The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 24: 55–68 (1999)
c 1999 The Geneva Association
°
Regulation of Insurance Markets
RAY REES
University of Munich, Ludwigstr 28/III VG, 80539 Munich, Germany
HUGH GRAVELLE
University of York, Heslington, York Y01 5DD, UK
ACHIM WAMBACH
University of Munich, Ludwigstr 28/III VG, 80539 Munich, Germany
Ray.Rees@lrz.uni-muenchen.de
hg8@york.ac.uk
A.Wambach@lrz.uni-muenchen.de
Abstract
There have been major changes in the way European insurance markets are regulated, and there is still considerable
debate about what the form and scope of regulation should be. This article examines the arguments for solvency
regulation when consumers are fully informed of the insurer’s insolvency risk. It is shown firms always provide
enough capital to ensure solvency, unless there are restrictions on the composition of their asset portfolios. The
conclusion holds even when competition means that only normal profits can be earned. This suggests that the role
of regulation in insurance markets should be confined to providing consumers with information about the default
risk of insurers.
Key words: insurance regulation, information, insolvency
1. Introduction
The framework of regulation of the European insurance markets is currently undergoing
major changes by the European Commission (EC), which is seeking to “complete the
common market” in insurance and in financial services generally. The aim is to facilitate
more competition among insurance companies, based in different countries, in each others’
home markets. This requires drastic change in regulatory regimes that until now have
presented major barriers to such competition.
The EC has adopted a two-step strategy. On the one hand it has harmonized regulations1
concerning the solvency and financial reporting of insurance companies across all countries
of the European Union (EU). The regulations are detailed and differ as between life and
nonlife insurance, but broadly speaking they require insurers to carry reserves of liquid capital, over and above normal “technical” or “mathematical” reserves, which are expressed as
proportions of premium income and claims expenses. The regulatory agency in the insurer’s
home country is responsible for enforcing the regulations. The solvency requirements are
rules of thumb arrived at by committee decision, and there is some debate about whether
they are “adequate” or “excessive.” It does not appear that economic analysis has played
any part in the determination of these solvency margins. In particular the welfare economics
56
RAY REES, HUGH GRAVELLE AND ACHIM WAMBACH
of the arguments for and against such solvency regulations does not seem to have received
formal analysis.
The second step in the strategy was to make the regulatory regime to which an insurer
is subject that of its home country rather than of the country whose market it is seeking to
enter.2 Because harmonization of the overall regulatory system turned out to be impossible
to achieve, the EC’s aim was to make it impossible for the regulator in any country to erect
barriers to entry of insurers from other EU member states.
A further consequence is the possibility of competition among regulatory regimes. A
country will be under pressure to modify its regime if it disadvantages its home insurers in
their competition with foreign entrants. Failure to do this could lead companies to relocate
or set up subsidiaries in other countries to benefit from competitively more favourable
regulatory regimes, as with “flags of convenience” in shipping and “Delaware companies”
in the United States. New entrants to the European market will choose to locate in countries
with the most favorable regulatory regimes while still having access to the entire European
market. In this way de facto harmonization might be achieved in the long run by competition
among regulatory systems.
The developments raise a number of interesting economic issues concerning the relationship between regulatory rules on the one hand and competitive interactions among
insurance firms on the other. The rationale for the changes would seem to be that firms
whose home countries have a light regulatory regime would hold a competitive advantage
over those subjects to a tighter regime. Regulation in Britain and France was relatively light,
while that in Germany was extremely detailed and centralized, with Italy also tending in
this direction.3 This suggests that British and French insurers could take over the German
market or alternatively that regulation in Germany will become as light as that in Britain
and the Netherlands.
There has already been a significant loosening of German regulation.4 The regulator’s
powers to specify the detailed form of standard contracts in the major areas of insurance, to
control premium levels, and to regulate entry have virtually disappeared. The result has been
innovation in product specification—for example, lower tariffs for nonsmokers and savings
plans involving greater equity participation in life insurance, a finer classification of risk
categories in motor insurance, and even the introduction of private unemployment insurance.
However, there is so far little sign of general price competition. Habits of collusive price
setting established under the centralized regulatory regime persist and have been reinforced
by the EC’s grant to European insurance trade associations of exemption from antitrust
legislation. Premium calculation will still be centralized by actuaries working for the trade
association, rather than by the regulatory agency. The latter will still monitor premium
levels in the interests of preventing “ruinous competition” and ensuring solvency of insurers.
