Crewe, 1983; Clarke and Stewart, 1984).
However, other evidence suggested that long-term stability existed in partisan
identification despite short-term volatility (Miller et aI., 1986).
Thus, scholarship on voting behavior in Great Britain became locked in a
battle between supporters of the social class model and partisan identification
model. Attempts to resurrect the sociological models of voting behavior occurred. Heath, Jowell, and Curtice (1985) conclude that social class forms the
basis of political support but manifest itself through political ideology. However, as an alternative to the pure class model, McAllister and Rose (1984)
suggest that territorial socialization within the various nations and regions of
the United Kingdom influences forms the basis of voting. A final, innovative
attempt to rescue class voting compares two types of class models: latent class
models rely solely on traditional concepts of class, comparing actual proportions of each class that vote for each party, and associational class models,
incorporating a Downsian unidimensional model in which class replaces issue
as the underlying basis of the model (Weakliem, 1995). Statistical tests of the
two models suggest that the associational model fits the data more accurately
and that a slight trend toward class de alignment occurs.
While much of the debate over this class-party nexus sits at the heart of
voting behavior in Britain, alternatives to these two approaches have also been
posited. While the above approaches might be labeled as primary or longterm factor models, the alternative models focus attention on short-term or
[147 ]
366
secondary consideration. The schools that advocate these approaches focus
on the role of ideology, the influence of party leader images, and the role of
issues in motivating electoral choice. Among these alternatives, the role and
influence of issues fall into two categories. Single-issue studies investigate the
role of an isolated issue, unique to one election, as the impetus for vote choice.
As an example, King (1982) suggests the question of unilateral nuclear disarmament, and the Labour party's position on this issue, as a possibility in the
1979 election. Likewise, political events like the Falklands War may disrupt
normal partisan identification to produce shifts in election outcomes (Mishler,
Hoskin, and Fitzgerald, 1989).
However, the second trend emphasizes the influence of issues across time.
General analysis suggests that issues, including the state of the economy,
unemployment, and inflation, become more prevalent as class declines as the
basis for vote choice (Franklin, 1985; Denver, 1994). Furthermore, Denver
and Hands (1990) discover that young voters just entering the electoral arena
choose a party as a result of opinions on issues rather than long-term factors like partisan identification and social class. Specific issues also play an
important role in vote choice; time-series analysis suggests that perceived priorities of parties on macroeconomic issues is important (Clarke et aI., 1986).
Some scholars tum toward leadership issues as an explanation for vote choice,
absent long-term factors like class voting. Even in parliamentary systems,
party leaders influence the distribution of votes (Bean and Mughan, 1989).
Whether the magnitude of leadership effects possess the power to alter the
electoral outcome remains uncertain (Graetz and McAllister, 1987; Clarke
and Stewart, 1992).
In addition, ideology has been suggested as an explanation for vote choice
and party electoral strategy. Beer (1982) discusses the political upheavals in
the 1970s as related to the shift in ideology from traditional collectivism to individualism of the liberal variety. Furthermore, some authors attempt to relate
the rise of Thatcherism to a shift in ideology, breaking the growth of ideological hostility toward industrial success and replacing this line of though with a
new pro-business culture (Wiener, 1981; Barnett, 1986). However, the role of
ideology has been discounted as a component of the party-class nexus (Heath,
Jowell, and Curtice, 1985). In addition, many scholars claim the Conservative
party contains many divergent, incompatible tendencies and lacks a coherent,
dominant ideology (Whitely et aI., 1994; Vincent, 1994).
[148]
367
3. Voting in Britain: Irrational choice?
Attempts at explaining British voting behavior using spatial concepts have
been made. For example, Budge and Farlie (1977) produce a "Synthesis model" of social class, partisan identification and rational choice. An examination
of the role of issues and the dimension of party programs contends that cityblock spatial models contain superior explanatory power over Euclidean distance measures; however, issue and ideological spaces contain cross-national
explanatory power. Budge (1994) tests several models of voting behavior,
including spatial models, cross-nationally. Concluding that parties do not
necessarily converge at election time, Budge also asserts that uncertainty and
ideology provide incentives for the failure to converge at the median position. Furthermore, Norris (1994) builds a Downsian model of British voting
behavior using a study of politicians and party members for the major parties
to test the degree of polarization, extremism, factionalism, and fragmentation
present in the Labour party in 1992. Finally, spatial analysis does not necessarily conflict with class-based approaches to the study of voting behavior as
suggested above (Weakliem, 1995).
Nevertheless, rational choice models of voting behavior, especially Downsian models, continue to be rejected by many scholars of British politics. According to Heath, Jowell, and Curtice (1985), rational choice models fail for
three reasons: the electorate lacks comprehension of the policy positions of
the parties, voters retain ideology and social class as a guide to voting thereby
rejecting pure self-interest motivations, and parties spurn vote-maximization
strategies, failing to convince the electorate that the party's position changes.
For example, using issue scales from 1983 BES, the party closest to median
voter on unemployment and inflation was Labour, then Alliance, then Conservative. Unfortunately, many scholars of British politics associate rational
choice models of voting behavior primarily with Downsian unidimensional
models (Budge and Farlie, 1977; Heath et aI., 1985; Whitely et ai. 1994).
Reduction of a multidimensional issue space to the unidimensional Downsian model may produce a number of problems. Without separability of issues, the median voter result does not hold, and equilibrium may be impossible. Norris (1996: Ch. 7), for instance, conducts a content analysis of
Labour and Conservative party manifestos over several decades and notes a
number of violations of traditional Downsian assumptions. The British parties
have exhibited considerable volatility on some issues, even leaping over one
another on some policy dimensions and alternating which parties are on the
right and on the left. Although Downsian indicates a relationship between
issues and ideology collapsing into a unidimensional model (Downs, 1957:
100), several empirical studies of voting behavior in the United States and
[149 ]
368
elsewhere suggest a multidimensional issue space appears appropriate. Budge
(1993) and Klingemann et al. (1995) analyze political conflict within western
democracies and find that elections simplify to a limited number of issue
dimensions, often just two.
Another arena for criticism of the application of rational choice and spatial models in British politics focuses on the role of issues in such models.
For example, Whitely et al. (1994: 202) believe that: "Spatial models fail
because they focus exclusively on issues. Voters do not (nor should they)
rely exclusively on issues in an uncertain world, where leadership reputations
may be a better guide to policy outcomes than pre-election issue positions".
However, they also write that when facing a rational electorate, a party strives
for support from majorities on all issues and seeks policies that converge
towards the center of the space and/or the median voter.
Given the emphasis of the social class and partisan identification approaches to voting behavior that dominate much of the scholarship on British voting behavior, another area for criticism focuses on the absence of long-term
forces in most rational choice models. According to Budge and Farlie (1977),
group loyalties inhibit movements of leaders in the policy space, while electors rely on group habits and party loyalty to produce vote choice and positions on issues.
Other critiques center on the basic assumptions of rational choice models and the relationship between the assumptions and reality. Claiming that
followers of economic approaches to voting recognize the lack of realism in
their assumptions, Budge and Farlie (1977: 512) say that the problems of
economic models of voting behavior, demonstrated in election studies, are
that rational choice specialists move from simple models to complex models
and that the process of relaxing assumptions destroys the mathematical basis
resulting in general, misleading, and paradoxical conclusions. Budge et al.
(1983: 27) review rational choice models: "The assumptions which support
formal voting models are, however, extremely restrictive and unlikely to apply directly to real life". Yet, they develop a new synthesis to overcome the
perceived inconsistencies of pure rational choice approaches while retaining
a market approach complete with competition, transaction costs, consumers,
and producers.
4. Parties, issues, and voters in 1992
The 1992 British General Election presents an interesting opportunity to examine the ability of issue-based spatial models of voting behavior in Great
Britain. First, the election features an apparent reversion to the class-party
nexus, or the best approximation since the 1970s (Weakliem, 1995); this situ-
[150]
369
ation seems paradoxically as a point to test issue-based approaches. Second,
the election featured the continuation of Conservative erosion in the Celtic
periphery and North England. Finally, the election occurs at a time of growing methodological and theoretical diversity in the study of British politics
(Gamble, 1990).
The 1992 British General Election Study consists of a nationally representative, cross-sectional sample contacted shortly after the election (Heath et aI.,
1993). A total of 3,534 personal interviews were conducted. In order to better
represent Scotland the 1992 study oversamples Scots and requires that individual responses be weighted to produce the nationally representative sample.
Throughout this analysis, data are weighted. The 1992 British Election Studies (BES) provides a battery of questions designed to elicit respondent preferences over a variety of issues. Like most surveys of public opinion, however,
respondents are offered few opportunities to make judgments concerning the
issue orientations of the political parties.
Embedded in the questionnaire are several scales which allow both selfplacement of the respondents as well as the perceived placement of the political parties. Respondents identify not only their own ideal positions on a
unidimensional policy scale but also where they would locate the Conservatives and Labour (as well as the Liberal Democrats and, for Scotland only, the
Scottish Nationals). A respondent in the 1992 BES is shown a left-right scale
marked with the letters ranging from A to K. A particular policy alternative
characterizes each endpoint, for instance, the European Community question
ranges from (A) Unite fully with Ee to (K) Protect independence (the Appendix lists all of the 1992 BES scales). An interviewer asks the respondent
"Which [ofthe eleven points on the scale] comes closest to your own views?"
A respondent chooses one of the eleven letters or may voluntarily opt for left
of A or right of K (though these extreme placements are unusual). The following two questions ask the respondent "Which [letter/point] comes closest
to the views of the Conservative Party?" and "Which comes closest to the
views of the Labour Party?"
The 1992 British survey employs a split-sample design. The survey includes a total of eight issue scales, but not all questions are posed to all
respondents. Half of the British sample considers five policy areas - unemployment/inflation, taxation/services, nationalisation/privatisation, redistribution of wealth, and the European Community. The other half of the sample
evaluates three policy areas - defence, welfare, and women's rights. For these
three scales, the letters range from A to G producing shorter, seven-point
scales. There are other important differences between the two samples. The
survey instrument for the first half of the sample asks respondents "When you
were deciding about voting, how important was this issue to you?" for each
[ 151 ]
370
of the five policy areas. Voters could respond one of four ways: Extremely
important, Important, Not very important, or Not at all important. The second
half of the sample did not evaluate the importance of the three-issue scales.
The full sample received identical questions pertaining to party affiliation,
voting behavior,l and social class.
The procedure utilized here transforms the survey responses to policy
distances suitable for a test of the spatial model. The respondent's self- and
party-placement on the alphabetic orderings are translated from letters to
numbers. Thus, the A to K interval corresponds to a numerical scale from
1 to 11, and the A to G interval corresponds to a 1 to 7 scale. Extremist
placements, those to the left of A or to the right of K or G, occur infrequently
and are simply recoded to the appropriate end of the eleven- or seven-point
scale. Differences between self-placement and location of a particular party
are then units counting the numbers of ticks separating the two. Thus, the
distance measure is equivalent to a traditional, numbered interval scale.
Table 1 reports average locations for self- and perceived party-placement
for all those responding to the surveys. The seven-point issue scales of the alternative questionnaire are transformed to eleven-point scales for purposes of
comparison2 (the actual values on the seven-point scales are used in the analysis below). In addition, the table identifies the percentage of those responding
who evaluated the issue as either 'extremely important' or 'important'. The
majority of respondents considered issues pertaining to aggregate economic
conditions as more important policy concerns (approximately one-third rated
the unemployment-inflation and taxation-services issues as extremely important). The indicators of preferences for the direction of the national economy
are important to slightly more than a third of the electorate (around 10%
consider each of these goals extremely important).
On all of the issue scales, Labour lies to the left of the Tories. The mean
perceived positions of the two parties differ by less than a unit on only two
policy dimensions, and on these two dimensions both parties are located to
one side of the mean voter. The average Briton is situated in the middle of the
eleven-point European Community scale at 6.0; the Tories fall slightly to the
left (5.6) with Labour a bit further out (5.2). On Women's Rights, the mean
among respondents is far to the left at 2.8; the Labour Party places at the
right at 3.7 and the Conservatives further at 4.1. On the other scales, the two
parties surround the average British voter. The Conservative party is placed
nearer the mean respondent on two scales - on the European question and on
defense. Labour locates closer to the average voter on the other six scales.
[152 ]
371
Table 1. Mean placement of respondent and parties on seven-issue scales (British
National Election Study, 1992)
Labour
Issue
Respondent
party
Conservative
party
importance
Unemployment/inflation
3.56
6.44
2.98
50.6%
Taxation/services
4.18
7.03
2.79
56.6%
Scale
N ationalisation/privati sat ion
5.75
8.35
3.56
32.4%
Redistribution of wealth
4.71
7.89
3.03
43.1%
European Community
5.98
5.56
5.18
38.7%
Defence
5.14
6.12
3.86
Welfare
3.89
7.09
3.23
Women's rights
2.81
4.12
3.71
Mean self- and party-placements are for all respondents. Defence, Welfare, and Women's
rights are seven-point scales transformed to eleven-point scales for consistency in this
table only. Respondents were not asked to rate the importance of these issues for these
three issues. Issue importance denotes the percentage of respondents rating the issue as
"impOJ1ant" or "extremely important".
5. A spatial model of the British electorate
Our contention is that party positions on issues are important to the contemporary British electorate and that discussions of party and class voting and
the unidimensionality of British partisanship mixes the unifying nature of political ideology with preferences on particular issues. Moreover, we contend
that voter preferences on issues have an independent effect on many voters
beyond the influence of party and class differences.
Our goal, then, is to test whether relative placements of respondents and
of perceived Labour and Conservative party locations on issue scales are related to vote choice in the 1992 election. We evaluate the effect of relative
placements on issue scales independently as well as when the respondent's
party affiliation and class are controlled.
Unlike American style political systems involving the distribution of power
among branches of government, the placement of the ruling (Conservative)
party essentially is the placement for the location of parties; this analysis
does not attempt to derive estimated party locations based on generalized
public perceptions. Instead, we compare each respondent's preferred position
on a series of unidimensional policy scales and with that same respondent's
perceptions of where the two major parties are positioned on those scales.
We assume that issue preferences can be measured as a function of simple
linear distance on the policy scales. In particular, for a respondent, i, and
[ 1531
372
an issue, j, the perceived relative distance, dij , between the Conservative and
Labour parties can be computed as:
dij = wij(lxijl - xijl - IXijc - xijl)
where Xij is the ilh respondent's self-placement on the jlh policy dimension, Xijc
and Xijl are the respondent's perceived placements of the Conservative and
Labour parties respectively, and Wij is the value or weight that the ilh respondent places on the jlh issue. Initially, we assume that Wij = 1 for all voters; later,
we allow for individual variation among the issue weights. Each dij measures
relative party distance. The Conservative policy position is preferred for positive values of dij and Labour is preferred for negative values. The magnitude
of the distance variable denotes the intensity of preference for one party's
perceived platform on that policy. An individual remains indifferent between
the parties if the distance between them is zero.
In other words, a voter perceives the value of voting for a political party (or
candidate) as inversely related to the policy distance that separates that party
from the voter. The voter casts a ballot for the political party which is closest
to personal ideological (or issue) preferences. A voter's assessment of the
voting decision depends on three items: preferred policies (the voter's ideal
points on issue dimensions), the perceived positions of each party, and the
weights for each dimension. A logistic regression model tests whether issues
- defined as these relative party distances - are factors related to vote choice
between the two parties. The simple model uses only distance measures as
predictors of party votes. An improved model also controls for other primary factors related to voting in British elections. The full logistic regression
equation can be represented as
where D is the matrix of policy distances, dij , and Z is the matrix of control
variables. 3 If issues matter for British voters, then they should be more likely
to cast ballots for parties perceived closer to voters' policy preferences and
the estimated coefficients for each policy distance variable should be significantly different from zero and in the direction of the party nearer to ideal
preferences. If class, party, and group ties (or other indicators) are responsible
for voting decisions, then the estimated coefficients for the issue scales should
not be significantly different from zero.
The dependent variables predicted by this model is a vote cast for either
the Labour or Conservative parties. Since the Tories won, predicted votes are
for this category, and positive signs for the estimated parameters suggest a
greater likelihood of a vote cast for the Conservative Party. Limiting observations to the two major parties does reduce the size of the 1992 sample in
[154 ]
373
areas with strong third party showings. This limitation primarily effects constituencies in which the Liberal Democrats ran well and in Scotland where the
Scottish National Party claimed many votes. 4 Restricting valid observations
to votes for the two major parties does circumvent a few difficult, though
interesting, problems. Abstention (indifference) and alienation (dissatisfaction) are avoided entirely since only citizens who choose to vote are admitted
into the model. Likewise, strategic voting among the range of permissible
alternatives can not occur (though voters are included who might otherwise
support a minor party in a proportional representation system). Since the
model requires respondents to place themselves and the major parties on each
policy dimension, the issue scales filter the sample as well. Of course, the
use of the scales divides the sample into halves. However, the subsample for
each model represents the national constituency of Labour and Conservative
supporters. Each weighted split sample used in a logistic regression contains
approximately eight hundred voters. s
The 1992 BES includes measures of political party and class affiliation.
This analysis excludes minor parties, so two partisanship dummy variables
are created. Each of these party affiliation variables has a value of 1 to indicate an identification withe (Labour or Conservative) Party and a value of
o otherwise. 6 Social class proved more difficult to quantify. An index was
constructed to identify association within one of six commonly accepted categories representing socioeconomic status. The social class variables ranges
from 5 for professionals to 0 for unskilled laborers and corresponds to a traditional ordering of social class in Britain.7 We experimented with a number
of other nominal and interval measures for class and social status, but our
findings of relationships among the variables remained consistent and this
procedure primarily demonstrated the problems with accurately quantifying
social status in contemporary Britain. The social class variable should reflect
the increasing propensity to vote with the Conservative Party as social status
nses.
6. Issues matter
Each of the following three tables presents three models, and each estimated
logistic regression equation is listed in a separate column. The first model
estimates choices of Conservative and Labour voters using only the relative
closeness of the two parties on the issue scales. The second model adds
the dummy variable indicating affiliation with the Conservative Party and
the ordered variable for social class to relative party placement on the issue
scales. The third model incorporates a dummy variable for identification with
the Labour Party with these other variables. Each table presents the maxi-
[155]
374
mum likelihood parameter estimates for each independent variable and their
associated asymmetric standard errors.
Also included in each table are statistics testing the null hypotheses of
dependence and several measures of the goodness of fit for the overall models. The likelihood ratio chi-square statistic tests the joint significance of the
explanatory variables. For each parameter estimate, the Wald chi-square statistic tests whether the estimated coefficients for each independent variable
is significantly different that zero, controlling for the other independent variables. The tables include two additional indicators to show the measure of
association between observed and predicted responses. The gamma statistic
indicates the relative occurrence of concordant to discordant pairs between reported votes of respondents and their predicted votes. Each table also presents
the percentage of Conservative and Labour votes correctly classified. This
computation predicts a Conservative vote for a respondent in cases for which
the probability of the fitted model exceed 0.5 and a Labour vote otherwise.
The first model compares reported vote choice and relative perceptions of
the parties on the policy questions. Table 2 reports the findings of the models
for the split sample responding to the five-issue scales, and Table 3 shows
results for those responding to the three-issue scales. The left column gives
the estimated parameters for the simple logistic regression model limited
to the issue dimensions only. Party proximity on each policy issue appears
significantly and independently related to the vote. Coefficients for the scales
are universally in the correct direction (here, and in the estimated equations
that follow). A party perceived nearer voters' policy preferences benefits by
receiving a greater share of their votes. The policy scale comparing jobs
and prices shows the weakest relationship with party choice, perhaps due to
the multidimensional nature of this "unidimensional" scale. In both samples,
proximity on the policy scales is strongly related to voters' loyalty; either
bundle of issues can explain about 85% of Labour and Conservative votes,
without the inclusion of other voter characteristics.
Policy preferences and perceptions, however, should also be related to
partisanship and social status. Whether issue preferences either influence or
are influenced by ideological, 8 partisan, and group affiliation, controls for
respondent party and class reduce or eliminate the independent effects of
party proximity. The middle and right-most columns of Table 2 and 3 present
estimated equations incorporating variables for party and social class. As
expected, variables indicating party affiliation are strongly associated with
party votes. Relative party proximity measures, however, remain important.
In the first split sample, party and class effects absorb the economic policies
of inflation-unemployment and privatisation-nationalisation. The effects of
social class on the vote disappear as variables indicating affiliation with each
[156 ]
375
Table 2. Issues, party, and social class influences on the vote - logistic regression
results - eleven-point scales (British National Election Study, 1992)
Estimated
Unemployment/inflation
Taxation/services
Estimated
Estimated
coefficient
coefficient
coefficient
(Standard error)
(Standard error)
(S tandard error)
.072*
.048
.040
(.030)
(.043)
(.051)
.192***
.256***
(.032)
Nationalisation
.155***
(.027)
Redistribution of wealth
.276***
European Community
(.055)
.076*
.045
(.037)
(.041)
.250***
(.030)
(.044)
.196***
.197***
(.037)
Party-Conservative
.262***
(.049)
.190***
(.047)
.182*
(.053)
(.058)
4.465***
2.839***
(.397)
Party-Labour
(.443)
-3.459***
(.633)
Social class
Intercept
Likelihood ratio
Gamma
Correctly classified
.413**
.286
(.137)
(.161)
-2.177***
-.389
(.124)
(.413)
(.529)
621.4***
851.8***
895.3***
.778***
.893
.973
.983
85.0%
94.4%
95.7%
* Chi-square statistic significant at .05 level.
** Chi-square statistic significant at .01 level.
*** Chi-square statistic significant at .001 level.
of the parties are included. Other political-economic policies retain close relationships with voting behavior. For the second sample, defence and social
welfare policies maintain an association with reported vote, although social
orientations, that is, policies on women's rights, fail to show any link with
vote choice one major party identification is incorporated into the model. The
logistic regression equations adding party affiliation explain a larger share of
Labour and Conservative voters; up to 95% of reported votes are predicted
correctly by these hybrid models.
[157 ]
376
Table 3. Issues, party, and social class influences on the vote -logistic regression
results - seven-point scales (British National Election Study, 1992)
Defence
Welfare
Estimated
Estimated
coefficient
coefficient
coefficient
(Standard error)
(Standard error)
(Standard error)
.613***
(.066)
.593***
(.052)
Women's rights
.380***
(.079)
Party-Conservative
.369***
(.084)
.471 ***
(.070)
.325**
Estimated
.296**
(.098)
.504***
(.085)
.173
(.1l2)
(.125)
4.459***
2.811 ***
(.431)
Party-Labour
(.457)
-3.681 ***
(.500)
Social class
Intercept
Likelihood ratio
Gamma
Correctly classified
.665***
.431 **
(.125)
(.146)
-2.324***
-.130*
(.1l6)
(.358)
(.454)
583.4***
827.7***
910.5***
.830***
.846
.955
.973
85.8%
92.7%
94.8%
* Chi-square statistic significant at .05 level.
** Chi-square statistic significant at .0llevel.
*** Chi-square statistic significant at .001 level.
These findings strongly support the thesis of the multidimensional nature
of issues in British electoral behavior. The simple proximity model measures
the influence of issues as comparative distance between perceived party locations but does not allow for intensity of preferences for particular issues.
Respondents in the first split sample not only describe policy preferences but
also rate the importance of these policies. These self-reported assessments
of policy importance can be used as a proxy for the weight an issue plays
in the relative evaluations of the parties. The weight, Wij, for computation
of each relative party distance, d ij , is operationally defined in the following
manner. Issues considered not very or not at all important have a unit weight
as outlined above. Issues described as "important" receive a weight of 2, and
those valued as "extremely important" are weighted by 4.
[158 ]
377
Table 4. Issues, party, and social class influences on the vote - logistic regression results
- eleven-point scales weighted by intensity (British National Election Study, 1992)
Unemployment/inflation
Estimated
Estimated
Estimated
coefficient
coefficient
coefficient
(Standard error)
(Standard error)
(Standard error)
.035**
(.011 )
Taxation/services
.080***
(.013)
Nationalisation/privatisation
.077***
(.014)
Redistribution of wealth
.149***
(.017)
Party-Conservative
.024
.023
(.014)
(.018)
.096***
.097***
(.017)
(.019)
.038*
.022
(.016)
(.018)
.138***
.101 ***
(.025)
(.026)
4.663***
2.976***
(.411 )
(.448)
-3.508***
Party-Labour
(.643)
.481***
Social class
Intercept
Likelihood ratio
Gamma
Correctly classified
.826***
.336*
(.135)
(.158)
-2.340***
-.487
(.121)
(.415)
(.519)
601.9***
853.2***
898.0***
.888
.976
.982
85.6%
94.7%
95.6%
* Chi-square statistic significant at .05 level.
** Chi-square statistic significant at .01 level.
*** Chi-square statistic significant at .001 level.
The perceived party differences are multiplied by their respective policy
weights and then serve as independent variables in new formulations of the
logistic regression models. The results for the weighted models are given in
Table 4. In general, the findings for weighted party preference are consistent with the uniform party model. Party proximity on policy issues remains
significantly related to vote choice. The two economic scales with weak relationships in the uniformly weighted model also show little association with
vote choice in weighted evaluations once partisanship and social class are
controlled. The importance attached to British participation in the European
Community appears somewhat more important in the weighted model. The
predictive power of the logistic models with weighted issues increases, but
[ 159]
378
only slightly. Intensity of preferences for certain policies may influence a
voter's loyalty for one party over another, but the parsimonious proximity
model of policy preference and vote choice explains as much with less information. The distance between voters' policy preferences and perceived party
programs accounts for the value attributed to certain policies. 9
7. Ideology and the British electorate
Our findings suggest that British voters do take issue preferences into account
as they choose among parties in national elections. Our results reconfirm that
party affiliation and, to a lesser extent, social class reinforce preferences and
the likelihood of vote choice for a political party. Voters, nevertheless, are
also able to make reasoned evaluations of party positions on policy questions
and compare these to their own preferences. British voters tend to choose the
political party which they perceive to be nearest their personal preferences as
they cast ballots.
Evidence suggests that British party elites are well aware of voters' reliance on issues and ideology when making decisions in an era of partisan
dealignment. Within recent years both major parties have tried to position
themselves strategically, near the center of the British electorate. Labour Party
reforms have repositioned it as a catch-all party, more attractive to voters
beyond the working class. The Conservative Party has abandoned some of
the more extremist elements of Thatcherism, adopting a moderate ideology.
Leaders of both parties recognize the need to appeal to moderate voters to win
elections and are now competing for the center of the ideological space. I 0
One element missing from this analysis is the influence of nonpolicy characteristics on voting decisions. Personal characteristics of party leaders (such
as Tony Blair) may appeal to British voters, just as these factors may be
influential to voters in the United States. The Americanization of political
campaigns seems to be affecting democratic elections globally, with its emphasis on technology and personalization of electoral alternatives. British
parties, moreover, also have nonpolicy characteristics (perhaps unlike their
American counterparts). The Labour Party, for instance, has made great pains
to shed its image as the "Looney Left", as the Tory campaign equating "New
Labour, New Danger" warns voters against trusting their opponents. The old
class divisions between the parties seems to give way to a new political-social
ideology epitomised by personalized characteristics of the parties. The nonpolicy component of partisan affiliation in Britain seems an important topic
for future research.
British political ideology remains an illusive concept, but our findings
strongly suggest that issue preferences are an important component underly-
[160 ]
379
ing voting decisions in Britain. Voters make assessments of their own policy
preferences and of the platforms promoted by the two parties. Voters are
more likely to cast ballots for the party perceived as nearer to their own
preferences on a wide range of issues. This evaluative process goes beyond
simple partisanship and class orientation. Voters take issues into consideration when evaluating parties, and the spatial model serves as an effective
means to describe the process of how voters make these judgments.
Notes
1. The split sample design also varied question order for items on partisan identification and
voting behavior. The split sample rating the five policy areas identified partisanship before
the vote. Half of respondents. those rating three policies, identified the 1992 party vote
prior to personal party affiliation.
2. The equation transforming a value from the seven point scale (X7) to a corresponding
point on the eleven-point scale (Xli) is: XII = [(X7-1)/6]*1O + 1.
3. This construction can-ies the primitive assumption that preferences on issues are unique
and separable, since the model tests for independent effects of relative distance on each
scale. On the other hand, if issue preferences were completely nonseparable or if private
opinions con-espond to party or class affiliations, then we would fail to find statistical
significance for rejecting a hypothesis of dependence. A factor analysis of placements on
the policy scales suggests multidimensionality in party- and self-placements.
4. In the full sample, the Tories receive 45.6% of the vote. Labour gets 34.3%. The remainder
of votes are distributed among the smaller parties: Liberal Democrat 17.1 %. Scottish
National 2.2%, Green 0.3%, Plaid Cymru 0.2%, and other 0.3%. The Conservatives win
57.1 % of the two-party vote in the 1992 BES.
5. The sample sizes for each logistic regressions are, in order of basic and hybrid models by
raw and weighted observations - Table I and 3: 973, 814: 951, 798: Table 2: 1014.847:
988, 826. Sample size for hybrid models is slightly lower because of missing values for
the class variable.
6. The BES prompts for party affiliation and, if none is supplied, presses for the party closer
to the respondent. If Labour or Conservative is answered at either stage. the variables
measure party affiliation.
7. The categories, in descending order, are: Professional, Managerial and technical, Skilled
nonmanual, Skilled manual, Partly skilled, Skilled.
8. Perhaps indicating British scholars' rejection of spatial models of ideology and issue
voting, the BES does not include questions regarding the general ideological orientation
of political parties or leaders other than the scales reviewed here.
9. Of course, all of the policy scales in the 1992 BES are important to a large segment of the
split sample. It is quite reasonable to assume that some issues are of no importance to all
but a few voters, and weighting across issues would better reflect such preferences.
10. This movement towards the middle is a search for centrist positions on the ideological dimension and not for a median location on each separate issue dimension, as many British
scholars have wrongly suggested. While individual issues are linked to ideology. parties
seek the median of voter ideal points induced from preferences on the issue dimensions
and perceived linkages to party ideology.
[ 161 ]
380
References
Alford, R.R. (1963). Party and society: The Anglo-American democracies. Chicago: RandMcNally.
Alt, J.E., Sarlvik, B. and Crewe, I. (1976). Partisanship and policy choice: Issue preferences
in the British electorate, February 1974. British Journal of Political Science 6: 273-290.
Barnett, C. (1986). The audit of war. London: Macmillan.
Bean, e. and Mughan, A. (1989). Leadership effects in parliamentary elections in Australia
and Britain. American Political Science Review 83: 1165-1179.
Beer, S. (1982). Britain against itself. New York: Norton.
Black, D. (1958). Theory of committee and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Budge, I. (1993). Issues, dimensions, and agenda change in postwar democracies: Long-term
trends in party election programs and newspaper reports in twenty-three democracies. In
W.H. Riker (Ed.), Agenda formation. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Budge, I. (1994). A new spatial theory of party competition: Uncertainty, ideology and policy
equilibria viewed comparatively and temporally. British Journal of Political Science 24:
443-467.
Budge, I. and Farlie, D. (1977). Voting and party competition: A theoretical critique and
synthesis applied to surveys from ten democracies. London: Wiley.
Budge, I., Farlie, D. and Laver, M. (1983). What is 'rational' choice?: Shifts in meaning within
explanations of voting and party competition. Electoral Studies 2: 23-38.
Butler, D. and Kavanagh, D. (1983). The British General Election of 1983. New York: St.
Martin's Press.
Butler, D. and Stokes, D. (1969). Political change in Britain. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Clarke, H.D. and Stewart, M.e. (1984). Dealignment of degree: Partisan change in Britain,
1974--83. Journal of Politics 48: 689-718.
Clarke, H.D. and Stewart, M.C. (1992). The (un)importance of party leader images and party
choice in the 1987 British election. Journal of Politics 54: 447-470.
Clarke, H.D., Stewart, M.e. and Zuk, G. (1986). Politics, economic, and party popularity in
Britain, 1979-83. Electoral Studies 5: 123-141.
Crewe, I. (1983). The electorate: Partisan dealignment ten years on. West European Politics 6:
183-215.
Crewe, I., Alt, 1. and Sarlvik, B. (1977). Partisan dealignment in Britain 1964--1974. British
Journal of Political Science 7: 129-190.
Davis, O.A. and Hinich, M.J. (1966). A mathematical model of policy formulation in a democratic society. In 1.L. Bernd (Ed.), Mathematical applications in political science, Vol. II.
Dallas: Southern Methodist University Press.
Denver, D. (1994). Elections and voting behavior in Britain. Deddington: Philip Alan.
Denver, D. and Hands, G. (1990). Issues, principles, or ideology?: How young voters decide.
Electoral Studies 9: 19-36.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper and Row.
Enelow, J.M. and Hinich, M.J. (1984). The spatial theory of voting. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Franklin, M.N. (1985). Assessing the rise of issue voting in British elections since 1964.
Electoral Studies 4: 37-56.
Franklin, M.N. (1992). Britain. In M.N. Franklin, T.T. Mackie, and H. Valen (Eds.), Electoral
change: Responses to evolving social and attitudinal structures in western countries. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
[162]
381
Franklin, M.N. and Mughan, A. (1978). The decline of class voting in Britain: Problems of
analysis and interpretation. American Political Science Review 72: 523-534.
Gamble, A. (1990). Theories of British Politics. Political Studies 38: 404-420.
Graetz, B. and McAllister, I. (1987). Party leaders and election outcome in Britain, 1974-1983.
Comparative Political Studies 19: 484--507.
Heath, A., Jowell, R. and Curtice, J. (1985). How Britain votes. New York: Pergamon Press.
Heath, A., Jowell, R., Curtice, J.K., Brand, J.A. and Mitchell, J.e. (1993). British General
Election Study, 1992 [computer file], ICPSR version. London: Social and Community
Planning Research [producer], 1992. Colchester: ESRC Data Archive/Ann Arbor: Interuniversity Consortium for Political and Social Research, 1996.
Hinich, M.J. (1977). Equilibrium in spatial voting: The median voter result is an artifact.
Journal of Economic Theory 16: 208-219.
Hinich, M.J. and Munger, M.C. (1994). Ideology and the theory ofpolitical choice. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Hinich, M.J. and Pollard, w.J. (1981). A new approach 0 the spatial theory of electoral
competition. American Journal of Political Science 25: 323-341.
King, A. (1982). Whatever is happening to the British party model? Parliamentary Affairs 35:
241-251.
Klingemann, H.D., Hofferbert, R.1. and Budge, I. (1994). Parties, policies, and democracy.
Boulder: Westview Press.
LeDuc, L. (1985). Partisan change and dealignment in Canada, Great Britain, and the United
States. Comparative Politics 17: 379-398.
McAllister, I. and Rose, R. (1984). The nationwide competition for votes. London: F. Pinter
and the Center for the Study of Public Policy.
Miller, w.L., Tagg, S. and Britto, K. (\986). Partisanship and party preferences in government
and opposition: The mid-term perspective. Electoral Studies 5: 31-46.
Mishler, w., Hoskin, M. and Fitzgerald, R. (1989). British parties in the balance: A timeseries analysis of long-term trends in Labour and Conservative support. British Journal of
Political Science 19: 211-236.
Norris, P. (1994). Labour party factionalism and extremism. In A. Heath, R. Jowell, and 1.
Curtice (Eds.), Labour's last chance: The 1992 election and beyond. Brookfield, VT:
Dartmouth Publishing.
Norris, P. (1996). Electoral change in Britain since 1945. Oxford: Blackwell.
Pulzer, P.G. (1967). Political representation and elections in Britain. London: Allen and
Unwin.
Sarlvik, B. and Crewe, I. (1983). Decade of dealignment: The Conservative victory of 1979
and electoral trends in the 1970s. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Vincent, A. (1994). British conservatism and the problem of ideology. Political Studies 42:
204--227.
Weakliem, D.L. (1995). Two models of class voting. British Journal of Political Science 25:
254--270.
Whiteley, P., Seyd, P., Richardson, 1. and Bissell, P. (1994). Thatcherism and the Conservative
party. Political Studies 42: 183-203.
Wiener, M. (1981). English culture and the decline of the industrial spirit. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
[163]
382
Appendix
Issue scales and endpoints (British National Election Study, 1992)
Issue scale
I (A)
7 (G) or II (K)
Keep prices down
Unemployment/inflation
Back to work
Taxation/services
Up taxes and spend more
Redistribution of wealth
tries
Greater effort to equalise in- Less concerned to equalise
European Community
come
Unite fully with European
income
Protect independence
Defence
Community
Spend less on defence
Greatly increase spending
Welfare
Govt responsible for job and Get ahead on own
Women's rights
Women have an equal role
Cut taxes and spend less
Nationalisation/privatisation Nationalise more industries Sell of nationalised indus-
on defence
good standard of living
[ 164 ]
Women's place in the home
Public Choice 97: 383-399, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
383
Retrospective and prospective voting in a one-party- dominant
democracy: Taiwan's 1996 presidential election
JOHN FUH-SHENG HSIEH l , DEAN LACy2 & EMERSON M.S. NIOU 3
1Department of Political Sciences, National Chengchi University, Taipei 11623, Taiwan;
2Department of Political Science, Ohio State University, Columbus, OR 43210- 1373, U.S.A.;
3Department of Political Science, Duke University, Durham, NC 27708-0204, U.S.A.
Abstract. Several theories of voting behavior suggest that voters evaluate candidates in an
election based on the candidates' past performance and future promise. There is a dispute
in the theory and ambiguity in empirical evidence about which direction voters look when
choosing candidates: do voters weigh past performance or future promise more heavily in the
voting booth? This paper contributes empirical support to the prospective voting model by
testing both retrospective and prospective voting in a pivotal case: the 1996 Taiwan presidential election. Taiwan's 1996 election represents the first popular election of the president from
a field of candidates that included the long-ruling KMT party incumbent, Lee Tent-hui. In the
Taiwan presidential election, voter evaluations of Lee's prospects for managing the economy
in the future prove statistically significant as a predictor of voter choice. Voter evaluations of
recent economic conditions do not appear closely related to voter choice. Voters' perceptions
of the candidates' abilities to influence ethnic relations, domestic safety, and international
security are better predictors of the vote than past ethnic relations or past security problems,
even in the face of Communist China's pre- election aggression toward Taiwan.
1. Introduction
Theories of voting behavior disagree on whether voters vote retrospectively
or prospectively. According to the retrospective voting model, voters evaluate an incumbent's past performance, typically on economic issues, and vote
against the incumbent if conditions worsened during his or her term in office
(Key, 1966; Fiorina, 1981). The prospective voting model suggests that even
if voters consider a candidate's past performance, they look primarily at each
candidate's future promise for managing national affairs, again typically economic (Downs, 1957; Achen, 1992). The empirical evidence weighing these
two models is mixed (Kiewiet, 1983; Lewis-Beck, 1990). This paper seeks
to adjudicate between prospective and retrospective voting models by testing
each in an important pivotal case: Taiwan's first popular presidential election,
on 23 March 1996.
