Chronotopologies of the Exception: Agamben and Derrida before
the Camps
Lorenzo Fabbri
diacritics, Volume 39, Number 3, Fall 2009, pp. 77-95 (Article)
Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press
DOI: 10.1353/dia.2009.0027
For additional information about this article
http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/dia/summary/v039/39.3.fabbri.html
Access provided by Cornell University (5 Jul 2013 20:56 GMT)
CHRONOTOPOLOGIES OF THE
EXCEPTION
AGAMBEN AND DERRIDA BEFORE THE
CAMPS
LORENZO FABBRI
Flash back. Germany, 1933.
“Der Reichstag brennt! Der Reichstag brennt! Hast du mich gehört? Der Reichstag
brennt.” On a quiet, brisk February night in 1933 a Berlin ire station received a panicked
phone call. A ire had lared up in the building that hosted the German parliament. The
Reichstag was burning. Squads were needed to put the ire out. Just six days before the
date set for the parliamentary election, the Reichstag ire represented an invaluable opportunity for Germany’s newly appointed chancellor [Mommsen 129–222; Tobias 10–
16]. Following up on what he deemed a “sign from heaven,” Chancellor Hitler denounced
the event as the inaugurating act in the Communists’ plot to seize power. Something
exceptional needed to be done in order to protect Germany against the menace of Bolshevik terrorism. On February 28, the day after the arson, Reich President Paul von Hindenburg approved what is commonly known as the Reichstag Fire Decree. This decree
suspended fundamental individual rights and handed full power to the chancellor. Having
seized emergency powers and with the pretext of the red threat, Hitler closed down unfriendly newspapers, incarcerated thousands of political opponents, and persecuted the
Communist Party. The substantial suppression of all oppositional forces allowed Hitler
to assemble at the March 5 election the majority he needed to pass the Enabling Act: the
executive acquired legislative powers and had now the prerogative to rule by decree with
neither the approval of the Reichstag nor of the president. Instituting de facto an endless
state of exception, Hitler had transformed Germany into a camp.
Following Giorgio Agamben’s work, one can in fact visualize the lager as a distortion
of the normal political time-space, arising from the suspension of the customary checks
protecting the people within a constitutional regime. The camp is the space produced by
the enforcement of an exception to the law, and those who end up in it are robbed of any
legal protection insofar as they are sanctioned as threats to the stability of the political
itself [Means without End 37]. This branding of certain social assemblages as guilty regardless of any proven criminal behavior uncovers the sacriicial logic at the heart of the
camp: the lives of others are sacriiced to protect the lives of a self-authenticated collectivity. In this way the polity gets fractured in two. There is a “they, the people,” stripped
of fundamental rights and abandoned to face bare the sovereign’s absolute power. And
there is a “We, the People,” who can enjoy its rights only because the rights of the others have been revoked.1 Such a fundamental split in the body politic is however what,
I would like to thank Scott Stuart, who provided invaluable linguistic assistance in the preparation
of this essay.
1
Legal theorist Geoffrey Stone reaches similar conclusions in Perilous Times: “as almost always
happens, the individuals whose rights are sacriiced are not those who make the laws, but minorities, dissidents, and noncitizens. In those circumstances, ‘we’ are making a decision to sacriice
‘their’ rights—not a very prudent way to balance the competing interests” [531]. Vik Kanwar’s
diacritics Volume 39.3 (2009) 77–95 © 2012 by the Johns Hopkins University Press
according to Agamben, intrinsically dooms a political space to its destruction. Once the
line between authentic and inauthentic life is drawn, once the humanity which, as bios,
lives fully, has been isolated from the humanity that merely exists as zoē, the frontier
keeps moving forward, creating an ever more inclusive group of excluded that can be
sacriiced. Eventually, the autoimmunitary thrust of the state of exception becomes clear:
the life of some, and in the end the life of the One, is guaranteed only by the death of
everyone else [Esposito 116].
It is important to recall, once again, that Hitler’s rise to power and the consequent
reduction of Germany into one gateless lager was accomplished by following the dictates
of the Weimar Constitution. The camps are not an accident that Hitler brought to his nation, but a paradoxical juridical space that inds its condition of possibility in Article 48
of the constitution. Article 48 in fact accorded plenary powers to the president in cases
where security and public order were seriously disturbed in the Reich.2 Beginning in
1930, President Hindenburg exploited the textual indeterminacy of this article to strategically strip the parliament of any functions and have the cabinet respond only to him. From
that moment on, Germany ceased to be a parliamentary regime. The Reichstag, in other
words, was destroyed well before the arson of 1933. Its eventual destruction and the rise
of the camps were actually already inscribed, via Article 48, in the Weimar Republic’s
founding text. And the only thing Hitler accomplished with the authority to suspend the
rule of law transferred from the president to the chancellery was to transform a presidential dictatorship into an executive dictatorship.
Flash forward. United States, ten years after 9/11.
Libraries are illed with books on the political and legal consequences of the terrorist
attacks on the World Trade Center and the Pentagon, and the vast majority of the interventions archived on those library shelves refer to the constitutional downfall of the Weimar
Republic as their obligatory precedent. Even if there were camps well before Hitler, what
happened in Nazi Germany stands as an exemplary case for two sets of reasons: the
memory of the Enabling Act imposes a relection on the risks connected with the delegation of discretionary sovereignty to the executive, and it allows for the understanding of
the juridical grounds that let camps emerge in modern democracies (as was the Weimar
Republic). At stake in the formalization of the relationship between the normal political
space and the state of exception, between rule of law and rule by law—between polis and
lager, that is—is the re-evaluation of the arguments concerning the proximity of democracy and dictatorship. Obviously it is not a matter of negating the differences between a
democracy governed by the rule of law and a dictatorship in which the law is a means to
govern, but of discussing the existence of a threshold that would keep these two regimes
clearly separated. In what follows, I will discuss three different topographies of the relationship between a state of exception and the rule of law.
Ackerman
Vermeule
Derrida
review of State of Exception discusses Agamben’s interventions against the backdrop of U.S. constitutional theory, drawing especially from the works of Stone and David Cole.
2
On the legal dispute regarding the constitutionality of Article 48—and the role that Carl Schmitt
played in such a battle—see David Dyzenhaus, “Legal Theory in the Collapse of Weimar.”
78
diacritics / fall 2009
I begin with Bruce Ackerman who in “The Emergency Constitution” tried to demarcate
an unmistakable threshold between the normal functioning of a constitutional democracy and its exceptional suspension. After having separated these two realms, Ackerman
concerns himself with determining the actor who should have the authority to switch
from normality to exceptionality (and vice versa). From this perspective he argues for
the necessity of a statutory reform that would unmistakably preserve the legislature authority over the exception threshold, and therefore prevent the executive from turning
a transitional emergency regime into a permanent police state. However imperative or
praiseworthy such an attempt may be, I argue that Ackerman’s legalist framework fails
to notice that the exception is not something that—sometimes and somewhere, in a local
and transitory context—needs to be enforced in order to deal with national emergencies.
Following Adrian Vermeule, my irst critical intervention consists in showing that any
defense of classic legalism overlooks the inevitable existence, within a system of rights,
of legal black and grey holes that always allow for negotiations with the rule of law.
Against Vermeule, I claim that these loopholes are not created by the judicial discretion
inscribed in administrative law, but provoked by the naked formality of laws, i.e., by the
very form of law. Inspired by Jacques Derrida’s description of the textual structure of our
relation to law and Agamben’s identifying the state of exception as the paradigm of government, I argue that spectacular exceptions granted to the executive when emergencies
transpire should not distract us from the micro-exceptions that are produced every time
the meaning of a certain law is decided upon. In other words, the executive’s reactions
to national crises should not prevent us from acknowledging that, for certain segments
of the population, freedom is normally, and strategically, negated. After highlighting the
structural afinities between Derrida and Agamben’s topologies of the exception, I will
show why, according to Agamben, deconstruction’s eternal and tactical negotiation with a
law recognized to always be in force without any ixed meaning is insuficient. In order to
improve our position in the struggle against an emergency that has always been the rule,
the task before us is the creation of truly extra-juridical spaces that might function as real
exceptions to sovereign power.