Moreover, the German regulators have succeeded in retaining restrictions on the types of
assets German insurers may hold, implying that German regulation is still tighter than that
in Britain. The old presumption that, in the insurance market at least, competition is against
the public interest seems not to have lost its support.
The normative aspects of insurance market deregulation are still contentious. The standard
defense of the detailed German regulation is that it is first and foremost in the consumer
interest but also in the longer term interests of insurance companies. Solvency is of prime
REGULATION OF INSURANCE MARKETS
57
importance. The buyer of insurance gives up a sum of money against a promise that she
will receive a payment in the future if specified random events occur. If the insurer does
not provide adequate reserves to fulfill this promise, the consumer is being cheated ex ante,
while insolvencies ex post undermine the confidence on which the market is based and
thus threaten the long-term interests of the insurers themselves: If there is perception of
default risk on the part of consumers one could speak of a “lemons problem,” in the sense
that uncertainty about product quality—solvency—could drive high-quality firms out of
the market, if there were difficulties of signaling high quality. It is further argued that price
competition may undermine the solvency of insurers by weakening their financial position.
Proponents of deregulation, on the other hand, argue that the solvency concerns do not
require the degree and type of regulation that has existed in Germany and that competition
and solvency are perfectly consistent with each other. Empirically, it is argued that the better
solvency record in Germany, as compared to, say, Britain, has been bought at much too
high a cost in terms of consumer welfare. There is also the strong suspicion of “capture” of
regulators by insurers with the implication that regulations exist mainly to benefit insurers
and not their customers. The regulatory agency was seen as effectively enforcing a cartel
in the interests of the insurance companies.
The EC policy can be viewed as providing some support to the position of the critics of
regulation to a limited extent. The process of deregulation subject to uniform constraints on
solvency certainly fits with their arguments, though the exemption from antitrust legislation
seems to be more consistent with the concern that unrestricted price competition could
undermine solvency.5 The signals from the EC are, not for the first time, conflicting.
The purpose of the present article is to extend the models currently available in the literature that provide an analytical basis for the discussion of solvency, capital requirements, and
price competition on insurance markets. We show that solvency regulation is unnecessary if
consumers are fully informed about the risks of the insurer’s insolvency. This is true in a very
strong sense: if consumers correctly perceive the risk of insolvency, then it is not optimal
for the monopoly insurer to run the risk of insolvency.6 It follows that solvency “regulation”
could in fact simply be restricted to informing consumers about the true insolvency risk.
Solvency regulation is justified only if it is the case that somehow consumers cannot be
appropriately informed of, or cannot accurately work out, the risks of insurer insolvency
or if the market in the provision of this information somehow fails.7 Moreover we show
that allowing Bertrand price competition does not change this result but strengthens it. In
the Nash equilibrium firms will hold enough capital to meet the maximum claims that they
may face.
2. Solvency and the insurer
It is usual in the insurance economics literature to consider the insurance market as perfectly
competitive.8 Descriptively there are strong arguments for modeling the insurance market
as an oligopoly. However, the appropriate model to use is that of Bertrand where prices are
the strategy variables so that, in the absence of product differentiation, even the duopoly
outcome is perfectly competitive, and so the difference seems to be inessential.
58
RAY REES, HUGH GRAVELLE AND ACHIM WAMBACH
It is convenient to start with a monopoly model that integrates the firm’s decisions over
pricing policy and capital provision. We then examine a duopoly with price-setting firms.
We begin by recasting and extending the model in Finsinger and Pauly [1984], which in
turn draws heavily on papers by Borch [1981], and Munch and Smallwood [1981]. There
is an infinite sequence of time periods. At the beginning of each period the insurer must
decide on a level of capital K for the insurance business. He faces a given distribution of
claims C, with distribution function F(C) and differentiable density f (C), defined over
the interval [0, Cu ]. For the moment, as in Finsinger and Pauly [1984], we take premium
income P also to be exogenous.
P is collected at the beginning of the period and invested along with the capital. We
assume initially that the only capital-market asset is a riskless security with gross return
r > 1. If at the end of the period assets A ≡ (P + K )r are at least enough to meet claims C,
then the insurer remains in business and receives a continuation value V that is the expected
present value of being in the insurance business at the end of the first period. If claims
costs turn out to be greater than assets,9 the insurer pays out his assets and defaults on the
remaining claims, losing the right to the continuation value V . Because of limited liability
he does not have to pay out more than A to claimants.