[165 ]
384
Taiwan represents an important case for the study of prospective and retrospective voting since it is, and has been for five decades, a one-party-dominant
regime. Though Taiwan is now a fully functioning democratic state with free
and fair elections for both the legislative and executive branches, Taiwan
remains a one-party-dominant regime with the ruling Kuomintang (Nationalist Party) controlling government at most levels. Taiwan's unique political
situation makes it an ideal test case for retrospective and prospective voting
models on three counts. First, Taiwan's legislative and executive branches
of government have been unified under one party for decades, thus allowing
voters to identify clearly who is responsible for past economic and social conditions. The United States often serves as a test case for retrospective voting
models (Fiorina, 1981), but given recent American experiences with divided
government (Fiorina, 1992; Jacobson, 1990), it is difficult for American voters to serve as "rational gods of vengeance and reward" (Key, 1966). Second,
Taiwan's executive branch has been controlled by President Lee Teng-hui
for eight years. Lee's tenure enables voters to attribute economic and social
conditions to Lee rather than having to decide whether Lee inherited conditions from recent predecessors. Most tests of retrospective voting models use
American electoral data, but when a candidate has served only four years or
less, as is the case in every American presidential election since 1948, it is
difficult for voters to decide whether the president is truly accountable for
national conditions. Finally, Taiwanese voters typically find four issues important in national elections: the economy, relations with Communist China,
public safety, and ethnic relations. In other countries many more issues - religious, racial, environmental, and cultural - often cloud any attempts to test a
parsimonious issue voting model. By tapping voter evaluations of past performance on a few issues along with their evaluations of candidates' potential to
improve or undermine those issues, we are able to determine whether voters
in the 1996 Taiwan presidential election simply looked at the past and decided
to stay the course or whether they looked to the future and evaluated the many
different paths offered by the competing candidates.
Our results are surprising. Using data provided by National Chengchi
University, we estimate a multinomiallogit model of the vote for Lee, Peng,
Chen, and Lin. We find that voter evaluations of past economic conditions
- both sociotropic and personal - are not statistically significant as an explanation of voter choice. Instead, voter evaluations of Lee's prospects for
managing the economy are statistically significant as an explanation of the
vote. Voters also evaluated the candidates' abilities to manage ethnic relations
and cross-straits relations in the future. Retrospective evaluations of ethnic
relations, straits relations, and public safety are not statistically significant
[166 ]
385
as explanations of the vote. However, the prospective and candidate-specific
versions of these issues are significant.
The paper proceeds as follows. We provide a brief background on Taiwan's first popular election of a president (Section 2). We then outline the
competing models of voting and discuss empirical findings to date (Section
3). We describe our model and data, and we present results using multinomiallogit to estimate the model (Section 4). We conclude by discussing the
importance of our findings in the general literature on voting behavior and on
the future of Taiwanese presidential elections (Section 5).
2. Background
On 23 March, 1996, voters in Taiwan went to the polls to participate in
the first direct election of the president in the history of the Republic of
China (ROC) on Taiwan. According to the original stipulations of the ROC
Constitution of 1946, the president and vice-president were elected by the
National Assembly. The 1994 amendments to the Constitution, known as the
Additional Articles, require direct popular election of the president and vicepresident. The presidential and vice-presidential candidates run as a single
ticket, and the ticket that attains a plurality of the popular vote is elected.
Although the ROC Constitution provides essentially for a parliamentary
form of government, the president has, for most of the past half a century,
exercised a great deal of power due to his control over the ruling Kuomintang
(Nationalist Party, KMT), which has always commanded a majority of seats
in the Legislative Yuan (Parliament) (Hsieh, 1993).
The KMT nominated Lee Teng-hui as its presidential candidate. Lee picked
Premier Lien Chan as his running mate. The major opposition party, the Democratic Progressive Party (DPP), after a two-stage primary, nominated Peng
Ming-min, a long- time political refugee residing overseas. His running mate
was Hsieh Chang-ting, a prominent DPP member of the Legislative Yuan.
Lin Yang-kang and Hau Pei-tsun, both of whom were KMT vice-chairmen,
bolted their party to run as an independent ticket. The fourth ticket in race
was Chen Li-an and Wang Ching-feng. Chen was a former member of the
KMT and president of the Control Yuan, an organ similar to the parliamentary
ombudsman in the Scandinavian countries. His running mate, Wang Chingfeng, a member of the Control Yuan, was the only female candidate in the
presidential race. The opposition New Party (NP), which split from the KMT
in 1993, did not formally nominate a candidate, but decided instead to endorse
the Lin- Hau ticket.
The election outcome was clear from the beginning of the campaign. President Lee was well ahead of his opponents according to the polls released by
[167 ]
386
Table 1. The result of the 1996 presidential
election
Party
Vote %
Lee Teng-hui
KMT
54.00
Peng Ming-rnin
DPP
21.13
Lin Yang-kang
Independent*
14.90
ChenLi-an
Independent
9.98
Candidate
*indicates endorsement by the New Party.
Source: China Times, 24 March 1996.
various organizations during the campaign. He ended up, as Table 1 shows,
with 54% of the valid vote, about 33 percentage points ahead of the second
vote-getter, DPP's Peng Ming-min.
3. Retrospective and prospective voting
Retrospective voting has gained widespread appeal as a simple yet powerful
explanation of voter choice. V.O. Key argued that voters are "rational gods
of vengeance and reward," who observe the performance of the incumbent
and "cast him out" if the incumbent's performance is poor. As va. Key,
Jr. claimed, "Voters may reject what they have known; or they may approve
what they have known. They are not likely to be attracted in great numbers by
promises of the novel or the unknown" (Key, 1966: 61). Rather than attempting to anticipate the consequences of various policy proposals, voters look at
past results. Elections, then, are plebiscites. Fiorina (1981) further develops
and tests the theory of retrospective voting in the United States. He finds
support for a theory of retrospection close to Key's. Voters appear to weigh
past outcomes heavily and to pay scant attention to policy prescriptions.
A very different theory of voting holds that voters look forward rather
than backward. Downs (1957) proposes a forward- looking theory of voting
that is grounded in, but not limited to, retrospective evaluations of the incumbent. While a pure retrospective voting theory such as Key's is rooted
in simple reward and punishment motives in voters, Downs argues that retrospective evaluations of candidates and parties become predictors of future
performance in office. In Downs's (1957: 49) terminology: "By comparing
the stream of utility income from government activity he has received under
the present government (adjusted for trends) with those streams he would
have received if the various opposition parties had been in office, the voter
finds ... his preference among the competing parties." Instead of evaluating
[168]
387
political candidates (or parties) based on their past performance, voters evaluate past policies in order to anticipate future policies. Downs attaches great
importance to retrospective voting, but, at its core, his thesis holds that voters
are investors maximizing future well-being.
Achen (1992) argues that voter rationality implies prospective rather than
retrospective voting. The inclusion and success of retrospective evaluations
in voting models is due to their correlation with other sources of candidate
evaluations. Retrospective evaluations are an instrumental and intermediate
step in voter evaluations of candidates, but they are not the ultimate decision
rule for voters. Achen, like Downs, believes that voters have the motivation
and information necessary to anticipate how different candidates or parties
will behave in office.
Theories of voting also disagree on whether voters care more about their
personal well-being or about national conditions. The theories of Key, Downs,
and Fiorina all suggest that a voter's ultimate concern is her own well-being.
Fiorina (1981) is a bit less restrictive in casting retrospective voting in purely
self-interested terms. He includes measures of voters' estimates of their own
condition and national conditions, finding that both are statistically significant as predictors ofthe vote. Kinder and Kiewiet (1981) and Kiewiet (1983)
argue that voters are sociotropic rather than self-interested, meaning that they
care more about the conditions of the national situation or of specific socioeconomic groups than about their own well-being. Different studies suggest
that different indicators of economic growth, unemployment, inflation and
personal income (Erikson, 1989, 1990; Fair, 1978, 1988; Hibbs, 1987; Tufte,
1978).
A prospective sociotropic voter evaluates the candidates by looking at
what they will do rather than what they have done, but, unlike prospective
personal voters, they care about national or regional conditions. MacKuen,
Erikson, and Stimson (1992) find empirical support for the idea that voters
are bankers (sophisticated and forward-looking) rather than peasants (uninformed and backward-looking). MacKuen, Erikson, and Stimson, unlike
Downs, believe that voters look at national conditions when evaluating the
prospects of different candidates. Their empirical model predicts changes
in presidential approval ratings based on fluctuations in inflation and unemployment and on retrospective and prospective evaluations of personal and
national conditions. Based on data from 1954 to 1988, they find that voter
expectations about national economic conditions are statistically significant
across several model specifications.
Lewis-Beck (1990) finds cross-national support for prospective voting.
His study of voting in Western Europe and the United States during the early
1980s reveals that "Economic voters in these nations do act retrospectively,
[169]
388
just as Key (and Downs) have described. However, they also respond to a
purely prospective component of economic evaluation" (p. 135).
Most of the studies on retrospective or prospective voting have focused on
national election in the United States and Western Europe. Only a few studies
have focused on a case such as Taiwan. Hwang (1994), in a study of Taiwan's
Legislative Yuan election, finds that economic conditions were not significant
to voter choice. However, Hsieh, Lacy, and Niou (1996) find that economic
conditions did matter in the Taipei mayor's race of 1995. Nevertheless, such
studies are rare, and the results are contradictory. The recent presidential election in Taiwan provides another opportunity to extend and refine the previous
findings.
In the case of Taiwan, one may suspect that economic voting may not
be significant since Taiwan's economic condition has been generally good
over the past several decades. For several decades, Taiwan's economy grew
at an annual rate of 8 to 9% on average, and the distribution of income and
wealth gradually improved. However economic growth has slowed recently
to an annual rate of about 6%, and even the distribution of income and wealth
has deteriorated to some extent. Given the recent changes in economic conditions, voters may have reason to disapprove of Lee Teng-hui's performance
as president.
The Election Study Center of National Chengchi University conducted
a nationwide face-to-face survey of 1396 respondents before and after the
election. The survey included questions to tap voter assessments of national
and personal economic conditions. One question that addresses retrospective
evaluations of the national economy condition is phrased as follows:
"Do you feel that the current economic condition of our whole society is
better or worse than one year ago, or stays the same?"
01. Much better 02. Better
03. About the same
04. Worse
05. Much worse 98. Don't know 95. Refuse to answer
A similar question asked voters to rate their personal finance over the past
year. Table 2 shows how respondents in Taiwan perceived national and personal economic performance over the previous year and anticipated economic
performance over the next year. Retrospective perceptions of the national
economy are quite pessimistic: about two thirds of respondents believe the
national economy worsened, 23% believe it stayed the same, and only slightly
more than one-tenth believe it got better. Retrospective evaluations of respondents' own economic well-being are much more concentrated: 28% of
respondents believe they were worse off, 61 % the same, and 12% better off.
Prospective evaluations reveal quite different patterns. The respondents are
very optimistic. On the national economy, only 18% of respondents believe
[170]
389
Table 2. Perceptions of the economy
Much
Worse
Same
Better
Much
N
better
worse
National
Last year
404
(31 )
467
(36)
297
(23)
114
(9)
21
(2)
1304
Personal
127
(9)
253
(19)
820
(61)
134
)10)
21
(2)
1355
33
(4)
124
(14)
302
(34)
402
(45)
33
(4)
894
12
(1)
78
(8)
516
320
(34)
31
(3)
956
(54)
Last year
National
Next year
Personal
Next year
Note. Cell entries are number of respondents, with row percentages
in parentheses. Row percentages may not sum to 100 due to rounding. Based upon survey conducted by the Election Study Center,
National Chengchi University.
the economy will get worse over the next year, 34% believe the economy will
stay the same, and nearly half of respondents believe the economy will get
better. Nine percent of respondents believe their own economic situation will
worsen, while 54% believe they will stay the same and 37% believe they will
be better off. The correlations among these variables are modest. The correlation between national prospective and national retrospective evaluations
is .24; between personal prospective and personal retrospective evaluations,
.37. The correlations between national prospective and personal retrospective is .34 while the correlation between national retrospective and personal
prospective is .34.
As Table 2 illustrates, there are obvious discrepancies among various types
of evaluations: people are more optimistic about the future than about the
past, and their evaluations of personal well-being are more concentrated than
their evaluations of the national economy. Moreover, the table reveals that
the number of people responding to questions regarding retrospective evaluations is much larger than the number offering prospective evaluations. Such
discrepancies are interesting and suggest a line of research into how people
form expectations of the economy. However, we do not pursue that here.
All these questions in the survey were asked before voters were asked about
their vote intentions, thus we do not expect that economic perceptions are
rationalizations about a person's choice of the incumbent or a challenger in
the election.
[ 171 ]
390
Voters may be concerned about issues other than the economy as they go to
the polls. National security is a paramount concern of Taiwanese voters due to
the threat from the Chinese Communists on the mainland. In the 1995 election
survey, two questions tap the status of the evaluations between Taiwan and the
mainland in the previous year and in the next year. The wordings are similar
to the previous questions concerning economic conditions.
Taiwanese voters also care about political and social stability. Four questions asked respondents to evaluate law and order in the previous year, law
and order in the next year, ethnic relations in the previous year, and ethnic
relations in the next year. These questions are all related to domestic stability,
and are certainly very important concerns for the voters in Taiwan.
Table 3 shows that, on the situations of cross-strait relations and law and
order, most people give quite negative responses to the past, but are generally
quite positive about the future. On cross-strait relations, more than threefifths of respondents believe the situation worsened in the previous year, 22%
believe it stayed the same, and only 16% believe it got better. This reflects
the tensions between Taiwan and the mainland prior to the election. On law
and order, 46% think that the situation was worse, 39% the same, and 15%
better. But when the respondents look to the future, their evaluations are
brighter. Only about 14% of respondents believe the cross-strait relations will
get worse, 29% believe the same, and 58% believe it will improve. On law
and order, 19% believe the situation will get worse in the future, 48% believe
the same, and one-third believe that it will get better. On ethnic relations the
respondents are generally optimistic. Retrospectively, only 14% of respondents think ethnic relations worsened, 48% believe relations remained the
same, and about 39% believe ethnic relations improved. Prospectively, only
5% believe the ethnic situation will get worse, 46% believe it will remain
the same, and nearly half believe that ethnic relations will improve. The correlations among these are modest. The highest correlation appears between
retrospective and prospective evaluations of ethnic relations (.69).
The relationship between retrospective evaluations and vote choice is
straightforward. If voters believe that economic, social, and political conditions worsened, they should vote against the incumbent, Lee Teng-hui. The
relationship between vote choice and prospective assessments of national
conditions is more complex. If voters believe that conditions will improve
during the next year, it is not clear for who they should vote, nor is it clear
why they expect conditions will improve. It is possible that a person who
believes conditions will improve does so because she believes Lee will win
reelection and that he will handle the national affairs capably. Another voter
may believe that national conditions will improve because she believes Lee
will be defeated.
[ 172]
391
Table 3. Perceptions of social and political situations
Much
Worse
Same
Better
worse
Much
N
better
Security
Last year
261
(24)
428
(39)
241
(22)
165
(15)
(I)
Law & order
196
(16)
379
(30)
499
(39)
177
(14)
(I)
32
(3)
124
550
(48)
372
(33)
65
(6)
1144
(11)
30
(4)
79
(10)
243
448
(54)
36
(4)
837
(29)
49
(6)
107
(13)
391
(48)
253
14
(2)
814
(31 )
20
(2)
33
(3)
446
(46)
408
(42)
72
(7)
979
Last year
Ethnic reI.
Last year
Security
Next year
Law & order
Next year
Ethnic reI.
Next year
16
17
1109
1269
Note. Cell entries are number of respondents, with row percentages in
parentheses. Row percentages may not sum to 100 due to rounding.
Based upon survey conducted by the Election Study Center, National
Chengchi University.
Prospective evaluations should be candidate-specific. That is, voters should
attach to each candidate an assessment of how well that candidate will perform in office. To tap prospective evaluations of the candidates, the National
Chengchi University Election Study asked voters which candidate or candidates would best handle the economy, law and order, ethnic relations, and
straits relations. Table 4 presents the percentage of respondents who believe
that each of the candidates is best able to handle each of the issues.
Lee dominates all other candidates in voters' assessments of his ability
to manage national affairs. Lee's strongest issue is the economy, followed
by relations with the mainland, public safety, and ethnic relations. Chen and
Peng earn their highest marks on ethnic relations; Lin, on public safety. The
low marks earned by the three challenges underscores a classic problem for
political challengers in one-party regimes or even competitive democracies:
until a person has held office, voters have little to evaluate.
4. The model and results
The purpose of this paper is to assess the beliefs related to vote choice. Particularly, we are interested in whether voters vote retrospectively or prospec-
[173 ]
392
Table 4. Percentage of voters who rate each candidate as
best able to manage issues
Issue
Economy
Ethnic relations
Public safety
Straits
Lee
70
Chen
2
Peng
Lin
4
3
N
1003
41
14
7
5
5
6
11
1003
48
51
8
3
7
1003
1003
Note. Entries are row percentages. Entries may not sum
to 100% since some respondents mentioned multiple candidates or no candidates as best able to handle each
issue.
tively. The dependent variables in our formulation will be vote choice in the
1996 Taiwan presidential election as reported by survey respondents. The
dependent variable has four unordered possibilities: vote for Lee, for Peng,
for Lin, and for Chen. We use multinomiallogit to estimate the model, normalizing coefficients for Lee at zero. All other coefficients from the model
are interpreted as the impact of that variable on vote choice, relative to a vote
for Lee.
Independent variables include party identification and evaluations of the
economy, public safety, ethnic relations, and cross-straits relations during the
past year. To determine the extent of prospective voting, we turn to questions
that ask voters which candidate would most capably handle each of four issue
areas: the economy, public safety, ethnic relations, and relations across the
straits. Respondents could list anyone candidate or combinations of two,
three, or four candidates as well as answering that none of the candidates
could capably handle an issue. We code a dummy variable for each candidate
on each issue. The dummy variable takes a value of (l) if a voter believes
that the candidate can handle the issue better than any other candidate. The
excluded category of response on each issue includes voters who believe
that combinations of two, three, all, or no candidates could capably handle the issue. We include party identification in our model, formulated as
three dummy variables, KMT, DPP, and NP, indicating which party a voter
generally supports. Table 5 present the results.
Partisanship is statistically significant as an explanation of voter choice.
KMT supporters are less likely to support candidates other than incumbent
President Lee Teng-hui; the DPP supporters are more likely to support Peng
Ming-min; and the NP supporters are more likely to support Lin Yang-kang.
But even after taking into consideration voters' party identification, retrospective and prospective evaluations of the economy, security, ethnic rela-
[174]
393
tions, and straits relations appear statistically significant as predictors of voter
choice.
Surprisingly, retrospective evaluations of the economy, both national and
personal, are not statistically significant, except that people who believe the
national economy improved during the last year are more likely to vote for
Lin than Lee. One explanation of this result may be that voters who believe
the economy improved during the last year are more willing to risk a vote for
Lin, who campaigned primarily on non-economic issues. Prospective evaluations of Lee's ability to handle the economy are statistically significant in the
comparison of Lee with each of the other candidates. The evidence suggests
that to the extent that voters vote economically, they rely more on prospective
evaluations than retrospective evaluations. Prospective evaluations are likely
a function of retrospective evaluations, but our results suggest that beliefs
about a candidate's future performance are more closely related to vote choice
than beliefs about past performance.
Retrospective evaluations of ethnic relations, straits relations, and public
safety are not statistically significant as explanations of the vote. However, the
prospective, candidate-specific versions of these issues are significant. People
who believe that Peng Ming-min is most able to handle ethnic relations and
straits relations are more likely to choose him over Lee. Chen draws support
from voters who believe he is best able to handle ethnic problems, and Lin
gets the votes of voters who believe he is capable of dealing with straits relations and ethnic problems. Lee appears to draw his support from prospective
evaluations of his ability to handle the economy and public safety. Prospective
evaluations of candidates' abilities to handle various problems may present
an endogeneity problem. That is, voters who vote for Lee may be rationalize
doing so by responding that he is best able to handle the economy, ethnic
relations, straits relations, and public safety. We believe this cannot explain
our findings in Table 5 for several reasons. First, we asked voters to evaluate
the candidates on each issue before asking them their vote. In doing so, we
intended to minimize the extent to which voters would say the candidate
they voted for would be best able to handle each of the issues. Second, if
prospective evaluations are rationalizations, then one should expect to find
that all prospective evaluations of the candidates are statistically significant.
If a voter rationalizes voting for Lee by claiming he is best able to manage
the economy, then why should she not also claim he is best able to handle
public safety, ethnic relations, and straits relations? The simple fact that only
a few prospective evaluations are statistically significant leads us to believe
that voters are not automatically claiming that the candidate they voted for is
best able to handle each of the issues. Finally, if prospective evaluations of
various issues are rationalizations of the vote, then should not retrospective
[ 175]
394
evaluations of the economy be rationalizations as well? If a voter claims that
Lee is best able to handle the economy simply because she voted for him, then
she should also have reason to claim that the economy has not worsened over
the past year. In short, voters appear not to simply rationalize their vote by
claiming that the candidate they voted for is best able to handle all relevant
issues. The prospective variables in our model suggest that voters choose a
candidate based on how well thev expect that candidate to handle important
issues.
A surprising finding to emerge from Table 5 is that non- security issues appear at least as important as cross-straits relations. Before and after the election, commentators argued that security concerns dominated the presidential
campaign, overshadowing almost all other issues. One plausible explanation
is that voters' concerns about cross-strait relations had been "absorbed" by
other factors such as economic concerns and party identification. Voters'
evaluations of the cross-strait relations, particularly retrospective evaluations
of the situation, are closely related to vote choice. Table 6 shows voters' retrospective evaluation of the cross-strait relations and their votes. President
Lee fared better among voters who believed the situation had stayed the
same or become better in the previous year than among those who thought
it worsened. Other candidates found relatively more support from voters who
believed the situation across the straits had worsened.
The relationship between prospective evaluations of the straits and vote
choice is less clear-cut. Table 7 shows how voters voted according to their
prospective evaluations of relations with mainland China. Only Lin acquired
more support from voters who thought the situation would get worse in the
next year. No clear pattern emerges for other candidates.
On balance, prospective evaluations of the candidates' abilities to solve
various social, political, and economic problems appear to better explain the
vote than retrospective evaluations. Retrospective evaluations of the economy
carry little weight as a predictor of voter choice, except to the extent that
prospective evaluations of Lee's ability to handle the economy stem from his
past performance. This seems unlikely, however, since Table 2 shows that
most voters believe the economy worsened during the year preceding the
election, yet most voters voted for Lee.
The results reported in Table 5 support Achen's (1992) contention that
rational voters vote prospectively rather than retrospectively. At least in Taiwan's first popular presidential election, voters appear to look forward rather
than backward. For elections in other countries, the findings presented here
suggests that economic conditions matter even in such a country as the ROC
on Taiwan where economic performance has been generally good by international standards. Taiwan is not the first place one would expect to find
[176]
395
Table 5. Multinomiallogit estimates of vote choice
Candidates
Independent
variable
Constant
KMT
DPP
Chen.Peng
Lin.
Coefficient
Coefficient
Coefficient
(S.E.)
(S.E.)
(S.E.)
-2.57
(1.66)
-2.05**
(0.52)
-1.61 **
(0.80)
NP
1.65**
(0.64)
Nat. econ.
0.10
(0.23)
Last year
Pers. econ.
Last year
Safety
Last year
Ethnic ReI.
Last year
Straits
Last year
Lee
-1.40
(1.55)
-3.96**
(1.07)
2.60**
(0.45)
-0.14
(0.28)
-0.56
(1.25)
-0.06
(0.23)
0.28
(0.24)
0.26
(0.23)
-0.11
(0.22)
-0.38
(0.24)
0.39**
(0.20)
-1.29**
-0.33
(0.24)
0.30
(0.19)
-1.92**
(0.59)
-5.36**
(1.83)
-1.26**
(0.56)
-1.80
(1.16)
3.04**
(0.64)
0.67**
(0.28)
-0.12
(0.30)
0.32
(0.24)
-0.15
(0.26)
-0.00
(0.22)
-1.77**
(0.57)
-0.62
( 1.12)
0.03
( 1.27)
-0.63
(l.48)
0.10
(0.76)
-0.33
( 1.01)
-0.12
(1.43)
-1.12
(1.79)
0.69
(0.55)
2.06*
(1.14)
3.74**
(0.84)
-0.86
(1.96)
3.28**
(0.66)
1.66**
(0.82)
2.26**
(0.89)
Lee
1.63*
(0.91)
-0.47
1.29**
(0.63)
-2.39*
(1.40)
-1.40**
Safety
(0.57)
(0.56)
Economy
Peng
Economy
Chen
Economy
Lin
Economy
Lee
Ethnic relations
Peng
Ethnic relations
Chen
Ethnic relations
Lin
Ethnic relations
(0.66)
-2.49
(1.61)
0.25
( 1.33)
-0.00
(1.12)
0.89
(0.80)
-1.30*
(0.72)
[177 ]
396
Table 5. Continued.
Candidates
Independent
variable
Chen.Peng
Lin.
Coefficient
Coefficient
Coefficient
(S.E.)
(S.E.)
(S.E.)
Peng
-10.34
-1.17
-10.46
Safety
(11S.04)
(0.83)
(108.S7)
Chen
--0.06
-1.84**
--0.68
(0.91)
Safety
(0.7S)
(0.92)
Lin
--0.71
-1.06
0.17
Safety
(U.67)
(0.77)
(0.72)
Lee
--0.47
Straits
(0.S8)
Peng
-9.66
Straits
(136.24)
0.9S**
(0.S4)
2.S2**
(1.30)
Chen
0.63
0.14
(0.74)
Straits
(0.6S)
Lin
--0.13
0.76
Straits
(0.81)
(0.88)
1.07
(0.79)
4.4S**
(1.92)
I.S2*
(0.90)
2.38**
(0.93)
Coefficients for Lee normalized at zero.
Log likelihood: -270.18.
Number of observations: 662
Percent correctly predicted: 8S.0S
Predicted vote shares: Lee 64.8%, Chen: 8.3%, Peng 16.2%, Lin 10.7%.
Actual vote shares: Lee 64.8%, Chen 8.3%, Peng 16.2%, Lin 10.7%.
* indicates statistical significance at p < .10, two- tailed.
** indicates statistical significance at p < .OS, two- tailed.
widespread economic voting. Yet the economy did matter. The results here
also confirm the most recent wave of work demonstrating that prospective
evaluations mean at least as much to voters as retrospective evaluations of the
economy (MacKuen, Erikson, and Stimson, 1992; Lewis-Beck, 1990). Voters
are not merely rational gods of vengeance and reward, as V.O. Key described
them. Instead, voters form expectations of how political candidates will shape
future economic performance.
[178]
397
Table 6. Retrospective evaluation of cross-strait relations and the vote
Evaluation
Vote
N
Chen
Lee
Peng
Lin
19
38
(22)
29
(17)
175
(I I)
89
(51)
Worse
37
(12)
198
(63)
47
(15)
30
(10)
312
Same
7
(4)
125
(76)
22
(13)
10
(6)
164
Better
5
(4)
91
(72)
15
(12)
16
127
(13)
1
(8)
10
(77)
1
(8)
1
(8)
Much worse
Much better
13
Note. Cell entries are number of respondents, with
row percentages in parentheses. Row percentages may
not sum to 100 due to rounding. Based upon survey conducted by the Election Study Center, National
Chengchi University.
Table 7. Prospective evaluation of cross-strait relations
and the vote
Evaluation
Vote
N
Chen
Lee
Peng
Lin
Much worse
2
(10)
13
(62)
2
(10)
4
(19)
21
Worse
8
(13)
31
(50)
15
(24)
8
(13)
62
Same
18
(10)
104
(60)
33
(19)
17
(10)
172
Better
23
(7)
226
(67)
51
(15)
35
(10)
335
Much better
1
(4)
16
4
4
25
(64)
(16)
(16)
Note. Cell entries are number of respondents, with
row percentages in parentheses. Row percentages may
not sum to 100 due to rounding. Based upon survey conducted by the Election Study Center, National
Chengchi University.
[179]
398
5. Conclusion
The results presented in this paper carry important implications for elections
in Taiwan and for the body of theory in political science that relates election
outcomes to retrospective or prospective voting. For Taiwanese elections,
these results suggest that the economy is an important factor affecting the
vote. Voters evaluate the economic performance and promise of competing
candidates. Security concerns are important to Taiwanese voters, but they
are not predominant. Public safety and ethnic relations are also important
issues, but only to the extent that candidates can credibly commit to future
improvements rather than campaigning on past success.
The results from Taiwan's first popular presidential election also serve as
an important test case for theories of retrospective voting. Taiwan is the ideal
case to evaluate retrospective voting since one party, the KMT, has been in
power for decades, controlling both the executive and legislative branches
of government, and since the incumbent candidate has been in power long
enough for voters to evaluate his performance. Retrospective voting appears
overshadowed by prospective voting, even in Taiwan. In other countries where
government is divided between competing parties or where the incumbent
executive has been in power only a short time, it is likely that voters will find
retrospective clues less helpful when choosing among candidates.
References
Achen, C.H. (1992). Social psychology, demographic variables, and linear regression: Breaking the iron triangle in voting research. Political Behavior 14: 195-211.
Campbell, A., Converse, P.E., Miller, W.E. and Stokes, D.E. (1960). The American voter. New
York: Wiley.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper and Row.
Erikson, R.S. (1990). Economic conditions and the congressional vote: A review of the
macrolevel evidence. American Journal of Political Science 34: 373-399.
Erikson, R. (1989). Economic conditions and the presidential vote. American Political Science
Review 83: 567-576.
Fair, R.c. (1988). The effects of economic events on votes for the President: A 1984 update.
Political Behavior 10: 168-179.
Fair, R.c. (1978). The effect of economic events on votes for President. Review of Economics
and Statistics 60: 159- 173.
Fiorina, M.P. (1981). Retrospective voting in American national elections. New Haven: Yale
University Press.
Fiorina, M.P. (1992). Divided government. New York: Macmillan.
Hibbs, D.A., Jr. (1987). The American political economy. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Hsieh, J.E-s. (1993). Parliamentarism vs. presidentialism: Constitutional choice in the
Republic of China on Taiwan. Chinese Political Science Review 21: 173-202.
[180 ]
399
Hsieh, J.E-s., Lacy, D. and Niou, E.M.S. (1996). Economic voting in the 1994 Taiwan
elections. American Asian Review 14: 51-70.
Hwang, S.-D. (1994). Economic conditions and voters' choices (in Chinese). Soochow Journal
of Political Science 3: 97-123.
Jacobson, G. (1990). The electoral origins of divided government. San Francisco: Westview
Press.
Key, V.O., Jr. (1966). The responsible electorate. Harvard University Press.
Kiewiet, D.R. (1983). Macroeconomic and micropolitics. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Kinder, D.R. and Kiewiet, R.D. (1981). Sociotropic politics: The American case. British
Journal of Political Science 11: 129-161.
Lewis-Beck, M.S. (1990). Economics and elections. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
MacKuen, M.B., Erikson, R.S. and Stimson, J.A. (1992). Peasants or bankers: The American
Electorate and the U.S. economy. American Political Science Review 86: 597--611. Tufte,
E.R. (1978). Political control of the economy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[ 181 ]
Public Choice 97: 401-428, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
401
Ideology and the construction of nationality: The Canadian
elections of 1993 *
MELVIN J. HINICH1, MICHAEL C. MUNGER2 & SCOTT DE MARCHI3
1Department of Government, University of Texas-Austin, Austin, TX 78712, USA; e-mail:
hinich@mail.la.utexas.edu; 2Department of Political Science, Duke University, Durham, NC
27708, USA; e-mail: munger@acpub.duke.edu; 3Department of Political Science,
Washington University, St. Louis, MO 63130, U.S.A.
Abstract. Canada is one nation, but it is in many ways two communities, one Francophone and the other Anglophone. We employ a formal model of "ideology" and analyze how
nationality is constructed in people's minds. The magnitude of the changes in expressed "preferences" in terms of ideology depends on the salience of the new issue, the extent to which
it confirms with the existing ideological cleavage, and the difference between the perceived
status quo on the new dimension and the voter's most preferred alternative. Using data from
the 1993 Canadian National Election Study, we consider the relative importance of different
policy dimensions in explaining voting decisions among educated Canadians. The issue of
Quebec sovereignty, alone, is shown to have significant power for predicting vote choice.
A plausible explanation, confirmed here by regression analysis, is that Quebec sovereignty
"stands" for other issues in voters' conception of Canadian politics.
1. Introduction
In 1967, French president Charles de Gaulle appeared on a balcony of Montreal's City Hall, at the height of Expo '67. General de Gaulle always ended
his addresses with a series of vivats, crowd p1easers like "Vive fa Canada", or
"Vive la France". That day, whether out of plan or passion, he said something
astonishing: "Vive Ie Quebec Libre" (Thompson, 1988: xi).
The sentiment itself, widely heard in Montreal, was unremarkable. What
angered the Canadian government, delighted the audience, and surprised the
* Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the annual meetings of the Public Choice
Society, April 12-14, 1996, Houston, TX. Seminar participants at Duke University, George
Washington University, George Mason University, Princeton University, University of Kentucky, and University of North Carolina all helped clarify the ideas contained herein. Finally,
specific comments by John Aldrich, John Brehm, Dennis Coates, Paul Gronke, William Keech,
Peter Lange, Mark Peffley, George Rabinowitz, Lee Sigelman, Genia Toma, Mark Toma, and
Peter VanDoren were particularly useful. Error are ours, however.
[183]
402
world was de Gaulle's call for the secession of a province (i.e., for a "free
Quebec") from a nation as part of a state visit. Why is the split between
French and British Canada so powerful, and so central to Canadian politics,
that even foreign leaders exploit the division?
In this paper, we advance a model of political dimensions, and dynamic
conflict, with an eye toward explaining some of the events in Canada. The
particular election we will analyze was the 1993 Canadian national elections.
The deep political divisions in Canada, however, predate the 1993 election,
and in fact predate de Gaulle's outburst, by a century. However, it was always
a federation "in which the provinces were expected to be little more than
glorified local governments" (Kornberg, 1988: 13).
The North America Act created a nation, but it has failed to create a
community, as we will argue below. The following section describes the
theoretical basis for the importance of "community" in the study of the construction of nationality. The key conception of community for our purposes, is
the work by Taylor (1976) and by Schofield (1985) on satisfying the requirements for common knowledge in achieving cooperation. Section 3 presents
our model of "ideology", which we argue is the repository of culture and
community in a society. Section 4 considers the application of the logic of
this model to the Canadian national election of 1993, using survey data from
the Canadian National Election Study.
2. Conceptions of "nationality"
In his controversial book, Alien nation, Brimelow (1995) defines a geographic
and political entity (the nation-state) as having an ethnic basis. Ethnicity
is much more restrictive than "culture", an elastic and encompassing concept that requires only a variety of shared experiences or symbols. Brimelow
(1995: 203) is quite explicit:
Let's start with a definition. What is a "nation-state"? It is the political
expression of a nation. And what is a "nation"? It is an ethno-cultural
community - an interlacing of ethnicity and culture. Invariably, it speaks
one language (emphasis in original).
Moynihan (1993: I) is no more equivocal: A nation is "a group of people who
believe they are ancestrally related. It is the largest grouping that shares that
belief".
Why equate nationality with ethnicity and language? Because functioning
nations are communities, with shared experiences and beliefs. If we think of
nations as large "communities", identity becomes fundamental. A community is not a collection of individuals, but a coherent organism made up of
[ 184 ]
403
individuals who think they belong. Achieving cooperative "best" solutions is
still a problem in such a setting, but it is an easier problem.
Taylor (1976, 1982) defines "community" as having three elements: First,
members share beliefs in norms, and have similar preferences. Second, people in a functioning community have direct, complex relations with one another, and expect these relations to continue indefinitely. Third, obligations
are viewed as reciprocal, so that all members of a community "owe" one
another respect or the promise of aid in a crisis.
Schofield (1985: 218) makes a compelling theoretical argument for why
communities matter: "The fundamental theoretical problem underlying the
question of cooperation is the manner by which individuals attain knowledge
of each others' preferences and likely behavior". Now, "attain" seems an odd
word; why not "obtain"? However, people cannot always obtain more information, in an asymmetric information setting. Rather, reliable information
about preferences and expectations is much like the technical condition of
common knowledge in game theory, requiring members attain an equilibrium
level of information about each other, through shared experiences, norms,
and reciprocal commitments. Community is a knife-edge, perhaps ephemeral,
condition: information is either common (in a community), or asymmetric (in
any other social context).
Taylor, of course, argued that communities must be small, and that large
nations could rarely meet his conditions. Schofield is more optimistic: nations
may in fact be able to solve the common knowledge problem on a scale
larger than Taylor's "communities". The problem is that the solutions are
fragile. Differences in language, customs, and political iconography strain the
common knowledge basis of cooperation, and crack the information nexus.
Hinich and Munger (1994) draw together several strands of thought on
the way people's political beliefs are structured, and how those beliefs do
not evolve in an incremental or continuous fashion. The key theoretical concept for Hinich and Munger is "ideology", or set of intellectual organizing
principles reflected in widely shared beliefs. As we shall see in the next
section, Hinich and Munger claim that ideologies are the means nations use
for communicating about political conflict. However, these conflicts may also
end communication, and cause cleavages among groups within a geographic
political jurisdiction, tearing nations apart. These centrifugal pressures derive from fault lines in communities, and the common knowledge basis of
cooperation in the formation of beliefs about other groups of citizens.
[ 185]
404
3. Ideology: An overview of a dynamic process
The advantage of a dynamic approach to spatial modeling based on ideology
is that it is possible to generate realistic predictions about change even if
voters' preferences about specific issues are fixed. There is no claim that new
issues are the only source of dynamic changes in political systems. What we
will argue is that the changes we have seen in Canadian politics over time,
and the tensions over national identity in Canada today, can be represented as
ideological conflict.
In adressing stability and change in a macropolitical context, we build on
a growing tradition of thought on dynamic processes. Intellectually, this view
derives from Riker's (1982, 1986, 1990) "heresthetics". Aldrich (1983, 1995)
explores the implications of placing party "activists" in the strategic role of
choosing which "new" issues to emphasize. Lupia (1992) considers the role
of information and attention in determining the agenda. Jones (1994) argues
that there may not be very many distinct "issues" at all. Instead, people apply
different, relatively stable, frames to problems over time. Dynamic change
then results from reframing of the problem, not from a change in fundamental
preferences. Poole and Rosenthal (1997) culminates a long series of papers
offering a powerful technique for measuring the dimensions of conflict in
the U.S. potential system, and examining how those dimensions change over
time.
In this section, we outline a view of new issues, and change, developed at
greater length in Hinich and Munger (1994, 1997). Because of the structure
our notion of ideology imposes on political competition, it is possible to
derive specific results on the introduction of new issues. Later, in applying
this model to the study of Canadian politics in the 1993 national election, we
will claim that fundamental changes in the partisan control can result from
strategic action by elites, holding voter preferences constant.
3.1. Specifying context: Ideology
The basic theoretical claim of the ideology model is that political debate in a
stable system has no more than two or three dimensions, although the "policy
space" seems complex. Ideology may be defined either as (a) a set of ideas
with implications for "good" policy, or (b) a widely shared belief system.'
Neither of these notions requires internal consistency among ideas or beliefs.
Instead, an ideology provides a means to organize political thinking, and to
let people understand each other.
Ideology exists, because issue positions cluster. If we know what you think
on defense policy, abortion rights, and environmental policy, we can guess
(with a small error) what you think of school lunch subsidies. Further, this
[186]
405
clustering phenomenon is not atomistic, so that ideological positions such as
"liberal" and "conservative" have similar meanings to different people.
If the understanding of clusters of issues is shared, we will call this clustering phenomenon "ideology". Ideology sharply constrains the strategies of
candidates (and hence the choices for voters) in the policy space are constrained. Poole and Rosenthal (1997: 12) note: "The basic implication of
the constraint hypothesis is that all issues tend to be mapped onto a fixed
ordering, or placement, of legislators". Our name, of course, for the "fixed
ordering" that organizes political conflict is ideology.
3.2. New issues and the ideology model: "Normal change"
The ideology model has been developed by Hinich and Pollard (1981), Enelow
and Hinich (1984), and Hinich and Munger (1994, 1997).2 We will give only
a summary of the model here. Let us begin by fixing notation.
Xik
The ideal point of voter i on policy k, i
E
{l, ... , n}, k
E
{l, ... , m}.