Agamben
Beyond the legal and political deadlock that so many authoritative voices produce, beyond the defense of liberal constitutionalism as well as beyond the normalization of
emergency regimes, beyond Schmitt, beyond Derrida, new common political spaces are
there to be explored. Beyond the exception, politics awaits.
1
Constitutional Fetishism
Shocked by the Bush administration’s reaction to 9/11, Ackerman’s ultimate goal is to
elaborate a set of constitutional devices that would immunize the United States from
Chronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
79
the risk of following the Weimar Republic’s catastrophic example. His “The Emergency
Constitution” is set in motion by the fear that episodic terrorist attacks will punctuate the
future of American history, and that each and every strike will lead the ruling executive
to adopt ever more repressive measures. In a climate of mounting paranoia against real
or presumed terrorists, “even if the next half-century sees only four or ive attacks on the
scale of September 11, this destructive cycle will prove devastating to civil liberties by
2050” [1030]. Discarding the respectable but naïve idea that all civil liberties should be
upheld no matter what emergency a country is facing, Ackerman cautiously concludes
that some constitutional rights can be suspended for some time, yet the executive cannot
be allowed to run wild. Even during the most perilous times, there must be unmistakable statutory norms framing the executive’s access to plenary powers. What ultimately
scares Ackerman is the kind of autoimmunitarian degeneration that Derrida in Rogues
has localized at the heart of modern constitutionalism [36–40]. For Derrida, the threats to
democracy do not only come from outside because, in the attempt to defend the security
of its body politic, a constitutional democracy has the power to suspend the very liberties around which it was established, thus harming itself “to an extent greater than any
‘terrorist’ could hope to achieve” [Haddad, “Derrida and Democracy” 29]. In the case
of the U.S. Constitution: Article 1, Section 9 authorizes the suspension of habeas corpus
when, in cases of rebellion or invasion, the public safety may require it. And although
the proclamation of such an emergency measure was the province of the Congress, the
president “has accreted more power than the original understanding might be understood
to permit” [Posner and Vermeule, “Accommodating Emergencies” 1n4]. It is exactly such
presidential “invasiveness” that Ackerman is afraid of. But is not the Supreme Court’s
role to protect the people against it?
In order to make the case for the necessity of statutory reform, Ackerman argues that
the judicial management of the exception is not a suficient deterrent to the executive’s
possible abuse of power, because the judiciary has been far too deferent to the president
during critical moments. Since the U.S. Constitution does not specify the cases in which
a suspension of habeas corpus is indeed constitutional, it is usually up to “judicial imagination” to determine whether the recourses to emergency measures such as indeinite
custody in detention camps is in line with the spirit—if not the letter—of the Constitution
itself. So while in “normal times” legal sages ramp up the requirements to condone a
suspension of the writ, they can easily switch to a more relaxed interpretation of constitutional dictates should the situation require it. The case Korematsu v. United States is
the ultimate proof that an excessive conidence in justices’ wisdom is hardly defendable.
In times of perceived emergencies, even justices as libertarian as Hugo Black will dangerously tend to defend the executive’s decisions. Furthermore, under the common law
system, one risks ending up with legal precedents that normalize, so to speak, the emergency. Ackerman points to the fact that Korematsu has never been formally overruled.
Therefore: “What will the Supreme Court say if Arab Americans are herded into concentrations camps? Are we certain any longer that the wartime precedent of Korematsu will
not be extended to the ‘war on terrorism’?” [1043]. As Justice Robert Jackson’s dissenting view in Korematsu claimed, once a judicial opinion justiies an emergency resolution
by inding it in conformity with the Constitution, one creates “a loaded weapon, ready
for the hand of any authority that can bring forward a plausible claim of an urgent need”
[Korematsu v. United States 246]. Pair then the presidential “invasiveness” with the traditional deference accorded to the executive by the judiciary during emergencies, and the
constitutional yet antidemocratic catastrophe to which the United States is exposed becomes clearer. The specter of an executive regime will be looming on the horizon as long
as the suspension of the habeas corpus remains a presidential prerogative restrained only
by judicial scrutiny. For these reasons, Ackerman deems it urgent to take pressure and
responsibility away from the common law cycle and the judiciary by having the Congress
80
diacritics / fall 2009
enforce a less extemporaneous approach to emergency situations. Rather than relying on
judges to accommodate emergency measures by stretching existing laws or creating dangerous precedents, it should be up to the legislature to create a precise framing of emergencies and specify how critical moments will be handled. In this way, it will be clear
that emergency decisions such as the suspension of the writ are not consistent with the ordinary Constitution, but instead permissible only within extraordinary instances that the
Congress itself is responsible for declaring. An unmistakable threshold would separate
normal times from emergency moments and therefore avoid any structural contamination
between the rule of law and the state of exception. Beside serving as a means to reassure
the population that the nation is prepared to face crises, new constitutional structures will
avoid the possibility of a lethal alliance between the executive and a permissive, or even
remissive, judiciary.3
The constitutional device on which Ackerman speciically relies to hold emergency
regimes in check is the “supermajoritarian escalator.” The executive will be allowed to
assume full power for no longer than two weeks if the Congress is already in session,
otherwise only for enough time for it to convene and consider the case. Without congressional approval, the state of emergency would automatically expire. With congressional
approval, the state of emergency will be assigned a two or three month life span. In order
to carry on, the state of emergency would need to pass through the Congress again—but
this time the required majority would be sixty percent. An escalating cascade of supermajorities would be required for each renewal. Giving veto power to the representatives of
ever-smaller minoritarian groups, the supermajoritarian escalator will be able to protect
a democracy from the risk of an executive regime backed up by the judiciary. The fractures within the social body are for Ackerman the ultimate antidote against a fallacious
separation of powers: modern pluralist societies are simply too fragmented to sustain an
indeinite violation of civil rights.
Laurence Tribe and Patrick Gudridge have pointed out that in “The Emergency Constitution” those civil rights that can be temporally revoked remain as vague as the nature
of the terrorist attacks that would justify their suspension [1803]. However, unlike Tribe
and Gudridge, I do not believe such a vagueness to be an unintentional blind spot in
Ackerman’s constitutional reframing. It is, on the contrary, the very heart of his proposal.
One must not forget that in Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology—the obvious reference for
any discussion regarding sovereignty in exceptional times—the sovereign does not only
have the power to decide in the emergency; he is also and foremost the authority who
decides on the emergency, being the only actor with the prerogative to determine what is
and what is not an emergency. Against the unitarian thrust of Schmitt’s political theology,
Ackerman’s supermajoritarian escalator tears sovereignty apart by depriving the executive, even in exceptional times, of the authority to decide whether or not the country is
really facing an emergency. Instead of setting actual restraints on what the executive can
do during emergencies, Ackerman makes “the threshold question of the existence of a
state of emergency—a matter for legislative deliberation, not executive iat” [Tribe and
Gudridge 1811]. Disassembling, if you will, the body of the Schmittian sovereign, Ackerman accords the executive the privilege to decide what needs to be done within the state
of exception. But it is the legislative branch that ultimately decides if the suspension of
the rule of law is justiied. While the executive is sovereign during the emergency, the
Congress is the sovereign on the emergency, being awarded the authority to cross or not
to cross the line that separates normal times from critical moments, the threshold that
leads from the polis to the camps.