The insurer can always choose to guarantee solvency by putting in enough capital, since
we assume that the upper limit Cu on possible claims is finite.10 The question of interest is:
under what circumstances would the insurer choose to stay solvent, thus making regulation
unnecessary, and what are the likely effects of competition on his choices?
Define V (K ∗ ) as the continuation value of the firm given that it chooses an optimal K ∗
in all future periods. Since the model is time invariant, so is the optimal capital input. We
assume the insurer is risk neutral and the only cost of capital put into the insurance business
is r , the riskless rate of return on the capital market. It follows that his optimal policy is to
choose capital in each period to maximize
1
V0 (K ) =
r
Z
0
A
1
[r (K + P) − C] dF − K + F(r (K + P))V (K ∗ )
r
(1)
subject to K ∈ [0, K u ], where K u = (Cu /r ) − P is the capital required to ensure no default.
So far nothing beyond differentiability has been assumed for the claims distribution F.
Empirically, however, insurance claims distributions typically belong to the class of “increasing failure rate” distributions, with the property that
·
¸
d 1 − F(C)
< 0.
dC
f (C)
(2)
As Munch and Smallwood [1981] showed, though in a somewhat different model, an
implication of this property is that only corner solutions to the insurer’s wealth maximization
problem are possible: either he chooses K = 0, or K = K u . We now show that this result
carries over to the present model.
Proposition 1: Given a claims distribution with the property (2) the insurer chooses a
corner solution: K ∗ = 0 or K ∗ = K u .
REGULATION OF INSURANCE MARKETS
59
Proof. Suppose not, so that K ∗ ∈ (0, K u ) maximizes V0 (K ), which implies
V0′ (K ∗ ) = F + f V(K ∗ ) − 1 = 0
(3)
V0′′ (K ∗ )
′
(4)
V (K ∗ ) = (1 − F)/ f,
(5)
∗
= V (K ) f + f ≤ 0.
Then (3) implies
while (2) implies
f 2 + f ′ (1 − F) > 0,
and so substituting for V (K ∗ ) from (5) into (4) yields a contradiction.
(6)
✷
Note that a solution to the problem does exist, since the objective function is continuous
on the compact interval [0, K u ]. Which endpoint is optimal is given by the straightforward
comparison of the values
¶
µ
C̄0
r/[r − F(r P)]
V (0) = F(r P) P −
r
¶
µ
C̄
r/[r − 1],
V (K u ) = P −
r
(7)
(8)
R rP
where C̄ is the mean of the claims distribution and C̄0 = [F(r P)]−1 0 CdF < C̄ is the
mean of the truncated distribution. As these expressions clearly show, the advantage of not
putting up any capital is that the expected present value of claims falls. The disadvantage
is the risk of going out of business, F(r P) < 1. It does not seem possible to say that one of
these endpoints is always better than the other.
However, the results do appear to lend support to the argument that competition is bad for
solvency. Competition can be expected to drive premiums down to equal expected claims, in
which case the insurer would be indifferent between the two positions. Intuitively, the insurer
does not care about the risk of going out of business if in fact future profits of being in the
business are zero. Thus in those cases where high premiums might induce the insurer to
choose K u , competition could lead to greater insolvency risk. However, we show below
that this argument does not survive the appropriate formal modeling of price competition.
There are two major limitations of this model of the insurance firm that could make any
policy conclusions derived from it of limited relevance. The first is that the only assets
available on the market are safe assets. We need to allow for the interaction between the
risks associated with insurers’ asset portfolios and those associated with their insurance
activities. The second limitation is the exogeneity of the premium income. This is not
simply a matter of allowing the monopolist to choose the premium or volume of insurance
sold by maximizing profit with respect to a given demand function. It also implies the
60
RAY REES, HUGH GRAVELLE AND ACHIM WAMBACH
assumption that the demand for insurance is independent of the solvency risk of the insurer.
This is a central issue that has to be considered explicitly.
The first of these limitations, but not the second, is dealt with by MacMinn and Witt
[1987]. They assume the insurer can invest in a risky as well as a riskless asset, is risk-averse,
and faces a given demand function for insurance with respect to which it maximizes expected
utility. The main purpose of the article is to consider the effects of various kinds of regulatory
constraints on the decisions of the insurer. In this it makes a valuable contribution. The article,
assumes, however, that the only source of investment funds is premium income—that is,
K = 0. Consequently, the article cannot shed light on the interesting question of whether
the “corner solution” property disappears when risky assets are introduced. Finsinger and
Pauly [1984] showed that the introduction of a positive marginal cost of raising insurance
company capital may have this result, in cases where the insurer would otherwise choose
K u , since at an interior point the marginal benefit to the insurer of increasing K may fall
below this cost. However, the reason for the existence of this cost is not clear, and it would be
interesting to see if the same result can be produced by the more plausible step of introducing
risky assets.
