Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
Title of publication ELS Article title Altruism – A Philosophical Analysis Article’s unique identifying number A23835 Authors’ names typed as for an index Clavien, Christine Chapuisat, Michel Authors’ full names Christine Clavien Michel Chapuisat Name of both authors’ institute Department of Ecology and Evolution, University of Lausanne City Lausanne Country Switzerland Altruism – A Philosophical Analysis Abstract Altruism is a malleable notion that is understood differently in various disciplines. The common denominator of most definitions of altruism is the idea of unidirectional helping behaviour. However, a closer examination reveals that the term altruism sometimes refers to the outcomes of a helping behaviour for the agent and its neighbours – i.e. reproductive altruism – and sometimes to what motivates the agent to help others – i.e. psychological altruism. Since these perspectives on altruism are crucially different, it is important to use a clear terminology to avoid confusion. In particular, we show that the notion of altruism used by biologists profoundly differs from the ones used by philosophers, psychologists and economists in cross-disciplinary debates about human altruism. Key words altruism, helping, kin selection, Hamilton’s rule, human altruism, motivation, proximate versus ultimate explanation, psychological altruism, reproductive altruism, weak altruism Key concepts Reproductive altruism refers to a behaviour that increases other organisms’ fitness and permanently decreases the actor’s own fitness It is important to distinguish reproductive altruism from cooperation, in which both partners gain direct fitness benefits Reproductive altruism decreases the direct fitness of the altruist and thus its persistence in the course of evolution requests an ultimate explanation Kin selection, the indirect transmission of genes through relatives, is the key process explaining the evolution and maintenance of reproductive altruism Psychological altruism refers to an other-directed motivation to help and increase others’ welfare independently of self-directed calculations Psychological altruism is a proximate mechanism; in contrast to reproductive altruism, it may confer direct fitness benefits To avoid misunderstandings, it is important to identify which form of altruism is at stake in interdisciplinary literature about human altruism Introduction When a single term covers different concepts in diverse disciplines and when scholars from these disciplines read each other’s papers, major confusions are to be expected. Mother Teresa’s self-abnegation for the sake of the poor of Calcutta, and the reproductive restraint of worker bees are obviously distinct phenomena, yet both are described as altruistic. Mother Teresa’s altruism refers to the common-sense use of the term – she is motivated by other-directed goals – whereas bees’ altruism refers to a technical term well-defined in biology and independent of any moral consideration. Hence, bees qualify for altruism, as does Mother Teresa, but the two forms of altruism are not equivalent. This paper provides the conceptual tools necessary for understanding and evaluating the original contribution of various research areas involved in the project of explaining the broad phenomenon of unidirectional helping behaviour. The first section deals with the way biologists define and explain altruism. The second section is an introduction to altruism as conceived in philosophy and the social sciences. The third section deals with the relationship one can build between these two main forms of altruism. The last section draws attention to the ambiguous use of the term altruism in recent anthropology and economics literature on human altruism. Altruism in Biology In biology, altruism is generally defined as a behaviour that increases other organisms’ fitness and permanently decreases the actor’s own fitness Frank 1998Grafen 1985West et al. 2007: . We label this form of altruism “reproductive altruism”. Fitness is defined as the number of an actor’s offspring that survive to adulthood Grafen 1984: 66Hamilton 1964: 1. In this acceptation, fitness is an absolute value – e.g. a meerkat with four offspring at the end of her life has a fitness of four. This value however, only makes sense when compared to the fitness of other individuals in the population – e.g. four offspring might be a great, medium or low reproductive achievement, depending on how many offspring meerkats usually have. Classical examples of “reproductive altruism” are found in the worker castes of eusocial insects such as termites, ants, some bees and some wasps. In these species, the workers are mostly sterile – their direct fitness is zero – and they raise the offspring of the queens and males Wilson 1971. Altruistic castes have been reported in several other invertebrates, including gall-making aphids and thrips, snapping shrimps and flatworms, as well as in two species of mole rats. Such permanently sterile castes should be seen as the endpoint of a continuum. Less pronounced forms of reproductive altruism and cooperation are widely distributed, from bacteria and amoebae to cooperatively breeding