3
On this issue, see Tushnet, “Defending Korematsu?”; and Gross, “Chaos and Rules.”
Chronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
81
Everything seems resolved. The supermajoritarian rule of the legislature over the
emergency border will prevent any political exploitation of emergencies, because minority congressional groups will not authorize unnecessary measures. Of course, one can
always claim that, especially under such conditions, the executive will be tempted to
produce ever more Reichstag ires in order to better defend its claims to power. As both
Agamben and Derrida have pointed out, a well-aimed politics of terrorism can easily be
employed as a catalyst for governmental re-legitimation [Agamben, Means without End
6; Derrida, Rogues 40]. However, one does not have to embark on a conspiracy theory hypothesis to show the ineffectuality of Ackerman’s solution. His constitutional reframing
does not work because the happy ending between the executive and the legislature will
always be upset by the specter of the judiciary. What if the executive continued to grant
itself emergency powers independent of the required congressional approval? In the case
of a conlict between the executive and the legislature, the judiciary, to which Ackerman
initially denied any say in the emergency, is now required to step up to the plate. Notwithstanding his dismissal of the judge-centered approaches to the emergency, Ackerman in
fact still attributes to the judiciary a crucial role during exceptional times. Not only are
courts the ultimate arbiters in eventual (and probable) dramatic contrasts between the executive and the Congress, engaging in what Ackerman calls “macromanagement.” Judges
are also required to “microadjudicate” in cases raised by individuals who claim their
fundamental rights have been violated. “The Emergency Constitution” was set in motion
by the distrust of juridical management of emergencies. The need that motivated Ackerman’s project from the outset was the development of a statutory framework that would
take the responsibility of dealing with emergencies away from the judiciary. And yet it is
not clear why and how his supermajoritarian escalator could resolve the issue. In case of
long-lasting emergencies, Ackerman can do no better than re-awarding the untrustworthy
courts the authority of overseeing the camps, and negotiating between the demands of the
executive and those of individual suspects, between national security and private liberty.4
In this way, Ackerman’s statutory framework allows for judicial interventionism and for
the subjective legal decisionism that, in the name of the rule of law, his emergency Constitution strived at all costs to avoid. Judicial arbitrariness, in other words, deconstructs
the elaborate framework statute put forth by Ackerman and punctures the barrier he tried
to erect between the normal political space and the state of exception. No singular threshold can be localized between the polis and the camp. The points of access to the exception of the law are in fact multiple and do not fall under the legislature’s control. Such a
realization creates a superimposition of the two spheres that Ackerman wanted to keep
clearly distinguished and paves the way for a different, terribly more convincing and terribly less reassuring topology of the relation between democracy and dictatorship.
2
No Power to the People: Or, We Are All (Potentially) Homines Sacri
The most signiicant result Vermeule achieves in “Our Schmittian Administrative Law”
is the demonstration that any attempt to exclude justices from emergency management
is destined to fail. Although Vermeule does not extensively address “The Emergency
Constitution,” mentioning it only in a brief footnote, I will approach his essay as a skillful demolition of Ackerman’s endeavor to keep the rule of law and the state of exception
separated by repositioning the latter within congressional reach.
4
For a discussion of Ackerman’s other inconsistencies, see Vermeule, “Self-Defeating Proposals”
[648–49].
82
diacritics / fall 2009
Vermeule inds the cue for his redescription of U.S. administrative law in Schmitt’s
Political Theology. While in 1921 with Dictatorship Schmitt examined the differences
between commissarial and sovereign dictatorships, his 1922 Political Theology sought
to distinguish the category of decision from that of norm. As Schmitt notes, norm and
decision are two autonomous yet irreconcilable categories that coexist within the juridical order, categories whose hierarchy is modiied by situations: “Unlike the normal situation, when the autonomous moment of the decision recedes to a minimum, the norm is
destroyed in the exception” [Political Theology 12]. The suspension of the norm in fact
gives space to an action which does not have anything to do with the realm of legality
because it is not a matter of applying a preexisting rule or standard. When the present is
endangered, when the coniguration of our lives is under threat, what is required is a totally autonomous and instantaneous decision on the best way to secure the persistence of
the polis. In the sovereign decision it is not merely a matter of defending this or that rule,
this or that standard. The sovereign exceptional decision is what transcends, what stands
outside the political space as its very condition of existence. The exception can be then
imagined as the transcendental of the polis.
Drawing from Schmitt, Vermeule demonstrates that it is not possible to eliminate the
dialectic between norm and decision by imposing a law to the exception. The texture of
administrative law does not only allow but actually requires what David Dyzenhaus has
recognized as grey and black holes, substantially lawless zones which exempt the executive and government agencies from legal constraints. Black holes are spaces that administrative law secures from the possibility of judicial review altogether. Under the category
of grey hole fall all the cases in which reverential lower courts dial down the intensity of
review to the point that the scrutiny of government agencies is only a formalism. Since
administrative law is organized around vague parameters such as the arbitrary and capricious standard, the substantial evidence test, and the good cause exception, federal courts
of appeal “during perceived emergencies [can and do] adjust to increase deference to
administrative agencies” [Vermeule, “Our Schmittian Administrative Law” 1097].
Vermeule notes that for classic liberal legalism, grey holes are far more problematic
than black ones because they consist in a substantial violation of the law that is formally
justiied on the basis of a certain reading of laws themselves. A body that is caught in
one is awarded some procedural rights by a deferent judiciary, but not enough to effectively confront the executive’s decision [Dyzenhaus, “Schmitt v. Dicey” 2026]. To put it
in Derridian terminology: the judiciary’s deference toward the executive takes the form
of a two-fold differential gesture. In order to prevent certain detainees from opposing
the measures to which they are subjected, courts defer the moment in which they will
be treated as normal persons, both by granting them a laughable amount of constitutional rights and by “ducking legal challenges with the help of the copious procedural
mechanisms at their disposal—standing doctrine, denial of certiorari, delay, and so forth”
[Posner and Vermeule, “Accommodating Emergencies” 2]. In black holes the executive’s
actions appear for what they are—exceptional decisions that take place outside of the
customs determined by the rule of law. Grey holes, on the other hand, allow courts to pass
administrative agencies’ extraordinary decisions as norms—compromising de jure and de
facto the distinction between norms and decisions, normality and exception, rule of law
and rule by law. While Ackerman tried to disseminate sovereignty across the different
branches in order to limit any dictatorial drift, Vermeule suggests that sovereign extra- or
pseudo-legal decisions are exactly what emergencies require. The attempt to limit the
executive is both impracticable—given the structure of our times—and infeasible—given
the structure of administrative law: grey and black holes are inevitable since it is impossible to subject government agencies to solid legal standards. The very idea of “standard”
implies in fact that it can rule only in ordinary cases, and that changing circumstances
require a different application of the standard itself, an application that actually allows for
Chronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
83
executive decisions to “proceed untrammeled by even the threat of legal regulation and
judicial review” [Vermeule, “Our Schmittian Administrative Law” 1133]. Then, in case
of emergencies there is “no real choice but to hand the reins to the executive and hope for
the best” [Posner and Vermeule, “Crisis Governance” 1614].
