Philos Stud
DOI 10.1007/s11098-017-0986-2
Slurs, roles and power
Mihaela Popa-Wyatt1
•
Jeremy L. Wyatt2
The Author(s) 2017. This article is an open access publication
Abstract Slurring is a kind of hate speech that has various effects. Notable among
these is variable offence. Slurs vary in offence across words, uses, and the reactions
of audience members. Patterns of offence aren’t adequately explained by current
theories. We propose an explanation based on the unjust power imbalance that a slur
seeks to achieve. Our starting observation is that in discourse participants take on
discourse roles. These are typically inherited from social roles, but only exist during
a discourse. A slurring act is a speech-act that alters the discourse roles of the target
and speaker. By assigning discourse roles the speaker unjustly changes the power
balance in the dialogue. This has a variety of effects on the target and audience. We
show how these notions explain all three types of offence variation. We also briefly
sketch how a role and power theory can help explain silencing and appropriation.
Explanatory power lies in the fact that offence is correlated with the perceived
unjustness of the power imbalance created.
Keywords Slurs Speech acts Conversational score Power Discourse and
social roles Silencing Appropriation
& Mihaela Popa-Wyatt
mihaela.popawyatt@gmail.com
Jeremy L. Wyatt
jeremy.l.wyatt@gmail.com
1
Department of Philosophy, University of Birmingham, Birmingham B15 2TT, UK
2
School of Computer Science, University of Birmingham, Birmingham B15 2TT, UK
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
1 Introduction
Slurring is a kind of hate speech that has special properties. There are thousands of
terms that are identified as slurs,1 including those based on race (‘‘nigger’’,
‘‘chink’’), gender (‘‘bitch’’), nationality (‘‘limey’’, ‘‘boche’’), and sexuality (‘‘faggot’’, ‘‘dyke’’)’’. Slurs can harm and degrade their targets, making them feel
humiliated, dehumanised, disempowered, and silenced. Slurs may also offend nontargets, often making them feel complicit, while meeting with approval from bigots.
A slur can also be reclaimed by the target group, so as to express solidarity and
pride. Slurs are interesting precisely because of this unusually rich set of effects.
Slurs vary in the strength of these effects. In particular, there is considerable
variation in the degree of offence caused. Offence varies across different slur words,
across different uses of the same slur word, and across the reactions of different
audience members. Current theories struggle to parsimoniously explain the resulting
patterns of offence. The contribution of this paper is to remedy this. A secondary
contribution is to show that the same mechanism also explains silencing and
appropriation.
The core of the explanation is that many slurring utterances are not just about
expressing contempt, but are also oppressive speech.2 The offence caused by a
slurring utterance varies with the degree of oppression that it plausibly seeks to
achieve. Slurs vary in their ability to be so used, from the most potent, such as
‘‘nigger’’ and ‘‘faggot’’, to the milder, such as ‘‘limey’’ and ‘‘yankee’’.3 All are
identified as slurs, and all can be used to convey contempt, which causes a baseline
offence. Additional offence is caused by those slurs used to oppress. We refer to any
slur that can plausibly be used to cause some degree of oppression as an oppressive
slur.
Oppression can be explained as unjust power using the power-over conception of
power (Weber 1978; Dahl 1957). According to this theory, power is the extent to
which a person A can affect a person B contrary to B’s interests (Lukes 1974). Thus,
A’s power over B becomes oppressive if it is used to cause harm to B. The goal of
oppressive slurring is to achieve and maintain unjust power over the target. A
slurring use draws and builds on historical and/or contemporary oppression of the
target group.4
1
The racial slur database contains more than 2500 racial slur terms, including derivatives. Jeshion
(forthcoming) estimates that 560 of these refer to people of African descent, 53 to those of Chinese
descent, and that higher numbers indicate stronger community backing and impact on the target group.
2
Our account relates to accounts of oppressive speech and discursive injustice by Matsuda et al. (1993),
Hornsby (1995), Tirrell (1999, 2012), McGowan (2009, 2012), Maitra (2012), Kukla (2014), Langton
(2012), and accounts relating slurs to ideology (Stanley 2015; Swanson ms.), and to analyses of
subordination and silencing of women through pornography (Langton 1993; Maitra 2009, among others).
3
Clearly, it is the case that there is a significant grey area, the transition from non-oppressive to
oppressive slurs is not sharp.
4
The oppression drawn upon is structural—(Young 1990; Cudd 2006; Haslanger 2012; Anderson 2012).
Once oppression has become institutionalised through laws, customs, and practices, unjust harm can
occur, whether or not the individuals maintaining those practices have oppressive intentions.
123
Slurs, roles and power
Most authors put contempt expression and derogation at the heart of what slurs
are used for.5 Slurs are used for this, but contempt alone can’t explain the greater
offence, nor the oppressive effects, of some slurring acts. Adding unjust power
explains phenomena that contempt can’t. Power is not, however, enough on its own.
Slurring uses are rich enough in their effects that a single mechanism cannot
account for all their properties. We should seek a set of relatively simple, interlinked
mechanisms, that work together to explain the various effects of slurring utterances.
We will argue that oppressive slurs achieve oppression via an act of role
assignment.6 The speaker takes the dominant role, while the target is assigned the
subordinate role. The notion of role assignment is best explained using speech-act
theory. Much of the paper shall be concerned with setting up the machinery we need
to support this. We suggest that the speech-act is best thought of as an exercitive
assignment of a discourse role. Discourse roles determine the status and rules that
govern the dialogue behaviour of participants. Thus, an exercitive assignment of a
discourse role is a meta-move that changes the rules governing other dialogue
moves.
To see the need for this approach, we must first understand variable offence and
how current theories fare regarding it (Sect. 2). We shall then detail our theory of
slurs as oppressive speech acts that alter power via discourse role assignment
(Sects. 3–6), and show how this theory’s predictions fit the data on variable offence,
silencing, and appropriation (Sects. 7–8).
2 Variable offence
We must first mention a key assumption. In some works (e.g. Hom 2008, 2012) the
focus in describing variability is on the derogative content of the word. Hom
distinguishes derogation and offence as follows: ‘‘offence is a psychological result
on the part of the discourse participants, and is a function of their beliefs and values
… derogation is an objective feature of the semantic contents of pejorative terms’’
(Hom 2012: 397). We would suggest that, to avoid committing too early to a
semantic or pragmatic solution, we should relax Hom’s statement, and think about
derogation simply in terms of it being part of speaker meaning. So, derogation is
part of the speaker’s communicative intentions, while offence is an achieved effect
on the audience members, determined in part by their beliefs and values.
As noted, slurs vary in the degree of offence they cause. As Jeshion (2013b: 309)
says, ‘‘‘nigger’ is said to be more offensive than ‘chink’, as well as ‘spook’ and
‘jigaboo’, terms used for the same socially relevant group. ‘Kike’, ‘yid’, and
‘hymie’ are said to differ in their offensive intensity.’’ Thus, offence doesn’t just
vary across different slur words for different groups (inter-group variation), but also
across different slur words for the same group (intra-group variation). We refer to
5
Hornsby (2001), Saka (2007), Hom (2008), Richard (2008), Jeshion (2013b), Camp (2013), among
others.
6
Note that we are not claiming that words are only slurs if they create an unjust power imbalance. Slurs
include words that are not necessarily oppressive.
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
these collectively as variability type-1 (VT1) or word-variation. This is the type of
variable derogation which previous authors have tried to explain.
Offence doesn’t just vary across different slur words. It also varies across
different uses of the same slur word, depending on speaker and context. We refer to
this as variability type-2 (VT2) or use-variation. Consider the following examples
(C marks contemptuous intonation, and NC non-contemptuous, friendly tone of
voice):
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
White person to African-American person: ‘‘You are one useless niggerC.’’
White person to African-American person: ‘‘Yo, my nigger NC, missed you.’’
African-American person to African-American person: ‘‘You are one useless
niggerC.’’
African-American person to African-American person: ‘‘Yo, my niggerNC,
missed you.’’
What offence would we expect these utterances to cause? In considering this we must,
since offence is a psychological property of the hearer, carefully define the meaning of
statements such as ‘‘slur X is more offensive than slur Y’’. Since offence is a
psychological and thus subjective property, such statements can only be meaningfully
defined with respect to a particular individual. However, by taking idealised
individuals, e.g. a non-racist, non-homophobic, non-sexist individual, we can make
statements about the ranking of offensiveness of slurring utterances taken by that
person. Thus, we can make statements such as ‘slurring utterance X is more offensive
than utterance Y to an idealised person A, where A is a non-racist, non-homophobic,
non-sexist individual’. This is how we define statements about the relative offence of
particular slurs in this paper. However, as a short-hand we will simply write statements
of the form ‘‘utterance/use X is more offensive than utterance/use Y’’, and the reader
should simply fill in the caveat regarding the ranking of subjective offence taken by the
idealised non-bigoted individual defined above.
Having taken this into account, let us consider the utterances (1)–(4). First,
consider contemptuous versus non-contemptuous uses. The contemptuous uses (1)
and (3) are more offensive than the non-contemptuous uses (2) and (4). Now
consider the in-group versus out-group uses. The out-group contemptuous use (1) is
widely considered more offensive than the identical in-group use (3), and the same
is true of the corresponding pair of non-contemptuous uses (2) and (4).