MacMinn and Witt [1987] assume that the demand for insurance is independent of the
insolvency risk. Buyers of insurance are assumed to behave as if they believed that insolvency was impossible. We regard this assumption as the single most important limitation
of the existing literature, and so the remainder of this article is concerned with tackling it.
3. Consumer perceptions and insolvency
3.1. Riskless assets
We begin by introducing an insurance market into the model in almost the simplest possible way, short of just assuming a given demand function. We assume there is just one
insurance buyer with loss distribution F(C) and utility function u(.), with u ′ > 0, u ′′ < 0. In
the absence of insurance she obtains an expected utility
ū 0 ≡
Z
Cu
u(y − C) dF
(9)
0
with y given. The insurer makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer of an insurance contract giving
“full cover” of loss at a premium P. However, the buyer is able to observe the choice of K
by the insurer, and so the premium must satisfy her reservation constraint
Z
A
u(y − P) dF +
0
Z
Cu
u(y − C − P + A) dF ≥ ū 0 .
(10)
A
In words, as long as the insurer’s assets cover claims the insured has a certain income, but if
her claim exceeds the insurer’s assets (that is, he is insolvent), she receives only the amount
of these assets, and so she is left with a residual risk. She determines her willingness to pay
accordingly.
61
REGULATION OF INSURANCE MARKETS
Let P0 denote the premium that satisfies (10) as an equality when A = P0 —that is, K = 0.
Likewise Pu is this premium defined by u(y − Pu ) = ū 0 when there is no default risk. The
amount of capital that leads to zero default risk is K u = Cu /r − Pu .
Proposition 2: When the insurance buyer is fully informed about the firm’s choice of
capital, the insurer’s expected value is larger at Pu , K u than at P0 and K = 0.
Proof. We have to show
1
r −1
Cu
Z
0
1
(r Pu − C) dF >
r − F(r P0 )
Z
r P0
(r P0 − C) dF,
(11)
0
which since r − 1 < r − F, is implied by
r Pu −
Z
Cu
CdF > F(r P0 )r P0 −
0
Z
r P0
CdF
0
or
r Pu > F(r P0 )r P0 +
Z
Cu
CdF.
(12)
r P0
Define P̃ to satisfy
u(y0 − P̃) =
1
1 − F(r P0 )
Z
Cu
u(y0 − C) dF.
(13)
r P0
By Jensen’s inequality
1
P̃ >
1 − F(r P0 )
Cu
Z
CdF
r P0
or
[1 − F(r P0 )] P̃ >
Z
Cu
CdF.
(14)
r P0
From (13) we have
u(y0 − Pu ) = F(r P0 )u(y0 − P0 ) + [1 − F(r P0 )]u(y0 − P̃)
(15)
and again Jensen’s inequality gives
Pu > F(r P0 )P0 + [1 − F(r P0 )] P̃,
(16)
62
RAY REES, HUGH GRAVELLE AND ACHIM WAMBACH
implying, using (14),
r Pu > F(r P0 )r P0 + r
Z
Cu
CdF > F(r P0 )r P0 +
r P0
Z
Cu
CdF
(17)
r P0
as required.
✷
A similar result can be proved for any K < K u . The intuition is that the consumer would
always be prepared to pay more than the fair premium to insure against the insurer’s insolvency, and so it pays the insurer to sell this to her, which in turn implies he must put up
enough capital to remain solvent.
The case of a single consumer is of course rather special but serves to bring out the
main point. We can generalize quite easily. Thus, suppose there are N consumers, each
with endowed wealth y and faced with an identical and independent risk of loss L < y with
probability p. Any risk of default is fully and correctly perceived by the buyers. In the case
of default it is necessary to make some assumption about how insurance claimants would
be rationed in the event that the value of claims exceeds the insurer’s end-of-period assets.
Thus we assume:
1. Insurance contracts are for full coverage.
2. There is random rationing in the following sense: if a consumer has a claim and total
claims exceed assets then with a probability equal to the ratio of assets to claims each
claimant will receive the indemnity in full, otherwise she receives nothing.