Policy position on the issue k.
\!k
The weight, or ideological translation term, for issue k.
bk
Status quo policy for issue k.
7rp
Ideological position of candidate p. For simplicity, we will
assume the ideological space is one-dimensional.
Zi
Induced ideal point of voter i in ideological space.
Ai
mxm matrix of weights, describing salience and complementarity of issues in the ith voter's utility function.
n
n-dimensional policy space, where "dimensions" come from
the set of existing, widely discussed issues. The set of possible
issues is, of course, infinite.
Voters have preferences over "issues", a n-dimensional space. Each voter
i, with ideal point Xi in the policy space n, chooses between two candidates
(Alpha and Beta) based on their imputed platforms tWa, w,B} in n. 3 We will
assume that the choice is based on a quadratic utility function, and for notation use [] to represent simple Euclidean Distance calculated from vector
differences:
Wk
(la)
(lb)
[ 187]
406
But the imputed platforms Wa and wp have to come from somewhere. What
is the source of voters' beliefthat these positions represent the likely policies
of Alpha and Beta if elected?
Our claim is that, though voters may have preferences defined over the
n-dimensional policy space n, political competition takes place in the pdimensional ideological space <1>, where p
n. Consequently, the choices
offered the voter (at least, the choices voters can identify, and candidates can
commit to) are constrained by ideology. The correspondence, or mapping,
from the ideological to policy spaces can be expressed as a linear function of
the various ideological dimensions. Though the model can handle multiple
dimensions (see Hinich and Munger, 1994), assume p = 1 for simplicity. The
imputed platform (for candidate Alpha, for example) can then be written:
«
(2)
The (n x 1) b vector is the set of status quo policies. The (n x 1) v is the
set of mappings from the ideological space to policy space. The ideological
position of each candidate is drawn from the set of feasible positions (that is,
Jrj E n, where in this case Jrj is scalar).4
The elements of v reflect the beliefs of voters that the prevailing ideology
has implications for policies. For example, if Vk is large (either positive or
negative), the voter believes abstract ideological statements are highly meaningful for policy k. Conversely, if Vk is near zero in absolute value, the issue
is not accounted for by the ideology of the prevailing party system. This does
not mean voters don't care about the issue. Instead, if Vk = 0, issue k is
outside the issues voters associate with the orthodox political debate they
hear from parties and candidates.
We are now in a position to consider the policy space n, which contains the voter ideal points. Suppose we allow voter i to have ideal point
Xi = (WI, (2), and be faced with the choice between two candidates ex and
f3 based on their platforms, Jra and Jrp, in the ideological space n. Let preferences around Xi be described by separable ellipsoidal, rather than circular,
indifference curves. The correspondence between the policy space n and the
ideological dimension n, given by equation (2) above, can then be depicted
in the graph in Figure 1. The feasible positions in n are constrained to appear
on the space n, with the status quo point in the policy space represented by
b = (b l , b 2 ) and the status quo ideological position being b + JrOV.
The induced ideal point on the b + JrV line is b + ZiV, the point tangent
to the highest feasible indifference curve. The corresponding ideal point in n
is Zi. The voter would prefer Xi, of course, but such a position is not feasible
for politicians to take given the prevailing ideological cleavage in the society.
The choice is between the partisans of the right, who favor Issue I, and the
[188]
407
Issue 2
,.
b+1tV
"'" ..;;,; ---b+ 1t av
: """/
I
I
Induce~
:
: Ideal Point
I
I
b+z. v
I
Status Quo Point
b+1[ov=(~'
""'1/
-~',
Is)
b+1t
Issue 1
:
V'l"1111
P
II11I1I1
Figure 1.
partisans of the left, who favor Issue 2.5 Consequently, in Figure voter i
chooses candidate ex over {J, because lTOi is closer (in weighted Euclidean
space) than IT fl to Xj.
We will find it useful to define more formally the induced ideal point (denoted b + Zj v in Figures 1) of voter i on the ideological dimension. Assuming,
for the sake of simplicity,6 separable preferences and equal issue salience
(i.e. circular, rather than elliptical, indifference curves). Enelow and Hinich
(1984) show that the ideal point (in an m-dimensional policy space) of a voter
presented with only those choices associated with existing parties, located
along a single ideological dimension, is:
Zi
=
L~l
Vk (Xik 2
L..k=l v k
"m
bik )
(4)
That is, the voter's induced ideal point on the ideological dimension is a
weighted sum of the differences between the voter's ideal point x and the
status quo policy vector b. The weights are a function of the ratio of the
ideological mapping terms Vk to the sum of squares of the weights on all
issues. The expression in Equation (4) is a simple model of voter choice:
Choose the candidate whose ideological position is closest to the induced
ideal point Zj on n.
We can express the induced ideological ideal point Zj under the more realistic assumption of different salience weights. This requires the addition of
an idiosyncratic (indexed by voter) matrix Ai of preference weights. Under
these circumstances, we can define Zj as follows:
Zj
=
VTA(x - b)
(5)
where v, x, and b are column vectors.
[ 189]
408
As Hinich and Munger (1997) show, it is possible to derive explicit direction and magnitude predictions for the change in the ideological ideal
point Zj resulting from a focus on a "new" issue WJc+l' Intuitively, the content
of these predictions can be summarized as involving the mapping terms v,
the preference matrix A j , and the perceived position of the status quo bk +1
compared to the voter's ideal point Xk+l'
• Mapping terms. Somewhat surprisingly, the larger the ideological mapping Vm+l, the smaller is the change in Zj. In fact, as Vm+l grows large,
the change in ideology vanishes completely.7 A moment's reflection
confirms the intuition behind this result, however: if the new issue is
well accounted for by, and tightly linked to, the old ideology, it does not
cause the voter to rethink his ideological position.
• Utility weights. The larger the salience ofthe new issue (am +l) compared
to those of the old issues, the larger the change in the voter's induced
ideological ideal point. In other words, if the "new" issue is important
enough, it dominates all the other issues and itself becomes the entire
ideological dimension. As we will see, there is some evidence that this
is exactly what is happening, or happens from time to time, in Quebec.
If, instead, the voter attaches no weight to the issue, then of course it
does not change his ideological identification.
• Status quo. The larger the difference between the voter ideal point and
the status quo on the new issue, the larger the change of the voter's
ideology. Notice that this has nothing to do with underlying preferences,
which have been fixed, though latent, all along. Rather, the set of issues
that make up the political world, and the ideology that organizes the
information in that world, are transformed by the introduction of the
new issue.
3.2.l. The analytics of normal change
Because Zj is induced on the ideological dimension by the preferences of
voter i in the n-dimensional policy space n, it is possible to dispense with
the presentation of n and represent voter choices solely on n, the ideological
dimension itself. Figure 2 depicts an arbitrarily drawn example of the ideological dimension, with far left and far right positions. The voter's ideal Zj is
drawn as before; the comparison for the voter is against rra and rrf3. Whichever
candidate is closer to Zj will receive i's vote.
As Figure 2 also shows, changes in Zj can change i's vote. In our example,
i votes for {J, given the original Zj. But suppose that a new issue is introduced.
The change in Z can be in either direction, depending on the relative values
of xm+ 1 and bm+1. The magnitude of the change will depend on the weight
(am+l,m+l) of the new issue in the voter's utility function, and the mapping
[190 ]
409
z. to z.': Unsuccessful New Issue
z'; to z ,\': Successful New Issue
(MIDPOINT)
Figure 2.
(Vm+l) of the policy onto the ideological dimension. In Figure 2, we have
drawn z; and z;" as examples of possible changes in z caused by the strategic
introduction of a new issue. As is clear from the figure, the change from Zj
to does not change the vote; the change from Zj to Zj" causes the voter to
switch from candidate Beta to Alpha. Candidate Alpha, by introducing a new
issue matching the particular parameters needed to change voters' minds, has
won the election.
This completes our discussion of the introduction of new issues when
the prevailing party system and associated ideological cleavage accounts for
the new issue. In the next section, we consider the implications of new issues when the new issue changes the dimensionality of the space of political
debate itself.
z;
3.2.2. New issues and the :,pace of political competition: Realignment
The preceding section addressed new issues that "fit" the prevailing context,
or the ideological frame of reference. To understand larger issues, particularly
the nature of nationhood, it is necessary to think more fundamentally. The
consideration of the strategic addition of new issues may make the political system unstable. What are the implications for political strategy of such
divisive, and potentially destructive, "new issues'''?
As is well known, majority rule election processes always have a determinate Condorcet winner at the ideal point of the median voter, provided
the relevant strategy set is one-dimensional and voter preferences are singlepeaked. While one might quarrel with the assumption of single-peakedness,
the obvious problem lies with the assumption of unidimensionality, particularly when we allow for strategic introduction of new dimensions. McKelvey
(1976) showed that if the core of the election game is empty, and voting is
sincere, then it is possible to choose an agenda (sequence of pairwise votes)
that lead to virtually any outcome in the policy space.
[ 191 ]
410
If a party out of power, or a cross-cutting coalition of disgruntled members, successfully introduce a new issue, the specter of chaos is raised. Those
advantaged by the status quo will try to use the institutions of the legislature
to defend stability, of course. Still, institutions cannot generically solve the
problem of conflict over dimensionality for very long without (nearly) universal agreement. Riker's (1982) example of the U.S. Civil war makes this
point very clearly. By raising the issue of slavery, the coalition that became
the Republicans after 1854 managed to annihilate the dimensions of the previously (fairly) stable political space. It wasn't clear they would "win" as a
result, but they did ensure that if they lost it would be in a different game.
The problem was not so much that there was a new issue, because this
happens all the time. Rather, chaos arose because the new issue could not be
handled within the existing ideological framework. Thus, slavery effectively
raised the dimensionality not just of politics, but of the strategy space.
Poole and Rosenthal (1993) claim that only a fundamental change in the
primary dimension of the ideological space is a "realignment". Thus, realignments should not be confused with temporary circumstances when a
"new" (for Poole and Rosenthal, second) dimension is added to the ideological space. Politics will look different (more chaotic) when there are two
dimensions, but the original fundamental cleavage will return unless there is a
realignment. The process of realignment when there is a genuinely new issue
can then be summarized as follows:
[W]ell before a realignment, congressional voting should be stable and
organized around the cleavage of the last realignment ... This means that
the policy space is stable - the same dimension(s) account for voting
over time, and legislator ideal points should show little change from
Congress to Congress. A new issue then emerges that splits the political
parties internally and begins the process of polarization. This can be
modeled as a new dimension, orthogonal to the stable set from the last
realignment, across which both parties become increasingly polarized.
We should see this polarization take place in two ways ... newly elected
representatives from the same party should take relatively polarized positions on the new dimension ... [Incumbents] should exhibit movement
that, relative to their earlier positions, resulted in polarization. As the
process continues, more and more of the voting is concerned with the
new issue, so that the old, stable set begins to wither away (Poole and
Rosenthal, 1993: 16).
To summarize: the ideological linkages between the new issue and all
other issues supplant the old linkages, which supported the old ideology. Not
all the roll calls are "about" the new issue, of course. Instead, as other matters
[192 ]
411
increasingly link to the new main cleavage, the symbolic relations of other
issues to the main cleavage increasingly become the basis for choice.
4. Quebec sovereignty and the construction of nationhood
The 1993 Canadian general election is a fascinating case of a "new" issue
changing the politics of a nation. The issue we have in mind, the sovereignty
of the province of Quebec, is of course not really new. Tensions between
Francophone and Anglophone Canadians predate the existence of Canada as
a nation. However, consider the definition of "issue" in Hinich and Munger
(1994: 111):
Issues: Social problem large numbers of citizens care about that (1)
politicians talk about in (a) public, (b) to contributors, or (c) among
themselves, OR (2) the press talks about either because some interest
group wants it discussed or because citizens care about it.
Many people cared a lot about Quebec independence before the 1993 election. In several previous elections the possibility of Quebec becoming a separate nation had been raised. What happened in 1993 was that large numbers of
people seemed to care, politicians debated the "issue", and the media covered
the story.
4.1. A brief history of Canadian realignments
We hope in a few diagrams to capture some of the essence of the main
conflicts in Canadian politics in the last century. There are several excellent
histories of Canada, and Quebec, including McRae (1964), Kornberg (1988),
and Bothwell (1995), as well as some significant analyses of the problem of
Quebec nationality, including Brimelow (1986), Kornberg and Clarke (1992),
and Gibson (1994). Our particular view of Canadian political history, and the
process ofrealignments, derives from Johnston (1993).
Johnston argues that there have been three major political epochs in Canada,
the first extending from 1866-1896, the second lasting from 1897-1957, and
the present epoch beginning around 1962. We will argue that a new, fourth
epoch may be beginning, with the "new issue" being the difficult old issue of
the place of Francophone Quebec in the Canadian provincial system. The interesting thing about Johnson's account is that it fits so well with the intuition
of the ideological model we have outlined in the preceding sections.
The first realignment in Canadian political history began around 1896.
From the independence of Canada in 1866 until the late 1890s, the nature
[ 193 ]
412
and form of the new country were debated, with a focus on urban-rural policies, monetary policy, and tariffs. According to Johnston, however, the chief
organizing cleavage was the conflict over the public school system. The status quo at independence in 1866 was hostility toward a separate Catholic
school system, with public schools being primarily affiliated with Protestant
denominations or the Church of England. The Catholic-Protestant division
corresponds fairly closely to the French-English split, but the actual policy
question was whether Catholic schools should be allowed as a parallel public
school system.
By the early 1890s, this division had become much less important as an
organizing principle. The Conservatives (previously the Confederation Tories of Upper Canada, before independence) had always supported lands and
funding for both Catholic and Protestant church schools. The opposition had
come from the Liberals, but by 1895 the Liberal party, too, had dropped its
opposition.
More important, after 1897 Canada found itself on the verge of military
conflict with the U.S., and other rival nations. Beginning in about 1901, the
Venezuelan debt crisis tested the resolve of the U.S. in defining the limits of
the "Monroe Doctrine", and by 1904 there were significant tensions between
the Americans and Great Britain. 8 Given British interest in Canada, and the
strategic importance of the lakes and rivers on Canada's southeastern border,
there seemed little question that this war would be fought in part on Canadian
soil.
Johnston (1993: 276-277) describes the change in political dimensions as
follows.
In this period Conservatives tended to be the party of separate [publicly
funded] schools ... The Liberals were the traditional party of opposition
to the religious establishment ... Operating at right angles to all of this
was the issue of imperial relations, specifically the moral claims of the
British Empire ... Before the 1890s, the rest of the Empire seemed too
distant to matter much ... By the 1890s, however, imperialist sentiment
was waxing and Britain began to look upon the self-governing colonies
and dominions as possible co-principals in imperial ventures. Canada
was driven to acquiesce in such ventures by practical necessities of statecraft ... If Canada was to have any hope of negotiating successfully with
the USA it could do so only as part of a rival concentration of power,
the British Empire ... But if Canada wanted to enlist the Empire on its
behalf, it had to be willing to reciprocate.
This many Canadians were happy to do ... But not all Canadians saw
things this way: Catholics ... were less enthusiastic about the Empire
than were Protestants. To Catholics a warm external-policy response
[194]
413
Separate Schools
No Separate
Catholic Schools
with Equal Funding
Figure 3a.
to the Empire paralleled pressures within the country toward cultural
homogenization ... (emphasis added).
We have adapted Johnston's discussion of this shift in issues, and the consequent realignment in the political system, in Figure 3. In Panel (a), we see
a single dimension of conflict, over the "issue" of separate schools. However,
many other issues also cleaved along the same line, so this dimension came
to be the organizing principle around which groups formed and argued. The
extreme Protestant voters favored no separate Catholic schools; the Liberal
party for decades opposed "church" schools. The Catholic voters, seeking
to control not just their schools but their culture, favored a separate system;
the Conservative party tended to favor greater Catholic school autonomy and
public funding.
In Panel (b), however two things have happened. First, the differences
between the parties on the issue of separate schools largely disappeared.
Both parties now accepted, or actively favored, separate public schools for
Catholics and Protestants. Consequently, the schools issue disappeared as
an organizing principle. The "new" issue over which coalitions split was
support for the British Empire. Interestingly, the Conservatives (before more
closely allied with the Catholics) were the party of Empire; Liberals were
largely neutral, and in many cases actively opposed imperial unity and military cooperation. 9 The result, in Johnston's (1993: 278) view, is that "the
polarity was reversed": As the schools issue became less important (in terms
of our model, the difference between the status quo b and voter's goals Xi was
reduced), Catholics came to support the Liberals, and Protestants found the
Conservatives much more attractive.
By the end of WWII, the "support for Empire" dimension had little meaning for most Canadians, because there was little organized opposition to participation in the Allied war effort. There was still an external vs internal
element to political conflict, but once again the party polarity had "reversed":
Canadian politics was now largely organized around a dimension where geographic region and industrial interests coincided. The eastern, more urban,
[ 195]
414
Active Military
Alliance with
British Empire
~:
1'~"
~
ff
\
\
#
.,6-c~
~(1
.,<;-'11
g
\
./
\GC~
..... ---4it-----l ----e-----I
'y"
No Separate
Catholic
Schools
\
New
t
\ Ideological §
\ Dimension ff
\,~g ,
Separate Schools
with Equal Funding
. t
'..... 1
Take NeutraJ,
Passive Military
Stance
Figure 3b.
provinces were much more heavily industrialized, but faced import competition from manufactured "secondary" products from other nations.
The eastern provinces (and the Conservative party) favored high tariff
barriers and other import restrictions, implying an "internal" focus for the
Conservatives in the 1950s. The western provinces were rich in minerals and
agriculture, but sought increased export markets for these nascent "primary"
industries. The western provinces (and the Liberal party) pursued a policy of
lower trade barriers, and subsidies for mining and agriculture. This (pre-1957)
situation is depicted in panel (a) of Figure 4.
Ease Import Restrictions
on Consumer Goods
Tariff Barriers
for Manufactured
Products
Figure 4a.
Interestingly, the Liberal party had always been, in Johnston's (1993) terms,
"the only option for a free trader". But by 1956 there was actually little difference between the parties. The Liberals had earlier proposed (but lost) a set of
free trade policies in 1891 and 1911, and had managed to win tariff reductions
in 1936 and 1938, "but only back to the levels from which a Conservative
government had raised them a few years before" (1993: 279).
Conservatives had consistently favored import restrictions of almost all
sorts, and viewed the "National Policy" (favoring domestic secondary indus-
[ 196 ]
415
Subsidize
Mines
Agriculture 8<
Other Prinuuy
Industries
Hi~
Tariffs
_ _ _ _ _ .....1 _ _
....
,
Pre-I9J7 ~
Ideology
IIl
';f
Ul
1957
Z.... ~-.
~.:
f
.J' I
v"
,
!
No Subsidies
for Pritruuy
btdustries
Figure 4b.
tries through tariffs, quotas, and subsidies) as a key part of their program.
Until the 1950s, however, the National Policy had not included much support for the developing primary industries in the western provinces. In fact,
when mining and agricultural subsidies had been proposed, the Conservatives
had opposed them. Consequently, what happened in the 1957-1962 period is
surprising: the Conservatives deemphasized (though they did not abandon)
protectionism, and moved from opposing to supporting investment in the
Canadian west. As panel (b) in Figure 4 shows, the Liberals' changed their
platform very little in this period, but the Conservatives moved away from the
eastern provinces and shifted toward the west.
We have drawn simple indifference curves in panel (b) for the eastern, and
western, provinces, and have included the implied ideological ideal points
for the western provinces, Zwest for 1957 and 1962. As the reader can see,
given the pre-1957 ideological cleavage along a dimension of free tradeprotectionism, the western provinces clearly favored the Liberals. After the
1957-1962 realignment, however, there is a new ideological dimension defined by the positions of the two parties. Given the new constraints for choice,
the induced ideal point z~;
is much closer to the new location of the Conservative party. Again, it is useful to summarize Johnston's (1993: 280-281)
account:
What changed? First, the 1950s saw an agricultural crisis. This suggested that the resource axis [gained salience]. But that alone would not
have produced a realignment, at least not one benefitting either old party,
[ 197]
416
given their pre-1957 policy orientations. The second key ingredient was
change in the Conservative leadership.
The Conservative party had, in a sense, run out of its traditional
alternatives. It had tried on several business-oriented imperialists. It had
genuflected toward Quebec. It had even had several Westerners as leader
but none who was prepared to articulate a credible agrarian programme
.... Finally, in 1956, the rank and file of the party chose someone who
did epitomize the Prairie West, John Diefenbaker.
Let there be no mistake: this was not a rejection of the Conservatives' beloved
National Policy. In fact, Diefenbaker's program of subsidy, generous credit,
and crop supports for agriculture were successful (politically, not economicallylo) precisely because Canadian wheat could not be successfully exported:
"For the first time, Central Canadian consumers were forced to subsidize a
Western industry which had no realistic prospect of comparative advantage
in the world market" (Johnston, 1993: 281).
So, there was little economic basis for this new issue emphasis. What happened was that the Conservatives dropped their regional emphasis in favor
of a logically coherent national program of "Canada first!" Farmers in the
western provinces, who had been a strong Liberal bloc for two generations,
now became the Conservatives' strongest electoral base. Conservatives didn't
change their position on the dimension (protectionism) that had organized
politics in the 1950s, and voters didn't change their preferences in any way.
What happened was that the Conservatives emphasized a "new" issue, agrarian support policies, which had before received only tepid and occasional
advocacy by the Liberals.
The account we have given of these three epochs in Canadian political history is highly selective. However, it captures a significant dynamic aspect of
the evolution of policies and coalitions. In the next section, we present some
measures of current issues in Canadian politics, taken from survey responses
during the 1993 Canadian national election campaign.
4.2. Some measures of issues in the 1993 Canadian National Election
Let us recall how we got here. The main theoretical claim of our model is
this: Even if voters have fixed preferences, changes in how issues map to the
ideological space can result in different electoral outcomes. That is not to say
voters never revise their beliefs. Instead, we are pointing out that fundamental changes in political conflict, partisan control of the legislature, and even
the essence of nationality, can result from strategic action by political elites,
holding mass preferences constant.
[198]
417
In essence, by introducing a new issue (or greatly increasing the importance of an issue), parties have an opportunity to change the location of the
voter's induced ideal point (Zi) even though the underlying issue positions
remain the same. This an important realization for the field of electoral politics, as most of our models are badly blunted when forced to cope with large
electoral shifts.
The 1993 Canadian general election is fascinating, in large part due to the
drastic changes that resulted from the reemergence of the issue of Quebec
independence. While it is certainly the case that voters both inside Quebec
and in the rest of Canada likely had established positions on Quebec independence, the importance of their positions in the national elections of the decade
preceding 1993 was minimal. Regressions performed on the data of the 1988
Canadian Election Survey show that a combination of familiar domestic issues coupled with concerns over NAFTA predict electoral choice, and that
Quebec independence was not a salient issue. In the terms of our model, the
ideological transform v had a near-zero coefficient for the issue of Quebec
independence. Thus it was largely unexplained by the existing ideologies.
With the increased importance of the issue in the 1993 elections, our
model suggests that the v vector would have a very large coefficient for
Quebec independence. This is a result of both increased public attention to
the issue of independence, an increase in the flow of information from the
parties that was narrowly tailored to the issue, and the fact that (at least one
of) the parties clearly diverged in their positions on this question. One would
also expect the issue to have the greatest importance inside Quebec, both due
to an increase in the salience of the issue across the population (Ai in the
model), and the greater proportion of voters who belong to the Quebecois
party.
For the purposes of analyzing the data from the 1993 survey, we focused
on the difference between the residents of Quebec and the rest of Canada
to highlight the role of a single new issue in the voting calculus. Though
many Canadians had stable positions on the issue of Quebec independence
prior to 1993, it was not until it became a greater part of the existing parties'
ideologies that the issue could affect choices.
In this example of how the model might account for dramatic political
shifts, our experiment consisted of two steps. A factor analysis was performed on issues taken from the 1993 Canadian Election survey, and issue
bundles were specified according to the results of the factor analysis. What
we looked for in this case, however, was not change over time, but rather
changes wrought by the campaign on residents of Quebec as differentiated
from the rest of Canada.
[199]
418
There is some precedent for these differences; Kornberg (1988: 21) claims
that responses to a series of surveys on political deference (1979 and 19831984) "divided neatly into two factors. One factor dealt with attitudes toward
government and its policies, and the other toward military service and obedience to authority". However, Kornberg confirmed what many others had
found: Quebec is different, with much less of political differences in opinion
being accounted for by the factors that organize the rest of Canada.
Since we do believe that both socialization and the campaign (and the
dissemination of information more generally) have an important place in
voting (i.e., through the v vector), we hypothesized that residents of Quebec
would be particularly sensitive to the issues revolving around Quebec, and
that the introduction of Quebec sovereignty into the election would result in
the formation of a drastically different ideological mapping. The 1993 data is
a good test case for this effect, as issues centering on Quebec independence
were particularly salient during the election (Table 1).
What we discovered in the factor analysis was interesting - the second
factor revolved almost completely around the issue of Quebec sovereignty,
while the first factor was inclusive and ordered along a left-right ideological
dimension. For the larger population, most of the issues in the first factor
were significant and salient in our regressions, with the exception of feelings
toward feminists (due in large part to its collinearity with feelings toward
minorities and homosexuals).
The second step was to see if regressions on electoral choice support
our conclusion that this second dimension based on independence actually
loomed large in the decision-making calculus of voters. The first regression
table shows results for the entire Canadian population, while the second focuses solely on Quebec residents. We focus first on educated respondents
(those who report attending at least some college) to get an idea of the overall
importance of issues among relatively sophisticated voters. As the first regression shows, the items from the first factor from the above factor analysis
are the main predictors of electoral choice (Table 2).
Predictably, when we focus on residents of Quebec, all issues from the first
factor drop out of the model except for Quebec sovereignty and aboriginal
rights. Of these, sovereignty has more salience. In terms of our model, the
v vector would be composed of very small coefficients for all issues save
independence, even though voter positions on these issues are important (and
they may care about them as expressed by the Ai matrix of weights). The two
issues that were weakly related to Quebec sovereignty in the factor analysis
are somewhat salient, but not significant at the .1 level (crime and feelings
toward the U.S.) (Table 3).
[200]
Table 1. Results of factor analysis on 1993 Canadian data
Eigenvalues of the correlation matrix: Total = 8. Average = 1
Eigenvalue
2.6356
Difference
Proportion
Cumulative
1.3914
0.3295
0.3295
2
3
4
5
5
8
8
1.2442
0.2343
1.0098
0.1515
0.1262
0.8583
0.8224
0.1939
0.1028
0.6285
0.2116
0.0786
0.4169
0.0326
0.0521
0.83843
0.0359
0.1073
0.6112
0.7185
0.8213
0.8999
0.9520
1.0000
0.1555
0.4850
0.0480
Initial factor method: principal components
~
Factor pattern
Factor 1
Factor 2
Factor 3
Quebec Sov
Aborig.S
Less Gov
Gay Rights
Feminists
0.07265
0.75158
0.15738
0.75574
0.69394
0.83877
0.22994
0.05389
-0.34641
0.01983
0.11131
0.94023
-0.13105
-0.10186
Minorities
Crime
Feel U.S.
0.78486
0.43735
0.42510
-0.09158
0.11223
-0.41452
0.41476
0.02409
0.08330
-0.27919
+:-
\0
420
Table 2. Logistic results a on sample from All of Canada b
Variable
Parameter
Standard
Asympt.
estimate
error
t-stateC
Intercept
0.8455
0.7277
Aborig
0.0583
0.0072
1.162
8.097**
Less Gov
0.0343
0.0753
0.456
Gay Rights
--0.0224
0.0075
-2.987**
Feminists
--0.0030
0.0073
Minorities
--0.0172
0.0087
--0.429
-1.977**
Crime
-0.1970
0.0645
-3.031 **
0.0211
0.0070
-2.857**
Feel U.S.
Association of predicted probabilities and observed responses
Concordant =84.6%
Somer's D = 0.697
Discordant = 14.9%
Gamma = 0.700
Tied = 0.4%
Tau-a = 0.127
(45936 pairs)
c = 0.849
Note. A vote for Bloc Quebicoise was coded "1"; all other votes
as "0".
a The issue of Quebec sovereignty was not included because it
was only asked of Quebec residents.
b The sample for this regression is all respondents with "Education" 2: 7. (n = 710).
C * implies significance at the .1 0 level; ** implies significance at
the .05 level, using a two-tailed test.
The large magnitude of Quebec sovereignty, and the overall good fit of
the model, supports our general notion of the role of the introduction of a
new issue in elections. As a new issue becomes more salient to a given part of
electorate, it should be the case, given our model of ideology, that other issues
drop out of the decision-making process. This clearly happened in Canada
for the residents of Quebec during the 1993, and analysis of the 1988 election
shows the same general effect at work for the entire Canadian electorate over
the issue of NAFTA. What makes the Canadian election unique is the (nearly
complete) independence of Quebec sovereignty as an issue.
In terms of the diagrammatic exposition we used to illustrate the 18961897 and 1956-1962 realignments, the Quebec "dimension" might become
the new ideological organizing principle. What are the main ideological conflicts in Canadian society today, and over the past twenty years? Interestingly,
[202]
421
Table 3. Logistic results a on sample from Quebec Onlyb
Parameter
Standard
Asympt.
Variable
estimate
error
t-state C
Intercept
-4.0865
1.2750
-3.205**
0.8686
0.0217
0.1415
6.143**
0.1220
-0.00248
0.1401
0.0117
0.871
-0.212
-0.0117
0.0111
-1.054
0.0139
-0.806
-\.505
Quebec Sov
Aborig.s
Less Gov
Gay Rights
Feminists
Minorities
Crime
Feel U.S.
-0.0112
-0.1641
0.0184
0.0114
0.1096
0.0123
1.904*
1.496
Association of predicted probabilities and observed responses
Concordant = 89.1 %
Somer's D = 0.783
Discordant = 10.8%
Gamma =0.784
Tied =0.1%
Tau-a =0.393
(5680 pairs)
c = 0.892
Note. A vote for Blow Quebecoise was coded "I "; all other votes
are "0".
a The issue of Quebec sovereignty was asked only on Quebec
residents.
b The sample for this regression is restricted to Quebec residents
with "Education" :::: 7. (n = 151).
C * implies significance at the. 10 level; ** implies significance at
the .05 level, using a two-tailed test.
Canadians do not seem "ideological" in classical left-right economic sense
(Kornberg, Mishler, and Smith, 1975; see also Clarke and Stewart, 1992, for
a review and update). There are, however, issues and values that appear to organize political conflict in Canada over this period. The single most important
dimension appears to be that identified by Clarkson (1978): Continentalism
vs nationalism. In paraphrasing this argument, Kornberg (1988: 19-20) says:
Nationalism is the opposition ideology. The reigning ideology, whether
it is called anti-nationalism or continentalism [is based on arguments
by liberal economists] .. , To be sure, they are not the only source of
anti-nationalism, but they are the chief intellectual force legitimizing
the continentalist economic and political policies pursued by Canadian
governments since World War II.
[203 ]
422
Table 4. Predicted - Actual patterns for Quebec voters
Panel A: Best model- Classification with all variables, from Table 3.
Educated voters only.
Actual vote
For Bloc
For some
Predicted vote
Quebecoise
other party
For Bloc Quebecoise
For some other party
66
14
16
55
Column correctly classified:
83%
77%
Panel B: Minimal model- Classification with "Quebec separatism" only.
Educated voters only.
Actual vote
For Bloc
For some
Predicted vote
Quebecoise
other party
For Bloc Quebecoise
For some other party
68
12
14
57
Column correctly classified:
85%
80%
Panel C: Minimal model - Classification with "Quebec separatism" only.
All voters sample, regardless of education.
Actual vote
For Bloc
For some
Predicted vote
Quebecoise
other party
For Bloc Quebecoise
337
71
70
297
For some other party
Column correctly classified:
83%
81%
What about 1993? Our factor analysis (in Table 1, above) found three
distinct factors, or dimensions, appeared to divide public opinion in Canada
in 1993. The first was a liberal-conservative division on social issues, such as
rights of aboriginal peoples and other minorities, homosexuals, and women.
The second dimension appears to be Quebec separatism, though fear of crime
and resentment of the u.s. also load on this dimension. The third dimension,
though weak statistically, does appear to have some explanatory power. This
third dimension is the desire for "less govemment".l1
[204 ]
423
If we are correct in claiming that independence for Quebec is the primary
issue that organized choice in the 1993 election, then position on that issue,
alone, should perform well in classifying voters' party choices. We can test
this claim, though only crudely, by comparing the classificatory power of
several models. These comparisons are presented in Table 4, which for sake
of conserving space presents only 2 x 2 tables of predicted vs. actual vote
choices by citizens in Quebec province.
Panel A of Table 4 shows the pattern of classification success of the "best"
model (from Table 3) in predicting whether a voter selects Bloc Quebecoise
(BQ) or some other party. The model performs adequately, overall classifying
80% correctly, and substantially outperforming the naive model prediction of
everyone voting for BQ (53%). Classification is slightly more accurate in
selecting those who will vote for BQ, but the difference is not substantial
(83% compared to 77%).
Panel B presents a stripped-down version of the model: the only right hand
side variable is support for Quebec sovereignty, with an intercept term. As
sometimes happens in ML estimation, less is more: the classification proportions go up, across the board, with overall classification now equal to 83%.
In terms of our model, this means that, even if voters care about other issues,
either they aren't using information about the other issues or party positions
imply these other issues map onto the "Quebec sovereignty" dimension with
little perceived error.
As we noted earlier, these results are for educated respondents (reported
at least some college). It is not clear whether sophistication (which was not a
parameter in the model we advanced in Section 3) should make voters more
or less likely to respond to salient issues. Panel C repeats the "strippeddown" version, using all respondents who answered the party choice and
Quebec sovereignty questions. Interestingly, there is no qualitative difference
in the results: overall classification is 82% (compared to a model prediction
of 53%).
The reader may shake his or her head at this point, and ask, "Why is it
surprising that Quebec voters use Quebec sovereignty to vote for, or against,
the BQ?" It is not surprising that voters use sovereignty at all, but we think
it is at least interesting that we can predict their vote choices using nothing else. Furthermore, as we see from comparing Panel A and Panel B of
Table 4, adding other explanatory variables does not improve classification,
even among the most sophisticated voters! 12
What may happen, in terms of the contest over the dimensions the divide
Canadian voters? We can make a guess which, though tentative, is consistent
with the process of adjustment we have outlined above. If there are, indeed,
three separate dimensions developing in Canadian politics, the key to the
[205 ]
424
Civil Rights (Aboriginals, Gays, Women, Minority)
More
~ 0(">
Rights
r------- . . . .~&Quebec
;'1
I ~
1,-
;'
;'
;'
;'
I
I
/
-~,t.
Less Intervention
;'1-;'/;'
;'1
q,.f.
(,0-# \.
~
f,~;'-t
;'
;'
;'/;';'
;';'
~
I;,
.-------
;'
~ry
0<i>",
I
I
I
/
;'
;' ;'
;' ;'
\~
;'
V-'Oq, , .
/ /
----=-"
~
;'
;'
;'
More Regulation
,--------------,
Existing primary
dimension of cleavage is
the difference(s) between
Liberal & Conservative parties
on civil rights and economic
policy. But the Quebec separatism
dimension may come to stand for all
other conflicts.
I"
_____ JI
1-1/
t
Canadian
Nationalism
;'
;';'/;'
r- -J.--
/;'
"'c.
;'
;'
."i'
o.oc;
I
--"7----(
,..----I---..J.
Extent of Government
Intervention in Economy
;' ,.-~
;' ;'
;';'
;'
;'
;' I
I Separatism /
/
-II
No Special
Protection
Figure 5.
future will be the contest over the dimension that dominates. One possible
depiction is in Figure 5.
The two solid lines depict orthodox political conflict within a viable national construct. More or less civil rights for minorities, and more or less
government intervention, are standard conflicts in most democracies. Liberals tend to support more regulation, and more civil rights, and conservatives
argue for less regulation and the absence of special treatment or affirmitive
action programs. The third dimension, the dotted line in Figure 5, is position
on a separate and sovereign Quebec. BQ is liberal, but hardly extremist, in
the political space described by the two solid lines. They might easily become part of a liberal coalition, and share power in a national government in
Ottawa. If, however, BQ chooses to emphasize the dotted line above all other
differences, there is no stable or predictable outcome.
In terms of the model we have advanced, a radical BQ might follow one
of three strategies:
(I) Add Quebec sovereignty to the political debate, with an understanding
that the mapping terms Vi for many voters would accommodate this
dimension as the primary organizing principle in politics. On its face,
this seems unlikely to succeed, since the liberal and conservative alternatives are already well-defined, and appear orthogonal to Quebec
[206 ]
425
separatism. It is important to remember, however, that Canadians are at
almost only weakly "ideological", in the sense of conforming to standard liberal-conservative cleavages. If Clarkson (1978), and Kornberg
(1988), are correct, then nationalism-continentalism is the omnipresent,
though latent, potential cleavage. Regionalism is but one more step, and
independence for Quebec is nothing but an extreme form of regionalism.
(2) Represent Quebec sovereignty as a very large change in policy, one
which would radically alter the economy and culture of Quebec province
for the better. In terms of our model, this means that BQ would have
to persuade voters that the status quo is dangerous, or unsupportable,
as insidious encroachments on French culture and language continue.
If the difference Xj - bj is large enough, Quebec voters may turn in
droves toward some more separatist, autonomous relationship with the
rest of Canada, even if Quebec separatism does not become the primary
dimension of conflict.
(3) Depend on high salience of the sovereignty issue. Though it seems trivial, the driving force behind any issue may be its comparative importance. We have conceived of the Ai as being invariant over time, but
voters do alter their beliefs and goals. If the salience of sovereignty is
large enough, it will swamp all other issues as the primary organizing
principle, even if literally no other issue maps onto it.
5. Conclusions
In this paper, we have argued that nationalism is a product of beliefs, more
than borders. The dimension of identity, and self-definition is latent in all
political communities. We have discussed some of the reasons that community, of language, experience, and identity, are crucial to the functioning of a
nation. The model outlined above seeks to give some purchase on the question
of how people may change these perceptions of shared goals. In considering
the Canadian national election in 1993, we found that there appear to be three
distinct dimensions vying for primacy in peoples' minds. The first two, civil
rights for minorities and the extent of government intervention in economics,
are found in most Western democracies, and are consistent with the survival
of Canada as a nation. The third dimension, however, is Quebec sovereignty.
Our primary empirical finding is striking: support for or opposition to Quebec
sovereignty, alone, can classify upwards of 80 percent of voters' choices in
the province. Canada may soon break apart.
[207]
426
Notes
1. On the importance of, and difficulty understanding, belief systems see Denzau and North
(1994).
2. The first suggestion that there might be several "spaces" of political conflict can be found
in Ordeshook (1976). Ordeshook's "basic space" is somewhat different from our notion
of ideology, but it was an important step. The contribution of Hinich and Pollard (1981),
and later work, was to formalize the relation between the policy space and the ideological
space, and suggest a consistent and defensible theory for voter choice.
3. We adopt the convention that lower case Greek letters are points, and upper case letters
are spaces. Thus, for policy: W E Q; for ideology: 7r E IT; and so on.
4. If P = 2, the 7rj E IT, IT = IT 1 x IT2, and so on in higher dimensions.
5. This theoretical discussion may sound similar to a related perspective, "directional" theory, advanced by MacDonald and Rabinowitz (1987), and Rabinowitz and MacDonald
(1989). The key difference, and the main point of contention, between the two the theories, is whether it makes sense to conceive of issues as being linked (as we have), or
claiming issues are evaluated in isolation because individual belief systems are diffuse (as
MacDonald and Rabinowitz have claimed). The theory of ideology claims that there are
important linkages, across issues, in the way that issues are presented. The reason may
be budget problem (the only way to increase spending in one area is to decrease spending
elsewhere), or pure ideology (defense spending is bad, social welfare programs are good,
for liberal ideologues, and the only way to commit is to claim to share beliefs).