The issue is to explain why, if the speakers of (2) and (4) don’t intend to convey
contempt, there is a difference in the offence we would expect. The same can be
said for (1) and (3), where contempt is intended, but where (1) is clearly more
offensive. We can make many variations to the context in which these utterances are
made and the relative offence within each pair will remain the same.7 For example,
suppose that the speaker and target of utterances (2) and (4) are close friends, or that
alternatively they are strangers. In either case (2) will be more offensive than (4).
Now suppose we adjust (1) and (3) so that they are not uttered with a contemptuous
7
Other contextual factors might be: speaker’s accent, familiarity between speaker and hearer, and
whether they belong to a close-knit social or cultural group. We are not making an empirical claim, but
merely delineating dimensions of use-variability.
123
Slurs, roles and power
tone, (1) is still more offensive than (3). This shows that the degree of contempt or
derogation conveyed by a slur word cannot be the only ingredient in variable
offence. Pragmatic factors, such as the speaker’s group-membership, are also
important.8
Finally, there is a third type of variability, not previously identified in the
literature. This is that the same slurring utterance may cause different levels of
offence to different audience members. Imagine a slurring utterance in front of an
audience who vary from the highly bigoted to non-bigoted. It is reasonable to
assume that different audience members will be offended to different degrees. We
refer to this offence variation as variability type-3 (VT3) or audience-variation.
3 Variable offence and current theories
How shall we explain VT1, VT2, and VT3? There are numerous accounts of slurs.
These are mostly concerned with whether slurs’ derogatory power is a matter of
meaning, and on which side of the semantics/pragmatics divide to locate that
meaning.9 As variable offence is our focus, we will review accounts that directly
address this issue. Our strategy is to argue that none has sufficient resources alone to
adequately explain all three varieties of variable offence. We offer a theory that
provides sufficient pragmatic resources to fill the explanatory gap required.
3.1 The truth-conditional semantic approach
Starting with semantic theories, we take Hom (2008) as representative. Take VT1,
there are two types of variation falling within VT1: intra-group and inter-group.
Inter-group variation is well explained by Hom. Hom talks not directly of variable
offence, but of variable derogation. On that account, slurs express that the target
‘‘ought to be subject to [deontic propositions about discrimination] p1 þ þ pn
because of being d1 þ þ dn ’’ all because of being part of such-and-such-group’’
(2008: 431). As Hom notes, ‘‘the d1 þ þ dn are the negative properties derived
from the racist ideology.’’ These form a negative stereotype of the target group.
Hom also makes clear that ‘‘the derogatory force … is directly proportional to the
content of the property it expresses, which is in turn directly proportional to the
turpitude and scope of the supporting racist institution’’ (2008: 432). While Hom
and May (2013: 10) later argue that it is not the meaning itself that is offensive—
offence being a psychological property—it is still clear that they view
8
These offence variations should be experimentally quantified.
9
Aside from Anderson and Lepore (2013a), most authors provide an account of the meaning of slur
words. Some treat meaning as propositional content—whether as part of truth-conditional semantics
(Hom 2008) or non-truth-conditional semantics (Saka 2007). Other treatments are as editorial comment
(Bach forthcoming), presupposition (Schlenker 2007), and conventional implicature (Williamson 2009;
Whiting 2013; Lycan 2015). Others take the meaning to be non-propositional and non-truth-conditional,
differing on the fundamental ingredient: e.g. contempt expression (Barker 2000; Copp 2001; Richard
2008; Jeshion 2013b), derogatory perspectives (Camp 2013), register (Predelli 2013), expressive meaning
(Potts 2007), identity-affiliation (Nunberg forthcoming), contrastive-choice (Bolinger 2015).
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
‘‘offensiveness as a property of utterances’’ and admit that ‘‘word meaning could be
part of an explanation of offensive uses of these words’’. On this ground, it is
reasonable to suggest that word meaning, insofar as it does explain inter-group
offence variation, relies on an increase in derogatory force to cause greater offence.
Thus, in simplified terms, offence can vary with word meaning because of
semantic encoding of more or less negative stereotypes for different groups. The
pejorative content is a function of the stereotype and the associated racist beliefs and
ideology about how the target ought therefore to be treated. Thus, ‘‘nigger’’ and
‘‘chink’’ are offensive to different degrees because the racist stereotypes predicated
are more negative for one group than the other. Note that this means that the
differences in offence ultimately rely on different institutions of racism: ‘‘variation
in derogatory force associated with different epithets is a result of having different
racist institutions causally support their predicative content’’ (Hom 2008: 433).
Because of this reliance, Hom’s explanation cannot account so easily for
variation across different slurs for the same group (intra-group variation). For
example, ‘‘nigger’’ is considered more offensive than ‘‘spook’’. But for Hom, in
order for it to be so, it must be the case that the stereotypes encoded by the slur rest
on two different racist ideologies. This is implausible, because it means that there
must be a different institution of racism for ‘‘nigger’’ to that for ‘‘spook’’, as argued
by Anderson and Lepore (2013a: 361). So Hom has mixed success in explaining
VT1.
VT2 is a bigger limitation for semantic theories. This is because if the stereotype
is encoded semantically, and as far as semantics is able to explain offence, then the
offence caused should be the same, whoever says it. This isn’t the case. Take the
examples (1)–(4). We saw that variations in speaker caused offence to vary. Then
how is the semantic theorist to explain VT2?
Hom appeals to the idea that slurs can have more than one meaning. So, for
example, to enable appropriated in-group uses they may acquire an additional, nonderogatory meaning. For example, consider the word ‘‘queer’’. It has two meanings:
one derogatory, one not. However, this fails to explain two things. First, why is it
the case that only in-group members can access one of these meanings? Having
meanings that only some language users can access seems odd. Second, what
happens during the process of appropriation? During this process bigots still used
the term ‘‘queer’’ contemptuously, and this contemptuous use can continue even
once reclamation is complete. But if derogation resides in semantic meaning, and
not pragmatic effects, then how can Hom explain that ‘‘queer’’ can be used both
derogatorily and non-derogatorily during the reclamation process? Presumably
during reclamation, ‘‘queer’’ has not yet acquired a non-derogatory meaning, and
thus the word has only one, derogatory, meaning.
To explain this, Hom could argue that for in-group uses—prior to reclaim—the
non-derogatory meaning is recovered via conversational implicature. The reasoning
might go something like this: ‘‘the speaker has just called me a queer, but the
speaker is also gay, and he is not speaking with a contemptuous tone, so perhaps he
is applying it in some positive way.’’ However, conversational implicature falls
down in explaining why a friendly out-group speaker still causes offence. The target
would correctly infer that the friendly tone means that the out-group speaker didn’t
123
Slurs, roles and power
intend to derogate them. But they are still offended, so the group-membership of the
speaker has trumped their intention. Thus, the semantic account can’t be saved by
conversational implicature.
What about VT3? Offence is at least partly caused by the stereotype, and this
varies with the racist institution. Thus, Hom can argue that an audience member’s
offence will vary inversely with their degree of subscription to this racist institution.
However, if the stereotype is semantically encoded, we should expect that
competent users know its precise details as part of their semantic understanding.
This is implausible: lots of users are equally offended without having a common,
precisely similar stereotype in their semantic understanding (Jeshion 2013a).
However, following Burge (1986), Hom could deny this, holding that competent
users can be partially ignorant or mistaken about the precise nature of these
stereotypes and norms. Thus, listeners can be offended while only knowing partial
details of the stereotype, or the detailed history that underpins it. As long as the
hearer’s partial understanding is good enough for them to understand sufficiently
well some of the difference between the extent to which different words encode a
subscription to a racist stereotype, then VT3 can be accounted for semantically.
In at least two cases not all of the offence variation can be explained by
semantics alone. If we want to follow Hom, we must at least admit that there are
gaps that semantics can’t fill alone. These must be filled pragmatically.
3.2 The expressivist approach
An alternative to a truth-conditional semantics is an expressivist semantics. Here,
we take Jeshion’s (2013a, b, forthcoming) account as representative. In expressivist
theories the main function of a slur is to conventionally express contempt for the
target. For Jeshion, this contempt expression is part of semantics.10 Critically, for
the topic of this paper, she maintains that this semantic expression of contempt is
uniform across all slurs, in that a common core attitude is expressed and there is no
semantic ‘‘intensity marker’’ attached to a slur to indicate variation in contempt.
Thus, semantics cannot explain variable offence as being caused by variable
contempt. Critics (e.g. Hom 2008) claim that this makes it impossible for
expressivism to explain variable offence, and thus reject it.
There are two possible responses to this. First, is it possible to have an
expressivist semantics that allows contempt expression to vary across terms? On
such an account, contempt would have a semantic intensity marker, and so ‘‘nigger’’
would be more offensive than ‘‘spook’’ because it expresses a greater degree of
contempt.11 This is tempting, but there is a problem. If this were the case, we would
expect the degree of offence to follow from the degree of contempt a word is able to
convey. But it does not. For example, there are many words that slur the rich and
powerful, such as ‘‘toff’’, ‘‘Lord Snooty’’, ‘‘nob’’, ‘‘suit’’, ‘‘the one percent’’ and
10
This does not mean that the speaker is asserting that she has contempt for the target, on account of
their being part of the target group.
11
This might be implemented by applying Potts’ (2007) model of ‘‘expressive indices’’; see Popa-Wyatt
(2016).
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
‘‘Hooray Henry’’, that all convey considerable contempt. Yet these are socially
acceptable. Degree of contempt cannot therefore be the right answer. We have to
explain why words that convey equal contempt are not equally offensive.