But is it true that our only alternative is between hope in the executive and despair,
between deference and destruction? The history of emergency powers in the twentieth
century has taught us that hope and despair, deference and destruction are not dialectical terms, but instead often work in solidarity with each other. Hope in the redemptive
power of executive actions leads to a more incurable despair, and deference to them leads
to an unthinkable level of destruction. With great responsibility comes great power: a
thanatopolitical détournement of President Roosevelt’s famous line from his undelivered
1945 Jefferson Day Address would sound more or less like this. And it would oblige
us to realize that by positioning ourselves in need of salvation, we expose our precarious lives to the eventuality of sacriice. To put it differently: should not the history of
emergency powers, along with Vermeule’s inscription of exception within the texture of
administrative law, generate a less hopeful, more worrisome attitude before a sovereign
power? How is it possible to restrain a government agency from treating not only “them”
as terrorists but “us” as well? What can prevent us from plunging into one of the infernal
circles where homines sacri live? In the pages that follow, I will explore Derrida and
Agamben’s readings of Kafka’s “Before the Law” in order to highlight the conceptual
similarities in their understanding of the relation between the exception and the law, and
the strategic differences in their confrontation with a camp discovered to be the foundation of the rule of law.
3
Kafka’s Lesson, Schmitt’s Specters: Deconstruction as Thanatopolitics
The parable is well known.
A man from the country travels a long and troublesome way to arrive before the law.
Believing the law to be accessible to all and at all times, he asks its doorkeeper for admittance. But he cannot get in. He inds himself standing not in front of the law, but before
an ugly thug of a doorkeeper—with a fur coat, a big, sharp nose, and a long, thin Tartar
beard—who denies him admittance. Days and years pass, and the countryman is turned
down numerous times. Even bribery is unsuccessful. The doorkeeper stands in his way.
Eventually, the man from the country loses his patience, and along with it, his eyesight.
He has little time left to live—or so it seems—and he wants to ask the doorkeeper a inal
question: “Everyone strives to reach the law, so how is it that for all these many years no
one but myself has ever begged for admittance?” The doorkeeper whispers in his ear: “No
one else could ever be admitted here, since this gate was made for you alone. I am now
going to shut it” [Kafka, Complete Stories 4].
The parable is well known. Published during Kafka’s life in 1916 as an independent
short story, it also appears posthumously in The Trial as a tale told in a cathedral by the
prison chaplain to K. The aim of the story in this case is to teach K.—who is facing trial
for an unspeciied crime—a lesson about the law and to dispel his delusions regarding
the workings of the court. K., however, is not sure he has understood the moral of the
parable, and he spends quite some time going over possible interpretations. At the end,
K. is literally left in the dark, unable to ind his way out as the prison chaplain leaves him
with this assertion: “The court does not want anything from you. It receives you when
you come and dismisses you when you go” [160]. So: what exactly is the lesson K. should
have learned? And what exactly is the parable about? Is it about an event that happens not
84
diacritics / fall 2009
to happen (as Derrida asserts), or about an event that happened to happen by seeming not
to happen at all (as Agamben maintains)? By exploring the antithetical readings Derrida
and Agamben give of Kafka’s parabolic riddle, I will highlight their different positions
before the law and the legal. This will also allow me to debunk the political meaning of
Agamben’s curse against Derrida in Homo Sacer: “Woe to you, who have not wanted to
enter into the door of the Law but have not permitted it to be closed either” [54].
Based on a lecture on Kafka delivered in London in 1982, Derrida’s reading of “Before the Law” was later reworked in a longer engagement with Jean-François Lyotard’s
theory of judgment. For this reason, it was published as an independent essay (“Before
the Law”) and as a section of “Préjugés: Devant la loi.” In both cases Derrida’s objective
is to highlight the textual structure of the relation Kafka sets up between the countryman and the law, and consequently also between K. and the court. The mistake both the
countryman and K. committed, the mistake that brought them to waste their lives away,
consists in failing to realize that appearing before the law equates to standing before a
text. The law of the law is textuality, therefore all attempts to approach the thing itself
and to make it present, all the attempts “to enter into a relation with it, indeed, to enter it
and become intrinsic to it,” are destined to fail [“Before the Law” 191]. For this reason,
the journey of the man from the country toward the law can never end. It is destined to go
on forever since the law exposes itself to our sight only in the form of a withdrawal. It is
there—sometimes we can glimpse its light through the gates and protective boundaries—
but it is always beyond our reach. As with the Sirens from another of Kafka’s stories, it
is silent. And through its silence the law impels us to decipher its enigmatic silhouette by
giving an account of it. The man from the country does not understand all of this. Rather
than deciding the meaning of the law himself by negotiating with the doorkeeper and then
going back to his village to do something with this acquired knowledge, he decides not
to decide. He decides to wait, as if one day the doorkeeper would grant him admission
to the law. He does not understand that, even if he had been able to sneak in, he would
have run away horriied, having discovered the inside of the law to be a void. Only an
interpretative reading decision could provide the legal doctrine with some consistency;
it is a reading decision that would have then given the countryman access (in the form of
a non-access) to the law. But reading itself, according to Derrida, is always marked by a
certain degree of violence.
Being that the law as text is absolutely transcendent and inaccessible, its actualization depends on the performative gesture that invents the meaning of the law every time it
is applied. This implies the impossibility of strictly distinguishing between founding and
enforcing a law, between constituent and constituted power. Therefore, all that Derrida
afirms regarding founding violence in the passage I am about to quote from “Force of
Law,” can also be applied to the decision to read the law: “the operation that amounts to
founding, inaugurating, justifying law, to making law, would consist of a coup de force, of
a performative and therefore interpretative violence that in itself is neither just nor unjust
and that no justice and no earlier and previously founding law, no preexisting foundation,
could, by deinition, guarantee or contradict or invalidate” [241]. The founding violence
inaugurates the law, and in doing so, legitimizes its arbitrary gesture through a deferred
effect. At the same time the founded law is a text: it is then destined to be refounded every
time it is reread and reapplied. Consequently, it is impossible to exclude force from the
law: enforceability is not an external eventuality which may or may not get attached to
laws. Enforceability is structurally implicit in every law, insofar as the existence of our
laws and their meanings is assured by the performative violence of an application. The
legible illegibility of the law imposes, as a necessity, “a juridicosymbolic violence, a
performative violence at the very heart of interpretative reading” [“Force of Law” 271].
The law must be read, and reading is always a matter of decision-making in the absence
of criteria that would guarantee the soundness of the decision. It is then dificult to mainChronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
85
tain Derrida’s distinction between instances in which sentences are delivered thanks to
calculated reference to existing rules and those in which judgment passes through the experience of the undecidable—the experience of the suspension of all guidelines. It is not
possible to hold on to this distinction, which leads Derrida to distinguish between justice
and justesse, for one can never simply apply a just rule without also inventing the rule
and example in each case. Applying the law always coincides, willingly or unwillingly,
with inventing it [“Force of Law” 245]. Therefore, one should not think of judicial arbitrariness as a contingent fact which could be eliminated by a clearer law-writing practice.
Judicial interventionism is not caused by the presence of vague parameters and loopholes
within the body of the law. Judicial arbitrariness and interventionism are implied by the
textual structure of the law itself. Moreover, law’s textuality deconstructs the possibility
of simply complying with the law and destines every application of a norm to always being more than a mere application. It destines it to be a responsible decision. Il faut juger.
One must judge and decide. Indeed, one always does precisely that because, as Derrida
puts it, the law is the pure transcendent [“Préjugés” 94–95].
In the chapters “Form of Law” and “Force-of-Law” (from Homo Sacer and State
of Exception respectively), Agamben suggests that conclusions similar to those Derrida
arrives at, via Kafka, in “Force of Law” were also reached by Carl Schmitt in his efforts
to construct a rigorous theory of the state of exception. Agamben’s arguments are quite
oblique and require some patient unpacking. I will start with State of Exception and then
move back to the irst installment of the Homo Sacer series.