The first of these assumptions is made for simplicity; the second seems quite reasonable.
We can imagine that losses hit consumers randomly throughout the period, are reported
as they occur, and then payouts are made at the end of the period in the order in which
losses were reported, until assets are exhausted or all claims are met.11 Given a full cover
insurance policy {P, I }, where P is the premium and I = L the indemnity, the representative
individual buys insurance if and only if the participation constraint
(1 − p)u(y − P) + p{(1 − π )u(y − P)
+ π [(1 − θ)u(y − P) + θ u(y − P − L)]} ≥ ū 0
or
(1 − q)u(y − P) + qu(y − P − L) ≥ ū 0
(18)
holds. Here, ū 0 has the same meaning as before, π is the probability that the insurer
is insolvent given the insured suffers the loss, and θ is the probability that she receives
nothing given she has a claim and the insurer is insolvent. In effect, then, there are still only
2 “income events” for the consumer—one in which she either has no loss or receives full
indemnity, and the other in which she bears the full loss. In both events, of course, she has
paid the premium. The probability of the latter event is q = pπ θ, and that of the former is
REGULATION OF INSURANCE MARKETS
63
1 − q. This probability can be written as follows. Suppose the insurer chooses to meet a
given number n < N of claims. Then
¶
¸
·
N −1 µ
X
n
N −1 m
N −1−m
p (1 − p)
1−
q=p
m
m +1
m=n−1
(19)
It is then straightforward to prove the equivalent result to Proposition 2 for this model. It
simply has to be noted that if the insurer has less capital than K m = N (L − r Pm )/r , where
Pm is the largest premium that can satisfy (18) with q = 0, then q > 0, and the expected cost
of claims is N ( p − q)L, since N q is the expected number of claimants that will receive
nothing. Then we have
Proposition 3: If buyers know the probability q that they will not be compensated, the
insurer maximises his expected value by choosing a capital K m so that there is no default
risk and q is zero.
Proof. We have to show that
1
1
N (r Pm − pL) >
N (r Pq − ( p − q)L),
r −1
r − (1 − d)
(20)
where d is the probability that the firm defaults and Pq is the largest value of P that can
satisfy (18) for the given value of q. Since r − 1 < r − (1 − d), it suffices to show that
r Pm ≥ r Pq + q L .
(21)
Since the buyer’s reservation constraint is satisfied as an equality, we have
u(y − Pm ) = (1 − q)u(y − Pq ) + qu(y − Pq − L),
(22)
and so by Jensen’s inequality we have
Pm > (1 − q)Pq + q(Pq + L),
(23)
which implies
r Pm > r Pq + rq L > r Pq + q L
as required.
(24)
✷
As for Proposition 2, the intuition is that the insured would always be prepared to pay
more than the fair premium to insure against the insurer’s insolvency, the insurer finds it
profitable to sell her this, but this requires him to put up enough capital so that he remains
solvent.
64
RAY REES, HUGH GRAVELLE AND ACHIM WAMBACH
These simple but far-reaching results suggest that the only purpose of regulation in
insurance markets should be to inform consumers of insolvency risks. That is, an insurer
would announce his capital, and the regulator would also know the parameters of the claims
distribution. The regulator would then announce the default probability for consumers,
who would then make their insurance decisions. The above argument then suggests that in
fact the capital will be sufficient to ensure no risk of insolvency. It could also be argued that
the present European system of solvency regulation in fact is a simpler way of achieving
the same result: the level of capital K is specified for insurers, and consumers can then
take their insurance decision consistent with the fact that there is a zero probability of
default. The danger is, as we see in the German case, that regulation rather than information
dissemination lends itself more readily to capture and extension of regulatory powers to
effective enforcement of a cartel.
3.2. Risky assets
To conclude this section we extend this point somewhat. A feature of tightly regulated
insurance markets is the imposition of constraints on the composition of the insurer’s asset
portfolio. We now show that this in itself can create the need for solvency regulation, in the
sense that without the constraints there is no insolvency risk but imposing them leads the
insurer to choose a smaller capital than K m and thus run the risk of insolvency, even though
this is perceived by buyers and results in a lower premium. This is a Pareto inefficiency,
since the insurer is worse off and insurance buyers no better off: they continue to receive
their reservation expected utility. The inefficiency is not removed by then requiring the
insurer to put K m into the insurance business.