As Jeshion correctly points out, the answer lies in pragmatics (2013b). She
suggests the Derogatory Variation-Utterance thesis: ‘‘utterances of different slurring
terms engender different degrees of intensity of offensiveness’’ (2013b: 320). She
then suggests several different pragmatic (perlocutionary) effects that could account
for derogatory variation. These are: the pragmatic (rather than semantic) activation
of stereotypes (2013b: 321), the compounding effect of a slur on the history of
oppression (Saka 2007: 148; Jeshion 2013b: 322), and the variable offence caused
by breaking prohibitions of varying strength (2013b: 323). Thus, different pragmatic
resources could be used to account for VT1 (e.g. history of oppression evoked by
the word and group stereotypes), VT2 (e.g. varying levels of taboo for different
uses), and VT3 (e.g. individual variations across audience members of the
pragmatics underpinning VT1 and VT2). This is reasonable, but then there isn’t just
one pragmatic mechanism that covers all the relevant dimensions of variability;
rather, distinct mechanisms account for each kind of variability. We should prefer a
more compact explanation.
3.3 The non-content approach
So far we have dealt with content theories. Do non-content theories do better at
covering all cases of variable offence? The leading contender is prohibitionism
(Anderson and Lepore 2013a, b). This starts with the observation that slurs are still
offensive when they occur in belief and speech reports, such as:
(5)
Eric said that a bitch ran for President of the United States in 2008.
Anderson and Lepore claim that this doesn’t automatically capture the offence of
Eric’s utterance, but that the reporter will certainly offend. They argue that since
content-based accounts predict that slurs should not offend when so embedded, and
that since they do, then content theories must be wrong.12 If the intuition about the
data’s pattern of offence is correct, this is compelling. Prohibitionism is their
alternative. It says that slur words are offensive simply because they are prohibited
(taboo).
How well does prohibitionism match variable offence phenomena? It tries to
accommodate VT1 by saying that there is a correlation between offence variation
across slur words and variation in their degree of taboo. It tries to accommodate
VT2 by saying that although slurs are taboo, the taboo can be suspended depending
on the context or speaker. So, for example, in-group uses come with a ‘‘defeasible
escape clause’’ (2013a: 42). Finally, although Anderson and Lepore do consider
this, VT3 could also be accounted for by saying that different audience members
have different levels of individual taboo. Prohibitionism is flexible, many additional
12
They make other arguments, which we have no space to describe, but this is a sufficient example to see
their general strategy.
123
Slurs, roles and power
clauses about taboo suspension or reduction can be created to fit the data. Thus, we
could create rules that non-contemptuous uses are less taboo than weapon uses; ingroup uses are taboo-free; and mentioning, rather than using, may (or may not) be
taboo, depending on who mentions the slur, their company, and the context (e.g.
legal, academic, political).
So, if taboo can be made to fit the data what’s wrong with this explanation?
Taboo lacks explanatory power. The advert for prohibitionism is its simplicity. This
is deceptive. Consider all the various defeasible escape clauses that are required to
rank offensiveness across our three types of variability. In examples (1)–(4) we saw
that in-group uses will require an escape clause. So, even if a white and black person
are close friends, use of ‘‘nigger’’ may still offend. But consider further cases. It
may not offend, even if they are not friends, if the target permits its use.
Furthermore, African-Americans who are only passingly familiar may use the term
to refer to each other without offence. But, in another case, reported in the press
(Gabbatt 2013), an African-American woman was offended, and successfully sued
her African-American manager for calling her ‘‘nigger’’. A complex web of
exceptions and non-exceptions must be written to cover all these cases. Prohibitionism is like Ptolemy’s earth-centric model of the solar system: the basic idea is
simple, but to fit the data the exception clauses must rise in number like epicycles.
Prohibitionism isn’t parsimonious. It merely echoes the facts of variable offence
rather than explaining them compactly. We should like a compact explanation of
why words are differentially taboo.
Another way of saying this is to pose the question: if offence variability is
explained by the degree of prohibition, what explains that degree of prohibition?
Anderson and Lepore try to get round precisely this objection, that ‘‘prohibitionism
gets it backwards; it is the offence that explains the prohibition, not the other way
round’’ (2013b: 354). They counter by pointing out that there are examples where
prohibition precedes offence, for example blasphemy. But, as they recognise, this
fact alone doesn’t compel, we must establish why this is the case for slurs. As a
possible answer, they say ‘‘it might be that groups prohibit names not explicitly
adopted by them, for calling a group by a name that its members have not chosen
may be viewed as an attempt to usurp their authority to choose’’ (2013b: 355). This
is not compelling. If this were the case surely all slurs would be equally offensive,
since all would violate the same prohibition. Their final improvement is to note the
effect of subordination: ‘‘in situations where one group is in a subordinate position
to another, uses of an expression by the dominant group to refer to the subordinate
group can provoke offence’’ (2013b: 355). This is insightful, but it puts the crack in
the dam. The difficulty is that once we have admitted, as we must, that the
prohibition arises from subordination we are better to turn to subordination as the
core explanation.
Prohibitionism is unsatisfying in another way. It is silent on why slurs have
different effects on audience members and targets than other pejoratives. This
leaves it impoverished. What is interesting about slurs is all the other effects they
have. They silence, dehumanise, assault, and oppress. On these effects prohibitionism is mute. Thus, it might be a part of a hybrid theory, but it cannot be the core.
A satisfactory theory of slurs must explain these other properties. This leads us to
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
our central question: does a parsimonious, pragmatic account of offence variation
exist? The answer to this question is yes. It is based on a speech-act account of
unjust power imbalance. We will set it out, and then show how it explains the data.
4 Roles and power
We contend that slurring utterances seek to create (or maintain) an unjust power
imbalance via role assignment. Our second contention is that the degree of offence
caused is correlated with the magnitude of the perceived unjustness of the power
imbalance associated with this role. So, what’s in a role?
Roles are social constructs that carry information about permissible and expected
behaviours, social status (i.e. rank relative to other roles), rights, and responsibilities.13 As Goffman notes, ‘‘role’’ is the basic unit of socialisation: ‘‘it is through
roles that tasks in society are allocated and arrangements made to enforce their
performance’’ (1961: 77). In society we allocate, by various means, many social
roles to individuals. Human interactions are informed by the expectations these
create. Roles also often come in pairs or groups, and convey information about
relative status and power. When roles change, power can change. While in many
situations roles with power imbalance are accepted and useful (e.g. parent and
child), others have unjust power imbalances that are created and maintained by
force (e.g. master and slave).
Different social roles taken on by an individual persist over different time
periods. Some commonly last an entire lifetime (ethnicity, gender), others typically
last for many years (profession, being a spouse), while some last for months
(pregnancy, trainee), days (being a workshop attendee, tourist, jury member) or
hours (being a customer in a restaurant). We can thus refer to the duration of a social
role, and thus to—relatively speaking—long-term social roles and short-term social
roles. During the period within which a person holds a role some number of
individual social interactions will occur. A discourse is a type of individual social
interaction, and so a role that lasts for a single discourse is thus a very short-term
social role.
There is an intimate relationship between social roles and discourse. Social roles
structure social interactions, and are structured by them. Discourse is structured by
social roles in several ways. Speakers signal information about the status of a social
role via honorifics and etiquette terms.14 In interpreting what speakers say, hearers
are guided by information about their interlocutors’ social roles. A socially
dominant speaker can rule out communicative possibilities for his dominated
interlocutors (Lewis 1979: 347). Finally, speakers can also say things that alter
social roles. Examples include declaring two people to be married, convicting a
criminal, and investing someone into a particular office, such as a monarch, an
13
Social roles are stable constructs, whether or not they are institutionalized (Mallon 2003).
14
Honorifics serve to establish power in discourse, e.g. when a speaker addresses someone with ‘‘Sir’’,
this signals to peers that they should treat that person with deference. Potts (2007) provides a semantic
modelling.
123
Slurs, roles and power
admiral, or a priest. Such role assignments are performatives in that they allocate a
long-term social role to a person, i.e. the role persists beyond the temporal duration
of the discourse in which it is allocated.
It is necessary to distinguish the social roles that speakers draw on from their use
in discourse. To do this, we introduce the notion of discourse roles. We will first
sketch the concept and then show its utility. Since discourse is a social interaction,
discourse roles are precisely short-term social roles that exist only for the purposes
of a particular dialogue. They often inherit from longer-term social roles which
participants hold externally to the conversation. Thus, a person may have many
social roles external to a particular conversation (employee, policeman, homicide
detective, parent, man, African-American). Which of these external roles is salient
within a particular conversation depends on the circumstance. So, someone talking
with their boss adopts a different external social role (employee) as their discourse
role than when talking with their child (parent). Discourse roles may be drawn from
social roles that neither of the participants actually have. For example, discourse
roles are sometimes play-acted, such as when an adult play-acts as a child, thus
inviting their interlocutor to take on a complementary role (e.g. a parent, or another
child). Finally, discourse roles can also be changed during a conversation.
A discourse role has three parts: discourse status, discourse rules, and the
associated social role. Discourse status denotes relative rank between a role and
other roles. It reflects the fact that human society is hierarchically organised, and
that many social interactions involve participants with a clear difference in rank.
Discourse rules govern expected moves, permissible moves, their expected effects,
and rules of interpretation. The same utterance—in an otherwise identical
situation—will be interpreted differently depending on the speaker’s discourse
role. For example, a person saying to a bank teller ‘‘I want $1000’’ will engender a
different interpretation depending on whether they are a customer or a bank robber.
A speech-act that changes the discourse role of a participant is thus important
because it changes the discourse rules and discourse status for that participant. It
also brings to salience the associated long-term social role.