6. The only difference implied by the use of circular indifference curves is that the matrix of
utility weights is all ones; that is, A = I.
7. IimV m+l-+OO(L1z) = 0/1 = O.
8. Venezuela had enormous debts to Germany and Great Britain, and refused to submit to
the edicts of the Hague Tribunal to pay. The Europeans imposed a naval blockade in 1902,
shelled Venezuelan ports, and destroyed several small naval craft. The Venezuelans capitulated, and the debts were restructured in such a way that all creditors had some chance of
being paid. In 1904, the situation was virtually repeated in the Dominican Republic. This
time, however, the government in Santo Domingo made a separate deal with the U.S., one
aspect of which was giving debts to U.S. creditors a "senior", or privileged, position. The
Europeans protested, and tensions were high. Roosevelt laid out his "big stick" corollary
to the Monroe Doctrine, transforming the U.S. pledge of preventing intervention to an
implied threat that the U.S. might intervene unilaterally (Morris, 1982: 349-350).
9. It is worth noting that the Liberals were in control over the period in question (Liberals
controlled the government from 1896-1911).
10. Kornberg (1988) notes that the National Policy and its elaboration in agricultural subsidies
may have hurt the Canadian economy. Because tariffs kept other products out, American
firms could "invest" in branch plants to produce consumer goods without significant competition. There are claims that there has been direct interference in Canadian policies by
U.S. firms bent on maintaining Canada as a captive market for consumer products, relegating Canadian-owned industry to relatively labor-intensive industries such as clothing,
textiles, and footwear.
11. Migue (1997) claims that both federal and provincial governments are trying to woo voters
in Quebec province, with the effect being an expansion of government size compared to
optimum. This may explain the importance of this dimension as a separate organizing
principle.
[208 ]
427
12. Using the full model for all voters (running the regression in Table 3 on a sample that includes college and noncollege-educated respondents) gives a classification of only around
75%, even worse than that in panel (a).
References
Aldrich, J. (1983). A spatial model with party activists: Implications for electoral dynamics.
Public Choice 41: 63-100.
Aldrich, J. (\995). Why parties?: The origin and transformation of party politics in America.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bothwell, R. (1995). Canada and Quebec: One country, two histories. British Columbia: UBC
Press.
Brimelow, P. (1986). The patriot game: National dreams and political realities. New York: K.
Porter Books.
Brimelow, P. (1995). Alien nation: Common sense about America's immigration disaster. New
York: Harper Collins.
Clarke, H. and Stewart, M. (1992). Light anchors, choppy seas: Social structure and party
choice in Canada. In M. Franklin, et al. (Eds.), Electoral change: Responses to evolving
social and attitudinal structures in western countries. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Clarkson, S. (1978). Anti-nationalism in Canada: The ideology of mainstream economics.
Canadian Review of Studies in nationalism 5: 45-65.
Denzau, A. and North, D. (1994). Shared mental models: Ideologies and institutions. Kyklos
47: 3-32.
Enelow, J. and Hinich, M. (1984). The spatial theory of voting. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Flanagan, T. (1994). Invasion from the right: The reform party in the 1993 Canadian election.
Papers in Political Economy, No. 42. Political Research Group: University of Western
Ontario, London, Ontario.
Gibson, G. (1994). Plan B: Thefuture of the rest of Canada. British Columbia: Fraser Institute.
Hinich, M. and Munger, M. (1994). Ideology and the theory of political choice. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Hinich, M. and Munger, M. (1997). New issues and the dynamics of political change.
Typescript. Department of Political Science, Duke University.
Hinich, M. and Pollard, W. (1981). A new approach to the spatial theory of electoral
competition. American Journal of Political Science 25: 323-341.
Johnston, R. (1993). Issues and party allignments: A review with Canadian examples. In
A. Breton, et al. (Eds.), Preferences and democracy, 265-286. Norwell, MA: Kluwer
Academic.
Jones, B. (1994). Reconceiving decision-making in democratic politics. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Kornberg, A. (1988). Politics and culture in Canada. Ann Arbor, Center for Political Studies,
Institute for Social Research, University of Michigan.
Kornberg, A. and Clarke, H. (1992). Citizens and community: Political support in a representative democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
[209]
428
Kornberg, A., Mishler, W. and Smith, 1. (1975). Political elite and mass perceptions of party locations in issue space: Some tests of two propositions. British Journal of Political Science
5: 161-185.
Lupia, A. (1992). Busy voters, agenda control. and the power of information. American
Political Science Review 86: 390-404.
MacDonald, S. and Rabinowitz, G. (1987). The dynamics of structural realignment. American
Political Science Review 81: 775-796.
McKelvey, R. (1976). Intransitivities in multidimensional voting bodies and some implications
for agenda control. Journal of Economic Theory 30: 283-314.
McRae, K.D. (1964). The structure of Canadian history. In L. Hartz (Ed.), Thefounding of
new societies. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Migue J.-L. (1977). Public choice in a federal system. Public Choice 90: OOO-Q()().
Morris, R.B. et al. (Eds.). (1982). Encyclopedia of American history. 6th edition. New York:
Harper & Row.
Moynihan, D.P. (1993). Pandaemonium: Ethnicity in international politics. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Ordeshook, P.C. (1976). The spatial theory of elections: A review and critique. In I. Budge, et
al. (Eds.), Party identification and beyond. New York: Wiley.
Poole, K. and Rosenthal, H. (1993). Spatial realignment and the mapping of issues in U.S.
history: The evidence from roll call voting. In W. Riker (Ed.), Agendaformation, 12-40.
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Poole, K.T. and Rosenthal, H. (1997). Congress: A political economic history of roll call
voting. New York: Oxford University Press.
Rabinowitz, G. and MacDonald, S. (1989). A direction theory of issue voting. American
Political Science Review 83: 93-121.
Riker, W. (1982). Liberalism vs. populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy
and the theory of social choice. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman.
Riker, W. (1986). The art of political manipulation. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Riker, W. (1990). Heresthetic and rhetoric in the spatial model. In J. Enelow and M. Hinich
(Eds.), Advances in the spatial theory of voting. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Schofield, N. (1985). Anarchy, altruism, and cooperation. Social Choice and Welfare 2: 207219.
Taylor, M. (1976). Anarchy and cooperation. London: Wiley.
Taylor, M. (1982). Community, anarchy, and liberty. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Thompson, D.C. (1988). Vive Ie Quebec libre. Toronto: Deneau Publishers.
[210]
Public Choice 97: 429---449, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
429
The "revival of communism" or the effect of institutions?: The
1993 Polish parliamentary elections *
MAREK M. KAMINSKI] , GRZEGORZ LISSOWSKI 2 & PIOTR
SWISTAK3
] Department of Politics, New York University, New York, NY 10003, U.S.A.; 21nstitute of
Sociology, Warsaw University, PL-00-324 Warsaw 64, Poland; 3Department of Government
and Politics, University of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742, U.S.A.
Abstract. In several Eastern European countries the breakdown of communism in 1989 was
followed by a surprising return to power of post-communist parties. Yet, some electoral victories of post-communists look puzzling when contrasted with a small size of a shift in voters'
preferences that has led to them. Such is the case of the 1993 Polish parliamentary elections.
Using partition-function form games and results of simulated elections, we estimate the impact
of three factors that were blamed, in addition to the "shift to the left" in voters' preferences,
for the 1993 victory of the post-communists in Poland. We show that the shift to the left
was insufficient to assure post-communists an electoral victory, and that this victory would
not have happened under the old electoral law or under a unified coalition of the Right. Our
results show the high sensitivity of emerging democracies to the details of their institutional
backbones.
1. Introduction
A few years after the breakdown of communism in 1989, some of the CentralEuropean political scenes experienced another unexpected and radical transformation. In October 1992, a post-communist party regained power in Lithuania. In September 1993, a similar comeback took place in Poland, and in May
1994, in Hungary. Yet, the electoral victories of the post-communist parties
were much more spectacular than one could have predicted from the size of
their popular support. In Lithuania, 46.6% of popular votes resulted in 56.7%
of lower house seats whereas in Hungary the corresponding numbers were
33% and 55%. In Poland, the disproportion between popular votes and seats
* The authors are grateful to the companies Case and SMG-KRC Poland for sponsoring a
survey used in this study, to the polling agency CBOS for granting access to their survey data,
to Jarek Gryz for implementing the simulation program SEATS, and to Jerzy Bartkowski,
Irena Jackiewicz, Lena Kolarska-Bobinska, Krzysztof Kruszewski, Marcin Kujawski, Marcin
Penconek, Antoni Sulek, and Jim Vreeland for comments and help with data collection. Swistak thanks the Office of International Affairs and the University of Maryland for a financial
support.
[211 ]
430
was even greater, a mere 20.4% of popular votes for a post-communist party
resulted in a total of 37.2% of Sejm (lower house) seats. The electoral success
of the post-communist party in Poland facilitated a coalition with another big
winner in the elections, the Left Peasants party (15.4% of votes and 28.7%
of seats). Since the Left Peasants party originated under communism as a
puppet-ally of the former Polish communist party, the coalition of these two
parties was labeled post-communist. For brevity and convenience we will
refer to this coalition as the post-communist Left or the Left. l This coalition
turned out to be very stable and has ruled Poland since 1993.
When the "revival of communism" was detected, the students of EasternEuropean politics focused mainly on the economic and social costs of transition. These costs were believed responsible for the widespread disillusionment with democracy and the increase in the support of the former communists. The "shift to the left" in the voter preferences was typically considered
identical with the "shift to the left" in the distribution of political power. The
interaction of the "shift to the left" in voters' preferences with the institutional
details of the political game (electoral law, coalitions, etc.) was noted but was
not closely examined (Gibson and Cielecka, 1995; Racz and Kukorelli, 1995;
Tworzecki, 1994; Zubek, 1994). Here we take a more careful look at this
interaction.
In this paper we focus entirely on the 1993 Sejm (lower House) elections
in Poland. We show that the electoral victory of the Left is only in part due
to a shift to the left in voters' preferences. Apart from the shift, which indeed
took place, three other factors contributed to the electoral results. We analyze
their effects through a series of computer simulations. It turns out that the
most powerful effect was that of a new electoral formula. The second most
powerful factor that contributed to the victory of the Left was the failure of the
fragmented post-Solidarity Right to form a coalition. Our simulation results
show that had the elections been run under the same formula as the 1991
elections, or had a coalition of the Right been formed, the post-communist
block would have remained in minority and, most likely, would have had
no part in the formation of the government. Interestingly, both the shift in
electoral preferences to the left and another factor that is often blamed for
the 1993 electoral failure of the Right, the unexpected last-minute entrance
of two new parties, show relatively small impact on the final distribution of
power. Our analysis suggests that neither one of the two factors alone would
have increased significantly the political power of the Left. In short, then, we
separate major from minor effects and show the political mechanism behind
the post-communist takeover. The results ultimately point to the power of
political institutions.
[212]
431
To model the logic of coalition formation, we use cooperative games in
the partition-function form. We apply this concept to get explanations, obtain simulated results of elections, and formulate a series of game-theoretic
questions. We show how the perception of the electoral game, the electoral
law, and the entrance of new players resulted in a massive failure of the postSolidarity Right to convert its large share of the popular vote to parliamentary
seats. Finally we simulate a series of potential electoral outcomes under various alternative electoral laws, with two last-minute entrants removed from
the political scene, and with a united coalition of the Right.
2. The short story of the 1993 elections
The story of the spectacular come back of the Left begins on 28 May 1993.
On that day a new electoral law was adopted by the Sejm. The new law was
more friendly to larger parties and almost all larger parties in the Sejm supported the change, whereas almost all smaller parties voted against it. 2 The
voting on the new law took place in a fervent situation due to another major
political problem. The non-confidence vote was on the agenda for the same
day. The cabinet fell by one vote, and the next day, unexpectedly, President
Lech Wales a dissolved the Sejm and called for new elections. The elections
took place in September, and brought a defeat to all post-Solidarity parties.
The relatively homogeneous bloc of the post-Solidarity Right did especially
poorly and, though its popular vote support was substantial (26.2%), the Right
received only a tiny portion, 3.5% of all Sejm seats (see Table 1).3
Before the election, almost 1 voter out of 3 declared that he would vote
strategically in the face of a sure electoral defeat of his most preferred party
(CBOS, 1993a: 13). Thus, the fragmented bloc of the post-Solidarity Right
probably lost some of its votes to the post-Solidarity Center and Left Peasants
party due to its supporters' strategic voting. It is quite likely that the potential
popular support of the Right in 1993 was higher than the actual one and
similar to that of 1991 elections, of about 30% of the electorate. Yet the total
number of seats that these parties won in the 1991 (34.4%) and 1993 elections
(3.5%) differed dramatically.
3. A model of rational coalition-building in a fragmented party system
The new electoral law of 1993 was designed to de-fragment the political
system and most of the rightist parties supported the change. The Right had
two good reasons to believe that the new law would not be harmful. First, the
post-Solidarity rightist parties believed that their popular support would be
[213 ]
432
Table 1. Percent of the popular vote and the percent of seats obtained by the Right in
the 1991 and the 1993 elections to the Sejm
Parties of the post
Percent of the popular vote
Percent of seats in Sejm
1991
1993
1991
1993
Coalition Fatherland
8.7
6.4
10.9
0.0
Centrum
8.7
4.4
9.6
0.0
6.1
0.0
5.9
0.0
solidarity Right
2.7
Movement
Right Peasants
5.5
2.4
Solidarity
5.1
4.9
Other parties
3.5
WalesaBioc
Total
0.0
5.4
31.5
3.5
2.0
26.2
34.4
3.5
Source: Monitor Polski (1993).
sufficient to meet the qualifying thresholds required by the new electoral law.
And, second, if the polls ever indicated possible problems with meeting the
thresholds, the Right would always have an option to form a coalition; given
the bloc's relative ideological homogeneity, coalescing was seen as a viable
option. Indeed, just a few days after the presidential decision to dissolve
the Parliament, the coalitional negotiations were well-advanced. Ultimately,
however, the rightist parties failed to coalesce. To understand the logic of the
failure, we will use the somewhat forgotten concept of a partition-function
form game (PF), a generalization of the standard characteristic-function form
game. 4
We believe that the PF games provide an intuitive and a proper tool to analyze the formation of pre-electoral coalitions in multiparty systems (Kaminski, 1994). The concept of the PF game naturally emerges in the context of the
following decision-making problem. Assume, first, that parties platforms are
fixed. Hence, in a multiparty system, the only important decisions to be made
by party leaders are whether to form coalitions with other parties. Consider,
first, the popular vote that parties and their coalitions may receive. Note that
some coalitions may be considerably harmful. For instance, a coalition of a
communist and a religious right partyS would require a merger of two largely
inconsistent ideologies - a manoeuver that would decrease the credibility of
the new party and lower its popular support (cf. Hinich and Munger, 1994).
[214 ]
433
Other coalitions, however, like between two parties with identical platforms,
may be beneficial. In general, then, if two parties coalesce, then their total
payoff, in terms of popular votes in elections, may be smaller, equal, or larger
than the sum of the popular votes of the partners.
However, the maximization of the popular vote is rarely the objective of
a political party, the ultimate goal is to maximize the number of seats won.
Though typically vote-maximization is equivalent to seat-maximization, in
some instances the two objectives do not agree. Sometimes a party is willing to sacrifice a few seats for a larger popular vote share, but, usually, the
seat-maximization objective supersedes the vote-maximization one. Under
all circumstances, votes and seats are the two main aspects of coalescing. The
decision to enter a coalition depends on the expected number of votes and the
expected number of seats. The latter is a function of both the distribution of
votes and the electoral law. As we will later see, the impact of the electoral
law on the outcome of elections can be profound.
Formally, we define an n-person cooperative game in partition-function
form as follows. Any family of disjoint and nonempty subsets of players
C = {C 1, •.. , C r } is a coalitional structure. 6 The partition function assigns
to every coalition C j , included in a coalitional structure C, a real number,
or a vector of numbers, F(C i, C). We assume that I;iF(Ci, C) is constant for
any coalitional structure C. The number F(C, C) is interpreted as an exact
payoff of C i under the circumstances C. (The obvious difference between a
PF game and cooperative games in characteristic function form is that the
payoff function for a given coalition may vary over various actual coalitional
structures whereas in a standard characteristic function game the impact of
actual coalitional structures is not represented.) There are two interconnected
PF games that describe the parameters of a political situation. The popular
votes of various coalitions under all possible coalitional structures in all electoral districts form a partition function of the first game, or the vote-game, G v.
The payoffs of this game are vectors of popular votes in the districts. An approximation of these payoffs are popular votes measured at the national level.
The electoral law, which converts popular votes in districts into parliamentary
seats, defines the partition function of the second game, or the seat-game, GS .
Thus, an electoral law EL is a function that assigns to any vote-game G V the
corresponding seat-game GS = EL(Gv ).
The PF games provide a convenient framework for explaining parties decisions to form coalitions, simulating possible outcomes, and posing normative
questions about multi-party systems. We begin with the explanations.
[215 ]
434
4. The failure of the Right?: An explanation
Media reports would indicate that, in their thinking about benefits and costs of
coalescing, the post-Solidarity Right leadership employed simplified versions
of PF games. Our analysis proceeds under this hypothetical, though highly
plausible, assumption. Players (parties) are assumed to be seat maximizers.
They observe results of the polls and use these results to estimate the parameters of the vote-game. The estimated vote-game together with an electoral law
provide proxies for payoffs in the seat-game. Two (or more) parties coalesce
if they expect the number of seats for the coalition to be greater than the sum
of seats they can secure individually.
After the fall of communism, polls quickly became an important political
tool. Politicians learned that polls are not only useful as a source of information but also as a strategic tool. For instance, the leaders of the fragmented
rightist bloc proclaimed polls as biased. The leader of Centrum, Jaroslaw
Kaczynski, attributed the bias to "manipulation": "So-called public opinion polls are manipulated. In the previous elections, our survey scores were
also very poor, but our election results were quite good".8 Kaczynski was
clearly right to claim that the polls seriously underestimated the strength of
the rightist parties (see Table 2). He might have been acting strategically,
however, when he claimed that the polls had been manipulated. Indeed, the
causes of the bias seem to be less Machiavellian. The reliability of polls in
a highly fragmented party system is much lower than in a two- or threeparty stable democracy. First, in the same sample, the standard error of the
estimated support for a party holding 50% of the popular vote is relatively
much smaller (though larger in objective terms) than the standard error for
a party holding 5% of the vote. Second, the pre-campaign bias of the media
towards larger parties produces a systematic underestimation of the poll predictions for the small- and medium-size parties. When, during the campaign,
all parties receive comparable media coverage, small- and medium-size parties improve their poll ratings significantly.9 Finally, voters may misrepresent
their preferences in pre-election polls. This effect was well-established in
1990 presidential and 1991 parliamentary elections in Poland when both the
Right and the Left's ratings were underestimated while the ratings of the
post-Solidarity centrist parties were overestimated.
When two parties consider the decision whether to coalesce, they are interested in a fragment of the partition function only. First, they would like
to know how their share of votes and seats will be affected by the decision
to coalesce given the current coalitional structure. Second, they would like
to estimate sensitivity of these payoffs to possible changes in the coalitional
structure. Even if the rightist leaders did not consider poll ratings as unbiased
estimates of their support, the polls generated the only estimate of the frag-
[216]
435
Table 2. Estimated support for the parties of the post-Solidarity
Right involved in negotiating coalition formation
Parties/coalitions of the
Estimated
post-Solidarity Right
support
Fatherland
4.5
2.2
6.37
4.42
2.1
2.70
3,607
2.1
2.37
3.607
Centrum
Movement
Right Peasants
Actual votes
Sample
size
14,874
14,874
Note. "undecided" excluded. "Estimated support" includes unweighted mean support from 11 surveys by CBOS, Demoskop,
and PBS Sopot (Fatherland and Centrum) and 3 surveys by CBOS
(Movement and Right Peasants). The surveys were conducted between July and September 1993.
Source: Domanski (1995); CBOS (I993a).
ment of partition function they needed. Moreover, a poll with an unknown
systematic bias, that is proportional to the size of the popular support, still
provides a reliable estimate of the ratio of the support for a coalition to the
total support for its members. The smaller this ratio, the lower the incentives
of the parties to maintain the coalitional arrangement. It is likely that the estimates generated by the polls had a decisive impact on the failure of coalitional
negotiations.
After the Parliament was dissolved on 29 May 1993, the initial plans for
coalition formation were announced just two days later. On 8 June, three
coalitions of the rightist parties were formed and further fusions were expected. Two weeks later the first signs of the problem were observed. The
polls suggested deep subadditivity for two rightist coalitions and approximate additivity for the third coalition in the vote-game (see Table 3). In
fact, the two sub additive coalitions received total support well below the
senior partner's support recorded just a few days earlier. The CBOS analysts
wrote about a "phenomenon of losing a large part of the electorate due to
coalescing" (CBOS, 1993a: 5). The required qualifying threshold of 5% for
parties and 8% for coalitions further undermined the incentives for maintaining the coalitions. The additive coalition survived but the two subadditive
ones dissolved a few days after the announcement of the poll results. The
coalition-formation process did not recover from this failure in time to meet
the 10 August deadline for declaring coalitions.
It is likely that the observed effect of the "loss of the electorate" was due
to the frequent changes of party labels rather than a real loss of the electorate.
Each new coalition substituted a new coalition name for two, or more, rela-
[217 ]
436
Table 3. CBOS poll standings of the coalescing parties of the Right
May
11-14 June
Right Peasants
3.7
3.7
Fatherland
3.7
3.7
Polish Convention
1.2
1.2
(three minor
1.2
0.4
Right parties)
2.4
0.2
Movement
3.5
5
Centrum
1.2
1.2
18-21 June
9-12 July
12-17 August
2.4
1.2
1.25
5
2.5
1.2
3.7
4
2.4
2.4
2.4
0.5
Source: CBOS (I993a, 1993b). Sample size N E [1086; 1376]. Note. "undecided" excluded.
Cells of the table that are merged correspond to a coalition of the respective parties at the time
the poll was conducted; the question concerned this coalition.
tively well-known brand names of its members. In addition to the information
noise caused by this relabeling, two new political actors, Walesa Bloc and
Solidarity trade union, entered the scene and took away some support of the
Right. The polls of 18-21 June asked for the support for the new-born Walesa
Bloc which had not been included in the preceding poll of 11-14 June (see
Table 3). The Bloc received the support of 12.5% of respondents. These votes
would have most likely gone to other rightist parties had the Walesa Bloc not
entered the scene. In addition to the Walesa Bloc, on 28 June, the Solidarity
trade union entered the elections. Both entrances added uncertainty to the
estimates and, by increasing the number of negotiating units, increased the
negotiation costs.
5. The shift to the left
When coalescing efforts failed in June and July of 1993, the post-Solidarity
Right might have estimated their potential support at the level of the 1991
elections (see Table 1). The Right was fragmented no more than in the 1991
elections and the polls were close to what they had been in 1991. It seems that
the Right parties' estimated probabilities of crossing the respective thresholds
required by the new law were high. When the political situation appeared
roughly predictable, the entrance of two new parties, Walesa Bloc and the
Solidarity trade union, changed the picture. The new configuration of the
parties induced substantial shifts in the popular vote. In addition, a significant
increase in the support for the Left, was detected in August of 1993. In the
meantime, coalition building efforts among the rightist parties were failing.
And 10 August was the deadline for registering coalitions and candidates on
local voting lists (see Figure 1).
[218]
437
.~l ...... .
40-~
.......... ~
30--
I~l.
25-
............. ~
...........
.....
~.
................. ~
.
10~
5-~
0+
June 11
June 18
___
....+...
July 9
Post-communists
Total
August 12
- •
-
August 27
September 17
Left Peasants
Figure 1. The estimated support for the post-communists and the Left Peasants. Source:
CBOS (l993a); Domanski (1995). Note. "undecided" excluded.
And so, the month of August brought a clearer picture of the strategic
properties of the political situation. It became apparent that total defeat of
the Right was possible. By 10 August no major coalitions of the Right were
formed and the Right entered into the 1993 elections fragmented. At that
point the game among the parties of the Right changed. Before 10 August,
the game had been cooperative. After the deadline, coalition building was
no longer possible (for the purpose of entering the elections, that is) and the
game turned into a non-cooperative one. The only two actions available to
the parties in the non-cooperative game were "to withdraw from the elections" (and encourage its supporters to vote for the other rightist parties) or
"to stay". Since the withdrawing party would not have been able to get any
compensation in seats for the withdrawal, and every party attached some nonzero probability to crossing the threshold, staying was a dominant strategy.
Also, the withdrawal of any of the parties would have increased the expected
payoffs to those remaining in the elections. Not surprisingly, almost all of
the rightist parties appealed to the others to withdraw, but were unsuccessful
(Sulek, 1995: 114). The equilibrium in dominant strategies was "to stay" for
all parties, and all of them chose their dominant strategies. Clearly, the payoff
structure of the game, under the parties' beliefs, was that of the Prisoner's
Dilemma.
[219 ]
438
Other aspects of the strategic environment were such that no apparent
solution to the problem of the inefficient equilibrium was readily available.
The race was close and the perceived reliability of the poll estimators was
low. The lack of an enforcement mechanism did not facilitate solution by a
contract. Whatever the potential contract could have been, no player would
have had an incentive to keep it - the Right was bound to dwell in the inefficient equilibrium. And it did. It was too late to correct for the effects of the
new electoral law, the failure to coalesce, and the fragmenting effect of the
entry of Solidarity and the Walesa Bloc.
But, what were these effects? How bad was the failure to coalesce? How
strong was the effect of the electoral law? Had the entry of the two new parties
contributed significantly - as a typical political analysis would want us to
believe - to the downfall of the right? What would have been the results of the
elections without the two parties entering the scene? The exact answers are
not feasible but we can offer some approximate answers. Election results can
be simulated under varying parameters of the game. We report and discuss
results of some computer simulations in the next section. The results turn out
to be robust with respect to the parameters of the PF game.
6. Possible results of the elections
In this section we will comment on the results of three sets of simulations.
The simulations were done in an attempt to assess the impact of the electoral
law and coalitional structure on the distribution of seats in the Sejm and the
consequent division of power on the Polish political scene. All simulations
use actual district-level election results, data from the CBOS surveys, and data
from a special survey that was designed by the authors to reconstruct second
preferences of voters (i.e., candidates/parties they would have voted for had
their first choice been not available). Simulations are based on the relevant
fragment of the partition function of the 1993 elections' vote-game. In all
simulations, the underlying vote-game (that is, the popular votes under various coalitional structures) is assumed to be the same and is reconstructed from
the electoral and survey data. This assumption simply means that the changes
in the electoral law do not induce voters to vote strategically. We comment
on the robustness of this assumption and discuss possible adjustments. In all
simulations we keep constant all factors of the 1993 elections except for the
one factor whose impact we want to assess. We begin by looking at the effect
of the new electoral law and then move to assess the impact of the rightist
coalitional structure.
[220]
439
91+R+A
VOTES
Post-communists
•
91+R
91
Post-Solidarity Right
Figure 2. The impact of the electoral law. "Votes" stands for the percent of the popular vote in
the 1993 elections. All the other numbers represent the percentages of seats in 1993 elections
(93 = 91 +R+A+ T) and in simulated elections with partial changes to the 1991 electoral law.
R stands for redistricting. A for a new apportionment method, and T for qualifying thresholds
(three changes introduced to the 1991 electoral law). "91 + R", for instance, stands for a
simulation in which all electoral rules are that of the 1991 with the exception of R, the new
districting.
6.1. The impact of adopting the new electoral law
Recall, first, that the 1993 electoral law changed three aspects of the 1991
rules: redistricting (R), a new apportionment method (A), and the introduction
of qualifying thresholds for parties and coalitions (T) (see note 2 for a more
detailed description). To denote this, we write, 93 = 91 + R + A + T. We also
use this convention to label electoral rules in Figure 2. "91 + R", for instance,
stands for a simulation in which all electoral rules are that of the 1991 with the
exception of R, the new districting. Our objective is to assess the effect of each
of the three factors (R, A and T) and their combinations (R + A, R + T, etc.)
to see which change in the electoral law had the largest marginal impact on
the results of the '93 elections. Figure 2 shows the simulated election results,
in percent of seats in Sejm, for selected combinations of factors. (Table A I in
the Appendix gives a detailed list of results.)
The first observation is that if the 1993 elections had been run under
the 1991 electoral law, the post-communist Left would have ended up with
37% of seats and the post-Solidarity Right with 26.7%. Redistricting alone
(91 + R) would not have had much of an effect on this distribution. The most
likely political consequence would have been a coalition cabinet of the Center
and the Right with no post-communist participation at all. Since redistricting
would not have had much of an impact on the election results, regardless of
[221 ]
440
what other changes were or were not present, we only include results with the
new districting (R).
Our second observation is that redistricting plus either of the other two
factors (A or T) would have been sufficient to secure a post-communist Left
majority of seats (55.1% and 57% respectively). The Right would have also
increased the number of seats significantly 04.8% and 6.5% respectively)
though not sufficiently to block the takeover by the post-communist Left.
The most dramatic shift in the distribution of seats is due, however, to the
joint effect of all three factors (R + A + T). This resulted in the actual 65.9%
vs. 3.5% split of seats between the Left and the right in the 1993 elections.
6.2. The impact of removing Solidarity and Walesa Bloc from the political
scene
There seems to be an agreement among political analysts that by entering
the elections, Solidarity and Walesa Bloc weakened the Right by increasing
its already serious fragmentation and led to the Right's infamous electoral
failure. However, how strong was the effect of the emergence of the two
new players? What would have happened had Solidarity and Wales a Bloc not
entered the elections? As before, we can approximate the answer by looking
at the simulated results. 10 The effect, as it turns out, is both more complex and
more interesting that the "common sense" political analysis asserts. Figure 3
shows the percent distribution of seats with the two actors removed under
four auxiliary conditions. (Table A-2 in the Appendix gives a more detailed
list of results.)
Perhaps the most obvious observation that can be made from Figure 3 is
the surprisingly small effect of Solidarity and Walesa Bloc on the percent of
seats gained by the Left. It varies from the actual 65.9% of seats to 57.6%
in the worst case scenario; the best the Right could have done was 12%.
Yet, the most surprising observation is that the effect of the two new players
could have been opposite to the expected - the percent of seats gained by the
Right could have been smaller without Solidary and Walesa bloc present in
the elections! This is due to the fact that Walesa Bloc was the only Right party
that actually won any seats. The first simulation (SYMl) shows only 1.7% of
seats gained by the Right, as opposed to the actual 3.5%. (The Left would
have lost some seats, but not too many, a decline from 65.9% to 62%.)
There is a possible problem, however, with the estimates obtained in the
first simulation. The estimates have large standard errors (due to a small
sample size in the survey on second preferences) and the estimated popular
support of two parties of the Right, Centrum and Fatherland, came close to
the required thresholds. 11 Thus in the next three simulations we have assumed
that Centrum has (barely) crossed the threshold (SYM2), that Fatherland has
[222]
441
62
SEATS
SYM 1
Post-Communists
SYM2
•
SYM3
SYM4
Post-Soiidarity Right
Figure 3. The impact of the two new entrants. "Seats" stands for the percent of seats received
in the 1993 elections. All simulations assume that Solidarity and Walesa Bloc did not participate in the elections. In addition, SYM 2 assumes that Centrum has (barely) crossed the
threshold, SYM 3, that Fatherland has (barely) crossed the threshold, and SYM 4 that both
Centrum and Fatherland have (barely) crossed the thresholds.
(barely) crossed the threshold (SYM3) and that both Centrum and Fatherland
have (barely) crossed the thresholds (SYM4). Very much like the first simulation (SYM I) these three scenarios would have affected the power of the
Right in a very limited way. In the best case scenario, the Right would have
obtained 12% of the seats while the Left would have ended with 57.6%. In
each case the Left maintains the majority in the Sejm while the power of the
Right does not significantly change. Going against the common beliefs, our
results show that the entry of Solidarity and Walesa Bloc would not have had
much of an effect on the final distribution of power.
6.3. The importance of the coalitional failure of the Right
The last effect that remains to be assessed is that of the failure of the Right to
enter the 1993 elections as a united coalition. This failure to coalesce has been
widely blamed for the electoral failure of the Right. As it turns out, results of
our simulations support the folk wisdom. As opposed to the latter, however,
the simulation shows the estimated magnitude of the effect. The results are
displayed in Figure 4.
If six rightist parties were to form a single coalition what part of the supporters of the six separate parties would have voted for the united coalition?
While the answer is not clear, a standard simplifying assumption, that of the
additivity of votes casted for all parties of the coalition, seems to be the
most likely scenario. While there are reasons to believe that a united right
[223]
442
65.9
J47.6L
1J32L
35.4
3.5
SEATS
90%
Posl-Communists
100%
110%
Post-50lidarily Right
Figure 4. The impact of the Right's failure to coalesce. "Seats" stands for the percent of seats
received in the 1993 elections. All the other numbers represent the percentages of seats in
elections simulated under the assumption that the Right coalesced and the vote for the coalition
was additive (100%), 10% more than additive (l1O%), and 10% less than additive (90%).
would have both lost some voters and gained some, there are no reasons to
believe that one of the two effects would have turned out to be significantly
stronger than the other. Hence our first simulation in Figure 4 labeled 100%
was run under this assumption. To assess the robustness of the result of this
simulation with respect to the assumption of additivity, we have run two other
simulations. The simulation labeled as 90% assumes 10% loss in votes as
compared to the vote under the additivity assumption and simulation labeled
110% assumes a 10% gain. In both cases we assume that the loss or the gain
is absorbed proportionally by all remaining parties. 12
Results turned out to be similar in all three simulations. The post-Solidarity
Right secures somewhere between 32 and 38.3% of the seats while the postcommunist Left gets between 44.1 and 47.6%. Consequently, the Left no
longer has the majority and the most likely scenario is a coalition cabinet
of the Center and the Right with no participation of the post-communists
parties. The second most likely scenario is a post-Solidarity coalition that
includes the Left Peasant party which was included as a junior partner in all
former post-Solidarity cabinets.
7. Conclusions
In this article, we have shown that the shift to the left in voters' preferences
was only one of a few factors in bringing the Left to power in the 1993 Polish
parliamentary elections. We have identified and analyzed three other factors
[224 ]
443
that had a significant impact on the course of events. Our simulations show
that under the old electoral law or with a grand coalition of the right, the electoral outcome would have been dramatically different. It is quite remarkable
that under the old electoral law, or under the united coalition of the Right, the
post-communist Left would have been most likely excluded from the cabinet.
Only the conjunction of the change in the electoral law, the coalitional failure
of the Right, and the increased electoral support for the post-communists
could have produced a post-communist controlled cabinet.
The key problem for the Right was the inability to cooperate. In part this
was a consequence of the absence of reliable procedures for the division
of future gains. Creating a coalition in a fragmented party system poses an
interesting mixture of game-theoretic and estimation problems for rational
players. These are formally addressed in a separate paper (Kaminski and
Gryz, 1997). Here, we will briefly describe the main aspects of the problem. The first issue to be resolved by members of a prospective coalition
is, what information should be taken into account to represent the power of
the members? The source of such information could be a carefully designed
poll. The second issue is to settle on a fair solution problem of dividing seats
among coalitional partners. In short, the problem is to identify the most preferred solution concept for the partition-function form games that is based
only on the available polls information. The solution would have to minimize
the incentives of the members to leave the coalition and would have to be
adopted by all members on the basis of some uniformly accepted principles.
Finally, the last problem is that of implementation. How should the solution
be implemented given the constraints of limited transferability of seats and
uncertain results of the elections? These are not only workable theoretical
problems, but important practical points that enter coalitional negotiations.
The science of politics can aid these decision processes significantly. The
problem of how to divide seats among coalition parties has continuous and
pressing significance for the Polish politics. Before the fall 1997 elections,
the post-Solidarity Right and one more pre-Solidarity rightist party managed
to create two large coalitions, and they are negotiating further merger. The
problem of the fair way to divide the pie continues to be the central issue.
Emerging political systems are highly sensitive to the details of their institutional backbones. Electoral laws, coalitional structures, existing survey
methodologies, or the timing of elections may strongly influence the results.
Under the 1989 electoral law in Poland, in the first semi-free elections in the
Soviet Bloc, Solidarity won 100% of the freely available seats 13 in the Sejm
with only about 70% of the popular vote. This unexpected victory contributed
decisively to the subsequent fall of the communist regimes in Eastern Central
Europe (Kaminski, forthcoming). Ironically, four years later the winners and
[225 ]
444
the losers, the wise men and the suckers, have switched places although their
total popular vote support has not changed too much.
Notes
1. Our naming convention is merely meant as a convenient shortcut in identifying the main
players. There are other than the post-communist leftist parties on the left of the Polish political scene. Hence, the label "Left" refers to the post-communist Left. Similarly,
the label "Right" denotes post-Solidarity Right parties not all parties on the right of the
political spectrum.
2. The following main changes were introduced in the new electoral law. A system of
country-level thresholds was established. For the 391 seats assigned in districts, the thresholds were 5% for parties and 8% for coalitions. For the 69 seats assigned from the national
list, the threshold was 7%. Minority parties or coalitions were granted the privilege of
having one of these thresholds, selected by them in advance, waived. The apportionment
method (the rule of turning the percentage of votes in a district to the number of seats in a
district) has been changed. The largest remainder, or Hamilton-Hare method with Droop
quota, was substituted by a divisor d'Hondt-Jefferson method. (For properties of the two
methods see Balinski and Young, 1982.) Finally, the 37 districts of the 1991 elections were
substituted by 52 districts. The average district magnitude (number of seats per district),
decreased from 10.6 to 7.3 (Dziennik Ustaw RP nr 45, 1993).
3. Full names of the parties were simplified to one- or two-word labels. Name changes,
minor coalitions, or minor mergers were neglected in the description in an effort to keep
the presentation simple. For the list of all major parties and coalitions, see the Appendix.
For the results of elections, see Table 4, columns "Votes" and "Seats".
4. PF games were introduced by Thrall (1962) under the name of "generalized characteristic
function form games". The name was later changed to PF-games by Thrall and Lucas
(1963).
5. Thrall (1962: 158) notes this possibility in his path-breaking paper: "In the political arena
[subadditive payoffs of two parties] might represent clashing ideologies ... in which an
open union would rather weaken support for both [... ]".
6. We assume a slightly more general concept of the PF here and allow that the coalition
structure be not exhaustive. For instance, the coalition structure with no party i denotes
the case of i withdrawing from the elections. Thus, players are interpreted as "potential'·
rather than "actual" players.
7. Recall that we use the label Right as a shortcut for the so called post -Solidarity Right.
8. Quoted in (Sulek, 1995). Sulek links the hostile opinions of politicians about surveys
with the low standings of their parties and assesses the overall performance of polling
agencies as good. In fact, CBOS reports bring many methodological caveats regarding
the interpretation of the results of their polls and discuss in detail possible biases.
9. The electoral law regulated political advertising. All main parties were allotted equal
time slots in the national and regional state-controlled TV and radio; paid advertising
was severely restricted.
10. The relevant fragment of the PF function was reconstructed with the use of two polls
reconstructing second preferences of the voters. The "omnibus" survey by SMG KRC
Poland was conducted in February 1994, and included a stratified non-random sample
of adults (N = 1000). The pre-electoral poll by CBOS was conducted on 27-29 August
[226]
445
1993, and included a representative sample of adults (N = 1104). Votes of the Walesa
Bloc and Solidarity supporters were transferred to other parties according to the distribution of second preferences for this group, adjusted for the biases detected in both
samples.