The intuition is straightforward. In the absence of constraints on portfolio composition
it is effectively costless to put capital in the insurance business when there is no risk of
insolvency. Exactly the same portfolio can be chosen as would be the case if the capital
were invested outside the insurance business. However, constraints on the portfolio of the
insurer create marginal opportunity costs of capital invested in insurance that would not
otherwise exist, and this could lead to an optimum at an interior point of the interval [0, K m ].
Suppose there are two types of assets, a riskless asset with gross return r and a risky asset
with expected gross return v̄ > r and minimum gross return v0 > 0. This latter assumption
is important because it ensures that there is always a finite amount of capital that can be
invested in the insurance business to ensure solvency even when entirely invested in the
risky asset.12 The risk-neutral insurer would put all his capital into the risky asset and so
would require
Km =
Cm
− NPm
v0
(25)
to ensure solvency, where Cm is the upper bound on total claims and Pm is the largest
premium each of the N fully informed buyers would pay for full cover with no risk of
insolvency. The earlier results imply K m is optimal in the absence of portfolio restrictions.
However, suppose a regulator requires that a proportion 1 ≥ λ > 0 of any capital put into
the insurance business must be invested in the riskless asset. Then we have
REGULATION OF INSURANCE MARKETS
65
Proposition 4: On the given assumptions the insurer will choose K ∗ < K m in the presence
of portfolio constraints.
Proof. The opportunity cost of capital put into the insurance business is v̄ K , while the
expected return on this capital is r λ = [λr + (1 − λ)v̄]K . It follows that the net opportunity cost of a unit of capital invested in the insurance business is β = λ(v̄ − r ) > 0. At
K = K m − ε the expected value of the insurer is
V (K m − ε) =
N [r λPq − ( p − q)L] β(K m − ε)
−
.
v̄ − (1 − d)
v̄ − (1 − d)
We know from Proposition 3 that the first term is maximized at ε = 0 and so
¯
β[(v̄ − 1) + K m dε]
d V (K m − ε) ¯¯
,
=
¯
dε
(v̄ − 1)2
ε=0
which is positive since default risk is increasing in ε.
✷
4. Price competition and solvency
The contention of the advocates of extensive regulation is that price competition undermines
solvency. This could perhaps be lent support by the results of the first model considered,
in Section 2, where it appeared that if there was a zero profit from the insurance business
there would be no incentive to avoid bankruptcy. We analyze the issue more explicitly in a
model of Bertrand competition, which seems the most appropriate one for insurance markets
since insurers are essentially price-setters. As we would expect, with identical firms and no
transactions costs, each firm sets the fair premium at a market equilibrium.
More to the point, there is no bankruptcy risk in equilibrium. Each firm puts enough
capital into the insurance business to cover the maximum total claims in the entire market.
This is costless, as long as there are no restrictions on insurance company asset portfolios.
The intuition is straightforward. The usual Bertrand logic says that if a firm’s price is above
marginal cost (here, the fair premium), the other can profitably undercut it by shading price
slightly and capturing the entire market. In the present model that can happen only if indeed
the firm cutting price has enough capital to ensure a zero rationing probability if it obtains
the entire market. In other words, having this amount of capital is required to make the
price competition credible. Price competition could hardly be more cut-throat than in this
market, but it does not undermine solvency because firms back it up with sufficient capital
reserves.
We use the model of the previous section, with N insurance buyers each faced with the
risk of a loss L with probability p, but now with two firms (this could easily be generalized).
To simplify, we assume here that r = 1. This is not essential in that the result holds for r > 1,
but because we have assumed that insurance firms’ only costs are their payments to insureds,
r > 1 would yield an equilibrium insurance premium, which is less than the expected loss
per insured.
66
RAY REES, HUGH GRAVELLE AND ACHIM WAMBACH
The firms simultaneously announce a premium P and an amount of capital K . If premiums
and insolvency risk are identical each firm receives half the market, while with no insolvency
risk the firm with a lower premium would take the entire market. We now define
K m = N (1 − p)L
(26)
as the amount of capital an insurer would require to supply the entire market with no
solvency risk, at the fair premium pL. Then we have
Proposition 5: In the Nash equilibrium each insurer announces a premium pL and a
capital K ≥ K m .
Proof. (i) Neither firm would choose a premium below pL, since this implies expected
losses.