What work do discourse roles actually do? Why is it necessary to separate longterm social roles external to the dialogue from the short-term social roles (discourse
roles) that are internal to the dialogue? The answer is that without such a distinction
we cannot have a coherent theory of how roles determine dialogue. Let’s take an
example from the film ‘‘In the Heat of the Night’’. After being arrested, in
Mississippi, in the 1960s, on suspicion of murder, the Sidney Poitier character, Mr
Tibbs, is taken to the police station. Mr Tibbs has four external social roles that are
relevant: first, he is an African-American in the deep south during a period of overt
racist practice; second, he is briefly15 a murder suspect; third, he is a police
officer; and fourth, he is the number one homicide expert with the Philadelphia
police department. The conversation with the chief of police begins with Mr Tibbs
15
Briefly, but still prior to the start of the dialogue in question, hence this is a ‘long-term’ social role for
Tibbs that exists external to the conversation.
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
as a murder suspect, and the fact of his race determining the conversational
trajectory, and the balance of power:
PC: Got a name boy?
MT: Virgil.
PC: Virgil? \laughs[ I don’t think we’re going to have any trouble, are we
Virgil?
MT: No.
PC: What d’you hit him with boy?
It should be clear that the power lies with the police chief. As the conversation
progresses it transpires that Mr Tibbs is a police officer:
PC: Just what you do up there in Pennsylvania, to earn that kind of money?
MT: I’m a police officer. \shows police badge[
PC: Oh. Yeah. \scratches head, sits down[
At this point the tone of the conversation changes. The fact that he is a policeman
and a homicide expert now determine the trajectory of the discourse. This is shown
with particular force, when, after further conversation, the police chief asks him to
look at the body of the murdered man as a favour:
PC: Look, if they pay you $162.39 a week to look at bodies. Why can’t you look at
this one?
MT: Why can’t you look at it yourself?
PC: Because I’m not an expert, officer.
Although the tone of the conversation has already changed, ‘‘officer’’ is the first
time Virgil Tibbs is referred to with an honorific. It is a clear statement of respect.
The request for a favour demonstrates a significant shift in the power balance during
the conversation.
This example shows that the salience of external social roles changes during a
discourse. To make sense of the conversation at any moment, we have to know
which external social roles of Mr. Tibbs are salient at that moment. Certain external
roles became less salient (murder suspect, member of an oppressed racial group),
while others (police officer, homicide expert) became more salient. But three of the
actual external social roles of Mr. Tibbs did not change: all the way through the
conversation, and before and after, he was an African-American, a police officer,
and a homicide expert.16 Thus, to describe the conversational kinematics we must
separate a participant’s external social roles, that exist beyond and throughout the
dialogue, from their corresponding changes in salience during the dialogue, and the
way that those changes in salience cause the conversational kinematics to change.
On the model proposed here, a discourse role is created when an external social
role becomes salient, and extinguished when the discourse ends, or when the
external social role ceases to be salient. We must, however, separate the discourse
and external social roles themselves. This is because their assignments last for
16
Only in the conversation did his external role as a murder suspect change.
123
Slurs, roles and power
different durations. When a discourse role is assigned it can only last as long as the
discourse. When an external social role is assigned it can last beyond the discourse.
If we only had external social roles we would not be able to explain the difference in
effect between the following two utterances, each of which makes a role
assignment:
(6)
(7)
We find you guilty of the charge of murder.
You dirty nigger.
In (6) the speaker (a jury member) assigns the roles of criminal and convicted
murderer to the target. In (7) the speaker (a work colleague) assigns a subordinate
role to the target by slurring. The effect of (6) lasts the rest of the life of the target
(unless the conviction is quashed on appeal). The effect of (7) does not. If we were
to only have external social roles, then there is no criterion to distinguish why one
assignment lasts and one doesn’t. Thus, if we are to have the notion of role
assignment in discourse, discourse roles are necessarily different from (though
closely related to) the external social roles from which they inherit.17
It is critical, however, to understand that these discourse roles are indeed shortterm social roles that exist internally in the discourse. Hence we use the term
‘discourse role’ as a short-hand for this short-term social role that is internal to a
specific dialogue. The discourse role is a social role that comes into being when it is
made salient in a dialogue, and which does not last beyond the dialogue. A discourse
role may, of course, result in the creation of an external social role that can last a
long time. This is exactly what happens when, for example, a couple are married. In
the moment that the discourse roles husband and wife are created, a pair of long
term-social roles, that will persist after the ceremonial conversation has ended, are
also created. We will hereafter use the terms discourse role and external social role
or simply social role.18
The conversational kinematics at each moment are determined by the combination of discourse roles currently held by each participant. In the first excerpt Mr
Tibbs is expected, under his discourse roles as a murder suspect and a black man in
Mississippi, to be subordinate and to respond with respect to his white counterparts,
17
Discourse roles could equivalently be described in terms of changes in the salience of external social
roles causing changes in the discourse rules that are in play at any one time. We would then simply note
that the salience of any social role ends with the end of a conversation. But, this would make talk about
role assignment impossible, since we would no longer have roles that could be ‘assigned’ in the
conversation, only saliences that could be altered. The term assignment would then need to be reserved
for classical performatives that have effects beyond the conversation. This terminological change would
also not change any of the predictions of the theory, only making it more cumbersome to explain. It
therefore seems rather easier to adopt the terminology of discourse roles, while recognising that the
assignment of a discourse role is equivalent to the external social role becoming salient. Another way to
say this is that the term ‘discourse role assignment’ is syntactic sugar for the phrase ‘an increase in
salience of an external social role during discourse’. We thank an anonymous referee for making points
that forced and enabled us to articulate this equivalence.
18
Discourse role refers to a short-term social role that only exists for the duration of a particular
dialogue. We will use social role as the short-hand for external social role, i.e. any social role that can be
ascribed to the person for a period beyond the duration of the dialogue in question. Clearly some social
roles will not persist for very long beyond the duration of the conversation, but the distinction stands.
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
who regard themselves as dominant. Subsequently, because he is acknowledged as a
police officer, he is talked to in a different way and is expected to give different
types of responses, both in content and tone.
Just as performatives can be used to assign high or low power social roles, so an act
of assigning a new discourse role can be used to shape the power dynamics in a
conversation. Discourse role assignment is thus a meta-move in the conversational
game in that it changes the discourse rules. We saw this in the excerpts above. Mr Tibbs
changes his discourse role, by providing the information that his long-term social role
is a police officer. At this point, the power balance in the conversation shifts.
Discourse roles are not solitary. A role assigned to one participant typically
presupposes complementary roles, to be adopted by other participants. Thus, by entering
into a role, a speaker can invite or compel other participants to take on new roles. When
Mr. Tibbs enters, the police chief assumes the role of interrogator, thus Mr. Tibbs is
compelled to take on the role of the suspect. This first role pairing is complemented by a
second, that Mr. Tibbs is a member of a subordinate racial group, and the police chief a
member of the dominant racial group. Later, Mr. Tibbs takes on the role of police officer,
thus influencing the police chief to take on a more colleague-like role. It is clear from this
example that relative power in a dialogue changes when discourse roles change.
The notion of a discourse role is also useful when considering how we talk about
non-participants. Social roles come in and out of salience in the same way. Talk
about an absent person is still determined in large part by these short-term salient
roles. Compare two dialogues:
(8)
(9)
Sue: Johnny is a good and honest boy.
Bob: Johnny says he didn’t take the biscuits.
Sue: Johnny is a thief and a liar.
Bob: Johnny says he didn’t take the biscuits.
The second utterance in each dialogue is interpreted differently because of the first
utterance. Once Johnny has been cast in a role, it influences how utterances about
him are interpreted. Either Johnny was a thief and a liar, or he wasn’t, both before
and after the dialogue. But if the information introduced is new to Bob and other
participants, it will change the way utterances about Johnny are interpreted only
after the role is introduced. Thus, Johnny’s role as discussed in the discourse
changes at that point. If Johnny were to enter the room after this point, he would be
treated differently depending on whether the start of the conversation was (8) or (9).
So at that point, he picks up the status with its discourse rules that were determined
for him by a role assignment made in the discourse prior to his entering the room.19
19
Later on we will describe how one way of describing the underlying mechanism of role assignment is
that of modification of the conversational score. Another way would be to think about this as altering the
beliefs in the common ground. So that when we allocate Johnny the role of liar we are altering beliefs
about what Johnny is likely to do in certain situations, together with beliefs about how Johnny’s
utterances ought to be interpreted. The purpose of the roles of ‘‘liar’’ and ‘‘thief’’ is that each puts a set of
beliefs on the common ground in one go. It is this idea of roles efficiently indexing many facts, norms and
rules that is important. For the purposes of the theory as we describe it here the common ground
explanation and the conversational score explanation can be seen as flip sides of the same mechanism for
implementing discourse roles and role assignments.
123
Slurs, roles and power
Thus, it seems sensible to think about all such role allocations in discourse as
allocating discourse roles, whether or not the person is present. If the person enters
the conversation they will be governed by the rules associated with that discourse
role, as earlier allocated. However, if the person is not present at any point, the role
allocated will still determine how they are spoken about during the conversation,
and may affect their social role after the conversation has ended. For example,
suppose that Bob didn’t previously believe Johnny to be a thief and a liar. If he
believes Sue he will certainly treat statements Johnny makes during future
conversations with him in a different way than before. This ability for nonparticipants to have discourse roles, and for those to affect the external social roles
of those non-participants post the conversation is important. It will serve as a
building block in our later consideration of whether role assignment can account for
the effects of both second and third person uses of slurs.