11. The estimate of the popular vote for Centrum was 4.42% and the threshold for this
political category (a party) in the elections was 5%. The estimate of the popular vote
for Fatherland was 7.7% and the threshold for this political category (a coalition) in the
elections was 8%.
12. Before the Fall 1997 elections, the Right Solidarity parties and one Rightist pre-Solidarity
party, the Confederates, have formed two large coalitions. The current polls (i.e., as of
May 1997) consistently show that the total support for both coalitions is at the level of
35%. This is close to the total of 32% of votes won by the Right and the Confederats
in the 1993 elections. Assuming that no significant changes have taken place in voters'
preferences, these results support the assumption of an approximate additivity of the votes
across members of a coalition. They also support a weaker hypothesis that coalescing does
not lead to a significant loss of votes (subadditivity). The weaker hypothesis was necessary
for the plausibility of our simulations.
13. The 1989 election was not yet fully democratic. 65% of the Sejm seats were guaranteed
to the candidates of the communist block.
References
Balinski, M. L. and Young, H. P. (1982). Fair representation. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
CBOS. (1993a). Preferencje polityczne spoleczenstwa trzy tygodnie przed wyborami
(BS/132/109/93). Warszawa: CBOS.
CBOS. (1993b). Preferencje wyborcze spoleczenstwa w lipcu '93 (BS/102/83/93). Warszawa:
CBOS.
Domanski, R. (1994). House effect w Polsce. Kultura i Spoleczenstwo 38: 69-84.
Dziennik U staw RP No 45. (1993). Ordynacja wyborcza do Sejmu Rzeczypospolitej Polskiej.
Warszawa: Urzad Rady Ministrow.
Gebethner, S. (1995). System wyborczy: Deformacja czy reprezentacja? In S. Gebethner
(Ed.), Wybory parlamentame 1991 i 1993 a polska scena polityczna, 9-48. Warszawa:
Wydawnictwo Sejmowe.
Gibson, J. and Cielecka, A. (1995). Economic influences on the political support for market
reform in post-communist transitions: Some evidence from the 1993 Polish parliamentary
elections. Europe-Asia Studies, 47: 765-785.
Hinich, M. J. and Munger, M. C. (1994). Ideology and the theory of political choice. Ann
Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.
Kaminski, M. M. (1994). Coalitional structures, Duverger's law, and 'split-merger stability'
hypothesis. Mimeo. IRIS Working Paper No. 108.
Kaminski, M. M. (1997). How communism could have been saved: Formal analysis of
electoral bargaining in Poland in 1989. Public Choice, forthcoming.
Kaminski, M. M. and Gryz, J. (1997). Koalicje wyborcze: Lekcja 1993 roku. In J. Wasilewski
(Ed.), Zbiorowi aktorzy polskiej polityki. Warszawa: ISP PAN (forthcoming).
Monitor Polski No. 50. (1993). Obwieszczenia Panstwowej Komisji Wyborczej, 610-799.
Warszawa: Urzad Rady Ministrow.
[227 ]
446
Racz, B. and Kukorelli, I. (1995). The 'second-generation' post-communist elections in
Hungary in 1994. Europe-Asia Studies 47: 251-279.
Sulek, A. (1995). Do czego sluza sondaze? Wykorzystanie badan opinii publicznej w kampanii
wyborczej 1993. Kultura i Spoleczenstwo 38: 103-117.
Thrall, R. M. (1962). Generalized characteristic functions for n-person games. In Recent
advances in game theory, 157-160. Princeton: Princeton University Conferences.
Thrall, R. M. and Lucas, W. F. (1963). n-person games in partition function form. Naval
Research Logistics Quarterly 10: 281-298.
Tworzecki, H. (1994). The Polish parliamentary elections of 1993. Electoral Studies 13: 180185.
Zubek, v. (1994). The reassertion of the left in post-communist Poland. Europe-Asia Studies
46: 801-837.
Appendix
Polish full names and common acronyms of major parties/coalitions in 1993 elections:
Centrum
Porozumienie Centrum (PC)
Fatherland
Right Peasants
KKW "Ojczyzna"
Polskie Stronnictwo Ludowe-Porozumienie
Confederats
Ludowe (PSL-PL)
Konfederacja Polski Niepodleglej (KPN)
Post-communists
Left Peasants
Liberal Democrats
Solidarity
Sojusz Lewicy Demokratycznej (SLD)
Polskie Stronnictwo Ludowe (PSL)
Kongres Liberalno-Demokratyczny (KLD)
Solidarnosc
Unia Demokratyczna (UD)
Democrats
Walesa Bloc
Bezpartyjny Blok Wspierania Reform (BBWR)
Labour
Unia Pracy (UP)
Libertarians
Unia Polityki Realnej (UPR)
Movement
Koalicja dla Rzeczypospolitej (KdR)
Party "X"
Partia"X"
Polish Convention
Konwencja Polska
Self-defense
German Minority
Samoobrona
Towarzystwo Spoleczno-Kulturalne Mniejszosci
Niemieckiej na Slasku Opolskim
[228]
447
Table A1. Actual and simulated results of 1993 elections under various electoral laws
Votes
Party/coalition
Seats
93
91 +R+T
91 +R+A
91 +R
91 a
26.2
3.5
6.5
14.8
24.5
26.8
Fatherland
6.4
0.0
0.0
5.2
8.7
8.3
Centrum
Movement
Right Peasants
4.4
2.7
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
2.0
0.9
3.0
1.5
4.6
0.9
WalesaBloc
2.4
5.4
0.0
3.5
0.0
6.5
0.4
3.5
1.7
4.6
5.9
Solidarity
4.9
0.0
0.0
2.8
5.0
5.4
21.9
25.0
28.7
21.6
25.2
23.3
4.0
10.6
0.0
16.1
0.0
17.0
2.2
12.2
3.0
12.6
3.3
11.5
7.3
8.9
11.7
7.2
9.6
8.5
35.8
65.9
57.1
55.1
37.6
37.0
Post-communists
20.4
37.2
21.3
20.9
15.4
28.7
32.8
24.3
30.1
Left Peasants
25.0
16.3
16.1
13.1
7.4
Post-Solidarity
Right (total)
Post-Solidarity Left
1.7
and Center (total)
Liberal Democrats
Democrats
Labor
Post-communist
Left (total)
Other (total)
15.2
5.7
7.6
7.8
12.7
Confederats
5.8
4.8
6.7
4.8
7.2
Libertarians
German Minority
3.2
0.7
0.0
1.1
2.2
0.9
0.0
0.9
0.6
0.9
Party "X"
Self-defense
2.7
2.8
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.4
0.9
1.3
1.1
2.2
0.9
0.9
1.7
aSource: Gebethner (1995).
[229 ]
448
Table A2. Actual and simulated results of 1993 elections under the assumption of the trade union Solidarity and Walesa Bloc not entering the
contest
Party/coalition
Seats
SYMI
SYM2
SYM3
SYM4
Post-Solidarity
0.0
1.7
4.1
10.0
12.0
0.0
1.7
1.7
10.0
10.0
Right (total)
Fatherland
Centrum
0.0
0.0
2.4
0.0
2.0
Movement
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
Right Peasants
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
25.0
30.4
29.8
27.1
26.1
0.0
16.1
3.9
16.1
2.8
15.0
2.4
14.8
8.9
10.4
3.7
15.9
10.2
9.3
8.9
65.9
62.0
60.9
58.0
57.6
Post-communists
37.2
33.0
32.4
28.7
29.0
28.5
31.5
26.5
31.3
Left Peasants
5.7
4.8
0.0
0.9
0.0
0.0
5.5
4.6
0.0
0.9
0.0
0.0
5.2
4.3
0.0
0.9
0.0
0.0
4.8
3.9
0.0
0.9
0.0
0.0
4.4
3.7
0.0
0.7
0.0
0.0
Post-Solidarity Left
and Center (total)
Liberal Democrats
Democrats
Labor
Post-communist
Left (total)
Other (total)
Confederats
Libertarians
German Minority
Party "X"
Self-defense
[230}
26.3
449
Table A3. Actual and simulated results of 1993 elections
under the assumption of a united PSR coalition including
Centrum, Fatherland, Right Peasants, Movement, the trade
union Solidarity, and Walesa Bloc
Party/coalition
Seats
90%
100%
110%
Post-Solidarity
3.5
32.0
35.4
38.3
25.0
17.0
15.5
14.6
0.0
Right coalition
Post-Solidarity Left
and Center (total)
Liberal Democrats
Democrats
Labor
Post-communist Left
0.0
0.0
0.0
16.1
11.3
10.7
9.8
8.9
5.7
4.8
4.8
65.9
47.6
45.8
44.1
37.2
28.7
27.4
20.2
26.5
19.3
25.6
18.5
5.7
4.8
3.5
2.8
0.0
3.0
2.6
0.0
(total)
Post-communists
Left Peasants
0.0
0.9
0.7
3.2
2.8
0.0
0.4
Party "X"
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
Self-defense
0.0
0.0
0.0
0.0
Other (total)
Confederats
Libertarians
German Minority
0.4
[231]
Public Choice 97: 451-474, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
451
A spatial analysis of candidate competition in dual member
districts: The 1989 Chilean senatorial elections *
JAYK.DOW
Department of Political Science, University of Missouri-Columbia, 113 Professional
Building, Columbia, MO 65211, U.S.A.; e-mail: polscdow@showme.missouri.edu
Abstract. This study uses empirical spatial theory to evaluate candidate and voter behavior
in senate elections contested during the 1989 Chilean general election. The study evaluates
whether senatorial candidates competing in dual member districts under Chilean d'Hondt
locate near the periphery or interior of the electoral space. Spatial analyses demonstrate the
Chilean senatorial electoral system is characterized by centrifugal forces. In particular, candidates of the right locate on the periphery of the space and face few incentives to pursue
moderate electoral strategies. The study also characterizes bases of party and candidate support and the underlying dimensions of political competition. Spatial analysis reveals both
change and continuity in the pre- and post-authoritarian electoral universes.
1. Introduction
Spatial models of voter choice are instrumental in the modem study of elections (Black, 1958; Downs, 1957; Enelow and Hinich, 1984; Enelow and
Hinich, 1990; Hinich and Munger, 1994, 1996; Rabinowitz and Macdonald,
1989). Despite this, empirical spatial theory has largely been confined to the
study of United States presidential elections. Laver and Schofield (1990),
Schofield et al. (1988), Schofield (1988), Adams and Merrill III (1988a), use
spatial theory to study party government in European parliamentary democracies. In addition, Macdonald, Rabinowitz, and Listhaug (Macdonald et al.,
1991; Macdonald et al., 1995; Rabinowitz et al., 1991), Merrill (1994, 1995),
Iversen (1994) and Adams and Merrill III (1988b) have recently completed
spatial analyses of Western European party systems, but these studies primarily seek to evaluate alternative model specifications rather than provide
substantive interpretations of particular elections.
* I thank Jorge Gonzalez, Larry Graham, Mel Hinich, Jeanne Kinney, Bob Luskin and Mike
Munger for helpful comments on this paper. I am responsible for all errors. This research was
partially supported by National Science Foundation grant SES-9022930
[233 ]
452
This study provides a spatial analysis of four senate elections contested
during the December 1989 Chilean general election. The Chilean electoral
system possesses several characteristics which make it extremely valuable
for spatial analysis. Most important, Chile has an institutionalized multiparty
system in which senators are elected from dual member districts under a
form of d'Hondt proportional representation. Under Chilean d'Hondt at least
some candidates have incentives to locate away from the ideal point of the
median voter. This study seeks to evaluate expectations of candidate behavior
by estimating spatial maps of the senatorial elections using a metric scaling methodology that locates voters and candidates in the same space. The
Chilean elections also derive significance by presenting a rare opportunity
to study party competition in a transitional election. The 1988 plebiscite on
the continuation ofPinochet's rule notwithstanding, the 1989 general election
marked the restoration of civil affairs in one of the most long-lived twentieth
century dictatorships in the Western Hemisphere. The maps provide information useful for interpreting party competition in the transitional election and
the relationship between the pre- and post-authoritarian periods.
2. Chilean senatorial elections
The December 1989 Chilean election was initiated by Augusto Pinochet's
loss in the 1988 plebiscite on the continuation of his rule. Under terms of
the Chilean constitution, the military junta which governed Chile since the
September 1973 overthrow of Socialist President Salvador Allende called
for elections the following year. Chilean political parties, free to organize
and campaign, contested the election in two broad coalitions: The centerleft Concertacion de los Partidos por la Democracia (CPD) coalition of
seventeen parties which led the fight against Pinochet in the 1988 plebiscite
and the rightist Democracia y Progreso (DP) coalition consisting primarily of the Independent Democratic Union (UDI) of nominally independent
presidential candidate Heman Buchi and the National Renewal (RN) party.
The latter parties were closely associated with the Pinochet regime. Chilean
political parties, despite military rule from 1973 to 1989, remain among the
strongest and most developed in the world (Valenzuela, 1985; Valenzuela and
Valenzuela, 1985; Caviedes, 1991; Scully 1992; Walker, 1993).
The election was largely a victory for the Concertacion and its leading Christian Democratic Party (PDq. Christian Democrat Patricio Aylwin
won the presidency over Buchi and independent candidate Francisco Errazuriz, and, through the election of Christian Democrats and members of the
Concertacion, secured working majorities in both chambers of the Chilean
legislature. 2 There exists a general consensus that the election was fair and
[234 ]
453
that turnout and return figures are accurate (Angell and Pollack, 1990; Scully,
1995).
The Chilean Senate consists of forty-seven members, thirty-eight of whom
are elected from dual member districts. The remaining nine senators are
appointed. 3 I study elections contested in the two Santiago senatorial districts,
a district encompassing the costal cities of Valparaiso and Vina del Mar, and
the district allocated to the south-central Sixth Administrative Region. 4 Approximately one-third of the Chilean electorate lives within the two Santiago
districts. Similarly, a disproportionate number of voters live in the Valparaiso
- Vina del Mar area. The agricultural Sixth Region is south of Santiago and
its principle city is Rancagua.
Parties contest legislative elections - the electoral system is the same for
the Senate and the 120 member lower chamber - by forming alliances and
presenting a joint list of up to two candidates in each district. Citizens receive
a single vote that is cast directly for candidates. The d'Hondt rule allocates
legislative seats by successively dividing each coalition's vote by integers up
to the number of available appointments. Seats are then distributed in order
of quotient size. Under the Chilean variant the first seat is awarded to the
candidate with the most votes on the list with the largest combined plurality.
If the combined vote of candidates on this list is two-thirds of the votes cast,
then both candidates on the list win seats. Otherwise, the second seat goes to
the candidate with the most votes on the list with the second largest combined
plurality (Angell and Pollack, 1990; Angell, 1990).5
The military regime adopted these rules to give parties incentives to form
broad coalitions and to give disproportionate representation to the minority
parties - understood to be those of the right - in each district. Parties are
encouraged to coalesce because the allocation of seats is a function of both
individual vote receipts and the combined pluralities of a list. Consequently,
a majority party candidate is not likely hurt by a coalition partner so long as
he or she ranks first in vote receipts. Further, parties increase the likelihood
of securing a legislature more to their liking by forming a coalition with
like-minded parties. Disproportionate representation for the minority list is
secured because to win both seats a coalition's plurality must be at least
twice that of the next closest list. Not only is this unlikely, but it is possible
that the second candidate on the majority list may receive more votes than the
leading candidate on minority list and still not win a seat. This occurred in the
Santiago-Poniente election in which right-wing candidate Jaime Guzman of
the Union of Independent Democrats (UDI) was elected to the second district
seat despite having obtained just over half vote share of Ricardo Lagos of the
Party for Democracy (PPD). Similarly, in the Valparaiso - Vina del Mar elec-
[235 ]
454
tion UDI candidate Beltran Urenda won the second seat with approximately
sixty percent of the plurality received by Christian Democrat Juan Hamilton. 6
Each map presents the estimated spatial locations of the four Concertacion and Democracia y Progreso candidates, the major Concertacion and
Democracia y Progreso parties, the Chilean Communist Party (PPCh) and the
Concertacion de los partidos por la Democracia. The scaled Concertacion
parties are the Christian Democratic Party (PDC), the party for Democracy
(PPD) and the Socialist Party (PS). Democracia y Progreso parties scaled
are the Union of Independent Democrats (UDI) and the National Renovation
Party (RN). These five parties secured a combined total of 85 percent of the
seats in the House of Deputies, the lower chamber of the Chilean legislature.
The Chilean Communist Party, which was not a member of the Concertacion and did not obtain legislative representation, is included because of
its traditional significance in Chilean electoral politics. The Concertacion is
scaled because it is an umbrella organization encompassing several political
organizations otherwise not considered in the analysis. Most of the senatorial
elections were contested by other lists, but these were not generally competitive. In the elections considered in this study, the combined plurality of the
two major coalitions averaged eighty-eight percent? Appendix I overviews
the political parties included in this study.
3. Theoretical expectations
Spatial analyses demonstrate that the centralizing tendencies of the two candidate model do not typically hold under multicandidate elections (Downs,
1957: 120-124; Hinich and Ordeshook, 1970; Palfrey, 1984; Greenberg and
Weber, 1985; Greenberg and Shepsle, 1987; Cox, 1987, 1990a, 1990b; Shepsle, 1991). The primary conclusion from this literature is that multicandidate
eqUilibrium generally do not exist. When multicandidate eqUilibria can be
supported they are typically non-central in that at least some candidates locate
away from the median voter ideal point. These equilibria, however, are often
sensitive to model specification.
Before characterizing expected candidate behavior under Chilean d'Hondt
a brief note regarding candidate objectives is in order. That citizens vote
for candidates rather than lists introduces very strong incentives for candidates to compete directly for votes even at the expense of coalition partners.
Intracoalition competition was indeed evident. For example, in the SantiagoOriente election Democracia y Progreso candidate Sebastian Pinera and
Hermogenes Perez de Arce campaigned almost as much against each other
as the opposition (Angell and Pollack, 1990). Further, rather than maximizing votes per se, candidates may instead seek maximize rank finish within
[236 ]
455
a coalition since it is unlikely that a coalition's vote share will exceed twothirds of the ballot cast. Only in the Sixth, Seventh and Twelfth Regions did
the Concertacion win both senate seats. This further exacerbates the tendency
for coalition partners to compete against each other.
The scarcity of multicandidate equilibria and expectations for the Chilean
Senate elections can be illustrated using a very simple spatial representation.
Consider a bounded, uni-dimensional electoral space which, for the sake of
simplicity, is set equal to the unit interval. Also assume that voters are distributed uniformly across the space and cast a single ballot for the closest of
four candidates (AI A2, BI B2). This corresponds to most Chilean Senatorial elections which were typically contested by four major candidates; two
representing the Concertacion and two representing Democracia y Progreso.
Cox (1990b), building on Eaton and Lipsey (1975), outlines the motivation
for a non-central equilibria illustrated in Example I in which four candidates
compete for a single seat. Here the candidate pairing at the outer quartiles
of the space is a Nash eqUilibrium as no candidate has a unilateral incentive
to relocate as doing so results in a loss in expected plurality. In this example
each candidate has an equal probability of winning the seat.
Example 1
I
o
I
I
Regardless of whether candidates are vote or rank maximizers, neither a
centralized eqUilibrium nor the non-central pairing result of Example I is
supported under Chilean d'Hondt. Considering Example I again and holding
constant the positions of all candidates except, for example, A 2 ; if candidate
A2 moves to the right up to position 3/4 her plurality remains unchanged
(always 25%) with the remaining votes in the interval redistributed from
candidate BI to candidate AI. Despite her constant plurality, candidate A2
faces incentives to move to the right as any location in the interval (7112, 3/4)
will guarantee the "1\' coalition at least two-thirds of the vote; hence not only
her election but that of her coalition partner as well.
More generally, Cox (1990b) shows that with vote maximizing candidates,
if the number of votes allotted citizens is less than twice the district magnitude, there is no convergent equilibrium and some candidates will locate away
from the ideal point of the median voter. Indeed, four candidate equilibrium
degenerate as the distribution of voters changes from uniform to a more plausible unimodal distribution. If candidates seek to maximize ranked placement
within the coalition, as seems likely in Chilean legislative elections, Denzau,
[237]
456
Kats, and Slutsky (1985), and Greenberg and Shepsle (1987) demonstrate
multi-agent equilibria are exceedingly rare and candidates should be dispersed across the electoral space. In either case, one expects centrifugal forces
to dominate candidate strategies in Chilean legislative elections and at least
some candidates to locate away from the ideal point of the median voter. 8
One might expect coalitions to pair strong and weak candidates to give
the strongest candidate more latitude in pursuing electoral strategies. The
balanced lists in all districts demonstrate this strategy was not generally
followed. In the four elections considered in this study the inter-coalitional
pluralities differed by an average of less than six percent, and this is heavily
weighted by the single lopsided Concertacion ticket in Santiago-Oriente in
which Eduardo Frei won approximately forty-one percent of the district vote.
Of the seven remaining lists, the intra-coalition vote shares in five differed
by less than two percent. In Santiago-Poniente, for example, the pluralities
received by Concertacion candidates Lagos and Zaldivar differed by less than
8500 of the over 800,000 votes cast for the list. Comparable intra-coalition
vote differences are found in the Concertacion and Democracy and Progress
lists in Valparaiso - Vina del Mar, the Concertacion list in Region Six and the
Santiago-Poniente Democracy and Progress list. Simply, as measured by aggregate vote receipts, each list presented two viable candidates. The plurality
received by each candidate is presented in the maps.
4. Data and methodology
The data used to estimate the spatial maps are seven point candidate and
party evaluation scores obtained from cross sectional surveys conducted using in person interviews in each of the four senatorial districts. The polls
completed in the last half of October, 1989, and average just over 600 respondents. Scores were obtained for all major candidates and political parties.
In addition, the surveys solicited respondent self-placement on a left-right
ideological scale and demographic information useful for interpreting the
maps.9
The spatial maps locate candidates, parties and voters in the same space,
and are estimated using a metric scaling methodology described by Cahoon,
Hinich, and Ordeshook (1978), Enelow and Hinich (1984), Endersby and
Hinich (1992) and Lin et al. (1996). Scaling methodologies and evaluation
scores are commonly used to estimate Euclidian representations of elections
(Weisberg and Rusk, 1970; Rusk and Weisberg, 1972; Rabinowitz, 1978;
Davis, 1984; Poole and Rosenthal, 1984; Enelow and Hinich, 1984; Brady,
1990; Endersby and Hinich, 1992), although some researchers (Aldrich and
McKelvey, 1977; Enelow, 1986, 1988; Enelow and Hinich, 1989, 1994) use
[238]
457
perceptual data, consisting of voter self and candidate placement on issue
scales, and factor analytic procedures for the same purpose. The details of the
methodology are presented in Enelow and Hinich (1984: Appendix 9.1). For
this reason the following discussion is brief.
The statistical methodology assumes the i-th voter's evaluation score for
candidate j, Tij, measures the spatial distance between the respondent and
candidate. Specifically:
where:
njk is candidate j's location on dimension, k, Xik is voter's 1's location on
the same axis and eij captures unmeasurable, non-systematic influences on
Tij and is distributed independently across voters and candidates. The survey
question soliciting Tij translates as:
Thinking of you and your family'S well-being, how do you evaluate the
following personalities as senator? Respond on a scale of 1 to 7 where 1
is very bad and 7 is very good.
The corresponding question for political parties is similarly phrased.
The statistical problem is to use the observed Tij to estimate n jk and X ik .
Once these parameters are estimated one may use a variety of internal and
external measures of validity to assess the quality of the maps. As Brady
(1991) notes, estimating njk and X ik is non-trivial because Tij is non-linear
in each parameter and restrictions must be imposed on the model to identify
and estimate its parameters.
The estimation method proceeds as follows. Consider an election with i =
L.n voters andj = L.p + 1 candidates and parties. Two data transformations
are used to make the observations linear in nj and Xi. First, the scores of a
preselected candidate or party, T ip +!, are squared and then subtracted from
the other similarly adjusted Tij scores. From this difference is subtracted the
difference between each candidate's average score and the mean Ti across
respondents. The choice of the candidate Tip +! is mathematically arbitrary,
but interpreting and comparing the maps is easier if the candidate represents
the status quo and is the same in each map. To this end, the centrist Christian
Democratic party is the p + 1 party in all maps and its location is defined
to be the origin of the space. This means the estimated positions of all other
candidates and parties are relative to the PDC.
The statistical methodology uses the variation in the transformed scores to
estimate candidate and voter positions in the predictive space. The first step
in the estimation procedure is to calculate the maximum likelihood factor
[239]
458
LD,
analysis of the sample covariance matrix,
of the transformed scores.
This produces, up to an arbitrary rotation, an estimate of the candidate and
party positions in the predictive space. to Parameters of the model still to be
estimated including the angle of rotation of the axes are obtained by two
least squares regressions, the elements of which are detailed in Enelow and
Hinich (1984: Appendix 9.1). Finally, the candidate positions are used in a
least squares regression with dependent variable Tie - Tip+1 to estimate voter
location, p, the predictive space. In the two dimensional case, this regression
is:
where
JLj = eij - eip+l·
The statistical methodology estimates a cartesian representation of the
positions of candidates and parties on the defined axes. Few measures of
statistical fit have been developed to assess the quality of spatial representations. Poole and Rosenthal (1984) propose the squared Pearson correlation
coefficient between the observed thermometer scores used to estimate their
spatial maps and those predicted by the recovered maps. This statistic, however, may overstate the quality of the spatial representation because the same
data is used to estimate and evaluate the spatial maps. I use two measures
of model fit in the same spirit as that proposed by Poole and Rosenthal, but
not subject to the same concern. The first is the Pearson correlation coefficient
between estimated voter axis location and voter self-placement on a five point
left (1) to right (5) ideological scale. This statistic, reported in the maps as p,
has two virtues. First, respondent ideological self-placement is not used in the
statistical methodology and provides something of an independent check on
the maps. If the estimated axes accurately reflects the electoral space, then one
expects voter location to be highly correlated with ideological views. Second,
because only p observations are used to estimate each voter's spacial location,
the voter ideal points are somewhat noisy and, arguably, the weakest link in
the methodology. If, despite this, one recovers strong statistical measures of
fit based on the estimated voter locations, one is justified in placing considerable confidence in the spatial representation. The second set of statistics used
to assess the quality of the spatial maps are obtained from a logistic regression
in which the dependent variable indicates whether the respondent anticipates
voting for a Concertacion (coded 1), or Democracy y Progreso (coded 0) candidate, and the single independent variable is estimated voter spatial location.
The few voters expressing an intention to vote for other coalition candidates
are treated as missing values. The logit analysis provides a simple means to
[240]
459
assess the extent to which spatial location accounts for voter choice. Statistics
reported with these regressions include the percentage of anticipated vote that
is correctly predicted and several other standard measures of model fit.
I estimated both one and two dimensional maps of the Chilean Senate
elections, although only the single dimensional results are presented and
discussed. The one dimensional maps are most appropriate for comparing
expected candidate behavior derived from spatial analyses of multicandidate
elections and observed candidate and voter behavior in the Chilean senatorial
elections. The second dimension also added only marginally to the fit of the
maps as measured by these statistics. Construction of the covariance matrix
of adjusted scores requires that respondents assign evaluation scores to all
scaled candidates and parties. Approximately 35% of all respondents were
able to do this, but this figure is influenced by the lower response rate in
Valparaiso - Vina del Mar. In the remaining districts the percentage of respondents able to assign evaluation scores to be scaled candidates and parties
is comparable to that typically found in established democracies. Consistent
with what one would expect in polity with a strong party system, the vast
majority of missing values are due to voters failing to assign evaluation scores
to candidates rather than parties. In the four senate elections, an average of
67% of respondents could assign evaluation scores to be seven scaled parties,
while only 40% could do the same for the four Concertacion and Democracy and Progress candidates. In Appendix 2, I provide summary statistics
for several respondent demographic characteristics for both the full survey
sample and the scaled subsamples. Although respondents scaled in the maps
are of slightly higher social class and better educated than those in the full survey sample, the selection mechanism introduces few systematic biases in the
types of respondents scaled in the maps. The number of scaled respondents is
reported with each map.
5. The spatial maps
5.1. Introduction and overview
I present the candidate maps in Figures 1-4 and review them simultaneously.
All were estimated for a one-dimensional solution and scale properly as evidence by p which exceeds 0.56 in all maps. I list the senatorial candidates,
their party affiliations and pluralities above each map. The election winners
are denoted by italics. I also present the standard deviation of the estimated
voter ideal points on the axis and label the median ideal point (Xm) in the
maps. The vertical axis measures the estimated density of the voter ideal
points. I I In all districts the distribution of voters exhibits a major node near
[241]
460
Moria II. c ........ Me Uadt)
t
tt ~:t"'-
JII.O
_TrII.
IIr,PDC!)
H_ _
doAno,BPtladm
4L1
14.1
_I'IMro,BPU""tt)
Il.8
Canc:orlacl... eondld.1o
Coadldolo
8D: - . . . _ _ oroollmolool _ _ poIDlo OD..-....I uiI.
u
u
u
n
U
i
-II
-0
-II
I
-IJ
rPllrra.
,II;'"
I
-J.t
l1li
... IJIII
I
I
PIJC
i
..II
-u
U
IF
BP.i U
i
U
J.t
IJ
II
0
II
II
U
U
iAA-R/Pl AlII
Figure 1. Santiago-Oriente.
the ideal point of the median voter and most maps display one or more secondary nodes near the periphery of the space. There are several noticeable
differences in the shapes of the four estimated densities. For example, the
distribution of voters in the Santiago districts tends to be flatter than those in
Vina del Mar and Region VI.
The estimated candidate and party locations present clear left-right alignments on the recovered axis. Parties scale in the expected order, with the
Christian Democratic Party located to the right of the other Concertacion parties and the Union of Independent Democrats consistently on the far right of
the space. In all districts except Valparaiso - Vina del Mar, the PDC is clearly
seen as distinct from the other Concertacion parties, but in relationship to the
distribution of voters these differences are relatively minor.
The Communist placement is the only possible exception to be natural
order on the left-right axis. In all districts except Region VI the Socialists
and the Party for Democracy scale to the left of the Communists. This would
be expected in Chile prior to the military coup as through most of its history the Communist Party was more moderate than the Socialist Party and
sought to achieve its political objectives through the electoral process (Gill,
1966; Burnett, 1970; Faundez, 1988; Garreton, 1989). This commitment to
moderation was undermined during the military regime when an important
faction, the Frente Patriotico Manuel Rodriguez, resorted to political violence
[242]
461
N-S""
P .0.80
BDVolerldoolPolDIc UO
29.8
29.2
14.8
18.4
And,... Zaidi...,.. ItZ (POCf)
RI..",. La.... RL(PPDtl
M1ruel Ote... MO (RNlt)
Joj_ 0 _ JO(1JDlttl
t
ConCt'rldc:ion Candidate
It De"""....10 y ,.,.".... CaDdidate
SD: Stondard d.... " . . .r ..Umated ...tor Idool polnte.n _ered ula.
u
u
PrIIrrao
PI
I
0.0
-II
-11
-1.0
-1.1
ij
Iiij J.
PUC
All
IlL
-u -OJ
to
Ji
OJ
1.1
LO
10
1.6
LD
III
I
\JIll
\
110
III
to
1.6
U
11
Figure 2. Santiago-Poniente.
N.I03
p.O.8'l
BIW..... ldool Poln.. lL81
ClUldld.tcund
Juan Hamilton, JH (Poct)
LaumBoto,lB(INDtl
8.lIran U..ndG, BU (UDItt)
Oonzelo Yuooer. OY (RNtl)
~ofV_
t
tt
27.3
'ZI.7
16.8
18.&
Com:ertocion Candidate
De....raci. y ,.,.",... C.ndidate
aD: Standard dnlalion or estimated "tar Ideal poiDta OD rec:mered axil.
o.a
pro rrao
i ~IJaT
0.0
-u
-1.6
-1.0
III
I
~
i
-u -u -u
IR
II
u
u
10
\JIll
GJ
1.6
II
!
I I
I1U
to
u
II
lAI\-RItht AlIa
Figure 3. Valparaiso - Vina del Mar.
[243 ]
462
N.I83
p.O.18
8DVoIAIr ...... PaInIoI1.17
CMd__
-..arv",",
!=:.'"1~fIm)
NICIJI.. DIa,NDIPDCIl
28.0
::9..
II....... v....... IIV (INDft)
t
Cnnatinc:iOlll o.nd......
II
Oem_:l"""" ean.J....'. , _.... _ _I poID'- DB _
SO: 1IIaad........_
u
.... _ .
u
u
fIG
...
I",
u
1ft
1
Ii
AI
-u -u -u -u -u
I
1jII'
lID
u
u
Ii
u
u
u
u
u
II\'
u
,
MU
' ,
10
u
u
u
LIA-1IIIId Alii
Figure 4. Region VI - O'Higgins.
culminating in a 1986 attempt on Pinochet's life, leading to the exclusion
of the Communist Party from the Concertacion. Likewise, the Socialist
Party moderated its stands toward civil affairs as reflected in its inclusion
in the Concertacion. The Communist-Socialist placements demonstrate these
changes in policies and tactics are not necessarily reflected in mass political
perceptions during early transitional periods, and voters perceive important
continuities with the pre-authoritarian political universe.
As one expects in a strong party system, candidates scale very close to
their respective parties and coalitions. In the Santiago districts Democracia
y Progreso candidates Guzman, Perez de Arce, Otero and Pinera scale to
the far right near the RN and UOI parties. Likewise, Christian Democratis
Eduardo Frei, Juan Hamilton and Nicolas Diaz are nearly adjacent to the
PDC locations in the recovered maps. Similar candidate-party proximity is
recovered for PPD candidate Ricardo Lagos in Santiago-Poniente and RN
candidates Gonzalo Yussef in Valparaiso - Vina del Mar and Alfonso Orueta
in Region VI. Independent members of the Concertacion and Democracia
y Progreso also scale quite close to those parties with which they are most
clearly associated.
Valenzuela and Valenzuela (1986), building on Lipset and Rokkan (1967)
and Sartori (1976) argue, "the political landscape is more or less impermeable to change once it has been established" and the effect of repressing
[244 ]
463
political actors as during the military regime is to hold parties and major
political figures in the positions they occupied during the democratic period.
The recovered Communist-Socialist placement, and the relative proximity of
candidates - especially those who rose to positions of party leadership before
the September 1973 coup - to associated political parties substantiates this
argument. The candidate-party placements closely resemble what one would
expect prior to the cessation of civil affairs, attesting to the strength of the
Chilean party system.
Table 1 presents the results of the logit regressions in which the dependent
variable indicates whether the respondent anticipates voting for Concertacion
or Democracy y Progreso candidate, and the single independent variable is
voter spatial location. The table reports the percentage of anticipated vote
that is correctly predicted by voter spatial location, a pseudo R 2 defined as 1InLpllnFR where InLp is the log-likelihood of the full model and InLR is the
log-likelihood of the model estimated with intercept only, and the likelihood
ratio statistic. The latter two statistics provide overall measures of model fit. I
also report the results of a second logistic analysis in which anticipated voter
choice is regressed on respondent spatial location, ideological self-placement
and several demographic characteristics. The latter regressions aid in interpreting the estimated maps and place the quality of the spatial representation
in perspective. To permit comparisons across the two sets of regressions, each
is estimated using the sample of respondents for whom there exist a complete
set of observations on the full set of independent variables.
The parameter estimates in Table I further confirm the maps accurately
reflect voter perceived relations among candidates and parties in the Chilean
Senate elections. In all districts the logit coefficient for axis location is statistically significant and in the correct direction. Respondent location in the
recovered space correctly predicts an average of about 92% of anticipated
vote choice between the two major coalitions. This, in conjunction with the
pseudo R 2 ,s and likelihood ratio statistics, verify the estimated maps capture
the salient characteristics of the election.
Detailed cross map comparison beyond candidate order on the recovered
axes are problematic because there is not absolute origin in the space. The political meaning of being a centrist in Valparaiso - Vina del Mar, for example,
may different considerably from what it means to be a centrist in the Santiago
districts or Region VI, and it is impossible to decipher these differences from
the maps alone. Consequently, cross district comparisons of the effect of a
change in spatial location on voter behavior as measured from a fixed point,
say the origin or the median voter ideal point, convey little useful information.
Nonetheless, since the scales on which the spatial positions are based are the
same across districts, comparisons of differences in positions are likely in-
[245 ]
464
Table 1. Logistic regression of voter choice by voter axis location
Santiago-
Santiago-
Valparaiso -
Poniente
Oriente
VinadelMar
Constant
1.62*
(0.31)
Axis location
-1.98*
(0.29)
N
Percent correctly
predicted
PseudoR2
LR Chi-square
245
91.0
0.64
203.1
1.15*
(.030)
-2.04*
(0.32)
202
90.6
0.64
172.3
Region VI
4.91*
(1.27)
3.05*
(0.77)
--4.09*
(1.14)
-1.87*
(0.63)
132
95.5
0.81
120.3
84
90.5
0.51
35.4
Dependent variable: Anticipated vote choice for coalition candidates. Coded 1
if respondent anticipates voting for either Concertacion candidate; 0 if respondent anticipates voting for either Democracy y Progreso candidate. Estimated
standard errors are in parentheses. LR Chi-square equals -2(lnLF-lnLR), and
is distributed chi-square with 1 degree of freedom.
p<0.05
formative. To provide an indication of the impact of a small change in spatial
location on the probability of voting for a Concertacion candidate, apclaXaxis,
across the maps I calculated the percentage change in the probability of voting
for a concertacion candidate Pc one half unit to the right measured from the
point on the recovered axis where probability of voting for a candidate of one
coalition or the other equals 0.5. This point, of course, varies across districts
depending on the scaled locations of candidates, the shape of the estimated
distribution of voter ideal points and the aggregate political preferences in
the districts. This measures, in some sense, the "typical" impact of a small
change in spatial location on the probability of voting for the Concertacion at
the most competitive location in each of the maps.
The largest marginal effect is Valparaiso - Vina del Mar. Here a one-half
unit change to the right from the point of indifference between candidates
of the two coalitions, Xind = 1.2, reduces the likelihood of voting for a Concertacion candidate to 12%, a decrease of approximately 76%. The impact
of a comparable change in spatial location is more modest in the remaining
districts. In Santiago-Poniente and Santiago-Oriente the points of indifference
between the coalitions are Xind = 0.82 and Xind = 0.57, respectively, with a
one-half unit shift to the right in both districts reducing the probability of
[246]
465
voting for a Concertacion candidate to 0.26. The corresponding figures for
Region VI are X ind = 1.63 and 0.28.
Table 2 presents the reestimated logistic regression of anticipated voter
choice on axis location, this time adding respondent ideological selfplacement and several demographic characteristics to the list of independent
variables. The demographic variables include an interviewer assessment of
the respondent's social class as measured on a seven point scale, as well as
respondent gender, age and level of education. 12 Previous studies of Chilean
political behavior indicate that social class is only modestly associated with
partisan preferences and women are generally more conservative than men
(Langton and Rapoport, 1976; Portes, 1976; Valenzuela, 1985; Panzer and
Paredes, 1991).
The second set of logistic regressions demonstrate that respondent ideological self-placement and demographic characteristics add little information
about voter choice in the senate elections beyond that summarized by the
spatial maps. The incorporation of this additional information increases the
proportion of correctly predicted vote by an average of only 3% relative to
estimates based solely on spatial location. This is reflected in the minimal
changes in the corresponding pseudo R2 ,s and likelihood ratio statistics. Only
in the Santiago districts does the ideology variable contribute significantly to
the explained variation in voter choice, but the relative importance of respondent ideology still lags that for respondent location in the estimated space.