(ii) Suppose one firm sets a premium strictly above pL, with arbitrary capital. The other
can gain the entire market at some premium just below this, and with at least the amount of
capital. Moreover, as we saw in the previous section (Proposition 3), the highest expected
profit can be made when the default probability is zero. Thus a firm’s best response to a
premium above pL is to choose capital K ≥ K m and offer a slightly lower premium. The
best response to this in turn is to choose capital K ≥ K m and offer a slightly lower premium,
and so on. Thus no premium above pL can be an equilibrium.
(iii) Suppose both firms offer the premium pL. It cannot be an equilibrium to have
K < K m . If K < 12 K m , buyers face a default risk, and we know that cannot be optimal for
the insurer. If 12 K m ≤ K < K m , one firm could raise the premium slightly without losing all
its customers and so make an expected profit. The reason is that if all its consumers switched
to the other insurer, there would be a default risk, while they would be compensated for sure
if they stayed with the original firm. Since their willingness to pay is higher in the absence
of default risk, the conclusion follows.
✷
Competition leads not only to a Pareto-efficient equilibrium but one in which there is
zero probability of insolvency. This suggests that the observation of insolvencies in markets
characterized by competition, such as in the United Kingdom, is more likely to be due to
the sorts of factors that cause bankruptcies in all markets—for example, excessively high
cost levels—rather than failure to provide capital.
5. Conclusions
Though there are local variations reflecting past history, we could say that regulation in
European insurance markets has made a significant move toward regulation of solvency
alone. While more extensive regulation of the German sort is hard to justify and probably
can be explained by the theory of capture, the inevitable asymmetry of information between
insurers and insured may justify some kind of solvency supervision.13 If consumers naively
believe that the insurer will always be solvent then the analysis of Section 2 showed that it
could be optimal for the insurer not to put up any capital and run the risk of insolvency.14
REGULATION OF INSURANCE MARKETS
67
However, if consumers are fully informed of insolvency risk, and there are no restrictions on
the insurer’s asset portfolio, then the insurer will always find it profitable to reduce this risk
to zero. This holds true when price competition leads to the elimination of all supernormal
profit. In these circumstances the purpose of regulation should be simply that of providing
consumers with the required information, and regulatory agencies should be restricted to
this role.
Acknowledgments
An early draft of this article was presented at the Twenty-Third Seminar of the European
Group of Risk and Insurance Economists, Hannover, September 1996. We are grateful to
participants for helpful discussion, as well as to Kai Konrad and Hans-Werner Sinn. We are
also grateful to two referees for interesting suggestions.
Notes
1. For a good, concise survey and discussion of these regulations, see Konrath [1966].
2. On the other hand, the relevant law, including contract law, is that of the country in which the insurance
business is done.
3. For informative accounts of European regulatory systems prior to the EC measures, see Finsinger and Pauly
[1986], Finsinger, Hammond, and Tapp [1985], and for a detailed critique of regulation in Germany, Finsinger
[1983]. For more general analysis of regulation on insurance markets, see Briys and de Varenne [1994],
Doherty and Garven [1986], Finsinger and Pauly [1984], and Joskow [1973]. Two important papers that
analyze insurance market regulation and model simultaneously the financial decisions of the firm and premium
determination are MacMinn and Witt [1987] and Munch and Smallwood [1981].
4. The assertions made in this paragraph are based on Hohlfeld [1996]. The author was at the time head of the
German regulatory authority.
5. Ostensibly the argument is that it is necessary to pool claims data in order to calculate loss probabilities more
accurately, a long-standing and well-refuted claim of the German regulatory authorities.
6. An important contribution in this area, Doherty and Schlesinger [1990], analyzes the individual’s insurance
demand in the presence of insurer default risk. A number of interesting results are derived that show that
the standard results on insurance demand do not carry over to this case. However, the decision of the insurer is not considered. Here we are arguing that if the consumer is fully informed of the default risk, as
Doherty/Schlesinger assume, it is optimal for the insurer not to default, and so the problem essentially disappears. Although for simplicity here we assume rather than derive the demand for insurance under positive
default probability, this basic result also carries over to the more general case.
7. It is certainly reasonable to argue that regulatory agencies may have greater coercive powers to obtain information than private agencies, as well as better sanctions to deal with adverse selection problems.
8. For interesting exceptions, see Polborn [1998], and Schlesinger and Schulenburg [1991].
9. Here, as elsewhere in this article, we ignore the possibility of reinsurance. We also ignore the fact that insurance
companies can be traded on stock markets. Both features would complicate our analysis, and we leave them
for future work.