Having established what a discourse role is, we now consider how a slurring
utterance alters power relations via speech-acts related to discourse roles. In
particular, are slurs oppressive speech?
5 Slurs and oppressive speech
McKinnon (1993) and Langton (1993) proposed that some types of speech, such as
pornography, can not only subordinate, but are constitutive of subordination. In
other words, the illocutionary act performed is an act of subordination, rather than
merely causing subordination through its perlocutionary effects. This position has
been attacked on the grounds that the speaker must have authority for the act to fire,
and that this is not obviously the case for the kinds of speech they want to so
classify. A variety of counter arguments have been marshalled. Langton (1998)
proposed that speakers have authority if they already have local control over aspects
of the lives of the targets. Maitra (2012), in extending the idea of oppressive speech
to hate speech, proposed that the required authority is licensed by the silent assent of
the audience. To see a problem with the second approach consider two utterances:
(10)
(11)
The neighbourhood has really gone downhill since those spics moved in.
Shut up, you fucking faggot!
While Maitra’s argument can explain (10) it cannot solve the authority problem for
(11). Suppose there is no audience other than the target for (11). If the speaker is to
have authority, then according to Maitra, they must wait on the silence of the target.
But, until subordinated, the target can speak out, being on equal terms with the
speaker. Thus, the speaker cannot wait for the silence of the target, for surely any
rational target would speak out. But targets often don’t speak out.20 Because of this,
20
Nielsen (2012) and West (2012).
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
Maitra’s argument cannot show that one-to-one uses of slurs constitute oppressive
speech because she can’t solve the authority problem.21
McGowan (2009, 2012) argues that, in fact, authority is not needed. To show this
she builds on Lewis’s (1979) idea of the conversational score. This comprises
entities that summarise and are necessary to make sense of the utterances so far in a
conversation. Examples of the latter include the relative salience of entities brought
under discussion, points of reference, standards of precision in description, relevant
possibilities, facts about the world changed by performative utterances, and plans.
Lewis (1979: 347) points out that conversational score evolves so as to make the
utterances that have occurred ‘‘correct play’’. This is achieved by various ‘‘rules of
accommodation’’. In turn, the conversational score and the rules of conversational
kinematics together determine what counts as correct play. So an utterance that
requires a rule of accommodation changes the conversational score, and thereby
changes what is conversationally permissible.
Because it changes what is conversationally permissible, McGowan (2003, 2004)
says that any such utterance is a ‘‘conversational exercitive’’. She argues that
conversational exercitives don’t need to display their communicative intentions, nor
have them understood by participants, in order to work, and so they can be what she
terms ‘‘covert’’. Critically, she claims that conversational exercitives do not require
authority in the way that standard exercitives do. In later work (2009) she extends
this idea of a covert exercitive to include any move in any rule (norm) governed
activity, i.e. any move in any game changes the state of the game, thus determining
the permissible next moves.
Permissible moves are simply defined by the rules of correct play. McGowan
splits rules governing games into two classes: g-rules (general rules), and s-rules
(specific rules). While g-rules always hold, s-rules can be changed by moves in the
game. She then claims that we can think of oppression as a rule governed activity.
So, if a verbal move enacts an s-rule within the oppression game then it is an
exercitive within the game of oppression, i.e. it changes what is a permissible move
in the oppression game. She suggests that sexist and racist speech falls into this
category. So sexist and racist speech is constitutive of a move within the game of
oppression.
We can use this to explain slurring utterances. We first add discourse roles as
being possible entities in the conversational score. These determine what is correct
play in the conversation. When a speaker slurs the target they assign them a
subordinate discourse role. Because of accommodation the conversational score
updates to include this assignment: the target now has the discourse role. This in
turn changes rules of interpretation, and rules of permissibility about what the target
can say. Thus, when a discourse role is assigned it adds these as s-rules to the
conversation. So we first extend Lewis’s notion of conversational score to include
discourse roles, and then utilise McGowan’s notion of a conversational exercitive to
give a mechanism by which the discourse roles are changed. In fact the speaker
21
We can think of (11) as a weapon use—an assault that employs its affective effects to subdue the
target, thus creating silence, thereby enabling the discourse role assignment to fire by demonstrating
power.
123
Slurs, roles and power
imposes not just one, but a complementary pair of discourse roles on the
conversational score: the speaker takes on a powerful, dominant role, while
assigning the target a subordinate role. Both have associated s-rules.
There is however, a slight difference between the examples of the s-rules that
McGowan gives, and the s-rules enacted by a discourse role assignment. This is
because the pair of discourse role assignments enacts different s-rules for each
participant. In other examples of conversational score, including the oppressive
speech examples that McGowan gives, the s-rules alter what is permissible for all
participants equally. Roles give a way that s-rules are specific for particular
participants. Thus, the s-rules for the dominant role permit the use of types of
utterances directed at the subordinate role that would never be permitted in a
conversation between participants with equal status. Conversely, the s-rules for the
subordinate role restrict the types of allowable utterances for the subordinate role.
Because of this the act functions as a mechanism of unjust and forceful discourse
power grab.
Does this bring light to bear on the debate on the constitutive or causal nature of
oppressive speech? It would seem natural, given our division between discourse
roles and external social roles, to say that slurs are constitutive of oppressive speech
with respect to the discourse roles, because they have the illocutionary force of
assigning a subordinate role for the purposes and duration of the discourse. So, in
this sense the theory clearly supports the notion that slurs constitute oppression in
the current social (conversational) interaction.
But what of the effect on the long-term social role external to the discourse? The
question is more open here. There are two options. On the one hand, we could
maintain that a slurring utterance is constitutive of oppression beyond the current
discourse. On the other hand, we could simply say that effects beyond the
conversation are causal. To decide between the two we would need to decide what it
would mean for the slurring speech-act to be constitutive of oppression beyond the
current dialogue. If oppression within the dialogue is the allocation of a subordinate
short-term social role (discourse role), then it would follow that oppression beyond
the dialogue would be the allocation of a subordinate long-term social role. That, in
other words, the target would in all social interactions thereafter, until some other
action released them, be in a subordinate social role relative to the speaker. It
follows that in order to answer the constitutive versus causal debate in oppressive
speech, that we would have to come to an answer as to whether this is plausibly the
case or not.
Although we cannot give a full answer in this paper, we sketch the following
three positions: local constitutive (LC), constrained distal constitutive (CDC) and
universal distal constitutive (UDC). Local constitutive is simply the view that the
speech-act is oppressive within the current (local) social interaction, i.e. within the
current discourse. Constrained distal constitutive is the view that the role
assignment persists beyond the current discourse, but that this is constrained to
future social interactions with the speaker and aligned audience members. Universal
distal constitutive would be the position that all future social interactions between
the target and others would be governed by the role assignment. It seems obvious
that UDC is false. It cannot be the case that if someone calls a person a slur, that this
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
triggers a role assignment that persists forever. Choosing between LC and CDC is
more complex, since one can easily imagine that some theorists will want to plump
for CDC, to maintain that the oppression is constitutive beyond the current social
interaction. But equally the LC position has merit, since it follows uncontroversially
if the model of this paper is accepted. The arguments are too complex to consider
here. But, without choosing between CDC and LC, we would maintain that either
satisfies the goal of defining a type of speech (slurring) as constituting oppression. In
the latter case (LC) the consequence would be that oppression beyond the current
social interaction (discourse) is caused by the slurring utterance.
Whether slurs constitute (CDC) or cause (LC) oppression beyond the dialogue,
we need to make it clearer how it happens. We now turn to this. We will argue that
it is clear that at least some of the effects are causal, i.e. perlocutionary.
6 How slurs contribute to oppression
We’ve argued that slurring acts are moves in a discourse that seek to shift power
from the target to the speaker. If a slurring act only affected the current discourse, its
effects would end when the discourse ends. But they don’t. So, how do they affect
the social roles of targets in the real world?
Just as the discourse role is influenced by the social roles of the participants, so
the social roles of the participants are influenced by the discourse. The discourse
role feeds back into the social role. This feedback is achieved via perlocutionary
effects of the slurring utterances.
First, these include changes to the attitudes of audience members and to their
dispositions about how to treat members of the target group. There is evidence that
social circumstances influence the extent to which people discriminate, and can
override an individual’s declared ideology. Warner and DeFleur (1969) shows that
those of low racial prejudice are more likely to act in a discriminatory manner if
they are members of a society in which there is a significant number of bigots, and
they know that their actions will be broadcast. Why? They factor in the social cost
of disapproval from a dominantly bigoted community. In predominantly nonbigoted societies the reverse is true: bigots hide their beliefs so as to avoid social
disapproval. Thus, when a bigot uses slur words, they make it more permissible for
others within their social circle to give voice to their bigotry. If there are sufficient
bigots they create a pressure for even non-bigots to discriminate. In this way, the
perlocutionary effect of a slurring use is to increase oppression by incrementally
increasing the social pressure for, and acceptability of, oppressive acts.
But these effects may have different results in different circumstances. So that
racial slurring, for example, in a racist society versus a non-racist society will have
different effects in inducing, or failing to induce, others to discriminatory acts. This
difference, in effect based on circumstance, can be explained in terms of Kukla
(2014) and Kukla and Lance (2009), Lance and Kukla (2013) who describe how
speech acts shift norms. They introduce the notion of uptake. In this, the pragmatic
context within which the utterance is made determines whether uptake is achieved.