Agamben begins the last section of “Force-of-Law” by noting that “application” is
a very problematic category. Its correct understanding was, for a long time, sidetracked
by Kant’s theory of judgment, where application is treated as a case of determinant judgment: the general is given and one only needs to logically translate this generality into
the particular case. By looking at the relation between the generality of langue and the
particularity of speciic parole acts in the realm of language, Agamben highlights the
conceptual fallacy of conceiving the application of a general norm to a particular case as
a mere logical operation. As in language, the virtuality of langue is actualized and comes
to existence only in the speciic utterances of a speaker or a community of speakers that
assumes that linguistic abstraction in its own parole, the law only acquires its meaning
thanks to the procedural machine of a trial. Here Agamben moves along the lines of
Feuerbach’s full-ledged critique of abstractions: langue and law are nothing more than
abstract fetishes produced by the attempt to isolate from the concrete customs and usages of individuals a common transcendental ground which would make such practices
intelligible as reoccurrences of a same general structure. Just as langue is presupposed in
order to explain actual discourse, the law is presupposed to justify applications—while,
in reality, parole and applications should be considered the conditions of possibility of
langue and law. This casual inversion of condition and conditioned provokes in the realm
of the linguistic the loating signiier (one of Derrida’s crucial concepts) and, in the legal
domain, the state of exception. In both instances, we are dealing with void forms—respectively of language and law—which, after having lost their historical grounding in
the realm of human praxis where they originated, return to haunt exactly such a realm.5
In other words: they return as texts which, as écriture, have force without having any
speciic signiicance.
5
All this resonates with Walter Benjamin’s critique of the Weimar Republic for forgetting its origin
in the 1919 revolution: see “Critique of Violence” 244. Moreover, I am not completely sure the
discussion of the similarities between language and law proposed by Agamben in the irst pages
of “Form of Law” in Homo Sacer is coherent with the one in State of Exception. My working
hypothesis, which I cannot elaborate in this context, is that Agamben in “Form of Law” is not
86
diacritics / fall 2009
As far as the state of exception is concerned, its spectral haunting constitutes the
most radical attempt to invert and naturalize the relation between life and law. It works by
producing an anomic zone in which legal customs are suspended in order to allow for an
effective governmentalization of human lives. Producing exceptions is a way to produce
normality by reafirming the grip on life not of this or that speciic norm, but of a political
ordering in general. This happens not only in the extraordinary space of the camp, but
also in the ordinary setting of the court. The crucial point here is that the tension between
norms and decisions that Schmitt had detected at the foundation of any juridical order
does not actually exist: just as the sovereign decides in the suspension of the rule of law,
judges also decide in the state of exception. Arguing against Kant, Agamben concludes
that the application of a law cannot be considered as a case of determinant judgment. It
cannot be considered a matter of logical subsumption because, in the passage from the
general to the concrete, there is a gap which no strictly logical operation can ill. The act
of bringing the law into actuality through enforcement consists in the decision which
assigns—each and every time it is applied—an actual and speciic meaning to the law
in question: “it is . . . perfectly obvious (and Schmitt had no dificulty theorizing this
obviousness) that, in the case of the law, the application of a norm is in no way contained
within the norm and cannot be derived from it” [State of Exception 40]. This also means
that the only way to enforce a norm is to suspend the law itself, for the law cannot determine how it will be applied. Norms need to be enforced in order to constitute the realm
of normality—the space where the ictional grip of the juridical order over life is naturalized. But this enforcement is an active performance since, as Wittgenstein also demonstrated when discussing the paradoxes of rule-following, a norm does not mandate, allow,
or forbid one singular and determinate course of action.6 There are multiple, divergent
ways to comply with the same norm. Therefore, in order to apply a norm, “it is ultimately
necessary to suspend its application, to produce an exception” [State of Exception 40].
In other words: to be enforced, the law must destroy itself in an autoimmunitary fashion.
To further highlight the resonance between Derrida’s deconstruction of the law and
Schmitt’s theorization of the state of exception, one could reformulate Agamben’s indings in this manner: there is no enforcement of a law that is not also an exceptional decision. There are no norms. There are only normative effects originating from always sovereign decisions. It is not a coincidence—but Derrida overlooks this—that the syntagma
“force of law” from a technical point of view refers not to the law, but to the executive’s
power to issue decrees that count as law even if technically they are not. However, since
there is no application which is not also an exception, one must conclude that all applications of a law are actually sovereign decrees whose force of law is a force of law: applications are extralegal, exceptional decisions rendered lawful by their power to impose
themselves as enforcements with force of law. But if this is the case, then the exception
cannot be considered merely “as the dominant paradigm of government in contemporary
politics” [State of Exception 2]. It is not simply that the ruling by emergency decrees
that has characterized the twentieth century collapsed the once-sound distinction between
legislative and executive powers. As Adam Thurschwell has summarized: there is surely
a history of exception regimes, but “the sovereign exception is also . . . the purely logical
structure of the rule of law in general” [“Specters of Nietzsche” 54]. It is for this reason
that the camps must be assumed as the paradigmatic spaces of modernity: the lager is the
presenting his own ideas on language and law, but merely repeating Derrida’s in order to expose
the ban structure implied by deconstruction and eventually move beyond it. For a precise account
of Agamben’s confrontation with Derrida’s philosophy of language, see Kevin Attell, “An Esoteric
Dossier: Agamben and Derrida Read Saussure.”
6
For the discussion of the connection between the state of exception and rule-following, see Paolo
Virno, Multitude Between Innovation and Negation 74–75.
Chronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
87
truth of the political as we know it. The logical conclusion we are then forced to confront
is the following: polis and camp coincide; we live in a permanent state of exception. Law
is in fact always in force without having any ixed meaning since its enforcement is a matter of sovereign decision, not of mechanical deduction. The situation is bleakly depressing, Kafkaesque indeed: “life under a law that is in force without signifying resembles life
in the state of exception, in which the most innocent gesture or the smallest forgetfulness
can have most extreme consequences” [Agamben, Homo Sacer 52]. Ackerman had tried
to erect an unmistakable barrier between the normal functioning of a political space and
the state of exception. Vermeule demonstrated that such a threshold is not as solid as
Ackerman wished it to be, for administrative law is replete with grey areas allowing for
the evasion of the rule of law even without the legislature’s attribution of plenary powers
to the executive. Derrida and Agamben expose the complete superimposition of the rule
of law and the state of exception: any application of a norm is a sovereign decision, since
judicial interventionism is not provoked by the vagueness of certain standards but by the
textual structure of any law whatsoever.
Going back to Benjamin’s “Critique of Violence,” Agamben in Homo Sacer dubs das
bloße Leben [bare life] the form of life that lives under a law which has form and force but
not a speciic content: a bare life living under the constant threat of die bloße Form des
Gesetzes [the bare form of the law] (as Kant, in his Critique of Practical Reason, deined
the law). And even if we are all potentially bare lives because the state of exception is the
rule, for law itself has always been naked [bloße], i.e., without content, there are speciic
social assemblages which, not having any decision power before the law, are actually
abandoned to face without any protection governmental doorkeepers. For this reason
Benjamin writes that das bloße Leben is the marked bearer of guilt [250]: naked life is
inevitably guilty, for it has been stripped of the performative means to enforce a reading
of the law which would prove its own innocence. Deconstruction deals with the “coextensivity of the political and the police” [Derrida, “Force of Law” 279] by proposing a
sort of microphysique of sovereignty that took away the monopoly over decision from the
hegemonic authorities, dispersed reading power over the law upon the entire social body,
and allowed for anti-hegemonic applications. Reading and counter-reading. Decision and
counter-decision. Enforcement and counter-enforcement. Violence and counter-violence.