10. This assumption represents a modification of the Finsinger-Pauly model, as does the assumption of a rate of
return r > 1 and the interpretation of the variable V . Finsinger and Pauly, in common with standard actuarial
practice, treat the claims distribution as unbounded above. In effect, then, solvency can never be guaranteed.
It seems to us both more realistic and interesting to take the claims distribution as bounded above so that
solvency could always in principle be achieved. An insurer always has a finite number of customers with an
upper bound on the loss under any contract.
68
RAY REES, HUGH GRAVELLE AND ACHIM WAMBACH
11. Notice that our assumption avoids the complications that arise because payouts are made as claims are made,
rather than at the end of the period as we assume. Without the assumption bankruptcy can occur during the
period, leaving some insureds who do not have an accident with no protection for the rest of the period and
some insureds will have had an accident but not had their claim processed.
12. Some risky assets may lead to a loss of more than the sum invested—for example, derivatives. In this case,
consumers need to know the portfolio composition as well as the total reserves.
13. Of course, it could be argued that this could also be left to “the market.” Private rating agencies would find
it profitable to perform this function, just as with quality assessment of other kinds of goods. In fact, already
in Germany since deregulation a number of “rating agencies” have set up business. Why be dogmatic? If it
appears that the informational function these agencies can fulfill makes a regulatory agency redundant, then
regulation should cease altogether.
14. A referee has suggested an interesting further justification for regulation as a substitute for the insurer’s
inability to commit to future portfolio composition when they write insurance contracts. When consumers are
aware of such lack of commitment, some Pareto-improving insurance contracts may not written.
References
BORCH, K. [1981]: “Is Regulation of Insurance Companies Necessary,” In Geld, Banken, Versicherungen, H.
Gŏppland, and R. Henn (Eds.), Königstein.
BRIYS, E. and VARENNE, F.D. [1994]: “Life Insurance in a Contingent Claim Framework: Pricing and Regulatory Implications,” Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 19(1), 53–72.
DOHERTY, N. and GARVEN, J. [1986]: “Price Regulation in Property/Liability Insurance: A Contingent Claims
Approach,” Journal of Finance, 41(5), 1031–1050.
DOHERTY, N. and SCHLESINGER, H. [1990]: “Rational Insurance Purchasing: Consideration of Contract
Nonperformance,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 105(1), 243–253.
EISEN, R., MÜLLER, W., and ZWEIFEL, P. [1993]: “Entrepreneurial Insurance: A New Paradigm for Deregulated Markets,” Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 3–56.
FINSINGER, J. [1983]: Versicherungsmärkte. Frankfurt/New York: Campus Verlag.
FINSINGER, J., HAMMOND, E., and TAPP, J. [1985]: Insurance: Competition or Regulation? London: Institute
for Fiscal Studies.
FINSINGER, J. and PAULY, M. [1984]: “Reserve Levels and Reserve Requirements for Profit Maximising
Insurance Firms,” In Risk and Capital, G. Bamberg and K. Spremann (Eds.), Berlin: Springer.
FINSINGER, J. and PAULY, M. (Eds.). [1986]: The Economics of Insurance Regulation. London: MacMillan.
HOHLFELD, K. [1996]: “Erste erfahrungen im Europäischen Binnenmarkt,” Versicherungswirtschaft, 11, 680–
682.
JOSKOW, P.J. [1973]: “Cartels, Competition and Regulation in the Property-Liability Industry,” Bell Journal of
Economics, 4(2), 375–427.
KONRATH, N. [1996]: “Solvency of Insurance Undertakings and Financial Groups,” Geneva Papers on Risk and
Insurance, 78, 22–35.
MACMINN, R.D. and WITT, R.C. [1987]: “A Financial Theory of the Insurance Firm Under Uncertainty and
Regulatory Constraints,” Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 12(42), 3–20.
MUNCH, P. and SMALLWOOD, D. [1981]: “Theory of Solvency Regulation in the Property and Casualty
Industry,” In Studies in Public Regulation, G. Fromm (Ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press, 119–180.
POLBORN, M. [1998]: “A Model of an Oligopoly in an Insurance Market,” Geneva Papers in Risk and Insurance
Theory, 23(1), 41–48.
SCHLESINGER, H. and SCHULENBURG, J.-M.G. [1991]: “Search Costs, Switching Costs and Product Heterogeneity in an Insurance Market,” Journal of Risk and Insurance, 58(1), 109–119.