They refer to the ‘‘output’’ of a speech act as the set of normative statuses it
123
Slurs, roles and power
institutes. They emphasise that ‘‘a speech act can be, in virtue of its uptake, a
different speech act than it would typically be, given its social context and standard
discursive conventions’’ (Kukla 2014: 3). To provide a complete account of how
slurs shift norms and how their effects change in different social circumstances we
will likely need to draw on such notions.
Second, by slurring the bigot shows others the power they can acquire. On the
power theory outlined here, the bigot is not talking about power, they are
demonstrating power. The speaker acquires discourse power. We posit that this is
emotionally appealing to audience members—who are not members of the target
group—who feel less powerful than they would like. They see that they can accrue
power to themselves by using a slur. Thus, a perlocutionary effect is to make others
desire the power the bigot has grabbed. Increasing desire is different to increasing
acceptability. Both are required for audience members to join the side of the bigot.
A slurring act also has perlocutionary effects on the target. First, targets are
affected as after a threat of physical assault. As Lawrence (1993) writes: ‘‘One of
my students, a white, gay male … told a story of being called ‘‘faggot’’ by a man on
a subway. His description included all of the speech inhibiting elements we have
noted previously. He found himself in a state of semi-shock, nauseous, dizzy, unable
to muster the witty, sarcastic, articulate rejoinder he was accustomed to making. He
was instantly aware of the recent spate of gay bashing in San Francisco, and that
many of incidents had escalated from verbal encounters.’’
This demonstrates that the effects on the target are those of the fight-flight
response, and that this is because the slurring use carries an implicit threat of
violence. This in turn, Lawrence noted, led to a speech inhibiting effect, to
silencing. Targets are more likely to be the victims of violence, either at the time of
slurring, or afterwards. Imagine a racist policeman who uses a racial slur while
arresting a member of an ethnic minority. Slurs associated with a history of violence
implicate the potential for this violence to be re-enacted. If you were an AfricanAmerican, and a policeman stopped you in your car and called you ‘‘Nigger’’, would
you merely feel offended, or would you also fear for your physical safety?
This ability to incite to action is shown by Tirrell (2012: 174), who argues that
deeply derogative words are ‘‘action-engendering’’ and ‘‘can be part and parcel of
genocide, not only an antecedent of it’’. When Tutsi were labeled ‘‘inyenzi’
(cockroach) or ‘inzoka’ (snake), this granted permission to hate and a mandate to
kill. As she says, ‘‘understanding these speech-acts helps to illuminate the important
ways that power is enacted through discourse, how speech-acts can prepare the way
for physical and material acts, and how speech generates permissions for actions
hitherto uncountenanced.’’
This is also recognised within the US law enforcement community. For example:
‘‘San Francisco’s public defender, Jeff Adachi, sharply criticized three city police
officers for text messages they exchanged … using racial slurs … ‘That’s the kind of
mentality that tells you it’s OK to shoot, OK to kill, OK to arrest’ people of color,
Adachi told reporters’’ (Chang and Tchekmedyian 2016). This is evidenced by
studies that show an association between increased rates of internet searches using
racial slurs for African-Americans and various social effects, including an increased
likelihood of voting against a black politician (Stephens-Davidowitz 2014), an
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
increased likelihood of African-Americans being shot by the police while unarmed
relative to white people (Ross 2015), and increased mortality rates among AfricanAmericans (Chae et al. 2015).
Thus, perlocutionary effects causing oppression beyond the discourse include:
emotional injury, implicit threat of physical injury, silencing, increased permissibility and/or pressure for other oppressive acts, and increased desire to act
oppressively so as to gain power.
7 Explaining variable offence
The theory set out so far has several elements. It is now worth running through
these, to see quickly how they lock together. First, we have the idea of both short
term-social roles (discourse roles) and of longer-term social roles. Second, we have
the idea that these roles often come in pairs, i.e. that they make most sense when
defined in relation to one another. Third, we noted that some pairs of long-term
social roles are associated with a power imbalance. Fourth, that some such power
imbalances are unjust. Fifth, we then have the idea that in a social interaction, such
as a conversation, a social role can be assigned. This can be a long-term social role,
such as achieved by a regular exercitive—‘‘I declare you man and wife’’—or it can
be a role that exists for the purposes of the discourse. Sixth, we then considered a
candidate mechanism for the assignment of such roles, and found that the notion of
a conversational game from Lewis, augmented by the notion of a conversational
exercitive from McGowan, seems to fit the bill. Finally, we laid out the range of
positions that seem plausible with regard to whether discourse role assignment of a
subordinate role could be seen as either constitutive or causal of oppression We
refer to this set of seven linked hypotheses as the ‘role and unjust power’ theory of
oppressive speech, or role-power theory for short.
This leads us to state the prediction that the theory makes about variable offence.
This is that the degree of offence taken by an audience member in relation to a
slurring speech-act is in proportion to the perceived unjustness—according to that
audience member—of the power imbalance that it plausibly achieves. Let’s unpack
this.
First, we need to understand how the power imbalance that it [the slurring
speech-act] plausibly achieves can vary across terms. The power imbalance created
is between the short-term social roles, i.e. the discourse roles allocated to each
participant. Earlier we saw that discourse roles draw upon longer-term social roles
that exist externally to the current discourse. An oppressive slur term can be used to
allocate a pair of discourse roles, where these roles draw upon a pair of roles that
had a history of oppression. Thus, the greater the degree of oppression associated
with the long-term historical roles, the greater the offence likely to be caused. This
would neatly explain across group word variation, e.g. why a racial slur directed at
African-Americans are generally considered to be more offensive than those
directed at other ethnic groups. So that ‘‘Nigger’’ is typically considered by a nonracist to be more offensive than ‘‘Chink’’.
123
Slurs, roles and power
The limiting case would thus be slur terms associated with a privileged group,
such as ‘‘Limey’’, ‘‘Yankee’’ or ‘‘Honkey’’. These are generally accepted as nonoffensive. In this case it could be said that these groups have, in relation to other
groups, actually been perpetuators of oppression. In such a case what would we
expect the theory to predict? It would be reasonable to suppose that if a word evokes
no long-term social role for the target subject to unjust oppression, then there can be
no offence. This is what we typically find. It is, of course, possible for the utterance
to be used with a contemptuous tone, and thus the speaker’s expression of contempt
via that tone to cause offence, but there is no additional offence caused by the use of
the particular word.
What about offence variation across words used to refer to the same group? We
know that ‘‘nigger’’ is widely considered more offensive than ‘‘spook’’. Does this
cause a problem? If both words reference the same role, then surely they reference
the same history of oppression. There are two positions that could be taken to
explain this. The first is based on the way that the historical use of each term varies,
so that ‘‘nigger’’ first had a five-fold upswing in its printed use between 1848 and
1862 when African-Americans were suffering the extreme oppression of slavery.22
‘‘Spook’’, on the other hand, does not appear as a racial slur until the twentieth
century, and could thus not be directly associated with the roles involved in slavery.
So, on this view, ‘‘nigger’’ and ‘‘spook’’ would actually index different roles,
because they index different (if overlapping) periods in the history of oppression.
A different explanation would be that words tend to be associated with the
history of oppression based on the frequency of their use. This account would also
be consistent with data on use frequency, as ‘‘spook’’ (not even removing the nonracial uses of the term) occurred, even during its history as a racial term, no more
than 1/10th as often as ‘‘nigger’’.23 This explanation would predict that offence
would rise with more frequent use. An extension of this second explanation would
be that since slur terms such as ‘‘spook’’ are now archaic, memory of them gradually
falls away altogether, so that they cause no offence to those who do not know their
earlier use. Thus zero use eventually leads to zero offence.
So, VT1 in general is a function of two factors. First, it depends on the extent to
which the slur word evokes (via association or familiarity of slurring use) a pair of
roles from the history of oppression. Second, it depends on the extent of the unjust
power imbalance present in the external social roles so indexed.
What about use-variation (VT2)? This covers the variation in offence caused
according to who the speaker is. So, for example, it is quite common now—
although it was not always—for African-American comedians to use the term
‘‘nigger’’ without offence, but extremely rare for a white comedian to be able to do
so. Can we provide an explanation of this? The answer lies in the dual role
22
Source: Google Books n-gram analysis. All the statements regarding word frequency and periods of
use are taken from this source.
23
Google n-gram shows that the usage of ‘‘spook’’ is between ten and sixteen times less frequent than
‘‘nigger’’ in the corpus of American English (2012). While this doesn’t track non-written uses, it is likely
that verbal and non-verbal uses track each other. It should also be noted that the frequency of ‘‘spook’’ as
a racial slur is even less frequent, because there are two other non-slur meanings of the term.
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
assignment that occurs. If the speaker cannot plausibly fit the role, then role
assignment is much less likely to work. It is a felicity condition for the slurring act.
If the speaker does not fit the role of the oppressor, then offence can be avoided.
Discourse roles often inherit from external social roles. When a discourse role is
assigned, it presupposes (typically via the associated external social roles) certain
facts about the speaker and target. While the conversational score updates using
accommodation, i.e. to make a move correct play, there are limits: accommodation
isn’t infinitely elastic. Thus, if the presupposed facts about speaker or target do not
fit the actual facts, then accommodation breaks. Thus, if the speaker is gay and the
target is heterosexual, the use of the slur ‘‘fag’’ presupposes facts (that the target is
gay and the speaker is prejudiced against gay people) which do not fit their actual
social identities.