“This ininite passage through violence is what is called history,” Derrida concluded visà-vis Levinas in his 1964 “Violence and Metaphysics” [162].7
However, according to Agamben, Derrida’s acceptance of the unavoidability of the
oscillatory movement organizing the political eludes the real problem: the fact that we,
like Kafka’s countryman and K., are delivered to the absolute power of a law which, not
demanding anything speciic, can potentially ind us guilty of anything. The law is all
the more pervasive insofar as it completely lacks content. Agamben and Derrida would
agree on this. However, Agamben diverges from Derrida on the best strategy to resist a
law found to be in force without signiicance. “It is precisely concerning the sense of this
being in force (and of the state of exception that it inaugurates) that our position distinguishes itself from that of deconstruction” [Homo Sacer 54]. Instead of trying to prevent
law’s pure potentiality from being actualized, deconstruction obliges humanity to the
ininite task of inluencing the outcomes of law’s transitus de potentia ad actum. Rather
than liberating humanity from the blackmail of the law as text, Derrida accepts life in the
7
I refer to Samir Haddad’s “A Genealogy of Violence” for a detailed discussion of Derrida’s accounts of violence and its unavoidability. Haddad argues that the suggestion, from “Violence and
Metaphysics,” that one ought to negotiate with the inevitability of violence by choosing the lesser
violence is a contradictory claim, and one that therefore disappears in Derrida’s later essays.
Curiously Haddad does not take into consideration The Gift of Death, where one witnesses the
ultimate collapse of the distinction between ethical choices and sacriicial decisions.
88
diacritics / fall 2009
state of exception as our only possible future, for such a form-of-life has always been
our past. We have always been préjugés because the law, in its unpresentability, forces
us to appear and respond before it. But since the law does not have signiicance in itself,
one cannot rely on statutory reforms for protection against law’s interpellation (to use an
Althusserian term). One can only be defended by the re-empowerment of bare lives, i.e.,
the strengthening of communities and lawyers who are working for alternative, “ethical”
enforcements of the law. Those who appear barest before the law are the ones whom
the judiciary should favor. What is wrong with all this? According to Agamben, Derrida
continues to imagine the political realm in Schmittian terms, that is, accepting the imputability of life and relying on the fundamental category in the architectonics of Schmitt’s
thought: decision. It is ultimately for this reason that Agamben detects in deconstruction
the risk both of reducing thought and politics to a negotiation with the doorkeepers who
control access to the law, and of attributing to thought and politics a door keeping function. Derrida is playing sovereign, in other words. Don’t we need new doorkeepers if we
want to subvert the decisions of the current ones, if we want the signiicance of the law to
be decided otherwise and with others’ interests in mind? Derrida’s decisions are of course
very different from Schmitt’s. They are taken within the horizon of a democracy to come,
“for the sake of more rather than fewer, and weaker rather than stronger, segments of the
population” [McCormick 1698]. This emancipatory thrust organizing deconstruction is
totally absent from Schmitt. But this is not Agamben’s point. Agamben does not suggest
a political syntony between Schmitt and Derrida. He highlights the structural afinity
between their frameworks and the crucial role that the category of decision plays in both
systems.
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, in her response to John McCormick’s “Schmittian Positions on Law and Politics?,” explained why Derrida’s decisions cannot be considered
sovereign decision in Schmitt’s sense. McCormick’s essay did not actually imply a direct
connection between Schmitt and Derrida. However, he went terribly close to it from
Spivak’s perspective: he underlined the similarity between Schmitt and the Critical Legal
Studies (CLS) project. Given the “conjunction or conjuncture” established by Derrida in
“Force of Law” between “his” deconstruction and the juridical one performed by CLS, it
is not a surprise that Spivak addressed the issue of a presumed analogy between Schmitt’s
and Derrida’s frameworks. Very schematically, Spivak’s argument goes as follows:
In Schmitt, the foundation of the political rests in the possibility of drawing a line
distinguishing the friend from the enemy. Derrida’s deconstructive intervention from The
Politics of Friendship shows how this original political distinction is never sound, for
the eventuality of civil war—a war between friends—always haunts the stability of any
political space whatsoever. Since the other cannot be accessed directly but through what
Husserl would call “analogical appresentation,” there is no certainty on who is really a
friend. Again, as it happened when standing before the law, the impossibility of touching
what stands before us obliges us to responsibility and decision—responsibility and decision which remain heterogeneous to cognition. Political decisionism must negotiate with
the undecidable, Spivak argues [1725–28].8 But this is exactly what the sovereign does,
isn’t it? Is he not the one who deals with the “perhaps” which makes any decision impossible, by deciding nonetheless? Beyond knowledge, beyond criteria, beyond the law—the
sovereign decides. He decides in the state of exception, but also on the state of exception,
meaning that his decision and his sovereignty do not depend on a concrete matter of fact,
since rather the signiicance of reality itself is a matter of sovereign (reading) decision.
Derrida in “Force of Law” had tried to pass off Benjamin as a leftist Heideggerian who
exorcised the spectral undecidability of the represented law in the name of a presentiica8
See also Thurschwell, “Specters of Nietzsche” 60–65.
Chronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
89
tion of justice. Agamben, in Homo Sacer and State of Exception, in a rather obscure way,
responds to Derrida’s critique of Benjamin by showing that Derrida’s recourse to the
category of decision is actually a capitulation to the structure of the exception. Derrida as
a leftist Schmittian. But can any form of decisionism (juridical, political, or ethical) avoid
the justiication of sacriice? Can it avoid thanatopolitics?
In the case of Caldwell v. Mississippi, the Supreme Court overturned a death penalty
sentence because the prosecutor had announced to the jury that it was not ultimately
responsible for its decision because the sentence would be subjected to further review:
judges with technical expertise would correct the jury’s possible mistake. The Court reversed the death sentence committed by the jurors and held that displacing the jury’s
responsibility of handing down death to a fellow human being onto technical formalism
violated the Constitution. According to Thurschwell, Caldwell v. Mississippi is an astonishing case because the Supreme Court deemed inadequate the formal law (represented
by the technical appellate courts) vis-à-vis the individual and untechnical ethical responsibility towards the other (represented by the jurors). In other words: the Supreme Court
pitted formal law against “a responsibility placed upon each of them [the jurors] singularly and alone, to confront the singularity of the defendant’s life and weigh it against the
heinousness of the crime, without the beneit of any normative guidance (in legal or any
other form) whatsoever” [Thurschwell, “Cutting the Branches” 187–88].
Before getting to the discussion of Caldwell v. Mississippi, Thurschwell had glossed
“with bemusement” over Agamben’s claim that any assumption of responsibility towards
the other in Levinassian terms (and, according to Thurschwell, also Derridian terms)
is genuinely juridical and not ethical. However, in his reading of Caldwell v. Mississippi, Thurschwell cannot avoid evoking the proximity between Levinas and Schmitt,
and therefore between the ethical “in Levinas’s sense” [185] and the juridical, but also
and foremost between Derrida and Schmitt. For Thurschwell, Caldwell v. Mississippi
represents in fact an invitation to capital defense lawyers to call the juries to their ethical
obligation toward the other, an obligation and a responsibility that cannot be assumed
within the boundaries of the law’s formalism. Beyond the law: ethics. Responsibility in
the “Levinassian-Derridian sense” is a matter of decision. Yet deciding on the life and
death of other citizens beyond the law (i.e., within the camp) is exactly what the sovereign does at all times. Thurschwell discussed Caldwell v. Mississippi with the intention
of showing how sovereignty is exceeded by moments of ethical responsibility. But at the
end of his analysis, he inds himself acknowledging that ethical responsibility is itself
structurally indistinguishable from sovereign absolute power, the power of he who decides in the state of exception. In the inal passages of “Cutting the Branches for Akiba,”
Thurschwell admits in fact that one can give a “more sinister and more Schmittian interpretation” to the “the language of ‘responsibility’ of Caldwell” [189]. That Schmittianism
is the dark side of any ethics of responsibility is especially clear if one looks at The Gift
of Death, where Derrida “interprets Abraham’s sacriice not as a hyperbolic exception but
as something which all of us perform again and again, every day, in our most common
ethical experience” [Žižek 22]. If ethical responsibility implies the extralegal decision on
who deserves to live and who does not (as it does for Derrida according to Thurschwell),
if it amounts to a sacriicial decision (as it indeed does for Derrida) then any ethics of
responsibility boils down to sovereignty. And, as we know, the proper space for the sovereign is the camp. Deconstruction does not merely dwell within the state of exception. Its
hope to strategically beneit from law’s indetermination to implement a progressive, ethical program actually reinforces the trope of the sovereign, and with it, the trope of bare
life. In order to move beyond the camps and the logic of exception, a different strategy
and a different ethics are, according to Agamben, necessary.