birds and mammals. See also: DOI: 10.1002/9780470015902.a0003670.pub2 (Eusociality and Cooperation). Reproductive altruism is an extreme form of helping behaviour, the evolution of which cannot be accounted for in terms of future reciprocity Trivers 1971 or individual reputation Zahavi 1975. It poses a challenge for evolutionary theorists because natural selection should favour traits increasing the reproduction of their bearers. Since altruistic behaviours are, by definition, detrimental with respect to survival and reproduction, their persistence in the course of evolution calls for a special explanation. See also: DOI: 10.1002/9780470015902.a0021910 (Theory of Cooperation) After several unsatisfying explanatory attempts Darwin 2007/1871Lorenz 2004/1963Wynne-Edwards 1962, William Hamilton 196419751970 provided a powerful explanation for reproductive altruism: kin selection theory. Hamilton generalised and formalised an idea already alluded to by Fisher 1958 and Haldane 1955. The latter famously said that he would jump into a river for two brothers or eight cousins quoted in Harman 2010: 82. The idea is that reproductive altruism can be favoured when the altruists help genetically related individuals, which carry identical copies of genes. In a gene-centred formulation, genes responsible for altruistic behaviour can spread in a population if the altruistic behaviour they induce is more likely to benefit organisms who possess copies of the same altruistic genes Frank 1998Grafen 1985Hamilton 1970Queller 1992West et al. 2011West et al. 2007. Such a situation typically occurs among close relatives, due to common ancestry. For example, altruists may preferentially help their parents, sisters or cousins, based on their ability to recognise close kin or simply because they live in spatial proximity. It is worth noting however, that common ancestry is only one way to increase the probability that the altruist and her recipient share the gene – or complex of genes – for altruism. Another way for altruists and recipients to share the altruism gene is the so called "green beard" effect, whereby a gene for altruism is responsible for a visible phenotype – a green beard or anything more realistic – that can be recognised by other altruists. If in addition, the tendency for altruism is coupled with a preference for helping those who share the visible phenotype, common ancestry is not needed for altruism to spread in the population. In the natural world, green beard cases have been reported Keller and Ross 1998 but they are rare because helping otherwise unrelated altruists is wasteful for all the genes of the organisms except for the altruistic gene; thus, any mutation that prevents this waste will be favoured by natural selection Dawkins 1979Maynard Smith 1976Okasha 2002. See also: DOI: 10.1002/9780470015902.a0003670.pub2 (Eusociality and Cooperation) & DOI: 10.1002/9780470015902.a0021910 (Theory of Cooperation) & DOI: 10.1002/9780470015902.a0006243 (Hamilton, William Donald) Hamilton formulated a simple rule delineating when reproductive altruism can evolve by kin selection: rb-c>0, where r is the coefficient of genetic relatedness between the altruistic actor and the recipient – which reflects the probability that both individuals carry the gene for altruism, compared to the population average Frank 1998 –, b the fitness benefit of the altruistic behaviour for the recipient and c the fitness cost of the altruistic behaviour for the actor. When the inequation is fulfilled, the altruist transmits more copies of his genes by helping his relative (rb) than by reproducing (c), and therefore reproductive altruism can evolve. In the literature, one can find an alternative way to model the evolution of altruism. The “group selection” approach Goodnight 1990Odling-Smee et al. 2003Sober and Wilson 1998Wade 1977Wilson 1975Wilson and Wilson 2008 considers groups as functional units and explicitly partitions selection into a between-group and a within-group component. In some circumstances, it might happen that an altruistic behaviour is so favourable at the group level that it compensates for the loss of individual fitness within groups. Interestingly, even if the two methods look at the same phenomenon from different perspectives Okasha 2010: 653, they rely on similar quantitative genetic approaches and yield fully compatible results Gardner 2008Lehmann et al. 2007. Using Price’s equation 1970, several authors have demonstrated mathematically that the change of frequency of an altruistic gene in a population can be equivalently expressed either in terms of Hamilton’s rule or in terms of a partition of selection within and between groups. In particular, the two approaches concur in the view that true reproductive altruism, with a permanent cost to the actor, will only evolve in groups of genetically related individuals Frank 19981997Gardner et al. 2007Lehmann and Keller 2006Queller 1992. See also: DOI: 10.1038/npg.els.0001712 (Selection: Units and Levels) & DOI: 10.1038/npg.els.0005447 (Group Selection) In practical cases, it might be difficult to distinguish true reproductive altruism from cooperation. Indeed, the long-term individual costs and benefits of a given behaviour are