It may also be that the existing discourse roles of the participants contain rules
that prevent one of the speakers from subordinating the other via slurring. This is
typically the case when the speaker is subordinate to the target at the start of the
discourse. Thus, take Lewis’s example of the master and slave. The normative
social interaction between these two is governed by the social roles of master and
slave, so the conversation starts with the roles of master and slave as the default
discourse roles. If the slave attempts to subordinate the master by slurring, this fails
because the discourse rules already governing the conversation prevent the slave
from subordinating the master. Thus, again, accommodation has limits. This
function of discourse roles limiting the moves that may be made by some speakers,
thus maintaining them in a subordinate role, is related to accounts of discursive
injustice (Kukla 2014).
But we need to be careful here. Some cases where social identities do not
perfectly fit still allow offensive slurring uses. It is the case that in-group uses can
sometimes offend, and also that out-group uses can sometimes fail to offend. What
causes this inconsistency? We would posit that it is not just group-membership, but
a whole variety of other factors that can modulate whether the felicity condition is
met. So if there is a plausible power differential between the speaker and target, that
can drive offence. Recall the account of an African-American woman being
offended when her African-American boss called her a ‘‘Nigger’’ (Gabbat 2013).
Other flags, such as tone, familiarity between the participants, appropriateness of
context, will all modulate whether the felicity condition is met. Thus, in-group
versus out-group is just one part of the felicity conditions. We would suggest that
one way to think of these felicity conditions is as additive: if a sufficient number are
met, then it is highly likely that the target will be offended. But the number of the
sub-conditions that have to be met for offence to be triggered varies across audience
members.
What of audience-variation (VT3) more generally? This is where one audience
member can be offended by a particular use and another not. In this case the theory
says that the offence rises with the perceived unjustness—according to that
audience member—of the power imbalance. Thus, the contention is that the degree
of offence taken by an individual is due to the difference between the power
imbalance they see as appropriate and the power imbalance they perceive as being
assigned by the slurring act. The more bigoted the listener is, the less offended they
123
Slurs, roles and power
are, because the more appropriate they see the power imbalance as being. Bigots
aren’t offended, because they believe it is just that the target group be subordinate.
Power imbalance through role assignment can be shown to thus neatly correlate
with all three types of variable offence. But all the uses so far are direct or secondperson uses. What happens when a third-person use occurs?24 To answer this
imagine that at a party two people are talking.
(12)
Bill: ‘‘The neighbourhood has really gone downhill since those spics moved
in.’’
Sue: ‘‘Actually my husband is Hispanic.’’
Here Sue is offended because Bill is making a statement about Hispanics that she
clearly disagrees with. But, how can the role assignment occur if the target isn’t
present? The clue to this is in the example of Johnny from earlier in the paper. We
saw that if the role assignment were accepted, Johnny would be treated according to
the role previously assigned to him, on entering the conversation. This is exactly
what is happening here. To see that the role assignment really occurs in third-person
uses imagine this variation of the above dialogue:
(13)
Bill: ‘‘The neighbourhood has really gone downhill since those spics moved
in.’’
Sue: ‘‘I know.’’
\later on Leila, who is one of their Hispanic neighbours, approaches and
joins in the conversation having failed to overhear the earlier remark[
In this case it will be clear that there is now agreement, by Sue, that Bill and Sue
will treat Leila according to the role he has allocated of ‘‘spic’’. So although Leila
was not present when the utterance was made, she will still be treated differently.
Now, of course, it could be the case that Bill and Sue in this second dialogue are
closet racists, that they don’t want to explicitly let Leila know what they think of
her, but even in this case they will treat her differently, and each of Bill and Sue will
understand the behaviour of the other towards Leila in terms of their view of how
someone with the role of ‘‘spic’’ is to be treated. By knowing that they are in
agreement about Leila’s role they will be able to oppress in concert with one
another. Thus, the third-person use does affect the social role of the target in the
interaction even though they were not present when the utterance was made.
Clearly, however, Leila was not offended, because she was not aware of the role
assignment. But Bill’s role assignment is picked-up by Leila when she enters the
conversation. We can see this because we can see that Sue would still know, when
Leila arrived, that Bill would treat Leila as a ‘‘spic’’.
We will now finish by sketching how power through role assignment can also
account for silencing and appropriation.
24
Slurs among out-group members are in fact quite common. There are many possible reasons for this.
As Nunberg (forthcoming) points out, intra-bigot talk serves to ‘‘create solidarity in a common sense of
resentment or superiority; to enjoy the complicit schoolyard-variety naughtiness in using forbidden
words, particularly in the form of racial or homophobic humour; or to underscore the normative values of
the group’’.
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
8 Explaining silencing and appropriation
In this final section we will very briefly sketch how two other phenomena associated
with slurs might be explained. These are silencing and re-appropriation or reclaim.
A full treatment requires a different paper, but a sketch can be instructive.
Silencing is actually a pair of phenomena. First, the target feels intimidated to
respond. Second, even if they do respond their responses cannot completely undo
the effects of the slur, and can be ignored. Let us take the example of the student of
Lawrence (1993), who suffered the perlocutionary effects of being in a state of
semi-shock, and unable to muster a rejoinder. This suggests not that the victim
accepts their role as subordinate, but that the role pair includes the potential for
violence by the speaker. This violence is part of what is seen as appropriate
treatment according to the bigot. It doesn’t matter whether the target disagrees.
Perpetrating a violent attack is part of the role of the oppressor, and thus via the dual
role assignment they signal they may carry this out. So this is both constitutive and
causal. The utterance constitutes a threat of violence by reference to the roles
assigned, and one of the perlocutionary effects is the fear of the target that selfsilences to try to self-preserve.
Furthermore, in constitutive terms the discourse role also includes rules that
permit participants to ignore future utterances by the target, including those that
disable objections from the target to the assignment itself. So, take the example of a
speaker calling a woman a ‘‘slut’’. An objection she makes could be disabled by
saying that it is part of her role to deny this, and that thus her denial can be safely
ignored. Or imagine an African-American man arrested by a racist policeman who
targets him with a slur: if he objects, his objections can be used as evidence of his
criminality—resisting arrest, talking back to a police officer. In this way, his
perfectly justified response is turned against him. So in the first case the target does
not speak, and in the second case they will not be heard. Both are demonstrations of
power.
What about appropriation? This is a complex phenomenon. We saw that, if the
speaker mis-matches the role of the oppressor,25 the act of discourse role assignment
doesn’t necessarily fire, because the felicity conditions aren’t met. Thus, when a
member of the target group uses a slur word, the felicity conditions for the role
assignment don’t automatically fire because their group-membership doesn’t match
that of the historical oppressor group. Because of this failure, the slur word is freed,
enabling appropriation as a possibility. This doesn’t mean that all in-group uses
enable appropriation. Cases of anger, contempt, or self-loathing may still trigger the
felicity conditions. Instead, the space for appropriation must be created by repeated
uses where the felicity conditions are violated.
Appropriation enables members of the target group to put the slur term to better
use.26 So when an African-American greets another African-American with
25
Matches can be accommodating, e.g. an ethnically Asian policeman in San Francisco used slurs
against African-Americans.
26
Bianchi (2014) and Herbert (2015), among others.
123
Slurs, roles and power
‘‘Nigger’’, a different pair of roles can be assigned—roles with equal discourse
rights and camaraderie. This is not universal; it is perfectly possible for in-group
uses to offend if some of the felicity conditions are met. Additionally, it is not the
case that anyone can use an appropriated term. A friendly white speaker of
‘‘Nigger’’ will likely offend, insofar as their group-membership fulfils the felicity
conditions for a speech-act that assigns roles with an unjust power imbalance. So the
two uses (in-group and out-group) have the potential to assign different pairs of
roles. Thus, all we have established is that by breaking the felicity conditions in
some cases, in-group uses can create a space within which re-appropriation can
begin. This does not say how that re-appropriation occurs, and this should be a topic
for further consideration.
Finally, the idea of unjust power is what draws the distinction between
oppressive slurs and other derogatory expressions, such as pejoratives. Take
‘‘dickhead’’: it expresses contempt, but it doesn’t oppress by allocating a low power
role that draws on a history of oppression. It is certainly the case that the target of a
pejorative such as ‘‘dickhead’’ may be offended. It is also true, however, that
‘‘dickhead’’ is a term with some kind of role. We think of a person who does
socially inappropriate things and doesn’t care about their consequences. But this
role is not an oppressed role in society. This distinction between pejoratives and
oppressive slurs thus rests on the notion of power, rather than the notion of role. It
can of course be said that in calling someone a ‘‘dickhead’’ the speaker is
performing a conversational exercitive, and all such exercitives can leave the target
with a sense that something has been done to them in the conversation that they did
not want or permit, and this is indeed an example of force being applied in dialogue.
In this sense, again, a pejorative and a slur are similar in that they take the initiative.
But there is a difference between this and the unjustness of the power associated
with the roles assigned. A pejorative such as ‘‘dickhead’’ does not have a natural
paired role that oppresses them.
9 Conclusion
Unjust power is an important dimension along which offence varies for slurring
utterances. I’ve argued that this explains three kinds of variability other accounts
struggle with. It also explains silencing and the possibility of appropriation. There
are other dimensions required to explain.
The shape of the solution is as follows. Power relations, and thus oppression, are
captured by social roles. Discourse roles inherit from social roles, and reflect the
power of those social roles in their discourse rules. Discourse roles are part of the
conversational score. They thus determine the rules of conversational kinematics via
their associated discourse rules. Discourse roles can be assigned by a variety of
utterances, which work as conversational versions of Austinian exercitives. A
slurring utterance assigns a pair of discourse roles, between which there is an unjust
power imbalance. This affects power in the dialogue. The slurring move also has
perlocutionary effects on both target and audience that cause the spread and
intensification of oppression.