Once one controls for estimated spatial location, demographic variables add
little information useful for understanding voter behavior in the Chilean senate elections. Neither social class nor gender is associated with voter choice,
although in three of the four districts the estimated gender coefficients are
in the expected conservative direction. Older and more educated voters in
Santiago - Poniente are less likely to vote for the Concertacion, although the
impact of age is quite minimal. That social class is not strongly associated
with voter choice and the estimated coefficient for women is in three of four
cases in the conservative direction further indicates the political universe that
emerged from military rule exhibits continuity with that prior to 1973.
5.2. Evaluation of spatial location
The Median Voter Result does not hold in the Chilean senatorial elections,
and at least some candidates are expected to be located outside the central
half of the distribution of voters.
In all maps there is a wide gap between liberal and conservative candidates and parties. The estimated maps confirm that the Concertacion and,
in particular, the Christian Democratic Party, owns the political high ground
at the center of the electoral space. The Union of Independent Democrats,
[247]
466
Table 2. Logistic regression of voter choice by spatial location, ideological
self-placement and demographic characteristics
Santiago-
Santiago-
Valparaiso -
Poniente
Oriente
Vinadel Mar
Constant
14.00
(4.29)
6.36
(3.28)
Axis location
-1.84*
(0.32)
-1.98*
(0.37)
-1.63*
(0.52)
Social class
Female
Ideology
Age
Education
predicted
PseudoR2
LR Chi-square
~.6*
-8.78
(8.29)
(2.21)
-2.73*
(1.25)
-1.07*
0.34
-1.14
(0.38)
(0.91)
(0.67)
-0.29
(0.45)
-0.27
(0.34)
2.19
(1.15)
2.36
(1.35)
-0.92
-0.12
(0.59)
(0.58)
1.58
(1.36)
-0.85
(1.10)
-0.06*
(0.02)
-1.21 *
-0.01
(0.02)
0.09
(0.05)
-0.02
(0.03)
-0.10
(0.49)
2.76
(1.63)
1.94
(1.26)
(0.55)
N
Percent correctly
-17.61
(9.52)
Region VI
245
94.3
0.71
227.7
202
90.6
0.68
183.1
132
98.5
0.87
128.9
84
95.2
0.63
43.2
Dependent variable: Anticipated vote choice for coalition candidates. Coded I
if respondent anticipates voting for either Concertacion candidate; 0 if respondent anticipates voting for either Democracy y Progreso candidate. Estimated
standard errors are in parentheses. LR Chi-square equals -2(lnLF-InLR), and
is distributed chi-square with 6 degrees of freedom.
p<0.05
the National Renovation and Democracy y Progreso candidates scale to the
right periphery of the space. In Valparaiso - Vina del Mar the Concertacion
parties and candidates are adjacent to the median voter ideal point, while in
the Santiago Districts and Region VI Concertacion parties other than the PDC
scale well to the left of the median voter ideal point. Indeed, Eduardo Frei in
Santiago-Oriente and Juan Hamilton in Valparaiso - Vina del Mar scale to the
right of the origin and the median voter ideal point, but even in these districts
the region between the left and right candidates is considerable.
[248]
467
The most appropriate measure for assessing whether centrifugal or centripetal forces dominate candidate strategies in Chilean senatorial elections is
candidate location relative to the distribution of voters. The standard deviation
of the estimated voter ideal points on the recovered axis is a natural measure
of distance in the recovered space as expectations of candidate locations derived from the spatial model are defined in terms of the distribution of voters.
These figures support the expectation that there are few electoral incentives
for all candidates to locate near the center of the voter distribution. The
average distance separating the innermost candidates in each map is nearly
1.7 standard deviations. Nearly half of the estimated voter ideal points in the
maps are between the interior candidates. This percentage ranges from 40%
in Valparaiso - Vina del Mar to 47% in Santiago-Poniente and Region VI.
An average of approximately 38% of the voter ideal points are to the left
of the exterior Concertacion candidate, while only a nominal proportion, an
average of approximately 6% are on the right of the exterior Democracia
y Progreso candidate. Finally, as the estimated distribution of voter ideal
points suggests, the number of voters between coalition partners, especially
those on the right, is minimal. For example, no voters scale between Manuel
Valdes and Anselmo Sule in Region VI nor are any voters located between
Hermogenes Perez de Arce and Sebastian Pinera in Santiago-Oriente. The
proportion of voters between Concertacion candidates is greater; ranging
from 5% of the estimated ideal points in Santiago-Poniente to approximately
18% in Santiago-Oriente.
6. Conclusion
The empirical spatial analysis largely support the thesis that centrifugal forces
dominate candidate strategies in elections held under Chilean d'Hondt in
dual member districts. In all districts candidates of the right clearly locate
away from the ideal point of the median voter. On the left, several candidates
including Maria E. Carrera in Santiago-Oriente, Ricardo Lagos in SantiagoPoniente and Anselmo Sule in Region VI scale further from the median voter
than one would expect if candidates enjoyed moderate spatial mobility in
an electoral system characterized by centripetal incentives. Collectively, the
maps indicate there are few centralizing tendencies in Chilean senatorial elections. This makes sense given under Chilean d'Hondt one can win a senate
seat with a nominal percentage of the vote. Jamie Guzman, Beltran Urenda,
Alfonso Orueta of the Democracia y Progreso won seats with pluralities of
less than 20%, indicating there are few incentives for these candidates to
moderate their positions to secure larger pluralities.
[249]
468
The existence of centrifugal electoral incentives means candidates most
likely to emerge and win Chilean legislative elections are those capable of
differentiating themselves from the center of the distribution of voter opinion. Indeed, over half of the candidates who won elections in the four senate
elections considered in this study scaled to the exterior of the space. This
suggests Chilean legislative candidates will primarily appeal to like-minded
voters and electoral competition will largely center on mobilizing supporters
in one's region of the electoral space.
The maps demonstrate the Chilean polity that emerged from military rule
shares both similarities and differences with that predating the Pinochet era.
The most important differences center on the breadth of the Concertacion
coalition and the lack of voter polarization relative to what one would expect
prior to 1973. The relative Socialist-Communist locations with the Christian
Democratic Party dominating the center of the political spectrum is similar to
what one would expect before 1973. The estimated locations of candidates,
parties and voters substantives the arguments of Scully (1992, 1995) and others that the Chilean political landscape reflects important continuities with
the pre-authoritarian era, and substantiates the argument that polities with
long histories of stable democratic governance are resilient to change. 13
The contemporary Chilean polity enjoys considerable stability and ranks
among the most consolidated of democratic transitions. A note a caution
is suggested by Chile's use of an extremely disproportional electoral system that provides incentives that, ceteris paribus, reward extremists and
punish moderates. Political moderates can win Chilean legislative elections
as demonstrated by the Santiago-Oriente election of Eduardo Frei and his
subsequent election to the Chilean presidency in 1994. The estimated maps
demonstrate, however, that parties, especially those on the right, have few incentives to nominate moderates and, at the margins, candidates face electoral
incentives to preserve parochial basis of support rather pursue more centrist
campaign strategies. These incentives can be reversed with relatively simple
changes in the electoral system such as providing citizens with an additional
vote.
Notes
1. An important exception is Lin, Chu, and Hinich (1996).
2. Concertacion candidates won approximately 60% of the seats in the House of Deputies,
the lower chamber of the Chilean legislature. The presence of nine appointed senators in
the Chilean senate left the Concertacion with just under 50% of the chamber seats.
3. Chilean regions are numbered from one in the north to twelve in the south, and are
generally referred to by number rather than name. The fifth, seventh, eighth, ninth and
tenth administrative regions are allotted two senatorial districts. Of these, regions five
[250]
469
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
II.
12.
(Valparaiso) and eight (Bio-Bio) have large urban areas. The other regions with two senate
district are in traditionally conservative southern Chile.
I study these elections because only data for these districts were made available by the
survey's principal investigator. See Section 4 and note 9 for a discussion of the survey
data and methodology.
d'Hondt is among the least proportional of all proportional representation rules (Jones,
1993; Lijphart, 1994). For a discussion of the d'Hondt rule see Taagepera and Shugart
(1989: 32-34).
All election results are obtained from La Epoca. 16 de diciembre de 1989.
In addition to the Concertacion and Democracia y Progreso candidates, the Region Six
map was estimated including the two candidates of the rightist Avanzada Nacional coalition. This is because the maximum likelihood estimation procedure described in Section
4 failed produced optimal estimates using the smaller covariance matrix. Perhaps not
coincidentally, only in Region Six did the Avanzada Nacional secure more than a nominal
plurality, winning nearly II % of the vote. Although these candidates scaled as expected
on the far right of the space, their locations are not presented to keep the graphical representation consistent with the other maps. The inclusion of the two additional candidates
did not significantly reduce the number of observations used to estimate this map.
Consistent with this, Adams' (1996) find greater ideological heterogeneity among Illinois
state legislators elected from dual member districts than those elected from single member
districts.
Polling was conducted by the INVESTMARK company and commissioned by the Buchi
presidential campaign. The surveys were designed and implemented to the highest academic standards. Since there may be concerns about the integrity of data collected for
partisan purposes, the data, survey questionnaires and translations, and details on the
survey methodology are available on request.
is a function of candidate positions in the underlying space, and under very weak
assumptions, the estimated candidate locations are normally distributed (Anderson and
Amemiya (1988).
The estimated density is used for graphical purposes only. All data analysis and interpretations are based on the raw estimated voter ideal points. The density is estimated using an
Epanechnikov kernel with a smoothing window of approximately 0.60. For a discussion
see Scott (1992: 125-145).
Social class is coded according to the interviewer's assessment of respondent social class
on a high (I) to low (7) scale, age is the respondent's age in years, and education is
measures on a I (no formal education), 2 (some or all primary), 3 (some or all secondary),
4 (some or all college) scale. The left-right ideological self-placement question translates
as:
Ln
In politics one normally speaks of right and left. On this chart different political
positions may be found (I left - 5 right). Please tell me where you place yourself.
13. See Valenzuela and Valenzuela (1986) for a discussion of the resilience of the Chilean
party system to military rule and Scully (1992: Ch. 5).
[251 ]
470
References
Adams, J. and Merrill III, S. (1998a). A Downsian model of candidate competition in the 1988
French presidential election. Typescript. Santa Barbara: University of California.
Adams, 1. and Merrill III, S. (1998b). Party structures and policy representation in multiparty
elections: An application to Norwegian politics. Typescript. Santa Barbara: University of
California.
Adams, G. (1996). Legislative effects of single-member vs. multi-member districts. American
Journal of Political Science 40: 129-144.
Aldrich, J.H. and McKelvey, R.D. (1977). A method of scaling with applications to the 1968
and 1972 presidential elections. American Political Science Review 71: 111-130.
Anderson, T.W. and Amemiya, Y. (1988). The asymptotic normal distribution of estimators in
factor analysis under general conditions. The Annals of Statistics 16: 759-771.
Angell, A. (1990). The Chilean elections of 1989. Electoral Studies 3: 241-245.
Angell, A. and Pollack, B. (1990). The Chilean elections of 1989 and the politics of the
transition to democracy. Bulletin of Latin American Research 9: 1-23. Black, D. (1958).
Theory of committees and elections. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Brady, H.E. (1991). Traits versus issues: Factor versus ideal-point analysis of candidate thermometer ratings. In J.A. Stimson (Ed.), Political Analysis, Vol. II. Ann Arbor: University
of Michigan Press.
Burnett, B.G. (1970). Political groups in Chile. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Cahoon, L.S. and Hinich, M.J. (1976). A method for locating targets using range only. IEEE
Transactions on Information Theory 22: 217-225.
Cahoon, L.S., Hinich, MJ. and Ordeshook, P.e. (1978). A statistical multidimensional scaling
method based on the spatial theory of voting. In P.e. Wang (Ed.), Graphical representation
of multivariate data. New York: Academic Press.
Caviedes, C.N. (1991). Elections in Chile: The road toward redemocratization. Boulder:
Lynne Rienner Publishers.
Cox, G.w. (1987). Electoral equilibrium under alternative voting institutions. American
Journal of Political Science 31: 82-108.
Cox, G.W. (1990a). Centripetal and centrifugal incentives in electoral systems. American
Journal of Political Science 34: 903-935.
Cox, G.w. (1990b). Multicandidate spatial competition. In J.M. Enelow and M.J. Hinich
(Eds.), Advances in the spatial theory of voting. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Davis, S.K. (1984). A nonmetric test of spatial theories of elections. Political Methodology
10: 1-28.
Denzau, A., Kats, A. and Slutsky, S. (1985). Multi-agent equilibria with market share and
ranking objectives. Social Choice and Welfare 2: 95-117.
Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper and Row.
Eaton, B.C. and Lipsey, R. (1975). The principle of minimum differentiation reconsidered:
Some new developments in the theory of spatial competition. Review of Economic Studies
42: 27-50.
Endersby, J.w. and Hinich, M.J. (1992). The stability of voter perceptions: A comparison of
candidate positions across time using the spatial theory of voting. Journal ofMathematical
and Computer Modeling 16: 67-83.
Enelow, J.M. (1986). The linkage between predictive dimensions and candidate issue positions
in American presidential elections: An examination of group based differences. Political
Behavior 8: 245-261.
[252]
471
Enelow, J.M. (1988). A methodology for testing a new spatial model of elections. Quality and
Quantity 22: 347-364.
Enelow, J.M. and Hinich, M.J. (1984). The spatial theory of voting: An introduction. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Enelow, J.M. (1989). The locations of American presidential candidates: An empirical test of
a new spatial model of elections. Mathematical and Computer Modeling 12: 461-470.
Enelow, J.M. (1994). A test ofthe predictive dimensions model in spatial voting theory. Public
Choice 78: 155-170.
Enelow, J.M. and Hinich, M.J. (Eds.). (1990). Advances in the spatial theory of voting. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Faundez, J. (1988). Marxism and democracy in Chile. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Garreton, M.A. (1989). The Chilean political process. Winchester, MA: Unwin Hyman.
Gill, EG. (1966). The political system of Chile. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina
Press.
Green, D.P. and Shapiro, I. (1994). Pathologies of rational choice theory New Haven: Yale
University Press.
Greenberg, J. and Shepsle, K. (1987). The effect of multiparty rewards in multiparty
competition with entry. American Political Science Review 81: 525-537.
Greenberg, J. and Weber, S. (1985). Multiparty equilibria under proportional representation.
American Political Science Review 79: 693--703.
Hinich, M.J. and Mungeer, M.e. (1994). Ideology and the theory of political choice. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Hinich, M.J. (1996). Analytical politics. New York: Cambridge University Press (forthcoming).
Hinich, M.J. and Ordeshook, P.C. (1970). Plurality maximization versus vote maximization:
A spatial analysis with variable participation. American Political Science Review 64: 772791.
Iversen, T. (1994). Political leadership and representation in West European democracies: A
test of three models of voting. American Journal of Political Science 38: 45-74.
Jones, M.P. (1993). The political consequences of electoral laws in Latin America and the
Caribbean. Electoral Studies 12: 59-75.
Langton, K.P. and Rapoport, R. (1976). Religion and leftist mobilization in Chile. Comparative Political Studies 9: 277-308.
Laver, M. and Schofield, N. (1990). Multiparty government. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Lijphart, A. (1994). Electoral systems and party systems. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lin, T.-M., Chu, Y.-h. and Hinich, M.J. (1996). Conflict displacement and regime transition in
Taiwan: A spatial analysis. World Politics (forthcoming).
Lipset, S.M. and Rokkan, S. (1967). Cleavage structures, party systems and voter alignments.
In S.M. Lipset and S. Rokkan (Eds.), Party systems and voter alignments: Cross national
perspectives. New York: The Free Press.
Macdonald, S.E., Listhaug, O. and Rabinowitz, G. (1991). Issues and party support in
multiparty systems. American Political Science Review 85: 1107-1131.
Macdonald, S.E., Rabinowitz, G. and Listhaug, O. (1995). Political sophistication and models
of issues voting. British Journal of Political Science 25: 453-483.
Merrill, S. III. (1994). A probabilistic model for the spatial distribution of party support in
multiparty elections. Journal of the American Statistical Association 1190-1197.
Merrill, S. 1lI. (1995). Discriminating between the directional and proximity spatial models of
electoral competition. Electoral Studies 14: 273-287.
[253]
472
Palfrey, T.R. (1984). Spatial equilibrium with entry. Review of Economic Studies 51: 139-156.
Panzer, J. and Paredes, R. (1991). The role of economic issues in elections: The case of the
1988 Chilean presidential referendum. Public Choice 71: 51-59.
Poole, K. and Rosenthal, H. (1984). U.S. presidential elections 1968-1980: A spatial analysis.
American Journal of Political Science 28: 282-312.
Portes, A (1976). Occupation and lower-class political orientation in Chile. In A. Valenzuela and lS. Valenzuela (Eds.), Chile: Politics and society. New Brunswick: Transaction
Books.
Rabinowitz, G. (1978). On the nature of political issues: Insights from a spatial analysis.
American Journal of Political Science 70: 804-809.
Rabinowitz, G. and Macdonald, S.E. (1989). A directional theory of issue voting. American
Political Science Review 83: 93-121.
Rabinowitz, G., Macdonald, S.E. and Listhaug, O. (1991). Old players in a new game: Party
strategy in multiparty systems. Comparative Political Studies 24: 147-185.
Rusk, J. and Weisberg, H. (1972). Perceptions of presidential candidates. Midwest Journal of
Political Science 16: 388-410.
Sartori, G. (1976). Panies and party systems. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Schofield, N., Martin, A, Quin, K. and Whitford, A (1998). Multiparty electoral competition
in the Netherlands and Germany: A model based on the multinomial probit. Public Choice
(forthcoming).
Schofield, N. (1998). A comparison of majoritarian and proportional electoral systems
based on spatial modeling and 'rational' politicians. Typescript. St. Louis: Washington
University.
Scott, D.W. (1992). Multivariate density estimation. New York: Wiley.
Scully, T.R. (1992). Rethinking the center: Party politics in nineteenth- and twentieth-century
Chile. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Scully, T.R. (1995). Reconstructing party politics in Chile. In S. Mainwaring and T.R. Scully
(Eds.), Building democratic institutions Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Shepsle, K.A. (1991). Models of multiparty electoral competition. New York: Harwood
Academic.
Shepsle, K.A. and Cohen, R.N. (1990). Multiparty competition, entry and entry deterrence
in spatial models of elections. In lM. Enelow and M.l Hinich (Eds.), Advances in the
spatial theory of voting. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Taagepera, R. and Shugart, M.S. (1989). Seats and vote. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Valenzuela, A (1985). Origins and characteristics of the Chilean system: A proposal for a
parliamentary form of government. Working Paper No. 164, The Woodrow Wilson Center.
Valenzuela, S. and Valenzuela, A. (1985). Chile and the breakdown of democracy. In
H.J. Wiarda and H.P. Kline (Eds.), Latin American politics and development. Boulder:
Westview Press.
Valenzuela, A and Valenzuela, S. (1986). Party opposition under the authoritarian regime. In
A Valenzuela and J.S. Valenzuela (Eds.), Military rule in Chile. Baltimore: The Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Walker, I. (1993). Political alliances and the role ofthe centre: The Chilean Christian Democratic Party. In A. Angell and B. Pollack (Eds.), The legacy of dictatorship. Liverpool:
Institute of Latin American Studies.
Weisberg, H. and Rusk, J. (1970). Dimensions of candidate evaluation. American Political
Science Review 64: 1167-1185.
[254 ]
473
Appendix 1
Political parties scaled in the spatial maps
Party!
coalition
Map
Christian
Democratic
Party
PDC
Center Left. Dominant legislative party. Opposes both
the far left and Pinochet. The PDC was the primary
legislative opposition to president Salvador Allende
between 1970 and 1973. Won 12 senate seats.
National Renovation
RN
Party for
Democracy
PPD
Union of
Independent
Democrats
Socialist
Party
UDI
Traditional Right. Economically conservative and
moderately sympathetic to political reforms. Won 11
senate seats.
Moderate Socialist party. Originally formed as an
instrumental party to organize voters to oppose the
military government in the 1988 plebiscite on the
continuation of Pinochet's rule. Several prominent
politicians sought election as PDC candidates in the
1989 legislative elections. Won four senate seats.
Right. Economically conservative and closely identified with the Pinochet regime. Opposed to major
political reforms. Won a single senate seat.
Far left of Chilean Politics. Traditionally more ambivalent towards the electoral process, and subject to
internal ideological divisions. Won a single senate
seat.
Left. Traditionally associated with the Soviet Union,
and the pursuit of electoral basis of political power.
Not part of the Concertacion because of its support of
violence against the Pinochet government. Failed to
secure legislative representation.
Left and Center-Left coalition consisting primarily of
the PDC, PPD and Socialists. Supported Aylwin for
the presidency.
Characteristics
acronym
PS
Communist
Party
PPCh
Concertacion
Coalition
CPD
[255 ]
474
Appendix 2
Mean and standard deviation of respondent characteristics in survey sample and
scaled subsample
District
Santiago-Oriente
Full sample
(n = 642)
Scaled respondents
(n =303)
Santiago-Poniente
Full sample
(n =610)
Scaled respondents
(n = 242)
Valparaiso - Vina del Mar
Full sample
(n =718)
Scaled respondents
(n = 133)
Region VI
Full sample
(n =482)
Scaled respondents
(n = 163)
1Percent female
Ideological
selfplacement
Female 1
Age
Social
class
Education
3.00
(0.91)
57.8%
5.18
(0.84)
2.86
(0.98)
50.8%
40.82
(16.07)
39.48
(14.89)
5.11
(0.91)
2.58
(0.71)
2.70
(0.72)
2.95
(1.00)
57.0%
38.4
(15.09)
4.85
(1.08)
2.80
(0.71)
2.97
(1.08)
52.9%
39.0
(15.00)
4.48
(1.08)
3.03
(0.70)
2.84
(1.17)
54.0%
2.56
(1.20)
45.1%
41.28
(16.49)
36.57
(14.37)
5.59
(0.66)
5.53
(0.71)
2.31
(0.73)
2.47
(0.78)
2.89
(0.95)
63.7%
42.06
(16.87)
5.11
(0.97)
2.62
(0.72)
2.83
(1.12)
50.3%
42.13
(16.89)
4.93
(0.97)
2.82
(0.73)
respondents in the sample and scaled subsample. All
variables measured as described in Note 12.
[256 ]
Public Choice 97: 475-490, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
475
Empirical evidence of paradoxes of voting in Dutch elections
AD M.A. VAN DEEMEN 1 & NOEL P. VERGUNST2
1 University of Nijmegen, Department of Political Science, P. O. Box 9108, 6500 HK
Nijmegen, The Netherlands; e-mail: A.vanDeemen@BW.KUN.NL; 2Free University
Amsterdam, Department of Political Science and Public Administration, De Boelelaan
108Ic, 1081 HV Amsterdam, The Netherlands; e-mail: NP.Vergunst@SCW.VUNL
Abstract. In this paper we analyze four national elections held in 1982, 1986, 1989 and 1994
in the Netherlands on the occurrence of the Condorcet paradox. In addition, we investigate
these elections on the occurrence of three so-called majority-plurality paradoxes. The first
paradox states that a party having a majority over another party may receive less seats. The
second states that a Condorcet winner may not receive the largest number of seats and even
may not receive a seat at all. The third says that the majority relation may be the reverse of the
ranking of parties in terms of numbers of seats.
1. Introduction
The Condorcet paradox is concerned with voting situations in which no majority winner exists, in spite of the fact that voters have consistent preferences.
The paradox was discovered in the eighteenth century by the French philosopher and mathematician Marquis de Condorcet (1743-1794). To illustrate the
paradox, we present an example constructed by Condorcet (1789). The voting
situation concerns sixty voters and three candidates called Pierre, Paul and
Jacques. The distribution of the voters is as follows:
23 voters:
Pierre
Paul
Jacques
2 voters:
17 voters:
Paul
Pierre
Jacques
Paul
Jacques
Pierre
10 voters;
Jacques
Pierre
Paul
8 voters:
Jacques
Paul
Pierre
The voter preferences are supposed to be transitive. Thus a voter with for
instance the preference (Pierre, Paul, Jacques) prefers Pierre to Paul, Paul
to Jacques and, because of transitivity, Pierre to Jacques. According to this
preference profile, Pierre has a 33 to 27 majority over Paul, Jacques has a
35 to 25 majority over Pierre and Paul has a 42 to 18 majority over Jacques.
[257 ]
476
Hence there is no candidate with a majority over every other candidate; there
is no majority winner or Condorcet winner.
Condorcet also compared the majority rule with other voting rules, in
particular the plurality rule. As is well known, the plurality rule selects the
candidate with the highest number of first places in the voter preferences.
Thus for the example above, this rule would have selected Pierre as the plurality winner, in spite of the fact that a majority of voters prefers Jacques to
Pierre. Condorcet (1785, 1789) also discovered that a plurality winner and a
Condorcet winner may differ. Moreover, he came to the general conclusion
that different voting rules may yield different outcomes for the same voting
situation. Though this insight seems trivial by now, it is in fact at the heart of
a controversy between liberalism and populism (or, better, majoritarianism)
in the theory of democracy. See, e.g., Riker (1982) and Tlinnsjo (1992).
Clearly, if the Condorcet paradox occurs, then either no winner can be
selected when the majority rule is used or a minority candidate is selected in
the case of another rule, for instance the plurality rule. Thus in the case of
a paradox, the plurality rule selects a candidate that can be beaten by a majority. If instances of the paradox frequently occur, then either many decision
deadlocks can be observed in the case of the majority rule or many minority
candidates will be selected in the case of the plurality rule. Therefore, the
question of how frequently the Condorcet paradox occurs is important.
In this paper we investigate four Dutch elections on the occurrence of the
Condorcet paradox. The elections were held in 1982, 1986, 1989 and 1994.
The party preferences of the voters in these elections are constructed by using
data of the Dutch Parliamentary Election Studies. We also investigate the occurrence of other paradoxes related to the plurality rule and the majority rule.
These so-called majority-plurality paradoxes are presented in Van Deemen
(1993). The first paradox of this kind occurs when a party is preferred by a
majority of the electorate to another party and yet receives less seats than that
other party. The second paradox occurs when a Condorcet winner does not
receive the largest number of seats. In fact, it is even theoretically possible
in list systems of proportional representation like the one used in the Netherlands that the Condorcet winner receives no seats at all. Also this possibility
will be investigated. Finally, the third majority-plurality paradox occurs when
the ranking of parties in accordance with the vote or seat distribution is the
reverse of the ranking of parties as obtained by the majority rule.
The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 shortly reviews existing research results concerning the relevance of the Condorcet paradox. In Section
3, the concept of election matrix is introduced and discussed. An election
matrix is a suitable tool for the empirical representation of voter preferences
in elections. Of course, we show how to detect a Condorcet paradox from an
[258 ]
477
election matrix. Section 4 presents the election matrices of the Dutch elections held in 1982, 1986, 1989 and 1994. Further we investigate the matrices
on the occurrence of the Condorcet paradox and majority cycles. In the subsequent section, we investigate the data on the occurrence of majority-plurality
paradoxes. The final section contains conclusions and discusses future research.
2. The relevance of the Condorcet paradox
After a long period of slumbering existence, the interest in the Condorcet
paradox was raised again by Arrow (1963) and Black (1958). Their rediscovery of the paradox has led to two important research fields in public choice.
In the first, conditions are formulated that require voter preferences to satisfy
certain regularities in such a way that the paradox is avoided. So the aim of
this research is to find conditions that forbid the occurrence of the paradox.
The most-known condition in this respect is single-peakedness formulated
by Black (1958). This condition requires that alternatives (or motions as
Black called them) can be linearly ordered in such a way that the graph of
each voter preference has one and only one peak. Black was able to prove that
in case of single-peaked preferences the optimum of the median voter preference must be the majority winner when the number of voters is odd. This
result is called the Median Voter Theorem. Further he showed that singlepeakedness ensures the transitivity of majority decision-making in the case of
odd numbers of voters and its quasi-transitivity in the case of even numbers
of voters.
The second research field does not forbid the Condorcet paradox, but
instead tries to find out how often it will occur in real decision-making situations. This research line can be split up into two sub-fields. The task in
the first sub-field is to calculate the probability of the Condorcet paradox for
several numbers of voters and alternatives. The second line aims at detecting
empirically instances of the paradoxes. We discuss both sub-fields.
The probability approach was initiated, again, by Black (1958). He arrived
at a probability of .0556 for the paradox in the case of three voters and three
alternatives and given the fact that voter preferences are linear orderings (i.e.,
rankings without ties). He was not able to give further calculations but he
conjectured that the probability of the paradox "increases rapidly with an
increase in the number of motions" (Black 1958: 51). Since Black, several
researchers have calculated the probabilities of the Condorcet paradox by
means of computer simulations (Campbell and Tullock, 1965; Klahr, 1966)
as well as by means of analytical expressions (DeMeyer and Plott, 1970;
May, 1971; Niemi and Weisberg, 1968; Garman and Kamien, 1968; Gehrlein
[259]
478
Table 1. Probabilities of no Condorcet-winners for Dutch elections (1982-1994)
Election year
Number of parties
Probability of
no Condorcet-winner
1982
13
.56869
1986
12
.54706
1989
9
9
.45453
1994
.45453
Source: Gehrlein (1983); Gehrlein & Fishburn (1976).
and Fishburn, 1976; Gehrlein, 1983). The general conclusion to be drawn
from the calculations is that, indeed, the probabilities rapidly increase with
an increasing number of voters but this increase is less thaI). in the case of a
growing number of alternatives.
To find the probabilities for the four Dutch elections under scrutiny, we
suppose that the size of the electorate approaches infinity so that we can use
the limit values for the several numbers of parties as calculated in the studies
mentioned above. The probabilities for the elections are given in Table 1.
However, the results in this table should be interpreted with care. First, the
calculations are based on the assumption of equally likely voter preferences.
This assumption, which is called Impartial Culture, is highly implausible.
Studies in which the probabilities of the paradox under alternative cultures
or distribution assumptions are calculated, are scarce. In addition, the limit
values under different cultures are still unknown.
The second reason to be careful is that most of the calculations start from
the assumption that voter preferences are linear orderings, i.e., rankings without ties. This is not .a realistic approach. As we shall see, we found many
ties in the voter preferences in the four Dutch elections under scrutiny. Also
see Niemi (1970). Recently, Jones, Radcliff, Taber, and Timpone (1995) calculated the probability of the paradox for weak orderings, thus for rankings
with ties. However, they did not provide limit values for several numbers of
alternatives so that their results cannot be used for national elections. Further
they defined the paradox as the absence of a unique Condorcet winner. Now
it is clear that in the case of weak orderings, two or more Condorcet winners
may exist. In this work, we retain the definition of the paradox as the absence
of a Condorcet winner and not as the absence of a unique one. So, situations
with two or more Condorcet winners will not be considered as paradoxes.
[260]
479
The second field in this research tradition is directed at finding empirical
instances of the paradox. This research was initiated by Riker (1965), who
found a paradox in the U.S. senate in 1911 and a paradox in the House of
Representatives in 1956. It is useful here to make a distinction between voting
in committees and voting in large elections. Since Riker's study, a number
of other empirical instances of the paradox have been found in committee
voting situations. Blydenburgh (1971) found two Condorcet paradoxes in the
U.S. House of Representatives in 1932 and 1938. Jamison (1975), using experimental data about preferences in small groups, also detected a Condorcet
paradox. More recently, Vergunst (1996) found a Condorcet paradox in a case
treated in the Second Chamber of the Dutch parliament in 1994. In contrast to
these results, instances of the paradox in large elections are difficult to detect.
This is remarkable, since probability calculations indicate that the paradox
should occur far more frequently in large elections than in comparatively
small committees. So, Chamberlin, Cohen, and Coombs (1984) did not find a
paradox in the case of elections for the American Psychological Association.
Similarly, Niemi and Wright (1987) did not find a paradox in the Presidential
Elections of 1980. Feld and Grofman (1992) investigated preference data of
36 elections held in professional organizations, unions and non-profit organizations. They did not find a Condorcet paradox either. Finally, Radcliff (1994)
investigated president elections in the U.S. Neither he was able to detect the
paradox. The only and so far unique exception is Niemi (1970), who discovered a paradox in a case of university elections. In this paper we search for
Condorcet paradoxes in four national elections held in the Netherlands. Basic
in our detection method is the concept of an election matrix.
3. Election matrices
Election matrices provide a powerful tool for analyzing election data. In particular, it is a convenient device for detecting paradoxes of voting. Let the
number of voters who strictly prefer Xi to Xj be denoted by N(Xi,PXj) and let m
be the number of alternatives. An election matrix is defined as a square matrix
E = «eij)), where eij = N(XiPXj) for each i,j = 1,2, ... ,m and i =1= j, and where ejj
=0 for i = 1,2, ... ,m. Thus each cell «eij)) in an election matrix contains the
number of voters who strictly prefer alternative Xi to alternative Xj.
The matrix (1/n).E denotes the proportional election matrix. A cell «Xi,
Xj)) in this matrix contains the proportion of voters strictly preferring Xi to
Xj. Let E' denote the transpose of E. Clearly, the matrix S = E - E' is skewsymmetric, that is, «sij)) = «-Sji)) for i, j = 1,2, ... ,m. The entries in S show the
margins of the voters for an alternative over another alternative. If the margin
is non-negative, then that alternative is preferred by a majority to the other
[261]
480
alternative. It is negative if the other alternative is strictly majority-preferred.
Clearly, if a row contains only non-negative numbers, the alternative represented by the row is a Condorcet winner. Thus the matrix S provides an
easy method for detecting Condorcet paradoxes: look for rows with only
non-negative numbers. If there are none, the paradox has occurred.
4. Empirical evidence in four Dutch elections
In this paragraph we present and analyze the preference data concerning the
four national elections of 1982, 1986, 1989 and 1994. First, the nature of the
preference data will be explained. In order to illustrate our working procedure, we then present and analyze the election matrix of 1994 obtained from
these data. Finally, the full majority relation for each of the elections of 1982,
1986, 1989 and 1994 is produced and analyzed. Of course, the data will be
investigated on the occurrence of the Condorcet paradox.
The data are taken from the Dutch parliamentary election study (NKO) of
1982, 1986, 1989 and 1994. In the period before and after each election of
the Dutch parliament, about 1500 respondents are interviewed about a wide
range of issues. One of the many questions concerns the probability that a
respondent will ever vote for a party. Each respondent can choose a point on
a scale from 1 ("certainly never") through 10 ("some time certainly"). We
will use the probability votes obtained in this way for the construction of
the voters' party preferences. We assume that if a voter gives more points to
party x than to party y, she strictly prefers x to y. Notation: Pi(X) > Pi(y) ~
xPiy, where Pi(X) stands for the probability future vote score of respondent
i for party x and where P stands for strict preference. Furthermore, p(x) =
p(y) for a voter means that this voter is indifferent with respect to parties x
and y; notation: xly. The voter preferences constructed in this way are then
aggregated by the majority rule. According to this aggregation procedure,
party x is majority-preferred to party y if the number of voters who strictly
prefer x to y is at least as large as the number of voters who prefer y to
x; notation: xMy ~ N(xPiy) ::: N(yPix). In this case, we say that party x
has a majority over party y. The binary relation M thus obtained over all
pairs of parties is called the majority relation. Notice that according to this
definition, indifference does not affect the majority relation between parties.
In this context, a Condorcet winner is a party having a majority over every
other party. In other words, x is a Condorcet winner if xMy for all parties y.
Table 2 contains the election matrix obtained from the individual scores
collected in the Dutch national election in 1994. For example, the cell (D66,
PvdA) in this matrix contains the number of 655 while the cell (PvdA, D66)
contains the number of 580. This means that 655 respondents strictly prefer
[262]
481
Table 2. Majority scores for the 1994 elections in the Netherlands: N(XPiY)
Party
D66
PvdA
CDA
VVD
Groen
Links
RPF
SGP
GPV
CD
D66
PvdA
CDA
VVD
GroenLinks
RPF
SGP
GPV
CD
0
580
480
471
208
152
136
146
50
655
0
608
540
300
191
194
191
81
818
715
0
594
508
99
89
92
61
753
767
607
0
505
160
154
153
51
988
905
779
783
0
240
237
238
87
995
914
901
847
723
0
107
74
56
1036
946
930
883
743
114
0
79
59
1026
946
937
885
743
94
95
0
61
1262
1183
1151
1137
996
545
573
562
0
Source: Dutch Parliamentary Election Study (n = 1527).
D66 to PvdA and that 580 strictly prefer the PvdA. Since the total number of
respondents is 1527, we conclude that 292 of the respondents are indifferent
or have not given a future probability score for at least one of the two parties. (This means that the numbers of respondents are not the same for each
pair.) The matrices for the elections of 1982, 1986, and 1989 are given in the
Appendix.
The skew-symmetric election matrix for 1994 is the matrix difference
between the election matrix and its transpose. It is given in Table 3. In this matrix, the first row contains only non-negative numbers. Therefore we conclude
that the corresponding political party D66 is the Condorcet winner. Hence, the
Condorcet paradox did not occur in this national election. Proceeding in the
same way for the elections of 1982, 1986, and 1989, we arrive at the conclusion that no Condorcet paradox did occur in any of these elections. Notice
that this does not mean that the concerned majority relations are acyclical. A
Condorcet winner may beat any other party involved in a cycle, as long as
this winner itself is not involved in a cycle. In other words, the existence of a
Condorcet winner only implies that there is no top-cycle.
To detect majority cycles, we need the majority relation for each election.
Such a relation can be constructed by means of the skew-symmetric election
matrices by using the fact that a non-negative number in such a matrix implies
the row party to have a majority over the column party. Proceeding in this way
we arrive at the following majority relations for the concerned elections (see
Table 4).
[263 ]
482
Table 3.
Skew-symmetric election matrix 1994
Party
D66
PvdA
CDA
VVD
GRLNKS
RPF
SGP
GPV
CD
D66
PvdA
CDA
VVD
GRLNKS
RPF
SGP
GPV
CD
0
-75
-338
-282
-780
-843
-900
-880
-1212
75
0
-107
-227
-605
-723
-752
-755
-ll02
338
107
0
282
227
-13
0
-278
-687
-729
-732
-1086
780
605
271
278
0
-483
-506
-505
-909
843
723
802
687
483
0
-7
-20
-489
900
752
841
729
506
7
0
-16
-514
880
755
845
732
505
20
16
0
-501
1212
llOI
1090
1086
909
489
514
501
0
-271
-802
-841
-845
-1090
13
Table 4.
Social rankings based on the majority rule and on the election results of the Dutch parliament,
1982-86-89-94
Ranking
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
1982
MR
CDA
VVD
PvdA
D66
DS70
PPR
PSP
SGP
CPN
GPV
RPF
CP
BP
PR
PvdA
CDA
VVD
D66
PSP
SGP
CPN
PPR
RPF
CP
GPV
DS70
BP
1986
MR
CDA
PvdA
D66
VVD
PPR
PSP
CPN
SGP
GPV
EVP
RPF
CP
PR
CDA
PvdA
VVD
D66
SGP
PPR
PSP
GPV
RPF
CPN
CP
EVP
1989
MR
CDA
PvdA
D66
VVD
GRLNKS
SGP
GPV
RPF
CD
PR
CDA
PvdA
VVD
D66
GRLNKS
SGP
GPV
RPF
CD
1994
MR
D66
PvdA
CDA
VVD
GRLNKS
RPF
SGP
GPV
CD
PR
PvdA
CDA
VVD
D66
GRLNKS
CD
RPF
SGP
GPV
MR: Majority Relation.
PR: Proportional Representation Ranking; ranking according to the proportions of votes in the
elections.
[264 ]
483
Table 4 also gives the rankings of the parties as yielded by the Dutch
system of proportional representation. In the next section, we will use this
information for detecting the majority-plurality paradoxes mentioned in the
introduction. In addition, we note that the majorities in all the four majority
relations are strict.