often difficult to measure. Many helping behaviours that might seem altruistic at first may provide delayed direct fitness benefit. For example vampire bats have been observed to feed their offspring as well as other individuals of their group Wilkinson 1984. Under close observation, it turns out that the latter pay back when they return from a successful hunting night. This behaviour is more correctly described as cooperative food sharing. Many behaviours might also be altruistic in some circumstances and cooperative in others. Finally, apparently altruistic behaviours may in fact confer delayed direct fitness benefits through reputation or prestige. Helping behaviours may indeed increase the individual reputation and be honest signals, e.g. for being a good mate or a reliable partner for future cooperative interactions Zahavi 1975. Reproductive altruism should not be confused with two other notions found in the literature: “reciprocal altruism” and “weak altruism”. In an important and influential paper, Trivers 1971 discussed reciprocal behaviour of the form “help your neighbour as long as she helps you back”. He labelled this behaviour “reciprocal altruism”, while making it clear that it provides a long term direct benefit for its bearer, and as such does not exemplify altruism in the classical Hamiltonian sense defined above. Reciprocal altruism is a form of cooperative behaviour. One illustration is the vampire bats food sharing example mentioned above. Proponents of group selection theory often use a slightly different notion of altruism, labelled “weak altruism” Wilson 1977. Weak altruism is not an absolute but a relative value that compares the actor’s number of offspring to that of the recipients. To qualify as weakly altruistic, a helping individual must be less fit than the group members who do not help, but benefit from help. Hence, this definition does not imply that altruistic individuals reduce their direct fitness Foster 2008. To illustrate this point, consider the case of an individual who builds a protective wall around a common nest. The wall is costly to build but this cost is compensated by the direct benefits it provides to the individual – say protection against floods. In this case, the wall-building behaviour is not “reproductively altruistic” because the individual cost is compensated by the benefit, but is “weakly altruistic” – because the other nest members benefit from the wall without having to build it. See also: DOI: 10.1038/npg.els.0001712 (Selection: Units and Levels) & DOI: 10.1038/npg.els.0005447 (Group Selection). These conceptual distinctions allow us to solve some apparent contradictions among authors. For example, in two famous papers, D.S. Wilson 1975 and Hamilton 1975 built very similar models for the evolution of a trait that Wilson described as altruistic and Hamilton as non-altruistic. In fact, Wilson had “weak altruism” in mind whereas Hamilton referred to reproductive altruism. These conceptual distinctions are also important to avoid cross-disciplinary misunderstandings. In the humanities and social sciences, scholars are often unaware of the various forms of altruism used in biology. They frequently mistake reproductive altruism for reciprocal altruism or psychological altruism. After having heard of Trivers’ theory, they infer that biologists deny the possibility of any form of altruism that would not be individually advantageous. This confusion is usually coupled with misunderstandings about the level of selection. Indeed, Hamilton’s explanation of the conditions under which genes for altruism can be successfully passed on from one generation to the next has been widely popularised by Richard Dawkins 1976 in the terminology of the “selfish gene”. This metaphorical use of the term “selfish” for genes simply emphasizes the fact that genes are the basic unit of selection. Dawkins made it clear that “selfishness” at the genetic level did not imply selfishness at the social, individual or psychological levels. However, this distinction is widely overlooked by scholars who are not trained in population genetics. Consequently, they erroneously think Gintis et al. 2005Sahlins 1976 that Hamilton and his followers, by adopting the gene-centred point of view that is now standard in evolutionary biology, deny the existence of any form of altruism. Reproductive versus Psychological Altruism Evolutionary theorists define altruism in terms of its consequences on the fitness of individuals. This focus on the outcomes of a behaviour, however, does not correspond to the common-sense use of the term altruism, which is more concerned with what motivates people to help. If we were to learn that Mother Teresa became a nun and served the poor on the streets of Calcutta only because she feared going to Hell, we would hardly describe her as an altruist. Conversely, a father might ruin himself to finance the legal studies of his son with the genuine hope of providing him with bright career opportunities and a happy future life, but if his son’s secret dream is to become a ballet dancer, the father’s altruistic motive might fail to achieve the purported goal. Despite the father’s erroneous judgement about what will make his son happy, common