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
This theory relates what people do with language to the social structure within
which language use is situated. The primary theoretical innovation has been to
extend Lewis’s notion of a scorekeeping in a language game with the notion of
discourse roles which can be changed by dialogue moves. The idea of related
discourse and social roles that feed off one another is, however, not restricted to
slurring, and may find application in other problems. For example, when nonslurring speech assigns roles, such as the case of Johnny being called a liar, it has
similar effects, as we saw. Another, more topical example is the use by Donald
Trump of names that assign roles to his political opponents: ‘‘Crooked Hillary’’,
‘‘Little Marco’’ and ‘‘Lyin’ Ted’’. These are not slurs, but deliberately turn names
into role allocations.
Acknowledgements We would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments
on the paper, and to the commentators on presentations made during its gestation: Adam Sennet, Connie
Rosati, Laura Silva. Last, but not least, we’d like to thank all those who took the trouble to comment on
previous drafts: Kent Bach, Laura Schroeter, Chris Hom, Pekka Väyrynen, Liz Camp, Renee Bolinger,
Rae Langton, Jimmy Lenman, Charles Mills, Michael Glanzberg, Rachel McKinney, Indrek Reiland,
Steve Barker, Max Kölbel, Zsófia Zvolensky, Alex Silk, Daniel Morgan, Daniel Whiting, Gary Ostertag,
Ivan Milić, David Copp, Eric Swanson, Robert Gooding-Williams. This work was supported by Beatriu
de Pinós Project Grant No. 2013 BP-B 00266 from AGAUR/European Commission.
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0
International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original
author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were
made.
References
Anderson, E. (2012). The imperative of integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Anderson, L., & Lepore, E. (2013a). Slurring words. Noûs, 47, 25–48.
Anderson, L., & Lepore, E. (2013b). What did you call me? Slurs as prohibited words. Analytic
Philosophy, 54(3), 350–363.
Bach, K. (Forthcoming). Mean and nasty talk: On the semantics and pragmatics of slurs. In D. Sosa (Ed.),
Bad words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Barker, S. J. (2000). Is value content a component of conventional implicature? Analysis, 60(267),
268–279.
Bianchi, C. (2014). Slurs and appropriation: An echoic account. Journal of Pragmatics, 66, 35–44.
Bolinger, R. J. (2015). The pragmatics of slurs. Noûs, 49(1), 1–24.
Burge, T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review, 95, 3–45.
Camp, E. (2013). Slurring perspectives. Analytic Philosophy, 54, 330–349.
Chae, D. H., Clouston, S., Hatzenbuehler, M. L., Kramer, M. R., Cooper, H. L. F., Wilson, S. M., et al.
(2015). Association between an internet-based measure of area racism and black mortality. PloS
One. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0122963.
Chang, C., & Tchekmedyian, A. (2016). Racial slurs by law enforcement are a legacy that’s becoming
more unacceptable. Los Angeles Times, May 3 2016.
Copp, D. (2001). Realist expressivism: A neglected option for moral realism. Social Philosophy and
Policy, 18, 1–43.
Cudd, A. (2006). Analyzing oppression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dahl, R. (1957). The concept of power. Behavioral Science, 2, 201–215.
123
Slurs, roles and power
Gabbat, A. (2013). Black woman wins civil case against black manager who used the N-word. The
Guardian, Wednesday 4 September. www.theguardian.com/world/2013/sep/04/black-woman-nword-court-case.
Goffman, E. (1961). Encounters: Two studies in the sociology of interaction. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Herbert, C. (2015). Precarious projects: The performative structure of appropriation. Language Sciences,
52, 131–138.
Hom, C. (2008). The semantics of racial epithets. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 416–440.
Hom, C. (2012). A puzzle about pejoratives. Philosophical Studies, 159, 383–405.
Hom, C., & May, R. (2013). Moral and semantic innocence. Analytic Philosophy, 54, 293–313.
Hornsby, J. (1995). Disempowered speech. Philosophical Topics, 23(2), 127–147.
Hornsby, J. (2001). Meaning and uselessness. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25(1), 128–141.
Jeshion, R. (2013a). Slurs and stereotypes. Analytic Philosophy, 54, 314–329.
Jeshion, R. (2013b). Expressivism and the offensiveness of slurs. Philosophical Perspectives, 27,
231–259.
Jeshion, R. (Forthcoming). Slurs, dehumanization, and the expression of contempt. In D. Sosa (Ed.), Bad
words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kukla, R. (2014). Performative force, convention, and discursive injustice. Hypatia, 29(2), 440–457.
Kukla, R., & Lance, M. (2009). ‘Yo!’ and ‘Lo!’: The pragmatic topography of the space of reasons.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lance, M., & Kukla, R. (2013). Leave the gun; take the cannoli! The pragmatic topography of secondperson calls. Ethics, 123, 456–478.
Langton, R. (1993). Speech acts and unspeakable acts. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 22(4), 293–330.
Langton, R. (1998). Subordination, silence, and pornography’s authority. In R. Post (Ed.), Censorship and
silencing: Practices of cultural regulation (pp. 261–284). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Langton, R. (2012). Beyond belief: Pragmatics in hate speech and pornography. In I. Maitra & M.
K. McGowan (Eds.), Speech and harm: Controversies over free speech (pp. 94–120). Ocford:
Oxford University Press.
Lawrence, C. R. (1993). If he hollers let him go. In M. Matsuda, C. R. Lawrence, R. Delgado, & K.
Williams Crenshaw (Eds.), Words that wound. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 339–359.
Lukes, S. (1974). Power: A radical view. London: Macmillan.
Lycan, W. (2015). Slurs and lexical presumption. Language Sciences, 52, 3–11.
Maitra, I. (2009). Silencing speech. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(2), 309–338.
Maitra, I. (2012). Subordinating speech. In I. Maitra & M. K. McGowan (Eds.), Speech and harm:
Controversies over free speech (pp. 94–120). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mallon, M. (2003). Social construction, social roles, and stability. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing
metaphysics: The nature of social reality (pp. 327–354). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Matsuda, M., Lawrence, C. R., Delgado, R., & Williams Crenshaw, K. (1993). Words that wound.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
McGowan, M. K. (2003). Conversational exercitives and the force of pornography. Philosophy and
Public Affairs, 31, 155–189.
McGowan, M. K. (2004). Conversational exercitives: Something else we do with our words. Linguistics
and Philosophy, 27, 93–111.
McGowan, M. K. (2009). Oppressive speech. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87(3), 389–407.
McGowan, M. K. (2012). On ‘‘whites only’’ signs and racist hate speech: Verbal acts of racial
discrimination. In I. Maitra & M. K. McGowan (Eds.), Speech and harm: Controversies over free
speech (pp. 222–250). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McKinnon, C. (1993). Only words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Nielsen, L. B. (2012). Power in public: Reactions, responses, and resistance to offensive public speech. In
I. Maitra & M. K. McGowan (Eds.), Speech and harm: Controversies over free speech (pp.
148–173). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nunberg, G. (Forthcoming). The social life of slurs. In D. Fogal, D. Harris, & M. Moss (Eds.), New work
on speech act. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Popa-Wyatt, M. (2016). Not all slurs are equal. Phenomenology and Mind, 11, 150–156.
Potts, C. (2007). The expressive dimension. Theoretical Linguistics, 33(2), 165–197.
Predelli, S. (2013). Meaning without truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
123
M. Popa-Wyatt, J. L. Wyatt
Richard, M. (2008). When truth gives out. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ross, C. T. (2015). A multi-level Bayesian analysis of racial bias in police shootings at the county-level in
the United States, 2011–2014. PloS One. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0141854.
Saka, P. (2007). How to think about meaning. Berlin: Springer.
Schlenker, P. (2007). Expressive presuppositions. Linguistics, 33(2), 237–245.
Stanley, J. (2015). How propaganda works. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Stephens-Davidowitz, S. (2014). The cost of racial animus on a black candidate: Evidence using Google
search data. Journal of Public Economics, 118, 26–40.
Swanson, E. (ms). Slurs and ideologies. In Ideology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tirrell, L. (1999). Derogatory words: Racisim, sexism, and the inferential theory of meaning. In C.
Hendricks & K. Oliver (Eds.), Language and liberation: Feminism, philosophy, and language (pp.
41–79). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Tirrell, L. (2012). Genocidal language games. In I. Maitra & M. K. McGowan (Eds.), Speech and harm:
Controversies over Free Speech (pp. 174–221). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Warner, L., & DeFleur, M. L. (1969). Attitude as an interactional concept: Social constraint and social
distance as intervening variables between attitudes and action. American Sociological Review, 34,
153–169.
Weber, M. (1978). Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology (trans: Ephraim Fischoff
et al.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
West, C. (2012). Words that silence? Freedom of expression and racist hate speech. In I. Maitra & M.
K. McGowan (Eds.), Speech and harm: Controversies over free speech (pp. 222–250). Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Whiting, D. (2013). It’s not what you said, it’s the way you said it: Slurs and conventional implicatures.
Analytic Philosophy, 54, 364–377.
Williamson, T. (2009). Reference, inference, and the semantics of pejoratives. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi
(Eds.), The philosophy of David Kaplan (pp. 137–158). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Young, M. (1990). Five faces of oppression. Justice and the politics of difference (pp. 39–65). Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
123