The results are surprising indeed. The majority relations are all transitive;
none of them contains a cycle. So not only top cycles are absent, but any
majority cycle whatsoever. What is the reason of "so much stability" (Tullock,
1981)? The research line on domain conditions as briefly discussed above
may provide an answer. It is possible that there is a underlying pattern that
restricts the voter preferences in such a way that the paradox cannot occur.
As we have seen, the best-known condition in this respect is Black's condition of single-peaked preferences. We apply this to the Dutch situation in the
concerned elections.
Remember that voter preferences are single-peaked if there is a linear
ordering of parties such that, in passing from one party to the next in this
ordering, each voter preference shows only one top (or a plateau in the case of
indifferent preferences at the top). In the four Dutch elections under scrutiny
we could not find such a linear ordering. First we tried out, of course, the
traditional left-right dimension in Dutch politics. For example, using data
of the National Parliamentary Election Studies we arrived at the following
left-right ranking of the parties for 1994:
GroenLinks - PvdA - D66 - CDA - VVD - SGP - GPV - RPF - CD
See also Vergunst (1995). For this linear ordering we found that only 35.1 %
of the voter preferences were single-peaked. The other possible orderings of
parties did not work either, not only for this case but for every case we studied.
Our conclusions concerning the observed stability cased by preference
regularities are preliminary. As the above results show, single-peakedness of
voter preferences in Dutch elections is not a very likely cause. However, other
domain restrictions like Sen's (1966) value restriction may be operational. In
order to be more conclusive, much more empirical research on preference
patterns and domain restrictions is needed.
5. Majority-plurality paradoxes in the four elections
The main goal of this paper is to analyze Dutch elections on the occurrence of
the Condorcet paradox. In order to detect the paradoxes and, as a by-product,
possible majority cycles, the majority relation for each election under scrutiny
was reconstructed (see Table 4). These majority relations now will be used
[265 ]
484
Table 5. Comparing rankings by
majority rule to rankings by
the proportional system in the
Netherlands (1982-1994)
Election year
1982
1986
1989
1994
Kendall's tau
.6410
.7576
.9444
.6667
Source: Rankings Table 4.
for detecting three possible majority-plurality paradoxes as discussed in the
introduction.
The three paradoxes are:
1. The More-Preferred-Less-Seats Paradox, which states that a party having
a majority over another party may receive less seats;
2. The Condorcet-Winner-Turns-Loser Paradox, which states that a Condorcet winner need not receive the largest number of seats and even may
not receive a seat at all, and;
3. The Majority-Reversal Paradox, which states that the majority relation
for an election may be the reversal of the ranking of the parties in correspondence with their number of seats as assigned by the system of
proportional representation.
It can be shown that each of these paradoxes may occur in the Dutch system
of proportional representation (Van Deemen, 1993). However, do they occur
in reality? Table 4 contains, besides the majority relations in the left part of
each column (called MR), the rankings in terms of the number of seats as
actually assigned to the parties by the system of proportional representation.
See the right part of each column (called PR) in Table 4. A first look at this
table immediately shows the differences between the two rankings MR and
PR. For the elections of 1982, 1986 and 1994, the More-Preferred-Less-Seats
Paradox occurs abundantly. It also occurs in 1989, but to a less extent. In that
year, there was only one pair of parties with reversed positions, namely VVD
and D66.
To gain more insight into the coherence of both relations for each election, we calculated Kendall's tau (Table 5). Clearly, the smaller Kendall's tau,
the more majority-plurality reversals can be observed. We conclude that the
election of 1982 contains the most reversals.
[266 ]
485
The Condorcet-Winner-Turns-Loser Paradox occurred twice. In 1994, D66
was the majority winner, but PvdA received the largest number of seats. Also
CDA and VVD received more seats than D66, in spite of the fact that D66 had
a majority over both parties. The second case occurred in 1982 when CDA
received more seats than the majority winner PvdA. We did not observe the
fact that a Condorcet winner may not receive a seat at all.
The Majority-Reversal Paradox did not occur in any of the four elections.
Although the rankings based on the majority rule can be quite different from
the rankings based on the system of proportional representation, there is no
election year in which the majority ranking is completely reversed.
6. Conclusions
Voting in accordance with the majority rule is often considered as a necessary
condition for real democracy (Dahl, 1989). The major problem of the majority rule, however, is the possibility of cycles that prevent the existence of a
Condorcet winner. If this is the case, we speak of the Condorcet paradox. In
this paper we tried to find instances of the Condorcet paradox in four national
elections held in 1982, 1986, 1989 and 1994 in the Netherlands. We did not
find the paradox. The majority relation for every election appeared to be fully
transitive.
This result is in line with previous research on cycles in large elections.
For some reason or another, cycles in large elections are scarce. Now it is
well-known from theoretical studies that regularities in voter preferences may
prevent the occurrence of the paradoxes. Single-peaked preferences constitute the most clear example of this. However, we did not find evidence for
single-peakedness in the four elections investigated by us. But of course,
other preference regularities we did not investigate yet, may be operational. In
order to reveal the real causes of the absence of Condorcet paradoxes, much
empirical research has to be done.
We also tried to detect instances of majority-plurality paradoxes. Two of
the three paradoxes formulated by us actually did occur. First, we found many
instances of the paradox that a party having a majority over another party
received less seats than that other party. A good indication for this paradox is
Kendall's tau. Especially the elections of 1982 and 1994 are characterized by
a small Kendall's tau and hence by a high number of reversals. Further, we
found two instances of the paradox that a Condorcet winner does not receive
the largest number of seats. In the election of 1994, three parties received
more seats than the Condorcet winner and in the election of 1982 only one.
We did not find instances of the paradox that the majority relation over the
[267 ]
486
parties is the complete reverse of the ranking of the parties as yielded by
proportional representation.
References
Arrow, K.J. (1963). Social choice and individual values. New Haven and London: Yale
University Press. Second Edition.
Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Blydenburgh, I.e. (1971). The closed rule and the paradox of voting. The Journal of Politics
33: 57-71.
Campbell, C. and Tullock, G. (1965). A measure of the importance of cyclical majorities.
Economic Journal 75: 853-857.
Chamberlin, J.R., Cohen, J.L. and Coombs, C.H. (1984). Social choice observed: Five presidential elections of the American Psychological Association. The Journal of Politics 46:
479-502.
Condorcet, M. (1785). Essai sur ['application de l'analyse a la probabiliti des decisions
rendues ala pluralite de voix. Paris.
Condorcet, M. (1789). Sur laforme des elections. Paris.
Dahl, R. (1989). Democracy and its critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.
DeMeyer, F. and Plott, C. (1970). The probability of a cyclical majority. Econometrica 38:
345-354.
Feld, S. and Grofman, B. (1992). Who's afraid of the Big Bad Cycle? Evidence from 36
elections. Journal of Theoretical Politics 4: 231-237.
Garman, M.B. and Kamien, M.l. (1968). The paradox of voting: Probability calculations.
Behavioral Science 13: 306-316.
Gehrlein, WV. (1983). Condorcet's paradox. Theory and Decision 15: 161-197.
Gehrlein, W and Fishburn, P. (1976). The probability of the paradox of voting: A computable
solution. Journal of Economic Theory 12: 14--25.
Jamison, D.T. (1975). The probability of intransitive majority rule: An empirical study. Public
Choice 23: 87-94.
Jones, B., Radcliff, B., Taber, e. and Timpone, R. (1995). Condorcet winners and the paradox
of voting: Probability calculations for weak preferences orders. American Political Science
Review 89: 137-147.
Klahr, D. (1966). A computer simulation of the paradox of voting. The American Political
Science Review 60: 384--390.
May, R.M. (1971). Some mathematical remarks on the paradox of voting. Behavioral Science
16: 143-151.
Niemi, R.G. (1970). The occurrence of the paradox of voting in university elections. Public
Choice 91-100.
Niemi, R.G. and Weisberg, H.F. (1968). A mathematical solution for the probability of the
paradox of voting. Behavioral Science 13: 317-323.
Niemi, R.G. and Wright, J.R. (1987). Voting cycles and the structure of individual preferences.
Social Choice and Welfare 4: 173-183.
Radcliff, B. (1994). Collective preferences in presidential elections. Electoral Studies 13: 5057.
[268 ]
487
Riker, W.H. (1965). Arrow's Theorem and some examples of the paradox of voting. In J,.M.
Claunch (Ed.), Mathematical applications in political science, 41-60. Dallas: Southern
Methodist University Press.
Riker, W.H. (1982). Liberalism against populism. San Francisco: Freeman.
Sen, A. (1966). A possibility theorem on majority decisions. Econometrica 34: 491-499.
Tiinnsjo, T. (1992). Populist democracy: A defence. London: Routledge.
Tullock, G. (1981). Why so much stability? Public Choice 37: 189-202.
Van Deemen, A.M.A. (1993). Paradoxes of voting in list systems of proportional representation. Electoral Studies 12: 234-241.
Vergunst, N.P. (1995). De empirische bruikbaarheid van de stemparadox. Master thesis.
Nijmegen: Katholieke Universiteit Nijmegen (In Dutch).
Vergunst, N.P. (1996). Besluitvorming over kemcentrale Borssele: Een analyse van de
stemparadox in de Nederlandse politiek. Acta Politica 31: 209-228.
Data sources
Dutch Parliamentary Election
Dutch Parliamentary Election
Dutch Parliamentary Election
Dutch Parliamentary Election
Studies
Studies
Studies
Studies
1982.
1986.
1989.
1994.
Steinmetz Archive/SWIDOC.
Steinmetz Archive/SWIDOC.
Steinmetz Archive/SWIDOC.
Steinmetz Archive/SWIDOC.
[269]
>-
N
-..l
't:l
't:l
0
~
=
....
Q.
~
Table App. 1. Majority scores for the 1982 elections in the Netherlands: N(XPiY)
Party
CDA
VVD
PvdA
D66
DS70
PPR
PSP
SGP
CPN
GPV
RPF
BP
CP
CDA
VVD
PvdA
D66
DS70
PPR
PSP
SGP
CPN
GPV
0
351
460
320
110
232
189
44
154
47
20
21
583
513
0
364
194
116
85
130
50
129
119
62
37
600
528
480
0
140
180
144
100
117
95
88
40
35
634
596
544
498
0
242
192
106
153
108
102
44
35
675
607
551
508
251
0
115
143
79
138
125
73
45
702
633
597
581
303
276
0
161
93
152
139
75
45
727
656
615
593
306
342
249
0
194
77
83
50
43
760
690
665
637
346
348
254
195
0
191
171
103
53
743
672
636
614
329
354
272
108
209
0
76
46
45
733
659
634
599
326
356
267
123
207
RPF
486
0
473
303
105
239
191
78
156
74
73
27
18
778
715
661
648
376
384
299
196
222
171
161
0
40
788
720
671
660
397
408
321
228
226
218
194
110
0
BP
CP
44
Source: Dutch Parliamentary Election Panel Study 1981-86 (n = 1206).
92
0
55
40
-I':-
00
00
Table App. 2. Majority scores for the 1986 elections in the Netherlands N(XPiY)
Party
CDA
PvdA
D66
VVD
PPR
PSP
CPN
SGP
GPV
EVP
RPF
CP
CDA
PvdA
D66
VVD
PPR
PSP
CPN
SGP
GPV
EVP
RPF
CP
0
575
456
286
301
234
212
56
53
85
53
645
0
472
471
168
120
90
174
171
114
141
28
624
536
0
403
162
154
122
109
106
86
86
17
668
672
565
0
355
283
254
121
113
145
100
14
762
727
706
590
0
152
109
179
163
121
132
20
800
760
757
622
349
0
146
177
163
133
137
21
844
805
825
661
445
329
0
247
224
206
196
25
855
756
804
634
445
314
265
0
77
163
77
23
860
769
815
642
467
333
281
133
0
155
55
21
848
794
830
653
477
334
275
201
164
846
772
821
646
474
334
367
148
100
160
0
21
944
875
930
759
588
467
367
328
314
330
285
0
11
0
139
23
Source: Dutch Parliamentary Election Study 1986 (n = 1356).
t-.)
--
-..I
+>-
00
1.0
490
Table App. 3. Majority scores for the 1989 elections in the Netherlands: N(xPiY)
Party
CDA
PvdA
D66
VVD
GRLNKS
SGP
GPV
RPF
CD
CDA
PvdA
D66
VVD
0
637
581
335
365
90
88
80
43
728
0
573
472
226
187
204
180
48
698
613
0
435
229
152
154
137
47
807
763
737
0
498
186
195
169
43
GRLNKS
SGP
GPV
RPF
CD
889
845
873
646
0
214
226
201
67
990
925
1002
761
646
0
151
125
61
989
931
1006
759
646
154
0
72
62
975
931
1008
762
651
181
149
0
62
1113
1074
1146
912
806
443
443
408
0
Source: Dutch Parliamentary Elections Study 1989 (n = 1506).
[272]
Public Choice 97: 491-523, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
491
The spatial character of Russia's new democracy
MISRA MYAGKOV 1 & PETER C. ORDESROOK2
1 Department of Political Science, University of Oregon, Eugene, OR 97403-1284, U.S.A.;
2Division of Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena,
CA 91125, U.S.A.
Abstract. To date, virtually all research on Russian elections, beginning in 1991, have used
tools and methodological approaches akin to voting research from the 1950s and 1960s. Researchers have relied either on public opinion polls that try to tease out correlations between a
standard menu of socio-economic characteristics, attitudes about candidates, and self-reports
of voting history; or on journalistic assessments of aggregate election returns, coupled with
substantive expertise of Russian politics. Here, then, we try to gain an understanding of those
elections in more contemporary theoretical terms - in terms ofthe spatial analysis of elections
and voting. Although our analysis relies on a less-than-optimal source of data - election returns
aggregated up to the level of individual rayons (countries) - we are able to draw a spatial
map of those elections that is not too dissimilar from what others infer using less explicit
methodologies. Specifically, we find that throughout the 1991-1996 period, a single issuereform - has and continues to dominate the electorate's responses to candidates and parties.
On the other hand, we find little evidence of the emergence of "nationalism" as an issue, but
conclude that to the extent we can detect this issue in the 1996 presidential contest, one candidate, General Alexander Lebed, did succeed in differentiating himself from other nationalist
candidates (most notably, Vladimir Zhirinovski) without abandoning the reformist camp. In
general, then, this preliminary analysis suggests that the same tools used elsewhere to uncover
the spatial map of elections and the connection between basic and actionable issues (individual
level thermometer score rankings of candidates and parties) can be applied to Russia with the
promise of coherent, understandable results.
1. Introduction
Russia's transition to democracy and its electoral processes in particular are
presumed to be bedeviled by a multitude of problems, including voters who
are not well-acquainted with democratic as opposed to Soviet-style elections,
an expansive menu of candidates and parties with ill-defined platforms and
policy positions, a political elite well-schooled in the mechanics of electoral
fraud and other forms of corruption, an economy that encourages acceptance
of radical policy proposals, and an international environment including the
expansion of NATO and the loss of super-power status that feeds the flames
of nationalism. Nevertheless, despite Vladimir Zhirinovski's meteoric rise
[273 ]
492
in the 1993 parliamentary election, and an apparent communist resurgence
accompanied by the virtual disappearance of the traditional electoral standard
bearer of reform, Russia's Choice, in the 1995 parliamentary contest, the
Russian electorate appears to be remarkably stable. Although Yeltsin's vote
in the 1996 presidential election did not equal his landslide victory in 1991,
he not only emerged as the strongest candidate in the first round of balloting,
but he also largely succeeded in the second round in pulling together all proreform voters to his side while simultaneously securing a disproportionate
and critical share of votes from Lebed's first round supporters (Myagkov et
aI., 1997).
This essay explores this apparent stability further by looking at what we
can infer about the structure of issues and candidate positions from the approximately 2,OOO-per-election rayon (county) level election returns. What
we want to reevaluate in particular is the electoral "map" of Russia drawn by
political commentators who have relied thus far on their general understanding of politics and candidates and on vote totals aggregated typically at the
regional and even national level. That map offers a picture of an electorate
first dominated by a single issue (attitudes toward reform) and that, with the
emergence of Zhirinovsky as a national figure in December 1993, saw the
addition of nationalism as a second relevant dimension. Subsequent elections
(the 1995 parliamentary and 1996 presidential elections) are assumed to have
reenforced this two-dimensional picture, with Zhirinovsky and a handful of
minor candidates and parties staking out nationalism as "their" issue, Yeltsin,
the communists led by Zyuganov, various splinter anti-reform parties, and
a fractured coterie of reformers jostling on a "reform" issue that seemed
mostly to be a referendum on Yeltsin's administration, and General Alexander
Lebed offering a compromise (centrist?) alternative on both issues. Indeed,
Lebed's emergence in 1995-96 as a potential successor to Yeltsin was attributed largely to his apparent ability to position himself on these issues so
as to secure a share of both pro-reform and nationalist voters in such a way
as to allow him to throw his support in one direction or the other between the
two rounds of presidential balloting.!
While public opinion surveys give credence to this electoral map (see,
e.g., Wyman et al., 1995; and Hough et al., 1996), its basic character derives
largely from inductive attempts to make sense of the ebb and flow of official
election returns from one election to another, aggregated up to the national
or regional levels, in the context of some strong priors as to the general
orientation of parties and candidates (see, e.g., McFaul, 1993; McFaul and
Fish, 1996; Boxer et aI., 1996; and Fish, 1995).
There is, of course, much to be learned from informed interpretations of
events. But such interpretations, when based on highly aggregated data, are
[274 ]
493
subject to the traditional statistical degrees-of-freedom problem and to the
informational limitations of the data analyzed. Thus, they cannot uncover
potential nuances that can profoundly affect the future course of events such
as the viability of Lebed's presumed electoral strategy in the event that only
he and some communist candidate compete in the nest presidential election.
Here, then, we reassess the extent to which a simple one- or two-dimensional
portrayal of the Russian electorate is appropriate using a less aggregated data
set and a methodology (factor analysis) whose limitations are more readily
deciphered than journalistic inference. Briefly, we find that although a shift
from a uni- to a two-dimensional structure characterizes the period 19911993, both the 1995 and 1996 elections give evidence of the emergence of
a more complex spatial structure - a structure that is not inconsistent with
the view that Russians, like voters elsewhere, not only judge on the basis of
ideological predispositions, but also on the basis of specific characteristics
of candidates (Enelow and Hinich, 1984; Hinich and Munger, 1994). We
support the general explanation for Lebed's ability to emerge as the third
largest vote-getter in 1996, but here at least we conclude that the extent of his
"compromise" is less than has been otherwise assumed. Perhaps as a portent
of the future, we argue that the compromise he achieved was no so great as to
alienate those who might support reform in the next presidential election. Finally, we also see evidence of the emergence in 1995 and 1996 of pro-reform
voters who nevertheless refuse to vote for Yeltsin or those associated with his
administration, except when their choice is between that administration and
a return to communist rule. It is these voters, in combination with Lebed's
overall strategy, that has thus far lent Lebed the aura in today's mass media
as "the man to beat" in the year 2000.
2. Methods and data
A spatial (Euclidean) construction in which issues are represented as segments of real lines, candidate platforms as points on these lines, and voters
as rational decision makers with well-defined issue preferences who vote
on the basis of their distance from candidate positions, is by now a wellaccepted representation of elections and a base paradigm for formal mathematical analyses of elections and candidate strategies (Ordeshook, 1997).
Correspondingly, statistically estimating the parameters of this representation
- the dimensionality of the issue space, the relative salience of issues, candidate positions, and distributions of voter preferences - using individual level
polling data in the form of responses to requests for cardinal (thermometer
score) or ordinal rankings of candidates has also advanced considerably (see,
e.g., Cahoon et al., 1978; Dow, 1997; Lin et al., 1996). This methodolog-
[275 ]
494
ical literature, though, reveals the difficulties associated with estimating a
complex nexus of parameters from even rich data: not only does the mathematical complexity of the underlying structural models make it difficult to
establish the statistical properties of estimates, but indeterminacies quickly
appear when estimating the requisite parameters.
Although these difficulties can be overcome with appropriate data drawn
from polls of individual voters and a few structural assumptions, they appear
to be insurmountable when the only numbers at our disposal are aggregate
election returns. For example, although it is tempting to conclude that if
candidate X's share of the vote exceeds candidate Y's share, then X must
on average rank higher than Y on the preference scales of voters, such an
inference is invalid unless a variety of restrictive assumptions about spatial
structure are satisfied. Candidate Y, may be sandwiched between two other,
more viable opponents so that despite aggregate returns, Y ranks higher than
X for a majority of the electorate. The fact is that aggregate data tells us,
in the absence of strategic voting, only the first-ranked alternative in each
voter's preference scale, whereas, as the methods of multidimensional scaling
reveal, reliable inferences about the parameters that concern us require data
on each voter's overall rank-ordering of the candidates and perhaps even some
cardinal measure of that ranking.
This is not to say that inferences from aggregate data are impossible or
injustifiable. The analysis of such data can often provide useful guidance
to further research, provided we appreciate fully their informational limitations and the assumptions that must be imposed in order to proceed. To
illustrate, suppose a single issue dominates campaign discourse, suppose the
electorate's preferences on that issue are normally distributed, and suppose
the candidates' (or parties') policy positions are uniformly dispersed so that
each occupies a unique position and each is approximately equidistant from
the candidate to his or her right and left. If all voters now vote for candidates nearest their preferred positions, then the candidates' vote totals should
decrease monotonically with their distance from the electorate's median preference. Notice also that as the overall distribution of preferences shifts from
one side to another, the votes for candidates on the same side of the issue
space will tend to rise and fall together whereas the votes for candidates on
opposite sides will tend to correlate negatively. Thus, if we have aggregate
data from a cross-section of election districts, each of which satisfies these
assumptions, and if the mean preferences across districts are themselves distributed so as to give some "meaningful" variance in election returns, then
we can use a simple factor analysis of aggregate returns to estimate the issue space (i.e., recover its unidimensionality) and the candidates' relative
positions on it.
[276 ]
495
Unfortunately, these assumptions (or their multidimensional extension)
need not be satisfied in any specific election. First, electoral rules such as
Russia's requirement that parliamentary seats can be won under proportional
representation only by those parties whose vote exceeds 5% of the total can
induce voters to act strategically - to vote for a competitive candidate or
party rather than the alternative closest to their ideal. Strategic voting can
also characterize Russia's presidential contest, since there, through the use of
majority rule with a runoff, voters might be concerned that a sincere vote will
result in a second-round choice between two wholly unacceptable alternatives. Second, absent any well-defined equilibrium and an evident clustering
of splinter parties at various issue positions, candidate positions need not
be uniformly distributed across the issue: a candidate who performs poorly
because he is squeezed out by adjacent opponents may actually be close to
the overall median preference. Third, nonvoting might correlate with policy
preferences so as to distort any statistical estimates: and in Russia in particular
there is evidence that turnout rates declined most rapidly among those who
supported Yeltsin in 1991 (Myagkov et aI., 1997). Fourth, preference distributions from one election district to another might not be sufficiently varied, as
when districts are either predominantly "pro" or "anti" reform, in which case
vote shares across regions will correlate in such a way as to produce a spatial
map in which candidates tend to be located at one of only two positions.
Finally, any monotonicity in the relationship between vote share and distance
from an electoral median can vanish if preferences are not unimodally distributed - something we cannot wholly discount for a country such as Russia
in which voters can be reasonably assumed to be polarized between pro- and
anti-reform policies.
Despite these limitations and indeterminacies, commentators and politicians find it hard or impossible to resist drawing inferences about the geography of an election using such data - to infer salient issues, voter perceptions
of the candidate's positions on those issues, and shifts from one election
to the next in issue salience, voter preferences, and candidate positioning.
This fact and the fact that the requisite individual level polling data remain
unavailable or unreliable for countries like Russia compels us to examine
more closely the things we can infer from aggregate data, including a factor analytic treatment of that data. After all, even though such an analysis
proceeds on tenuous theoretical grounds, our advantage here is that our assumptions can be made wholly transparent. Thus, we can suggest alternative
hypotheses for the patterns we find in the aggregate data that can be explored
subsequently in future elections with more refined data. So even though we
cannot offer definitive conclusions, we can give direction to the gathering of
more precise individual-level data. Briefly, the data we use consist of official
[277 ]
496
rayon-level election returns for all Russian elections beginning with 1991
through the 1996 presidential election, including the April 1993 referendum
that amounted to a vote of confidence on Yeltsin's administration in his conflict with the increasingly recalcitrant Congress of People's Deputies. The
sole exception to the comprehensiveness of our data is the December 1993
parliamentary contest. There, since Russia's Central Election Commission
has, suspiciously, never published official election returns except at the regional level, we rely on unofficial returns covering approximately half the
rayons and which appear to represent a relatively unbiased cross-section of
the country (for additional discussion of this data see Myagkov and Sobyanin,
1995). Thus, with the exception of 1993, we have approximately 2,000 observations for each election, where the specific elections considered are these:
the 1991 presidential contest held before the dissolution of the Soviet
Union in which Boris Yeltsin first assumed the office of the presidency
of the Russian Republic,
the April 1993 referendum in which voters were asked to answer four
questions that directly or indirectly amounted to a vote of confidence in
Yeltsin's reform efforts,
the December 1993 parliamentary election in which the neo-Nazi Vladimir Zhirinovsky out-polled all other parties with 23% of the vote but
in which Yeltsin succeeded in securing majority approval for his constitution for the now-sovereign Russian Federation.
the December 1995 parliamentary contest that saw a resurgence in communist party support, the virtual disappearance of the old standard bearer
of reform, Russia's Choice, and the first electoral appearance of General
Alexander Lebed,
the 1996 June-July presidential contest in which Yeltsin won reelection, but only after being required to confront his communist challenger,
Gennady Zyuganov in the second round of balloting after forming an
explicit coalition with Lebed and an implicit and grudging one with
another reform candidate, Gregory Yavlinski.
In the next section, 3, we briefly review the results of a simple factor analysis
of the returns for each of these elections in order to see whether our results
correspond to the electoral maps drawn by commentators on those elections.
Here we see evidence of increasing dimensionality in the issue space from
one election to the next (excepting the April 1993 referendum) although
the issue of reform remains predominant throughout the period. The issue
[278]
497
of nationalism, on the other hand, barely registers on our radar screen, and
then only in 1996. In Section 4 we divide our data into three categories
- rayons that strongly support reform (or Yeltsin), those that support antireform candidates or parties, and "others". What we infer from this analysis
is that although the Russian electorate appears to be remarkably stable and
consistent in terms of the dimensionality of the issue space and in terms of
the spatial positioning of candidates, there is interesting evidence that voters
in June 1996 (the first round of balloting in the presidential contest) voted
strategically for the primary contenders and that Yeltsin's strategy - allowing
Lebed full reign to campaign in that round in the expectation that he would
draw votes from other nationalist candidates but that these votes would be
won over by Yeltsin in the second round - largely succeeded. Section 5 concludes with a variety of cautionary notes about the inferences we can draw
from the aggregate data.
3. Trends from 1991 to 1996
3.1. The 1991 presidential contest
Beginning with the 1991 presidential election in which Yeltsin won with
57.3% of the votes and in which his nearest rivals, the communist Ryzhkov
and the neo-Nazi Zhirinovski, won only 16.9% and 7.8% respectively, Table 1 reports the results of a factor analysis of the data that considers these
three candidates, two minor contestants, and the category "against all", while
Figure 1 offers a spatial portrayal of their estimated positions.
Table 1. 1991 presidential election
Factor
Eigenvalue
% Variance
Cumulative %
"explained"
2.71
45.2
19.4
45.1
64.6
2
1.16
3
4
.77
12.9
77.4
.67
11.1
88.6
5
.49
8.1
96.7
The picture drawn by Figure 1 should come as no surprise to those with
even a passing familiarity with the 1991 election. As that figure shows, the
1991 contest was largely a competition between Yeltsin and the rest of the
[279]
498
1.0
0.8
0.6
0.4
=~:+
...VELJSiN..............+....................................;.................................../.............................Q........~L
..........................
C\I
g
0.2
()
<II
u..
0.0
Z1RINOVS
o
-0.2
-0.4
-0.6
-1.0
-0.6
-0.2
0.2
0.6
1.0
Factor 1
Figure 1. 1991 Presidential election, national data.
field, where the first and dominant dimension corresponds closely to the issue
of pro- versus anti-reform (or at least to a referendum on Yeltsin's "stick-itin-your-eye" stance with respect to anyone associated with the old regime).
Rizhkov and Makashov were clear stand-ins for the old communist regime,
Bakatin, although not an opponent of reform, was nevertheless likely to be
associated with the status quo owing to his position as Gorbachev's Interior
Minister, and Zhirinovski was by then a vocal opponent of nearly everything
and anything.
Admittedly, Table 1 presents us with the usual dilemma in determining the
dimensionality of the issue space. There is a rapid drop in percent variance
explained after the first factor, but thereafter it is a matter of taste whether,
in reporting these results, we should pay heed to factors 2, 3 or 4. In this
regard it is worth noting that with only six candidates, including the Against
All ballots, we will necessarily see an appreciable increase in "variance explained" as additional factors are considered. Thus, it is best to postpone the
interpretation of this table until we examine additional elections, except to
say that the first dimension takes clear precedence over all others in that it
alone accounts for nearly half the variance in election returns.
[280]
499
3.2. The April 1993 referendum
As part of the increasingly nasty conflict between Yeltsin and Russia's parliament, the Congress of People's Deputies, Russians were asked in Aprill993
to answer four questions:
Do you have confidence in President Boris Yeltsin?
Do you approve of the socioeconomic policy carried out by the president
of the Russian Federation and the government of the Russian Federation
since 1992?
Do you consider it necessary to carry out early elections for the president
of the Russian Federation?
Do you consider it necessary to carry out early elections for the deputies
of the Russian Federation?
Clearly, the pro-Yeltsin position on these questions was to vote Yes-YesNo-Yes, and it seemed clear that the only issue under consideration in this
vote would be people's attitudes toward reform. This presumption is largely
verified in Figure 2 and Table 2, where the positioning of the "Yes" response
to the third question is diametrically opposite that of "Yes" responses to the
other three questions and where the first factor alone accounts for 73% of
the variance. There is, nevertheless, some residual variance explained by a
second factor that differentiates questions three and four from the first two,
thereby reflecting the fact that although a voter might support Yeltsin and his
policies in general, he or she might also prefer new elections for all national
offices.
Table 2. 1993 April referendum
Factor
Eigenvalue
% Variance
Cumulative %
"explained"
2
2.20
73.4
73.4
.22
7.4
80.8
[281]
500
0.45 , . . . . - - - - . . . - - - - - , - - - - - , . . - - - - - - - , , - - - - - - , , - - - - - - ,
,
,
0.35 ......
,
·y~I
t\I
j
~05-
~-!I+lr
-0.15
L -_ _ _' - -_ _ _' - -_ _ _' - -_ _ _' - -_ _ _' - -_ _---.J
-1.2
-0.8
-0.4
0.0
0.4
0.8
1.2
Factor 1
Figure 2. 1993 April referendum.
3.3. The 1993 parliamentary election
Following Yeltsin's artillery assault on and termination of the Congress of
People's Deputies, Russia's first party-based election as a sovereign state
occurred in December 1993. Thirteen parties vied for the 225 seats allocated
by national party list proportional representation, and eight succeeded in surpassing the 5% threshold for representation. 2 Judging by their platforms and
the public utterances of those who headed the list, the most visible pro-reform
party lists were the ones headed by Yeltsin's ex-Prime Minister and economic
reform guru, Yegor Gaidar, the explicitly pro-Western economist Yavlinski,
and Yeltsin's legal advisor, Sergi Shakrai (for an ordering of the parties and
candidates based on their public utterances and reputations see, e.g., McFaul
and Fish, 1996). The centrist or moderate pro-reform positions were presumed to included Travkin's list and Women of Russia. The Communist Party
(CPRF) and their fellow-traveling Agrarians (APR) anchored the opposition,
while Zhirinovski's Liberal Democrats (LDPR) sought to claim nationalism
as its issue along with ambiguous utterances on reform. Table 3 and Figure 3
summarize the results of our analysis, which in this instance, is limited to
unofficial data and which excludes the important heavily pro-reform regions
of Moscow and St. Petersburg.
.
As with 1991 and April 1993, we see again that the first factor cleanly separates pro- from anti-reform lists ("Small" in Figure 3 refers to the four small-
[282]
501
Table 3. 1993 parliamentary election
Eigenvalue
% Variance
"explained"
Cumulative %
3.93
43.7
43.7
2
1.35
15.0
58.8
3
4
1.05
11.7
70.5
.83
.67
9.3
79.8
7.4
87.2
Factor
5
0.6
TRAVKIN
0
C';,RF
YAVLINSK
0
0.4
GAlpAR
0.2
SM~h
0.0
C\I
~ 01
LL
LDPR
0
-0.2 ..........
.................
~
APR
0
FORC93
0
SH, iKHRAI
-0.4 .........
!O
R""wr".."",
-0.6
-0.8
-1.0
0
-0.6
-0.2
0.2
0.6
1.0
Factor 1
Figure 3. 1993 Duma election.
est parties who failed to win any seats) and confirms to some extent the commonly perceived ideological orientation of the parties. Specifically, the ordering "Agrarian (APR), Communist (CPRF), Zhirinovski (LDPR), Women
of Russia (Ruswomen), Travkin, Shakrai, Yavlinksi, and Gaidar" is probably
not much different, if at all from, what most commentators would offer as
the ideological ordering of the parties. The position of Zhirinovski's LDPR,
though, is interesting in that we do not see here any evidence of "nationalism"
as an issue that differentiates the LDPR from the rest of the field. Instead, the
LDPR appears as a centrist party on both the first and the second dimensions.
We cannot, then, reject the argument that Zhirinovski's success derived more
[283 ]
502
from his relative positioning on the issues than from his presumed ability
to introduce new issues into the electoral debate. That is, the LDPR's firstplace finish in 1993 appears to derive more from Zhirinovski's abilities as a
campaigner - an ability that most commentators believed surpassed that of
his rivals, especially Yegor Gaidar, who believed that arguing for "macroeconomic stability" was a viable campaign platform with which to attract
people "experiencing" his reforms.
Insofar as the dynamics of dimensionality are concerned, we should keep
in mind that we are treating four more "candidates" here than in 1991, which
should require additional factors to achieve an equivalent level of significance. Correspondingly, Table 3 shows that it is increasingly difficult to assert
a unidimensional or even a 2-dimensional issue space. Although the first
factor, as above, clearly dominates the rest, the cumulative percent variance
explained increases a bit more slowly in 1993 than 1991, and after the first
factor, there is no clear cutoff point with which to argue that two dimensions
are "better" than three or that three is "better" than four. Notice though that
although this contrast with 1991 may be primarily an artifact of the number
of candidates considered, this same methodological problem would also be
likely to characterize journalistic assessments of election returns, especially
ones that are dependent on even a higher level of aggregation of the data. This
fact might account for the ease with which events in 1991 were interpreted as
unidimensional, while in 1993 - especially when explanations were offered
for Zhirinovski's success - the search commenced for additional issues, including that of nationalism. These methodological issues, though, should not
detract from the conclusion that attitudes toward reform remained the primary
basis for classifying parties.
3.4. The 1995 parliamentary election
The picture for the 1995 election to the State Duma portrays a contest in
which one dimension is no longer adequate to represent matters, but in which
the issue of reform remains, as in 1993, the primary basis for structuring
perceptions of candidates. Here, because of the great number of party lists (a
total of 43 were listed on the ballot and only four, with a fraction less than half
of the vote, surpassed the 5% threshold for representation 3 ), to compare our
results with previous elections, we offer two sets of eigenvalues and two sets
of spatial representations - one that considers only 7 parties, and the second
which considers 9 plus the "party of nonvoters". 4 First, looking at Table 4, we
see that with only seven parties, three factors account as before for over 70%
of the variance. However, the first factor accounts for only 36.2% as against
45.2% in 1991 (when we consider 6 candidates) and 43.7% in 1993 (when
we consider 10 party lists).5 Moreover, when we add three parties - two
[284 ]
503
party lists plus nonvoters - so as to make our analysis here comparable to our
analysis of the 1993 parliamentary contest, the importance of the first factor
declines to 30.7% and it becomes virtually impossible to choose between a
3,4 or greater-dimensional representation - the decline in variance explained
from one factor to the next exhibits no discernable step. Clearly, then, the
dimensionality of the issue space in 1995 exceeds that for 1993 and 1991.
Table 4. 1995 parliamentary election
Eigenvalue
% Variance
"explained"
Cumulative %
Factor 1
2.53
36.2
36.2
Factor 2
1.37
19.5
55.7
Factor 3
1.04
15.0
70.7
Factor 4
.81
11.5
82.2
Factor 5
.58
8.3
90.5
Factor 1
3.06
30.7
30.7
Factor 2
1.47
14.7
45.3
Factor 3
1.17
11.7
57.0
Factor 4
.90
9.0
66.0
Factor 5
.87
8.7
74.7
Factor 6
.81
8.1
82.8
7-candidate recovery
lO-candidate recovery
Turning now to the graphical representation of these factors, note first
from Figures 4a,b and 5a,b that the recovery of spatial positions on the first
three dimensions is largely insensitive to the number of candidates considered
(a similar picture obtains with a 5-candidate recovery). Insofar as the substantive interpretation of these dimensions is concerned, we see that once again,
the first dimension differentiates between pro-reform and anti-reform parties,
with Yeltsin's stand-in, Chernomyrdin's Our Home Is Russia (OHR), being
the most centrally located "reform" party. And as with 1993, the positioning
of candidates on the second dimension again fails to reveal nationalism as
a salient issue. Although Zhirinovski and Lebed after him occupy one end
of that dimension, Chernomyrdin occupies the other extreme. Indeed, Chernomyrdin's position here suggests that this second dimension has less to do
with nationalism per se, but instead corresponds to something more like "the
party in power versus everyone else". We suspect, in fact, that to the extent
[285 ]
504
1.0 ....------,----,----r---...,----..,-----r---,----o----,
OHR
°
i
! .................. ;....................;..
·············1······················j··
0.8
.
..... \......................1.. .................. ;......................i......................~.
0.4
(\I
~
~.
....... 1...................... 1. ...................
0.6
0.2 .....................: ....................:.................... :.................... :..... .
.
..... :..... ............... j..•... ,............... ~ .....................
j
j
....... "....................,............... ····+···········AMPIl-oV··············
.
~
0.0 ···········G:4:iDAR·········j··············!·· ·············i··········· ..... !
io
-0.2
YIl'v~NL
......... ~ ....
°i
..... j..................
.~
.................... .
~gr
.
. . . . . ; . . . . + ......! .;+~RF
-0.4 ..................... :...................... :........... ·····... ·lj.~-
... ,
.... :.....
....................... .~ .....................
uj)PR
-0.6 ...... ····· ........ ··;·······....··· .... ·· ..;..·.. ·· ....·· ...... ···i..
.................... i..·.···· .....·....·.··i.......····· .....·)l.···················t···
-0.8 L-_--'_ _--'-_ _-'-_ _-'-_ _-'--_--'_ _--'-_ _-'-_ _.J
0.4
0.8
-1.0
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.6
Factor 1
Figure 4a. December 1995 Duma election.
that this second dimension serves essentially as a way to differentiate the current regime, represented by Chernomyrdin, it is much like a valence issue in
spatial theory (Enelow and Hinich, 1984) - something like "either you believe
that Chernomyrdin is the least risky alternative, or you prefer change, left or
right". However, whatever interpretation we give this second dimension, it
seems clear that a simple left-right conceptualization of political competition
became less relevant in 1995 than it had been in previous elections.