sense will appreciate the altruistic nature of his motivation, as long as it is not tainted by self-directed calculations. An important and longstanding cross-disciplinary debate is based on this common-sense understanding of altruism. The debate is about deciding whether humans are capable of “psychological altruism”, which, as the psychologist Daniel Batson describes it, is “a motivational state with the ultimate goal of increasing another’s welfare”. Under this acceptation, altruism refers to an “energy, a force within the individual” which drives the person to achieve an other-directed goal Batson 1991: 6. Psychological altruism is mainly discussed in philosophical circles Butler 1991/1726Hobbes 2005/1651Hutcheson 2004/1725Mandeville 1997/1714-1728Rand 1964Stich et al. 2010 as well as in the social sciences more generally, e.g. psychology Batson 1991Cialdini et al. 1987 and sociology Comte 1851-1854Durkheim 1897. In order to avoid confusion, it is important to understand that reproductive altruism and psychological altruism are two distinct notions Sober and Wilson 1998. Worker bees are paradigmatic examples of the former, but their limited cognitive abilities do not permit them to conceptualise others’ welfare. Thus, it does not even make sense to ask the question whether they are psychological altruists. Conversely, mothers caring for their offspring are not reproductive altruists although they might be genuinely motivated to promote their children’s well-being. The Relationship between Reproductive and Psychological Altruism The distinction between ultimate and proximate explanations is central to evolutionary biology Mayr 1961Tinbergen 1963West et al. 2007. Ultimate explanations refer to the adaptive value and fitness consequences of a trait; they answer the question of why a trait has evolved. Proximate explanations provide details about the causal mechanisms responsible for a trait. These explanations are distinct but complementary. Biologists rely on both to fully comprehend a phenomenon. For example, kin selection elucidates why soldier ants defend their colony against intruders threatening their mother and relatives – an ultimate explanation – whereas other studies provide details on how these soldiers detect intruders thanks to their sensitivity to chemical cues – a proximate explanation. The same distinction applies to the two ways of conceiving altruism presented in the previous sections. The Hamiltonian or group selection explanations for the evolution of reproductive altruism are ultimate explanations for this behaviour. In contrast, psychological altruism refers to motivations that are causal mechanisms prompting individuals to take care of others’ welfare; this psychological phenomenon provides a proximate explanation for the broad phenomenon of unidirectional helping behaviour. It should be clear, however, that the demonstration of an individual’s altruistic motivation – proximate explanation – does not indicate that this individual is reproductively altruistic. For example, the individual may care for his own children. Conversely, an ultimate evolutionary explanation of reproductive altruism provides no direct insight into what motivates individuals to help others – for example, we don’t know what worker bees think. There are however, interesting indirect links between the two types of altruism. If a form of reproductive altruism has been selected in humans, there are good reasons to think that some proximate mechanisms prompting this fitness-costly behaviour have co-evolved. Such proximate mechanisms might be caring and empathic emotions, which may qualify as psychological altruism Clavien forthcomingSober and Wilson 1998. More generally, mechanisms based on psychological altruism such as caring and empathic emotions are effective ways to make individuals behave altruistically or cooperatively, depending on whether or not these behaviours have long term direct fitness costs to the individual. Thus, in highly cooperative species in which individuals are endowed with developed cognitive and emotional capacities – such as humans and probably apes – various forms of psychological altruism are likely to be selected Clavien 2010Kitcher 2011. Other Forms of Human Altruism More recently, the notion of altruism has been heavily used in the emerging fields of experimental economics and evolutionary anthropology de Quervain et al. 2004Fehr and Fischbacher 20032004Fehr and Gächter 2002Gintis et al. 2005Henrich et al. 2005: 812. This literature provides empirical data – gathered in laboratory experiments – that highlight humans’ cooperative and fair behaviour. In these studies, the meaning of the term altruism is variable and often ambiguous Clavien and Chapuisat submittedWest et al. 2011. Sometimes, altruism refers to a particular type of behaviour that can be observed in socio-economic contexts, much in the same spirit as the biological use of the term. At other times, altruism refers to people’s willingness to cooperate and punish shirkers, which is close to the common-sense use of the term. However, a closer look at the literature shows that the authors often use more fuzzy and less restrictive notions of altruism than the ones presented