90
diacritics / fall 2009
Davide Bertocchi, Limo, 2001–2002
3D animation on DVD, 30-minute loop
3D graphic animation by Christian Dubroca
Courtesy the artist
This 3D animation acts as a virtual site-specific sculpture for the Guggenheim
Museum in New York. A curved stretch limousine is rendered to fit the circular
shape of the interior of the museum and follow its spiral. The radius of the curved
limousine and that of Frank Lloyd Wright’s famous cylindrical building are the
same, enabling the car to move up and down the different levels of the building
following a “natural” orbit and transforming the museum into a galaxy itself.
4
Conclusion: For an Ethics of Sabotage
Until a completely new politics—that is, a politics no longer founded on the
exceptio of bare life—is at hand, every theory and every praxis will remain imprisoned and immobile, and the “beautiful day” of life will be given citizenship
only either through blood and death or in the perfect senselessness to which the
society of the spectacle condemns it. [Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer 11]
Let us pause and recapitulate.
According to Derrida, the countryman from Kafka’s parable overlooked the fact that
the meaning of the law is undecidable because it is a text. The countryman should have
determined the law’s meaning himself through a singular and non-delegable decision: he
should have become a deciding authority and gained control over the passage of law from
potential indetermination to concrete application. For deconstruction, what is decisive
is not to come out of the state of exception, but to inhabit it in an ethically responsible
way. For Agamben, however, Derrida’s suggestion of dwelling in the camp differently is
unacceptable for it still implies biopolitically deciding on other people’s lives within the
suspension of the law. What to do then? How to deal with the law’s being in force without
signiicance? Obviously it is not a matter of defending the signiicance of the law against
Derrida’s deconstructive approaches: the prestige of deconstruction, Agamben admits in
Homo Sacer, is due to its having exposed the law’s textual indetermination as an impassable condition [54]. However, for the reasons I enumerated above, Derrida’s route—deciding the signiicance of the laws after having demonstrated their undecidability—is out
of the question. Since one cannot take a stance with regard to the “without signiicance”
of a juridical order, acting on its “being in force” appears then the only option. And this is
exactly the strategy that the countryman followed according to Agamben. In Agamben’s
Benjamin-driven reading of Kafka, the countryman is not idle nor is the legend about an
event that happens not to happen. As a matter of fact, an event does take place before the
law. It is provoked by the countryman himself. Does not the guardian close the door of
the law at the end? In Homo Sacer we read:
If it is true the door’s very openness constituted, as we saw, the invisible power
and speciic “force” of the Law, then we can imagine that all the behavior of the
man from the country is nothing other than a complicated and patient strategy
to have the door closed in order to interrupt the Law’s being in force. And in the
end, the man succeeds in his endeavor, since he succeeds in having the door of
the Law closed forever (it was, after all, open “only for him”), even if he may
have risked his life in the process (the story does not say that he is actually dead
but only that he is “close to the end”). [55]9
The man from the country does not die. He pretends to pass away, as his inal act in
a long and complicated confrontation with the doorkeeper. The countryman never actually wanted to access the law; his plan was to defer the moment of the dispositif—i.e., the
deciding part in a sentence [Agamben, “What Is an Apparatus?” 7]—until the doorkeeper
Agamben targets Derrida’s interpretation of Kafka (and therefore Benjamin) also in “The Messiah and the Sovereign” 173–74 and in “K.” In State of Exception, Agamben “sneakingly” authorizes his own reading of Benjamin (and therefore Kafka) via an essay by a scholar close to
Derrida’s “inner circle”: Samuel Weber’s “Taking Exception to Decision.”
9
92
diacritics / fall 2009
would eventually cave in and deinitively close the door of the law. The apparent defeat
of the countryman is actually his victory, for it coincides with the liberation of life from
the law’s blackmail. Since the law has no signiicance, it should also have no force—no
force and no authority over people’s lives. The man from the country knew this well.
While faking submission, he resisted the temptation to have his body co-implicated in
the workings of a trial. After all, so many of Kafka’s other characters had taught him that
by crossing the law’s gate, one becomes either victim or tormentor, sacriicial object or
sacriicing subject, bare life or sovereign. In order to move beyond this desperate set of
alternatives, it was urgent to dissociate oneself from the spaces dominated by the logic of
the exception, the spaces where ethics and politics amount to sovereignly, even if responsibly, deciding on other people’s lives. A true exception to the exception was imperative.
The countryman did not want anything else. The only thing he sought was the transformation of his village into an exceptional place, a space where men and women would
need to come to terms with each other without recourse to the death threat grounding any
sovereign decision. By tricking the guardian into closing the door of the law, by rendering the law not only content-less but also force-less, the countryman brought forth one
such exceptional space, liberating human praxis and politics from the spectral violence
of any law whatsoever. He was eventually able to open up a common place for human
interaction beyond the camp. And he did it, according to Agamben at least, not by enforcing decisions, but by deactivating the very capacity of sovereign power to decide and to
enforce its dispositifs. His ethics is then an ethics of sabotage. It does not seek to impose
a will and a direction on life, but to enable alternative modalities of being-together. It deposes rather than imposes, liberates instead of condemning. From Kafka’s parable, Derrida drew an ethics of responsibility in which it was a matter of deciding “responsibly.” In
Agamben, on the other hand, the countryman’s ethics is a matter of space and amounts to
the creation of dwelling places in which living beings could experiment new possibilities
of life in common.10
In 2001, Tiqqun—a transnational collective heavily inluenced by Italian unorthodox
Marxism (autonomia) and by the work of Italian theorists like Agamben, Negri, Virno,
and De Martino—published an article called “Une métaphysique critique pourrait naître
comme science des dispositifs . . .” in the second issue of its short-lived review. The
irst essay of the issue, “Introduction à la guerre civile,” targeted Derrida, among others.
Deconstruction is denounced here as a writing style compatible with the Empire insofar
as its only effect is to depotentialize life, passing for mystical or proto-fascist any actual
revolt program and erecting a cordon sanitaire around anything marked by some sort
of revolutionary charge [26]. Tiqqun deals with French critical theory more in general
in “Une métaphysique critique,” which is presented as the founding document of The
Society for the Advancement of Criminal Science, a nonproit organization dedicated
to the diffusion of knowledge useful to anti-imperial resistance. After describing French
critique as a resentful denunciation of contemporary life that ends up sheltering what is so
iercely exposed from any concrete intervention, Tiqqun concludes: “A science of apparatuses, a critical metaphysics, is thus indeed necessary, but not to depict some appealing
certainty behind which one could hide oneself, nor even to add to life the thought of itself.