Figures 4a and 5a are interesting in two other respects. First, note that
nonvoters in Figure 4a fall on the reform side of the first factor, which is to
say that those who voted in 1996 but not in 1995 were predominantly proreform voters. Thus, if we combine this fact with the finding that the general
decline in turnout between 1991 and 1993 came largely at the expense of
pro-reform candidates (M yagkov et al., 1997), we see some of the stability of
the Russian electorate. That is, it appears as though a significant share of the
shifting fortunes of Yeltsin and his allies between 1991 and 1996 derived from
decreased turnout among pro-reform voters as opposed to fundamental shifts
in preference, and that when those voters returned to the polls in 1996, they
reappeared once again as Yeltsin voters. Thus, Yeltsin's strategy in 1996 of
encouraging turnout appears to have been more than mere civic-mindedness.
The second interesting thing to notice about Figures 4a and 5a is Lebed's
relative positioning. Generally identified in the Moscow media as a sane
alternative to Zhirinovski's nationalism, Lebed in fact appears to belong to
[286 ]
505
0.6
l. . . . . . . . . . lf>. . . . . .·Or. ·. . . . . . . .
L$PR
0.4
. . . . . . . . . . r. . . . . . ·. . . ·!· ..................
0.2
......
i
....
·YAV~NK
!....................
......................'.. ·........ ~·
tC~
·I"....·............T................
l
..
l
AMPI~OV
r--....·............·T. . . . . . . . . . ·. . . . . . . . . . . ·. . . . . . . . . .
·r. . . . . . . . .
0.0 ·····················!······················r·····················!······················1······················!······················r·····················r·····················r····················
. . . .~IDAR ·r. . . . . . . . :i ·. . . . . . . . ;. . . . . . . . . . . !'......................!....................·T:, ....................-r. . . . . . . . . . r. . . . . . .
t')
~
LL
-0.4 ··....······.. ·······;······················1······ ..............,............
-0.6
-0.8
l...
i
,0
-0.2
'
i
········1················· ...:......................,......................1".................... ]"...................
-T~;=r:
-1.0 ~-'
-1.0
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
Factor 1
Figure 4b. December 1995 Duma election.
1.0
1
0.8
0.6
0.4
C\I
~
LL
0.2
:
....................·!..........· ........··i.... ·, ................!..............~
1
......................:......................:......................:...................... t ....................
--i-,.!---t---,---l-I----l-f-~
·. :. :·.rt~J
0.0 ......
·.FA~'R
1
:
~
r-· ........·......
...... :
YAVLINSK,
1
. . .
. .:·.·.::::"·:::::J..:::::::.::::"::::J.:.:·::..:.·r~,;f"'j
,
.
!......
...... -·i,~.
:
1
1
:
1
.................--... ~"., .......................
i
,
,
,
i,,:::. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
,
-0.2 .................. o .. ·.................. ·!......................!......................!......................!......................!...................... !....................1"...................
-0.4
. . . . . . . . . . .,. . . . . .~l . . . . . . . . . .!......................i"....................,......................l...................~
. . . . . . . . . . ,. . . . . . . . . . . :. . . . . . . . . . . (. . . . . . . . . ,. . . . . . . . . . ·r. . . . . . . . . ·r. . . . . . . . .
,
-0.6
-0.8
"
..............
+. . . . . . . . . .
T. . . . . . . . ·.
LOP-R'
9....................
1--_ _' - -_ _' - - _ - - - '_ _---'_ _---'_ _---'-_ _---'-_ _---'-_ _- '
-1.0
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
Factor 1
Figure 5a. December 1995 Duma election.
[287 ]
506
,
0.8
0.6
0.4
0.2
:=Ifl-i1"~t
CO)
j
0.0
-0.2
-0.4
-0.6
-0.8
-1.0
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
Factor 1
Figure 5b. December 1995 Duma election.
the camp of refonners on the first dimension, whereas his distance from Our
Home Is Russia on the second dimension suggests his success at establishing
himself as an outsider to Moscow's politics or at least as distancing himself
from Yeltsin's administration.
3.5. The 1996 presidential election
Finally we come to June 1996, the first round of balloting in Russia's first
presidential election since the dissolution of the USSR. Focusing again on
the primary contenders - the five candidates who account for approximately
95% of the ballots (Yeltsin 35.3%, Zyuganov 32%, Lebed 14.5%, Yavlinski
7.3% and Zhirinovski 5.7%) - Table 5 reports the eigenvalues for the first
three factors, while Figures 6a,b given the associated spatial positions.
The first thing to notice is that the dimensionality here is approximately
the same as what we estimate for 1991 when considering 6 candidates. Thus,
whatever evidence we thought we saw through 1995 of an increase in dimensionality appears to have reversed itself somewhat in 1996. 6 More interesting,
though, is the spatial configurations portrayed in Figures 6a,b. Here, again,
we see Zyuganov to one side of the issue space and Yeltsin, Yavlinski and
Lebed on the other. The second dimension, though, more clearly than in
1995, appears to correspond to nationalism with Zhirinovski and Lebed anchoring one end of this dimension and Yeltsin the other. Arguably, though,
this second dimension, given Zyuganov's position, might be interpreted as
[288 ]
507
0.8
,
,
,
0,
............................................j................................. +................................. j.......................¥Q;l'$w ....................
0.6
0.4 ..·· .......................... t ......................·........ ..!................................·+ .................................,..............................................
0.2
................................ ":'...............................i·································t····............................. j..................................}................................
ZVUGANOV ,
C\I
5
()
If
,
,
,
t. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ·l.··································}·····...........................
i
i
...............................+.................................!. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . +...............................!. . . . . . . . . Y.~N!L
........................ .
0.0 .................9. ............ ~ ..............................·!................................
t
-0.2
:
j
·········· . ·t··
-0.4
-0.6 .............................................
~
: : : : L...
.._...._..._.... ..._...._..._
...._...
-1.2
:
· _ ···············1·.. ····
·~
ZlRINOVS
-0.4
·~
;
·-i....i
.. ·..
_·....
__.. ...._..·....
__...._..
0.0
1
·······1·································l············....................
................. .LEBED ....................1.........
..........,.................. ...........
....i
.. -_
...._._...._.. ·_
...._..·_
...._...._.. ·.i.·i.._.. ...._.. ·_
...._...._..·_·I?_
..·_
..
-0.8
.
···t························
0
;
'
,
~
·....i·l_
.. ·_
...._...._..·_
...._..·_
...._..·_
.....i.
...._......._..._
...._..._
...._.. ---I
0.4
0.8
1.2
Factor 1
Figure 6a. June 1996 presidential election.
0.6r-~,
,
lEBED
0.4
i
........· .................. ·.. f................................ ·:..............·................ t ...............................1" ............................+
..............
0.2
.......Z'tU~NOV
0
..
,
·t. . . . . . . . ·............!. . . . ·. . . . . . . . . . . ·t. . ·. . . . . . . . . . . ·. . ·!.................. ~·l
:
0
..............·
i
j ;
i
i
0.0 ................................ y..................... ············!·································t·································i·································f································
L~
-0.2
.
-0.4 .................. ........·+-..............................·i.. ·............................
.
,
,
0,
,
,
..~ ............................. ··j· ....··· ....·· ......··VeiTtiij.. ..
.
................................ '\" ................................. ! .......... .
·t. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
:
0,
I. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ·
~
1
:
j..................................
-0.6 ................................ +........· ...................... ·, ................l.\RINO.Vi ................................. j...............................,) ................................
!----..!. ----"-!-----'
-0.8 ' - - - - - - ' - - - - - - - " - - - -......
-1.2
-0.8
-0.4
0.0
0.4
0.8
1.2
Factor 1
Figure 6b. June 1996 presidential election.
[289]
508
Table 5. 1996 presidential election, first round
Factor
Eigenvalue
% Variance
Cumulative %
"explained"
1
2.29
45.8
45.8
2
1.33
26.7
72.6
3
.77
15.5
88.1
"old faces versus new faces" and, absent other evidence, should not then be
taken as evidence that Russian's are increasingly sympathetic to allowing
their sense of nationalism to overtake their attitudes toward reform as the
primary basis for evaluating candidates. The third factor, moreover, primarily
differentiates between Zhirinovski and Lebed, and suggests that even if the
second dimension captures some part of the issue of nationalism, Russian
voters can differentiate a sane alternative (ostensibly Lebed) and one who,
although admittedly a skilled campaigner, is willing arguably to make any
utterance to gain media attention.
Equally interesting is the inference we can draw from this figure as to
Yeltsin's strategy for defeating Zyuganov in the second round. If we take
Figure 6a and, after scaling to reflect relative eigenvalues, draw the bisecting
lines so as to map out the areas of support for each candidate, we would
find that once Zhirinovski, Lebed, and Yavlinski are eliminated, Zyuganov
wins most of Zhirinovski's voters, while Yeltsin gets all of Yavlinski's and
Lebed's. Making an explicit appeal for Zhirinovski's vote by promising him
a position in his government was, of course, out of the question for Yeltsin,
and of the two other possibilities, the most uncertain block is Lebed's even
though, ceteris paribus, they should vote for Yeltsin in the second round. 7
But an interim coalition between Yeltsin and Lebed, as events revealed, came
at no cost to Yeltsin (indeed, he arguably gained not only votes, but a cease
fire in Chechnya whose unraveling could be blamed on Lebed) and rendered
the support of Lebed's voter more secure.
4. The "anomaly" of the pro-reform regions
Aside from the substantive importance of the contest, Russia's 1996 presidential election is interesting because of its strategic complexity, the uncertain
response of voters to the war in Chechnya, and the fact that "reform" had
brought something other than beneficial results to an increasingly large part
[290]
509
of the population. First, with respect to strategic complexity, we know that
majority rule with a runoff gives candidates ample incentive to try to position
themselves so that, if they fail to progress to the second round, they can use
their support as currency in negotiations with one or both of the two leading
candidates. Lebed in particular understood this strategic environment and,
with an eye to both the current contest and to the next presidential election,
appeared to have successfully positioned himself to become pivotal in 1996
and Yeltsin's heir apparent in 2000. The strategic environment for voters is no
less interesting since for many of them the choice in the first round is between
a sincere vote for a most-preferred candidate versus a strategic vote for the
least objectionable viable one. Pro-reform and anti-reform voters, though,
confronted different environments in 1996. The clear leader of the anti-reform
camp was Zyuganov, who was virtually certain to be on the ballot in the event
of a second round. Indeed, until Yeltsin's resurgence in the polls, the question
here was whether Zyuganov could win an outright victory on the first ballot,
and, if not, how great his margin of victory would be over a candidate such
as Zhirinovski. Thus, the average voter in a rayon in which most voters are
opposed to Yeltsin or any reform candidate has the lUXury of not having to
cast a strategic ballot. They can vote straightforwardly for Zyuganov, or, if nationalism is most salient, for Lebed. In contrast, pro-reform voters needed to
decide which "reform" (i.e., anti-communist) candidate - Yeltsin, Yavlinski,
or Lebed - had the best chance of defeating Zyuganov. And although Yeltsin,
as the product of a skilled campaign staff and not a little "maneuvering" (e.g.,
briefcases filled with non-consecutively marked $100 bills) emerged in the
end as the front runner, that position may have been hidden from view for all
but those voters with access to and a taste for weekly public opinion polls.
Thus, it is reasonable to speculate that one concern of voters who ranked
Yeltsin below any reform candidate but above Zyuganov or Zhirinovski is
that absent strategic voting on their part, the second round of voting would
present them with the Hobson's choice of a communist, Zyuganov, versus a
neo-Nazi, Zhirinovski.
Rendering 1996 more complex still is the fact that the definitions of "reform" and "anti-reform" also arguably blurred. Yeltsin, the clear leader of
the pro-reform camp in 1991 and 1993, could readily be seen to have eroded
his position owing to the general increase in corruption within his administration, policies that benefitted only a handful of "New Russians", and the
unsuccessful yet bloody pursuit of a military victory in the secessionist republic of Chechnya. And although Yavlinski could unambiguously be classified
as "pro-reform", and Zyuganov as "anti-reform",8 it remained unclear even
as voters entered the voting booths how they would perceive Yeltsin and
[291]
510
how their perceptions would interact with the electoral system's strategic
imperatives.
Finally, there is the argument that by 1996 at least, the Russian electorate
had become wholly polarized between reform and anti-reform positions, reflecting the attitudes of those who had by then benefitted directly or indirectly
from privatization versus those who continued to wait for pension checks
that would not even pay for a below-subsistence grocery list. Yeltsin's support, however defined, had been in continual decline since 1991, whereas
Zyuganov and the old guard appeared to have been able to maintain all of
their original support while taking full advantage of Zhirinovski's diminished
standing. If anyone occupied "the middle" is was Lebed, but few gave him
much of a chance of entering the second round of balloting by countering
Zyuganov's communist party organization or Yeltsin's influence over the regional authorities who would administer the election or the bankers who
might fund a campaign.
With these ideas in mind, let us now consider June 1996, but rather than
look at the national sample taken as a whole, we first divide regions into three
categories: "strong pro-Yeltsin" (n = 510), "strong anti-Yeltsin" (n = 510),
and "moderate" (n '" 1000) so that we can try to get a sense of how, on
average, voters of different types responded to the candidates. 9 Table 6, then,
begins by giving the eigenvalues and variance "explained" for the first three
factors for each of these subpopulations and reveals that although rayons from
"moderate" and "anti-Yeltsin" regions give approximately the same results in
terms of the relative importance of the first and second factors, with the first
factor explaining two or three times the variance of the second, the rayons
from strongly pro-Yeltsin regions produce two factors that are nearly equal
in terms of variance explained. This, of course, is the first instance in our
analysis in which the first factor does not wholly outweigh the second.
The spatial portrayal of these factors and the candidates' positions on
them, given in Figures 7a,b, 8a,b, and 9a,b, is no less interesting.
Specifically, comparing Figures 8a and 9a notice that the relative positions
of the five candidates considered are approximately equivalent and not much
different from Figure 6a when we considered the national data set as a whole.
The third factor in Figures 8b and 9b primarily differentiates Lebed from
the other candidates, and, in particular, distinguishes between the two "nationalist" candidates - Lebed and Zhirinovski. Overall, then, it is apparent
from these figures that, as in our analysis of the national sample, Lebed is
something more than a refined version of Zhirinovski. His vote came predominantly from the "moderate" and "pro-reform" parts of the popUlation,
and, as such, was a natural coalition partner for Ye1tsin going into the second
round.
[292]
511
1.4
1.0
. :. . . . . . . . . . .:. . . . . . . . . . . !. . . . . . . . . . +. . . . . . . . . . j.....................+. . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . :. . . . . . . . . ..lv~O
i
1
r-r-i--'--r-+---'---I.:·····················
0.6
<'Ii
i
1
0.2 .....................1...................... \...................... \...................... j ....•••..•.••••.. ,•••. : ..•••.••••.•••••••.•••i ..,...................
I
II-
-0.2
. . . . . . . . . . .\. . . . . . . . . .+. . . . . .
.
-0.6
-1.0
.
;
.
:
: ,
I
:
;
ZI~NOVS
t.....................~ .....................
L~ED
AV~INSKY
10
·········1······················1······················1··················+····················1···.9.········....... j....................
I
:
·l:~;!1+
:
.........:....................,................... -:-...................
!
0
L--_ _- ' -_ _- ' -_ _
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
_ _-'--_ _-'-_ _-'-_ _---J'--_---'
-'_~L
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
1.0
Factor 1
Figure 7a. June 1996 presidential election, pro-Yeltsin regions.
0.8
:
-tI;+*~
0.6
:
:
:
0.4 ·····················:·····················r··················:····················r································································l·············......... ]""" ................. .
0.2
C')
~
~
.................
·····!··········· .. ·;~r
0.0 .................... .YEL.TSIN.......l. ...... ~
:
0
1
-j-...... ·!l~;
............ .
............i......................l ......................t.....................i......................~ ......................l.?.................
'
:
:
•
i
:
+. . . . . . . . . .
-0.2 ·····················,·····················r··················r··················i····················j·····............... 1...................... ,.....................
-0.4
-0.6
:~;-I=
!
!
!0
-0.8 L-_ _.l--_ _- ' -_ _-!' -_ _- ' -_ _- '!-_ _......L_ _- 'i-_ _-.i-_ _--'
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
1.0
Factor 1
Figure 7b. June 1996 presidential election, pro-YeJtsin regions.
[293 ]
512
0.4
0.2
"YA~NSKr'l,V
0.0
·'[~ri!I
.
.
.
i
t
!
i
j
i
I
I
..........................
..............i.................................;.................................~ ................................. J......•......•....................i................................
-0.2
Iii
C\I
j
YELJSIN.
--I----t--I---I---+. . . . . . . . . . ·. . . . . l. . . . . ·. . . . . . ·. . . . . . . . . . .r. . . . . . . . . . .
-0.4
-0.6
••••••••••..••••••.••••••••••••• .; •••••••••••••••.••••••.•••••••••. j •••.•••••••••••••••••••••••••••••.j. ••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••• j ..•••••...••••...•••..•••...••....j. ••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••
-0.8
1"...............................1"..............................
·:~;
································t·································!····Q··························t..·······························1·································t································
-1.0
-1.2 L-_ _ _--'-_
_ _---'1
_ _ _ _--'--_
_ _ _.i....-_
_ _- l
1 _ _ _-'-_
~
·1
l
-1.0
-0.6
-0.2
0.2
0.6
1.0
1.4
Factor 1
Figure 8a. June 1996 presidential election, anti-Yeltsin regions.
0.6
0.4
0.2
..,
j
0.0
-0.2
-0.4
-0.6
~l=-I:
•••••.••••••••..••••••.••••••••• +..••••••••••••••••••.
-0.8
-1.0
-0.6
············1·································0)···············..·····..·········1·····························..... ................................
~
-0.2
0.2
0.6
1.0
Factor 1
Figure 8b. June 1996 presidential election, anti-Yeltsin regions.
[294 ]
1.4
513
0.8
0.6 ·.. ·· ..·..·...... ·.. ·····.. ·· .. ·:. ··....·...... ·· .. ·· ......·..· .. ·1'·. ....... ····.. ·· ..··· ....·....
0.4
f· ........···· ....·. ··....···....j..·.... ···......·· ..·'Yr;:[f~N
:
:
0:
..·....··.... ·· .. ····· ....
0.2
0.0
N
~
01
u. -0.2
-0.4
-0.6 ................................L. .............................. j......................·.....··...t··....··.·· . ····..····..·..··.··I..····....
-0.8 ................................+.................................1................
~vL·
·~
...........······..f..·····..·..·····..···· ....·····
. . · ·. . . · · . · · . ·. I·....···..·. ·····. ·········....t. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ..
-1.0 L._ _ _-'-_ _ _---''--_ _ _-'-_ _ _--'-_ _ _ _......._ _ _....I
-0.8
-1.2
-0.4
0.0
0.4
0.8
1.2
Factor 1
Figure 9a. June 1996 presidential election, moderate regions.
0.6
0.4
0.2
..,
0.0
~
01
u. -0.2
~.=:i-rf
:!~=tI
-0.4
-0.8
-1.2
-0.8
-0.4
0.0
0.4
0.8
1.2
Factor 1
Figure 9b. June 1996 presidential election, moderate regions.
[295 ]
514
Table 6. 1996 presidential election, first round
Eigenvalue
% Variance
Cumulative %
"explained"
Pro-Yeltsin regions
Factor I
1.91
38.3
38.3
Factor 2
1.62
32.4
70.6
Factor 3
0.83
16.8
87.4
60.1
Anti-Yeltsin region
Factor I
3.00
60.1
Factor 2
1.16
23.2
83.3
Factor 3
0.44
8.8
92.1
2.48
49.7
49.7
Factor 2
1.20
23.9
73.6
Factor 3
0.79
15.8
89.5
Moderate regions
Factor I
However, Figures 7a and 7b, which concern the pro-Yeltsin regions, stand
in sharp contrast to these results. First, factor 1 seemingly inexplicably has
Yeltsin and Zyuganov occupying approximately the same position, while
the other three candidates, including Zhirinovski, occupy the polar opposite
point. Second, although factor 2 divides Yeltsin and Zyuganov so that it is
tempting to think of it as corresponding to an anti- versus pro-reform dimension, unlike factor 1 in Figures 8a and 9a, it leaves the remaining three candidates at the same position near the center. Figure 7a, then, is wholly unlike
any earlier counterpart, including Figures 8a and 9a for the anti-Yeltsin and
Moderate subpopulations. Moreover, even the third factor for the pro-Yeltsin
regions is unlike that factor in the remaining population. In Figure 7b, factor 3
essentially differentiates Yavlinski from Zhirinovski, whereas in Figures 8b
and 9b, it more or less differentiates Lebed from the others.
There are any number of explanations for such results, ranging from a
violation of the assumptions necessary to allow factor analysis to accurately
recover spatial maps to speculations about strategic voting under Russia's
runoff rules for presidential elections. However, before we speculate, it is
useful to reconsider the December 1995 parliamentary contest, which preceded the first round of presidential balloting by only six months. Dividing
our sample as before on the basis of the final round of balloting into Pro-
[296] .
515
1.2
,-'iI~:T_
C'I
~-'r",.
: LDPR
: 0
0.4············ ·..
l. . . . . . . . . . ·, . . . . . . . . . .
! O.~-!I:=Lr;
-0.4 ..........· ......
T. ·OHR....
!
0
r
1...................... ,..............
......j ........ ..,...
j
j
j
,
·l.......... · ......··\ ....·.... · ....:--· ...... ·....t .. ..
.
-0.8 L-_--'_ _--'-_ _--'-_ _-'-_ _-'--_ _'---_---i_ _--'-_ _-I
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
1.0
Factor 1
Figure JOa. December 1995 Duma election, pro-Yeltsin regions.
Ye1tsin, Anti-Yeltsin and Moderate regions, Table 7 reproduces Table 6, while
Figures 1Oa,b, lla,b, and 12a,b parallel those we show for the presidential
election.
Notice first with respect to Table 7 that the data from all three sub-populations look essentially equivalent - and in particular, unlike Table 6, there
is no sub-population for which the first two factors are of approximately
equal importance. The plots here of candidate positions also seem more in
keeping with initial expectations. Nevertheless, there is an important exception: although factor 1 appears to correspond to an anti- versus pro-reform
dimension and factor 2 appears primarily to separate Zhirinovski's LDPR
from other party lists, the list headed by prime minister Chernomyrdin, Our
Home Is Russia (OHR), is, like Ye1tsin himself in 1996, located far to the
right in pro-Yeltsin regions but, in keeping with our intuition about things,
is given a more centrist and pro-reform position in all other regions. Thus,
if we treat Yeltsin and Chernomyrdin as equivalent, the parallelism between
Figures 7a and 10a leads us to reject any speculation about strategic voting
and the like - speculations that relate to voting rules, since the rules in 1995
(party-list PR) and 1996 (majority rule with a runoff) are wholly distinct.
Insofar as other potential explanations are concerned, perhaps the one
most consistent with the usual journalistic interpretations of events concerns
the attitudes toward Yeltsin and his administration among pro-reform voters
in combination with the distribution of preferences in pro-reform regions.
[297 ]
516
0.6
0.4
~
0.2
..,...
0.0
-0.2
-0.4
-0.6
-0.8
-1.0 L-_.l~
-0.8
_ _-L._ _...L._ _. i . - _ - - - i_ _--i.._ _- ' -_ _.J
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
1.0
Factor 1
Figure lOb. December 1995 Duma election, pro-Yeltsin regions.
1.0
,
,
CPAF
o
!
0.6
GAlbAA
q
0.2
C\I
~
?f.
-0.2
-0.6
························r························;·························r·······················i························!························r·······················AMPiiov········
,
,
!
ii,
I
0
-1.0 L-_ _..L-_ _..L._ _--'-_ _--i.._ _- - '_ _ _' - -_ _.L-_ _.J
-1.0
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
Factor 1
Figure 11Q. December 1995 Duma election, anti-Yeltsin regions.
[298]
0.4
0.6
517
1.0
0.6
........................t........................
L........................;. .........................;.........................,c. •••••••••••••••••••••••• (. •••••••••••••••••••••••
i .........................
·"GA~R
0.4
r
C')
j
. . . . .···········t·..····················
··l··············..·····.. ·t................... ~J-B.
0.8 ........................;..................... ··l·························t
~=r:,l;I[-
0.2
0.0
-0.2
:
0:
~R'
.
.l........................~ ........................l. . . . . . . . . . . . l. . . . . . . . ~ . . . . . . . ..
:
::: I
.......•......................
:
.
:
:
AMPILOV
i
:
l". . . . . . . . . . . . .t................ ____.. 1
;
-0.4 ........................j.........................;...·····················t························
:
.
0
1 ........................1 .. __ _
1
_0.61....--_ _-'-_ _ _i........_ _--'--_ _---'_ _ _...i...._ _- - '_ _ _....i....._ _--'
-1.0
-0.6
-0.8
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
Factor 1
Figure 11 b. December 1995 Duma election. anti-Yeltsin regions.
0.8
,
_=:It~!
0.6
0.4
0.2
...
j
.
.
·!GA1D~R-i
.
o·
t\I
.s
0.0
..................... i .....................
i
:6
LL
-0.2 .... ·.. ·'iAVlJ~Sr
0:
-0.4
-0.6
;
i
;
~
I
j
j
: :
............... j.................... ~ ...................... !.................... j"...................... t ... .
.l......................L.....................!......................t .....................;,.....................J......................
'
,
.
........... ( ................... +..................... ;.........
I
:
..,......................,...
I
.j.................... .
AMPiLOV
j.....................q.................. ..
LEBED :
--__~!,i"-lj;.T+ . . . . . . .,. . . . . ,. . . . . . . . . ., . . .. . . . ,.
..rJR.........,......
_0.81....--_ _.i..-._ _..i..-_ _....i....._ _...i...._ _--'--_ _--'--_ _- ' -_ _- L_ _--'
-1.0
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
Factor 1
Figure 12a. December 1995 Duma election, moderate regions.
[299]
518
0.8
0.6
0.4
0.2
C')
~
:s
0.0
-0.2
-0.4
-0.6
-0.8
-1.0
-0.8
-0.6
-0.4
-0.2
0.0
0.2
0.4
0.6
0.8
Factor 1
Figure 12b. December 1995 Duma election, moderate regions.
First, in earlier elections, pro-reform voters, unlike their pro-communist counterparts, demonstrated a clear willingness to divide their vote among a variety
of party lists (Yabloko, Russia's Choice, Our Home Is Russia, and a double
handful of smaller parties led by individual personalities) or, when dissatisfied, to simply stay home. Indeed, reform candidates themselves in 1993 and
1995, viewed sometimes as a collection of prima donnas with presidential
aspirations, seemed to spend more time focusing on the policy and personality
differences among themselves than the things that set them apart from their
communist or anti-reform opposition. Thus, Yavlinski and Gaidar, both proWestern economists, found it impossible to coalesce in 1995, while it did
not seem at times in 1996 that Yavlinski cared whether his candidacy might
help elect Zyuganov. Add in economic and social circumstances along with
the war in Chechnya, and we can reasonably suppose that in December 1995
and June 1996 the more liberal and pro-reform a voter might be, the greater
would be the dissatisfaction with Yeltsin and his administration, and the more
likely would that person be to cast a ballot in 1995 for anyone of a handful of
splinter democratic parties or, in June 1996, for someone like Yavlinski or the
enigmatic General Lebed. This behavior, of course, would move Yeltsin (and,
extending that argument backwards, to December 1995, Chernomyrdin's Our
Home Is Russia), to the right, in the direction pro-reform electorate - one
that would never vote communist but that also would not support Yeltsin
[300]
519
Table 7. 1995 parliamentary contest
Eigenvalue
% Variance
Cumulative %
"explained"
Pro-Yeltsin regions
Factor 1
2.70
38.7
38.7
Factor 2
1.42
20.3
59.0
Factor 3
1.18
16.9
75.9
Factor 1
2.76
39.4
39.4
Factor 2
1.52
21.8
61.3
Factor 3
1.00
14.3
75.6
Anti-Yeltsin regions
Moderate regions
Factor 1
2.46
35.2
35.2
Factor 2
1.30
18.6
53.9
Factor 3
1.01
14.3
68.2
unless the choice were between him and a communist - would generate data
in which Zyuganov and Yeltsin appear on the same side of the first factor.
In effect, then, the supposition here is that among pro-reform regions,
with voters sensitive to the nuanced differences between pro-reform candidates and parties, the electorate's mean preference consistently falls between
Yeltsin in 1996 or Our Home Is Russia in 1995 and all other pro-reform
parties and candidates, in which case a significant share of any increase in
Yeltsin's or Chernomyrdin's vote there comes from the reformist camp and
not exclusively from Zyuganov or any of his communist, anti-reform counterparts. In this event (i.e., absent adequate variance in mean preferences) factor
analysis sets Yeltsin and Our Home Is Russia apart from the remaining proreform alternatives and near the anti-reform bloc. On the other hand, because
Yeltsin and Zyuganov's vote still correlate negatively, a second nearly equally
important dimension is required to distinguish these two candidates just as the
second dimension in 1995 distinguishes Our Home Is Russia from the other
party lists. In the second round of the presidential election, however, with the
population mean to the right of Yeltsin and Yeltsin to the right of Zyuganov,
these regions vote most heavily for Yeltsin.
For anti-reform or communist voters, of course, Yeltsin, Chernomyrdin,
and the rest of the administration are little different than any other advocate
[301]
520
of reform, democracy, and a market economy. But insofar as explaining the
relative consistency in Zyuganov's estimated spatial position in contrast to
the inconsistency in Yeltsin's or Chernomyrdin's, we note that Zyuganov
appears to have been much more successful at holding the communist and
anti-reform voting blocks together, so that voters in anti-reform regions saw
no nuanced difference among anti-reform alternatives. Especially in 1996,
Zyuganov stood virtually alone on the right. His only semi-serious competition there was Anpilov, whose vote appears largely to have been limited
to winning some disaffected voters who had abstained in previous elections
(Myagkov, Ordeshook, Sobyanin, 1997). And although in 1995 the Communist Party under Zyuganov confronted nearly as many splinter anti-reform
challengers as did Our Home Is Russia, Zyuganov largely succeeded in consolidating the anti-reform vote, as witnessed by the fact that much of his
party's increased support came from voters who had cast ballots in 1993 for
the fellow-traveling Agrarian Party. Put differently, the speculation here is
that the median preference in 1995 and 1996 in anti-reform regions varied
around Zyuganov and not merely to his right or left, and thus allowed factor
analysis to recover a relatively undistorted estimate of his positn~
Or to put
matters differently still, Zyuganov in 1995 succeeded in positioning himself
at the overall median of voters likely to support him; in contrast, Yeltsin
and Chernomyrdin found themselves closer to the overall population median
(hence Yeltsin's eventual victory), but consistently to the right of preferences
among voters most supportive of reform.
5. Conclusions
Naturally, any conclusions we offer here about spatial positions need to be
tempered by the methodological limitations of our analysis - most notably,
the fact that we rely here on data with relatively low information content.
Nevertheless, the broad sweep of our conclusions is consistent with the intuition that throughout the 1991-1996 period Russia remained divided between
pro- and anti-reform positions and that no candidate succeeded in establishing
a viable middle or centrist position. Our Home Is Russia appears to come
closest to establishing that position in 1995 as its identity, but even then it is
best identified as pro-reform except perhaps among those voters who made
sharp distinctions among such parties. This finding may, of course, be an
artifact of our methodology. But we suspect that it is also a consequence of
a sharply polarized electorate and the fact that no candidate or party has thus
far attempted or succeeded at being the happy face of democratic capitalism
- the "Social Democratic" alternative to communist and reformist camps. It
was assumed during the early stages of the 1996 presidential campaign that
[302]
521
such a platform was available to Zyuganov. But apparently out of fear of
alienating other more radical members of his coalition (or perhaps because
he IS a communist of the old school, pure and simple), Zyuganov ran the
lackluster campaign of a person more familiar with old communist election
procedures and slogans. That center, then, appears to remain unoccupied.
It is unlikely, moreover, that any of the current crop of reform personalities
can change this spatial map. Throughout the 1991-1996 period, reformersmost notably Gaidar and Yavlinski - have anchored one end of the first dimension of competition and it is unlikely that any of their kind can transform
the electorate's view of them so that they are perceived in more moderate
terms. Of course, the difficulty with filling the center is that if the electorate is
bipolar, then under majority rule with a runoff, no person is likely to advance
such a platform and advance to the second round of presidential balloting. But
here we need to enter another note of caution with respect to drawing conclusions about the future. Political leadership does not always involve acting like
a Bill Clinton so as to mold one's policies and campaign pronouncements on
the basis of the latest public opinion polls. Leadership also entails shaping
issues and public opinion to one's own purposes - in this case, reformulating
the issue of reform so as to create a viable center. Unfortunately, Russia today
appears to have few if any leaders capable of performing this task.
Insofar as the feared issue of nationalism is concerned, it is nowhere to
be found until 1996, and even then it (the second factor) does not wholly
set Lebed and Zhirinovski apart from all other candidates or at least from
pro-reform candidate like Yavlinski whose pro-Western orientation manifests
itself with frequent visits to Washington D.C. and Cambridge (Mass.). Interestingly, though, notice that although nationalist rhetoric in 1996 may have
resonated with voters in the anti-Yeltsin and "Moderate" regions (see the
second dimension in Figures 8a and 9a), that issue within pro-Yeltsin regions
appears to take a backseat to the structuring of preferences around reform and
Yeltsin himself.
Of course, none of our conclusions or spatial maps can be approached with
confidence until they are confirmed or otherwise replicated (in subsequent
elections) with richer data - with individual poll results that measure each
respondent's cardinal rankings of the candidates or parties. Only then can we
ascertain the relationship between the "fundamental" dimensions uncovered
by a multidimensional scaling methodology and the more narrowly construed
issues discussed in a campaign (see, e.g., Enelow and Hinich, 1984). Nevertheless, the most general albeit tentative conclusion we reach here is that the
Russian electorate is not altogether infertile ground for the development of
a coherent party system that would primarily pit a left-learning and rightleaning party against each other. Although we cannot reject the hypothesis
[303 ]
522
of a polarized electorate, the relative constancy and coherence of the issue
space over five years of tumultuous socio-economic change seems a firm
basis upon which parties can fashion coherent ideological positions. And
even if secondary issues in the form of valence dimensions (e.g., ORR's
position on the second dimension in 1995) arise from time to time, Lebed's
apparent ability to moderate other secondary Euclidean issues (i.e., nationalism) without negating his pro-reform positioning suggests that parties can
accommodate this multi-dimensionality. It is indeed unfortunate, then, that
Russia's electoral system discourages such a development. National partylist PR in parliamentary contests followed by a majority rule plus runoff
presidential election can only sustain the highly fragmented and personalized
"party system" we see today. This fragmentation may present social scientists
with interesting data, but it is unlikely to facilitate political stability or a viable
federal state (Ordeshook, 1996; Ordeshook and Shvetsova, 1997).
Notes
1. For presidential elections, Russia uses majority rule with a runoff. For its parliamentary
contests to the State Duma, it uses a split system in which one-half of the deputies (225)
are elected from single-mandate constituencies and one half using national party list proportional representation. For the party list contests, only those parties with at least 5%
of the vote are awarded seats. The data we use here from the parliamentary elections are
restricted to the party list totals.
2. Zhirinovski's LDPR won 21.1 %, Yegor Gaidar's Russia's Choice won 14.3%, the Communist Party (CPRF) won 11.5%, the Agrarians won 7.4%, Women of Russia 7.5%,
Yavlinksi's Yabloko 7.3%, Shakrai's list 6.2%, and Travkin's DPR 5.1%.
3. Those four were the CPRF with 22.7%, the LDPR with 11.4%, OHR with 10.3%, Yabloko
with 7.0%.
4. Since turnout increased in 1996 from 1995, "the party of nonvoters" here corresponds to
those who voted in 1996 but not in 1995. That is, the share of the vote attributed to this
"party" in each rayon equals the percentage increase in turnout between 1995 and 1996.
5. And even if we limit the analysis to 5 candidates (CPRF, LDPR, OHR, Yavlinski, and
Nonvoters), the first factor accounts for a mere 37.6% of the variance.
6. If for purposes of comparison we perform a 5-candidate recovery for 1995 (OHR, Nonvoters, Yavlinski, CPRF, and Zhirinovski), the cumulative variance explained by the first
four factors is, in sequence, 37.6%, 59.5%, 78,5% and 94.3%. Thus, even if we limit the
analysis to the same number of candidates, the variance explained increases more rapidly
in 1996 than 1995.
7. Elsewhere we estimate that Yeltsin won 5 out of every 8 of Lebed's voters, and 6 out of
every 8 of Yavlinski's, whereas Zyuganov won 6 out of every 7 of Zhirinovski's voters
(Myagkov, Ordeshook, and Sobyanin, 1997).
8. Out of fear of alienating the more extreme members of his coalition (and perhaps even
as a matter of ideological preference) Zyuganov never embraced a "Social Welfare Democratic" platform and instead left broad hints of massive renationalization of industries,
and other wholesale reversals of Yeltsin's policies. In any event, it was clear that Yeltsin's
[304 ]
523
coterie of pro-Western economic reformers would have no role to play in a Zyuganov
administration, except perhaps as residents of one gulag or another.
9. Pro-Yeltsin regions are those that gave Yeltsin more than 60% of the vote in the second
round of balloting; whereas anti-Yeltsin regions are those that gave him less than 42%.
References
Boxer, Y., McFaul, M. and Ostashev, V. (1996). Elections 1993-1996: Stable and metastable
electorates. Working Paper. Moscow: Carnegie Institute.
Cahoon, L., Hinich, M.J. and Ordeshook, P.e. (1978). A statistical multidimensional scaling
method based on the spatial theory of voting. In P.C. Wang (Ed.), Graphical representation
of multidimensional data. New York: Academic Press.
Dow, J. (1997). A spatial analysis of the 1989 Chilean presidential election. Working Paper,
Department of Political Science, University of Missouri at Columbia.
Enelow, J. and Hinich, M.J. (1984). The spatial theory of voting. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Fish, M.S. (1995). The advent of multipartism in Russia, 1993-1995. Post-Soviet Affairs 11:
340-383.
Hinich, M.J. and Munger, M.e. (\994). Ideology and the theory ofpolitical choice. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Hough, J.F., Davidheiser, E. and Lehmann, S.G. (1996). The 1996 Russian presidential
election. Washington DC: The Brookings Institution.
Lin, T.M., Chu, Y.-h. and Hinich, M.J. (1996). Conflict displacement and regime transition in
Taiwan: A spatial analysis. World Politics 48: 453-481.
McFaul, M. (1996). Russia between elections: What the 1995 results really mean. Moscow:
Carnegie Endowment for International Peace.
McFaul, M. and Fish, M.S. (1996). Russia between elections. Journal of Democracy 19: 90118.
Myagkov, M., Ordeshook, P.e. and Sobyanin, A. (1997). The Russian electorate, 1991-1996.
Post Soviet Affairs 13: 30-62.
Myagkov, M. and Sobyanin, A. (1995). Irregularities in the 1993 Russian election. Working
Paper. Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute of Technology.
Ordeshook, P.e. (1996). Russia's party system: Is Russian federalism viable? Post-Soviet
Affairs 12: 195-217.
Ordeshook, P.e. (1997). The spatial analysis of elections and committees: Four decades of
research. In D.e. Mueller (Ed.). Perspectives on public choice. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Ordeshook, P.C. and Shvetsova, O. (1995). If Madison and Hamilton were merely lucky, what
hope is there for Russian federalism? Constitutional Political Economy 6: 107-126.
Wyman, M., White, S., Miller, B. and Heywood, P. (1995). Public opinion, parties and voters
in the December 1993 Russian elections. Europe-Asia Studies 47: 591-614.
[305 ]