above more on this topic in Clavien and Chapuisat submitted. Their outcome-oriented notion is less restrictive than reproductive altruism because they count any type of individual success – rather than exclusively reproductive success – and show little interest in the broad evolutionary impact of the behaviours they observe in laboratory. Their motivation-oriented notion refers to preferences, as defined in neo-classical economic theory, which are weak indicators of people’s actual motivations. Overall, the results obtained in these experiments are important for understanding cooperation, but not reproductive altruism. Conclusion We have specified two main understandings of altruism. The first concentrates on the fitness outcomes of a behaviour, whereas the second focuses on the individual motivation underlying an action. These two notions of altruism are distinct but complementary ways of shedding light on unidirectional helping behaviour. We have also hinted at the fact that other concepts of altruism pervade current literature on human altruism. We conclude that a true interdisciplinary understanding of human altruism crucially relies on distinguishing the multifarious notions covered by the term altruism in diverse disciplines. References Further Reading list Clavien C (forthcoming) Altruistic emotional motivation: An argument in favour of psychological altruism. In: Plaisance K and Reydon T (eds) Philosophy of Behavioral Biology. Boston Studies in Philosophy of Science, Springer Press. Clavien C and Chapuisat M (submitted) Altruism across disciplines: one word, multiple meanings. Foster KR (2008) Altruism. In: Jorgensen SE and Fath B (eds) Encyclopedia of Ecology. 154-159. Keller L and Chapuisat M (1999) Cooperation among Selfish Individuals in Insect Societies. BioScience 49(11): 899-909. Lehmann L, Bargum K and Reuter M (2006) An evolutionary analysis of the relationship between spite and altruism. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 19(5): 1507-1516. Lehmann L and Keller L (2006) The evolution of cooperation and altruism; a general framework and a classification of models. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 19(5): 1365-1376. Stich SP, Doris JM and Roedder E (2010) Altruism. In: Doris JM (ed) The moral psychology handbook. 147-205. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Trivers RL (1971) The evolution of reciprocal altruism. The Quarterly Review of Biology 46(1): 35-57. West SA, El Mouden C and Gardner A (2011) Sixteen common misconceptions about the evolution of cooperation in humans. Evolution and Human Behavior: 231-262. West SA, Griffin A and Gardner A (2007) Social semantics: Altruism, cooperation, mutualism, strong reciprocity and group selection. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 20: 415-432. Glossary Fitness: A measure of the survival and reproductive success of an entity. Hamilton’s rule: rb-c>0, where r measures the genetic relatedness between the altruistic actor and the recipient, b the fitness benefit of the altruistic behaviour for the recipient and c the fitness cost of the altruistic behaviour for the actor. This rule is at the core of Hamilton’s kin selection theory. Group selection: A theory that partitions the effect of natural selection at the individual and the group levels. It is often used to explain the evolution of altruistic traits. Green beard effect: A term coined by Richard Dawkins in The Selfish Gene. It refers to the idea that one gene – or a group of genes – can bring about distinct phenotypes: a visible trait – e.g. a green beard – and a propensity to behave altruistically towards individuals who possess this observable trait. This effect illustrates the fact that Hamilton’s kin selection theory can explain the evolution of altruism in systems that are not composed of relatives due to common ancestry. Kin selection: Selection on genes for social actions influencing the fitness of individuals that are genetically related. In effect, the altruist indirectly favours the transmission of copies of his genes carried by genetically related individuals. Proximate explanations: As opposed to ultimate explanations, proximate explanations provide details about the causal mechanisms responsible for a behaviour. Psychological altruism: Motivations prompting actions directed towards the goal of improving others' interests and welfare. Reciprocal altruism: A behaviour that temporarily reduces the actor’s fitness while increasing another organism's fitness, with the expectation that this short term investment will be compensated by help in return in the course of future reciprocal interactions. Reproductive altruism: A behaviour that increases other organisms’ fitness and permanently decreases the actor’s own fitness. Ultimate explanations: As opposed to proximate explanations, ultimate explanations refer to the adaptive value and fitness consequences of a trait; they answer the question of why a trait has evolved. Weak altruism: A behaviour is weakly altruistic if it increases the fitness of other group members at the expanse of the actor. In contrast with reproductive altruism, weak altruism does not necessarily imply a decrease in absolute fitness for the actor. 10