We do need to think about our lives, but in order to dramatically intensify them. . . . What
do I care about a knowledge that does not increase my potentialities?” [134–35]. Perhaps
here one can locate the lesson of Italian radical thought on critical theory. In order to be
Thurschwell also highlights that Agamben’s “spatial ethics” is inluenced by Heidegger’s “Letter on ‘Humanism,’” where ethics is deined as the adobe where mortals and gods meet. On the
contrast between Agamben’s Heideggerianism and Derrida’s Levinassianism, see Catherine Mills,
“Agamben’s Messianic Politics” 50–57.
10
Chronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
93
relevant, critical theory will have to be a science of dispositifs. A general sabotage of
sovereign apparatuses and a potentialization of truly exceptional living spaces. Isn’t this
what the desire for commonality and communism in the end amounts to?
WORKS CITED
Ackerman, Bruce. “The Emergency Constitution.” The Yale Law Journal 113.5 (2004):
1029–91. Print.
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford: Stanford UP,
1998. Print.
———. “K.” Nudities. Trans. Stefan Pedatella and David Kishik. Stanford: Stanford UP,
2010. 20–36. Print.
———. Means without End: Notes on Politics. Trans. Vincenzo Binetti and Cesare Casarino. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print.
———. “The Messiah and the Sovereign: The Problem of Law in Walter Benjamin.”
Potentialities: Collected Essays in Philosophy. By Agamben. Ed. and trans. Daniel
Heller-Roazen. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1999. 160–75. Print.
———. State of Exception. Trans. Kevin Attell. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2005. Print.
———. “What Is an Apparatus?” “What Is an Apparatus?” and Other Essays. Trans.
David Kishik and Stefan Pedatella. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2009. 1–24. Print.
Attell, Kevin. “An Esoteric Dossier: Agamben and Derrida Read Saussure.” ELH 76.4
(2009): 821–46. Print.
Benjamin, Walter. “Critique of Violence.” Selected Writings, Volume 1, 1913–1926. Ed.
Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings. Trans. Edmund Jephcott. Cambridge:
Harvard UP, 2004. 236–52. Print.
Derrida, Jacques. “Before the Law.” Acts of Literature. By Derrida. Ed. Derek Attridge.
New York: Routledge, 1992. 181–220. Print.
———. “Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority.” Acts of Religion. By
Derrida. Ed. Gil Anidjar. New York: Routledge, 2002. 230–98. Print.
———. The Gift of Death. Trans. David Wills. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1995. Print.
———. “Préjugés: Devant la loi.” La faculté de juger. By Derrida et al. Paris: Minuit,
1985. 87–139. Print.
———. Rogues: Two Essays on Reason. Trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Nass.
Stanford: Stanford UP, 2005. Print.
———. “Violence and Metaphysics: An Essay on the Thought of Emmanuel Levinas.”
Writing and Difference. By Derrida. Trans. Alan Bass. New York: Routledge, 2001.
97–192. Print.
Dyzenhaus, David. “Legal Theory in the Collapse of Weimar: Contemporary Lessons?”
The American Political Science Review 91.1 (1997): 121–34. Print.
———. “Schmitt v. Dicey: Are States of Emergency Inside or Outside the Legal Order?”
Cardozo Law Review 27.5 (2006): 2005–39. Print.
Esposito, Roberto. B́os: Biopolitics and Philosophy. Trans. Timothy Campbell. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2008. Print.
Gross, Oren. “Chaos and Rules: Should Responses to Violent Crises Always Be Constitutional?” The Yale Law Journal 112.5 (2003): 1011–134. Print.
Haddad, Samir. “Derrida and Democracy at Risk.” Contretemps 4 (2004): 29–44. Web.
14 Mar. 2012.
———. “A Genealogy of Violence, from Light to the Autoimmune.” Diacritics 38.1–2
(2008): 121–42. Print.
Kafka, Franz. “Before the Law.” Franz Kafka: The Complete Stories. Trans. Nahum N.
Glatzer. New York: Schocken, 1988. 3–4. Print.
94
diacritics / fall 2009
———. The Trial. Trans. Mike Mitchell. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2009. Print.
Kanwar, Vik. Rev. of State of Exception, by Giorgio Agamben. International Journal of
Constitutional Law 4.3 (2006): 567–75. Print.
Korematsu v. United States. 323 US 214. Supreme Court of the US. 1944. Supreme Court
Collection. Legal Information Inst., Cornell U Law School, n.d. Web. 13 Mar. 2012.
McCormick, John P. “Schmittian Positions on Law and Politics?: CLS and Derrida.”
Cardozo Law Review 21.1 (2000): 1693–721. Print.
Mills, Catherine. “Agamben’s Messianic Politics: Biopolitics, Abandonment and Happy
Life.” Contretemps 5 (2004): 42–62. Web. 14 Mar. 2012.
Mommsen, Hans. “The Reichstag Fire and Its Political Consequences.” Republic to
Reich: The Making of the Nazi Revolution. Ed. Hajo Holborn. Trans. Ralph Manheim. New York: Pantheon, 1972. 129–222. Print.
Posner, Eric A., and Adrian Vermeule. “Accommodating Emergencies.” U of Chicago
Public Law Working Paper 48 (2003). Sept. 2003. Web. 13 Mar. 2012.
———. “Crisis Governance in the Administrative State: 9/11 and the Financial Meltdown of 2008.” The University of Chicago Law Review 76.4 (2009): 1613–82. Print.
Schmitt, Carl. Dictatorship. 1921. Cambridge: Polity, 2010. Print.
———. Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty. 1922. Trans.
George Schwab. Cambridge: MIT P, 1985. Print.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. “Schmitt and Postructuralism: A Response.” Cardozo Law
Review 21.1 (2000): 1723–37. Print.
Stone, Geoffrey R. Perilous Times: Free Speech in Wartime from the Sedition Act of 1798
to the War on Terrorism. New York: Norton, 2004. Print.
Thurschwell, Adam. “Cutting the Branches for Akiba: Agamben’s Critique of Derrida.”
Politics, Metaphysics, and Death: Essays on Giorgio Agamben’s Homo Sacer. Ed.
Andrew Norris. Durham: Duke UP, 2005. 173–97. Print.
———. “Specters of Nietzsche: Potential Futures for the Concept of the Political in
Agamben and Derrida.” Social Science Research Network. 1 Sept. 2004. Web. 10
Mar. 2012.
Tiqqun. “Introduction à la guerre civile.” Tiqqun 2 (2001): 2–37. Print.
———. “Une métaphysique critique pourrait naître comme science des dispositifs . . .”
Tiqqun 2 (2001): 109–65. Print.
Tobias, Fritz. The Reichstag Fire. Trans. Arnold Pomerans. New York: Putnam, 1964.
Print.
Tribe, Laurence H., and Patrick O. Gudridge. “The Anti-Emergency Constitution.” The
Yale Law Journal 113.8 (2004): 1801–70. Print.
Tushnet, Mark. “Defending Korematsu?: Relections on Civil Liberties in Wartime.” Wisconsin Law Review 23.2 (2003): 273–307. Print.
Vermeule, Adrian. “Our Schmittian Administrative Law.” Harvard Law Review 122.4
(2009): 1096–149. Print.
———. “Self-Defeating Proposals: Ackerman on Emergency Powers.” Fordham Law
Review 75.2 (2006): 631–49. Print.
Virno, Paolo. Multitude Between Innovation and Negation. Trans. Isabella Bertoletti,
James Cascaito, and Andrea Casson. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2008. Print.
Weber, Samuel. “Taking Exception to Decision: Walter Benjamin and Carl Schmitt.”
Diacritics 22.3–4 (1992): 5–18. Print.
Žižek. Slavoj. “Carl Schmitt in the Age of Post-Politics.” The Challenge of Carl Schmitt.
Ed. Chantal Mouffe. London: Verso, 1999. 18–37. Print.
Chronotopologies of the Exception / Lorenzo Fabbri
95